Models Numbers and Cases Methods For Studying International Relations Detlef F Sprinz PDF Download
Models Numbers and Cases Methods For Studying International Relations Detlef F Sprinz PDF Download
https://ebookbell.com/product/models-numbers-and-cases-methods-
for-studying-international-relations-detlef-f-sprinz-2339800
https://ebookbell.com/product/models-numbers-and-cases-methods-for-
studying-international-relations-draft-detlef-f-sprinz-2160516
https://ebookbell.com/product/linear-programming-models-and-methods-
of-matrix-games-with-payoffs-of-triangular-fuzzy-numbers-1st-edition-
dengfeng-li-5357988
How Economists Model The World Into Numbers Routledge Inem Advances In
Economic Methodology 1st Edition Marcel Boumans
https://ebookbell.com/product/how-economists-model-the-world-into-
numbers-routledge-inem-advances-in-economic-methodology-1st-edition-
marcel-boumans-2163966
Governance By Numbers The Making Of A Legal Model Of Allegiance Alain
Supiot Saskia Brown
https://ebookbell.com/product/governance-by-numbers-the-making-of-a-
legal-model-of-allegiance-alain-supiot-saskia-brown-50677820
https://ebookbell.com/product/models-and-idealizations-in-science-
artifactual-and-fictional-approaches-alejandro-cassini-46245004
https://ebookbell.com/product/models-of-the-church-dulles-
avery-46437820
https://ebookbell.com/product/models-of-criminal-procedure-system-
ruihua-chen-46456212
https://ebookbell.com/product/models-of-society-and-complex-systems-
sebastian-ille-46639760
MODELS, NUMBERS, AND CASES
Edited by
Detlef F. Sprinz
and Yael Wolinsky-Nahmias
Preface vii
Appendix 383
Contributors 387
Name Index 391
Subject Index 401
vi
1. Introduction: Methodology in
International Relations Research
1
Models, Numbers, and Cases
2
Introduction
There are three main issues that can help to evaluate the intellectual
progress of an academic ‹eld. The ‹rst issue is the set of empirical phe-
3
Models, Numbers, and Cases
nomena and questions being studied; the second issue is the state of theo-
retical development; and the third is the methodology used to form theo-
retical claims and test their empirical implications. This book focuses on
the issue of methodology, but also addresses the question of how method-
ology informs both theoretical and empirical debates. The links between
theory and methodology are complex and require some elaboration.3
Theory is de‹ned by the American Heritage Dictionary (1985) as
4
Introduction
5
Models, Numbers, and Cases
60
50
40
30
20
10
0
1975-1979 1980-1984 1985-1989 1990-1994 1995-2000
1. Descriptive analysis
2. Case studies
3. Quantitative (statistical) analysis
4. Formal modeling
5. Cross-methods studies
The broad trajectory over the period between 1975 and 2000 (grouped
as ‹ve-year intervals with the exception of the most recent group which
comprises six years) demonstrates important methodological trends in
international relations. The most profound trend evident in ‹gure 1 is the
continuing decline in the number of articles using a descriptive-historical
6
Introduction
7
Models, Numbers, and Cases
The survey of these leading journals also shows that few scholars in the
‹eld employ multimethod research. Less than 4 percent of all articles pub-
lished during the late 1990s in the journals surveyed combined two
methodological approaches. Cross-method analysis obviously requires
more training (or alternatively, cross-‹eld collaboration). However, it
allows scholars to investigate alternative explanations, compensate for
weaknesses in each of these methods, and corroborate research results.
This volume can foster a dialogue among scholars of international rela-
tions and reduce the costs of cross-method discourse by providing in-depth
discussions of methodological concerns associated with different methods
and substantive areas of IR research.
8
Introduction
9
Models, Numbers, and Cases
the generation of new theories. The chapter also provides guidance about
the criteria to use IR for selecting cases and deciding on the number of
variables to be studied. Bennett concludes by stressing the complementary
nature of case study methods, statistical analysis, and formal methods.
Following the introductory chapter on case study methodology, John
Odell reviews the intellectual development of case study analysis in the
sub‹eld of international political economy (chap. 3). The chapter discusses
various forms of single case studies, including the “method of difference,”
and explains both the advantages and limitations of these methods. Using
central studies in the ‹eld, ranging from E. E. Schattschneider’s classic
Politics, Pressures, and the Tariff (1935) to Richard Haass’s Economic
Sanctions and American Diplomacy (1998), Odell shows how qualitative
research has been instrumental in developing theories of international
political economy. He argues that case studies may support a theoretical
relationship but do not provide proof of causality. Therefore, he stresses the
value of using statistical methods empirical case studies.
In chapter 4, Ronald Mitchell and Thomas Bernauer examine the appli-
cation of case study methods to the study of international environmental
policy and outline procedures for designing and conducting qualitative
case studies. They discuss the problems inherent in analyzing small sam-
ples. The chapter offers ways to increase validity and reliability in small-n
studies by disaggregating cases into multiple events or observations.
Mitchell and Bernauer suggest that in order to advance positivist case
study research in international environmental policy and more broadly in
international relations, scholars must aim to derive testable hypotheses
with clearly identi‹ed variables and values.
The ‹rst part of the book concludes with Arie Kacowicz’s review of case
study methods in international security studies (chap. 5). Kacowicz
describes the contribution of empirical case study to ongoing debates in
international relations, such as the democratic peace thesis. He identi‹es
limitations of the method of difference and discusses recurring issues in the
application of case studies such as selection bias and endogeneity problems.
Kacowicz proposes several strategies for overcoming the methodological
limitations of case studies and recommends using case studies to generate
conditional theoretical statements. Finally, Kacowicz evaluates how case
study analysis has advanced research on international security.
Part 2 of the book focuses on the use of quantitative methods in IR
research. In their introductory chapter, Bear Braumoeller and Anne Sartori
10
Introduction
11
Models, Numbers, and Cases
12
Introduction
13
Models, Numbers, and Cases
tistical analyses, and formal methods) have advanced our knowledge of cen-
tral issues in international relations. We discuss some of the methodologi-
cal challenges raised in the book and address the opportunities and chal-
lenges of cross-methods analysis. We suggest a few thoughts about new
methodological developments and how they may affect future research on
international relations.
In summary, this book introduces the main methods of research in
international relations and addresses a broad range of questions, from how
empirical case studies of international relations can be designed to over-
come methodological challenges to how quantitative analysis can be inte-
grated with formal methods to advance IR research. It discusses limitations
and trade- offs in using case studies, statistical analysis, and formal meth-
ods in the study of international relations and evaluates applications of
these methods in studies of international political economy, international
environmental politics, and security studies. Improving methodologies
and generating a dialogue among scholars who specialize in different issue
areas and methods will enhance the ability of researchers to conceptualize,
theorize, and better understand trends and changes in international poli-
tics.
Notes
We would like to thank Roshen Hendrickson and especially So Young Kim for
their research assistance.
1. We chose to focus on these three methods because these are the most com-
mon methods used in IR research.
2. Helen Milner (chap. 11) suggests that studies of international institutions
and cooperation should be thought of as part of the ‹eld of international political
economy if they involve the study of economic variables.
3. Books on methodology in the social sciences do not always distinguish
between theory and methodology. For example, some consider “quantitative stud-
ies” and “formalized rational choice” either a “metatheoretical orientation” or
“theoretical position” (Wæver 1998, 701–3). More generally, some social science
methodology books, in particular in Europe, restrict themselves to a philosophy-
of-science perspective—at the expense of more modern methodological considera-
tions for social science research.
4. We also reviewed the statistical data excluding APSR because the journal
publishes political science research not limited to the study of international rela-
14
Introduction
tions. We found that excluding APSR led to higher ratios of formal and statistical
articles, but the reported trends remain the same.
5. International Security began publishing in 1976, so we surveyed the period
1976–2001.
6. The authors thank So Young Kim for her research assistance for this survey.
7. The classi‹cation is based on the following criteria: “Descriptive analysis”
includes articles based on historical analysis that lack clearly detectable methodol-
ogy; “Case studies” include articles that use any of the research approaches dis-
cussed in chapter 2 and justi‹cation for the case selection; “Quantitative analysis”
ranges from simple correlation/covariance analysis and factor analysis to more
sophisticated regression analysis; “Formal modeling” ranges from soft rational
choice theory, simulation, and game-theoretic models to more sophisticated for-
mal analysis that includes a mathematical proof; and “Cross-methods” analysis
includes articles that combine at least two methodologies (mostly quantitative and
formal analyses).
8. The book can also be read in conjunction with other books that have a dif-
ferent focus. One of the prominent books on methodological problems in the social
sciences is Designing Social Inquiry by Gary King, Robert O. Keohane, and Sid-
ney Verba (1994). It considers general methodological problems of social inquiry
such as research design and causal inference (but it does not focus on issues that are
of particular importance to the study of international relations). Another valuable
book in the area of methodology, more speci‹c to international relations, is Daniel
Frei and Dieter Ruloff’s Handbook of Foreign Policy Analysis (1989), which cov-
ers mostly formal and statistical approaches to the study of foreign policy. Other
books that discuss theories of international politics include Patrick M. Morgan’s
Theories and Approaches to International Politics (1987) and Michael Don
Ward’s Theories, Models, and Simulations in International Relations (1985).
These books, however, were published during the late 1980s or early 1990s. A
more recent edited volume that offers a re›ective evaluation of methodology in
international studies is Frank P. Harvey and Michael Brecher’s Evaluating
Methodology in International Studies (2002).
References
15
Models, Numbers, and Cases
Frei, D., and D. Ruloff. 1989. Handbook of Foreign Policy Analysis : Methods for
Practical Application in Foreign Policy Planning, Strategic Planning, and
Business Risk Assessment. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.
Goldmann, K. 1995. Im Westen Nichts Neues: Seven International Relations
Journals in 1972 and 1992. European Journal of International Relations 1 (2):
245–58.
Guetzkow, H. S., and M. D. Ward. 1985. Theories, Models, and Simulations in
International Relations: Essays and Research in Honor of Harold Guetzkow.
Boulder: Westview.
Haass, R. N., ed. 1998. Economic Sanctions and American Diplomacy. Washing-
ton, DC: Brookings Institution Press.
Harvey, F. P., and M. Brecher, eds. 2002. Evaluating Methodology in Interna-
tional Studies. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Hirschman, A. 1945. National Power and the Structure of Foreign Trade. Berke-
ley: University of California Press.
King, G. 1991. On Political Methodology. In Political Analysis: An Annual Pub-
lication of the Methodology Section of the American Political Science Associa-
tion, edited by J. A. Stimson. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
King, G., R. O. Keohane, and S. Verba. 1994. Designing Social Inquiry: Scienti‹c
Inference in Qualitative Research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Lakatos, I. 1986. Falsi‹cation and the Methodology of Scienti‹c Research Pro-
grammes. In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, edited by I. Lakatos and
A. Musgrave. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Morgan, P. M. 1987. Theories and Approaches to International Politics: What
Are We to Think? New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
Schattschneider, E. E. 1935. Politics, Pressures, and the Tariff. Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice- Hall.
Schultz, K. A. 1999. Do Democratic Institutions Constrain or Inform? Contrast-
ing Institutional Perspectives on Democracy and War. International Organiza-
tion 53 (2): 233–66.
Wæver, O. 1998. The Sociology of a Not So International Discipline: American
and European Developments in International Relations. International Organi-
zation 52 (4): 687–727.
16
Part I. Case Study Methods
2. Case Study Methods: Design, Use,
and Comparative Advantages
Andrew Bennett
19
Models, Numbers, and Cases
20
Case Study Methods
Within this general de‹nition of case studies, there are many types of case
studies. Some methodological texts focus on theory-testing cases at the
expense of theory development. It is important to keep in mind, however,
that there are several kinds of contributions to theory, including the gen-
eration of new hypotheses (the “logic of discovery”) as well as the testing of
existing ones (the “logic of con‹rmation”). In addition, there are several
kinds of research objectives, including not only the development of gener-
alized theories but the historical explanation of particular cases, that is,
explanation of a sequence of events that produce a particular historical out-
come in which key steps in the sequence are in turn explained with refer-
ence to theories or causal mechanisms. Case studies can contribute to all of
these kinds of theory building, as Arend Lijphart (1971) and Harry Eck-
stein (1975) indicated in their similar taxonomies of different kinds of case
studies, outlined in table 1 (from George 1979a).
21
Models, Numbers, and Cases
Apart from the ‹rst type, which is simply a kind of chronological narra-
tive, case studies have an explanatory or theory-building purpose. “Inter-
pretive” or “disciplined con‹gurative” cases use theoretical variables to
provide historical explanations of particular cases. In other words, they use
theories to show that in the particular historical circumstances of the case,
the outcome was to be expected. Heuristic case studies seek to generate
new hypotheses inductively. “Deviant” cases, or cases whose outcomes are
not predicted or explained well by existing theories, can be particularly
useful in identifying new or left-out variables. Finally, researchers can use
case studies to test whether extant theories accurately explain the processes
as well as the outcomes of particular cases. Herein, I use Eckstein’s termi-
nology, which is more common, with the addition of Lijphart’s term for
the study of “deviant” cases.
Process Tracing
22
Case Study Methods
23
Models, Numbers, and Cases
detective to look for “new” evidence in the case that had previously been
ignored or considered irrelevant. If the new evidence ‹ts the prediction of
the new theory, this is considered an independent corroboration.4
Process tracing is not infallible. Measurement error and omitted vari-
ables can lead to incorrect inferences in process tracing just as they can in
statistical methods. There are also practical limits on our ability to observe
or trace processes in all of their nearly in‹nite detail and to establish fully
continuous sequences. The requisite evidence may not be available at key
steps in the process, and even where evidence is available, we may not have
the time to go through all of it. Yet by insisting that we establish explana-
tions that document the intervening variables and processes through which
the hypothesized independent variables are purported to have brought
about the observed outcome, process tracing differs from and complements
statistical inferences. Although no case study is undertaken in the in‹nite
level of detail that would be needed to establish a fully continuous process,
case study explanations are open to challenge if they are inconsistent with
the ‹nest level of detail that is observable. For example, if a rational choice
theory posits that an individual should have gone through a rational calcu-
lation that led to a certain behavior, but it can be shown in a case study that
the individual’s thinking process was actually very different from that
posited by the theory, then the theory cannot constitute a satisfactory
explanation of the case even if its predicted outcome is consistent with the
observed outcome.
Congruence Testing
24
Case Study Methods
posed necessary or suf‹cient conditions, and they may weaken the plausi-
bility of particular historical explanations of cases.
Counterfactual Analysis
25
Models, Numbers, and Cases
There are ‹ve research design tasks common to both single and compara-
tive case studies, many of them common to statistical studies as well
(George 1979a; George and McKeown 1985). First, the researcher must
de‹ne the research objective, including the class of events to be explained,
the alternative hypotheses under consideration, and the kind of theory
building to be undertaken. Second, the researcher must specify the inde-
pendent, dependent, and intervening variables and decide which of these
are to be controlled for and which are to vary across cases or types of cases.
Third, the researcher selects the cases to be studied, possibly assisted by the
typological space that results from the speci‹cation of the variables and
alternative hypotheses. Fourth, the researcher should consider how best to
describe variance in the independent and dependent variables, considering
not only individual variables but also types of cases, or combinations of
variables, and the sequential pathways that characterize each type. Finally,
the researcher speci‹es the structured questions to be asked of each case in
order to establish the values of the independent, intervening, and depen-
dent variables.
An example from my own work illustrates how these tasks were accom-
plished in one study.5 I chose to study Soviet and Russian military inter-
ventionism and to try to explain the puzzle of why such interventionism
appeared to increase in the 1970s, decrease in the 1980s, and increase once
again in the mid-1990s. I ‹rst had to de‹ne interventionism, the propensity
for intervention, as distinct from actual military interventions. This required
de‹ning in a general way what constituted an inviting or uninviting
26
Case Study Methods
27
Models, Numbers, and Cases
28
Case Study Methods
Within the context of general research design tasks, there are speci‹c con-
siderations that apply to single and comparative case studies. Some
methodologists have downplayed the theory-building contributions that
can be made by single-case research designs (King, Keohane, and Verba
1994, 209–11). In contrast, most case study researchers have argued that
single-case studies can provide tests that might strongly support or
impugn theories. Many in›uential research ‹ndings in political science
have come from single-case studies that presented anomalies for accepted
theories.8
An important single-case research design is the study of crucial, most
likely, and least likely cases that pose severe tests of theories. Harry Eck-
stein developed the idea of a “crucial case,” or a case that “must closely ‹t a
theory if one is to have con‹dence in the theory’s validity, or, conversely,
must not ‹t equally well any rule contrary to that proposed” (1975, empha-
sis in original). Because true crucial cases were rare in Eckstein’s view, he
pointed to the alternative of “most likely” and “least likely” cases. A most
likely case is one that is almost certain to ‹t a theory if the theory is true
for any cases at all. The failure of a theory to explain a most likely case
greatly undermines our con‹dence in the theory. A least likely case, con-
versely, is a tough test for a theory because it is a case in which the theory
is least likely to hold true. Eckstein’s conception is a useful starting point
on theory testing in case studies, but it is at best incomplete because he
does not address whether the cases in question are most or least likely for
competing theories, or whether these theories predict the same outcome as
the theory of interest or a different outcome altogether. Thus, a more com-
plete version of Eckstein’s insight would be that a theory is most strongly
supported when it makes a clear prediction on the outcome or process of a
29
Models, Numbers, and Cases
case, all other theories make clear predictions that we should not ‹nd this
outcome or process, and the ‹rst theory is corroborated in the case. Con-
versely, if both our theory of interest and the alternative theories make the
same prediction on the outcome or process of a case, but this prediction
proves wrong, then the theory of interest is strongly impugned because its
failure cannot be explained away by the operation of other theories or
mechanisms.9 Single-case studies that ‹t either of these situations can
greatly increase or decrease our con‹dence in a theory or require that we
alter its scope conditions, although we can never entirely rule out the pos-
sibility that the outcome or process of the case was caused by probabilistic
processes analogous to those of quantum mechanics.
Another important single-case research design is the study of a deviant
or outlier case. Research on deviant cases can help inductively identify
variables and hypotheses that have been left out of existing theories.
Deviant cases may also uncover measurement errors that may exist in less
extreme forms in other cases.
Single-case study designs can ful‹ll the other theory-building purposes
identi‹ed by Lijphart and Eckstein as well. Idiographic studies, while
often disdained, may provide data for later more theoretically oriented case
studies. Also, a study of a newly de‹ned puzzle or phenomenon might
begin with a fairly open-ended effort—sometimes called “soaking and
poking” in the data—to generate hypotheses that can then be tested more
systematically.10
Comparative Methods
30
Case Study Methods
This corresponds with the “most similar case” research design (Prze-
worski and Teune 1970). It has also been called the method of “controlled
comparison,” because if two cases in fact are the same in all but one inde-
pendent variable, then we have the functional equivalent of a controlled
experiment. The practical limitation here, of course, is that two cases are
almost never identical in all but one independent variable (George
1979a).11
In actual practice, case study researchers almost never draw conclusions
on the basis of Mill’s methods alone because these methods require
demanding and unrealistic assumptions in order to provide nonspurious
inferences. One key limitation of Mill’s methods, which Mill himself
identi‹ed, is that they cannot work well in the presence of equi‹nality
(George 1982). A condition of equi‹nality, or what Mill called a “plurality
31
Models, Numbers, and Cases
of causes,” holds when the same outcome can arise through different path-
ways or combinations of variables. Thus, when equi‹nality is present, there
might be no single necessary or suf‹cient variable for a phenomenon: it
might be that either ABC or DEF causes Y, and that none of the variables
A through F is by itself suf‹cient to cause Y. In such circumstances, pair-
wise comparisons of cases might lead us wrongly to reject variables that can
cause an outcome in conjunction with some contexts but not others, and it
might also lead us to accept a confounding variable as causal rather than
recognizing that its relationship to the outcome is spurious.
Thus Mill’s methods can work well at identifying causal relations only
under three conditions that are impossible to realize fully in practice. First,
the causal relations being investigated must be deterministic regularities
involving conditions that by themselves are either necessary or suf‹cient
for a speci‹ed outcome. This implies that there can be no causally relevant
interaction effects. Second, all variables that contributed causally to the
outcome would have to be identi‹ed and included in the analysis. Third,
cases that represent the full range of all logically and socially possible
causal paths must be available for study (Little 1998; George and McKe-
own 1985).
Because these requirements are unrealistic, case study researchers use
Mill’s methods in only a very general and preliminary way to identify
potentially relevant variables, but they then rely heavily on process tracing
to compensate for the evident weakness of Mill’s methods (Mahoney
1999).12 For example, when it is not possible to ‹nd cases similar in all but
one independent variable and the dependent variable, process tracing can
test whether each of the potentially causal variables that differ between the
imperfectly matched cases can be ruled out as having causal signi‹cance.13
32
Case Study Methods
the cases to be studied and compared; (4) decides how best to characterize
variance in the independent and dependent variables; and (5) formulates a
detailed set of standard questions to be applied to each case.
In addition, consistent with his emphasis on equi‹nality, George
argued that case studies could be especially useful in developing what he
called “typological theories,” or contingent generalizations on “the variety of
different causal patterns that can occur for the phenomena in question [and]
the conditions under which each distinctive type of causal patterns occurs” (1979a,
emphasis in original). He advocated a kind of “building block” approach to
the development of theories. In this approach, each case, while rendered in
terms of theoretical variables, might prove to be a distinctive pathway to
the outcome of interest. Typological theories treat cases as con‹gurations of
variables that may involve complex interactions among all of the variable
values in the case. While statistical methods can model interactions effects
as well, this puts added pressure on the sample size necessary to be
con‹dent in one’s results, and statistical studies rarely model interactions
among all the variables acting together, as a typological theory may do.
Typological theories make less restrictive assumptions about case com-
parisons than Mill’s methods. Speci‹cally, typological theory assumes that
if cases within the same type, or with the same mix of independent vari-
ables, have different outcomes on the dependent variable, the difference in
the outcome is due to measurement error or left-out variables, not to the
type of probabilistic relations theorized in quantum physics. This
addresses a common misinterpretation of case study methods, namely, that
they assume or require restrictive forms of determinism (Lieberson 1992).
It is certainly true that all forms of case comparison are much stronger
sources of inference when a variable is a necessary or suf‹cient condition for
a particular outcome. But it is also true that some forms of case comparison
require more deterministic assumptions than others, and most case study
researchers appear to assume that equi‹nality is a common condition in
social life (Ragin 1987). The minimal assumptions of typological theory
are in fact similar to those of the statistical researchers who interpret the
“error term” in their equations as including measurement error or left-out
variables.14 This assumption sets aside a third possibility, which can never
be de‹nitively ruled out, namely, that the error term can also represent a
fundamentally stochastic element analogous to the irreducible probabilism
of quantum mechanics.
33
Models, Numbers, and Cases
Construct Validity
34
Case Study Methods
Case studies can also heuristically identify new variables and hypotheses.
This can take place through the study of deviant cases, as noted earlier, but
it also happens in the ordinary course of ‹eldwork, such as archival research
and interviews with participants, area experts, and historians. The popular
refrain that observations are theory-laden does not mean that they are the-
ory-determined. When a case study researcher asks a participant, “Were
you thinking x when you did y,” and they get the answer, “No, I was think-
ing z,” they may have a new variable demanding to be heard. Statistical
methods lack any counterpart for this process; some methods of “data min-
ing” or “exploratory data analysis” can be used to identify potentially rele-
vant variables, but even these methods can use only data that is already
coded into data sets, or data that someone has already identi‹ed as
suf‹ciently useful to be worth coding. Statistical studies that do not
involve archival work or interviews to measure or code variables have no
inductive means of identifying new variables, although deductive theoriz-
ing, whether by a researcher using statistical methods or a formal modeler,
can also identify new variables.16
Case studies can use process tracing to examine in detail the observable
implications of hypothesized causal mechanisms in individual cases. Causal
mechanisms can be de‹ned as the ultimately unobservable entities or
structures that operate in speci‹c contexts to generate the phenomena that
we observe in the physical or social world.17
35
Models, Numbers, and Cases
36
Case Study Methods
Conversely, not only can we use a case study to explore causal mechanisms,
we can use causal mechanisms to give historical explanations of cases. His-
torical explanation is quite different from the development and testing of
variable-centered theories based on the statistical study of a large number
of cases. In historical explanation, the researcher uses theories at each step
of a historical process to show how the variables made subsequent steps and
the ultimate outcome likely under the historical circumstances of the case
(Roberts 1996). This is quite different from establishing statistical gener-
37
Models, Numbers, and Cases
38
Case Study Methods
One of the most common critiques of case study methods is that they are
prone to “selection bias” (Achen and Snidal 1989; Geddes 1990). Selection
bias, in statistical terminology, occurs “when some form of selection
process in either the design of the study or the real-world phenomena
under investigation results in inferences that suffer from systematic error”
(Collier and Mahoney 1996, 59). Such biases can occur when the researcher
selects cases that represent a truncated sample along the dependent vari-
able of the relevant universe of cases (Collier and Mahoney 1996, 60; King,
Keohane, and Verba 1994, 128–32). In statistical research, the standard
presentation of selection bias suggests that a truncated sample typically
understates the strength of the relationship between the independent and
dependent variables. In other words, it reduces the magnitude of the esti-
mated beta coef‹cients; Huth and Allee note that in some instances selec-
tion biases can also reverse the sign of the coef‹cients in statistical studies
(see chap. 9, this vol.). This is why statistical researchers are recurrently
admonished not to select cases on the dependent variable (Collier and
Mahoney 1996, 60).
Practitioners and analysts of case study methods, however, have argued
that cases selected on the dependent variable can test whether a variable is
necessary for the selected outcome (Dion 1997; Collier 1995; Goertz and
Starr 2003, 30). If a variable hypothesized to be necessary for a speci‹ed
outcome can be shown to have been absent in even a single case in which
the outcome occurred, then this case can disprove the claim that the vari-
39
Models, Numbers, and Cases
40
Case Study Methods
Potential Indeterminacy
41
Models, Numbers, and Cases
Lack of Representativeness
42
Case Study Methods
Another issue concerns whether cases are independent of one another. Here
again, there is a particular statistical version of this problem that does not
apply to case studies, and a more fundamental version that does. In a sta-
tistical study, if a correlation is the result not of the hypothesized relation-
43
Models, Numbers, and Cases
ship under consideration but of learning or diffusion from one case to the
others, then the additional cases do not provide as much new information
as if they were fully independent of one another, so in effect the sample size
is smaller than if the cases were independent (George 1982, 19–23; King,
Keohane, and Verba 1994, 222; and see Huth and Allee, chap. 9, this vol.,
for a related discussion of this issue in the context of statistical methods).
This is sometimes referred to as Galton’s problem. In case studies, there is
a danger that the researcher will fail to identify a lack of independence
between cases, but this danger does not manifest itself as a problem related
to the sample size or number of cases studied, and it is not necessarily
ampli‹ed by the intentional selection of cases based on a preliminary
knowledge of their variables (indeed, such intentional selection may be
designed speci‹cally to assess the independence of cases or the diffusion
processes among them). As Alexander George has argued, the question of
whether the independence of cases is a relevant consideration is not a ques-
tion that can be answered “on a priori grounds; the answer surely depends
on the research objectives of a particular study, what theory or hypothesis
is being developed, and how the comparison of cases is structured” (1982,
21). As George notes, process tracing can inductively uncover linkages
between cases and reduce the dangers of any unanticipated lack of inde-
pendence of cases. When learning or diffusion processes are anticipated or
uncovered and taken into account, they need not undercut the value of
studying partially dependent cases. Indeed, only cases that are perfectly
dependent provide no additional information (King, Keohane, and Verba
1994, 222). Moreover, as George points out, case study methods can be
particularly effective at examining precisely the kinds of path-dependent
learning and diffusion processes that give rise to Galton’s problem (George
1982, 21).
Other limitations of case study methods require only brief mention.
Case studies are better at determining the scope conditions under which
variables have an effect than estimating the magnitude of that effect. This
latter task of assessing the causal “weight” or causal effect of variables is
better performed through statistical studies. Case study researchers also
face a trade-off between doing richly detailed studies of a small number of
cases versus seeking broader generalizations across a larger number of cases.
Often the best approach is for each researcher to focus in detail on a small
but well-de‹ned subset of cases or types of cases, while making compar-
44
Case Study Methods
isons to existing research in the same research program so that the ‹eld as
a whole incrementally ‹lls out the typological space.
In sum, critiques of case study methods through the prism of statistical
concepts have often misconstrued the strengths and weaknesses of case
studies. On the issues of degrees of freedom, “representativeness,” inde-
pendence of cases, and the use of Mill’s methods, case studies are generally
stronger than their critics have suggested. On the question of case selection
and selection bias, standard statistical critiques have overstated some
methodological problems but understated others. The two most constrain-
ing limits of case study methods are the problem of getting a range of cases
for study that covers many of the possible causal paths or types and the
problem of interpreting outcomes and processes that are consistent with
more than one theory. Both of these problems have received less attention
because they do not ‹t as readily into statistical terms (for exceptions see
Little 1998; Ragin 1987; Lieberson 1992; Njolstad 1990).
45
Models, Numbers, and Cases
visual display, and the high degree of replicability of studies using the
same database. Limitations of standard statistical methods include the
challenges they face in identifying new variables, dealing with multiple
conjunctural causality or equi‹nality, devising conceptually valid opera-
tionalizations of qualitative variables, and providing or testing historical
explanations of individual cases. Some of these limitations may be inherent
in statistical methods, while others may involve trade-offs that could ease
somewhat with the development of more sophisticated statistical tech-
niques. Notably, these advantages and limitations are almost precisely the
converse of the ones associated with case study methods, which are poor at
partial correlations and measures of frequency but good at identifying new
variables, dealing with complex causal relations, and devising and testing
historical explanations.
46
Exploring the Variety of Random
Documents with Different Content
so small as to embarrass Government, it would be much worse than
if they were to vote for a little too much. There would be a certain
number of men who must be fed, and he thought they might rely
upon the Administration's not giving more for rations than was
necessary. But, if the sum voted was too small, what would be the
consequence? The rations must be got, be the prices what they
may; the men must be fed. Difficulties would arise if the fund
appropriated should prove inadequate. He did not see that there
would be any real saving by reducing the sum appropriated.
Mr. Bourne hoped the blank would be filled up with the sum proposed
by the gentleman from South Carolina. It had been stated that
rations might be purchased at Pittsburg for 11 cents, but they could
not be bought for less than 30 at Detroit, and he thought they could
not calculate upon any other price than that, as it was uncertain
whether or not the contract would be fulfilled; and if it failed, and
the Secretary of the Treasury was obliged to purchase at Detroit, if
they calculated the rations at 20 cents only, he would not be able to
purchase the necessary provisions for their men; but if, on the
contrary, 30 cents were agreed to, there would be enough in any
case, and if the ration could be bought for 20 cents, he did not fear
that the money would be expended unnecessarily.
Mr. Venable said he should not feel himself justified in appropriating
more than was necessary for the object before them; for, if they
were not to be guided by a proper estimate, they might as well at
once give an unlimited power on the Treasury. All the expenses
could not be estimated to be made at Detroit. If one-third of our
men were kept at Detroit, he should think it a large number. Why,
then fix the price as if the whole Army was to be kept there? And,
even in that case, 20 cents would be a large appropriation. Why,
then, embarrass themselves by making a larger appropriation than
was necessary? The Army would be extended on the whole frontier,
and at some places rations would be bought cheaper than at
Pittsburg.
Mr. Dayton (the Speaker) observed, that the gentleman from
Pennsylvania (Mr. Gallatin) assumed as undeniable, and established
as the foundation of his arguments and objections, what he did not
only not admit, but absolutely denied, viz: that the rations of
provisions would cost the United States more when delivered at
Detroit, than at any other post. He believed there were two or three
others at which the price would be higher than at Detroit, and
mentioned Michilimacinac in particular. The gentlemen who were for
reducing this item of appropriation, had referred to the contract
which had been made some time since, and had, at the same time,
acknowledged the extraordinary advance in the price of the
necessaries of life, even in the interior of the country. The latter
event, said Mr. D., was of a nature to excite much fear that the
contract would be thrown back upon the United States, owing to the
inability it would create in the individuals to fulfil it, and ought,
therefore, to prompt Congress to guard against such an exigency, by
a more ample provision than would otherwise have been requisite.
Mr. W. Smith said there was one fact which he forgot to mention. The
Secretary of the Treasury informed the Committee of Ways and
Means that the contractor would lose money by the contract to
deliver the rations at 11 cents at Pittsburg, and it was possible,
therefore, that it might not be fulfilled. Gentlemen say—why provide
the money if it be not wanted? They seemed to mistake the
business; the money was to be borrowed, and if not wanted, it
would not be taken. No more would be expended because there was
more than sufficient appropriated. There would be no money lying
unemployed in the Treasury.
Mr. Gallatin believed the gentleman from South Carolina (Mr. Smith)
would not deny that his information was correct. The contract was
made to deliver the rations either at Pittsburg or Detroit, at the
option of Government. To calculate the whole number of rations at
30 cents, was considering the whole Army at Detroit; and, though it
be true, that there be one post more distant than Detroit, yet, the
greater number were far nearer, and consequently, where provisions
would be got cheaper. Therefore, considering the price at Detroit to
be the general price, was allowing too much. This, he believed,
would not be controverted.
Mr. Nicholas said, he should be glad to know what was the price of
rations in the Atlantic States. One half of the Establishment would be
upon the Eastern waters, and, therefore, the money necessary to be
appropriated would depend, in some degree, upon the price of
rations there. He thought 20 cents would be a full average price for
the whole.
Mr. Havens said, that if they were to fix the price too high, it might
produce a combination amongst the contractors to advance the price
—as he believed there was a greater likelihood of combination than
competition amongst them. He knew this was no reason why they
should fix the price too low, but he thought it was a consideration
which should lead them to vote for the proposition of the gentleman
from Pennsylvania.
The original motion was put, and negatived, 34 to 31; and then Mr.
Gallatin's, to fill the blank with $45,606, was put, and carried.
Mr. W. Smith moved to fill the next blank, for the subsistence of non-
commissioned officers and privates, with $369,282, which was
calculating the rations at 30 cents each.
The question was put, and negatived, 33 to 30.
Mr. Gallatin then moved to have the blank filled with $246,188,
which was calculating the rations at 20 cents each.
Mr. Dayton hoped that the sum named would not be agreed to; if it
were, he believed that the soldiers of the Army would not be
subsisted. He was satisfied that gentlemen who proposed and
advocated so scanty and inadequate sums had the same views as he
had; but he was, nevertheless, convinced, that so far from
promoting economy, they would eventually produce profusion.
Mr. Dayton concluded with saying, that he did not wish to appropriate
lavishly, but his sole aim was to avoid any of those serious
consequences which would inevitably flow from an ill-judged
parsimony; and he should sit down and console himself under any
event, with the reflection, that he had discharged his duty.
Mr. W. Smith moved to fill the blank with $360,000, which was
carried, 34 to 31.
On motion of Mr. W. Smith, the blank for forage was filled with
$16,592, and that for clothing was filled with $70,000, without
debate. He proposed to fill the blank for providing horses for cavalry,
with $7,500; when
Mr. Blount observed, that he thought it unnecessary to provide for
the purchase of horses, when they had resolved upon reducing the
number of troops.
Mr. Gallatin said he would just notice, that when the full number of
horses was kept up, the appropriations for clothing were the same
as now, and those for horses were less. The former estimate was
$6,000 for horses; now, $7,500; so that the more they reduce the
Army, the greater was the expense.
Mr. Macon believed, there were as many horses now in the service as
would complete two companies, and they could not, with any
propriety, calculate upon one-half dying. He moved to strike out the
item altogether.
The motion was put and negatived, 33 to 26.
Mr. Havens said, he did not vote for striking out the item altogether,
as he supposed some money would be wanted, but could not think
so much as had been mentioned was necessary.
The motion for $7,509 was put and carried, 34 to 31.
On motion of Mr. W. Smith, the blank for bounty was filled with
$10,000, and that for Hospital Department with $30,000, without
objection. He also proposed to fill the blank for the Ordnance
Department with $48,907, when
Mr. Gallatin said, that this sum was $11,000 more than the former
estimate; $1,000 of which was owing to an increase of rent. The
other additional item of $10,000 was for contingent expenses; but,
as they had a distinct head for contingent expenses he thought that
the contingencies would be best, all of them, placed under that
head. He therefore moved to have the blank filled with $38,907.
Mr. Williams proposed $40,000, which was carried.
Mr. W. Smith proposed to fill the blank for the Indian Department
with $70,000.
Mr. Gallatin said, it would be recollected that they had already made
two appropriations under this head; the one for establishing trading-
houses with the Indian tribes, the other for carrying into effect
several treaties. On inquiry what reason there was for this
appropriation, he could only find one, viz: that a treaty was expected
to be held in Georgia, at which 3,000 Indians were to be present. He
had supposed this expense was to have been borne by Georgia, but
it was alleged that a part of it would fall on the United States.
The motion was put and negatived, 33 to 26; when
Mr. W. Smith proposed $60,000. He would mention, that the
Secretary of War had been called upon to give a reason why so large
a sum should be appropriated; when they were told of the treaty
which the gentleman from Pennsylvania had mentioned, and that it
would be necessary to have a large store for the purpose of feeding
and clothing the Indians who attended it. The motion was then put
and carried, 31 to 28.
Mr. W. Smith moved to fill the blank for the Quartermaster's
Department with $250,000.
Mr. Gallatin said, it would be remembered that in the estimate at the
opening of the session, this item was calculated at $200,000. The
reason given for this advance, was, that the expense of removing
stores, ordnance, &c., to new posts, would be very considerable;
but, it would be recollected, that $200,000 only were appropriated
for that purpose in the time of war, when the Army was liable to be
removed very often. The present estimate was for a Peace
Establishment, when their men, once removed to the new posts,
would be stationed; and the appropriation, instead of for 6,000 men,
was now only for 3,000. He moved to insert $200,000, instead of
$250,000.
Mr. Blount said, he supposed the taking possession of the posts was
contemplated when the first estimate was made. It was then known
the British had stipulated to surrender them on the 1st of June.
Mr. W. Smith said, it was not certain when the first estimate was
made, whether that House would have ratified the treaty; and, if not
ratified, the posts would not have been got. The increased
calculation was owing to the expense in transporting ordnance,
stores, &c., to the posts.
Mr. Isaac Smith said, it would require more cannon for one of those
posts, than were required by all the Army.
Mr. Blount said, they had had sufficient proof to lead them to
believe, that the President did not think that House had the power
mentioned by the gentleman from South Carolina, and, therefore, he
doubted not but the first estimate was made with reference to the
expense of taking possession of the posts.
The motion for $250,000 was put and negatived, 31 to 26; when
$200,000 was put and carried.
Mr. W. Smith, moved to fill the blank for contingencies of the War
Department with $30,000; which was carried without opposition. He
then proposed to fill the blank for the defence and protection of the
frontiers with $150,000.
Mr. Gallatin said, he certainly wished the frontier to be protected, but
he could not think so large a sum necessary for that purpose. The
sum last year appropriated was $130,000; and now we had peace
with the Indians, which was secured not only by a treaty with them,
but by treaties with Great Britain and Spain, he could not account for
an increased expense.
The motion for $150,000 was put and negatived; $130,000 was then
proposed and carried, 34 to 33.
Mr. W. Smith proposed to fill the next blank, for the completion of the
fortifications, &c., at West Point, with $20,000.
Mr. Nicholas inquired if there was any law on this head?
Mr. W. Smith said, there was an act to authorize a provision for this
purpose, but that act had expired. He believed, however, it might
properly come in there. This expense, he was told, was necessary to
make the posts tenable, and that if no money was expended, the
fortifications would be lost. He believed this item might properly be
considered as a part of the Military Establishment.
Mr. Nicholas said, he did not object to the propriety of the expense,
but to the manner of introducing it. It would apply to New York as
well as West Point. He considered the admission of West Point as the
admission of a principle to which all the surplus appropriations might
be applied. All the fortifications, he said, were in the power of the
Executive; but, as they had had a committee appointed on the
business, whose report they had considered, he thought they should
act consistently. He therefore moved to strike out the clause.
Mr. Williams hoped this item would not be struck out, and that the
President would be enabled to extend aid to the fortifications at New
York; if not, the works would go to decay.
Mr. Van Cortlandt said, that fortifications ought to be attended to,
and that he should vote for them.
Mr. Giles hoped the motion would prevail. There had been a
committee most of the session, to consider the subject of
fortifications. If these fortifications stood in need of repair, the
President should have given the information to that committee. He
thought the item improper in the present bill.
Mr. Gallatin believed the gentlemen from Virginia were mistaken. The
committee which had been appointed was to consider the
fortifications of our harbors only. The works at West Point were of a
different description, and the estimate included not only the
completing of the fortifications, but the building and repairs of
barracks and stores which had been destroyed. The present item
could not extend to fortifications in general, as had been
apprehended; for, though the Secretary of the department does not
confine the money appropriated to one object, to that particular
purpose, yet, he cannot expend it on any object which was not
contained in the act of appropriation. He moved to add, "magazines,
store-houses, and barracks." Agreed to, and also the sum.
Mr. W. Smith then moved to fill the blank for the fortification of forts
and harbors with $50,000.
Mr. Gallatin said, this item he should move to strike out. A committee
had been appointed, and had reported on this subject, and that it
was not necessary to attend to it at present, as there was a surplus
of $23,000 unexpended. If they were to agree to the present sum, it
would be appropriating an additional sum of $50,000 for the same
object; he hoped, therefore, that it would be struck out.
Mr. W. Lyman was in favor of striking it out.
Mr. Williams hoped it would be agreed to, on the ground of the
necessity of some attention being paid to the works at New York.
Mr. Dayton was in favor of striking out this item altogether, as there
really was not money to spare for objects not essential. If any
particular harbor had been, or could be mentioned, the committee
might better be enabled to judge whether it would be fit, at this
time, pressed as they were for resources, to make an appropriation
for fortifying it, and how much. But, as he knew of none, and
believed there were no such, he should certainly be opposed to
appropriating a single shilling for this purpose. He meant not to say,
that there were not ports in the United States which might be
advantageously fortified, but only, that this country was not yet in a
situation to justify their encountering such an expense, especially as
it did not appear to be immediately necessary.
The motion for striking out was put, and carried.
Mr. W. Smith moved to fill the blank for the pay of officers, seamen,
and marines, with $113,025.
Mr. Nicholas hoped this item would be struck out. It was certainly an
expense for which there was no occasion. He did not wish to see
men raised when they could be of no service. The frigates, he said,
could not be fit for service before the next session. He hoped,
therefore, no opposition would be made to the striking out of the
clause.
Mr. W. Smith said, they had authorized by law the building of three
frigates, and it was wished that they should go into service the
present year. If the whole sum was not appropriated, there would
certainly be a necessity for a part of it.
Mr. Nicholas moved to strike out the item as it stood, and insert, "the
pay of the captains of three frigates."
Mr. Macon believed these were the only officers at present appointed.
Mr. Havens wished gentlemen to say why these captains should be
paid at all. He believed that building of ships was not their business,
and that these places were at present mere sinecures. He should
therefore vote against the amendment.
Mr. W. Smith said, it would be necessary to add subsistence as well
as pay of three captains, and moved to fill the blank with five
thousand dollars; which, after a few observations, was agreed to.
On motion of Mr. W. Smith, the blank for military pensions was filled,
without opposition, with $114,259.
The committee then rose and the House entered upon the
consideration of the amendments which had been made, when all
were agree to, except that relative to the subsistence of the non-
commissioned officers and privates.[81]
The motion only goes to prevent the raising any more troops, it does
not disband a man, 405;
militia always more spirited soldiers, and fitter for fighting the
Indians than regulars, 405;
experience with militia, 405;
no peace can be obtained from the Indians unless dictated by
British agents in Canada, 406;
any immediate alteration of the system dangerous under present
circumstances, 406;
the spirit of the motion in regard to the prevention of standing
armies is good, 407;
the reduction of the military establishment will neither put an end
to the savage war, nor to the enormous expense, 407;
consider the state of the exposed parts of the Union, 407;
these people demand the protecting arm of Government, 408;
commenced wrong in warring with the Indians, 408;
if public officers have misapplied the public money, the
constitution pointed out a mode to punish them, 408;
the defence of the frontier is of superior concern to the
redemption of the public debt by savings to be made by a reduction
of the army, 408;
a particular plan is set in operation, and it should be tried, 409;
confidential communications referred to, 409;
this protection of the frontiers is a test of the Government, 409;
this Indian war differs from any other, 410;
not sufficient information respecting the prospect of peace to
warrant a reduction of the army, 410;
any abuses in the war establishment are insignificant, 410;
regular troops grow experienced, and by a line of forts trade can
be cultivated with the Indians, 411;
the most important question before the House—on its decision are
suspended the hopes of the people for peace and their fears of a
standing army, 411;
the principle of keeping up standing armies, though highly
obnoxious to the people, has not been equally so to the
Government, 411;
effects of standing armies, 411;
much deliberation is not necessary to form an opinion of military
establishments, 411;
the arguments of the opponents lead to four points, 412;
these points considered, 412;
although a war establishment is objectionable, this system should
not be arrested at the moment of its efficiency, 414;
a standing army is impossible so long as this House holds the
purse-strings, 414;
motion lost, 415;
further considered, 416.
Ashe John Baptist, Representative from North Carolina, 239, 259, 317.
ebookbell.com