Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-s22k5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-22T07:38:43.883Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Irrationality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 January 2025

Ema Sullivan-Bissett
Affiliation:
University of Birmingham

Summary

This Element surveys contemporary philosophical and psychological work on various forms of irrationality: akrasia, strange beliefs, and implicit bias. It takes up several questions in an effort to better illuminate these more maligned aspects of human behaviour and cognition: what is rationality? Why is it irrational to act against one's better judgement? Could it ever be rational to do so? What's going wrong with beliefs in conspiracy theories, those arising from self-deception, or those which are classed as delusional? Might some of them in fact be appropriate responses to evidence? Are implicit biases irrational when they conflict with our avowed beliefs? Or might they be rational insofar as they track social realities?
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009641883
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 28 February 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

American Psychiatric Association 2013: Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders: DSM-5. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.Google Scholar
Ames, David 1984: ‘Self-Shooting of a Phantom Head’. The British Journal of Psychiatry. Vol. 145, no. 2, pp. 193–4.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Amodio, David M. and Devine, Patricia G. 2006: ‘Stereotyping and Evaluation in Implicit Race Bias: Evidence for Independent Constructs and Unique Effects on Behavior’. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 91, pp. 652–61.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Archer, Sophie 2013: ‘Nondoxasticism about Self-Deception’. Dialectica. Vol. 67, no. 3, pp. 265–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arpaly, Nomy 2000: ‘On Acting Rationally against One’s Best Judgment’. Ethics. Vol. 110, no. 3, pp. 488513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert 1982: ‘Self-Deception, Action and Will’. Erkenntnis. Vol. 18, no. 2, pp. 133–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert 1990: ‘Weakness of Will and Rational Action’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 68, no. 2, pp. 270–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basu, Rima 2020: ‘The Specter of Normative Conflict: Does Fairness Require Inaccuracy?’ In Beeghly, Erin and Madva, Alex (eds.) An Introduction to Implicit Bias: Knowledge, Justice, and the Social Mind. New York: Routledge, pp. 191210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bayne, Tim and Pacherie, Elisabeth 2004: ‘Bottom-Up or Top-Down: Campbell’s Rationality Account of Monothematic Delusions’. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. Vol. 11, pp. 111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Begby, Endre 2021: ‘Evidential Preemption’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Vol. 102, pp. 515–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentall, Richard P., Corcoran, Rhiannon, Howard, Robert, Blackwood, Nigel, and Kinderman, Peter 2001: ‘Persecutory Delusions: A Review and Theoretical Integration’. Clinical Psychology Review. Vol. 21, no. 8, pp. 1143–92.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bermúdez, José Luis 2000: ‘Self-Deception, Intentions, and Contradictory Beliefs’. Analysis. Vol. 60, no. 4, pp. 309–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermúdez, José Luis 2001: ‘Normativity and Rationality in Delusional Psychiatric Disorders’. Mind & Language. Vol. 16, no. 5, pp. 457–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berrios, Germán E. 1991: ‘Delusions as “Wrong Beliefs”: A Conceptual History’. British Journal of Psychiatry. Vol. 159, pp. 613.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bongiorno, Federico 2022: ‘Spinozan Doxasticism about Delusions’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. Vol. 103, no. 4, pp. 720–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bortolotti, Lisa 2009: Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bortolotti, Lisa 2015a: Irrationality. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Bortolotti, Lisa 2015b: ‘The Epistemic Innocence of Motivated Delusions’. Consciousness and Cognition. Vol. 33, pp. 490–99.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bortolotti, Lisa 2016: ‘Epistemic Benefits of Elaborated and Systematized Delusions in Schizophrenia’. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 67, no. 3, pp. 879–900.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bortolotti, Lisa 2018: ‘Stranger than Fiction: Costs and Benefits of Everyday Confabulation’. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. Vol. 9, pp. 227–49.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bortolotti, Lisa 2020: The Epistemic Innocence of Irrational Beliefs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bortolotti, Lisa and Broome, Matthew 2008: ‘Delusional Beliefs and Reason Giving’. Philosophical Psychology. Vol. 21, no. 6, pp. 821–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bortolotti, Lisa and Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2020: ‘The Epistemic Innocence of Clinical Memory Distortions’. Mind & Language. Vol. 3, no. 3, pp. 263–79.Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael 1979: ‘Practical Reasoning and Weakness of the Will’. Noûs. Vol. 13, no. 2, pp. 153–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Briñol, Pablo, Petty, Richard E., and McCaslin, Michael J. 2009: ‘Changing Attitudes on Implicit Versus Explicit Measures: What Is the Difference?’ In Petty, Richard E., Fazio, Russell H., and Briñol, Pablo (eds.) Attitudes: Insights from the New Implicit Measures. New York: Psychology Press, pp. 285326.Google Scholar
Brotherton, Rob 2015: Suspicious Minds: Why We Believe Conspiracy Theories. London: Bloomsbury Sigma.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rob, Brotherton, and French, Christopher. C. 2015: ‘Intention Seekers: Conspiracist Ideation and Biased Attributions of Intentionality’. PLoS ONE. Vol. 10, no. 5, e0124125.Google Scholar
Brownstein, Michael 2018: ‘Implicit Bias and Race’. In Taylor, , Paul, C., Alcoff, , Martin, Linda, and Anderson, , Luvell (eds.) The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Race. New York: Routledge, pp. 261–76.Google Scholar
Brownstein, Michael, Madva, Alex, and Gawronski, Bertram 2019: ‘What Do Implicit Measures Measure?WIREs Cognitive Science. Vol. 10, no. 5, e1501.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brownstein, Michael, Madva, Alex, and Gawronski, Bertram 2020: ‘Understanding Implicit Bias: Putting the Criticism into Perspective’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. Vol. 101, no. 2, pp. 276307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, John 2001: ‘Rationality, Meaning, and the Analysis of Delusion’. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology. Vol. 8, pp. 89–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, Jennifer Rose 2022: ‘Why Ideal Epistemology?’. Mind. Vol. 131, pp. 1131–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cassam, Quassim 2018: ‘Epistemic Insouciance’. Journal of Philosophical Research. Vol. 43, pp. 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coady, David 2003: ‘Conspiracy Theories and Official Stories’. International Journal of Applied Philosophy. Vol. 17, no. 2, pp. 199211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coltheart, Max and Davies, Martin 2021: ‘Failure of Hypothesis Evaluation as a Factor in Delusional Belief’. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry. Vol. 26, no. 4, pp. 213–60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coltheart, Max, Langdon, Robyn , and McKay, Ryan 2007: ‘Schizophrenia and Monothematic Delusions’. Schizophrenia Bulletin. Vol. 33, no. 3, pp. 642–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coltheart, Max, Menzies, Peter, and Sutton, John 2010: ‘Abductive Inference and Delusional Belief’. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry. Vol. 24, no. 3, pp. 165–77.Google Scholar
Coppock, Alexander 2022: Persuasion in Parallel. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corlett, Philip, Taylor, Jane R., Wang, Xiao-Jing, Fletcher, Paul C., and Krystal, John H. 2010: ‘Toward a Neurobiology of Delusions’. Progress in Neurobiology. Vol. 92, pp. 345–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crimmins, Mark 1992: ‘I Falsely Believe That P’. Analysis. Vol. 52, no. 3, p. 191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Currie, Gregory 2000: ‘Imagination, Hallucination and Delusion’. Mind & Language. Vol. 15, pp. 168–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1980: ‘How Is Weakness of the Will Possible?’ In Davidson, Donald (ed.) Essays on Actions and Events: Philosophical Essays Volume 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 2142.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1982: ‘Paradoxes of Irrationality’. In Wollheim, Richard, and Hopkins, James (eds.) Philosophical Essays on Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 289305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Martin and Coltheart, Max 2000: ‘Introduction: Pathologies of Belief’. Mind and Language. Vol. 15, no. 1, pp. 146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Martin, Coltheart, Max, Langdon, Robyn, and Breen, Nora 2001: ‘Monothematic Delusions: Towards a Two-Factor Account’. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. Vol. 8, nos. 2–3, pp. 133–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Martin, Davies, Aimola Anna, and Coltheart, Max 2005: ‘Anosognosia and the Two-Factor Theory of Delusions’. Mind and Language. Vol. 20, no. 2, pp. 209–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, Richard 2006: The God Delusion. London: Bantam Press.Google Scholar
De Houwer, Jan, Teige-Mocigemba, Sarah, Spruyt, Adriaan, and Moors, Agnes 2009: ‘Implicit Measures: A Normative Analysis and Review’. Psychological Bulletin. Vol. 135, pp. 347–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Houwer, Jan 2014: ‘A Propositional Model of Implicit Evaluation’. Social and Personality Psychology Compass. Vol. 8, no. 7, pp. 342–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dentith, Matthew R. X. 2018: ‘The Problem of Conspiracism’. Argumenta. Vol. 3, no. 2, pp. 327–43.Google Scholar
DeRose, Keith 1992: ‘Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Vol. 52, no. 4, pp. 913–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dodd, Dylan 2009: ‘Weakness of Will as Intention-Violation’. European Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 17, no. 1, pp. 4559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Karen M. and Sutton, Robbie M. 2023: ‘What Are Conspiracy Theories? A Definitional Approach to Their Correlates, Consequences, and Communication’. Annual Review of Psychology. Vol. 74, pp. 271–98.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Douglas, Karen Sutton, M., Robbie, M., Callan, Mitch J., Dawtry, Rael J., and Harvey, Annelie J. 2016: ‘Someone is Pulling the Strings: Hypersensitive Agency Detection and Belief in Conspiracy Theories’. Thinking and Reasoning. Vol. 22, no. 1, pp. 5777.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dub, Richard 2017: ‘Delusions, Acceptances, and Cognitive Feelings’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Vol. 94, no. 1, pp. 2760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dudley, Robert E. J., John, Carolyn H., Young, Andrew W., and Over, David E. 1997: ‘Normal and Abnormal Reasoning in People with Delusions’. British Journal of Clinical Psychology. Vol. 36, pp. 243–58.Google ScholarPubMed
Anna, Ebel-Lam, Fabrigar, Leandre R., MacDonald, Tara K., and Jones, Sarah 2010: ‘Balancing Causes and Consequences: The Magnitude-Matching Principle in Explanations for Complex Social Events’. Basic and Applied Social Psychology. Vol. 32, no. 4, pp. 348–59.Google Scholar
Egan, Andy 2008: ‘Imagination, Delusion, and Self-Deception’. In Bayne, Tim and Fernandez, Jordi (eds.) Delusion and Self-Deception. New York: Psychology Press, pp. 263–80.Google Scholar
Fazio, Russ 1990: ‘Multiple Processes by Which Attitudes Guide Behavior: The MODE Model as an Integrative Framework’. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology. Vol. 23, pp. 75109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankish, Keith 2009: ‘Delusions: A Two-level Framework’. In Broome, Matthew and Bortolotti, Lisa (eds.) Psychiatry as Cognitive Neuroscience: Philosophical Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 269–84.Google Scholar
Frankish, Keith 2016: ‘Playing Double: Implicit Bias, Dual Levels, and Self-Control’. In Brownstein, Michael and Saul, Jennifer (eds.) Implicit Bias and Philosophy, Vol. 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 2346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Cordelia, Craigie, Frankieian, and Gold, Ian 2005: ‘The Explanation Approach to Delusion’. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology. Vol. 12, no. 2, pp. 159–63.Google Scholar
Flores, Carolina forthcoming: ‘Why Think that Belief Is Evidence-Responsive?’ In Jong, Jonathan and Schwitzgebel, Eric (Eds.) The Nature of Belief. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Friedrich, James 1993: ‘Primary Error Detection and Minimization (PEDMIN) Strategies in Social Cognition: A Reinterpretation of Confirmation Bias Phenomena’. Psychological Review. Vol. 100, pp. 298319.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Funkhouser, Eric 2005: ‘Do the Self-Deceived Get What They Want?Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. Vol. 86, no. 3, pp. 295312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gao, Jie 2020: ‘Self-Deception and Pragmatic Encroachment: A Dilemma for Epistemic Rationality’. Ratio. Vol. 34, pp. 2032.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garety, Philippa A., Hemsley, David R., and Wessely, Simon 1991: ‘Reasoning in Deluded Schizophrenic and Paranoid Patients: Biases in Performance on a Probabilistic Inference Task’. The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease. Vol. 179, no. 4, pp. 194201.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gawronski, Bertram, Walther, Eva, and Blank, Hartmut 2005: ‘Cognitive Consistency and the Formation of Interpersonal Attitudes: Cognitive Balance Affects the Encoding of Social Information’. Journal of Experimental and Social Psychology. Vol. 41, pp. 618–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gendler, Tamar Szabó 2007: ‘Self-Deception as Pretense’. Philosophical Perspectives. Vol. 21, pp. 231–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gendler, Tamar 2011: ‘On the Epistemic Costs of Implicit Bias’. Philosophical Studies. Vol. 156, pp. 3363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerrans, Philip 2000: ‘Refining the Explanation of Cotard’s Delusion’. Mind & Language. Vol. 15, no. 1, pp. 111–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerrans, Philip 2001: ‘Delusions as Performance Failures’. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry. Vol. 6, no. 3, pp. 161–73.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gerrans, Philip 2002: ‘A One-stage Explanation of the Cotard Delusion’. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology. Vol. 9, no. 1, pp. 4753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerrans, Philip 2024: ‘Cotard Syndrome: The Experience of Inexistence’. In Sullivan-Bissett, Ema (ed.) Belief, Imagination, and Delusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 181204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibson, Quinn Hiroshi 2020: ‘Self-Deception as Omission’. Philosophical Psychology. Vol. 33, no. 5, pp. 657–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, Dan T., Tafarodi, Romin W., and Malone, Patrick S. 1993: ‘You Can’t Not Believe Everything You Read’. Attitudes and Social Cognition. Vol. 65, no. 2, pp. 221–33.Google ScholarPubMed
Gold, Ian and Gold, Joel 2024: ‘Delusion and Culture’. In Sullivan-Bissett, Ema (ed.) The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Delusion. Oxon: Routledge, pp. 533543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griggs, Richard A. and Cox, James R. 1982: ‘The Elusive Thematic-Materials Effect in Wason’s Selection Task’. British Journal of Psychology. Vol. 73, pp. 407–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helton, Grace 2018: ‘If You Can’t Change What You Believe, You Don’t Believe It’. Noûs. Vol. 54, no. 3, pp. 501–26.Google Scholar
Ralph, Hertwig, Christina, Leuker, Thorsten, Pachur, Leonidas, Spiliopoulos, and Pleskac, Timothy J. 2022: ‘Studies in Ecological Rationality’. Topics in Cognitive Science. Vol. 14, pp. 467–91.Google Scholar
Holroyd, Jules 2016: ‘What Do We Want from a Model of Implicit Cognition?Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Vol. CXVI, no. 2, pp. 153–79.Google Scholar
Holroyd, Jules and Sweetman, Joseph 2016: ‘The Heterogeneity of Implicit Bias’. In Brownstein, Michael and Saul, Jennifer (eds.) Implicit Bias and Philosophy. Volume one. Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 80103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holton, Richard 1999: ‘Intention and Weakness of Will’. The Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 96, no. 5, pp. 241–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holton, Richard 2009: Willing, Wanting, Waiting. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hubin, Donald C. 1990: ‘Irrational Desires’. Philosophical Studies. Vol. 62, pp. 2344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, Sean, Barnes-Holmes, Dermot, and Houwer, De, Jan 2011: ‘The Dominance of Associative Theorizing in Implicit Attitude Research: Propositional and Behavioural Alternatives’. The Psychological Record. Vol. 61, pp. 465–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, David 1739/2004: A Treatise of Human Nature. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Ichino, Anna 2020: ‘Superstitious Confabulations’. Topoi. Vol. 39, pp. 203–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ichino, Anna 2024: ‘Religious Imaginings’. In Sullivan-Bissett, Ema (ed.) Belief, Imagination, and Delusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ichino, Anna and Räikkä, Juha 2021: ‘Non-Doxastic Conspiracy Theories’. Argumenta. Vol. 7, no.1, pp. 247–63.Google Scholar
Johnson, Gabbrielle 2020: ‘The Psychology of Bias’. In Beeghly, Erin and Madva, Alex (eds.) An Introduction to Implicit Bias: Knowledge, Justice, and the Social Mind. Routledge, pp. 2040.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson-Laird, Phil N., Legrenzi, Paolo, and Sonino Legrenzi, Maria 1972: ‘Reasoning and Sense of Reality’. British Journal of Psychology. Vol. 63, pp. 395400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kiesewetter, Benjamin and Worsnip, Alex 2023: ‘Structural Rationality’. In Zalta, Edward N. and Nodelman, Uri (eds.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2023 Edition). URL: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rationality-structural/Google Scholar
Kelly, Daniel and Roedder, Erica 2008: ‘Racial Cognition and the Ethics of Implicit Bias’. Philosophy Compass. Vol. 3, no. 3, pp. 522–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan L. 2011: ‘Against Pragmatic Encroachment’. Logos & Episteme. Vol. II, no. 1, pp. 7785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer 2021: ‘Echo Chambers, Fake News, and Social Epistemology’. In Sven, Bernecker, Flowerree, Amy K., and Grundmann, Thomas (eds.) The Epistemology of Fake News. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 206–27.Google Scholar
Leary, Stephanie 2017: ‘In Defense of Practical Reasons for Belief’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 95, no. 3, pp. 529–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leitgeb, Hannes 2014: ‘A Way Out of the Preface Paradox?Analysis. Vol. 74, no. 1, pp. 1115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leman, Patrick J. and Cinnirella, Marco 2007: ‘A Major Event has a Major Cause: Evidence for the Role of Heuristics in Reasoning about Conspiracy Theories’. Social Psychology Review. Vol. 9, no. 2, pp. 1828.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Letheby, Christopher 2015: ‘The Epistemic Innocence of Psychedelic States’. Consciousness and Cognition. Vol. 39, pp. 2837.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levy, Neil 2015: ‘Neither Fish Nor Fowl: Implicit Attitudes as Patchy Endorsements’. Noûs. Vol. 49, no. 4, pp. 800–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, Neil 2021: Bad Beliefs: Why They Happen to Good People. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, Neil and Mandelbaum, Eric 2014: ‘The Powers that Bind: Doxastic Voluntarism and Epistemic Obligation’. In Matheson, Jonathan and Vitz, Rico (eds.) The Ethics of Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Livingstone-Smith, David 2014: ‘Self-Deception: A Teleofunctional Approach’. Philosophia. Vol. 42: pp. 181–99.Google Scholar
Machery, Edouard 2016: ‘De-Freuding Implicit Attitudes’. In Brownstein, Michael and Saul, Jennifer (eds.) Implicit Bias and Philosophy. Volume one. Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 104–29.Google Scholar
Madva, Alex 2016: ‘Why Implicit Attitudes are (Probably) Not Beliefs’. Synthese. Vol. 193, pp. 2659–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, Brendan 1974: ‘Delusional Thinking and Perceptual Disorder’. Journal of Individual Psychology. Vol. 30, No. 1, 98113.Google ScholarPubMed
Maher, Brendan 1988: ‘Anomalous Experience and Delusional Thinking: The Logic of Explanations’. In Oltmanns, Thomas and Maher, Brendan (eds.) Delusional Beliefs. John Wiley and Sons, pp. 1533.Google Scholar
Makinson, David C. 1965: ‘The Paradox of the Preface’. Analysis. Vol. 25, no. 6, pp. 205–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandelbaum, Eric 2013: ‘Against Alief’. Philosophical Studies. Vol. 165, pp. 197211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandelbaum, Eric 2016: ‘Attitude, Inference, Association: On the Propositional Structure of Implicit Bias’. Noûs. Vol. 50, pp. 629–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandik, Peter 2007: ‘Shit Happens’. Episteme. Vol. 4, no. 2, pp. 205–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manktelow, Ken and Evans, Jonathan St B. T. 1979: ‘Facilitation of Reasoning by Realism: Effect or Non-effect?British Journal of Psychology. Vol. 70, no. 4, pp. 477–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCormick, Miriam Schleifer 2015: Believing Against the Evidence: Agency and the Ethics of Belief. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
McIntyre, Alison 2006: ‘What Is Wrong with Weakness of Will?The Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 103, no. 6, pp. 284311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKay, Ryan 2012: ‘Delusional Inference’. Mind & Language. Vol. 27, no. 3, pp. 330–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKay, Ryan 2015: ‘Bayesian Accounts and Black Swans: Questioning the Erotetic Theory of Delusional Thinking’. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry. Vol. 20, no. 5, pp. 456–66.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McKay, Ryan and Mercier, Hugo 2023: ‘Delusions as Epistemic Hypervigilance’. Association for Psychological Science. Vol. 32, no. 2, pp. 125–30.Google Scholar
McKenna, Peter 2017: Delusions: Understanding the Un-understandable. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKenna, Robin 2023: Non-Ideal Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, Brian 2009: ‘Monothematic Delusions and Existential Feelings’. In Bayne, Tim and Fernández, Jordi (eds.) Delusion and Self-Deception. New York: Psychology Press, pp. 139–64.Google Scholar
Mele, Alfred 2001: Self-Deception Unmasked. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mele, Alfred 2009: ‘Self-Deception and Delusions’. In Bayne, Tim and Fernandez, Jordi (Eds.) Delusion and Self-Deception. New York and London: Taylor and Francis, pp. 5569.Google Scholar
Mishara, Aaron L. 2010: ‘Klaus Conrad (1905–1961): Delusional Mood, Psychosis, and Beginning Schizophrenia’. Schizophrenia Bulletin. Vol. 36, no. 1, pp. 913.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, Chris J., Houwer, De, Jan, and Lovibond, Peter F. 2009: ‘The Propositional Nature of Human Associative Learning’. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. Vol. 32, pp. 183–98.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Miyazono, Kengo, Bortolotti, Lisa, and Broome, Matthew 2014: ‘Prediction-Error and Two-Factor Theories of Delusion Formation: Competitors or Allies?’ In Galbraith, Neil (ed.) Aberrant Beliefs and Reasoning. Psychology Press, pp. 3454.Google Scholar
Miyazono, Kengo and Salice, Alessandro 2021: ‘Social Epistemological Conception of Delusion’. Synthese. Vol. 199, pp. 1831–51.Google Scholar
Murphy-Hollies, Kathleen and Caporuscio, Chiara 2023: ‘What Is Left of Irrationality?Philosophical Psychology. Vol. 36, no. 4, pp. 808–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nanay, Bence 2021: ‘Implict Bias as Mental Imagery’. Journal of the American Philosophical Association. Vol. 7, pp. 329–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Napolitano, M. Giulia 2021: ‘Conspiracy Theories and Evidential Self-Insulation’. In Sven, Bernecker, Flowerree, Amy K. and Grundmann, Thomas (eds.) The Epistemology of Fake News. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 82105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nguyen, C. Thi 2020: ‘Echo Chambers and Epistemic Bubbles’. Episteme. Vol. 17, no. 2, pp. 141–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noordhof, Paul 2009: ‘The Essential Instability of Self-Deception’. Social Theory and Practice. Vol. 35, no. 1, pp. 4571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noordhof, Paul 2024a: ‘Delusion and Doxasticism’. In Sullivan-Bissett, Ema (ed.) The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Delusion. Routledge. Oxon: Routledge, pp. 292–307.Google Scholar
Noordhof, Paul 2024b: ‘Delusion and Doxasticism’. In Sullivan-Bissett, Ema (ed.) The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Delusion. Routledge. Oxon: Routledge, pp. 308–323.Google Scholar
Noordhof, Paul manuscript: ‘Sub-Category Generalism About Conspiracy Theories’.Google Scholar
Noordhof, Paul and Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2021: ‘The Clinical Significance of Anomalous Experience in the Explanation of Delusion Formation’. Synthese. Vol. 199, pp. 1027710309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noordhof, Paul and Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2023: ‘The Everyday Irrationality of Monothematic Delusion’. In Henne, Paul and Murray, Sam (eds.) Advances in Experimental Philosophy of Action. London: Bloomsbury, pp. 87111.Google Scholar
Oswald, Frederick L., Mitchell, Gregory, Blanton, Hart, Jaccard, James, & Tetlock, Philip E. (2013). ‘Predicting Ethnic and Racial Discrimination: A Meta-analysis of IAT Criterion studies’. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. Vol. 105, no. 2, pp. 171–92.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Over, David E. and Evans, Jonathan St B. T. 2024: Human Reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Payne, Keith B. and Gawronski, Bertram 2010: ‘A History of Implicit Social Cognition: Where Is It Coming From? Where Is It Now? Where Is It Going?’ In Gawronski, Bertram and Payne, Keith B. (eds.) Handbook of Implicit Social Cognition: Measurement, Theory, and Applications. New York: Guilford Press, pp. 115.Google Scholar
Pierre, Joseph M. 2020: ‘Mistrust and Misinformation: A Two-Component, Socio-Epistemic Model of Belief in Conspiracy Theories’. Journal of Social and Political Philosophy. Vol. 8, no. 2, pp. 617–41.Google Scholar
Puddifoot, Katherine 2017: ‘Dissolving the Epistemic/Ethical Dilemma over Implicit Bias’. Philosophical Explorations. Vol. 20, pp. 7393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Puddifoot, Katherine 2021: How Stereotypes Deceive Us. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reimer, Marga 2010: ‘Only a Philosopher or a Madman: Impractical Delusions in Philosophy and Psychiatry’. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. Vol. 17, no. 4, pp. 315–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rey, Georges 1988: ‘Toward a Computational Account of Akrasia and Self-Deception’. In Rorty, Amelie O. and McLaughlin, Brian P. (eds.) Perspectives on Self-Deception. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 264–96.Google Scholar
Rinard, Susanna 2017: ‘No Exception for Belief’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Vol. XCIV, no. 1, pp. 121–43.Google Scholar
Rorty, Amelie Oksenberg 1980: ‘Where Does the Akratic Break Take Place?Australasian Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 58, no. 94, pp. 333–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, Robert M., Pennycook, Gordon, McKay, Ryan, Gervais, Will M., Langdon, Robyn, and Coltheart, Max 2016: ‘Analytic Cognitive Style, Not Delusional Ideation, Predicts Data Gathering in a Large Beads Task Study’. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry. Vol. 21, no. 4, pp. 300–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rysiew, Patrick 2008: ‘Rationality Disputes – Psychology and Epistemology’. Philosophy Compass. Vol. 3, no. 6, pp. 1153–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuels, Richard, Stich, Stephen, and Faucher, Luc 2004: ‘Reason and Rationality’. In Niiniluoto, I., Sintonen, M., and Woleński, J. (Eds.) Handbook of Epistemology, pp. 131179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, Mark 2012: ‘Stakes, Withholding, and Pragmatic Encroachment on Knowledge’. Philosophical Studies. Vol. 160, pp. 265–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott-Kakures, Dion 1996: ‘Self-Deception and Internal Irrationality’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Vol. 56, no. 1, pp. 3156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sechrist, Gretchen and Stangor, Charles 2001: ‘Perceived Consensus Influences Intergroup Behavior and Stereotype Accessibility’. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. Vol. 80, no. 4, pp. 645–54.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spaulding, Shannon 2015: ‘Imagination, Desire, and Rationality’. The Journal of Philosophy. Vol. CXII, no. 9, pp. 457–76.Google Scholar
Stein, Edward 1997: Without Good Reason: The Rationality Debate in Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stone, Tony and Young, Andrew W. 1997: ‘Delusions and Brain Injury: The Philosophy and Psychology of Belief’, Mind & Language. Vol. 12, no. 3–4, pp. 327–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stroud, Sarah and Tappolet, Christine 2003: ‘Introduction’. In Stroud, Sarah and Tappolet, Christine (eds.) Weakness of Will and Practical Irrationality. Oxford University Press, pp. 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Justin, Sulik, Ross, Robert M., Ryan, Balzan, and McKay, Ryan 2023: ‘Delusion-Like Beliefs and Data Quality: Are Classic Cognitive Biases Artifacts of Carelessness?Journal of Psychopathology and Clinical Science. Vol. 132, no. 6, pp. 749–60.Google Scholar
Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2015: ‘Implicit Bias, Confabulation, and Epistemic Innocence’. Consciousness and Cognition. Vol. 33, pp. 548–60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2018: ‘Monothematic Delusion: A Case of Innocence from Experience’. Philosophical Psychology. Vol. 31, no. 6, pp. 920–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2019: ‘Biased by Our Imaginings’. Mind & Language. Vol. 34, pp. 627–47.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2020: ‘Unimpaired Abduction to Alien Abduction: Lessons on Delusion Formation’. Philosophical Psychology. Vol. 33, no. 5, pp. 679704.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2022: ‘Against a Second Factor’. Asian Journal of Philosophy. Vol. 1, article 33, pp. 110.Google Scholar
Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2023: ‘Implicit Bias and Processing’. In Thompson, Robert (ed.) The Routledge Handbook of Implicit Cognition. Routledge, pp. 115–25.Google Scholar
Sullivan-Bissett, Ema 2024: ‘Introduction’. In Sullivan-Bissett, Ema (ed.) The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Delusion. Routledge. Oxon: Routledge, pp. 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan-Bissett, Ema forthcoming: ‘Evolutionary Pressures on Belief Capacities’. In Lombrozo, Tania and Leeuwen, Van, Neil (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of the Cognitive Science of Belief.Google Scholar
Tetlock, Philip 2017: Expert Political Judgment: How Good Is It? How Can We Know? Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Tetlock, Philip, Kristel, Orie, Elson, Beth, Green, Melanie, and Lerner, Jennifer 2000: ‘The Psychology of the Unthinkable: Taboo Trade-offs, Forbidden Base Rates, and Heretical Counterfactuals’. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. Vol. 78, no. 5, pp. 853–70.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thorstad, David 2024: ‘Why Bounded Rationality (in Epistemology)?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Vol. 102, no. 2, pp. 396413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todd, Peter M. and Gigerenzer, Gerd 2012: Ecological Rationality: Intelligence in the World. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Toribio, Josefa 2018: ‘Implicit Bias: from Social Structure to Representational Format’. Theoria. Vol. 33, pp. 4160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trope, Yaacov and Liberman, Akiva 1996: ‘Social Hypothesis Testing: Cognitive and Motivational Mechanisms’. In Higgins, Edward T. and Kruglanski, Arie W. (eds.) Social Psychology: Handbook of Basic Principles. New York: Guilford Press, pp. 239–70.Google Scholar
Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel 1974: ‘Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases’. Science. Vol. 185, no. 4157, pp. 1124–31.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel 1983: ‘Extensional Versus Intuitive Reasoning: The Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgement’. Psychological Review. Vol. 90, pp. 293315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van der Wal, Reine C., Sutton, Robbie M., Lange, Jens, and Braga, Joao, P. N. 2018: ‘Suspicious Binds: Conspiracy Thinking and Tenuous Perceptions of Causal Connections between Co-occurring and Spuriously Correlated Events’. European Journal of Social Psychology. Vol. 48, no. 7, pp. 970–89.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Van Leeuwen, Neil 2007: ‘The Product of Self-Deception’. Erkenntnis. Vol. 67, pp. 419–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Prooijen, Jan-Willem and Douglas, Karen M. 2018: ‘Belief in Conspiracy Theories: Basic Principles of an Emerging Research Domain’. European Journal of Social Psychology. Vol. 48, no. 7, pp. 897908.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
van Prooijen, Jan-Willem, Wahring, Iris, Mausolf, Laura, Nicole, Mulas, and Shwan, Shayda 2023: ‘Just Dead, Not Alive: Reconsidering Belief in Contradictory Conspiracy Theories’. Psychological Science. Vol. 34, no. 6, pp. 670–82.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wason, Peter C. 1964: ‘The Effect of Self-Contradiction on Fallacious Reasoning’. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology. Vol. 16, pp. 30–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wason, Peter C. 1966: ‘Reasoning’. In Foss, Brian (ed.) New Horizons in Psychology. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Wason, Peter C. and Shapiro, Diana 1971: ‘Natural and Contrived Experience in a Reasoning Problem’. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology. Vol. 23, pp. 6371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Daniel 2021: ‘Socially Adaptive Belief’. Mind & Language. Vol. 36, pp. 333–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Daniel 2023: ‘Bad Beliefs: Why they Happen to Highly Intelligent, Vigilant, Devious, Self-Deceiving, Coalitional Apes’. Philosophical Psychology. Vol. 36, no. 4, pp. 819–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, Michael J., Douglas, Karen M., and Sutton, Robbie M. 2012: ‘Dead and Alive: Beliefs in Contradictory Conspiracy Theories’. Social Psychological and Personality Science. Vol. 3, no. 6, pp. 767–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
World Health Organisation 2023: ‘World Health Statistics 2023’. www.who.int/data/stories/world-health-statistics-2023-a-visual-summary.Google Scholar
Yachanin, Stephen A. 1980: ‘Differential Effects of Thematic Materials and Order of Rule Presentation on a Reasoning Task’. Unpublished Masters Thesis, Bowling Green State University.Google Scholar
Young, Andrew W., Robertson, Ian H., Hellawell, D. J., de Pauw, Karel W., and Pentland, Brian 1992: ‘Cotard Delusion after Brain Injury’. Psychological Medicine, Vol. 22, pp. 799804.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Young, Garry 2024: ‘The Capgras Delusion: An Interactionist Approach Revisited’. In Sullivan-Bissett, Ema (ed.) Belief, Imagination, and Delusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 151182.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Irrationality
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Irrationality
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Irrationality
Available formats
×