Lectures 6-7: Deontological & Consequential Ethics
Lectures 6-7: Deontological & Consequential Ethics
Consequential Ethics
Consider these quotes:
Before we consider
consequential and
deontological
ethics, let’s explore
some other basic
terms that are
important to know:
A. Theistic:
1. Given to us by God;
2. Is required by Natural Law (theistic connection);
our own law- 2. Test our maxims by asking, whether, supposing the
maxims were natural laws, there would be a society
making ought to of that kind. In other words, we are obligated to act
only by maxims which would harmonize a possible
harmonize with a kingdom of ends.
possible kingdom of 3. We have a perfect duty not to act by maxims that
ends as a kingdom create incoherent or impossible states of natural
affairs when we attempt to universalize them;
of nature." We have an imperfect duty not to act by maxims that
promote unstable or greatly undesirable states of
Grounding for the affairs.
Metaphysics of “Kant seems to assume that those who apply the categorical
imperative to their maxims will come out with answers that
Morals, 4:436/104. agree when the maxims tested are alike.” J.B. Schneewind,
“Autonomy, Obligation, & Virtue,” pg. 338.
Third Categorical Imperative introduces a
social dimension to Kantian Morality
The formulation of the CI states that we must “act in accordance with the
maxims of a member giving universal laws for a merely possible
kingdom of ends” (4:439).
It combines the others in that (i) it requires that we conform our actions
to the maxims of a legislator of laws (ii) that this lawgiver lays down
universal laws, binding all rational wills including our own, and (iii) that
those laws are of ‘a merely possible kingdom’ each of whose members
equally possesses this status as legislator of universal laws, and hence
must be treated always as an end in itself.
The intuitive idea behind this formulation is that our fundamental moral
obligation is to act only on principles which could earn acceptance by a
community of fully rational agents each of whom have an equal share in
legislating these principles for their community.
Summary of first three categorical
imperatives:
The Categorical Imperative requires that I act
only on maxims that I can will as universal law.
“Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the
person of any other, never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an end.”
Rather than thinking that humanity is the goal or proper end of our action, he presupposes
that humanity is a limit or constraint on our action.
This kind of constraint can be seen mostly clearly by tracing the connection with the first formula, the
Formula of Universal Law. Remember, the agent must be willing to eliminate all individual reference
from the maxim of her action. The most significant exclusion here is that of herself. Therefore, be
prepared go on willing the maxim even if it contains no reference to herself.
The constraint that the second formula imposes is that the maxim of an action must be such that any
other free and rational person can adopt it. Treating humanity as an end in itself is, for Kant,
respecting our capacity for free and rational choice; in his term, it is respecting our autonomy. I am
constrained, according to this first formula, by the consideration that is wrong, other things being
equal, to impede the agency of others. To treat another human being as merely a means is to ignore
the other as a center of agency. The clearest cases here are those of coercion and deception.
For example: If I take the hand of one of my students in my class and with it I strike the neighbouring
student’s face, I have bypassed the first student’s agency. I have treated her merely as a means, as
though she were merely an organic hitting implement. The same is true when I deceive somebody,
because if I conceal the nature of the situation, I impede her ability to make a free and rational choice
for that situation.
1st Categorical Imperative:
The constraint that the second formula imposes is that the maxim of
an action must be such that any other free and rational person can
adopt it. Treating humanity as an end in itself is, for Kant, respecting
our capacity for free and rational choice; in his term, it is respecting
our autonomy. I am constrained, according to this first formula, by
the consideration that is wrong, other things being equal, to impede
the agency of others. To treat another human being as merely a
means is to ignore the other as a center of agency. The clearest cases
here are those of coercion and deception.
1. Lying and not keeping promise can’t be a universal law for one
can’t will that would be universal will.
"A third finds in himself a talent which with the help of some culture
might make him a useful man in many respects. But he finds himself in
comfortable circumstances and prefers to indulge in pleasure rather
than to take pains in enlarging and improving his happy natural
capacities. He asks, however, whether his maxim of neglect of his
natural gifts, besides agreeing with his inclination to indulgence,
agrees also with what is called duty. He sees then that a system of
nature could indeed subsist with such a universal law although men
(like the South Sea islanders) should let their talents rest and resolve to
devote their lives merely to idleness, amusement, and propagation of
their species- in a word, to enjoyment; but he cannot possibly will that
this should be a universal law of nature, or be implanted in us as such
by a natural instinct. For, as a rational being, he necessarily wills that
his faculties be developed, since they serve him and have been given
him, for all sorts of possible purposes." (Quoted from the Fundamental
Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals, as translated by T.K. Abbott)
3rd example: Developing One’s
Habits
“When I’m comfortable as I am, I shall let all my
talents rust.”
1. Everyone necessarily wills that some of his or her talents be developed.
3. Non-use of talents is morally right if and only if the agent thinking about
non-use of talents can consistently will that non-use of talents be a
universal law. (The Categorical Imperative)
2. If everyone necessarily wills this, then no one can consistently will that
non-help be a universal law.
3. Not helping others is morally right if and only if the agent thinking
about not helping others can consistently will that not helping others be
a universal law. (The Categorical Imperative)
1. No clear way to resolve moral duties when they come into conflict with each
other.
3. Do not readily allow for gray areas because they are based on absolutes.
4. Which duties qualify given time or location: Are old duties still valid?
5. Human welfare and misery: Some principles may result in a clash with what
is best for human welfare & prescribe actions which cause human misery.
7. Exclusive focus on “rationality” ignores our relations to & with other human
beings.
There is no clear way to deal with moral conflicts
consider the following:
a. Killer comes to the door: If a killer comes to the door and ask
for a friend of yours inside whom he intends to kill, you must
tell the truth (illustration by Kant).
But there is only one exceptionless rule in Kant’s philosophy and that is
given in the categorical imperative: We are never permitted to do what we
cannot will as a universal law or what violates the requirement to treat
persons as persons.
Kant may not give us adequate help in deciding what to do when moral
conflicts are involved because in the above example, both to tell the truth
and preserve life are moral obligations.
Regarding Impartiality & Rationality:
4. I purchase another
expensive “GQ suit” to
add to my already stuffed
closet-for it will bring me
pleasure. But is that small
increment of pleasure
even remotely comparable
to the pleasure and relief
of suffering that would
result if I took that same
money and purchased
clothes to orphan children
or a threadbare family?
A closer look at Utilitarianism:
Mill did not regard all pleasures equally. He made a distinction between
higher and lower pleasures.
Mill rejects Bentham's hedonic calculus because he believes that
pleasures and pains are incommensurable.
Individuals who have not taken the time to develop their intellectual capabilities are
unlikely to share the view that the improvement of the human condition is of
paramount importance.
11. On Democracy:
Although he favored democracy, Mill sees the possibility for domination of the
minority by the majority under a strict system of "mob rule.“
Accordingly, Mill argues that safeguards be put in place to protect the interests and
viewpoints of minorities in the political process. Note that the term minority is not
meant to denote racial minorities, but rather all types of political and social
minorities that do not share majority/mainstream views.
Utilitarianism vs. Deontological Ethics: