0% found this document useful (0 votes)
8 views32 pages

Lecture 03

The document covers propositional logic, including tautologies, contradictions, and contingencies, as well as logical equivalence and truth tables. It introduces predicate logic, variables, and quantifiers, explaining their roles in expressing logical statements and translating English into logical expressions. Additionally, it discusses negating quantified expressions and provides examples of translating sentences into predicate logic.

Uploaded by

ZenitsuAgatsuma
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
8 views32 pages

Lecture 03

The document covers propositional logic, including tautologies, contradictions, and contingencies, as well as logical equivalence and truth tables. It introduces predicate logic, variables, and quantifiers, explaining their roles in expressing logical statements and translating English into logical expressions. Additionally, it discusses negating quantified expressions and provides examples of translating sentences into predicate logic.

Uploaded by

ZenitsuAgatsuma
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 32

Lecture 3:

Propositional Equivalence
Section 1.3
Tautologies, Contradictions, and
Contingencies
● A tautology is a proposition which is always true.
○ Example: p ∨¬ p
● A contradiction is a proposition which is always false.
○ Example: p ∧¬ p
● A contingency is a proposition which is neither a
tautology nor a contradiction, such as p

P ¬p p ∨¬ p p ∧¬ p
T F T F
F T T F
Logical Equivalence: Examples
● Two compound propositions p and q are logically equivalent if p↔q
is a tautology.
● We write this as p ⇔ q or as p ≡ q where p and q are compound
propositions.
● Two compound propositions p and q are equivalent if and only if the
columns in a truth table giving their truth values agree.
● This truth table shows that ¬p ∨ q is equivalent to p → q.
p q ¬p ¬p ∨ q p→ q
T T F T T
T F F F F
F T T T T
F F T T T
Example: De Morgan’s Laws
Augustus De Morgan

1806-1871

This truth table shows that De Morgan’s Second Law holds.

p q ¬p ¬q (p∨q) ¬(p∨q) ¬ p∧¬q


T T F F T F F
T F F T T F F
F T T F T F F
F F T T F T T
Example: Distributive Laws

This truth table shows that distributive law of disjunction over conjunction holds.

p q r q∧r p ∨ (q ∧ r ) p∨q p∨r (p ∨ q) ∧ (p ∨ r)


T T T T T T T T
T T F F T T T T
T F T F T T T T
T F F F T T T T
F T T T T T T T
F T F F F T F F
F F T F F F T F
F F F F F F F F
Predicates and Quantifiers
Section 1.4
Section Summary
● Predicates
● Variables
● Quantifiers
○ Universal Quantifier
○ Existential Quantifier
● Negating Quantifiers
○ De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
● Translating English to Logic
Introducing Predicate Logic
● Predicate logic uses the following new features:
○ Variables: x, y, z
○ Predicates: P(x), M(x)
○ Quantifiers (to be covered in a few slides):
● Propositional functions are a generalization of
propositions.
○ They contain variables and a predicate, e.g., P(x)
○ Variables can be replaced by elements from their
domain .
Propositional Functions
● Propositional functions become propositions (and
have truth values) when their variables are each
replaced by a value from the domain (or bound by a
quantifier, as we will see later).
● For example, let P(x) denote “x > 0” and the domain
be the integers. Then:
○ P(-3) is false.
○ P(0) is false.
○ P(3) is true.
● Often the domain is denoted by U. So in this example U
is the integers.
Examples of Propositional
Functions
● Let “x + y = z” be denoted by R(x, y, z) and U (for all
three variables) be the integers.
Find these truth values:
R(2,-1,5) Solution: F
R(3,4,7) Solution: T
R(x, 3, z) Solution: Not a Proposition

● Now let “x - y = z” be denoted by Q(x, y, z), with U as


the integers. Find these truth values:
Q(2,-1,3) Solution: T
Q(3,4,7) Solution: F
Q(x, 3, z) Solution: Not a Proposition
Compound Expressions
● If P(x) denotes “x > 0,” find these truth values:
P(3) ∨ P(-1) Solution : T
P(3) ∧ P(-1) Solution : F
P(3) → P(-1) Solution : F
P(3) → ¬P(-1) Solution : T
● Expressions with variables are not propositions and
therefore do not have truth values. For example,
P(3) ∧ P(y)
P(x) → P(y)
● When used with quantifiers (to be introduced next),
these expressions (propositional functions) become
propositions.
Quantifiers Charles Peirce (1839-1914)

● We need quantifiers to express the meaning of English


words including all and some:
○ “All men are Mortal.”
○ “Some cats do not have fur.”
● The two most important quantifiers are:
○ Universal Quantifier, “For all,” symbol: ∀
○ Existential Quantifier, “There exists,” symbol: ∃
● We write as in ∀x P(x) and ∃x P(x).
● ∀x P(x) means P(x) is true for every x in the domain.
● ∃x P(x) means P(x) is true for some x in the domain.
● The quantifiers are said to bind the variable x in these
expressions.
Universal Quantifier
○ ∀x P(x) is read as “For all x, P(x)” or “For every x, P(x)”
Examples :
■ If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then ∀x P(x) is
false.
■ If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the positive integers, then
∀x P(x) is true.
■ If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers, then ∀x
P(x) is false.
Existential Quantifier
● ∃x P(x) is read as “For some x, P(x)”, or as “There is an
x such that P(x),” or “For at least one x, P(x).”
Examples :
■ If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then ∃x P(x) is
true. It is also true if U is the positive integers.
■ If P(x) denotes “x < 0” and U is the positive integers, then
∃x P(x) is false.
■ If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers, then ∃x
P(x) is true.
Thinking about Quantifiers
● When the domain is finite, we can think of quantification as
looping through the elements of the domain.
● To evaluate ∀x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
○ If at every step P(x) is true, then ∀x P(x) is true.
○ If at a step P(x) is false, then ∀x P(x) is false and the loop
terminates.
● To evaluate ∃x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
○ If at some step, P(x) is true, then ∃x P(x) is true and the loop
terminates.
○ If the loop ends without finding an x for which P(x) is true, then ∃x
P(x) is false.
● Even if the domains are infinite, we can still think of the
quantifiers this fashion, but the loops will not terminate in some
cases.
Properties of Quantifiers
● The truth value of ∃x P(x) and ∀ x P(x) depend on
both the propositional function P(x) and on the
domain U.
● Examples :
○ If U is the positive integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then ∃x P(x) is true, but ∀x P(x) is false .
○ If U is the negative integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then both ∃x P(x) and ∀x P(x) are true .
○ If U consists of 3, 4, and 5, and P(x) is the statement
“x > 2”, then both ∃x P(x) and ∀x P(x) are true .
○ But if P(x) is the statement “x < 2”, then both ∃x P(x)
and ∀ x P(x) are false .
Precedence of Quantifiers
● The quantifiers ∀ and ∃ have higher precedence than
all the logical operators.
● For example, ∀x P(x) ∨ Q(x) means (∀x P(x))∨ Q(x)
● ∀x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)) means something different.
● Unfortunately, often people write ∀x P(x) ∨ Q(x) when
they mean ∀x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)).
Translating from English to Logic
Example 1 : Translate the following sentence into
predicate logic: “Every student in this class has taken a
course in Java .”
Solution :
First decide on the domain U.
Solution 1 : If U is all students in this class, define a
propositional function J(x) denoting “x has taken a
course in Java” and translate as ∀x J(x).
Solution 2 : But if U is all people, also define a
propositional function S(x) denoting “x is a student in
this class” and translate as ∀x (S(x)→ J(x)).
∀x (S(x) ∧ J(x)) is not correct. What does it mean?
Translating from English to Logic
Example 2 : Translate the following sentence into
predicate logic: “Some student in this class has taken a
course in Java .”
Solution :
First decide on the domain U.
Solution 1 : If U is all students in this class, translate as
∃x J(x)
Solution 2 : But if U is all people, then translate as
∃x (S(x) ∧ J(x))
∃x (S(x)→ J(x)) is not correct. What does it mean?
Equivalences in Predicate Logic
● Statements involving predicates and quantifiers are
logically equivalent if and only if they have the same
truth value
○ for every predicate substituted into these statements and
○ for every domain of discourse used for the variables in
the expressions.
● The notation S ≡T indicates that S and T are logically
equivalent.
● Example : ∀x ¬¬S(x) ≡ ∀x S(x)
Thinking about Quantifiers as
Conjunctions and Disjunctions
● If the domain is finite, a universally quantified proposition
is equivalent to a conjunction of propositions without
quantifiers and an existentially quantified proposition is
equivalent to a disjunction of propositions without
quantifiers.
● If U consists of the integers 1,2, and 3:

● Even if the domains are infinite, you can still think of the
quantifiers in this fashion, but the equivalent expressions
without quantifiers will be infinitely long.
Negating Quantified Expressions
● Consider ∀x J(x)
“Every student in your class has taken a course in Java.”
Here J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java” and
the domain is students in your class.
● Negating the original statement gives “It is not the case
that every student in your class has taken Java.” This
implies that “There is a student in your class who has
not taken Java.”
Symbolically ¬∀x J(x) and ∃x ¬J(x) are equivalent
Negating Quantified Expressions
(continued)
● Now Consider ∃ x J(x)
“There is a student in this class who has taken a course in
Java.”
Where J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java.”
● Negating the original statement gives “It is not the case
that there is a student in this class who has taken Java.”
This implies that “Every student in this class has not
taken Java”
Symbolically ¬∃x J(x) and ∀x ¬J(x) are equivalent
De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
● The rules for negating quantifiers are:

● The reasoning in the table shows that:


Translation from English to Logic
Examples :
1. “Some student in this class has visited Mexico.”
Solution : Let M(x) denote “x has visited Mexico” and S(x)
denote “x is a student in this class,” and U be all
people.
∃x (S(x) ∧ M(x))
2. “Every student in this class has visited Canada or
Mexico.”
Solution : Add C(x) denoting “x has visited Canada.”
∀x (S(x)→ (M(x)∨C(x)))
Some Translating from English into
Logical Expressions
● U = {fast, slow, turning}
F(x): x is fast
S(x): x is slow
T(x): x is turning
Translate “Everything is fast.”

Solution: ∀x F(x)
Translation (cont)
● U = {fast, slow, turning}
F(x): x is fast
S(x): x is slow
T(x): x is turning
“Nothing is slow.”

Solution: ¬∃x S(x) What is this equivalent to?


Solution: ∀x ¬ S(x)
Translation (cont)
● U = {fast, slow, turning}
F(x): x is fast
S(x): x is slow
T(x): x is turning
“All fast things are slow.”

Solution: ∀x (F(x)→ S(x))


Equivalent to: For all things, fast implies slow.
Translation (cont)
● U = {fast, slow, turning}
F(x): x is fast
S(x): x is slow
T(x): x is turning
“Some fast things are turning.”

Solution: ∃x (F(x) ∧ T(x))


Equivalent to: Some things are fast and turning
Translation (cont)
● U = {fast, slow, turning}
F(x): x is fast
S(x): x is slow
T(x): x is turning
“No slow thing is a turning.”

Solution: ¬∃x (S(x) ∧ T(x)) What is this equivalent to?


Solution: ∀x (¬S(x) ∨ ¬T(x))
Translation (cont)
● U = {fast, slow, turning}
F(x): x is fast
S(x): x is slow
T(x): x is turning
“If anything fast is a slow then it is also a turning.”

Solution: ∀x ((F(x) ∧ S(x))→ T(x))


Charles Lutwidge Dodgson
Lewis Carroll Example (AKA Lewis Caroll)
(1832-1898)
● The first two are called premises and the third is called the
conclusion.
○ “All lions are fierce.”
○ “Some lions do not drink coffee.”
○ “Some fierce creatures do not drink coffee.”
● Here is one way to translate these statements to predicate
logic. Let P(x), Q(x), and R(x) be the propositional functions “x
is a lion,” “x is fierce,” and “x drinks coffee,” respectively.
○ ∀x (P(x)→ Q(x))
○ ∃x (P(x) ∧ ¬R(x))
○ ∃x (Q(x) ∧ ¬R(x))
● Later we will see how to prove that the conclusion follows from
the premises.

You might also like