The Structure of Sociological Theory - Jonathan H - Turner - 2002 - Rawat Publications, Rawat - 9788170332664 - Anna's Archive
The Structure of Sociological Theory - Jonathan H - Turner - 2002 - Rawat Publications, Rawat - 9788170332664 - Anna's Archive
: ’ 5 ¢
, 4 , bi. Seg
os o 9 ’
L , ae ts
SE Se
ower
‘alae, cer Po a
"
The Structure of
Sociological
Theory
The Structure of
Sociological
Theory
Jonathan H. Turner
Uni versity of California, Riverside
Rawat Publications
Jaipur
30!
TUh
ISBN 81-7033-042-4 (hardcover)
ISBN 81-7033-266-4 (paperback)
Reprinted, 2004
Published by
Prem Rawat for Rawat Publications
Satyam Apts., Sector 3, Jawahar Nagar, Jaipur - 302 004 (India)
Phone: 0141 265 1748 / 7006 Fax: 0141 265 1748
E-mail : [email protected]
Website: rawatbooks.com
Delhi Office
4858/24, Ansari Road, Daryaganj, New Delhi 110 002
Phone: 011-23263290
Jonathan H. Turner
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I wish to thank the Academic Senate of the University of California,
Riverside, for providing support for this and all my previous research.
Also, I must thank my typist of 15 years, Clara Dean, who corrects my
spelling, catches all my referencing mistakes, and reads my horrible
handwriting.
J.H.T.
Contents
Part One
Functional Theorizing
Part Two
Conflict Theory
Part Three
Exchange Theory
Part Four
Interactionist Theory
14, Early Interactionism and Phenomenology 309
Early American Insights 309
William James (1842-1910) and the Concept of “Self”. 310
Self
and Social Process: Charles Horton Cooley. 311 Pragmatism
and
CONTENTS xiii
Part Five
Structural Theory
Name Index i
xvi
LIST OF TABLES xvii
List of Tables
2-1 Requisites of System Levels 51
6-1 Marx’s Key Propositions 136
6-2 Simmel’s Propositions on Conflict Intensity 141
6-3 Simmel’s Propositions on the Functions of Conflict for
the Respective Parties 142
6-4 Simmel’s Propositions on the Functions of Conflict for
the Systemic Whole 143
Weber’s Propositions on Inequality and Conflict 148
Dahrendorf’s Abstract Propositions 159
Coser’s Propositions on the Causes of Conflict 169
Coser’s Propositions on the Violence of Conflict 171
Coser’s Propositions on the Duration of Conflict 172
Coser’s Propositions on the Functions of Conflict for
the Respective Parties 174
Coser’s. Propositions on the Functions of Conflict for
the Social Whole 175
Georg Simmel’s Exchange Principles 232
Homans’s Exchange Principles 246
Blau’s Implicit Exchange Principles 264
Blau’s Conditions for the Differentiation of Power in
Social Exchange 268
Blau’s Principles of Exchange Conflict 273
The Operant Propositions and Initial Corollaries 295
{The Initial Theorems 296
Convergence and Divergence in the Chicago and Iowa
Schools of Symbolic Interactionism 300
Others and Role Merger in One Situation 381
Others, Person, and Role in Multiple Settings 382
Individual Efforts at Role Merger 383
A Revised List of Blau’s “Axioms” 431
A Revised List of Blau’s Basic Theorems 431
Key Propositions on the Conditions Producing Talk
and Conversation 443
Key Propositions on the Conditions Producing Ritual
Activity 445
Key Propositions on Deference and Demeanor 447
Key Propositions on Class Cultures 448
Key Propositions on Sex Stratification 449
Key Propositions on Age Stratification 450
Key Propositions on Organizations 452
Key Propositions on the State, Economy, and Ideology 453
The Typology of Institutions 465
; as ;
E \.SaugaT 70 Teyae
iat
20 Tea
soto + :
tf ar. ch <tonshes ox!
MMM Bi h) nO anode ”
Tite MIBIF ad! ao nto
#10; ! iter) Yo “ar
J . CHAPTERD
‘Auguste Comte, System of Positive Philosophy, vol. 1 (Paris: Bachelier, 1830). Subse-
quent portions were published between 1831-42. For a more detailed analysis of Comte’s
thought, see my and Leonard Beeghley’s, The Emergence of Sociological Theory (Homewood,
Ill.: Dorsey Press, 1981), Chapter 2.
2 CHAPTER 1 / THE NATURE OF SOCIOLOGICAL THEORIZING
Yes No
Ideologies; or Religions; or
beliefs that state beliefs that state
Yes
the way the world the dictates of
should be supernatural forces
Is knowledge to :
be evaluative? Science; or the Logics; or the
belief that all rious systems of
knowledge is to je onin ,oak
No
reflect the actual ona te of
operation of the calculation
empirical world
knowledge about human affairs.? The typology asks two basic questions:
(1) is the search for knowledge to be evaluative or neutral? and (2) is the
knowledge developed to pertain to actual empirical events and processes
or is it to be about nonempirical realities? In other words, should knowl-
edge tell us what should be or what is? and should it make reference to
the observable world or to other, less observable realms? If knowledge is
to tell us what should exist (and by implication, what should not occur)
in the empirical world, then it is ideological knowledge. If it informs us
about what should be but does not pertain to observable events, then the
knowledge is religious or about forces and beings in another realm of
existence. If knowledge is neither empirical nor evaluative, then it is a
formal system of logic, such as mathematics. And if it is about empirical
events and nonevaluative, then it is science.
I concede that this typology is crude, but it makes the essential point:
There are different ways to look at, interpret, and develop knowledge
about the world. Science is only one way. It is based upon the presumption
that knowledge can be value free, that it can explain the actual workings
of the empirical world, and that it can be revised on the basis of careful
observations of empirical events. These characteristics distinguish science
from other beliefs about how we should generate understanding and in-
sight.4 However, even this portrayal of science is questioned by many who
would regard it as rather idealized. For these critics, values always figure
into what we study. The empirical world is not “just there”; rather it is
filtered through concepts and presuppositions. And rarely are facts dis-
passionately collected to test theories.
And so, I must caution again. Many people, including a large number
of philosophers of science and professional sociologists, would question
my portrayal of scientific activity. For example, some would argue that
science is highly ideological because in depicting what is, it implicitly says
3] am borrowing the general idea from Talcott Parsons’, The Social System (New York:
Free Press, 1951). For another version of this typology, see my The Science of Human
Organization (Chicago: Nelson-Hall Publishers, 1985), Chapter 2.
“Among several fine introductory works on the nature of scientific theory, the discussion
in this chapter draws heavily upon Paul Davidson Reynolds’ excellent A Primer in Theory
Construction (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1971). For excellent introductory works, see Ar-
thur L. Stinchcombe, Constructing Social Theories (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World,
1968), pp. 3-56; Karl R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (New York: Harper &
Row, 1959); David Willer and Murray Webster, Jr., “Theoretical Concepts and Observables,”
American Sociological Review 35 (August 1970), pp. 748-57; Hans Zetterberg, On Theory
and Verification in Sociology, 3d ed. (Totowa, N.J.. Bedminister Press, 1965); Jerald Hage,
Techniques and Problems of Theory Construction in Sociology (New York: John Wiley &
Sons, 1972); Walter L. Wallace, The Logic of Science in Sociology (Chicago: Aldine Pub-
lishing, 1971); Robert Dubin, Theory Building (New York: Free Press, 1969); Jack Gibbs,
Sociological Theory Construction (Hinsdale, Ill.: Dryden Press, 1972); Herbert M. Blalock,
Jr., Theory Construction: From Verbal to Mathematical Formulations (Englewood Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1969); Nicholas C. Mullins, The Art of Theory: Construction and Use
(New York: Harper & Row, 1971).
IZING
4 CHAPTER 1 / THE NATURE OF SOCIOLOGICAL THEOR
that present conditions in society must always be the way things are. In
so doing, science is an ideology supporting the status quo.° It makes the
present seem invariant and lawlike, thereby arresting our imagination
about other possibilities for the organization of humans in society. But
these kinds of criticisms anticipate what will come in later chapters. For
the present, I simply want to emphasize that if we follow Comte’s “law
of the three stages” or the simple typology in Figure 1-1, others will
disagree with the conclusion that sociology can be a science that is easily
distinguished from other forms of knowledge.®
The fact that there is disagreement over sociology’s status as a science
makes a review of sociological theory highly problematic, for the vehicle
for developing scientific knowledge is theory. Scientific theory provides
an interpretation of events, but this interpretation must be constantly
checked and rechecked against the empirical facts. Yet, if the whole en-
terprise of science is questioned, then sociological theories that tell us
how and why events occur will be very diverse. Depending upon what
kind of science, if any, that sociology is considered to be, our theories
will vary. Some theories will look like those that Auguste Comte envi-
sioned—that is, very much like those in the natural sciences. Other the-
oretical approaches will be very different because they are formulated by
those who have serious reservations about a social science that fits neatly
into the lower left box in Figure 1-1.
These considerations present me with very real problems in defining
theory in sociology, but undaunted, let me try to present a minimal por-
trayal of what I think all sociological theories have in common. Then, we
can return to the controversial issues that divide theorists and that make
for different kinds of theoretical activity in sociology.
7For more detailed work on concept formation, see Carl G. Hempel, Fundamentals of
Concept Formation in Empirical Science (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952).
*For a useful and insightful critique of sociology’s inability to generate abstract concepts
and theory, see David and Judith Willer, Systematic Empiricism: Critique of a Pseudoscience
(Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1973).
IZING
6 CHAPTER 1 / THE NATURE OF SOCIOLOGICAL THEOR
specific times and locations. Other more abstract concepts point to phe-
nomena that are not related to concrete times or locations. For example,
in the context of small-group research, concrete concepts would refer to
the persistent interactions of particular individuals, whereas an abstract
conceptualization of such phenomena would refer to those general prop-
erties of face-to-face groups, which are not tied to particular individuals
interacting at a specified time and location. Whereas abstract concepts
are not tied to a specific context, concrete concepts are. In building theory,
abstract concepts are crucial, although we will see shortly that theorists
disagree considerably on this issue.
Abstractness poses a problem: how do we attach abstract concepts to
the ongoing, everyday world of events? While it is essential that some of
the concepts of theory transcend specific times and places, it is equally
- critical that there be procedures for making these abstract concepts rel-
evant to observable situations and occurrences. After all, the utility of an
abstract concept can only be demonstrated when the concept is brought
to bear on some specific empirical problem encountered by investigators;
otherwise, concepts remain detached from the very processes they are
supposed to help investigators understand. Just how to actach concepts
to empirical processes, or the workings of the real world, is an area of
great controversy in sociology. Some argue for very formal procedures for
attaching concepts to empirical events. Those of this persuasion argue
that abstract concepts should be accompanied by a series of statements
known as operational definitions, which are sets of procedural instructions
telling investigators how to go about discerning phenomena in the real
world that are denoted by an abstract concept. Others argue that the
nature of our concepts in sociology precludes such formalistic exercises.
At best, concepts can be only sensitizing devices that must change with
alterations of social reality; and so, we can only intuitively and provi-
sionally apply abstract concepts to the actual flow of events. To emulate
the natural sciences in an effort to develop formal operations for attaching
concepts to reality is to ignore the fact that social reality is changeable;
it does not reveal invariant properties like the other domains of the uni-
verse.® And thus, to think that abstract concepts denote enduring and
invariant properties of the social universe and to presume, therefore, that
the concept itself will never need to be changed is, at best, naive.'°
And so the debate rages, taking many different turns. I need not go
into detail here, since these issues will be brought out again and again as
I move into the substance of sociological theory in subsequent chapters.
For the present, I only want to draw the approximate lines of battle.
/Analytical schemes
Modeling schemes
12For a forceful and scholarly advocacy of this point, see Jeffrey C. Alexander, Theoretical
Logic in Sociology, 4 vols. (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, 1982-1984).
Webster's New Collegiate Dictionary (Springfield, Mass.: G & C Merriman, 1976).
10 CHAPTER 1 / THE NATURE OF SOCIOLOGICAL THEORIZING
‘ Riconageervl work is more in this tradition. See also Richard Minch, Theory of Action:
econstructing the Contributions of Talcott Parsons, Emile Durkheim, and MaxWeber
Eeehten Poe 1982). I have translated
the German title and emphasized this work
cause it will soon be out in an English
translation.
1
re 3ae Parsons’ ; work is; of this? nature, as we will see in the next chapter.
See also
THE ELEMENTS OF THEORY 11
the universe; then, the ordering of the concepts into a typology gives the
social world a sense of order. Explanation of an empirical event comes
whenever a place in the classificatory scheme can be found for the em-
pirical event. For example, if one is using an “action theoretical frame-
work” with four types of action, explanation occurs when behavior can
be classified as one of these four types. I have oversimplified here, but
the general point is, I think, correct: analytical schemes explain empirical
events by finding their niche in a typology.
There are, however, wide variations in the nature of the typologies
in analytical schemes. I think that there are two basic types: naturalistic/
positivistic schemes, which try to develop a tightly woven system of cat-
egories that is presumed to capture the way in which the invariant prop-
erties of the universe are ordered!*; and descriptive/sensitizing schemes,
which are more loosely assembled congeries of concepts intended only
to sensitize and orient researchers to certain critical processes.!’
Figure 1-3 summarizes these two types of analytical approaches. Natur-
alistic/positivistic schemes assume that there are timeless and universal
processes in the social universe, much as there are in the physical and
biological realms. The goal is to create an abstract conceptual typology
that is isomorphic with these timeless processes. In contrast, déscriptive/
sensitizing schemes are typically more skeptical about the timeless quality
of social affairs. Instead, they argue that concepts and their linkages must
always be provisional and sensitizing because the nature of human activity
is to change those very arrangements denoted by the organization of
concepts into theoretical statements. Hence, except for certain very gen-
eral conceptual categories, the scheme must be flexible and capable of
being revised as circumstances in the empirical world change. At best,
then, explanation is simply rendering an interpretation of events by seeing
them as an instance or example of the provisional and sensitizing concepts
in the scheme.
Often it is argued that analytical schemes are a necessary prerequisite
for developing other forms of theory. Until one has a scheme that orga-
nizes the properties of the universe, it is difficult to develop propositions
and models about specific events. For without the general analytical
framework, it is asked by proponents of this view, how can a theorist or
researcher know what to examine?
Sensitizing/Descriptive
Abstract
Abstract «————~> category 2
-~ category 1
7 alt pete ¥ Explanation =
Z interpreting events
Abstract” a=“ A by invoking various
category n =. Te Abstract combinations of
is _y category 3 categories
x Oe it -
Abstract
category 4
function of external conflict with other groups,” says that as group conflict
increases so does the internal sense of solidarity among members of the
respective groups involved in the conflict. Thus, two properties of the
social universe denoted by variable concepts, “group solidarity” and “con-
flict,” are connected by the proposition that as one increases in value, so
does the other.
Propositional schemes vary perhaps the most of all theoretical ap-
proaches. They vary primarily along two dimensions: (1) the level of
abstraction and (2) the way propositions are organized into formats. Some
are highly abstract and contain concepts that do not denote any particular
case but all cases of a type (for example, group solidarity and conflict are
abstract because no particular empirical instance of conflict and solidarity
is addressed). In contrast, other propositional systems are tied to empirical
facts and simply summarize relations among events in a particular case
(for example, as World War II progressed, nationalism in America in-
THE ELEMENTS OF THEORY 13
poe more details of this argument, see Lee Freese, ‘Formal Theoriz
ing,” Annual Review
$ af em 6 (1980), pp. 187-212 and Herbert L. Costner and Robert K. Leik, “Deductions
des Ayr Theory,” American Sociological Review 29 (December 1964), pp. 19-35.
Theoryee,of tor example
Social , Peter
Structu Blau’s
re (New excellen
Yok: Ban t cle
Inequal ity
nen and Heterogeneity:
ity: A Primiti
imiti ve
See Freese.
THE ELEMENTS OF THEORY 15
our rule or law, such as America’s involvement in the Vietnam War, that
contradicts the principle, forcing its revision or the recognition that “all
things were not equal.” In this case, we might revise the principle by
stating a condition under which it holds true: when parties to a conflict.
perceive the conflict as a threat to their welfare, then the level of solidarity
of groups is a positive function of their degree of conflict. Thus, the
Vietnam War did not produce internal solidarity in America because it
was not defined as a threat to the general welfare (whereas for the North
Vietnamese, it was a threat and produced solidarity).
The essential idea here is that in formal theory, an effort is made to
create abstract principles. These principles are often clustered together
to form a group of laws from which we make rather loose deductions to
explain empirical events. Much like axiomatic systems, formal systems
are hierarchical, but the restrictions of axiomatic theory are relaxed con-
siderably. Most propositional schemes in sociological. theorizing are,
therefore, of this formal type.
(c) Yet, much of what is defined as theory in sociology is more em-
pirical. These empirical formats consist of generalizations from specific
events in particular empirical contexts. For example Golden’s Law states
that ‘‘as industrialization increases, the level of literacy in the population
increases.” Such a proposition is not very abstract; it is filled with em-
pirical content—industrialization and literacy. Moreover, it is not about
a timeless process, since industrialization is only a few hundred years old
and literacy emerged, at best, only 15,000 years ago. There are many such
generalizations in sociology that are considered theoretical. They repre-
sent statements of empirical regularities that scholars think are important
to understand. Indeed, most substantive areas and subfields of sociology
are filled with these kinds of propositions.
Strictly speaking, however, these are not theoretical. They are too
tied to empirical contexts. In fact, they are generalizations that are in
need of a theory to explain them. Yet, I caution that my opinion about
such empirical generalizations is not shared by all.. And if we ask scholars _
working in substantive areas if their generalizations are theory, a good
many would answer affirmatively.
There are other kinds of empirical generalizations, however, that raise
fewer suspicions about their theoretical merits. These are often termed
middle-range theories, as we will see in Chapter 4, because they are more
abstract than a research finding and because their empirical content per-
tains to variables that are also found in other domains of social reality.’
For example, a series of middle-range propositions from the complex or-
ganization’s literature might be stated: ‘Increasing size of a bureaucratic
"See Chapter 4 on Robert K. Merton’s work. In particular, consult his Social Theory
and Social Structure (New York: Free Press, 1975).
16 CHAPTER 1 / THE NATURE OF SOCIOLOGICAL THEORIZING
a e
wel ve tem this example from Peter M. Blau’s “Applications of aMacrosocio
net n Mathmatizche Analyse von Organisationsstrukktaren logical
nationale Wissenschaftliche Facnkonferenz, vol. und Prozessen (Inter-
5, March 1981).
THE ELEMENTS OF THEORY 17
Axioms
”
:
o =
2 Theorems pits
c
~ ;
cUgy
o**y=
oO aS [© ie| -
g g 50 Explanation =
wake x= os j
Fe Propositions to G9 . neces begeah of .
| connect with data 2 Be ie = ed re
c ofE6 - :
= { ox abstract axioms
30) Ooo 8
. @no
2 Hypothesis ZEo
iT? oO 2 =
=
" aa
Empirical regularity
Formal:
Abstract formal
principles
2 { ee
7) ~
€ a S223
5 connect with data cSoa 9 subsumption of
2 t %25¢£ empirical regularity
%, ZEs6 under abstract
£ ' 35 Sa principle or
es Hypothesis 9% => principles
© 6% 2q
Oo } On ED
c o © ® 5
Empirical regularity
*Actually, these are typically “regression equations” and would not constitute modeling
as I think it should be defined. A series of differential equations, especially as they are
simulated or otherwise graphically represented, would constitute a model.
IZING
18 CHAPTER 1 / THE NATURE OF SOCIOLOGICAL THEOR
e
a
Middle-range:
General statement of
scope conditions for
propositions
iti 4 825eC
can
' = = ;
Se 2 ! 1 £259 Explanation =
oa® ®6%6 _ ability to see
r Some effort to make oa sO specific empirical
oS oe
to abstract statemen ts ©Foes
Dd w P ? as one
regularity
28 5 + | S458 of a general class
as5 EMQs * — of regularities for
o5° Formal statement of ° go this type of
oc= empirical regularities =EUn phenomena
Eos 2% G2
a SBBE
Jo
Specific empirical
findings
Empirical generalization:
That is, they are designed to show how changes in the values of one set
of variables are related to changes in the values of other variables. Models
are typically constructed when there are numerous variables whose causal
interrelations an investigator wants to highlight.
With the issue far from clear, my sense is that sociologists generally
construct two different types of models, which I will term analytical models
and causal models. This distinction is, I admit, somewhat arbitrary, but
I think that it is a necessary one if we are to appreciate the kinds of
models that are constructed in sociology. The basis for making this dis-
tinction is twofold: First, some models are more abstract than others in
that the concepts in them are not tied to any particular case, whereas
other models reveal concepts that simply summarize statistically relations
among variables in a particular data set. Secondly, more abstract models
almost always reveal more complexity in their representation of causal
connections among variables. That is, one will find feedback loops, cycles,
mutual effects, and other connective representations that complicate the
causal connections among the variables in the model and make them
difficult to summarize with simple statistics. In contrast, the less abstract
models typically depict a clear causal sequence among empirical varia-
bles. They typically reveal independent variables that effect variation
in some dependent variable; and if the model is more complex, it might
also highlight intervening variables and perhaps even some interaction
effects among the variables.
Thus, analytical models are more abstract; they highlight more generic
properties of the universe; and they portray a complex set of connections
among variables. In contrast, causal models are more empirically grounded;
they are more likely to devote particular properties of a specific empirical
case; and they are likely to present a simple lineal view of causality. These
modeling strategies are summarized in Figure 1-5.
Causal models are typically drawn in order to provide a more detailed
interpretation of an empirical generalization. They are designed to sort
out the respective influences of variables, usually in some temporal se-
quence, as they operate on some dependent variable of interest. At times,
a causal model becomes a way of representing the elements of a middle-
range theory so as to connect these elements to the particulars of a specific
empirical context. For example, if we wanted to know why the size of a
bureaucratic organization is related to its complexity of structure in a
particular empirical case of a growing organization, we might translate
the more abstract variables of size and complexity into specific empirical
indicators and perhaps try to introduce other variables that also influence
the relationship between size and complexity in this empirical case. The
*The “path analysis” that was so popular in American sociology in the 1970s is a good
example of such modeling techniques.
ICAL THEORIZING
20 CHAPTER 1 / THE NATURE OF SOCIOLOG
Analytical models:
v pares
pares2
| Explanation =
Abstract te danni ability to map crucial
property 1 ° danni
3 connections (perhaps
weighted) among basic
properties of a
+
specific class of
er 6) process or phenomenon
er 56)
Causal models:
Empirical
variable 1
Explanation =
tracing of causal connection:
among measured variables
accounting for variation in
the occurrence of interest
Empirical
variable 2
causal model thus becomes a way to represent with more clarity the em
pirical association between size and complexity in a specific context.”
Analytical models are usually drawn to specify the relations amon,
more abstract and generic processes. Often they are used to delineate th
processes that operate to connect the concepts of an axiomatic, or mor
likely, a formal theory.2” For example, we might construct a model tha
tells us more about the processes that operate to generate the relationshij
between conflict and solidarity ot between size and differentiation it
*For an example of a model for these variables, see Peter M. Blau’s “A Formal Theor
of Differentiation in Organizations,” A American Sociological Review
: 35 (April 1970), pp. 201.
218. See also Chapter 12. s,”
Ori e +
High Meta-
Axiomatic/ Analytical
formal schemes theory
schemes schemes
e
Analytical
models
Level of
abstraction
e
Middle-range
propositions
s e
Empirical Causal
generalization model
Low
Low High
empirical case, the higher is its level of abstraction; and the greater the
range of substantive phenomena encompassed by the concepts and state-
ments of an approach, the greater is its scope. Naturally, these are not
mutually exclusive, since the process of abstraction by its very nature
leads to the inclusion of more cases and, hence, increases the scope of
phenomena denoted by concepts. I can certainly be criticized for plotting
along nonexclusive dimensions, but my point in Figure 1-6 is not to create
an elegant typology. Rather, I simply want to communicate that abstract
schemes encompass more substantive phenomena in the social universe.
But I also want to emphasize that abstraction, per se, does not always
lead to the breadth of coverage. A theoretical format can be highly abstract
in that it contains no direct empirical referents, but it can denote only a
delimited range of phenomena. Thus, I think that axiomatic and formal
propositions tend to be highly abstract, but they typically pertain to a
limited range of phenomena. In contrast, analytical schemes and meta-
theory are no more abstract than formal or axiomatic theories, but they
usually contain more concepts and statements denoting a broader range
of social phenomena. And so, while I admit to an overlap in the dimensions
of Figure 1-6, the figure communicates my essential point: theoretical
AN ASSESSMENT OF THEORETICAL APPROACHES 23
*Karl R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations (New York: Basic Books, 1962), p. 243.
26 CHAPTER 1 / THE NATURE OF SOCIOLOGICAL THEORIZING
for Building
FIGURE 1-7 Relations among Theoretical Approaches and Potential
Theory
TT ee ee
The Ideal Relationship Potential for Building
Scientific Theory
Meta-theory
Axiomatic,
when possible «—-* Formal propositions
} Most likely to generate
testable theory
UL ——_—_— ——~-— + Analytical models |
more abstract
Causal models
Data in need of theoretical
in interpretation
Empirical generalizations
of their
propositions, then I will explore these considerations in light
implications for the theoretical scheme.
Thus, in the pages to follow, the core structure of sociological theory
revolves around analytical schemes and formal propositional systems. At
times, analytical models and meta-theoretical issues are part of these
analytical and propositional schemes, but the essence of sociological the-
ory today is a series of naturalistic analytical schemes, sensitizing ana-
lytical schemes, and variously structured systems of abstract formal
propositions.
*See notes 9 and 10 for examples of the two sides on this issue.
“This has reemerged as a major issue in sociological theory. For some recent commen-
pdt na perso and A. V. Cicourel, eds., Advances in Social Theory and
& Kegan ik 9a), an Integration of Micro- and Macro-sociologies (Boston: Routledge
g aul, 1); Jonathan H. Turner, “Theoretical Strategies for Linking Micro and
Macro Processes: Y a
Socic!ogical Review 14,
no. 1 (1983), pp.Foo" erage of Seven Approaches,” Western
THE STATE OF SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY 31
“For examples, see Giddens, The Constitution of Society, and Randall Collins, Conflict
Sociology (New York: Academic Press, 1975). As we wili see shortly, many specific per-
spectives besides these two examples try to provide a reconciliation of micro- and
macroprocesses.
*T he best of these arguments is George Ritzer’s Sociology: A Multiple Paradigm Science
(Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1975).
*Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1962, 1970).
32 CHAPTER 1 / THE NATURE OF SOCIOLOGICAL THEORIZING
ita
hege ss tests
ve Hh emer_e ic
ha sfeage, | wr
¢ tet geetacr
PART ONE
Functional Theorizing
35
The Emergence
of Functionalism_
1As I will outline later, exchange theory typically begins with these assumptions. But it
also penetrates other perspectives, as we will come to see.
2Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (London:
Davis, 1805; originally published in 1776). Only volume 1 contains these extreme statements.
Subsequent portions of the book are quite sociological in nature.
37
38 CHAPTER 2 / THE EMERGENCE OF FUNCTIONALISM
3 : rom et
“ sai — Smith, had originally posed the question that all French thinkers were
to ask: as societies become more complex and differentiated, and as actors live in different
worlds, what “force” can hold the social fabric together?
FUNCTIONALISM AND THE ORGANISMIC ANALOGY 39
‘Auguste Comte, The Course of Positive Philosophy (1830-1842). References are to the
more commonly used edition that Harriet Martineau condensed and translated, The Positive
Philosophy of Auguste Comte, vols. 1, 2, and 3 (London: Bell & Sons, 1898, originally
published in 1854).
40 CHAPTER 2 / THE EMERGENCE OF FUNCTIONALISM
biology,
Comte visualized that with initial borrowing of concepts from
es, the
and later with the development of positivism in the social scienc
first
principles of sociology would inform biology. Thus, sociology must
recognize the correspondence between the individual organism in biology
and the social organism in sociology:
We have thus established a true correspondence between the Statistical
Analysis of the Social Organism in Sociology, and that of the Individual
Organism in Biology ... If we take the best ascertained points in Biology,
we may decompose structure anatomically into elements, tissues, and organs.
We have the same things in the Social Organism; and may even use the same
names.®
; *Auguste Comte, System of Positive Polity or Treatise on Sociology (London: Burt Frank-
lin, 1875, originally published 1851), pp. 239-40.
*Ibid., pp. 241-42.
"By the time he wrote Positive Polity in 1851, Comte was, in a very real sense, a broken
intellectual. Far more important, I feel, is the first work on Positive Philosophy.
‘
a3 was forced to abandon his preferred name because the Belgian statistician Adol
, phe
Quete et,had already usurped the label for his statistical analyses.
*Positive Philosophy, vol. 1. p. 2.
FUNCTIONALISM AND THE ORGANISMIC ANALOGY 41
What was such theory to look like? His answer is, I think, very im-
portant because he warned against the very functional analysis that he
helped initiate in his later works, while he cautioned against excessive
concern with the causal modeling so prominent in contemporary sociol-
ogy. As he stressed:
The first characteristic of Positive Philosophy is that it regards all phe-
nomena as subject to invariable natural Jaws. Our business is,—seeing how
or vain any research into what are called causes, whether first or final,—to pursue
an accurate discovery of these laws, with a view to reducing them to the
smallest possible number.”
Tbid., p. 5.
“Jbid., p. 6.
2Emile Durkheim, The Rules of the Sociological Method (New York: Free Press, 1938;
originally published in 1895).
“Organicism was not original with Comte, of course. Plato and other more distant
thinkers had also made organismic analogies; Comte simply reintroduced this idea.
42 CHAPTER 2 / THE EMERGENCE OF FUNCTIONALISM
r’s
an unacknowledged debt to Spencer.'* Moreover, analyses of Spence
work tend to focus on the weakest portion of his sociology, its function-
alism. But unlike Durkheim two decades later, the anthropological func-
tionalists of the early decades of this century, or the modern functionalists
of the contemporary era, Spencer’s functional analysis was comparatively
recessive. Yet, in what may seem like a contradiction, Spencer anticipated
in those few pages devoted to functional analysis all of the main features
of modern functionalism.
Like many contemporary functionalists, Spencer saw the universe as
divided into realms or domains. For Spencer, these basic realms are the
inorganic (physical, chemical), the organic (biological, psychological), and
superorganic (sociological).!* His great philosophical project was to gen-
erate a series of abstract principles or laws—what he termed the first or
cardinal principles—that could explain all of these realms.'* Needless to
say, he was a bit over-ambitious on this score, but the general idea was
to explain social processes with abstract laws or principles. The content
of these principles borrows from the physics of his time, not the biology.
Yet, it is his biological analogizing for which we most remember Spencer;
and when making these analogies, he introduced analytical functionalism.
But I emphasize again that Spencer saw both the organic and superorganic
realms as obeying the same abstract laws, or first principles. Indeed, his
organicism is secondary to his effort at making deductions from his ab-
stract first principles.’
Spencer published his monumental Principles of Biology before his
first sociological works.'® As a consequence, I think, he wanted to dem-
onstrate that both organic and superorganic bodies reveal “parallels in
principles of organization” that could be deduced from the first principles.
And so, it is not surprising that he compared societies and organisms in
terms of their similarity and dissimilarity. Among the points of similarity
he emphasized:
“See my Herbert Spencer: Toward a Renewed Appreciation (Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage
Publications, 1985) for a more detailed presentation of this line of argument.
*Herbert Spencer, The Principles of Sociology (1874-1896). This work has been reissued
in varying volume numbers. References in this chapter are to the three-volume edition (the
third edition) issued by D. Appleton and Company, New York, in 1898. In reading this long
work, it is much more critical to note the parts (numbered I through VII) than the volumes,
since pagination can vary with editions.
“These are contained in his First Principles (New York: A. C. B 5 ot
published in 1862). _ . C. Burt, 1880, originally
"For a more detailed analyses of these, see my and Leonard Beeghley’s Emergenc
e of
Sociological Theory (Homewood, IIL: Dorsey Press, 1981), pp. 67-76; 106-7.
‘Herbert Spencer, The Principles of Biology (New York: D. Appleto
n, 1864-1867).
See my Herbert Spencer: Toward a Renewed Appreciation, Chapter
4. See also his
Principles of Sociology, vol. I, part II, pp. 449-57. The bulk of Spencer’s organicism is on
these few pages of » work
) that . sSpans more than 2,000 pages, and vet, is this i
remember about Spencer. an ee
FUNCTIONALISM AND THE ORGANISMIC ANALOGY 43
has a set of agencies which bring the raw material . . .; it has an apparatus
of major and minor channels through which the necessities of life are drafted
out of the general stocks circulating through the kingdom . .; it has appliances
... for bringing those impulses by which the industry of the place is excited
or checked; it has local controlling powers, political and ecclesiastical, by
which order is maintained and healthful action furthered.
2B mile Durkheim, The Division of Labor in Society (New York: Macmillan, 1933, orig-
inally published in 1893). Durkheim tended to ignore the fact that Spencer wore several
intellectual hats. He reacted to Spencer’s advocacy of utilitarianism, seemingly ignoring the
similarity between Spencer’s organismic analogy and his own organic formulations as well
as the close correspondence between their theories of symbols.
“Emile Durkheim, The Rules of the Sociological Method, p. 96.
46 CHAPTER 2 / THE EMERGENCE OF FUNCTIONALISM
Thus, despite giving analytical priority to the whole and viewing parts
as having consequences for certain normal states and hence meeting sys-
tem requisites, Durkheim remained aware of the dangers of asserting that
all systems have “purpose” and that the need to maintain the whole causes
the existence of its constituent parts. Yet, Durkheim’s insistence that the
function of a part for the social whole always be examined sometimes led
him, and certainly many of his followers, into questionable teleological
reasoning. For example, even when distinguishing cause and function in
his major methodological statement, he leaves room for an illegitimate
teleological interpretation: “Consequently, to explain a social fact it is
not enough to show the cause on which it depends; we must also, at least
in most cases, show its function in the establishment of social order.”
In this summary phrase, I think that the words “in the establishment
of” could connote that the existence of system parts can be explained
only by the whole, or social order, that they function to maintain. From
this view, it is only a short step to outright teleology: the social fact in
question is caused by the needs of the social order that the fact fulfills.
Such theoretical statements do not necessarily have to be illegitimate, for
it is conceivable that a social system could be programmed to meet certain
needs or designated ends and thereby have the capacity to cause variations
in cultural items or “social facts” in order to meet these needs or ends.
But if such a system is being described by an analyst, it is necessary to
document how the system is programmed and how it operates to cause
variations in social facts to meet needs or ends. As the above quotation
illustrates, Durkheim did not have this kind of system in mind when he
formulated his particular brand of functional analysis; thus, he did not
wish to state his arguments teleologically.
Despite his warnings to the contrary, Durkheim appears to have taken
this short step into teleological reasoning in his substantive works. In his
first major work on the division of labor, Durkheim went to great lengths
to distinguish between cause (increased population and moral density)
and function (integration of society).
However, the causal statements often become fused with functional
statements. The argument is, generally, like this: population density in-
creases moral density (rates of contact and interaction); moral density
leads to competition, which threatens the social order; in turn, compe-
tition for resources results in the specialization of tasks; and specialization
creates pressures for mutual interdependence and increased willingness
to accept the morality of mutual obligation. This transition to a new
social order is not made consciously, or by “unconscious wisdom”; yet,
the division of labor is necessary to restore the order that “unbridled
*Tbid., p. 97.
FUNCTIONALISM AND THE ANTHROPOLOGICAL TRADITION 47
*Ibid., p. 35. For a more detailed analysis, see my and Alexandra Maryanski’s Func-
tionalism (Menlo Park, Calif.: Benjamin-Cummings, 1978). See also Percy S. Cohen, Modern
Social Theory (New York: Basic Books, 1968), pp. 35-37.
27Robert A. Nisbet, Emile Durkheim (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1965), pp.
9-102.
For basic references on Malinowski’s functionalism, see his “Anthropology,” Encyclo-
pedia Britannica, supplementary vol. 1 (London and New York, 1936); A Scientific Theory
of Culture (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1944); and Magic, Science, and
Religion and Other Essays (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1948). For basic references on A, R.
Radcliffe-Brown’s functionalism, see his ‘““Structure-and Function in Primitive Society,”
American Anthropologist 37 (July-September 1935), pp. 58-72; Structure and Function in
Primitive Society (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1952); and The Andaman Islanders (Glencoe,
Ill.: Free Press, 1948). See also Turner and Maryanski, Functionalism.
48 CHAPTER 2 / THE EMERGENCE OF FUNCTIONALISM
*Radcliffe-Brown, Structure and Function in Primitive Society, pp. 31-50. For a sec-
ondary analysis of this example, see Arthur L. Stinchcumbe, ‘“Specious Generality and
Functional Theory,” American Sociological Review 26 (December 1961), pp. 929-30.
50 CHAPTER 2 / THE EMERGENCE OF FUNCTIONALISM
Radcliffe-
reasoning.*! However, I think that much like Durkheim, what
the concrete
Brown asserted analytically was frequently not practiced in
red
empirical analysis of societies. Such lapses were not intended but appea
and
to be difficult to avoid when functional needs, functional integration,
equilibrium are operating assumptions.”
Thus, while Radcliffe-Brown displayed an admirable awareness of the
dangers of organicism—especially of the problem of illegitimate teleology
and the hypothetical nature of notions of solidarity—he all too often slipped
into a pattern of questionable teleological reasoning. Forgetting that in-
tegration was only a working hypothesis, he opened his analysis to prob-
lems of tautology. Such problems were persistent in Durkheim’s analysis;
and despite his attempts to the contrary, their spectre haunted even Rad-
cliffe-Brown’s insightful essays and ethnographies.
Malinowski
By describing each institution along these six dimensions,
tick for com-
believed that he had provided a common analytical yards
societies. He
paring patterns of social organization within and between
ns as they
even went so far as to construct a list of universal institutio
resolve not just structural but also biological and symbolic requisites.
In sum, I think that Malinowski’s functional approach opened new
possibilities for sociologists who had long forgotten Spencer’s similar ar-
guments. He suggested to sociologists that attention to system levels is
critical in analyzing requisites; he argued that there are universal requi-
sites for each system level; he forcefully emphasized that the structural
level is the essence of sociological analysis; and much like Spencer before
him and Talcott Parsons a decade later (see next chapter), he posited —
four universal functional needs at this level—economic adaptation, polit-
ical authority, educational socialization, and social control—which were
to be prominent in subsequent functional schemes. Moreover, he provided
a clear method for analyzing institutions as they operate to meet func-
tional requisites. It is fair to say, therefore, that Malinowski drew the
rough contours for modern sociological functionalism.
8% or basic references on Weber, see his The Theory of Social and Economic Organization
(New York: Free Press, 1947); “Social Action and its Types” in Theories of Society, ed.
Talcott Parsons et al. (New York: Free Press, 1961); Hans Gerth and C. Wright Mills, eds..
From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (New York: Oxford University Press, 1958).
54 CHAPTER 2 / THE EMERGENCE OF FUNCTIONALISM
a category system for individual social action and then elaborated this
initial system of categories into an incredibly complex, analytical edifice
of concepts. What is important to recognize is that this strategy of de-
veloping category systems first and then propositions about the relation-
ships. among categorized phenomena lies at the heart of contemporary
functionalism. This emphasis on category systems is, no doubt, one of
the subtle ways that Weber’s ideal-type strategy continues to influence
functional theorizing in sociology.
*For a more thorough analysis of the historical legacy of functionalism, see Don Mar-
tindale’s The Nature and Types of Sociological Theory and his “Limits of and Alternatives
to Functionalism in Sociology,” in Functionalism in the Social Sciences, American Academy
of Political and Social Science Monograph, no. 5 (Philadelphia, 1965), pp. 144-62; see also
in this monograph, Ivan Whitaker, “The Nature and Value of Functionalism in Sociology,”
pp. 127-43.
56 CHAPTER 2 / THE EMERGENCE OF FUNCTIONALISM
Talcott Parsons was probably the most dominant theorist of his time. It
is unlikely, I suspect, that any one theoretical approach will so dominate
sociological theory again. For in the years between 1950 and the late 1970s,
Parsonian functionalism was clearly the focal point around which theo- |
retical controversy raged. Even those who despised Parsons’ functional
approach could not ignore it; and even now, several years after his death
and well over a decade since its period of dominance, Parsonian func-
tionalism is still the subject of controversy.! To appreciate Parsons’
achievement, I think it best to start at the beginning in 1937 when he
published his first major work, The Structure of Social Action,? and then,
I will trace the continuity of the scheme as it evolved over the next four
decades.°
1Although few appear to agree with all aspects of Parsonian theory, rarely has anyone
quarreled with the assertion that he has-been the dominant sociological figure of this century.
For documentation of Parsons’ influence, see Robert W. Friedrichs, A Sociology of Sociology
(New York: Free Press, 1970); and Alvin W. Gouldner, The Coming Crisis of Western
Sociology (New York: Basic Books, 1970).
2Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1937); the
most recent paperback edition (New York: Free Press, 1968) will be used in subsequent
footnotes.
3]t has been emphasized again and again that such continuity does not exist in Parsons’
work. For the most often quoted source of this position, see Joseph F. Scott, ‘““The Changing
Foundations of the Parsonian Action Scheme,” American Sociological Review 28 (October
1969), pp. 716-35. This position is held to be incorrect in the analysis to follow. In addition
to the present discussion, see also Jonathan H. Turner and Leonard Beeghley, “Current
Folklore in the Criticisms of Parsonian Action Theory,” Sociological Inquiry 44 (Winter
1974). See also Parsons’ reply and comments on this article, ibid. For more recent comments
57
OF TALCOTT PARSONS
58 CHAPTER 3 / THE ANALYTICAL FUNCTIONALISM
subsequent theoretical and substantive work makes sense, I feel, only after
this classificatory strategy is comprehended. For indeed, throughout his
intellectual career—from The Structure of Social Action to his recent
death—Parsons adhered to this strategy for building sociological theory.
Parsons’ strategy for theory building maintains a clear-cut ontological
position: the social universe displays systemic features that must be cap-
tured by a parallel ordering of abstract concepts. Curiously, the substan-
tive implications of this strategy for viewing the world as composed of
systems were recessive in The Structure of Social Action. Much more
conspicuous were assumptions about the “voluntaristic” nature of the
social world.
The “voluntaristic theory of action” represented for Parsons a syn-
thesis of the useful assumptions and concepts of utilitarianism, positivism,
and idealism. In reviewing the thought of classical economists, Parsons
noted the excessiveness of their utilitarianism: unregulated and atomistic
actors in a free and competitive marketplace rationally attempting to
choose those behaviors that will maximize their profits in their trans-
actions with others. Such a formulation of the social order presented for
Parsons a number of critical problems: Do humans always behave ra-
tionally? Are they indeed free and unregulated? How is order possible in
an unregulated and competitive system? Yet, Parsons saw as fruitful sev-
eral features of utilitarian thought, especially the concern with actors as
seeking goals and the emphasis on the choice-making capacities of human
beings who weigh alternative lines of action. Stated in this minimal form,
Parsons felt that the utilitarian heritage could indeed continue to inform
sociological theorizing. In a similar critical stance, Parsons rejected the
extreme formulations of radical positivists, who tended to view the social
world in terms of observable cause-and-effect relationships among phys-
ical phenomena. In so doing, he felt, they ignored the complex symbolic
functionings of the human mind. Furthermore, Parsons saw the emphasis
on observable cause-and-effect relationships as too easily encouraging a
sequence of infinite reductionism: groups were reduced to the causal re-
lationships of their individual members; individuals were reducible to the
cause-and-effect relationships of their physiological processes; these were
reducible to physicochemical relationships, and so on, down to the most
®See ibid., especially pp. 3-43, 727-76. For an excellent secondary analysis of Parsons’
position and why it does not appeal to the critics, see Enno Schwanenberg, “The Two
Problems of Order in Parsons’ Theory: An Analysis from Within,” Social Forces 49 (June
1971), pp. 569-81.
*For a more recent analysis of Parsons’ work in relation to the issues he raised in The
Structure of Social Action, see Leon Mayhew, “In Defense of Modernity: Talcott Parsons
and the Utilitarian Tradition,” American Journal of Sociology 89 (May 1984), pp. 1273-
1306; and Jeffrey C. Alexander, “Formal and Substantive Voluntarism in the Work of Talcott
Parsons: A Theoretical Reinterpretation,” American Sociological Review 43 (Winter 1978),
pp. 177-98.
T PARSONS
60 CHAPTER 3 / THE ANALYTICAL FUNCTIONALISM OF TALCOT
"Recently, there has been considerable debate and acrimony over “de- Parsonizing” Weber
and Durkheim. The presumption is that Parsons gave a distorted portrayal of these and
other figures and it is necessary to reexamine their works in an effort to remove Parsons’
interpretation from them. This plea ignores two facts: (1) Parsons never maintained that
he was summarizing works; instead he was using works and selectively borrowing concepts
to build a theory of action. (2) All sociologists can read these classic thinkers for themselves
and derive their own interpretations; there is no reason that they should be overly influenced
by Parsons. For the relevant articles, see Jere Cohen, Lawrence E. Hazelrigg, and Whitney
Pope, De-Parsonizing Weber: A Critique of Parsons’ Interpretation of Weber’s Sociology,”
American Sociological Review 40 (April 1975), pp. 229-41; and Whitney Pope, Jere
Cohen
and Lawrence Hazelrigg, “On the Divergence of Weber and Durkheim: A Critique of Parsons
Convergence Thesis,” American Sociological Review 40 (August 1975), pp. 417-27.
THE STRUCTURE OF SOCIAL ACTION 61
a a ote
Means,
aaa ae
Means»
Actor
Means3 Goals
Means,
a
Situational conditions
its most elementary components. Second, given his position on what the-
ory should be, the first analytical task in the development of sociological
theory is to isolate conceptually the systemic features of the most basic
unit from which more complex processes and structures are built.
Once these basic tasks were completed, I think Parsons began to ask:
how are unit acts connected to each other, and how can this connectedness
be conceptually represented? Indeed, near the end of The Structure of
Social Action, he recognized that “any atomistic system that deals only
with properties identifiable in the unit act ... will of necessity fail to
treat these latter elements adequately and be indeterminate as applied to
complex systems’ However, only the barest hints of what was to come
were evident in those closing pages.
Yet, perhaps only through the wisdom of hindsight, Parsons did offer
several clues about the features of these more complex systems. Most
notable, near the close of this first work, he emphasized that “the concept
of action points again to the organic property of action systems” [em-
phasis added].’ Buttressed by his strategy for building theory—that is, the
development of systems of concepts that mirror reality—it is clear that
he intended to develop a conceptual scheme that would capture the sys-
temic essence of social reality.
By 1945, eight years after he published The Structure of Social Action,
Parsons became more explicit about the form this analysis should take:
“The structure of social systems cannot be derived directly from the actor-
situation frame of reference. It requires functional analysis of the
complications introduced by the interaction of a plurality of actors.”
More significantly, this functional analysis should allow notions of needs
to enter: “The functional needs of social integration and the conditions
necessary for the functioning of a plurality of actors as a ‘unit’ system
sufficiently well integrated to exist as such impose others.”"! Starting from
these assumptions, which bear a close resemblance to those of Spencer,
Durkheim, Radcliffe-Brown, and Malinowski, Parsons began to develop
a complex functional scheme. Let me now attempt to reconstruct this
transition from voluntaristic unit acts to a functional scheme emphasizing
the systemic properties of action.
Talcott Parsons, “The Present Position and Prospect of Systemic Theory in Sociology
,”
Essays in Sociological Theory (New York:-Free Press, 1949), p. 229.
7
"Ibid.
“See also my “The Concept of ‘Action’ in Sociological Analysis” in Analytical and
Sociological Theories of Action, ed., G. Seeba3 and Raimo Toumea (Dordrecht, Holland:
Reidel, 1985). ,
"Talcott Parsons, The Social System (New York: Free Press, 1951).
second, points
the systemic features of society at all its diverse levels and,
social systems,
to the modes of articulation among personality systems,
and cultural patterns.
To capture conceptually the systemic features of culture, social sys-
s
tem, and personality, Parsons wastes little time in introducing notion
of functional requisites for each of these basic components of action. Such
requisites pertain not only to the internal problems of the action com-
ponents but also to their articulation with one another. Following both
Durkheim’s and Radcliffe-Brown’s lead, he views integration within and
among the action systems as a basic survival requisite. Since the social
system is his major topic, Parsons is concerned with the integration within
the social system itself and between the social system and the cultural
patterns, on the one hand, and between the social system and the per-
sonality system, on the other. In order for such integration to occur, at
least two functional requisites must be met:
, :
ete pattern variables were developed in collaboration with Edward Shils and were
oe ry in Toward a General Theory of Action (New York: Harper & Row, 1951).
+a “ , 20% “caycnlg Again, Parsons’ debt to Max Weber's concern with constructing
ypes can be seen in his presentation of the pattern variables.
THE SOCIAL SYSTEM 67
Cultural <—_——
Personality
culture are integrated into the social system, thereby providing assurance
of some degree of normative coherence and a minimal amount of com-
mitment by actors to conform to norms and play roles. In developing
concepts of this kind, Parsons begins to stress the equilibrating tendencies
of social systems, which, I believe, was a fatal mistake. For as I will discuss
shortly, Parsons left himself open here to severe criticism. But for the
moment, let me concentrate on his argument. I have diagrammatically
represented his reasoning in Figure 3-3. Now, I will fill in the details.
Just how are personality systems integrated into the social system,
thereby promoting equilibrium? At the most abstract level, Parsons con-
ceptualizes two mechanisms that integrate the personality into the social
system: (1) mechanisms of socialization and (2) mechanisms of social
control. It is through the operation of these mechanisms that personality
systems become structured such that they are compatible with the struc-
ture of social systems. Let me elaborate on each of these mechanisms.
1. In abstract terms, mechanisms of socialization are seen by
Parsons as the means through which cultural patterns—values, beliefs,
language, and other symbols—are internalized into the personality
system, thereby circumscribing its need structure. It is through this
process that actors are made willing to deposit motivational energy
in roles (thereby willing to conform to norms) and are given the
interpersonal and other skills necessary for playing roles. Another
function of socialization mechanisms is to provide stable and secure
interpersonal ties that alleviate much of the strain, anxiety, and ten-
sion associated with acquiring proper motives and skills.
2. Mechanisms of social control involve those ways in which sta-
tus-roles are organized in social systems to reduce strain and deviance.
There are numerous specific control mechanisms, including (a)
M OF TALCOTT PARSONS
68 CHAPTER 3 / THE ANALYTICAL FUNCTIONALIS
clear and
institutionalization, which makes role expectations
adictory ex-
unambiguous while segregating in time and space contr
actors sub-
pectations; (b) interpersonal sanctions and gestures, which
in
tly employ to mutually sanction conformity; (c) ritual activities,
which actors act out symbolically sources of strain that could prove
-
disruptive while they reinforce dominant cultural patterns; (d) safety
valve structures, in which pervasive deviant propensities are segre-
gated in time and space from normal institutional patterns; (e) rein-
tegration structures, which are specifically charged with coping with
the bringing back into line deviant tendencies; and, finally, (f) the
institutionalization into some sectors of a system the capacity to use
force and coercion.
These two mechanisms are thus viewed as resolving one of the most
persistent integrative problems facing social systems. The other major
integrative problem facing social systems concerns how cultural patterns
contribute to the maintenance of social order and equilibrium. Again at
the most abstract level, Parsons visualizes two ways in which this occurs.
(1) Some components of culture, such as language, are basic resources
necessary for interaction to occur. Without symbolic resources, commu-
nication and hence interaction would not be possible. Thus, by providing
common resources for all actors, interaction is made possible by culture.
(2) A related but still separable influence of culture on interaction is
exerted through the substance of ideas contained in cultural patterns
(values, beliefs, ideology, and so forth). These ideas can provide actors
with common viewpoints, personal ontologies, or, to borrow from W. I.
Thomas, a common “definition of the situation.’”’ These common mean-
ings allow interaction to proceed smoothly with minimal disruption.
Naturally, Parsons acknowledges that the mechanisms of socializa-
tion and social control are not always successful, hence allowing deviance
and social change to occur. But it is clear that the concepts developed in
The Social System weigh analysis in the direction of looking for processes
that maintain the integration and, by implication, the equilibrium of
social systems. In Figure 3-4, I have summarized the logic of Parsons’
functionalism at this stage in the elaboration of his conceptual scheme.
I see subsequent developments in Parsons’ action theory as an attempt
to expand upon the basic analytical scheme of The Social System that is
summarized in Figures 3-2, 3-3, and 3-4 while trying to accommodate
some of the critics’ charges of a static and conservative conceptual bias
(see later section). I do not imagine that the many critics of Parsons will
ever be silenced, but some interesting elaborations of the scheme occurred
in the quarter century following Parsons’ first explicitly functional work.
Let me now turn to these.
The
Specific General ech
structures ————————» mechanisms for ———————________» oT
are types of integrating oe
evsinatndiines social system
personality into
social systems,
thereby allowing
for
Talcott Parsons, Robert F. Bales, and Edward A. Shils, Working Papers in the Theory
of Action (Glencoe, IIl.: Free Press, 1953).
Talcott Parsons and Neil J. Smelser, Economy and Society (New York: Free Press,
1956). These requisites are the same as those enumerated by Malinowski. See previous
chapter, Table 2-1.
OF TALCOTT PARSONS
70 CHAPTER 3 / THE ANALYTICAL FUNCTIONALISM
onalism
FIGURE 3-5 Parsons’ Functional Imperativism or Requisite Functi
The survival
Specific A universal capacity of
ao gai — toy i
the social
:
Latency Integration
ll action system.
one of the four system requisites—A, G, I, L—of the overa
g the most con-
The organism is considered to be the subsystem havin
ately through
sequences for resolving adaptive problems since it is ultim
to the other
this system that environmental resources are made available
system, per-
action subsystems. As the goal-seeking and decision-making
ving goal-
sonality is considered to have primary consequences for resol
rat-
attainment problems. As an organized network of status-norms integ
ing the patterns of the cultural system and the needs of personality sys-
tems, the social system is viewed as the major integrative subsystem of
the general action system. As the repository of symbolic content of in-
teraction, the cultural system is considered to have primary consequences
for managing tensions of actors and assuring that the proper symbolic
resources are available to assure the maintenance of institutional patterns
(latency).
After viewing each action system as a subsystem of a more inclusive,
overall one, Parsons begins to explore the interrelations among the four
subsystems. What emerges is a hierarchy of informational controls, with
culture informationally circumscribing the social system, social structure
informationally regulating the personality system, and personality infor-
mationally regulating the organismic system. For example, cultural value
orientations would be seen as circumscribing or limiting the range of
variation in the norms of the social system; in turn, these norms, as
translated into expectations for actors playing roles, would be viewed as
limiting the kinds of motives and decision-making processes in personality
systems; these features of the personality system would then be seen as
circumscribing biochemical processes in the organism. Conversely, each
system in the hierarchy is also viewed as providing the “‘energic condi-
tions” necessary for action at the next higher system. That is, the or-
ganism provides the energy necessary for the personality system, the per-
sonality system provides the energic conditions for the social system, and
the organization of personality systems into a social system provides the
conditions necessary for a cultural system. Thus, the input-output rela-
tions among action systems are reciprocal, with systems exchanging in-
formation and energy. Systems high in information circumscribe the uti-
lization of energy at the next lower system level, while each lower system
provides the conditions and facilities necessary for action in the next
higher system. This scheme has been termed a cybernetic hierarchy of
control. I have diagramed it in Figure 3-7.
Action,” in Psychology: A Science, ed. S. Koch, vol. 3 (New York: McGraw-Hill. 1958). pp.
612-711. By 1961, these ideas were even more clearly formulated: see Talcott Parsons, “An
Outline of the Social System,” in Theories of Society, ed. T. Parsons, E. Shils, K. D. Naegele,
and J. R. Pitts (New York: Free Press, 1961), pp. 30-38. See also Jackson Toby, “Parsons”
Theory of Social Evolution,” Contemporary Sociology 1 (September 1972), pp. 395-401,
GENERALIZED MEDIA OF EXCHANGE 73
SE ES RAT RIT PB DEES TELE DA DETE NRE ADE PP SE BID Ett EAN ECT
21Parsons’ writings on this topic are incomplete, but see his “On the Concept of Political
Power,” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 107 (June 1963), pp. 232-62;
Talcott Parsons, “On the Concept of Influence,” Public Opinion Quarterly 27 (Spring 1963),
pp. 37-62; and Talcott Parsons, “Some Problems of General Theory,” in Theoretical So-
ciology: Perspectives and Developments, ed. J. C. McKinney and E. A. Tiryakian (New
York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1970), pp. 28-68. See also Talcott Parsons and Gerald M.
Platt, The American University (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1975).
OF TALCOTT PARSONS
74 CHAPTER 3 / THE ANALYTICAL FUNCTIONALISM
money as the
Within the social system, the adaptive sector utilizes
attainment
medium of exchange with the other three sectors; the goal-
its principal
sector employs power—the capacity to induce conformity—as
m relies upon
medium of exchange; the integrative sector of a social syste
commit-
influence—the capacity to persuade; ard the latency sector uses
changes
ments—especially the capacity to be loyal. The analysis of inter
-
of specific structures within social systems should thus focus on the input
output exchanges utilizing different symbolic media.
Among the subsystems of the overall action system, a similar analysis
of the symbolic media used in exchanges should be undertaken, but Par-
sons never clearly described the nature of these media.”” What he appeared
to be approaching was a conceptual scheme for analyzing the basic types
of symbolic media, or information, linking systems in the cybernetic hi-
erarchy of control.”
Empirical Analysis of Social Change and Conflict,” in Institutions and Social Exchange:
The Sociologies of Talcott Parsons and George C. Homans, ed. H. Turk and R. L. Simpson
(Indianapolis, Ind.: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970).
*See last chapter for references.
27Talcott Parsons, Societies: Evolutionary and Comparative Perspectives and The Sys-
tem of Modern Societies (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1966, 1971, respectively).
The general stages of development were first outlined in Talcott Parsons, “Evolutionary
Universals in Society,” American Sociological Review 29 (June 1964), pp. 339-57.
76 CHAPTER 3 / THE ANALYTICAL FUNCTIONALISM OF TALCOTT PARSONS
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
i]
Physico-
Organic
chemical
|
|
behavioral | personality
|
|
|
i]
Acton
t
|
|
|
cultural social
{
|
|
had earlier called this the organismic). And finally, in this desire to un-
derstand basic parameters of the human condition, he viewed these four
action systems as only one subsystem within the larger system of the
universe. This vision is portrayed in Figure 3-8.
As can be seen in Figure 3-8, the universe is divided into four sub-
systems, each meeting one of the four requisites—-that is, A, G, I, or L.
The four action systems resolve integrative problems; the organic system
handles goal-attainment problems; the physicochemical copes with ad-
aptation problems; and the telic (“‘ultimate” problems of meaning and
cognition) deals with latency problems.
Each of these subsystems employs its own media for intra- and in-
tersubsystem activity. For the action subsystem, the distinctive medium
is symbolic meanings; for the telic, it is transcendental ordering; for the
organic, it is health; and for the physicochemical, it is empirical ordering
(lawlike relations of matter, energy, etc.). There are double interchanges
of these media among the four A, G, I, L sectors, with “products” and
“factors” being reciprocally exchanged. That is, each subsystem of the
TT PARSONS
78 CHAPTER 3 / THE ANALYTICAL FUNCTIONALISM OF TALCO
a factor
universe transmits a product to the others, while it also provides
necessary for the operation of other subsystems. Let me illustrate with
the L (telic) and I (action) interchange. At the product level, the telic
system provides “definitions of human responsibility” to the action sub-
systems and receives “sentiments of justification” from the action sub-
system. At the factor level, the telic provides “categorical imperatives”
and receives “acceptance of moral obligations.” These double interchanges
are, of course, carried out with the distinctive media of the I and A
subsystems—that is, transcendental ordering and symbolic meaning,
respectively.
The end result of this analysis, is, I feel, a grand metaphysical vision
of the universe as it impinges upon human existence. It represents an
effort to categorize the universe in terms of systems, subsystems, system
requisites, generalized media, and exchanges involving these media. As
such, it is no longer sociology but philosophy, or at best, a grand meta-
theoretical vision. Parsons had indeed come a long way since the humble
unit act made its entrance in 1937.
American Journal of Sociology 64 (September 1958), pp. 115-27. This polemic echoed the
earlier assessments by others, including David Lockwood, “Some Remarks on “The Social
System,’” British Journal of Sociology 7 (June 1950), pp. 134-46; C. Wright Mills, The
Sociological Imagination (New York: Oxford University Press, 1959), pp. 44-49; and Lewis
Coser, The Functions of Social Conflict (New York: Free Press, 1956), pp. 1-10.
Leslie Sklair, “The Fate of the Functional Requisites in Parsonian Sociology,” British
Journal of Sociology 21 (March 1970), pp. 30-42.
PARSONS
80 CHAPTER 3 / THE ANALYTICAL FUNCTIONALISM OF TALCOTT
Or, in reality,
on those rare occasions when system needs are not met?
which are
are not these phenomena pervasive features of social systems,
inadequately grasped by the proliferating system of concepts?
The elaboration of the informational hierarchy of control among the
not
overall systems of action and its use to analyze social change did
silence the critics because the only type of change that is conceptualized
is evolution, as opposed to revolution and other forms of violent disruption
to social systems. Much like Durkheim and Spencer, Parsons’ views change
as a “progressive” differentiation and integration, with the inexorable
progress of societal development delayed from time to time by a failure
to integrate the differentiating cultural and social systems.*?
32Perhaps the most recent and scholarly attempt to document the reasons behind these
problems in Parsonian action theory is provided by Alvin Gouldner, The Coming Crisis of
Western Sociology (New York: Basic Books, 1970). However, John K. Rhoads, “On Gould-
ner’s Crisis of Western Sociology,” American Journal of Sociology 78 (July 1972), pp. 136-
54, emphasizes that Gouldner has perceived what-he wants to perceive in Parsons’ work,
ignoring those passages that would connote just the opposite of stasis, control, consensus,
and order. See also Rhoads, “Reply to Gouldner,” American Journal of Sociology 78 (May
1973), pp. 1493-96, which was written in response to Gouldner’s defense of his position
(Alvin Gouldner, “For Sociology: ‘Varieties of Political Expression’ Revisited,’ American
Journal of Saciology 78 [March 1973], pp. 1063-93, particularly pp. 1083-93).
For analyses of the logic of functionalist inquiry, see R. B. Braithwaite, Scientific
Explanation (New York: Harper & Row, 1953), Chapters 9 and 10; Carl G. Hempel, “The
Logic of Functional Analysis” in Symposium on Sociological Theory, ed. L. Gross (New
York: Harper & Row, 1959), pp. 271-307; Percy S. Cohen, Modern Social Theory (New
York: Basic Books, 1968), pp. 58-64; Francesca Cancian, “Functional Analysis of Change,”
American Sociological Review 25 (December 1960), pp. 818-27; S. F. Nadel, Foundations
of Social Anthropology (Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press, 1951), pp. 373-78; Ernest Nagel,
Teleological Explanation and Teleological Systems,” in Readings in the Philosophy of
Science, ed. H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck (New York: Harper & Row, 1953), pp. 537-58; Phillip
Ronald Dore, “Function and Cause,” American Sociological Review 26 (December 1961),
pp. 843-53; Charles J. Erasmus, “Obviating the Functions of Functionalism,” Social Forces
45 (March 1967), pp. 319-28; Harry C. Bredemeier, “The Methodology of Functionalism,”
American Sociological Review 20 (April 1955), pp. 173-80; Bernard Barber, “Structural-
Functional Analysis: Some Problems and Misunderstandings,” American Sociological Re-
view 21 (April 1956), pp. 129-35; Robert K. Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure
(Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1957), pp. 44-61; Arthur L. Stinchcombe, Constructing Social
Theories (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1968), pp. 80-116; Hans Zetterberg, On
Theory and Verification in Sociology (Totowa, N.J.: Bedminister Press, 1965), pp. 74-79.
CRITICISMS OF PARSONIAN FUNCTIONALISM 81
“For example, see Talcott Parsons, “Authority, Legitimation and Political Action” in
Authority, ed. C. J. Friedrich (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1958); Parsons, “On
the Concept of Power”; and Talcott Parsons, ‘The Political Aspect of Structure and Process,”
in Varieties of Political Theory, ed. David Easton (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1966).
T PARSONS
82 CHAPTER 3 / THE ANALYTICAL FUNCTIONALISM OF TALCOT
**For basic references on the issue, consult G. Bergman, “Purpose, Function and Scientific
Explanation,” Acta Sociologica 5 (1962), pp. 225-28; J. Canfield, “Teleological Explanation
in Biology,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 14 (1964), pp. 285-95; K.
Deutsch, “Mechanism, Teleology and Mind,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
12 (1951), pp. 185-223; C. J. Ducasse, “Explanation, Mechanism, and Teleology,” in Read-
ings in Philosophical Analysis, ed. H. Feig] and W. Sellars (New York: D. Appleton, 1949);
D. Emmet, Function, Purpose and Powers (London: Routledge-Kegan, 1958); L. S. Fever,
“Causality in the Social Sciences,” Journal of Philosophy 51 (1954), pp. 191-208; W. W.
Isajiw, Causation and Functionalism in Sociology (New York: Shocken Books, 1968); A.
Kaplan, “Noncausal Explanation,” in Cause and Effect, ed. D. Lerner (New York: Free
Press, 1965); C. A. Mace, “Mechanical and Teleological Causation”: I. Scheffler, “Thoughts
on Teleology,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 9 (1958), pp. 265-84; P.
Sztompka, “Teleological Language in Sociology,” The Polish Sociological Bulletin (1969),
pp.an ag System and Function: Toward a Theory of Society (New York: Academic
ress, ,
*Nagel, ““Teleological Explanation and Teleological Systems.”
“Nadel, Foundations of Social Anthropology, p. 375.
CRITICISMS OF PARSONIAN FUNCTIONALISM 83
ositions point to reverse causal chains that are typical of many social
phenomena. By emphasizing that the function served by a structure
in maintaining the needs of the whole could cause the emergence of
that structure, Parsons’ functional imperativism forces analysis to be
attuned to those causal processes involved in the initial selection,
from the infinite variety of possible social structures, of only certain
types of structures. The persistence over time of these selected struc-
tures can also be explained by the needs and/or equilibrium states of
the whole: those structures having consequences for meeting needs
and/or maintaining an equilibrium have a “selective advantage”’ over
those that do not. I do not think that such statements are illegitimate
teleologies, for it is quite possible for the systemic whole to exist prior
in time to the structures that emerge and persist to maintain that
whole. Furthermore, I do not think it necessary to impute purpose
to the systemic whole. Just as in the biophysical world, where ecol-
ogical and population balances are maintained by nonpurposive se-
lective processes (for example, predators increase until they eat them-
selves out of food and then decrease until the food supply regenerates
itself), so social wholes can maintain themselves in a state of equi-
librium or meet the imperatives necessary for survival.
This line of argument has led Stinchcombe to summarize:
Functional explanations are-thus complex forms of causal theories. They
involve causal connections among... variables as with a special causal prior-
ity of the consequences of activity in total explanation. There has been a
good deal of philosophical confusion about such explanations, mainly due to
the theorist’s lack of imagination in realizing the variety of reverse causal
processes which can select behavior or structures according to their
consequences.”
basic unit acts he first described in The Structure of Social Action. The
more the system of concepts was brought to bear on increasingly complex
patterns or organization among unit acts, the more Parsons relied upon
the requisites to sort out what processes in these complex patterns will
help explain the most variance. Thus, Parsons’ imperatives constitute not
so much a metaphysical entity, but a methodological yardstick for dis-
tinguishing what is crucial from not crucial among the vast number of
potential processes in social systems. Despite the fact that Parsons was
unable to specify exact criteria for assessing whether adaptive, goal-
attainment, integrative, and latency needs are being met, he used these
somewhat vaguely conceptualized requisites to assess the theoretical sig-
nificance of concrete social phenomena. I am sure that Parsons implicitly
employed the requisites this way in his many essays, which even the critics
must admit are insightful. And perhaps this fact alone can justify use of
the requisites to assess social phenomena.
Furthermore, I can see that the requisites are particularly useful in
studying complex empirical systems, because in empirical systems it may
be possible to specify more precisely criteria necessary for their survival.
With these empirically based requisites as criteria, it may then be possible
to distinguish significant from less significant social processes in these
systems, thereby assuring more insightful explanations. It appears, then,
that despite some of the logical problems created by their retention, Par-
sons felt that the strategic value of the requisites in explaining social
processes more than compensates for the logical difficulties so frequently
stressed by the critics. Other functionalists agree, but I think that we
should maintain some skepticism here until functional analyses of em-
pirical events prove superior to less problematic alternatives.
1As will be recalled, Parsons in 1945 began to conceptualize unit acts in systemic terms
and began to visualize such systems in terms of requisites. See Talcott Parsons, “The Present
Position and Prospects of Systemic Theory in Sociology,” in Essays in Sociological Theory
(Glencoe, IIl.: Free Press, 1949). Moreover, Merton may have introduced Parsons to func-
tional analysis, since Merton conducted a seminar at Harvard, where Parsons was a young
instructor, on functional theorists such as Malinowski. In fact, I suspect that Merton was
a functional theorist several years before Parsons made the conversion. Yet, from the be-
ginning Merton was a critic of the Parsonian approach.
2Robert K. Merton, “Discussion of Parsons’ “The Position of Sociological Theory’,”
American Sociological Review 13 (April 1948), pp. 164-68.
3Ibid. Most of Merton’s significant essays on functionalism have been included, and
frequently expanded upon, in Robert K. Merton, Social+-Theory and Social Structure (Glen-
coe, Ill.: Free Press, 1949). Quotation taken from page 45 of the 1968 edition of this classic
work. Most subsequent references will be made to the articles incorporated into this book.
For more recent essays on Merton’s work, see Lewis A. Coser, ed., The Idea of Social
Structure (New York: Free Press, 1975).
87
ROBERT K. MERTON
88 CHAPTER 4 / THE EMPIRICAL FUNCTIONALISM OF
since the
For Merton, such grand theoretical schemes are premature
etion has
theoretical and empirical groundwork necessary for their compl
emerge without
not been performed. Just as Einsteinian theory did not
, so sociol-
a long cumulative research foundation and theoretical legacy
se “it has
ogical theory will have to wait for its Einstein, primarily becau
,
not yet found its Kepler—to say nothing of its Newton, Laplace, Gibbs
Maxwell or Planck.”
,
In the absence of this foundation, what passes for sociological theory
in Merton’s critical eye, consists of “general orientations toward data,
suggesting types of variables which theorists must somehow take into
account, rather than clearly formulated, verifiable statements of relation-
ships between specified variables.”® Strategies advocated by those such
as Parsons are not really theory, but philosophical systems, with “their
varied suggestiveness, their architectonic splendor, and their sterility.’
However, to pursue the opposite strategy of constructing inventories of
low-level empirical propositions will prove equally sterile, thus suggesting
to Merton the need for “theories of the middle range” in sociology. As I
emphasized in Chapter 1 (see Figure 1-1), such theories are not highly
abstract nor broad. And I am not as optimistic as Merton that they will
yield much theoretical payoff. Yet, despite my reservations, Merton’s ad-
vocacy has developed a wide following, and so, let me try to indicate what
made Merton’s middle-range strategy so appealing.
In Merton’s view, theories of the middle range offer more theoretical
promise than Parsons’ grand theory. They are couched at a lower level
of abstraction and reveal clearly defined and operationalized concepts that
are incorporated into statements of covariance for a limited range of
phenomena. Although middle-range theories are abstract, they are also
connected to the empirical world, thus encouraging the research so nec-
essary for the clarification of concepts and reformulation of theoretical
generalizations. Without this interplay between theory and research, Mer-
ton contended, theoretical schemes will remain suggestive congeries of
concepts, which are incapable of being refuted, while, on the other hand,
empirical research will remain unsystematic, disjointed, and of little utility
in expanding a body of sociological knowledge. Thus, by following a middle-
range strategy, the concepts and propositions of sociological theory will
become more tightly organized as theoretically focused empirical research
forces clarification, elaboration, and reformulation of the concepts and
propositions of each middle-range theory.
From this growing clarity in theories directed at a limited range of
phenomena and supported by empirical research can eventually come the
s as to whether
his advocacy for middle-range theory did. I have my doubt
logists do not
this was for the good of sociological theory, but most socio
theory in research
share my reservations. Indeed, they see the grounding of
little more than
as a great virtue, whereas for me, these “theories of” are
set of prop-
statements of empirical regularity that need a more abstract
strategy for
ositions to explain them. And so the debate over the best
Merton’s
developing theory rages. My concern here, however, is with
ional
functionalism. And so, let me now turn to his paradigm for funct
analysis.
*Robert K. Merton, “Manifest and Latent Functions,” in Social Theory and Social
Structure (1968), pp. 74-91.
"See Robert K. Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure, pp. 45-61.
"Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure (1968), pp. 81-82.
MERTON'S PARADIGM FOR FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS 91
12See Parsons, “Present Position and Prospects of Systemic Theory” and Talcott Par-
sons, The Social System (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1951).
Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure (1968), p. 84.
OF ROBERT K. MERTON
92 CHAPTER 4 / THE EMPIRICAL FUNCTIONALISM
consequences
earlier forms of analysis by focusing on the crucial types of
e, for the social
of sociocultural items for each other and, if the facts dictat
whole.
4 This quote is from an encyclopaedia article where Malinowski was arguing against
ethnocentrism. His more scholarly work (see Chapter 2) is much less extreme. See also my
and Alexandra Maryanski’s Functionalism (Menlo Park Calif.: Benjamin-Cummings, 1978).
MERTON’'S PARADIGM FOR FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS 93
other items
a particular item having a specified set of consequences for
anal-
and systemic wholes. To assure adherence to this form of structural
ting
ysis, Merton went so far as to outline a set of procedures for execu
the general guidelines of his functional orientation.
Specified Empirically
Social structural empirical established
level part ——————______________» needs of
Consequences _ social context
for meeting
Assessment of net
balance of
consequences of the
item
Understanding of /
Psychological
Psychological “meaning” to—————————»
level individuals Consequences needs served
for meeting
‘*Tbid., p. 136.
K. MERTON
96 CHAPTER 4 / THE EMPIRICAL FUNCTIONALISM OF ROBERT
item
in a structure. In this way, the net balance of consequences of an
at diverse levels of social organization can be assessed.
ILLUSTRATING MERTON’S
FUNCTIONAL STRATEGY
Merton’s paradigm and protocol for constructing functional theories of
the middle range are remarkedly free of statements about individual and
system needs or requisites. In his protocol statements, Merton approaches ~
the question of the needs and requisites fulfilled by a particular item only
after description of (1) the item in question, (2) the structural context in
which the item survives, and (3) its meaning for the individuals involved.
With this information, it is then possible to establish both the manifest
and latent functions of an item, as well as the net balance of functions
and dysfunctions of the item for varied segments of a social system. Un-
fortunately, the implied sequencing of functional analysis is not always
performed by Merton, presumably for at least two reasons. First, in se-
lecting an established structure in a system for analysis, the investigator
usually assumes that the item persists because it is fulfilling some need.
As I will make evident, Merton begins (as opposed to concludes) with
this assumption in his analysis of political machines—thus leaving him
to conclude that “structure affects function and function affects struc-
ture.”” Wher description of items begins with an implicit assumption of
their functions for fulfilling needs, then I think that the descriptions will
be performed in ways assuring confirmation of this implicit assumption.
Second, in analyzing the structural context of an item and assessing why
it emerges and persists over alternative items, | believe it inevitable that
there will be preconceptions of the functions served by an item in order
to know why it fulfills a set of needs better than would various alternatives.
Otherwise, I do not see how it is possible to determine what potential
alternatives could exist to substitute for the present item.
For at least these two reasons, then, execution of Merton’s strategy
is difficult. Let me indicate how this is so by examining Merton’s illus-
tration of it. This illustration involves an analysis of American political
machines. Much like that of his anthropological straw men, such as Rad-
cliffe-Brown and Malinowski, Merton’s need to analyze separately the
causes and functions of structural items is not as evident in his actual
account of empirical events.
. Merton begins his analysis of American political machines with the
simple question: “How do they manage to continue in operation?” Fol-
lowing this interesting question is an assumption reminiscent of Mali-
nowski’s functional analysis:
"Tbid., p. 125.
ILLUSTRATING MERTON’S FUNCTIONAL STRATEGY 97
— Durkheim, The Rules of the Sociological Method (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press. 1938).
p. 96.
ILLUSTRATING MERTON’S FUNCTIONAL STRATEGY 101
'There are some notable exceptions, for one still finds elements of Parsons in the work
of such scholars as Neil J. Smelser, Jeffrey Alexander, Dean Gerstein, Victor Lidz, Bernard
Barber, Adrian Hayes, and other Americans. Most of this work, however, is more empirical
and only selectively borrows from Parsons’s great conceptual edifice.
For example, the work of Richard Minch is very prominent in both Europe and America.
For a recently translated sample, see his Theory of Action: Reconstructing the Contributions
of Talcott Parsons, Emile Durkheim and Max Weber (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1986).
‘Luhmann has published extensively, but unfortunately most of his work is in German.
The only comprehensive sample of his work in English is his The Differentiation of Society,
trans. S. Holmes and C. Larmore (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982). The bulk
of this chapter borrows from chapters in this book.
102
LUHMANN’S ‘GENERAL SYSTEMS’ APPROACH 103
‘Ibid., p. 88.
6] should stress this is not an approach that most scholars, who view themselves as
general systems theorists, would recognize.
°This definition, it should be noted, is the same as Talcott Parsons’s. See Chapter 3.
NN
104 CHAPTER 5 / THE SYSTEMS FUNCTIONALISM OF NIKLAS LUHMA
"Talcott Parsons, The Social System (New York: Free Press, 1951).
*Luhmann, The Differentiation, Chapter 12.
LUHMANN'S ‘GENERAL SYSTEMS’ APPROACH 105
In making this assertion, Luhmann directly attacks Parsons. See Luhmann. The Dif-
ferentiation, Chapter 3.
“Ibid., p. 73.
'"Tbid., p. 79.
LUHMANN'S ‘GENERAL SYSTEMS’ APPROACH 107
entrance and exit rules (“work for money’’); and it will be oriented to the
future, with the past as only a collapsed framework to guide present ac-
tivity in the pursuit of future outcomes (such as profits and promotions).
In addition to these nesting processes, integration is promoted by the
deflection of people’s activities across different organizations in diverse
functional domains. When there are many organizations in a society, none
consumes an individual’s sense of identity and self since people’s energies
are dispersed across several organization systems. As a consequence of
their piecemeal involvement, members are unlikely to be emotionally drawn
into conflict among organization systems; and when individual members
cannot be pulled emotionally into a conflict, its intensity and potential
for social disruption is lessened. Moreover, because interaction systems
are distinct from the more inclusive organization, any conflict between
organizations is often seen by the rank and file as distant and remote to
their interests and concerns; it is something ‘‘out there” in the environ-
ment of their interaction systems, and hence, it is not very involving.
Yet another source of conflict mitigation is the entrance/exit rules of
an organization. As these become elaborated into hierarchies, offices, es-
tablished procedures, salary scales, and the like, they reduce the relevance
of members’ conflicts outside the organization—for example, their race
and religion. Such outside conflicts are separated from those within the
organization, and as a result, their salience in the broader societal system
is reduced.
And finally, once differentiation of organizations is an established
mechanism in a society, then specific social control organizations—law,
police, courts—can be easily created to mitigate and resolve conflicts. That
is, the generation of distinct organizations that are functionally specific
represents a new “‘social technology”; and once this technology has been
used in one context, it can be applied to additional contexts. Thus, the
integrative problems created by the differentiation and proliferation of
organizations creates the very conditions that can resolve these prob-
lems—the capacity to create organizations to mediate among organizations.
And so, while differentiation of three system levels creates problems
of integration and conditions conducive to conflict, it also produces coun-
tervailing forces for integration. In making this argument, Luhmann em-
phasizes that in complex systems, order is not sustained by consensus on
common values, beliefs, and norms. On the contrary, there is likely to be
considerable disagreement over these, except perhaps at the most abstract
level. I think that this is an important contribution of Luhmann’s soci-
ology, for it distinguishes his theoretical approach from Talcott Parsons,
who, I think, overstressed the need for value consensus in complex social
systems. Additionally, Luhmann stresses that individuals’ moral and emo-
tional attachment to the social fabric is not essential for social integration.
To seek a romantic return to a cohesive community, as Emile Durkheim,
LUHMANN’S ‘GENERAL SYSTEMS’ APPROACH 109
notes, “language makes negative copies available” by its very nature. Third,
in implying their opposite, codes create the potential for the opposite
action—for instance, “to be a bad boy.” In human codes, then, the very
process of selecting lines of action and in reducing complexity with a code
also expands potential options (to do just the opposite or some variant
of the opposite). This fact makes the human system highly flexible, be-
cause the communications codes used to organize the system and reduce
complexity also contain implicit messages about alternatives.
; "Obviously, Luhmann is borrowing Parsons’ idea about generalized media. See Chapter
'*Much like Parsons, this analysis of communications media is never fully explicated or
systematically discussed for all functional domains. ;
19 We will
: see shortly,. , . :
however, that money is the sole exception here.
LUHMANN’S GENERAL SYSTEMS’ APPROACH 111
how power is to be exercised; they can analyze love to decide what is true
love; they can use truth to specify the procedures to get at truth; and so
on. Luhmann sees this reflexivity as a mechanism that facilitates adap-
tation of a system to its environment. It does so by ordering responses
and reducing complexity, on the one hand, while it provides a system
with the capacity to think about new options for action, on the other.
For example, it becomes possible to mobilize power to think about new
and more adaptive ways to exercise power in political decisions, as is the
case when a society’s political elite create a constitutional system based
on a separation of powers.
As communications media are used reflexively, they allow for what
Luhmann terms self-thematization. Using media, a system can come to
conceptualize itself and relations with the environment in terms of a
“perspective” or “theme.” Such self-thematization reduces complexity. by
providing guidelines about how to deal with the temporal, material, and
symbolic dimensions of the environment. It becomes possible to have a
guiding perspective on how to orient to time, to organize people in space,
and to order symbols \into codes. For example, money and its reflexive
use for self-thematization in a capitalist economy create a concern with
the future, an emphasis on rational organization of people, and a set of
codes emphasizing impersonal exchanges of services and commodities.
The consequence of these self-thematizations is for economic organiza-
tions to reduce the complexity of their environments and, thereby, to
coordinate social action more effectively.
all of his work with this scheme has been on the related processes of social
evolution and societal differentiation, especially of organization systems
in the political, legal, and economic domains of a society.
This is essentially Parsons’ definition (see Chapter 3). It was Spencer’s and Durkheim's
as well (see Chapter 2).
*“Luhmann, The Differentiation, pp. 255-57.
LUHMANN’S CONCEPTION OF SOCIAL EVOLUTION 113
z. ‘ Z h ; :
Luhmann is borrowing here from Emile Durkheim's analysis in The Division of Labor
24 . :
LUHMANN’S CONCEPTION OF SOCIAL EVOLUTION 115
in Society (New York: Free Press, 1949; originally published in 1893) as well as Talcott
Parsons’ discussion of “value generalization.” See Chapter 3
*Iuhmann, The Differentiation, pp. 229-54.
*Ibid., p. 235.
116 CHAPTER 5 / THE SYSTEMS FUNCTIONALISM OF NIKLAS LUHMANN
*Luhmann fails to cite the earlier work of Georg Simmel on these matters. See Simmel's
The Philosophy of Money.
*Luhmann, The Differentiation, p. 207.
THE FUNCTIONAL DIFFERENTIATION OF SOCIETY 123
*[bid., p. 216.
124 CHAPTER 5 / THE SYSTEMS FUNCTIONALISM OF NIKLAS LUHMANN
wi
re ~ the
Wi Somecdoe
7 ~
' s fi
enaeias
om a . ™ ear
Gaaee ano pha
jueien aslo ote pecihegs basa
weiie:
|
Fhfe 'y
_ ral
: Lee
¥; ta Ty “a
ca
?
Conflict Theory
127
at a
. CHAPTER 6 ae
'\David Lockwood, “Some Remarks on ‘The Social System,’ ” British Journal of Sociology
7 (June 1956), pp. 134-46.
129
130 CHAPTER 6 / THE ORIGINS OF CONFLICT AND CRITICAL THEORIZING
over the distribution of these resources. And finally, the fact that different
interest groups pursue different goals and hence vie with one another
assures that conflict will erupt. These forces, Lockwood contended, rep-
resent mechanisms of social disorder that should be as analytically sig-
nificant to the understanding of social systems as Parsons’s mechanisms
of socialization and social control.
As I noted in Chapter 3, Ralf Dahrendorf crystallized this line of
argument toward the end of the decade by comparing functional theory
to a utopia.? Utopias usually have few historical antecedents—much like
Parsons’s hypothesized equilibrium, utopias display universal consensus
on prevailing values and institutional arrangements—in a vein remarkably
similar to Parsons’s concept of institutionalization; and utopias always
display processes that operate to maintain existing arrangements—much
like the mechanisms of Parsons’s social system. Hence, utopias and the
social world when viewed from a functional perspective do not change
very much, since they do not concern themselves with history, dissension
over values, and conflict in institutional arrangements.
At the same time, another body of conflict criticism was emerging.
This criticism was mounted against all positivistic social science, espe-
cially the functional variety but also any system of theory that proclaimed
itself as objective and neutral.’ All theory that seeks to understand the
social world without also exposing the patterns of oppression and dom-
ination is, in effect, an ideology supporting the status quo. For in studying
the world “‘as it is,” there is an implicit assumption that this is how the
social order must be. Theoretical knowledge cannot, therefore, merely
describe events. It must expose exploitive social arrangements and, at the
same time, suggest alternative ways to organize humans in less oppressive
ways. Social theory cannot be neutral; rather, it must be emancipatory.
To some extent, the critiques of Parsonian functionalism and posi-
tivism owe their inspiration to what I see as contradictory strains in the
work of Karl Marx. Those who were to criticize Parsons for his failure
to examine conflict tended to accept the positivistic strains in Marx and
to propose a conflict sociology that tried to develop abstract propositions
explaining the conflictual nature of social reality.4 In contrast, those who
Conflict (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1973); Anthony Oberschall, Social Conflict
and Social Movements (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1973); Robin M. Williams,
Jr., Mutual Accommodation: Ethnic Conflict and Cooperation (Minneapolis, Minn.: Uni-
versity of Minnesota Press, 1977); Randall Collins, Conflict Sociology (New York: Academic
Press, 1975); Ted Gurr, “Sources of Rebellion in Western Societies: Some Quantitative
Evidence,” The Annals 391 (September 1970), pp. 128-44; A. L. Jacobson, “Intrasocietal
Conflict: A Preliminary Test of a Structural Level Theory,” Comparative Political Studies
6 (1973), pp. 62-83; David Snyder, “Institutional Setting and Industrial Conflict,” American
Sociological Review 40 (June 1975), pp. 259-78; David Britt and Omer R. Galle, “Industrial
Conflict and Unionization,” American Sociological Review 37 (February 1972), pp. 46-57;
E. McNeil, ed., The Nature of Human Conflict (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1965);
Jessie Bernard, American Community Behavior (New York: Dryden Press, 1949), ‘““Where
is the Modern Sociology of Conflict?” American Journal of Sociology 56 (1950), pp. 111-
16, and “Parties and Issues in Conflict,” Journal of Conflict Resolution 1 (June 1957), pp.
111-21; Kenneth Boulding, Conflict and Defense: A General Theory (New York: Harper &
Row, 1962); Thomas Carver, “The Basis of Social Conflict,” American Journal of Sociology
13 (1908), pp. 628-37; James Coleman, Community Conflict (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1957);
James C. Davies, “Toward A Theory of Revolution,” American Journal of Sociology 27
(1962), pp. 5-19; Charles P. Loomis, “In Praise of Conflict and Its Resolution,” American
Sociological Review 32 (December 1967), pp. 875-90; Raymond Mack and Richard C. Snyder,
“The Analysis of Social Conflict,” Journal of Conflict Resolution 1 (June 1957), pp. 388-
97; John S. Patterson, Conflict in Nature and Life (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts,
1883); Anatol Rapoport, Fights, Games and Debates (Ann Arbor, Mich.: University of Mich-
igan Press, 1960); Thomas C. Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
Univ. Press, 1960); Pitirim Sorokin, ‘“Solidary, Antagonistic, and Mixed Systems of Inter-
action,” in Society, Culture, and Personality (New York: Harper & Row, 1947); Nicholas
S. Timasheff, War and Revolution (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1965); Robin M. Williams,
Jr., The Reduction of Intergroup Tensions (New York: Social Science Research Council,
1947); and Clinton F. Fink, “Some Conceptual Difficulties in the Theory of Social Conflict,”
Journal of Conflict Resolution 12 (December 1968), pp. 429-31.
132 CHAPTER 6 / THE ORIGINS OF CONFLICT AND CRITICAL THEORIZING
*Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology (New York: International Pub-
lishers, 1947; originally written in 1846).
*Karl Marx, Capital: A Critical Analysis of Capitalist Production, vol. 1 (New York:
International Publishers, 1967; originally published in 1867).
"Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto (New York: International
Publishers, 1971; originally published in 1848).
*Marx and Engels, The German Ideology.
KARL MARX (1818-1883) AND THE ORIGINS OF CONFLICT AND CRITICAL THEORY 133
*Tbid., p. 15.
10Indeed, Marx was as much an evolutionist as any functionalist, and in fact, there is
much functional reasoning in his arguments. For illustrations, see Arthur L. Stinchcombe.
Constructing Social Theories (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1968).
134 CHAPTER 6 / THE ORIGINS OF CONFLICT AND CRITICAL THEORIZING
“For criticism of my efforts along these lines, see Richard P. Abbelbaum, “Marx’s Theory
of the Falling Rate of Profit: Towards a Dialectical Analysis of Structural Socia) Change,”
American Sociological Review 43 (February 1978), pp. 64-73.
136 CHAPTER 6 / THE ORIGINS OF CONFLICT AND CRITICAL THEORIZING
NN EE
reside with the more positivistic approach in Marx’s work, but there are
many who would disagree. Indeed, I would guess that most contemporary
Marxists disavow positivism and the search for universal and timeless
laws of human organization. And they certainly do not condone my and
others’ efforts to translate Marx’s ideas into the language of positivism
(as I did in Table 6-1). Such is clearly the case, as I will document in
Chapter 9, for most critical theorists, but it is also true for the vast
majority of Marxist sociologists. But in terms of actual theory develop-
ment, I think that the more positivistic efforts to translate Marx’s ideas
have been more dominant than the work of Marxists and critical theorists.
And even the most prominent critical theorist, Jurgen Habermas, who is
the topic of Chapter 9, has increasingly sought to make such theory more
objective. All this will become more evident, I think, as we proceed into
the next chapters. But for the present, let me return to examining the
origins of contemporary conflict theory.
The structure may be sui generis, its motivation and form being wholly
self-consistent, and only in order to be able to describe and understand it,
do we put it together, post factum, out of two tendencies, one monistic, the
other antagonistic.”
'2A]l subsequent references to this work are taken from Georg Simmel. Conflict and the
Web of Group Affiliation, trans. K. H. Wolff (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1956).
'3]bid., p. 23. However, with his typical caution, Simmel warns: “This fact should not
lead us to overlook the numerous cases in which contradictory tendencies really co-exist in
separation and can thus be recognized at any moment in the over-all situation” (pp. 23-
24).
GEORG SIMMEL AND CONFLICT THEORIZING 139
Part of the reason for this emphasis, I think, lies in Simmel’s “or-
ganismic”’ view of the social world. In displaying formal properties, social
processes evidence a systemic character—a notion apparently derived from
the organismic doctrines dominating the sociology of his time. This subtle
organicism led Simniel to seek out the consequences of conflict for social
continuity rather than change:
Conflict is thus designed to resolve dualisms; it is a way of achieving some
kind of unity, even if it be through the annihilation of one of the conflicting
parties. This is roughly parallel to the fact that it is the most violent symptom
of a disease which represents the effort of the organism to free itself of
disturbances and damages caused by them. [Italics added. ]'*
‘Ibid, p. 13.
140 CHAPTER 6 / THE ORIGINS OF CONFLICT AND CRITICAL THEORIZING
Simmel was not concerned with developing scientific theory, but rather, he was inter-
ested in inducting social forms from interaction processes. This emphasis on forms makes
many of Simmel’s analytical statements rather easily converted into propositions. I should
emphasize, however, that transforming Simmel’s analytical statements into propositions
involves some risk of misinterpretation.
Simmel, Conflict, p. 58.
“For an excellent summary of this debate, see C. F. Fink, “Some Conceptual Difficulties
in the Theory of Social Conflict.” See also iny closing remarks in Chapter 8.
‘Pierre van de Berghe has argued that a dialectical model of conflict is ultimately one
where unification, albeit temporary, emerges out of conflict. But, as I will examine extensively
in the next chapter, the differences between Marx and Simmel have inspired vastly different
theoretical perspectives in contemporary sociology. See Pierre van de Berghe, “Dialectic
and Functionalism: Toward a Theoretical Synthesis,” American Sociological Review 28
(October 1963), pp. 695-705.
GEORG SIMMEL AND CONFLICT THEORIZING 141
RE RTT TLE ERG LPL SPODELI gE LEG IED LED ELPAI BOTE Be PE EO IA AUG AEE EEE BITE SET i Tf IB ERT
Admittedly, Marx’s late awareness of the union movement in the United States forced
him to begin pondering this possibility, but he did not incorporate this insight into his
theoretical scheme.
142 CHAPTER 6 / THE ORIGINS OF CONFLICT AND CRITICAL THEORIZING
|. The more violent are intergroup hostilities and the more frequent is conflict
among groups, the less likely are group boundaries to disappear.
ll. The more violent is the conflict and the less integrated is the group, the more
likely is despotic centralization of conflict grouos.
lil. The more violent is the conflict, the greater will be the internal solidarity of
conflict groups.
A. The more violent is the conflict and the smaller are the conflict groups, the
greater will be their internal solidarity.
1. The more violent is the conflict and the smaller are the conflict groups,
the less will be the tolerance of deviance and dissent in each group.
B. The more violent is the conflict and the more a group represents a minority
position in a system, the greater will be the internal solidarity of that group.
C. The more violent is the conflict and the more a group is engaged in purely
self-defense, the greater will be its internal solidarity.
occurs. Simmel first analyzed how violent conflicts increase solidarity and
internal organization of the conflict parties, but when he shifted to an
analysis of the functions of conflict for the social whole, he drew attention
primarily to the fact that conflict promotes system integration and ad-
aptation. I think it reasonable to ask, however: how can violent conflicts
promoting increasing organization and solidarity of the conflict groups
suddenly have these positive functions for the systemic whole in which
the conflict occurs? For Marx, such a process is seen to lead to polarization
of conflict groups and then to the violent conflicts, which radically alter
the systemic whole. But for Simmel, the increased level of organization
within conflict groups enables them to realize many of their goals without
overt violence (but perhaps with a covert threat of violence), and such
partial realization of clearly defined goals cuts down internal system ten-
sion and hence promotes integration. Let me document Simmel’s rea-
soning with his propositions.
In Table 6-3, I have listed Simmel’s propositions on the functions of
violent conflict for the parties to the conflict. In these propositions, violent
conflict is seen, under certain conditions, to increase the degree of cen-
tralization and the level of internal solidarity of groups. Unlike Marx,
however, Simmel’s does not assume that conflict begets increasingly vi-
olent conflicts between ever more organized and polarized segments that,
in the end, will cause radical change in the system. This difference between
their analyses is most clear when Simmel’s propositions on the conse-
quences of conflict for the systemic whole are reviewed. The most notable
feature of several key propositions, which I have listed in Table 6-4, is
that Simmel was initially concerned with less violent conflicts and with
their integrative functions for the social whole, and only then, did he turn
GEORG SIMMEL AND CONFLICT THEORIZING 143
propositions allow for inquiry into the conditions under which initially
violent conflicts can become less intense and thereby have integrative
consequences for the social whole. This insight dictates a search for the
conditions under which the level of conflict violence and its consequences
for system parts and the social whole can shift and change over the course
of the conflict process. I see this expansion of options as representing a |
much broader and firmer foundation for building a theory of conflict. -
Finally, Propositions II and III in Table 6-4 note the functions of
violent conflict for integrating systemic wholes. These propositions could
represent a somewhat different way to state Marx’s polarization hypoth-
esis, since conflict was seen by Simmel as drawing together diverse ele-
ments in a system as their respective interests become more clearly rec-
ognized. But Simmel was not ideologically committed to dialectical
assumptions. Thus, unlike Marx, he appeared to be arguing only that
violent conflicts pose threats to many system units that, depending upon
calculations of their diverse interests, will unite to form larger social wholes.
Such unification will persist as long as the threat of violent conflict re-
mains. Should violent conflict no longer be seen as necessary, with in-
creasing articulation of interests and the initiation of bargaining relations,
then Simmel’s Propositions 1-A and 1-B on the consequences of conflict
for the social whole would become operative.
Simmel’s abstract propositions on conflict processes represent, I feel,
an important qualification of Marx’s reasoning. While various conflict
theorists have focused on either Marx or Simmel as their principle re-
source, there has been sufficient cross-fertilization to knock off the ex-
tremes in their respective analyses—for Marx, the overemphasis on or-
ganization and polarization and for Simmel, the unmitigated functionalism
and analysis of positive consequences.
*Georg Simmel, The Philosophy of Money (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978;
originally published in 190%
146 CHAPTER 6 / THE ORIGINS OF CONFLICT AND CRITICAL THEORIZING
human nature and its capacity for conscious reflection; and as I will
document in Chapter 9, they moved away from Marx who had ‘‘turned
Hegel on his head” and put “Hegel back on his feet.”
Thus, Weber becomes a critical link in the reinterpretation of Marx
in this century by critical theorists. But Weber also presents, I feel, an
important corrective to Marx’s more formal theory of revolutionary con-
flict. Weber’s analysis of stratification and social change presents some
important propositions that consistently reappear in the more positivistic
conflict theoretic literature. And so to understand the development of
either critical theory or positivistically oriented conflict theory, we need
to examine some of the works of Max Weber.
MAX WEBER’S
“For a fuller discussion, see my and Leonard Beeghley’s The Emergence of Sociological
Theory (Homewood, IIl.: Dorsey Press, 1981), pp. 232-45 and 256-59. For original sources,
see Max Weber, Economy and Society (New York: Bedminister Press, 1968).
MAX WEBER'S (1864-1920) THEORY OF CONFLICT 147
then those who are excluded from power, wealth, and prestige become
resentful and receptive to conflict alternatives.
Another condition is dramatic discontinuity in the distribution of
rewards, or the existence of divisions in social hierarchies that give priv-
ilege to some and very little to others. When only a few hold power, wealth,
and prestige and the rest are denied these rewards, then tensions and
resentments exist. Such resentments become a further inducement for
those without power, prestige, and wealth to engage in conflict with those
who hoard these resources.
A final condition encouraging conflict is low rates of social mobility.
When those of low rank have little chance to move up social hierarchies
or to enter a new class, party, or status group, then resentment accu-
mulates. Those denied opportunities to increase their access to resources
become restive and willing to challenge the system of traditional authority.
The critical force that galvanizes the resentments inhering in these
three conditions is charisma. Weber felt that whether or not charismatic
leaders emerge is, to a great extent, a matter of historical chance. But if
such leaders do emerge to challenge traditional authority and to mobilize
resentments over the hoarding of resources by elites and the lack of op-
portunities to gain access to wealth, power, or prestige, then structural
change would ensue.
When successful, such leaders confront organizational problems of
consolidating their gains. One result is that charisma becomes routinized,
as leaders create formal rules, procedures, and structures for organizing
followers after their successful mobilization to pursue conflict. If routin-
ization takes a traditional form, thus creating a new system of traditional
authority, renewed conflict can be expected as membership in class, status,
and party becomes highly correlated; as the new elites hoard resources;
and as mobility is blocked. However, if rational-legal routinization occurs,
then authority is based upon equally applied laws and rules; and perfor-
mance and ability become the basis for recruitment and promotion in
bureaucratic structures. Under these conditions, conflict potential will be
mitigated.
I have, of course, ripped Weber’s discussion out of its historical con-
text, but this is just what contemporary conflict theorists do when using
Weber’s work to develop principles about social conflict. In Table 6-5, I
have abstracted even further these ideas and presented them as a series
of propositions. When stated in this way, | think their similarity and
differences with those by Marx become more evident. For me, the unique
feature of Weber’s Proposition I is the recognition that inequality exists
along several dimensions and that the level of correlation among incum-
bents along these dimensions is critical. Moreover, the degree of discon-
tinuity in the distribution of resources and the rates of social mobility
are also crucial.
THEORIZING
148 CHAPTER 6 / THE ORIGINS OF CONFLICT AND CRITICAL
l authority, the
|. The greater is the degree of withdrawal of legitimacy from politica
more likely is conflict between superordinates and subordinates.
group, and
A. The greater is the correlation of membership in class, status
party (or alternatively, access to power, wealth, and prestige), the more
(or
intense is the level of resentment among those denied membership
access), and hence, the more likely are they to withdra w legitima cy.
B. The greater is the discontinuity in social hierarchies, the more intense is the
level of resentment among those low in the hierarchies, and hence, the more
likely are they to withdraw legitimacy.
C. The lower are the rates of mobility up social hierarchies of power, prestige,
and wealth, the more intense is the level of resentment among those denied
opportunities, and hence, the more likely are they to withdraw legitimacy.
_ The more charismatic leaders can emerge to mobilize resentments of
subordinates in a system, the greater will be the level of conflict between
superordinates and subordinates.
A. The more conditions I-A, |-B, and I-C are met, the more likely is the
emergence of charismatic leadership.
The more effective are charismatic leaders in mobilizing subordinates in
successful conflict, the greater are the pressures to routinize authority through
the creation of a system of rules and administrative authority.
IV. The more a system of rules and administrative authority increases conditions
|-A, |-B, and I-C, the greater will be the withdrawal of legitimacy from political
authority, and the more likely is conflict between superordinates and
subordinates.
conflict. Marx, on the other hand, makes similar points but with much
more optimism about leaders’ capacity to further the evolutionary prog-
ress of societies toward his utopian end state, communism.
22F'or example, there is the structuralist Marxism of Louis Althusser and Maurice Godelier
(who will not be examined in this book), the exchange theory of Peter Blau (whose blending
of conflict ideas into exchange theories is examined in Chapter 12), the conflict exchange
approach of Randall Collins (the subject of Chapter 21), and the structuration theory of
Anthony Giddens (who is examined in Chapter 22).
CHAPTER 7
‘e ,
\
In the late 1950s, Ralf Dahrendorf persistently argued that the Parsonian
scheme and functionalism in general presents an overly consensual, in-
tegrated, and static vision of society. In Dahrendorf’s view, society has
two faces—one of consensus, the other of conflict. And it is time to begin
analysis of society’s ugly face and abandon the utopian image created by
functionalism. To leave utopia, Dahrendorf offered the following advice:
Concentrate in the future not only on concrete problems but on such
problems as involve explanations in terms of constraint, conflict, and change.
This second face of society may aesthetically be rather less pleasing than the
social system—but, if all sociology had to offer were an easy escape to Utopian
tranquility, it would hardly be worth our efforts.’
151
RALF DAHRENDORF
152 CHAPTER 7 / THE DIALECTICAL CONFLICT THEORY OF
, I feel, still
theoretical calling is a dialectical-conflict perspective, which
Marx and,
represents one of the best efforts to incorporate the insights of
propositions.
to a lesser extent, Weber into a coherent set of theoretical
rphic
I have my doubts that this dialectical conflict theory is more isomo
than functional with what occurs in the actual world, but I do think that
it represents an important corrective to Parsonian functionalism, which
tended to overemphasize social integration.
In his analysis, Dahrendorf is careful to note that processes other
than conflict are evident in social systems and that even the conflict
phenomena he examines are not the only kinds of conflict in societies.
Having said this, however, my sense is that Dahrendorf believes his con-
flict model represents a more comprehensive theory of society that pro-
vides a more adequate base for theorizing about human social organization
than either functionalism or other alternatives.
For Marx, the source of conflict ultimately lies beneath cultural values
and institutional arrangements, which represent edifices constructed by
those with power. In reality, the dynamics of a society are found in its
substructure, where the differential distribution of property and power
inevitably initiates a sequence of events leading to revolutionary class
conflict. While borrowing much of Marx’s rhetoric about power and coer-
cion in social systems, Dahrendorf actually ends up positing a much dif-
ferent source of conflict: the institutionalized authority relations of ICAs.
Such a position is. much different from that of Marx, who viewed such
authority relations as simply a superstructure erected by the dominant
classes, which, in the long run, would be destroyed by the conflict dy-
namics occurring below institutional arrangements. While Dahrendorf
acknowledges that authority relations are imposed by the dominant groups
in ICAs and frequently makes reference to “factual substrates,” the source
of conflict becomes, upon close examination, the legitimated authority
role relations of ICAs. I think that this drift away from Marx’s emphasis
on the institutional substructure forces Dahrendorf to seek the source of
conflict in those very relations that integrate, albeit temporarily, an ICA.
By itself, I see this shift in emphasis as desirable, since Dahrendorf clearly
recognizes that not all power is a reflection of property ownership—a fact
Marx’s polemics tended to underemphasize. But as I will later observe,
viewing power only in terms of authority can lead to analytical problems
as severe as those in Marx’s model and, in fact, somewhat reminiscent
of those in Parsons’ “social systems.”’
Although emphasizing different sources of conflict; Dahrendorf’s and
Marx’s models reveal similar causal chains of events leading to conflict
and the reorganization of social structure. Relations of domination and
subjugation create an “objective” opposition of interests; awareness or
consciousness by the subjugated of this inherent opposition of interests
occurs under certain specifiable conditions; under other conditions, this
newfound awareness leads to the political organization and then polari-
zation of subjugated groups, who then join in conflict with the dominant
group; the outcome of the conflict will usher in a new pattern of social
organization; this new pattern of social organization will have within it
relations of domination and subjugation that set off another sequence of
events leading to conflict and then change in patterns of social organization.
The intervening conditions affecting these processes are outlined by
both Marx and Dahrendorf only with respect to the formation of aware-
ness of opposed interests by the subjugated, the politicization and polar-
ization of the subjugated into a conflict group, and the outcome of the
conflict. The intervening conditions under which institutionalized pat-
terns generate dominant and subjugated groups and the conditions under
which these can be typified as having opposed interests remain , unspec-
ified—apparently because they are in the nature of institutionalization,
or ICAs, and do not have to be explained.
CRITICISMS OF THE DIALECTICAL CONFLICT MODEL 155
In Figure 7-1, I have outlined the causal imagery of Marx and Dah-
rendorf. At the top of the figure are Marx’s analytical categories, stated
in their most abstract form. The other two rows specify the empirical
categories of Marx and Dahrendorf, respectively. Separate analytical cat-
egories for the Dahrendorf model are not enumerated because they are
the same as those in the Marxian model. As I think is clear, the empirical
categories of the Dahrendorf scheme differ greatly from those of Marx.
But the form of analysis is much the same, since each considers as non-
problematic and not in need of causal analysis the empirical conditions
of social organization, the transformation of this organization into rela-
tions of domination and subjugation, and the creation of opposed inter-
ests. The causal analysis for both begins with an elaboration of the con-
ditions leading to growing class consciousness (Marx) or awareness among
quasi groups (Dahrendorf) of their objective interests; then analysis shifts
to the creation of a politicized class ‘for itself’ (Marx) or a true ‘“‘conflict
group” (Dahrendorf); and finally, emphasis focuses on the emergence of
conflict between polarized and politicized classes (Marx) or conflict groups
(Dahrendorf).
4J@MOd
Sesse|d OM} SassE|o
JamMod wilwO? Oju!
Ajald0s JO ~— pue
Ayadoid jo JQ@U}O JBAO saobajeo
pue
Ayadoud uoljeziuejod jndbos jo ppinee~ pue = ti
UOIINQUISIP SASSPIO 4BAO |B190S bees jeduidwe
UOIINQSIPaY ssejo
payeBniqns umd ati SaSSe|d pe patjedoid [2190S 10
CIYSIOUMO ueIXIeEW
lOAeu JO UONEZIDIVOg | ee jO uoijisoddo jO uoleUuIWOGg
suoijejndod paywoniqns uonebniqns sau0bale2
oneziueb DIyuood | aye6niqns pue 1p Aa Sneiag
la wes ee aa ee JO uoljisoddo yO oe
uoly!isoddo - ue uoijeziuebi0
eet ,
jeoijAjeue
|B190S }USIOIA }UBUIWOP O}jU! aarjoalqo jo Sanioalqo uoneulwop |BI90S URIXJEW
UOIeZURI|Od SS@USNOIDSUOD JO SUON}E|9Y
Asabewy jesneo jeonoejeiq euL $-Z SYNDIA
SS SS SE IT ST a I IAS ABLE EES AE ER BS a mms
CRITICISMS OF THE DIALECTICAL CONFLICT MODEL 157
(1) conflict not only causes change of social structure but changes of struc-
ture also cause conflict (under conditions that need to be specified in
greater detail than Simmel’s initial analysis); and (2) conflict can inhibit
change (again, under conditions that need to be specified).’ Unless these
conditions are part of the causal imagery, conflict theory merely states
the rather obvious fact that change occurs, without answering the the-
oretical questions of why, when, and where such change occurs.
Despite the vagueness of Dahrendorf’s causal analysis, I see the great
strength of his approach residing in the formulation of explicit proposi-
tions. These state the intervening empirical conditions that cause quasi
groups to become conflict groups, as well as the conditions affecting the
intensity (involvement of group members) and violence (degree of regu-
lation) of the conflict and the degree and the rate of structural change
caused by it. More formally, Dahrendorf outlines three types of inter-
vening empirical conditions: (1) conditions of organization that affect the
transformation of latent quasi groups into manifest conflict groups; (2)
conditions of conflict that determine the form and intensity of conflict;
and (3) conditions of structural change that influence the kind, speed,
and the depth of the changes in social structure.®
Thus, the variables in the theoretical scheme are the (1) degree of
conflict-group formation; (2) the degree of intensity of the conflict; (3)
the degree of violence of the conflict; (4) the degree of change of social
structure; and (5) the rate of such change. I think it significant, for crit-
icisms to be delineated later, that concepts such as ICAs, legitimacy,
authority, coercion, domination, and subjugation are not explicitly char-
acterized as variables requiring statements on the conditions affecting
their variability. Rather, these concepts are simply defined and interre-
lated to each other in terms of definitional overlap or stated as assump-
tions about the nature of social reality.
For those phenomena that are conceptualized as variables, Dahren-
dorf’s propositions appear to be an elaboration of those developed by
Marx. I have reworked them a bit and placed them in Table 7-1.°
Like Marx, Dahrendorf sees conflict as related to subordinates’ grow-
ing awareness of their interests and formation into conflict groups (Prop-
osition I). Such awareness and group formation is a positive function of
the degree to which (a) the technical conditions (leadership and unifying
ideology), (b) the political conditions (capacity to organize), and (c) the
For a convenient summary of these, see-Percy Cohen, Modern Sociological Theory (New
York: Basic Books, 1968), pp. 183-91.
®Dahrendorf, “Toward a Theory of Social Conflict.”
*The propositions listed in the table differ from a list provided by Dahrendorf, Class
and Class Conflict, pp. 239-40 in tw - respects: (1) they are phrased consistently as statements
of covariance, and (2) they are phrased somewhat more abstractly without reference to
“class,” which in this particular work was Dahrendorf’s primary concern.
CRITICISMS OF THE DIALECTICAL CONFLICT MODEL 159
|. The more members of quasi groups in ICAs can become aware of their
objective interests and form a conflict group, the more likely is conflict to occur.
A. The more the ‘technical’ conditions of organization can be met, the more
likely is the formation of a conflict group.
1. The more a leadership cadre among quasi groups can be developed, the
more likely are the technical conditions of organization to be met.
2. The more a codified idea system, or charter, can be developed, the more
likely are the technical conditions of organization to be met.
3. The more the ‘‘political’’ conditions of organization can be met, the more
likely is the formation of a conflict group.
1. The more the dominant groups permit organization of opposed interests,
the more likely are the political conditions of organization to be met.
C. The more the ‘‘social’’ conditions of organization can be met, the more likely
is the formation of a conflict group.
1. The more opportunity for members of quasi groups to communicate, the
more likely are the social conditions of organization to be met.
2. The more recruiting is permitted by structural arrangements (such as
propinquity), the more likely are the social conditions to be met.
ll. The less the technical, political, and social conditions of organization are met,
the more intense is the conflict.
lll. The more the distribution of authority and other rewards are associated with
each other (superimposed), the more intense is the conflict.
IV. The less the mobility between super- and subordinate groups, the more intense
is the conflict.
V. The less the technical, political, and social conditions of organization are met,
the more violent is the conflict.
VI. The more the deprivations of the subjugated in the distribution of rewards shifts
from an absolute to relative basis, the more violent is the conflict.
Vil. The less the ability of conflict groups to develop regulatory agreements, the
more violent is the conflict.
VII. The more intense the conflict, the more structural change and reorganization it
will generate.
IX. The more violent the conflict, the greater is the rate of structural change and
reorganization.
Tbid., p. 169.
CRITICISMS OF THE DIALECTICAL CONFLICT MODEL 161
and the rate of social change. In fact, it is likely that these unstated
variable properties of authority, domination, and interests have as much
influence on the scheme’s explicit variables as the “intervening empirical
conditions” that Dahrendorf chooses to emphasize. Furthermore, as I
noted earlier, when viewed as variables, the concepts of authority, dom-
-ination-subjugation, and interests require their own intervening empirical
conditions. These conditions may in turn influence other subsequently
intervening conditions in much the same way as the “conditions of or-
ganization” also influence the subsequent intensity and violence of con-
flict in the scheme.
My criticisms suggest an obvious solution: to conceptualize ICAs,
legitimacy, authority, domination-subjugation, and interests as variable
phenomena and to attempt a statement of the intervening empirical con-
ditions influencing their variability. Expanding the propositional inven-
tory in this way would, I feel, reduce the vagueness of the causal imagery
in the present scheme. Such an alteration would also cut down on the
rather protracted set of dialectical assumptions—which are of dubious
isomorphism in reality—and address a theoretical (rather than philo-
sophical) question: under what conditions do ICAs create legitimated
authority relations that generate clear relations of domination and sub-
jugation leading to strongly opposed interests?
Methodological Problems
To his credit, Dahrendorf provides formal definitions of major concepts
and suggests operational clues about their application in concrete empir-
ical settings, as is evident in his analysis of class conflict in industrial
societies.!! Furthermore, the incorporation of at least some concepts into
an explicit propositional inventory—albeit an incomplete one—makes the
scheme appear more testable and amendable to refutation.
A number of methodological problems remain, however. One of these
concerns the extremely general definitions given to concepts. Although
these definitions are stated formally, they are often so general that they
can be used in an ad hoc and ex post facto fashion to apply to such a
wide variety of phenomena that their current utility for the development
and testing of theory can be questioned. For example, I think that the
concepts of power, legitimacy, authority, interests, domination, and even
conflict are defined so broadly that instances of these concepts can be
found in almost any empirical situation. Thus, Dahrendorf can rather
easily confirm his assumption that social life is rife with conflict. But
how is one to measure these vaguely and globally defined concepts? I
noted this problem earlier when discussing Dahrendorf’s reluctance to
both Parsons and Dahrendorf view the social world in terms of institu-
tionalized patterns—for Parsons, the “social systems,” for Dahrendorf,
“imperatively coordinated associations.” Both view societies as com-
posed of subsystems involving the organization of roles in terms of le-
gitimate normative prescriptions. For Dahrendorf, these legitimated nor-
mative patterns reflect power differentials in a system; and, despite his
rhetoric about the coercive nature of these relations, I see this vision of
power as remarkably similar to Parsons’s conception of power as the
legitimate right of some status-roles to regulate the expectations attendant
upon other statuses.'4 Furthermore, in Dahrendorf’s model, deviation from
the norms established by status-roles will lead dominant groups to attempt
to employ negative sanctions—a position that is very close to Parsons’s
view that power exists to correct for deviations within a system.
The apparent difference between Dahrendorf’s and Parsons’s em-
phasis with respect to the functions of power in social systems (or ICAs)
is that Dahrendorf argues explicitly that power differentials cause both
integration (through legitimated authority relations) and disintegration
(through the persistence of opposed interests). However, to state that
conflict emerges out of legitimated authority is nothing more than to state,
a priori, that opposed interests exist and cause conflict. The emergence
of conflict follows from vague assumptions about such processes as the
“inner dialectic of power and authority” and the “historical function of
authority,’® rather than from carefully documented causal sequences.
Thus, I think that the genesis of conflict in Dahrendorf’s model remains
as unexplained as it does in his portrayal of the inadequacies of the func-
tional utopia, primarily because its emergence is set against a background
of unexplained conceptions of system norms and legitimated authority.
Dahrendorf’s problem in explaining why and how conflict groups can
emerge from a legitimated authority structure is partly a reflection of
hidden assumptions about functional requisites. In a subtle and yet con-
sistent fashion, he assumes that authority is a functional requisite for
system integration and that the conflict that somehow emerges from au-
thority relations is a functional requisite for social change. As Dahrendorf
argues, “the historical function of authority” is to generate conflict and
thereby maintain the vitality of social systems. From this notion of the
requisite for change, it is all too easy to assert that conflict exists to meet
the system’s needs for change—an illegitimate teleology that echoes Marx’s
18]bid.; Pierre L. van den Berghe, “Dialectic and Functionalism: Toward a Theoretical
Synthesis,” American Sociological Review 28 (October 1963), pp. 695-705.
“For example, see Talcott Parsons and Edward Shils, eds., Toward a General Theory
of Action (New York. Harper & Row, 1962), pp. 197-205.
*Tbid., p. 230.
Weingart, “Beyond Parsons,” p. 161.
164 CHAPTER 7 / THE DIALECTICAL CONFLICT THEORY OF RALF DAHRENDORF
1Lewis A. Coser, The Functions of Social Conflict (London: Free Press of Glencoe, 1956).
*Ibid., pp. 22-23.
165
166 CHAPTER 8 / THE CONFLICT FUNCTIONALISM OF LEWIS A. COSER
over a decade, since after the 10th anniversary of his first polemic Coser
was moved to reassert his earlier claim that it was “high time to tilt the
scale in the direction of greater attention to social conflict.’*® Yet, while
Coser has consistently maintained that functional theorizing “has too
often neglected the dimensions of power and interest,” he does not follow
either Marx’s or Dahrendorf’s emphasis on the disruptive consequences
of violent conflict.4 On the contrary, Coser seeks to correct Dahrendorf’s
analytical excesses by emphasizing the integrative and “adaptability”
functions of conflict for social systems. Thus, Coser justifies his efforts
by criticizing functionalism for ignoring conflict and conflict theory for
underemphasizing the functions of conflict.®
SLewis A. Coser, “Some Social Functions of Violence,” Annuals of the American Academy
of Political and Social Science 364 (March 1966), p. 10.
‘Lewis A. Coser, Continuities in the Study of Social Conflict (New York: Free Press,
1967), p. 141.
5A listing of some of Coser’s prominent works, to be utilized in subsequent analysis,
reveals the functional flavor of his conflict perspective: Functions of Social Conflict; “Some
Social Functions of Violence”; “Some Functions of Deviant Behavior and Normative Flex-
ibility,” American Journal of Sociology 68 (September 1962), pp. 172-81; and “The Func-
tions of Dissent,” in The Dynamics of Dissent (New York: Grune & Stratton, 1968), pp.
158-70. Other prominent works with less revealing titles but critical substance include:
“Social Conflict and the Theory of Social Change,” British Journal of Sociology 8 (Sep-
tember 1957), pp. 197-207; “Violence and the Social Structure,” in Science and Psychoa-
nalysis, ed. J. Masserman, vol. 7 (New York: Grune & Stratton, 1963), pp. 30-42. These
and other essays are collected in Coser’s Continuities in the Study of Social Conflict. One
should also consult his Masters of Sociological Thought (New York: Harcourt Brace Jov-
anovich, 1977).
*Lewis Coser, “Durkheim’s Conservatism and Its Implications for His Sociological The-
ory, ’ in Emile Durkheim, 1858-1917: A Collection of Essays, ed. K. H. Wolff (Columbus:
Ohio State University Press, 1960); also reprinted in Coser’s Continuities, pp. 153-80.
"Coser, “Some Functions of Violence,” pp. 12-13.
IMAGES OF SOCIAL ORGANIZATION 167
eee
Nee
in his analysis of the “functions of dissent,”’ Coser rejects the notion that
dissent is explainable in terms of individual sickness and embraces the
assumption that “dissent may more readily be explained as a reaction to
what is perceived as a sickness in the body social.’’® I do not think that
this form of analogizing fatally wounds Coser’s analysis, but it does reveal
that he has not rejected organicism. Apparently, Coser has felt compelled
to criticize Durkheim’s organicism because it did not allow the analysis
of conflict as a process that could promote the further adaptation and
integration of the body social.®
In rejecting the analytical constraints of Durkheim’s analogizing, Coser
embraces Georg Simmel’s organicism (see Chapter 6). Conflict is viewed
as a process that, under certain conditions, functions to maintain the
body social or some of its vital parts. From this vantage point, Coser
develops an image of society that stresses:
1. The social world can be viewed as a system of variously interrelated
parts.
2. All social systems reveal imbalances, tensions, and conflicts of in-
terests among variously interrelated parts.
3. Processes within and between the system’s constituent parts op-
erate under different conditions to maintain, change, and increase
or decrease a system’s integration and adaptability.
4. Many processes, such as violence, dissent, deviance, and conflict,
which are typically viewed as disruptive to the system, can also be
viewed, under specifiable conditions, as strengthening the system’s
basis of integration as well as its adaptability to the environment.
From these assumptions, Coser articulates a rather extensive set of
propositions about the functions (and to a limited extent, the dysfunc-
tions) of conflict for social systems. Coser offers some propositions about
the conditions under which conflict leads to disruption and malintegration
of social systems, but I see the main thrust of his analysis as revolving
around statements on how conflict maintains or reestablishes system in-
tegration and adaptability to changing conditions. In so doing, I see Cos-
er’s analysis as emphasizing: (1) imbalances in the integration of system
parts lead to (2) the outbreak of varying types of conflict among these
parts, which, in turn, causes (3) temporary reintegration. of the system,
which causes (4) increased flexibility in the system’s structure, increased
capability to resolve future imbalances through conflict, and increased
capacity to adapt to changing conditions.
‘It is somewhat tragic for theory building in sociology that the early promising lead of
Robin M. Williams, Jr., in his The Reduction of Intergroup Tensions: A Survey of Research
on Problems of Ethnic, Social, and Religious Group Relations (New York: Social Science
Research Council, 1947) was not consistently followed. Most of the propositions developed
by Dahrendorf and Coser were summarized in this volume 10 years prior to their major
works. More important, they are phrased more neutrally, without an attempt to reveal
society’s “ugly face” or correct for inattention to the “functions of conflict.”
PROPOSITIONS ON CONFLICT PROCESSES 169
“Again, it should be emphasized that it is dangerous and difficult to pull from diverse
sources discrete propositions and attempt to relate them systematically without doing some
injustice to the theorist’s intent. However, unless this kind of exercise is performed, the
propositions will contribute little to the development of sociological theory. The propositions
in Table 8-1 were extracted from: Functions of Social Conflict, pp..8-385, “Social Conflict
and the Theory of Social Change,” pp. 197-207; “Internal Violence as a Mechanism for
Conflict Resolution”; and “Violence and Social Structure.”
170 CHAPTER 8 / THE CONFLICT FUNCTIONALISM OF LEWIS A. COSER
I. The more groups engage in conflict over realistic issues (obtainable goals), the
more likely are they to seek compromises over the means to realize their
interests, and hence, the less violent is the conflict.
Il. The more groups engage in conflict over nonrealistic issues, the greater is the
level of emotional arousal and involvement in the conflict, and hence, the more
violent is the conflict.
A. The more conflict occurs over core values, the more likely is it to be over
nonrealistic issues.
B. The more a realistic conflict endures, the more likely is it to become
increasingly nonrealistic.
lll. The less functionally interdependent are relations among social units in a
system, the less is the availability of institutional means for absorbing conflicts
and tensions, and hence, the more violent is the conflict.
A. The greater are the power differentials between super- and subordinates in a
system, the less functionally interdependent are relations.
B. The greater is the level of isolation of subpopulations in a system, the less
functionally interdependent are relations.
the opposite fact: to specify the conditions under which conflict will be
more violent. Yet, the inverse of Coser’s first proposition can indicate a
condition under which conflict will be violent. The key concept in this
proposition is “realistic issues.”” For Coser, realistic conflict involves the
pursuit of specific aims against real sources of hostility, with some esti-
mation of the costs to be incurred in such pursuit. As I noted in Chapter
6, Simmel recognized that when clear goals are sought, compromise and
conciliation are likely alternatives to violence. Coser restates this prop-
osition but adds Proposition II on conflict over “nonrealistic issues,” such
as ultimate values, beliefs, ideology, and vaguely defined class interests.
When nonrealistic, then the conflict will be violent. Such nonrealism is
particularly likely when conflict is over core values, which emotionally
mobilize participants and make them unwilling to compromise (Propo-
sition II-A). Moreover, if conflicts endure for a long period of time, then
it becomes increasingly nonrealistic as parties become emotionally in-
volved, as ideologies become codified, and as “the enemy” is portrayed in
increasingly negative terms (Proposition II-B).
Proposition III adds a more structural variable to the analysis of
conflict violence. In systems where there are high degrees of functional
interdependence among actors—that is, where there are mutual exchanges
and cooperation—then conflict is less likely to be violent. However, if
there is great inequality in power among units (Proposition III-A) or
isolation of subpopulations (Proposition III-B), functional interdepend-
ence decreases, and hence when conflict occurs, it will tend to be non-
realistic and violent. |
172 CHAPTER 8 / THE CONFLICT FUNCTIONALISM OF LEWIS A. COSER
aaa
. The less limited are the goals of the opposing parties to a conflict, the more
prolonged is the conflict.
ll. The less is the degree of consensus over the goals of conflict, the more
prolonged is the conflict.
Ill. The less the parties in a conflict can interpret their adversary’s symbolic points
of victory and defeat, the more prolonged is the conflict.
IV. The more leaders of conflicting parties can perceive that complete attainment of
goals is possible at only very high costs, the less prolonged is the conflict.
A. The more equal is the power between conflicting groups, the more likely are
leaders to perceive the high costs of complete attainment of goals.
B. The more clear-cut are the indexes of defeat or victory in a conflict, the more
likely are leaders to perceive the high costs of complete attainment of goals.
V. The greater is the capacity of leaders of each conflict party to persuade
followers to terminate conflict, the less prolonged is the conflict.
A. The more centralized are the conflict parties, the greater is a leader’s
capacity to persuade followers.
B. The fewer are the internal cleavages within conflict parties, the greater is a
leader’s capacity to persuade followers.
These propositions are taken from Coser, Functions of Social Conflict, pp. 37-38, 45,
69-72, 92-95.
174 CHAPTER 8 / THE CONFLICT FUNCTIONALISM OF LEWIS A. COSER
el
|. The more violent or intense is the conflict, the more clear-cut are the boundaries
of each respective conflict party.
ll. The more violent or intense is the conflict and the more internally differentiated
are the conflict parties, the more likely is each conflict party to centralize its
decision-making structure.
Ill. The more violent or intense is the conflict and the more it is perceived to affect
the welfare of all segments of the conflict parties, the more conflict promotes
structural and ideological solidarity among members of each conflict party.
IV. The more violent or intense is the conflict, the more conflict leads to the
suppression of dissent and deviance within each conflict party as well as forced
conformity to norms and values.
V. The more conflict between parties leads to forced conformity, the greater is the
accumulation of hostilities, and the more likely is internal group conflict to
surface in the long run.
'*Ibid., pp. 45-48; Lewis A. Coser, “Internal Violence as Mechanisms for Conflict Res-
olution”; “Social Conflict and the Theory of Social Change,” British Journal of Sociology
8 (September 1957), pp. 197-207; “Some Social Functions of Violence,” Annals of the
American Academy of Political and Social Science 364 (March 1966), p. 10; “The Functions
of Dissent,” in The Dynamics of Dissent, ed. L. A. ‘Coser (New York: Grune & Stratton,
1968); and “Social Conflict and the Theory of Social Change.”
"See third edition of The Structure of Social Theory (Homewood, Ill: The Dorsey Press,
1982).
PROPOSITIONS ON CONFLICT PROCESSES 175
SS IAT LRA TEELEAL LEA BALD DD GRR ETE ADI LD LSE LPT PLES LILES. GELATO EY TERRES VEE
TABLE 8-5 Coser’s Propositions on the Functions of Conflict for the Social Whole
changes are more likely to have frequent conflicts that are less emotionally
involving and violent than those systems that are less complex and where
tensions accumulate. It is in the nature of interdependence, Coser argues,
for conflicts to erupt frequently, but since they emerge periodically, emo-
tions do not build to the point where violence is inevitable. Conversely,
systems where there are low degrees of functional interdependence will
often polarize into hostile camps; and when conflict does erupt, it will be
intense and violent. In Proposition II, frequent conflicts of low intensity
and violence are seen to have certain positive functions. First, they will
force those in conflict to reassess and reorganize their actions (Proposition
IIa). Second, such conflicts will release tensions and hostilities before
they build to a point where adversaries become polarized around non-
realistic issues (Proposition IIb). Third, frequent conflicts of low intensity
and violence encourage the development of normative procedures—laws,
courts, mediating agencies, and the like—to be developed in order to reg-
ulate tensions (Proposition IIc). Fourth, these kinds of conflicts also in-
crease a sense of realism over what the conflict is about. That is, frequent
conflicts where intensity and violence are kept under control allow conflict
parties to articulate their interests and goals, thereby allowing them to
bargain and compromise (Proposition IId). Fifth, conflicts promote co-
alitions among units who are threatened by the action of one party or
another. If conflicts are frequent and of low intensity and violence, such
coalitions come and go, thereby promoting flexible alliances (Proposition
Ile). However, if conflicts are infrequent and emotions accumulate, co-
alitions often polarize threatened parties into ever more hostile camps,
with the result that when conflict does occur it is violent. And Proposition
III simply asserts Coser’s functional conclusion that when conflicts are
frequent and when violence and intensity are reduced, conflict will pro-
mote flexible coordination within the system and increased capacity to
adjust and adapt to environmental circumstances. This increased flexibility
176 CHAPTER 8 / THE CONFLICT FUNCTIONALISM OF LEWIS A. COSER
‘Ibid.
REDIRECTING CONFLICT THEORY: OVERCOMING UNRESOLVED ISSUES 177
What is Conflict?
To my constant surprise, one of the most controversial issues in conflic.
theory is the definition of conflict. What is and what is not conflict? A
quick review of the conflict theory literature will produce a surprisingly
diverse array of terms denoting different aspects of conflict: hostilities,
178 CHAPTER 8 / THE CONFLICT FUNCTIONALISM OF LEWIS A. COSER
‘Ralf Dahrendorf, Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Society (Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 1957), p. 135.
Clinton F. Fink, “Some Conceptual Difficulties in the Theory of Social Conflict,”
Journal of Conflict Resolution 12 (December 1968), p. 456.
REDIRECTING CONFLICT THEORY: OVERCOMING UNRESOLVED ISSUES 179
Few would, for example, want to consider the kind of definition that
I prefer: “A conflict is direct and overt interaction between parties in
which the actions of each party are directed at inhibiting their adversary’s
attainment of its goals.” Such a definition makes conflict an overt and
direct interaction between parties, but it allows for considerable variability
in how one party inhibits the actions of the other. Such actions can be
normatively regulated or unregulated and violent. Other forms of inter-
action could be labeled with different terms; and as a result, I think that
we could avoid the lumping together of apples and oranges under the
generic rubric of conflict. At present, I see the term as so global and
encompassing that it embraces diverse forms of relationships, which, in
all probability, are highly distinctive and reveal somewhat different laws
of operation.
One of the few conflict theorists who has sought to develop a more
limited definition that also embraces diverse forms of conflict is Robin
Williams, Jr. Although he is not always this explicit, he defines conflict
in one essay as:
“Robin M. Williams, Jr., “Social Order and Social Conflict,” Proceedings of the Amer-
ican Philosophical Society 114 (June 1970), pp. 217-25. Yet, in a more thorough analysis
of the “law of social conflict,” Williams does not present this kind of explicit definition.
See “Conflict and Social Order: A Research Stratecy for Compiex Propositions,” Journal
of Social Issues 28 (1972). nn. 11-96
180 CHAPTER 8 / THE CONFLICT FUNCTIONALISM OF LEWIS A. COSER
cerned itself with how social relations vary with different types of units.
For example, Parsonian functionalism developed an elaborate conceptual
scheme around processes occurring in one type of unit—the social system—
which could be anything from a small group to a system of societies. Little
attention was devoted to indicate how social processes. varied with dif-
ferent types of social units.
As conflict theorists begin to define conflict more explicitly and to
develop theories that distinguish among phenomena denoted by such la-
bels as fights, games, war, revolution, competitions, and disputes, I think
that the units of analysis will become more relevant. For I believe that
the type of conflict will vary with the type of: unit. Or at least, certain
types of units will be found to be more likely to engage in one type of
conflict than in another. For example, a fight may be an interpersonal
conflict, whereas a revolution is a type of conflict among other types of
social units, such as social classes. Until these kinds of problems in dis-
tinguishing types of units and types of conflicts are resolved, conflict
theory will tend to remain somewhat vague. Coser’s and Dahrendorf’s
schemes illustrate this fact, for although I see them both as highly in-
sightful, they are nonetheless vague.”4
“Lest there be a misunderstanding, I should emphasize that this point is not intended
as a critique of highly abstract conflict schemes. Indeed, these tend to be far superior to
the lower-level empirical analyses, which abound in the literature. But the schemes of Coser,
unit
Dahrendorf, Williams, Gamson, Gurr, and others are now sufficiently developed that
of analysis questions can be profitably addressed.
Brace
*Arthur L. Stinchcombe, Constructing Social Theories (New York: Harcourt
Jovanovich, 1968), p. 94; Piotr Sztompka , System and Function : Toward a Theory of Society
(New York: Academic Press, 1974).
182 CHAPTER 8 / THE CONFLICT FUNCTIONALISM OF LEWIS A. COSER
ee
Inequality : Reorganization
All | of resource |Causes Sone Caan: ofsocial
socia distribution
systems aiaiets then system
1Some basic reviews and analyses of critical theory and sociology include: Paul Connerton,
ed., Critical Sociology (New Ycrk: Penguin Books, 1970); Raymond Geuss, The Idea of a
Critical Theory (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981); David Held, Jntroduction
to Critical Theory (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, 1980); Trent Schroyer,
The Critique of Domination: The Origins and Development of Critical Theory (New York:
George Braziller, Inc., 1973); Albrecht Wellmer, Critical Theory of Society (New York:
Seabury Press, 1974); Ellsworth R. Fuhrman and William E. Snizek, “Some Observations
on the Nature and Content of Critical Theory,”” Humboldt Journal of Social Relations 7
(Fall-Winter 1979- 80), pp. 33-51; Zygmunt Bauman, Towards a Critical Sociology (Boston:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1976); Robert..1. Antonio, “The Origin, Development, and Con-
temporary Status of Critical Theory,” The Sociological Quarterly 24 (Summer 1983), pp.
325-51; Jim Faught, “Objective Reason and the Justification of Norms,” California Soci-
ologist 4 (Winter 1981), pp. 33-53.
184
EARLY CRITICAL THEORY: LUKACS, HORKHEIMER, ADORNO 185
*For descriptions of this activity, see Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination (Boston:
Little, Brown, 1973) and “The Frankfurt School’s Critique of Marxist Humanism,” Social
Research 39 (1972), pp. 285-305; David Held, Introduction to Critical Theory, pp. 29-110;
Robert J. Antonio, “The Origin, Development, and Contemporary Status of Critical The-
ory,” The Sociological Quarterly 24 (Summer 1983), pp. 325-51; Phil Slater, Origin and
Significance of The Frankfurt School (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1977).
’Other prominent members included: Friedrich Pollock (economist), Erich Fromni (psy-
choanalyst, social psychologist), Franz Neumann (political scientist), Herbert Marcuse (phi-
losopher), and Leo Loenthal (sociologist). During the Nazi years, the school relocated in
America, and many of its members never returned to Germany.
‘George Lukacs, History and Class Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1968;
originally published in 1922).
5Max Horkheimer, Critical Theory: Selected Essays (New York: Herder and Herder,
1972) is a translation of essays written in German in the 1930s and 1940s; Eclipse of Reason
(New York: Oxford University Press in 1947; reprinted by Seabury Press in 1974) was the
only book by Horkheimer originally published in English. It takes a slightly 4\ferant\turn
than earlier works, but it does present ideas that emerged from his association with ‘T heodor
Adorno; and Critique of Instrumental Reason (New York: Seabury Press, 1974) Se 4 David
Held, Introduction to Critical Theory, pp. 489-91 for a more complete listing of Horkheimer’s
works in German.
*Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics (New York: Seabury Press, 1973; originally
published 1966); and with Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment (New York: Herder
and Herder, 1972; originally published in 1947). See Held, Introduction to Critical Theory,
pp. 485-87 for a more complete listing of his works.
186 CHAPTER 9 / THE CRITICAL THEORIZING OF JURGEN HABERMAS
All of these scholars are important for the purposes of this chapter
because they directly influenced the intellectual development and sub-
sequent work of Jurgen Habermas, the most prolific contemporary critical
theorist. Thus, to appreciate fully the nature of critical theory in general
and Habermas’ work in particular, I will briefly examine Lukacs’s, Hork-
heimer’s, and Adorno’s ideas and how Habermas interpreted and reacted
to them.’ Then, I will move directly into a more detailed review and
analysis of Habermas’s work as it has developed over the last decades.
1K ar] Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology (New York: International Pub-
lishers, 1947; originally written in 1846).
11Max Horkheimer, “Zum Rationalismusstreit in der gegenwartigen Philosophe,” orig-
inally published in 1935, reprinted in Kritische Theorie, vol. 1, ed. A. Schmidt (Frankfurt:
Fischer Verlag, 1968), pp. 146-7. This and volume 2, by the way, represent a compilation
of many of Horkheimer’s essays while at the Institute in Frankfurt.
12Habermas is to take up this idea, but he will extend it in several ways.
188 CHAPTER 9 / THE CRITICAL THEORIZING OF JURGEN HABERMAS
FPN a W. Adorno, et al., The Authoritarian Personality (New York: Harper & Row,
‘*Means-ends rationality is action designed to use the most efficient means to achieve
stated ends or goals. For Max Weber’s use of this concept, see Chapter 6.
“Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1, Chapter 4.
THE CRITICAL APPROACH OF JURGEN HABERMAS 189
16Indeed, the English translations of his work are difficult, but the German versions are
even worse. Translators consistently improve Habermas’s prose, but it still remains highly
obscure.
17In some ways, I find these tangents more interesting than the main argument.
1’That is, the spread of means-end rationality into ever more spheres of life.
190 CHAPTER 9 / THE CRITICAL THEORIZING OF JURGEN HABERMAS
nemann, 1970; originally published in German in 1968). The basic ideas in Zur Logik der
Sozialwissenschaften and Knowledge and Human Interest were stated in Habermas's in-
augural lecture at the University of Frankfurt in 1965 and were first published in “Knowledge
and Interest,” Jnquiry 9 (1966), pp. 285-300.
THE CRITICAL APPROACH OF JURGEN HABERMAS 193
\
;
}
J] am simplifying here. See also Jim Faught’s discussion in his “Objective Reason and
the Justification of Norms.”
21Jurgen Habermas, “Toward a Theory of Communicative Competence,” Inquiry 13
(1970), pp. 360-75.
198 CHAPTER 9 / THE CRITICAL THEORIZING OF JURGEN HABERMAS
**Habermas sometimes calls this aspect of his program “depth hermeneutics.” And the
idea is to create a methodology of inquiry for social systems that parallels the approach of
psychoanalysis—that is, dialogue, removal of barriers to understanding, analysis of under-
lying causal processes, and efforts to use this understanding to dissolve distortions in
interaction.
*For an early statement, see “Some Distinctions in Universal Pragmatics: A Working
Paper,” Theory and Society 3 (1976), pp. 155-67.
THE CRITICAL APPROACH OF JURGEN HABERMAS 199
capacity of the society to cope with the environment.* That is, complex
systems that are integrated are better adapted to their environments than
less complex systems. The key issue, then, is what conditions increase or
decrease integration? For without integration, differentiation produces
severe problems.
Habermas’s analysis of system integration is both protracted and
vague; and so, I will offer only a cursory review. He argues that contained
in the world views or stocks of knowledge of individual actors are learning
capacities and stores of information that determine the overall learning
level of a society. In turn, this learning level determines the society’s
steering capacity to respond to environmental problems. At times, Ha-
bermas refers to these learning levels as organization principles. Thus,
as systems confront problems of internal integration and external con-
tingencies, the stocks of knowledge and world views of individual actors
are translated into organization principles and steering capacities, which,
in turn, set limits on just how a system can respond. For example, a
society with only religious mythology will be less complex and less able
to respond to environmental challenges than a more complex one with
large stores of technology and stocks of normative procedures determining
its organization principles. But societies can “learn’*4 that when con-
fronted with problems beyond the capacity of their current organization
principles and steering mechanisms, they can draw upon the “cognitive
potential” in the world views and stocks of knowledge of individuals who
reorganize their actions. The result of this learning creates new levels of
information that allow for the development of new organization principles
for securing integration in the face of increased societal differentiation
and complexity. |
I have only skimmed the surface of Habermas’s views, but the details
are perhaps best left out since they are ambiguous. Yet, there is an implicit
line of argument that I should emphasize: the basis for societal integration
lies in the processes by which actors communicate and develop mutual
understandings and stores of knowledge. To the extent that these inter-
active processes are arrested by the patterns of economic and political
organization, then the society’s learning capacity is correspondingly di-
minished. One of the main integrative problems of capitalist societies is
the integration of the material forces of production (economy as admin-
istered by the state), on the one side, and the cultural stores of knowledge
that are produced by communicative interaction, on the other side. So-
cieties that differentiate materially in the economic and political realms
**He borrows from Niklas Luhmann here (see Chapter 5), although much of Habermas's
approach is a reaction to Luhmann.
“Habermas analogizes here to Piaget's and Kohlberg’s analysis of the cognitive devel-
opment of children, seeing societies as able to “learn” as they become more structurallv
complex.
THE CRITICAL APPROACH OF JURGEN HABERMAS 201
%Jurgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, 2 vols. Only volume 1 is, at
this writing, translated. Its subtitle, Reason and the Rationalization of Society, gives some
indication of its thrust. The translator, Thomas McCarthy, has done an excellent service
in translating what is very difficult prose. Also, his “Translators Introduction” to volume
1, pp. v-xxxvii is the best summary of Habermas’s recent theory that I have come across.
Perhaps by the time this book is published, McCarthy will have finished the translation of
volume 2. My understanding of volume 2 is limited by my lack of fluency in German, but
I have waded through the text and consulted German colleagues. I would, in particular, like
to thank Angscar Weyman, Universitat Bremen.
*Thomas McCarthy, ‘Translators Introduction,” p. vii.
37Tbid.
%*Jurgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1, p. 397.
202 CHAPTER 9 / THE CRITICAL THEORIZING OF JURGEN HABERMAS
claims, resides a rationality that can potentially serve as the basis for
reconstructing the social order in less oppressive ways. The first volume
of The Theory of Communicative Action thus focuses on action and ra-
tionality in an effort to reconceptualize both processes in a manner that
shifts emphasis from the subjectivity and consciousness of the individual
to the process of symbolic interaction. In a sense, volume 1 is Habermas’s
microsociology, whereas volume 2 is his macrosociology. In this second
volume, Habermas introduces the concept of system and tries to connect
it to microprocesses of action and interaction through a reconceptualization
of the phenomenological concept of lifeworld (see Chapters 14 and 18).
“Ibid., p. 95.
“Tbid., p. 99.
“Recall Habermas’s earlier discussion of nondistorted communication and the ideal speech
act. This is his most recent reconceptualization of these ideas.
“Ibid., p. 100. Emphasis in original.
THE CRITICAL APPROACH OF JURGEN HABERMAS 205
“Ibid., p. 302.
“Ibid., p. 137.
206 CHAPTER 9 / THE CRITICAL THEORIZING OF JURGEN HABERMAS
solidarity; and (3) communicative action that socializes agents meets the
need for the formation of personal identities.*’
Thus, the three components of the lifeworld—culture, society, per-
sonality—meet corresponding needs of society—cultural reproduction, so-
cial integration, and personality formation—through three dimensions
along which communicative action is conducted—reaching understanding,
coordinating interaction, and socialization. As Habermas summarizes in
volume 2:
“We are now into volume 2, ibid., pp. 205-40, which is entitled System and Lifeworld:
A Critique of Functionalist Reason, which is, I think, a somewhat ironic title because of
the heavily functional arguments in volume 2. But as I pointed out earlier, even Habermas's
earlier work has always had an implicit functionalism.
“Ibid., p. 208.
“This is the old functionalist argument of “differentiation” produces “integrative prob-
lems,” which is as old as Spencer and which is Parsons reincarnated with a phenomenological
twist.
THE CRITICAL APPROACH OF JURGEN HABERMAS 207
%] have shifted now, back to portions of volume 1. All quotes here are from p. 70 of
volume 1.
6t\Here Habermas is borrowing from Simmel’s analysis in The Philosophy of Money (see
Chapter 6) and Parsons’s conceptualization of generalized media (see Chapter 3).
8] am now back in volume 2 of The Theory of Communicative Action, pp. 256-76.
‘Habermas appears in these arguments to borrow heavily from Parscns’s analysis of
evolution (see Chapter 3).
“Volume 2, p. 227.
208 CHAPTER 9 / THE CRITICAL THEORIZING OF JURGEN HABERMAS
ways that reduce political and economic crises but which increase those
crises revolving around lifeworld reproduction. For the new crises and
conflicts “arise in areas of cultural reproduction, of social integration and
of socialization.”®
“Ibid. p. 576.
AN ASSESSMENT OF HABERMAS'S CRITICAL THEORY AND PROJECT 209
Indeed, it is both “ideological” and “scientific” in terms of the scheme drawn in Figure
1-1.
‘Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1937) does
not go much beyond Weber’s analysis.
“Erving Goffman, The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life (Garden City, N.Y.: Dou-
bleday Publishing, 1959).
210 CHAPTER 9 / THE CRITICAL THEORIZING OF JURGEN HABERMAS
¢1Habermas has also refined Mead’s view of “role-taking” with the ‘generalized other”
in this conceptualization. See Chapter 14.
*See Chapter 3, Figure 3-7.
212 CHAPTER 9 / THE CRITICAL THEORIZING OF JURGEN HABERMAS
“Niklas Luhmann, The Differentiation of Society (New York: Columbia University Press,
1982). Indeed, Luhmann and Habermas have had a number of stimulating debates on the |
issue, with Luhmann emerging the victor in my opinion.
PART THREE
Exchange Theory
213
e
oe
.
x. sti ee-
et
ea
aa
pa
oi
SN
ERC
Nt
CT
A
tl
IEE
CT
a
Ct
L
N
A
N
AAa
t
Early Forms of
Exchange Theorizing
Aside from this revised substantive legacy, I believe that some forms
of modern exchange theory have also adopted the strategy of the utili-
tarians for constructing social theory. In assuming humans to be rational,
utilitarians argued that exchanges among people could also be studied by
a rational science,-ene in which the “laws of human nature” would stand
at the top of a deductive system of explanation.‘ Thus, utilitarians bor-
rowed the early physical-science conception of theory as a logico-deductive
system of axioms or laws and various layers of lower-order propositions
that could be rationally deduced from the laws of ‘“‘economic man.” Thus,
most exchange theories are presented in a propositional format, typically
in what I called a formal propositional scheme in Chapter 1.
In reviewing the tenets of utilitarianism, however, I think that only
part of the historical legacy of exchange theory is revealed. For utilitar-
ianism excited considerable debate and controversy in early anthropology.
In fact, I sense that much of the influence of utilitarianism on current
exchange theory /has been indirect, passing through social anthropology
around the turn of this century.
‘Jurgen Habermas would, of course, make this a much more complicated issue. See his
The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1 (Boston: Beacon Press, 1981).
’For a similar treatment of these materials, see Peter Ekeh, Social Exchange Theory
and the Two Sociological Traditions (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1975).
‘Sir James George Frazer, Folklore in the Old Testament, vol. 2 (New York: Macmillan,
1919); see also his Totemism and Exogamy: A Treatise on Certain Early Forms of Super-
stition and Society (London: Dawsons of Pall Mall, 1968; original publication 1910); and
his Preface to Bronislaw Malinowski’s Argonauts of the Western Pacific (London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul, 1922), pp. vii-xiv.
7Quote taken from Ekeh’s Social Exchange Theory, pp. 41-42, discussion of Frazer
(original quote in Frazer, Folklore, p. 199).
218 CHAPTER 10 / EARLY FORMS OF EXCHANGE THEORIZING
*Ibid., p. 195.
*Frazer, Folklore, p. 198.
EXCHANGE THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY 219
1™Marcel Mauss, The Gift, trans. I. Cunnison (New York: Free Press, 1954; originally
published as Essai sur le don en sociologie et anthropologie [Paris: Presses universitaires
de France, 1925]). It should be noted that Mauss rather consistently misinterpreted Mali-
nowski’s ethnography, but it is through such misinterpretation that he came to visualize a
“structural” alternative to “psychological” exchange theories.
18Jn Peter Ekeh’s excellent discussion of Mauss and Lévi-Strauss (Social Exchange The-
ory, pp. 55-122), the term collectivist is used in preference to structural and is posited as
the alternative to individualistic or psychological exchange perspectives. I prefer the terms
structural and psychological; thus, although I am indebted to Ekeh’s discussion, these terms
will be used to make essentially the same distinction. My preference for these terms will
become more evident in subsequent chapters, since in contrast with Ekeh’s analysis, I
consider Peter M. Blau and George C. Homans to have developed, respectively, structural
and psychological theories. Ekeh considers the theories of both Blau and Homans to be
individualistic, or psychological.
Mauss, The Gift, p. 1.
*Ibid., p. 3.
222 CHAPTER 10 / EARLY FORMS OF EXCHANGE THEORIZING
See, for relevant articles, lectures, and references, I. P. Pavlov, Selected Works, ed. K.
S. Kostoyants, trans. S. Belsky (Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House, 1955); and
Lectures on Conditioned Reflexes, 3d ed., trans. W. H. Grant (New York: International
Publishers, 1928).
41. P, Pavlov, “Autobiography” in Selected Works, pp. 41-44.
%F or an excellent summary of their ideas, see Robert I. Watson, The Great Psychologists,
3d ed. (Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott, 1971), pp. 417-46.
#*Edward L. Thorndike, “Animal Intelligence: An Experimental Study of the Associative
Processes in Animals,” Psychological Review Monograph, Supplement 2 (1898).
226 CHAPTER 10 / EARLY FORMS OF EXCHANGE THEORIZING
See Edward L. Thorndike, The Elements of Psychology (New York: Seiler, 1905), The
Fundamentals of Learning (New York: Teachers College Press, 1932), and The Psychology
of Wants, Interests, and Attitudes (New York: D. Appleton, 1935).
*Others who recognized their importance included: Max F. Meyer, Psychology of the
Other-One (Columbus: Missouri Book, 1921); and Albert P. Weiss, A Theoretical Basis of
Human Behavior (Columbus: Adams Press, 1925).
*J. B. Watson, “Psychology as the Behaviorist Views It,” Psychological Review 20 (1913),
pp. 158-77. For other basic works by Watson, see Psychology from the Standpoint of a
Behaviorist, 3d ed. (Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott, 1929); Behavior: An Introduction to
Comparative Psychology (New York: Henry Holt, 1914).
*For example, in his Mind, Self, and Society (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1934), Mead has 18 references to Watson's work.
“For a more detailed discussion of the emergence of behaviorism, see Jonathan H. Turner
= Leonard Beeghley, The Emergence of Sociological Theory (Homewood, Ill: Dorsey
ress, 1981).
PSYCHOLOGICAL BEHAVIORISM AND EXCHANGE THEORY 227
Georg Simmel, The Philosophy of Money, trans. T. Bottomore and D. Frisby (Boston:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978; originally published in 1907).
%See Chapter 6.
230 CHAPTER 10 / EARLY FORMS OF EXCHANGE THEORIZING
1. Those who need scarce and valued resources that others possess
but who do not have equally valued and scarce resources to offer
in return will be dependent upon those who control these resources.
2. Those who control valued resources have power over those who
do not. That is, the power of one actor over another is directly
related to (a) the capacity of one actor to monopolize the valued
resources needed by other actors and (b) the inability of those
actors who need these resources to offer equally valued and scarce
resources in return.
3. Those with power will press their advantage and will try to extract
more resources from those dependent upon them in exchange for
fewer (or the same level) of the resources that they control.
4. Those who press their advantage in this way will create conditions
that encourage those who are dependent on them to (a) organize
in ways that increase the value of their resources and, failing this,
to (b) organize in ways that enable them to coerce those on whom
they are dependent.
from Simmel’s discussion. For Simmel, social exchange involves the fol-
lowing elements:
1. The desire for a valued object that one does not have.
2. The possession of the valued object by an identifiable other.
3. The offer of an object of value to secure from another the desired
object.
4. The acceptance of this offer by the possessor of the valued object.°°
Contained iftthis portrayal of social exchange are several additional
points that Simmel emphasized. First, value is idiosyncratic and is, ul-
timately, tied to an individual’s impulses and needs. Of course, what is
defined as valuable is typically circumscribed by cultural and social pat-
terns, but how valuable an object is will be a positive function of (a) the
intensity of a person’s needs and (b) the scarcity of the object. Second,
much exchange involves efforts to manipulate situations so that the in-
tensity of needs for an object are concealed and the availability of an
object is made to seem less than what it actually is. Inherent in exchange,
therefore, is a basic tension that can often erupt into other social forms,
such as conflict. Third, to possess an object is to lessen its value and to
increase the value of objects that one does not possess. Fourth, exchanges
will only occur if both parties perceive that the object given is less valuable
than the one received.*” Fifth, collective units as well as individuals par-
ticipate in exchange relations and, hence, are subject to the four processes
listed above. Sixth, the more liquid the resources of an actor in an ex-
change—that is, the more that resources can be used in many types of
exchanges—the greater will be that actor’s options and power. For if an
actor is not bound to exchange with any other and can readily withdraw
resources and exchange them with another, then that actor has consid-
erable power to manipulate any exchange.
Economic exchange involving money is only one case of this more
general social form. But it is a very special case. For when money becomes
the predominate means for establishing value in social relationships, the
properties and dynamics of social relations are transformed. This process
of displacing other criteria of value, such as logic, ethics, and aesthetics,
with a monetary criterion is precisely the long-term evolutionary trend
in societies. This trend is, as I mentioned earlier, both a cause and effect
of money as the medium of exchange. Money emerged to facilitate ex-
changes and to realize even more completely humans’ basic needs. But
e
a
once established, the use of money has the power to transform the struc-
ture of social relations in society.
Thus, the key insight in The Philosophy of Money is that the use of
different criteria for assessing value has an enormous impact on the form
of social relations. Thus, as money replaces barter and other criteria for
determining values, social relations are fundamentally changed. But they
are transformed in accordance with some basic principles of social ex-
change, which are never codified by Simmel but which, as I have indicated
above, are very clear. In Table 10-1, I have codified these ideas into
abstract exchange principles, because I see them as the basic processes
depicted in sociological analysis of exchange. At. the risk of repeating
myself, let me summarize again the ideas behind the propositions. Prin-
ciple I states that interaction occurs because actors value each other’s
resources, and in accordance with Principle II, value is a dual function
of (a) actors’ needs for resources and (b) the scarcity of resources. Prin-
ciples III and IV underscore the fact that power is a part of the exchange
process. Actors who have resources that others value are in a position to
extract compliance from those seeking these resources (Principle III), and
actors who have liquid or generalized resources, such as money, will be
more likely to have power, since liquid resources can be more readily
exchanged with alternative actors. Principle V states that as actors seek
to manipulate situations in order to conceal the availability of resources
and their needs for resources, tensions are created, and these tensions can
result in conflict.
MODERN EXCHANGE THEORY: A PREVIEW 233
‘I would like to thank George C. Homans for his constructive criticisms of this chapter
as it appeared in an earlier edition of this book.
234
THE EARLY INDUCTIVE STRATEGY 235
easy to simply raise the level of abstract and create abstract theory. Rather,
a creative leap in abstraction is necessary, and then, armed with more
abstract principles, one makes deductions back down to empirical gen-
eralizations. Homans’s “creative leap” involved borrowing from behav-
ioristic psychology, and so, perhaps I should view his exchange work as
creative borrowing. Nonetheless, Homans recognized that induction from
empirical contexts can only go so far; at some point, one must construct
deductive propositional schemes to explain what one has induced from
these contexts.
*George C. Homans, The Human Group (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1950).
‘Jbid., p. 13.
236 CHAPTER 11 / THE EXCHANGE BEHAVIORISM OF GEORGE C. HOMANS
‘In his work, Homans rarely makes direct observations himself. Rather. he has tended
to rely on the observations of others, making from their reports inferences about events.
As would be expected, Homans has often been criticized for accepting too readily the im-
precise and perhaps inaccurate observations of others as an inductive base for theorizing.
‘This extended example is adapted from the discussion of Homans’ propositions in M.
THE EARLY INDUCTIVE STRATEGY 237
between two or more persons increases, the degree of their liking for one
another will increase, and vice versa.® (2) Persons whose sentiments of
liking for one another increase will express these sentiments in increased
activity, and vice versa.” (3) The more frequently persons interact with
one another, the more alike their activities and their sentiments tend to
become, and vice versa.® (4) The higher the rank of a person within a
group, the more nearly his activities conform to the norms of the group,
and vice versa.® (5) The higher the person’s social rank, the wider will be
the range of this person’s interactions.'°
These propositions describe some of the group-elaboration processes
that Homans “observed” in the Bank Wiring Room. Propositions 1 and
2 summarize Homans’s observations that the more the workers interacted,
the more they appeared to like one another, which, in turn, seemed to
cause further interactions above and beyond the work requirements of
the external system. Such elaboration of interactions, sentiments, and
activities also results in the differentiation of subgroups that reveal their
own levels of output, topics of conversation, and patterns of work assis-
tance. This tendency is denoted by Proposition 3. Another pattern of
differentiation in the Bank Wiring Room is described by Proposition 4,
whereby the ranking of individuals and subgroups occurs when group
members compare their activities with those of other members and the
output norms of the group. Proposition 5 describes the tendency of high-
ranking members to interact more frequently with all members of the
group, offering more on-the-job assistance.
Having tentatively established these and other empirical regularities
in the Bank Wiring Room, Homans then analyzes the equally famous
Norton Street Gang, described in William Whyte’s Street Corner Society.
In this second case study, Homans follows his strategy of confirming his
earlier propositions, while inducing further generalizations: (6) The higher
a person’s social rank, the larger will be the number of persons that
originate interaction for him or her, either directly or through interme-
diaries." (7) The higher a person’s social rank, the larger will be the
number of persons toward whom interaction is initiated, either directly
or through intermediaries.'? (8) The more nearly equal in social rank a
J. Mulkay, Functionalism and Exchange and Theoretical Strategy (New York: Schocken
Books, 1971), pp. 135-41. As was done by Mulkay, some of Homans’ propositions are
reworded for simplification.
*Homans, Human Group, p. 112.
TTbid., p. 118.
*Tbid., p. 120.
*Tbid., p. 141.
Ibid., p. 145.
“Tbid., p. 182.
Tbid.
238 CHAPTER 11 / THE EXCHANGE BEHAVIORISM OF GEORGE C. HOMANS
number of people are, the more frequently they will interact with one
another.'®
I see Propositions 6 and 7 as simply corollaries of Proposition 5. It
follows, almost by definition, that those with a wide range of interactions
will receive and initiate more interaction. However, Propositions 6 and
7 are induced separately from his observations of the Bank Wiring Room.
For the Norton Street Gang, Homans observes that Doc, the leader of
the gang, was the center of a complex network of communication. Such
a pattern of communication was not observable in the Bank Wiring Room
because stable leadership ranks had not emerged. Proposition 8 describes
another process Homans sees in groups with clear leadership: the internal
system tends to differentiate into super- and subordinate subgroups, whose
members appear to interact more with each other than those of higher
or lower rank.
After using the group-elaboration processes in the Norton Street Gang
to confirm and supplement the propositions induced from the Bank Wir-
ing Room, Homans then examines the Tikopia family, as described in
Raymond Firth’s famous ethnography. As with the Norton Street Gang,
the Tikopia family system was used to confirm earlier propositions and
as a field from which to induce further propositions: (9) The more fre-
quently persons interact with one another, when no one of them originates
interaction with much greater frequency than the others, the greater is
their liking for one another and their feeling of ease in one another’s
presence.'* (10) When two persons interact with one another, the more
frequently one of the two originates interaction for the other, the stronger
will be the latter’s sentiment of respect (or hostility), and the more nearly
will the frequency of interaction be kept to a minimum."
These propositions reveal, I should emphasize, another facet of Ho-
mans’s inductive strategy. They establish some conditions under which
Proposition 1 will hold true. In Proposition 1, Homans notes that in-
creased interaction between two persons increases their liking, but in the
Tikopia family system Homans discovered that this generalization holds
true only under conditions where authority of one person over another
is low. In the Tikopia family system, brothers revealed sentiments of liking
as a result of their frequent interactions, primarily because they do not
have authority over one another. However, frequent interaction with their
father, who does have authority, was tense because the father initiated
the interaction and because it usually involved the exercise of his authority.
Perhaps less critical than the substance of Propositions 9 and 10, I
think, is the strategy they reveal. Homans has used an inductive technique
8Tbid., p. 184.
“Tbid., p. 243.
*Ibid., p. 247.
THE ADDITION OF A DEDUCTIVE STRATEGY 239
'%*George C. Homans, Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms (New York: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich, 1961), p. 10.
1] bid.
IT bid.
240 CHAPTER 11 / THE EXCHANGE BEHAVIORISM OF GEORGE C. HOMANS
‘*George C. Homans, The Nature of Social Science (New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World,
1967), p. 13. Parsons has replied that such systems of concepts can be theory: “I emphatically
dispute this [deductive theory] is all that can legitimately be called theory. In biology, for
example, I should certainly regard the basic classificatory schemes of taxonomy, for example
in particular the comparative anatomy of vertebrates, to be theoretical. Moreover very
important things are, with a few additional facts, explained on such levels such as the
inability of organisms with lungs and no gills to live for long periods under water” (Talcott
Parsons, “Levels of Organization and the Mediation of Social Interaction,” Sociological
Inquiry 34 (Spring 1964], pp. 219-20).
*Homans has championed this conception of theory in a large number of works; see,
for example, Homans, Social Behavior; Homans, Nature of Social Science: George C. Ho-
mans, “Fundamental Social Processes,”- in Sociology, ed. N. J. Smelser (New York: John
Wiley & Sons, 1967), pp. 27-78; George C. Homans, “Contemporary Theory in Sociology,”
in Handbook of Modern Sociology, ed. R.-E. L. Faris (Skokie, Ill: Rand-McNally. 1964).
pp. 251-77; and George C. Homans, “Bringing Men Back In,” American Sociological Review
29 (December 1964), pp. 809-18. For an early statement of his position, see George C.
Homans, “Social Behavior as Exchange,” American Journal of Sociology 63 (August 1958),
pp. 597-606. For a recent statement, see “Discovery and the Discovered in Social Theory.”
Humboldt Journal of Social Relations 7 (Fall-Winter 1979-80), pp. 89-102.
THE EXCHANGE MODEL 241
21George C. Homans and David M. Schneider, Marriage, Authority, and Final Causes:
A Study of Unilateral Cross-Cousin Marriage (New York: Free Press, 1955). There are,
however, hints of this interest in exchange theory in Homans’s first major work, English
Villagers of the 13th Century (New York: Russell & Russell, 1941).
"Homans and Schneider, Marriage, p. 15.
In so doing, Homans advocates the principle of “methodological individualism,” which
sees social reality as the result of aggregated individual actions and behaviors. If social
structure is aggregations of individual behavior, then the highest order principles in the
deductive schemes of sociology must be about individual behavior. For another version of
this, see Chapter 21 on Randall Collins’s exchange perspective.
*Homans and Schneider, Marriage, p. 15.
Homans, Social Behavior, pp. 1-83. For an excellent summary of the Skinnerian prin-
ciples incorporated into Homans’s scheme, see Richard L. Simpson, “Theories of Social
Exchange” (Morristown, N.Y.: General Learning Press, 1972), pp. 3-4. As an interesting
aside, Peter P. Ekeh, Social Exchange Thecry and the Two Sociological Traditions (Cam-
242 CHAPTER 11 / THE EXCHANGE BEHAVIORISM OF GEORGE C. HOMANS
bridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1975) has argued that had Homans not felt so compelled
to reject Lévi-Strauss, he would not have embraced Skinnerian principles. Ekeh goes so far
as to offer a hypothetical list of axioms that Homans would have postulated, had he not
cast his scheme into the terminology of behaviorism.
*For a more detailed analysis of this point and the problems it presents, see Richard
M. Emerson, “Social Exchange Theory,” in Annual Review of Sociology 2 (Palo Alto, Calif.:
Annual Reviews, 1976).
THE EXCHANGE MODEL 243
Indeed we are out to rehabilitate the economic man. The trouble with him
was not that he was economic, that he used resources to some advantage, but
that he was antisocial and materialistic, interested only in money and material
goods and ready to sacrifice even his old mother to get them.’
Thus, to be an appropriate explanation of human behavior, this basic
economic assumption must be altered in four ways: (1) People do not
always attempt to maximize profits; they seek only to make some profit
in exchange relations. (2) Humans do not usually make either long-run
or rational calculations in exchanges; for, in everyday life, “the Theory
of Games is good advice for human behavior but a poor description of
it.” (3) The things exchanged involve not only money but also other
commodities, including approval, esteem, compliance, love, affection, and
other less materialistic goods. (4) The marketplace is not a separate do-
main in human exchanges, for all interaction involves individuals ex-
changing rewards (and punishments) and seeking profits.
27Homans, Social Behavior, p. 79. Kenneth Boulding (“An Economist’s View of ‘Social
Behavior: Its Elementary Forms,’” American Journal of Sociology 67 [January 1962], p.
458) has noted that in Homans’s work “economic man is crossed with the psychological
pigeon to produce what the unkind might call the Economic Pigeon theory of human in-
teraction.” For a more detailed and serious analysis of Homans’s meshing of elementary
economics and psychology, see Ekeh, Social Exchange Theory, pp. 162-71.
**George Caspar Homans, Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms (New York: Harcourt
Brace Jovanovich, 1974), pp. 15-47. In contrast to the first edition of The Structure of
Sociological Theory, which concentrated on the earlier edition of Homans’s book, I have
relied almost exclusively on the revised edition of Social Behavior. For a discussion of
Homans’s original formulation of his exchange theory, the reader is referred to pp. 235-47
of my The Structure of Sociological Theory (Homewood, Ill: Dorsey Press, 1974).
244 CHAPTER 11 / THE EXCHANGE BEHAVIORISM OF GEORGE C. HOMANS
: *The concept of cost does not appear in Homans’s actual axioms, but it is so prominent
in his scheme that it is listed here with his other important concepts.
See Homans, Social Behavior, pp. 11-68. Masculine pronouns are maintained, since
this is how Homans wrote the propositions.
THE EXCHANGE MODEL 245
%1S¢e the first edition of The Structure of Sociological Theory and my “Building Social
Theory: Some Questions about Homans’ Strategy,” Pacific Sociological Review 20 (Apri’
1977), pp. 203-20.
Homans, “Bringing Men Back In.”
246 CHAPTER 11 / THE EXCHANGE BEHAVIORISM OF GEORGE C. HOMANS
|. Success Proposition: For all actions taken by persons, the more often a
particular action of a person is rewarded, the more likely the person is to
perform that action.
ll. Stimulus Proposition: If in the past the occurrence of a particular stimulus or set
of stimuli has been the occasion on which a person's action has been
rewarded, then the more similar the present stimuli are to the past ones, the
more likely the person is to perform the action or some similar action now.
lll. Value Proposition: The more valuable to a person is the result of his action, the
more likely he is to perform the action.
IV. Deprivation-Satiation Proposition: The more often in the recent past a person
has received a particular reward, the less valuable any further unit of that
reward becomes for him.
V. Aggression-Approval Propositions: (a) When a person's action does not receive
the reward he expected or receives punishment he did not expect, he will be
angry and become more likely to perform aggressive behavior, and the results
of such behavior become more valuable to him. (b) When a person's action
receives the reward expected, especially greater reward than expected, or does
not receive punishment he expected, he will be pleased and become more likely
to perform approving behavior, and the results of such behavior become more
valuable to him.
Vi. Rationality Proposition: In choosing between alternative actions, a person will
choose that one for which, as perceived by him or her at the time, the value of
the result, multiplied by the probability of getting that result, is greater.
insists, social scientists assume that the basic laws of social organization
will be more esoteric—and certainly less familiar—since for them the game
of science involves the startling discovery of new, unfamiliar, and pre-
sumably profound principles. In reference to these social scientists, Ho-
mans writes:
All this familiarity has bred contempt, a contempt that has got in the way
of the development of social science. Its fundamental propositions seem so
obvious as to be boring, and an intellectual, by definition a wit and a man
of the world, will go to great lengths to avoid the obvious.”
However, if the first principles of sociology are obvious, despite the
best efforts of scientists to the contrary, Homans suggests that sociology
cease its vain search for the esoteric and begin constructing deductive
systems that recognize the fact that the most general propositions are
not only psychological but familiar. In fact, if sociologists crave com-
plexity, this task shouid certainly be satisfying, since the deductive sys-
tems connecting these simple principles to observed empirical regularities
will be incredibly complex.
Unfortunately, Homans himself never offers a well-developed expla-
nation. He has tended to simply invoke, in a rather ad hoc fashion, his
axioms and to reconcile them in a very loose and imprecise manner with
empirical regularities. Or he has constructed brief deductive schemes to
illustrate his strategy. These limitations in themselves constitute an im-
portant criticism of Homans’s work, because he has not fully implemented
his own theoretical strategy. Yet I do not see Homans’s failure to actually
do what he says should be done as negating the utility of the strategy.
Let me examine one of Homans’s deductive schemes to assess its potential
as well as its problems.
One of Homans’s explanations is reproduced below. Homans recog-
nizes that this is not a complete explanation, but he argues that it is as
good as any other that exists. Moreover, although certain steps in the
deductive scheme are omitted, it is the proper way to develop scientific
explanations from Homans’s point of view. In this scheme, Homans seeks
to explain Golden’s Law that industrialization and the level of literacy
in the population are highly correlated. As I emphasized in Chapter 1,
such empirical generalizations are often considered to be theory, but Ho-
mans has correctly perceived that this “law” is only an empirical gen-
eralization that belongs at the bottom of the deductive scheme (see Figure
1-4). Propositions move from the most abstract statement, or the ax-
iom(s),*4 to the specific empirical regularity to be explained. Golden’s Law
is thus explained in the following manner.
1. Men are more likely to perform an activity the more valuable they
perceive the reward of that activity to be.
2. Men are more likely to perform an activity the more successful
they perceive the activity to be in getting that reward.*
3. Compared with agricultural societies, a higher proportion of men
in industrial societies are prepared to reward activities that in-
volve literacy. (Industrialists want to hire bookkeepers, clerks,
and persons who can make and read blueprints, manuals, and so
forth.)
4. Therefore a higher proportion of men in industrial societies will
perceive the acquisition of literacy as rewarding.
. And [by (1)] a higher proportion will attempt to acquire literacy.
Oo. The provision of schooling costs money, directly or indirectly.
ao
*George C. Homans, “Reply to Blain,” Sociological Inquiry 41 (Winter 1971), pp. 19-
24. This article was written in response to a challenge by Robert Blain for Homans to
explain a sociological law: “On Homans’ Psychological Reductionism,” Seviological Inquiry
41 (Winter 1971), pp. 3-25.
CRITICISMS OF HOMANS'S STRATEGY AND EXCHANGE THEORY 249
to the critical sociological questions have been avoided, such as why people
perceive as valuable and rewarding certain crucial activities. +
Homans’s reply to such criticisms is, I think, important}to note.°”
First, he emphasizes that this deductive scheme was just an example or
illustrative sketch, leaving out many details. Second, and more impor-
tantly, Homans contends that it is unreasonable for the critic to expect
that a theory can and must explain every given condition (Propositions
3 and 7, for example). He offers the example of Newton’s laws, which can
help explain the movement of the tides (by virtue of gravitational forces
of the moon relative to the axis of the earth), but these laws cannot explain
why oceans are present and why the earth exists. I think that this latter
argument is reasonable, in principle, since deductive theories explain only
a delimited range of phenomena, as can be recalled by reference to Figure
1-6 in Chapter 1. But let me anticipate a point that I will emphasize
shortly: while Homans does not need to explain the givens of a deductive
scheme, all of the interesting sociological questions are contained in those
givens. Moreover, these questions beg for the development of abstract
sociological laws to explain them (Golden’s Law is not an abstract prin-
ciple, only an empirical generalization). And so, I wonder why Homans
devotes his time to the construction of quasi-axiomatic (formal) systems
that contain no sociological laws. Why concentrate on the psychological
laws from which sociological laws are to be ultimately deduced when the
real task of sociology is to develop these sociological laws? But this is one
of many criticisms leveled at Homans’ scheme in particular and, to some
extent, at all exchange theory. Let me now turn to these criticisms and
discuss them in more detail.
Parsons, who similarly has dealt with the rationality issue (“Levels of Organization,”
in Institutions and Social Exchange, ed. H. Turk and R. L. Simpson [Indianapolis, Ind.:
Bobbs-Merrill, 1971], p. 219), notes: “History thus seems to become for Homans the ultimate
residual categoiy, recourse to which can solve any embarrassment which arises from in-
adequacy of the more specific parts of the conceptual scheme. The very extent to which he
has narrowed his conceptualization of the variables, in particular adopting the atomistic
conception of values, . . . increases the burden thrown upon history and with it the confession
of ignorance embodied in the statement, ‘things are as they are because of ways in which
they have come to be that way.’ ”
*Robert Bierstedt, “Review of Blain’s Exchange and Power,” American Sociological
Review 30 (1965), pp. 789-90.
“For enlightening discussions of this problem, see Morton Deutsch, “Homans in the
Skinner Box,” in Institutions and Social Exchange, ed. H. Turk and R. L. Simpson (In-
dianapolis, Ind.: Bobbs-Merrill, 1971), pp. 81-92; Bengt Abrahamsson, “Homans on Ex-
change: Hedonism Revived,” American Journal of Sociology 76 (September 1970), pp. 273-
85; Pitirim Sorokin, Sociological Theories of Today (New York: Harper & Row, 1966),
especially Chapter 15, “‘Pseudo-Behavioral and Empirical Sociologies,” and Mulkay, Func-
tionalism and Exchange, pp. 166-69.
CRITICISMS OF HOMANS'S STRATEGY AND EXCHANGE THEORY 251
I think that the thrust of the last phase has been underemphasized
in the criticisms of Homans’s reductionism. Critics have too often implied
that his reductionism forces him to embrace a particular variety of nom-
inalism. Yet, for Homans, the issue has always been one of how to explain
with deductive—or axiomatic—systems the groups and institutions studied
by sociologists.
they could analyze the universe into its constituent parts and thereby
eventually discover the basic elements or building blocks of all matter.*’
Once the basic building block had been found, it would only then be
necessary to comprehend the laws of its operation for an understanding
of everything else in the universe. In the eyes of Whitehead and others,
these scientists had erroneously assumed that the basic parts of the uni-
verse were the only reality. In so doing, they had ‘“‘misplaced” the con-
creteness of phenomena. In reality, the relationships among parts forming
a whole are just as real as the constituent parts. The organization of parts
is not the sum of the parts, but rather, the constitution of a new kind of
reality.
Has Homans fallen into this fallacy? Numerous critics think that he
has when he implies that the behavior of persons or “men” are the basic
units, whose laws need only be understood to explain more complex so-
ciocultural arrangements. I think that these critics are overreacting to
Homans’s reductionism, perhaps confusing his reductionist strategy with
the mistaken assumption that Homans is a nominalist in disguise. Ac-
tually, Homans has never denied the importance of sociological laws de-
scribing complex sociocultural processes; on the contrary, they are critical
propositions in any deductive system that attempts to explain these pro-
cesses. In my view, all that Homans asserts is: these sociological laws are
not the most general; they are subsumable under more general psycho-
logical laws (his axioms), which, with more knowledge and sophisticated
intellectual techniques, will be subsumable under a still more general set
of laws. At no point in this reductionist philosophy is Homans asserting
that the propositions subsumed by a more general set of laws are irrelevant
or unimportant. Thus, Homans has not misplaced the concreteness of
reality. He has not denied the existence of emergent properties such as
groups, organizations, and institutions, nor the theoretical significance of
the laws describing these emergent phenomena. Homans is not a nomi-
nalist in disguise, but a sociological realist, who is advocating a particular
strategy for understanding sociocultural phenomena.
47Alfred North Whitehead, Science and the Modern World (New York: Macmillan, 1925).
“For example, see Blain, “On Homans’ Psychological Reductionism”; and Walter Buck-
ley, Sociology and Modern Systems Theory (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1967),
pp. 109-11.
254 CHAPTER 11 / THE EXCHANGE BEHAVIORISM OF GEORGE C. HOMANS
1 2 3
Individuals New patterns of social Creating elaborated social
with capital organization which patterns employing
or resources provide capital for secondary reinforcers and
investors and payoffs explicit norms
for followers
Inturn, —
this elaborated
organizational
base allows
Organization allows for for expanded social
O Invest in expanded investment organization
(ne OS
The Human Group and Social Behavior. For I think that the substantive
vision of the social world first communicated in The Human Group and
expanded upon in the later exchange works is provocative and likely to
be the most enduring feature of Homans’s theoretical perspective. And
thus, Iet me close this chapter on Homans’s approach with a review of
this more substantive image of society.
In The Human Group, Homans’s numerous empirical generalizations
describe the processes of group elaboration and disintegration. Groups
are observed to differentiate into subgroups, to form leadership ranks, to
codify norms, to establish temporary equilibriums, and then, in his last
case study of a dying New England town, to reveal the converse of these
processes. In the later exchange works, the concepts of activities, inter-
actions, and sentiments, which are incorporated into the propositions
describing such group elaboration, are redefined in order to give Homans
the opportunity to explain why these processes should occur. Human
activity becomes action directed toward the attainment of rewards and
avoidance of punishments. Interaction becomes social behavior where the
mutual actions of individuals have cost and reward implications for the
parties to the interaction. People are now seen as emitting those activities
that increase the likelihood of profits—rewards less costs—measured against
a set of expectations. Such rewarding and costly exchanges of activities
are not viewed as necessarily involving the exchange of material rewards
and punishments, but more frequently “psychic profits.”
HOMANS'’S IMAGE OF SOCIETY 257
a Eee er to ee ioe
4 5 6
Involving differentiation That can provide the basis
of social structures in for even more complex
terms of power and social patterns, but which
enforcement capacities fail to meet the primary
needs of some individuals
This differentiation
allows for more complex
social patterns
At the level of the smali group, society has always been able to cohere.
We infer, therefore, that if civilization is to stand, it must maintain, in the
258 CHAPTER 11 / THE EXCHANGE BEHAVIORISM OF GEORGE C. HOMANS
relation between the groups that make up society and the central direction
of society, some of the features of the small group itself.
keep going because they have pay-offs, ultimately pay-offs for individuals.
Nor is society a perpetual-motion machine, supplying its own fuel. It cannot
keep itself going by planting in the young a desire for these goods and only
those goods that it happens to be in shape to provide. It must provide goods
that men find rewarding not simply because they are sharers in a particular
culture but because they are men.
The fact that institutions of society must also meet primary needs
sets the stage for a continual conflict between institutional elaboration
and the primary needs of humans. As one form of institutional elaboration
meets one set of needs, it may deprive people of other important rewards—
opening the way for deviation and innovation by those presenting the
alternative rewards that have been suppressed by dominant institutional
arrangements. In turn, the new institutional elaborations that may ensue
from innovators who have the capital to reward others will suppress other
needs, which, through processes similar to its inception, will set off an-
other process of institutional elaboration.
In sum, this sketch of how social organization is linked to elementary
processes of exchange represents an interesting perspective for analyzing
how patterns of social organization are built up, maintained, altered, and
broken down. Although there are obvious conceptual problems—for ex-
ample, the difficulty of distinguishing primary rewards from other types—
the image of society presented by Homans is provocative. It can perhaps
lead Homans to a fruitful strategy for developing a theory of exchange
relations.
Peter M. Blau has been one of the most productive social theorists over
the last three decades. In his early work on informal processes within
bureaucracies, he noted how frequently employees exchanged assistance
with their work for respect, information for social approval, and other
processes of giving and receiving nonmaterial rewards. Yet, in looking
back on this early empirical work, he recently remarked, “I was not aware,
or did not remember, that conceptions of social exchange had been used
by many others before, from Aristotle to Mauss.”! In some ways, I think
that this ignorance may have been an advantage because in rediscovering
exchange processes, Blau created a constructive blend of exchange, func-
tional, and dialectical conflict theories. And although Blau has in recent
years abandoned his exchange approach for another theoretical strategy
(see Chapter 20),? I think that his exchange orientation is still very im-
portant and worthy of a more detailed analysis.®
261
262 CHAPTER 12 / THE STRUCTURAL EXCHANGE THEORY OF PETER M. BLAU
*Talcott Parsons, The Social System (New York: Free Press, 1951), especially pp. 1-
200.
7Blau, Exchange and Power, p. 6.
*‘Thid., p. 88.
*Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1937).
264 CHAPTER 12 / THE STRUCTURAL EXCHANGE THEORY OF PETER M. BLAU
e
ee
I should note that this marginal utility principle is the same as Homans’s
axiom on “deprivation-satiation.” For both Blau and Homans, then, ac-
tors will seek alternative rewards until their level of satiation declines.
Blau’s exchange model is vitally concerned with the conditions under
which conflict and change occur in social systems, and so, these justice
principles become crucial generalizations. As I will document shortly, the
deprivations arising from violating the norms of fair exchange can lead
to retaliation against violators.
Proposition V on imbalance completes my listing of Blau’s abstract
laws. For Blau, as for all exchange theorists, established exchange relations
are seen to involve costs or alternative rewards foregone. Since most actors
must engage in more than one exchange relation, the balance and sta-
bilization of one exchange relation is likely to create imbalance and strain
in other necessary exchange relations. For Blau, social life is thus filled
with dilemmas in which people must successively trade off stability and
balance in one exchange relation for strain in others as they attempt to
cope with the variety of relations they must maintain. In his last chapter
on institutionalization, Homans hinted at this principle when he em-
phasized that, in satisfying some needs, institutional arrangements deny
others and thereby set into motion a perpetual dialectic between dominant
institutions and change-oriented acts of innovation and deviance.’ It is
from this concluding insight of Homans into the dialectical nature of
relationships between established social patterns and forces of opposition
that Blau is to begin his analysis of exchange in social life. Indeed, we
might even term Blau’s approach a dialectical exchange theory because
inherent in exchange relations are potentials for conflict. Indeed, as I
have indicated in the last chapter, Marxian conflict theory and exchange
theory have much in common, for both are concerned with the conditions
under which actors feel deprived of expected rewards and are mobilized
to redress their grievances.
"Homans, Social Behavior, pp. 390-98 (1961 ed.); pp. 366-73 (1974 ed.).
BASIC EXCHANGE PROCESSES IN SOCIAL LIFE 267
presentation of self so as to convince each other that they have the valued
qualities others appear to desire. In adjusting role behaviors in an effort
to impress others with the resources that they have to offer, people operate
under the principle of reciprocity, for by indicating that one possesses
valued qualities, each person is attempting to establish a claim on others
for the receipt of rewards from them. All exchange operates under the
presumption that people who bestow rewards will receive rewards in turn —
as payment for value received.
Actors attempt to impress each other through competition in which
they reveal the rewards they have to offer in an effort to force others, in
accordance with the norm of reciprocity, to reciprocate with an even more
valuable reward. Social life is thus rife with people’s competitive efforts
to impress each other and thereby extract valuable rewards. But as in-
teraction proceeds, it inevitably becomes evident to the parties to an
exchange that some people have more valued resources to offer than others,
putting them in a unique position to extract rewards from all others who
value the resources that they have to offer.
It is at this point in exchange relations that groups of individuals
become differentiated in terms of the resources that they possess and the
kinds of reciprocal demands they can make on others. Blau then asks an
analytical question: What generic types or classes of rewards can those
with resources extract in return for bestowing their valued resources upon
others? Blau conceptualizes four general classes of such rewards: money,
social approval, esteem or respect, and compliance. Although Blau does
not make full use of his categorization of rewards, he offers some sugges-
tive clues about how these categories can be incorporated into abstract
theoretical statements. Let me elaborate upon his argument.
Blau first ranks these generalized reinforcers in terms of their value
in exchange relations. In most social relations, money is an inappropriate
reward and hence is the least valuable reward. Social approval is an ap-
propriate reward, but for most humans it is not very valuable, thus forcing
those who derive valued services to offer with great frequency the more
valuable reward of esteem or respect to those providing valued services.
In many situations, the services offered can command no more than re-
spect and esteem from those receiving the benefit of these services. At
times, however, the services offered are sufficiently valuable to require
those receiving them to offer, in accordance with the principles of reci-
procity and justice, the most valuable class of rewards—compliance with
one’s requests.
When people can extract compliance in an exchange relationship, they
have power. They have the capacity to withhold rewarding services and
thereby punish or inflict heavy costs on those who might not comply. To
conceptualize the degree of power possessed by individuals, Blau for-
mulates four general propositions that determine the capacity of powerful
268 CHAPTER 12 / THE STRUCTURAL EXCHANGE THEORY OF PETER M. BLAU
TABLE 12-2 Blau’s Conditions for the Differentiation of Power in Social Exchange
|. The fewer services people can supply in return for the receipt of particularly
valued services, the more those providing these particularly valued services can
extract compliance.
ll. The fewer alternative sources of rewards people have, the more those providing
valuable services can extract compliance.
lll. The less those receiving valuable services from particular individuals can
employ physical force and coercion, the more tnose providing the services can
extract compliance.
IV. The less those receiving the valuable services can do without them, the more
those providing the services can extract compliance.
*Tbid., p. 208.
270 CHAPTER 12 / THE STRUCTURAL EXCHANGE THEORY OF PETER M. BLAU
*Thid., p. 221.
As will be recalled from Chapter 11, these processes were insightfully described by
George C. Homans in The Human Group (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1950).
BASIC EXCHANGE PROCESSES IN SOCIAL LIFE 271
lectively, the greater is the sense of deprivation and the greater is the
potential for opposition. While he does not explicitly state the case, he
appears to hold that increasing ideological codification of deprivations,
the formation of group solidarity, and the emergence of conflict as a way
of life will increase the intensity of the opposition—that is, members’
emotional involvement in and commitment to opposition to those with
power. I think that these propositions offer a suggestive lead for concep-
tualizing inherent processes of opposition in exchange relations. More-
over, unlike Dahrendorf’s dialectical model, Blau’s scheme presents the-
oretical insight into how the creation of relations of authority can also
cause opposition. Indeed, I see Blau’s conceptualization of the processes
of institutionalization and conflict in terms of the same abstract exchange
principles as representing a significant improvement over Dahrendorf’s
model, which failed to specify either how institutionalized patterns of
latent conflicts first emerge in authority systems. I also believe that Blau’s
presentation represents an improvement over Homans’s analysis of in-
stitutionalization and of the inherent conftict between the institutional
and subinstitutional. In Blau’s scheme there is a more adequate concep-
tualization of the process of institutionalization of those power relations
from which opposition, innovation, and deviance ultimately spring.
274 CHAPTER 12 / THE STRUCTURAL EXCHANGE THEORY OF PETER M. BLAU
of the general classes and types of media differ, each is concerned with
how social relationships utilize in varying contexts distinctive symbols,
not only to establish the respective values of actions among exchange
units but also to specify just how the exchange should be conducted. For
without shared values, exchange is tied to the direct interpersonal inter-
actions of individuals. Since virtually all known social systems involve
indirect exchange relations among various types of social units—from
individuals and groups to organizations and communities—it is necessary
to conceptualize just how this can occur. For Blau, mediating values are
a critical condition for the development of complex exchange systems.
Without them, social organization beyond face-to-face interaction would
not be possible.
*Ibid., p. 278.
*Tbid.
*~Ibid., p. 279. It is of interest to note that Blau implicitly defines institutions in terms
of their functions for the social whole. Although these functions are not made explicit, they
are similar to Parsons’s requisites. For example, integrative institutions appear to meet
needs for latency; distributive institutions, for adaptation; and organizational institutions,
for integration and goal attainment.
278 CHAPTER 12 / THE STRUCTURAL EXCHANGE THEORY OF PETER M. BLAU
*Tbid., p. 284.
*Tbid., p. 285.
*“Thid.
*Tbid.
*Thid.
280 CHAPTER 12 / THE STRUCTURAL EXCHANGE THEORY OF PETER M. BLAU
*[bid., p. 301. Such a position is inevitable in light of Blau’s explicitly stated belief that
“our society is in need of fundamental reforms” (Blau, “Dialectical Sociology,” p. 184).
*Blau, “Dialectical Sociology,” p. 187; Blau, Exchange and Power, pp. 301-9.
282 CHAPTER 12 / THE STRUCTURAL EXCHANGE THEORY OF PETER M. BLAU
MICROEXCHANGE
Strains toward integration
(creation of organized
collectivity)
1. Legitimation of
inf power through
authority
Exchange of ——» Competition for ———» Differentiation 2. Subordinate Social —
j —+s
eg 1. Esteem social control attraction
pre ee
1. Impression 2. Power pees SE
among
*However, Blau recognizes that high rates of mobility in a society can also increase the
sense of relative deprivation of those who are denied opportunities for advancement, thereby
making them likely constituents of an opposition organization.
THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF SOCIETY 283
MACROEXCHANGE
Potential conflict
—_ . Norms of
“fair
s exchange”
2. Political
authority
3. Laws
that conflict and opposition are regenerative forces in societies that “con-
stitute countervailing forces against . . . institutional rigidities, rooted in
vested powers as well as traditional values, and . . . [that] are essential for
speeding social change.’’*°
In sum, then, Blau has offered a most varied image of society. By
incorporating—al' eit in an unsystematic manner—the fruitful leads of
sociology’s other dominant conceptual perspectives, Blau has indeed of-
fered a suggestive theoretical prolegomenon that can serve as a guide to
more explicit theoretical formulations. I have summarized both the micro-
and macroprocesses of this prolegomenon in Figure 12-1. As is evident,
Blau has synthesized several theoretical traditions, and in so doing, he
offers something for everyone. For the functionalist, Blau offers the con-
cept of mediating values, types of institutions, and the counterpart of
mechanisms of socialization and control that operate to maintain ma-
crosocial wholes. For the conflict theorist, Blau presents a dialectical-
conflict perspective emphasizing the inevitable forces of opposition in
relations of power and authority. For those concerned with interactions
among individuals, Blau’s analysis of elementary exchange processes places
considerable emphasis on the actions of people in interaction. And for
the critic of Homans’s reductionism, Blau provides an insightful portrayal
of exchanges among emergent social structures, which leaves the integrity
of sociological theorizing intact.
In offering a theoretical resting place for the major perspectives in
sociology, I think that Blau provides a useful example of how sociological
theorizing should proceed: rather than becoming bogged down in contro-
versies and debates among proponents of various theoretical positions, it
is much wiser to borrow and integrate the useful concepts and assumptions
of diverse perspectives. In offering this alternative to continued debate,
Blau left a number of theoretical issues unresolved, but I think that the
most important one is the question of how micro- and macroprocesses
can be incorporated into one theoretical approach.*! This issue is obscured
by the insightfulness of his synthesis, and yet its resolution constitutes
a critical next step in his theoretical strategy. And I suspect that the
failure to resolve it is what caused Blau to abandon this exchange approach.
1For some basic references on network analysis, see Jeremy F. Boissevain and J. Clyde
Mitchell, eds., Network Analysis (The Hague, Holland: Mouton Publishers, 1973); Paul
Holland and Samuel Leinhardt, eds., Perspectives on Social Network Research (New York:
287
288 CHAPTER 13 / THE EXCHANGE NETWORK THEORY OF RICHARD EMERSON
Emerson’s death at the peak of his career was thus a great tragedy,
but fortunately, his colleague and collaborator, Karen S. Cook, has con-
tinued to explore this blending of exchange theory and network analysis.®
In my review of this promising approach, I will emphasize the basic ideas
in Emerson’s work, but I will also indicate some of the ways that Cook
has extended the theoretical foundation provided by Emerson.
Theory in Sociology, ed. R. Hamblin (New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Books, 1977).
Other more conceptual works include “Operant Psychology and Exchange Theory,” in Be-
havioral Sociology, ed. R. Burgess and D. Bushell (New York: Columbia University Press,
1969) and “Social Exchange Theory,” in Annuai Review of Sociology, ed. A. Inkeles and
N. Smelser, 2 (1976), pp. 335-62.
*For example, see Karen S. Cook and Richard Emerson, ‘Power, Equity and Commit-
ment in Exchange Networks,” American Sociological Review 43 (1978), pp. 712-39; Karen
S. Cook, Richard M. Emerson, Mary R. Gillmore, and Toshio Yamagish, “The Distribution
of Power in Exchange Networks,” American Journal of Sociology 89 (1983), pp. 275-305;
Karen S. Cook and Richard M. Emerson, “Exchange Networks and the Analysis of Complex
Organizations,” Research in the Sociology of Organizations 3 (1984), pp: 1-30. See also
Karen S. Cook, “Exchange and Power in Networks of Interorganizational Relations,” So-
ciological Quarterly 18 (Winter 1977), pp. 66-82; ““Network Structures from an Exchange
Perspective,” in Social Structure and Network Analysis, ed. P. Marsden and N. Lin; and
Karen S. Cook and Karen A. Hegtvedt, “Distributive Justice, Equity, and Equality,” Amer-
ican Sociological Review 9 (1983), pp. 217-41.
2390 CHAPTER 13 / THE EXCHANGE NETWORK THEORY OF RICHARD EMERSON
7There are, of course, notable exceptions to this statement. See, for examples, Alfred
Kuhn, Unified Social Science (Homewood, IIl.: Dorsey Press, 1975) and the articles in
Berger, Zelditch, and Anderson, Sociological Theory in Progress.
EMERSON’S EXCHANGE NETWORK APPROACH 291
Power: The degree to which one actor can force another actor to
incur costs in an exchange relation.
Resources: Any reward that an actor can use in an exchange relation
with other actors.
These concepts are the givens of any existing exchange relation. Thus,
in contrast to Homans’s approach, social structure is not a theoretical
given. Instead, behavioral dispositions are the givens, and it is social
structure that is to be explained.
Third, in accordance with the emphasis on the structure of the ex-
change relation, as opposed to the characteristics of the actors, the con-
cepts of (a) dependence, (b) power, and (c) balance in exchange relations
become central. The key questions in Emerson’s scheme thus revolve
around how dependence, power, and balance in exchange relations help
explain the operation of more complex social patterns.
Fourth, actors are viewed as either individuals or collective units. The
same processes in exchange .elations are presumed to apply to both in-
dividuals and collectivi:ies of individuals, thus obviating many problems
in the micro versus macro schism in sociological theorizing. This emphasis
is possible when attention is shifted away from the attributes of actors
to the form of their exchange relationship.
Thus, while this partial list of Emerson’s concepts appears to be
similar to that developed by Homans and other behavioristically oriented
exchange theorists, | see an important shift in emphasis from concern
with the values and other cognitive properties of actors to a concern with
the structure of an exchange relation. This concern with structure takes
as a given the flow of valued resources among those involved in the ex-
change. Theoretical attention then focuses on the structural attributes of
the exchange relation and on the processes that maintain or change the
structural form of an ongoing exchange relationship.
have a power advantage is to use it, with the result that actor A forces
increasing costs on actor B within the exchange relationship.
In Emerson’s view, a power advantage represents an imbalanced ex-
change relation. A basic proposition in Emerson’s scheme is that, over
time, imbalanced exchange relations tend toward balance. He visualized
this process as occurring through a number of “balancing operations”’:
1. A decrease in the value for actor B of reinforcers, or rewards, from
actor A.
2. An increase in the number of alternative sources for the reinforcers,
or rewards, provided to B by A.
3. An increase in the value of reinforcers provided by B for A.
4. A reduction in the alternative sources for the rewards provided by
B for A.
These balancing operations are, I think, somewhat similar to the
propositions enumerated by Blau on the conditions for differentiation of
power (see Table 12-2). But in contrast to Blau’s emphasis on the inherent
and incessant dialectic for change resulting from power imbalances, Emer-
son stressed that through at least one of these four balancing operations
the dependency of B and A on each other for rewards will reach an equi-
librium. Thus, exchange transactions reveal differences in power that,
over time, tend toward balance. Naturally, in complex exchange relations
involving many actors, A, B, C, D, ..., n, the basic processes of depen-
dence, power, and balance will ebb and flow as new actors and new rein-
forcers or resources enter the exchange relations. |
FIGURE 13-1
el
meet
A Nademcees
—————— B>
1.3 argues that A will use its power advantage and increase costs for each
B. Corollary 1.1 indicates that with each increment in costs for the Bs,
their behaviors will vary and they will seek alternative rewards from A),
A,,..., A, If another A can be found, then the structure of the network
would change.
Emerson developed additional corollaries and theorems to account
for the various ways this unilateral monopoly can become balanced. For
instance, if no A,, Ag, . . .. A, exist and Bs cannot communicate with each
other, the following corollary would apply (termed by Emerson, Exploi-
tation Type I):
Corollary 1.3.1: The more an exchange relation between A and
multiple Bs approximates a unilateral monopoly, the more addi-
tional resources each B will introduce into the exchange relation,
with A’s resource utilization remaining constant or decreasing.
Emerson saw this adaptation as short-lived, since the network will
become even more unbalanced. Assuming that Bs can survive as an entity
without resources from A, then Theorem 8 applies (termed by Emerson,
Exploitation Type II):
Theorem 8: The more an exchange relation between A and multiple
Bs approximates a unilateral monopoly, the less valuable to Bs the
resources provided by A across continuing transactions. (From Cor-
ollary 1.3, Theorem 4, and Corollary 4.1).
This theorem thus predicts that balancing operation 1—a decrease in
the value of the reward for those at a power disadvantage—will operate
to balance a unilateral monopoly where no alternative sources of rewards
exist and where Bs cannot effectively communicate.
Other balancing operations are possible, if other conditions exist. If
Bs can communicate, they might form a coalition (balancing operation
4) and require A to balance exchanges with a united coalition of Bs. If
one B can provide a resource not possessed by the other Bs, then a division
cf labor among Bs (operations 3 and 4) would emerge. Or if another source
of resources, A,, can be found (operation 2), then the power advantage of
A, is decreased. Each of these possible changes will occur under varying
conditions, but Corollary 1.3.1 and Theorem 8 provide a reason for the
initiation of changes—a reason derived from basic principles of operant
psychology.
FIGURE 13-2
A
.
ee
A a changes to: Ae
B3 a
FIGURE 13-3
ea oe oe
Closed circle Closed network
A, —————— Ap en As
A3 ———————_- 44 A3 ————_- 44
FIGURE 13-4
Ay
A2
A3
FIGURE 13-5
——— Ao
Upper
social class
As 6
Ag A4
Lower
social class
Died stern Ag
FIGURE 13-6
As Ag Az
The critical point here is that Cook and her associates are trying to
use the basic principles developed by Emerson to address more complex
network systems. In so doing, they can explain the process of centrality
(and perhaps other network properties) in terms of theoretical deductions.
Up to this point, network analysis has typically described centrality using
various measures, whereas the Emerson-Cook approach allows these net-
work properties to be explained in terms of an abstract theoretical
proposition. .
"Again, let me emphasize that others are also working with this approach. See, in
pa.ticular, the references to Willer cited in note 4.
EXCHANGE NETWORK ANALYSIS: A CONCLUDING COMMENT 305
:
+ a 4
ceptiagsicet
sarited gules:
r weeps cM eerie
cate ee, om
af
PART FOUR |
Interactionist Theory
307
CHAPTER 14
Early Interactionism
and Phenomenology
|!
I think that some of the most intriguing questions in social theory concern
the relationships between society and the individual. In what ways does
one mirror the other? How does society shape individuals, or how do
individuals create and maintain and change society? How are society and
the personality of individuals interrelated and yet separate emergenu phe-
nomena? Indeed, as I have already emphasized for virtually all theorists
in the previous chapters, the issue of micro versus macro sociological
analysis boils down to a question of the relationship between the prop-
erties of individuals and interaction, on the one side, and those of social
structure, on the other.
It was near the close of the 19th century that the grand analytical
schemes of Marx, Durkheim, Spencer, and other Europeans were sup-
plemented by a concern for the specific processes that link individuals to
one another and to society. Instead of focusing on macrostructures and
processes, such as evolution, class conflict, and the nature of the body
social, attention shifted to the study of processes of social interaction and
their consequences for the individual and the society. And out of this
shift in concern came a variety of interactionist theories. For the most
part, the theory is American, but we will need to be aware of important
European contributions to the emergence of interactionism.
‘William James, The Principles of Psychology (New York: Henry Holt, 1890), pp. 292-
99 of vol. 1.
*Ibid., p. 294.
EARLY AMERICAN INSIGHTS 311
’Charles Horton Cooley, Human Nature and the Social Order (New York: Charles Scrib-
ner’s Sons, 1902) and Social Organization: A Study of the Larger Mind (New York: Charles
Scribner’s Sons, 1916).
312 CHAPTER 14 / EARLY INTERACTIONISM AND PHENOMENOLOGY
‘John Dewey, Human Nature and Human Conduet (New York: Henry Holt, 1922), p.
yea —" statement of these ideas, see John Dewey, Psychology (New York: Harper
w, 1886).
EARLY AMERICAN INSIGHTS 313
’Mead’s most important sociological ideas can be found in the published lecture notes
of his students. His most important exposition of interactionism is found in his Mind, Self,
and Society, ed. C. W. Morris (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1934). Other useful
sources include George Herbert Mead, Selected Writings (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964);
and Anselm Strauss, ed., George Herbert Mead on Social Psychology (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1964). For excellent secondary sources on the thought of Mead, see Tam-
otsu Shibutani, Society and Personality: An Interactionist Approach (Englewood Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1962); Anselm Strauss, Mirrors and Masks: The Search for Identity
The
(Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1959); Bernard N. Meltzer, “Mead’s Social Psychology,” in
Social Psychology of George Herbert Mead (Ann Arbor, Mich.: Center for Sociological Re-
search, 1964), pp. 10-31; Jonathan H. Turner, “Returning to Social Physics: Illustrations
H.
from George Herbert Mead,” Perspectives in Social Theory 2 (1981). Also see Jonathan
of Sociological Theory (Homewood, IIL.:
Turner and Leonard Beeghley, The Emergence
Dorsey Press, 1981).
314 CHAPTER 14 / EARLY INTERACTIONISM AND PHENOMENOLOGY
hearsal of action can take on a new level of efficiency, since actors can
better gauge the consequences of their actions for others and thereby
increase the probability of cooperative interaction.
Thus, when an organism develops the capacity (1) to understand
conventional gestures, (2) to employ these gestures to take the role of
others, and (3) to imaginatively rehearse alternative lines of action, Mead
believed such an organism to possess “mind.”
Self. Drawing from James and Cooley, Mead stressed that just as
humans can designate symbolically other actors in the environment, so
they can symbolically represent themselves as an object. The interpret-
ation of gestures, then, can not only facilitate human cooperation, but it
can also serve as the basis for self-assessment and evaluation. This ca-
pacity to derive images of oneself as an object of evaluation in interaction
is dependent upon the processes of mind. What Mead saw as significant
about this process is that, as organisms mature, the transitory “self-im-
ages” derived from specific others in each interactive situation eventually
become crystallized into a more or less stabilized “self-conception’’ of
oneself as a certain type of object. With these self-conceptions, individ-
uals’ actions take on consistency, since they are now mediated through
a coherent and stable set of attitudes, dispositions, or meanings about
oneself as a certain type of person.
Mead chose to highlight three stages in the development of self, each
stage marking not only a change in the kinds of transitory self-images an
individual can derive from role-taking but also an increasing crystalli-
zation of a more stabilized self-conception. The initial stage of role-taking
in which self-images can be derived is termed play. In play, infant or-
ganisms are capable of assuming the perspective of only a limited number
of others, at first only one or two. Later, by virtue of biological maturation
and practice at role-taking, the maturing organism becomes capable of
taking the role of several others engaged in organized activity. Mead
termed this stage the game because it designates the capacity to derive
multiple self-images from, and to cooperate with, a group of individuals
engaged in some coordinated activity. (Mead typically illustrated this
stage by giving the example of a baseball game in which all individuals
must symbolically assume the role of all others on the team in order to
participate effectively.) The final stage in the development of self occurs
when an individual can take the role of the “generalized other” or ‘““com-
munity of attitudes” evident in a society. At this stage, individuals are
seen as capable of assuming the overall perspective of a community, or
general beliefs, values, and norms. This means that humans can both (1)
increase the appropriateness of their responses to others with whom they
must interact and (2) expand their evaluative self-images from the ex-
pectations of specific others to the standards and perspective of the broade1
community. Thus, it is this ever-increasing capacity to take roles witk
316 CHAPTER 14 / EARLY INTERACTIONISM AND PHENOMENOLOGY
*For a more detailed analysis, see Jonathan H. Turner, “A Note on G. H. Mead’s Be-
havioristic Theory of Social Structure,” Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 12 (July
1982), pp. 213-22.
™ead, Mind, Self, and Society, p. 254.
‘Ibid., pp. 256-57.
EARLY AMERICAN INSIGHTS 317
ities. ... [But] there is no necessary or inevitable reason why social insti-
tutions should be oppressive or rigidly conservative, or why they should not
rather be, as many are, flexible and progressive, fostering individuality rather
than discouraging it.®
the concepts of mind and self denote crucial processes through which this
dependency is maintained, they do not allow for the analysis of variations
in patterns of social organization and in the various ways individuals are
implicated in these patterns. To note that society is coordinated activity
and is maintained or changed through the role-taking and the self-as-
sessment processes of individuals offers only a broad conceptual portrait
of the linkages between the individual and society. Indeed, Mead’s picture
of society does not indicate how variable types of social organization
reciprocally interact with variable properties of self and mind. Thus, in
the end, Mead’s concepts appeared to emphasize that society shapes mind
and self, whereas mind and self affect society—a simple but profound
observation for the times but one that needed supplementation.
The difficult task of filling in the details of this broad portrait began
only four decades ago, as researchers and theorists began to encounter
the vague and circular nature of Mead’s conceptual perspective. The initial
efforts at documenting more precisely the points of articulation between
society and the individual led to attempts at formulating a series of con-
cepts that could expose the basic units from which society is constructed.
In this way, the linkages between society and the individual could be more
adequately conceptualized.
"Robert E. Park, “Behind Our Masks,” Survey Graphic 56 (May 1926), p. 135. For a
convenient summary of the thrust of early research efforts in role theory, see
Ralph H.
Turner, “Social Roles: Sociological Aspects,” Jnternational Encyclopaedia of the Social
Sciences (New York: Macmillan, 1968).
EARLY AMERICAN INSIGHTS 319
12Robert E. Park, Society (New York: Free Press, 1955), pp. 285-86.
18{ndeed, Park studied briefly with Simmel in Berlin and apparéntly acquired insight
into Simmel’s study of the individual and the web of group affiliations (see later discussion).
Coupled with his exposure to William James at Harvard, who also stressed the multiple
sources of self, it is clear that Mead’s legacy was supplemented by Simmel and James through
the work of Robert Park.
“Jacob Moreno, Who Shall Survive (Washington, D.C., 1934); rev. ed. (New York:
Beacon House, 1953).
320 CHAPTER 14 / EARLY INTERACTIONISM AND PHENOMENOLOGY
The more macro-oriented work of Max Weber and Emile Durkheim be-
came increasingly concerned with meaning and how society “sets inside”
the individual. But neither Weber nor Durkheim were as interactionistic
in approach as Georg Simmel. But in the end, the main theoretical con-
tribution to interactionism from Europe comes from philosophical phen-
omenology. And so, I will briefly summarize Weber’s, Durkheim’s, and
Simmel’s interactionist ideas; and then, I will turn to the early pheno-
menologists Edmund Husserl and Alfred Schutz.
%Georg Simmel, “Sociability,” in The Sociology of Georg Simmel, ed. K. H. Wolff (New
York: Free Press, 1950), pp. 40-57. For an excellent secondary account of Simmel’s signif-
icance for interactionism, see Randall Collins and Michael Makowsky, The Discovery of
Society (New York: Random House, 1972), pp. 138=42.
“Conflict and the Web of Group Affiliations, trans. R. Bendix (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press,
1955; originally published in 1922).
‘8Tbid., p. 141.
322 CHAPTER 14 / EARLY INTERACTIONISM AND PHENOMENOLOGY
mile Durkheim, The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (New York: Free Press, 1954:
originally published in 1912),
Randall Collins, Conflict Sociology (New York: Academic Press, 1975) develops this
idea. See Chapter 21.
EARLY EUROPEAN INSIGHTS vee .
shift from macro to micro theorizing was occurring, even among the most
avowed macrotheorist, Emile Durkheim.
European Phenomenology
Phenomenology began as the project of the German philosopher Edmund
Husserl (1859-1938). In his hands, I think, this project showed few signs
21Max Weber, Basic Concepts in Sociology (New York: Citadel Press, 1964), p. 29.
Max Weber, The Theory of Social and Economic Organization (New York: Free Press,
1947; originally published after Weber’s death), p. 88.
For some readable, general references on phenomenology, see George Psathas, ed.,
OGY
324 CHAPTER 14 / EARLY INTERACTIONISM AND PHENOMENOL
Phenomenological Sociology (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1973); Richard M. Zaner, The
Way of Phenomenology: Criticism as a Philosophical Discipline (New York: Pegasus, 1970);
Peter L. Berger and Thomas Luckman, The Social Construction of Reality (Garden City,
N.Y.: Doubleday Publishing, 1966); Herbert Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement,
vols. 1 and 2, 2d ed. (The Hague, Holland: Martinus Nijhoff, 1969); Hans P. Neisser, “The
Phenomenological Approach in Social Science,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Re-
search 20 (1959), pp. 198-212; Stephen Strasser, Phenomenology and the Human Sciences
(Pittsburgh, Pa.: Duquesne University Press, 1963); and Maurice Natanson, ed., Pheno-
menology and the Social Sciences (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1973);
oe Lauer, Phenomenology: Its Genesis and Prospect (New York: Harper Torchbooks,
out
brought Husserl back to his original problem: How do humans break
of their lifeworld and ascertain what is real? If people’s lifeworld structures
human
their consciousness and their actions, how is an objective science of
behavior and organization possible? These questions led Husser! to crit-
icize what he termed naturalistic-science, or the position that I advocated
in Chapter 1.
For basic ideas of Alfred Schutz, see his The Phenomenology of the Social World
(Evanston, IIl.: Northwestern University Press, 1967; originally published in 1932); Collected
Papers, vols. 1, 2, 3 (The Hague, Holland: Martinus Nijhoff, 1964, 1970, and 1971, respec-
tively). For excellent secondary analyses, see Maurice Natanson, “Alfred Schutz on Socia!
Reality and Social Science,” Social Research 35 (Summer 1968), pp. 217-44.
279Schutz, The Phenomenology of the Social World, 1921.
328 CHAPTER 14 / EARLY INTERACTIONISM AND PHENOMENOLOGY
to note that the basic critique turns on Weber’s failure to use his verstehen
method and to explore why, and through what processes, actors come to
share common meanings. In Schutz’s eye, Weber simply assumes that
actors share subjective meanings, leading Schutz to ask: Why and how
do actors come to acquire common subjective states in a situation? How
do they create a common view of the world? This is the problem of
“intersubjectivity,” and it is central to Schutz’s intellectual scheme. As
Richard D. Zaner summarizes:
How is it possible that although I cannot live in your seeing of things,
cannot feel your love and hatred, cannot have an immediate and direct per-
ception of your mental life as it is for you—how is it that I can nevertheless
share your thoughts, feelings, and attitudes? For Schutz the “problem” of
intersubjectivity is here encountered in its full force.
G. H. Mead and W. I. Thomas. But I am not sure that Mead and other
Chicago School interactionists exerted great influence on Schutz, who did
devote some attention to symbolic interactionism.” Indeed, their influ-
ence may have been subtle, if not subliminal. The early symbolic inter-
actionist’s concern with the process of constructing shared meanings was,
of course, similar to Schutz’s desire to understand intersubjectivity. Schutz
thus found immediate affinity with W. I. Thomas’s “definition of the
situation,” since this concept emphasizes that actors construct orienta-
tions to, and dispositions to act in, situations. Moreover, Thomas’s rec-
ognition that definitions of situations are learned from past experiences
while being altered in present interactions appears to have influenced
Schutz’s conceptualization of the process of intersubjectivity. Mead’s rec-
ognition that mind is a social process, arising out of interaction and yet
facilitating interaction, probably had considerable appeal for Schutz. But
if there was any direct influence from Chicago, I think it was Mead’s
concept of role-taking. For Schutz became vitally concerned with the
process whereby actors come to know each other’s role and to typify each
other as likely to behave in certain ways. Additionally, Mead’s concept
of the generalized other may have influenced Schutz in that actors are
seen as sharing a “community of attitudes” —or, in other words, common
subjective states. Yet, although there is considerable affinity and perhaps
some cross-fertilization between early symbolic interactionists’ concep-
tualizations and Schutz’s phenomenology, Schutz was to inspire a line of
sociological inquiry that often challenges the interactionism initiated by
Mead.
Having reviewed some of the intellectual influences on Schutz, let me
now summarize his scheme and indicate some of its implications for
sociological theorizing. Unfortunately, Schutz died just as he was begin-
ning a systematic synthesis of his ideas, and as a result, only a somewhat
fragmented but suggestive framework is evident in his collective work.
But his early analysis of Weber, Husserl, and interactionism led to a
concern with a number of key issues: (1) How do actors create a common
subjective world? (2) What implications does this creation have for how
social order is maintained?
All humans, Schutz asserted, carry in their minds rules, social recipes,
conceptions of appropriate conduct, and other information that allows
them to act in their social world. Extending Husserl’s concept of lifeworld,
Schutz views the sum of these rules, recipes, conceptions, and information
as the individual’s “stock knowledge at hand.” Such stock knowledge gives
people a frame of reference or orientation with which they can interpret
events as they pragmatically act on the world around them.
Several features of this stock knowledge at hand are given particular
emphasis by Schutz:
‘Bernard N. Meltzer and Jerome W. Petras, “The Chicago and Iowa Schools of Symbolic
Interactionism,” in Human Nature and Collective Behavior, ed. T. Shibutani (Englewood
Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1970).
333
334 CHAPTER 15 / THE SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM OF BLUMER AND KUHN
SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM:
POINTS OF CONVERGENCE
Before turning to the points of divergence between the Iowa and Chicago
Schools, let me review the common legacy of Mead’s assumptions that
all symbolic interactionists employ. These points of convergence are, I
believe, what make symbolic interactionism a distinctive theoretical
perspective.
2Jonathan H. Turner, “The Rise of Scientific Sociology,” Science 227 (March 15, 1985);
see also, Martin Bulmer, The Chicago School of Sociology (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1984) and Lester R. Kurtz, Evaluating Chicago Sociology (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1984).
3For examples, consult Jerome G. Manis and Bernard N. Meltzer, eds., Symbolic Inter-
action: A Reader in Social Psychology (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1972); J. Cardwell, Social
Psychology: A Symbolic Interactionist Approach (Philadelphia: F. A. Davis Co., 1971); Alfred
Lindesmith and Anselm Strauss, Social Psychology (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston,
1968); Arnold Rose, ed., Human Behavior and Social Process (Boston: Houghton Mifflin,
1962); Tamotsu Shibutani, Society and Personality (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1961); C. K. Warriner, The Emergence of Society (Homewood, IIl.: Dorsey Press, 1970);
Gregory Stone and H. Farberman, eds., Symbolic Interaction: A Reader in Social Psychology
(Walthum, Mass.: Xerox Learning Systems, 1970); John P. Hewitt, Self and Society: A
Symbolic Interactionist Social Psychology (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1976); Robert H. Laver
and Warren H. Handel, Social Psychology: The Theory and Application of Symbolic In-
teractionism (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1977); Sheldon Stryker, Symbolic Interactionism
(Menlo Park, Calif.: Benjamin-Cummings, 1980); Clark McPhail, “The Problems and Pros-
pects of Behavioral Perspectives,” The American Sociologist 16 (1981), pp. 172-74
SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM: POINTS OF CONVERGENCE
335
Symbolic Communication
-Humans use symbols to communicate with each other. By virtue of their
capacity to agree upon the meaning of vocal and bodily gestures, humans
can effectively communicate. Symbolic communication is, of course, ex-
tremely complex, since people use more than word or language symbols
in communication. They also use facial gestures, voice tones, body coun-
tenance, and other symbolic gestures in which there is common meaning
and understanding. |
The following comparison draws heavily from Meltzer’s and Petras’s ‘““The Chicago and
Iowa Schools” but extends their analysis by drawing from the following works of Blumer
and Kuhn. For Blumer, Symbolic Interactionism: Perspective and Method (Englewood Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1969); ‘Comment on ‘Parsons as a Symbolic Interactionist,’”’ Socio-
logical Inquiry 45 (Winter 1975), pp. 59-62. For Kuhn, “Major Trends in Symbolic Inter-
action Theory in the Past Twenty-Five Years,” Sociological Quarterly 5 (Winter 1964), pp.
61-84; “The Reference Group Reconsidered,” Sociological Quarterly 5 (Winter 1964), pp.
6-21; “Factors in Personality: Socio-Cultural Determinants as Seen through the Amish,”
in Aspects of Culture and Personality, ed. F. L. Kittsu (New York: Abelard-Schuman, 1954);
“Self-attitudes by Age, Sex, and Professional Training,” in Symbolic Interaction, ed. G.
Stone and H. Farberman, pp. 424-36; T. S. McPartland, ‘““An Empirical Investigation of
Self-Attitude,” American Sociological Review 19 (February 1954), pp. 68-76; “Family Impact
on Personality,” in Problems in Social Psychology, ed. J. E. Hulett and R. Stagner (Urbana,
Ill.: University of Illinois, 1953); C. Addison Hickman, Individuals, Groups, and Economic
Behavior (New York: Dryden Press, 1956).
338 CHAPTER 15 / THE SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM OF BLUMER AND KUHN
As self theory views the individual, he derives his plans of action from the
roles he plays and the statuses he occupies in the groups with which he feels
identified—his refererce groups. His attitudes toward himself as an object are
the best indexes to these plans of action, and hence to the action itself, in
that they are the anchoring points from which self-evaluations and other-
evaluations are made.!?
18Prominent thinkers leaning toward Blumer’s position include Anselm Strauss, Alfred
Lindesmith, Tamotsu Shibutani, and Ralph Turner. For a critique of Blumer’s use of Mead,
see Clark McPhail and Cynthia Rexroat, “Mead vs. Blumer,” American Sociological Review
44 (1979), pp. 449-67.
4Prominent Iowa School interactionists include Frank Miyamoto, Sanford Dornbusch,
Simon Dinitz, Harry Dick, Sheldon Stryker, and Theodore Sarbin. For a list of studies by
Kuhn’s students, see Harold A. Mulford and Winfield W. Salisbury II, “Self-Conceptions
in a General Population,” Sociological Quarterly 5 (Winter 1964), pp. 35-46. Again, these
individuals and those in note 12 would resist this classification, since none advocate as
extreme a position as Kuhn or Blumer. Yet, the tendency to follow either Kuhn’s or Blumer’s
assumptions is evident in their work and in that of many others.
16, L. Quarantelli and Joseph Cooper, “Self-conceptions and Others: A Further Test of
Meadian Hypotheses,” Sociological Quarterly 7 (Summer 1966), pp. 281-97.
342 CHAPTER 15 / THE SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM OF BLUMER AND KUHN
Instead of going to the empirical social world in the first and last instances,
resort is made instead to a priori theoretical schemes, to sets of unverified
concepts, and to canonized protocols of research procedure. These come to
be the governing agents in dealing with the empirical social world, forcing
research to serve their character and bending the empirical world to their
premises.'®
‘For an interesting discussion of the contrasts between these research strategies, see
Llewellyn Gross, “Theory Construction in Sociology: A Methodological Inquiry,” in Sym-
— on Sociological Theory, ed. L. Gtoss (New York: Harper & Row, 1959), pp. 531-
63.
For an eloquent and reasoned argument in support of Blumer’s position, see Norman
K. Denzin, The Research Act: A Theoretical Introduction to Sociological Methods (C hicago:
Aldine Publishing, 1970), pp. 185-218; and Norman K. Denzin, “Symbolic Interactionism
and Ethnomethodology,” in Understanding Everyday Life: Toward a Reconstruction of
Sociological Knowledge, ed. J. D. Douglas (Chicago: Aldine Publishing, 1970), pp. 259-84.
AREAS OF DISAGREEMENT AND CONTROVERSY 345
self, social act, social object, and reference group.” His most famous mea-
suring instrument—the Twenty Statements Test (TST)—can serve to il-
lustrate his strategy. With the TST, he sought to measure core self—the
more enduring and basic attitudes that people have about themselves—
by assessing people’s answers to the question, “What kind of person are
you?’”4 For example, the most common variant of the TST reads as
follows:
In the spaces below, please give 20 different answers to the question, “Who
Am I?” Give these as if you were giving them to yourself, not to somebody
else. Write fairly rapidly, for the time is limited.
sures that the actual instances denoted by concepts will shift and vary,
thereby defying easy classification through rigid operational definitions.
These facts, Blumer argued, require the use of “sensitizing concepts,”
which, although lacking the precise specification of attributes and events
of definitive concepts, do provide clues and suggestions about where to
look for certain classes of phenomena. As such, sensitizing concepts offer
a general sense of what is relevant and thereby allow investigators to
approach flexibly a shifting empirical world and feel out and pick one’s
way in an unknown terrain. The use of this kind of concept does not
necessarily reflect a lack of rigor in sociological theory but rather a rec-
ognition that if ‘our empirical world presents itself in the form of dis-
tinctive and unique happenings or situations and if we seek through the
direct study of this world to establish classes of objects and relations
between classes, we are ... forced to work with sensitizing concepts.”
The nature of the empirical world may preclude the development of
definitive concepts, but sensitizing concepts can be improved and refined
by flexibly approaching empirical situations denoted by sensitizing con-
cepts and then by assessing how actual events stack up against the con-
cepts. Although the lack of fixed bench marks and definitions makes this
task more difficult for sensitizing concepts than for definitive ones, the
progressive refinement of sensitizing concepts is possible through “careful
and imaginative study of the stubborn world to which such concepts are
addressed.” Furthermore, sensitizing concepts formulated in this way
can be communicated and used to build sociological theory; and although
formal definitions and rigid classifications are not appropriate, sensitizing
concepts can be explicitly communicated through descriptions and illus-
trations of the events to which they pertain.
In sum, the ongoing refinement, formulation, and communication of
sensitizing concepts must inevitably be the building block of sociological
theory. With careful formulation, they can be incorporated into provi-
sional theoretical statements that specify the conditions under which
various types of interaction are likely to occur. In this way, the concepts
of theory will recognize the shifting nature of the social world and thereby
provide a more accurate set of statements about social organization.
The nature of the social world and the type of theory it dictates have
profound implications for just how such theoretical statements are to be
constructed and organized into theoretical formats. Blumer’s emphasis
on the constructed nature of reality and on the types of concepts that
this fact necessitates has led him to emphasize inductive theory construc-
tion. In inductive theory, generic propositions are abstracted from ob-
servations of concrete interaction situations. This emphasis on induction
contrast to Blumer, then, theory for Kuhn was ultimately to form a unified
system from which specific propositions about different aspects or phases
of symbolic interactionism could be derived.
SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM:
A CONCLUDING COMMENT
Blumer’s vision of symbolic interactionism advocates a clear-cut strategy
for building sociological theory. The emphasis on the interpretive, eval-
uative, definitional, and mapping processes of actors has come to dictate
that it is only through induction from these processes that sociological
theory can be built. Further, the ever-shifting nature of these symbolic
processes necessitates that the concepts of sociological theory be sensi-
tizing rather than definitive, with the result that deductive theorizing
should be replaced by an inductive approach. Thus, whether as a preferred
strategy or as a logical necessity, the Blumer interactionist strategy is to
induce generic statements, employing sensitizing concepts, from the on-
going symbolic processes of individuals in concrete interaction situations.
Such a strategy is likely to keep theorizing attuned to the processual
nature of the social world. However, I feel that this approach and, to a
lesser extent, Kuhn’s has not been able to link conceptually the processes
of symbolic interaction to the formation of different patterns of social
organization. Furthermore, the utility of induction from the symbolic
exchanges among individuals for the analysis of interaction among more
macro, collective social units has yet to be demonstrated. Unless these
problems can be resolved, I do not think it wise to follow exclusively the
strategy of Blumer and others of his persuasion. Until symbolic inter-
actionists of all persuasions demonstrate in a more. compelling manner
than is currently the case that the inductive approach utilizing sensitizing
350 CHAPTER 15 / THE SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM OF BLUMER AND KUHN
TABLE 15-1 Convergence and Divergence in the Chicago and lowa Schools of
Symbolic Interactionism
Darke) Tay AP rr Ee eee ee
Theoretical Issues Convergence of Schools
The nature of humans Humans create and use symbols to denote aspects of the world
around them.
The nature of social Social structure is created, maintained, and changed by processes of
organization symbolic interaction.
It is not possible to understand patterns of social organization—even
the most elaborate—without knowledge of the symbolic processes
among individuals who ultimately make up this pattern.
The nature of Sociological methods must focus on the processes by which people
sociological methods define situations and select courses of action.
Methods must focus on individual persons.
The nature of Theory must be about processes of interaction and seek to isolate
sociological theory out the conditions under which general types of behaviors and
interactions are likely to occur.
SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM: A CONCLUDING COMMENT 351
Sociological methods must seek to penetrate Sociological methods must seek to measure
the actors’ mental world and see how they with reliable instruments actors’ symbolic
construct courses of action. processes.
Researchers must be attuned to the multiple, Research should be directed toward defining
varied, ever-shifting, and often indeterminate and measuring those variables that causally
influences on definitions of situations and influence behaviors.
actions.
Research must therefore use observational, Research must therefore use structured
biographical, and unstructured interview measuring instruments, such as
techniques if it is to penetrate people’s questionnaires, to get reliable and valid
definitional processes and take account of measures Cf key variables.
changes in these processes.
Only sensitizing concepts are possible in Sociology can develop precisely defined
sociology. concepts with clear empirical measures.
Deductive theory is thus not possible in Theory can thus be deductive, with a limited
sociology. number of general propositions subsuming
lower-order propositions and empirical
generalizations on specific phases of
symbolic interaction.
At best, theory can offer general and tentative Theory can offer abstract explanations that can
descriptions and interpretations of behaviors allow for predictions of behavior and
and patterns of interaction. interaction.
352 CHAPTER 15 / THE SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM OF BLUMER AND KUHN
concepts can account for more complex forms of social organization, pur-
suit of its strategy will preclude theorizing about much of the social world.
Yet, I feel that both Blumer’s and Kuhn’s strategies call attention to
some important substantive and theoretical issues that are often ignored
in social theory. First, it is necessary that sociological theorizing be more
willing to undertake the difficult task of linking conceptually structural
categories to classes of social processes that underlie these categories. For
this task, symbolic interactionism has provided a wealth of suggestive
concepts. Second, macrosociological theorizing has traditionally remained
detached from the processes of the social world it attempts to describe.
Much of the detachment stems from a failure to define concepts clearly
and provide operational clues about what processes in the empirical world
they denote. To the extent that symbolic interactionist concepts can sup-
plement such theorizing, they will potentially provide a bridge to actual
empirical processes and thereby help attach sociological theory to the
events it purports to explain.
Symbolic interactionism has great potential for correcting the past
inadequacies of sociological theory, but it has yet to demonstrate exactly
how this corrective influence is to be exerted. At present, symbolic in-
teractionism seems capable of analyzing micro social patterns and their
impact on personality, particularly the self. Although interactionism has
provided important insights in the study of socialization, deviance, and
micro social processes, it has yet to demonstrate any great potential for
analyzing complex, macro social patterns. At best, it can provide in its
present form a supplement to macroanalysis by giving researchers a frame-
work and measuring instruments to analyze microprocesses within macro
social events.
I find that much of symbolic interaction, especially Blumer’s advo-
cacy, consists of gallant assertions that “‘society is symbolic interaction”
but without indicating what types of emergent structures are created,
sustained, and changed by what types of interaction in what types of
contexts. Much like the critics’ allegations about Parsons’s social system,
Dahrendorfs imperatively coordinated association, Homans’s institu-
tional piles, or Blau’s organized collectivities, social structural phenomena
emerge somewhat mysteriously and are then sustained or changed by
vague references to interactive processes. The vagueness of the links be-
tween the interaction process and its social structural products leaves
symbolic interactionism with a legacy of assertions but little in the way
of carefully documented statements about how, when, where, and with
what probability interaction processes operate to create, sustain, and
change varying patterns of sociak organization. It is to this goal that
interactionist theory must redirect its efforts.
Probably the most significant effort to overcome this problem is an unfinished man-
uscript by Tamotsu Shibutani, Social Processes: An Introduction to Sociology (Berkeley
Calif.: University of California Press, 1986).
CHAPTER 16
1See, for example, Anthony Giddens, The Constitution of Society (Berkeley, Calif.: Uni-
versity of California Press, 1984).
2For two recent efforts to play down this distinction, see Warren Handel, “Normative
Expectations and the Emergence of Meaning as Solutions to Problems: Convergence of
Structural and Interactionist Views,” American Journal of Sociology 84 (1979), pp. 855-
81; and Jerold Heiss, “Social Roles,” in Social Psychology: Sociological Perspectives, ed. M.
Rosenberg, and R. H. Turner (New York: Basic Boeks, 1981), pp. 94-132._
3Bernard Farber, “A Research Model: Family Crisis and Games Strategy,” in Kinship
and Family Organization, ed. B. Farber (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1966), pp. 430-
34. Walter Wallace (Sociological Theory (Chicago: Aldine Publishing, 1969], pp. 34-35) has
more recently chosen this same analogy to describe symbolic interactionism.
353
354 CHAPTER 16 / STRUCTURAL ROLE THEORY
The analogy is then drawn between the players on the stage and the
actors of society. Just as players have a clearly defined part to play, so
actors in society occupy clear positions; just as players must follow a
written script, so actors in society must follow norms; just as players must
obey the orders of a director, so actors in society must conform to the
dictates of those with power or those of importance; just as players must
react to each other’s performance on the stage, so members of society
must mutually adjust their responses to one another; just as players re-
spond to the audience, so actors in society take the role of various au-
diences or “generalized others”; and just as players with varying abilities
and capacities bring to each role their unique interpretations, so actors
with varying self-conceptions and role-playing skills have their own styles
of interaction.
‘For the first early analytical statements, see Jacob Moreno, Who Shall Survive, rev.
ed. (New York: Beacon House, 1953; original ed., 1934); and Ralph Linton, The Study of
Man (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1936).
‘For an example of this form of analogizing, see Bruce J. Biddle and Edwin Thomas,
Role Theory: Concepts and Research (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1966), pp. 3-4. For
the best-known dramaturgical model, see Erving Goffman, The Presentation of Self in
Everyday Life (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday Publishing, 1959).
IMAGES OF SOCIETY AND THE INDIVIDUAL 355
*For a recent effort to bring together structurally oriented conceptions of role, see Bruce
Biddle, Role Theory: Expectations, Identities, and Behaviors (New York: Academic Press,
1979).
7See, for example, Jacob L. Moreno, “Contributions of Sociometry to Research Meth-
odology in Sociology,” American Sociological Review 12 (June 1947), pp. 287-92; Jacob L.
Moreno, ed., The Sociometry Reader (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1960); Oscar A. Oeser and
Frank Harary, “Role Structures: A Description in Terms of Graph Theory,’ Human Re-
lations 15 (May 1962), pp. 89-109; and Darwin Cartwright and Frank Harary, “Structural
Balance: A Generalization of Heider’s Theory,” Psychological Review 63 (September 1956),
pp. 277-93.
356 CHAPTER 16 / STRUCTURAL ROLE THEORY
of positions, per se, but also of the kinds of expectations that inhere in
these positions.
The range of expectations denoted by role-theoretic concepts is di-
verse. Pursuing the dramaturgical analogy to a play, I see three general
classes of expectations as typifying structural role theory’s vision of the
world: (a) expectations from the “script”; (b) expectations from other
“players”; and (c) expectations from the “audience.”
’Mead’s concept of the generalized other anticipated this analytical concern with ref-
erence groups. For some of the important conceptual distinctions in the theory of reference
group behavior, see Robert K. Merton, “Continuities in the Theory of Reference Groups
and Social Structure,” pp. 225-80; Tamotsu Shibutani, “Reference Groups as Perspectives,”
American Journal of Sociology 60 (May 1955), pp. 562-69; Harold H. Kelley, “Two Func-
tions of Reference Groups,” in Readings in Social Psychology, ed. G. E. Swanson et al. (New
York: Henry Holt, 1958); Ralph H. Turner, “Role-Taking, Role Standpoint, and Reference
Group Behavior,” American Journal of Sociology 61 (January 1956), pp. 316-28; and Herbert
Hyman and Eleanor Singer, eds., Readings in Reference Group Behavior (New York: Free
Press, 1968).
IMAGES OF SOCIETY AND THE INDIVIDUAL 357
status. The degree and form of conformity are usually seen as the result
of a variety of internal processes operating on individuals. Depending on
the interactive situation, these internal processes are conceptualized in
terms of variables such as (1) the degree to which expectations have been
internalized as a part of an individual’s need structure,’ (2) the extent to
which negative or positive sanctions are perceived by the individual to
accompany a particular set of expectations,’ (3) the degree to which
expectations are used as a yardstick for self-evaluation,'! and (4) the extent
to which expectations represent either interpretations of others’ actual
responses or merely anticipations of their potential responses.'* Just which
combination of these internal processes operates in a particular inter-
action situation depends upon the nature of the statuses and attendant
expectations. While this complex interactive process has yet to be codified
into an inventory of theoretical statements, it remains one of the principal
goals of role theory.
From this conceptualization, the individual is assumed to be not so
much a creative role entrepreneur who tries to change and alter social
structure through varied and unique responses, but rather a pragmatic
performer who attempts to cope with and adjust to the variety of expec-
tations inhering in social structure. These implicit assumptions about the
nature of the individual are consistent with Mead’s concern with the
adaptation and adjustment of the human organism to society, but they
clearly underemphasize the creative consequences of mind and self for
the construction and reconstruction of society. Thus, structural role the-
ory has tended to expand conceptually upon only part of the Meadian
legacy. This tendency assures some degree of assumptive one-sidedness,
which is understandable in light of the role theorists’ concern for sorting
out only certain types of dynamic interrelationships between society and
the individual.
°*For example, Talcott Parsons, The Social System (New York: Free Press, 1951). pp. l-
94; and William J. Goode, “Norm Commitment and Conformity to Role-Status Obligations,”
American Journal of Sociology 66 (November 1960), pp. 246-58.
‘For example, B. F. Skinner, Science and Human Behavior (New York: Macmillan.
1953), pp.313-55, 403-19; Biddle and Thomas, Role Theory, pp. 27-28; Shaw and Costanzo,
Theories of Social Psychology, pp. 332-33.
"Kelley, “Two Functions of Reference Groups”; Turner, “Role-Taking, Role Stand-
point”; and Ralph H. Turner, “Self and Other in Moral Judgement,” American Sociological
Review 19 (June 1954), pp. 254-63.
Turner, “Role-Taking, Role Standpoint.”
IMAGES OF SOCIETY AND THE INDIVIDUAL 359
13F'or summaries of the various uses of the concept, see Lionel J. Neiman and James W.
Hughes, “The Problem of the Concept of Role—A Re-survey of the Literature,” Social Forces
60 (December 1981), pp. 141-49; Ragnar Rommetveit, Social Norms and Roles: Explorations
in the Psychology of Enduring Social Pressures (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1955); Biddle and Thomas, Role Theory; Marvin E. Shaw and Philip R. Costanzo,
Theories of Social Psychology (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1970), pp. 334-38; and Morton
Deutsch and Robert M. Krauss, Theories in Social Psychology (New York: Basic Books),
pp. 173-77.
“Deutsch and Krauss, Theories in Social Psychology, p. 175; Daniel J. Levinson, “Role,
Personality, and Social Structure in the Organizational Setting,” Journal of Abnormal and
Social Psychology 58 (March 1959), pp. 170-80.
360 CHAPTER 16 / STRUCTURAL ROLE THEORY
Specific causal
chains among
analytical units
Role-playing
Reference groups skills
Specific causal
linkages within
analytical units
Reference groups
Self-esteem
the reason ’ * this vagueness stems from the fact that the label “role
theory” embraces a wide number of specific perspectives in a variety of
substantive areas. Despite these qualifications, I think that role theorists
have tended to develop concepts that denote specific interaction processes
without revealing the precise ways these concepts are interrelated. To the
extent that I can bring into focus role theory’s causal images, they appear
to emphasize the deterministic consequences of social structure on in-
teraction. However, rarely are larger, more inclusive units of culture and
structure included in this causal analysis. Rather, concern tends to be
with the impact of specific norms, others, and reference groups associated
with particular clusters of status positions on (a) self-interpretations and
evaluations, (6) role-playing capacities, or (c) overt role behavior. While
there is considerable variability in the role-theoretic literature, my sense
is that self-interpretations and evaluations are usually viewed as having
a deterministic impact on role-playing capacities, which then circumscribe
overt role behavior. I have depictest these causal images in Figure 16-1.
As I have portrayed in the middle section of Figure 16-1, the specific
causal images evident in the literature are more complex than the general
portrayal at the top of the figure. Expectations are still viewed as deter-
minative, but role theorists have frequently emphasiged the reciprocal
IMAGES OF SOCIETY AND THE INDIVIDUAL 361
nature of causal processes. That is, certain stages in the causal sequence
are seen as feeding back and affecting the subsequent causal relations
among analytical units, which are portrayed in the middle section of
Figure 16-1. Although there are numerous potential interconnections
among these units, I find that structural role theory has emphasized only
a few of these causal linkages, as is designated by the arrows in the figure.
Furthermore, to the extent that specific units of analysis are concep-
tualized for expectations, self-variables, role-playing skills, and overt be-
havior, only some of the causal interconnections among these units are
explored, as I have indicated at the bottom of Figure 16-1.
_ With respect to the interrelations among expectations, self, role-play-
ing skills, and overt behavior, I see structural role theory as being primarily
concerned with conceptualizing how different types of expectations are
mediated by self-interpretations and evaluations and then circumscribed
by role-playing skills in a way that a given style of role performance is
evident. This style is then typically analyzed in terms of its degree of
conformity to expectations. However, at each stage in this sequence,
certain feedback processes are also emphasized so that the degree of sig-
nificance of norms, others, or reference groups for the maintenance of
individuals’ self-couceptions is considered critical in influencing which
expectations are most likely to receive the most attention. For this causal
nexus, emphasis is on the degree of imbeddedness of self in certain groups,’
the degree of intimacy with specific others,’ and the degree of commit-
ment to, or internalization of, certain norms.'® Another prominent feed-
back process that has received considerable attention is the impact of
overt behavior at one point in time on the expectations of others as they
shape the individual’s self-conception and subsequent role behavior at
The study of deviance, socialization, and role -playing in complex organizations and
small groups has profited from this form of analysis.
16F'or example, see Norman Denzin, “Symbolic Interactionism and Eikoomebisdblosy,.’
in Understanding Everyday Life: Toward a Reconstruction of Sociological Knowledge, ed.
J. D. Douglas (Chicago: Aldine Publishing, 1970), pp. 259-84. For the most thorough set
of such studies in this area, see Sarbin’s examinations of the intensity of self-involvement
and role-playing behavior: Theodore R. Sarbin, “Role Theory,” in Handbook of Social
Psychology, ed. G. Lindzey, vol. 1 (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley Publishing, 1954), pp.
223-58; Theodore R. Sarbin and Norman L. Farberow, “Contributions to Role-Taking
Theory: A Clinical Study of Self and Role,” Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 47
(January 1952), pp. 117-25; and Theodore R. Sarbin and Bernard G. Rosenberg, “Contri-
butions to Role-Taking Theory.” Journal of Social Psycholegy 42 (August 1955), pp. 71-
81.
See, for example, Tamotsu Shibutani, Society and Personality (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Prentice-Hall, 1961), pp. 367-403.
%John Finley Scott, Internalization of Norms: A Sociological Theory of Moral Com-
mitment (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1971), pp. 127-215; William Goode, “Norm
Commitment and Conformity”; B. F. Skinner, Science and Human Behavior.
362 CHAPTER 16 / STRUCTURAL ROLE THEORY
another point in time. In this context, the childhood and adult socialization
of the individual and the emergence of self have been extensively studied,”
as has the emergence of deviant behavior.”
With respect to interrelations within the analytica! units of the overall
causal sequence, I think that the arrows at the bottom of Figure 16-1
portray the current theoretical emphasis of the literature. In regard to
the interrelations among types of expectations, analytical attention ap-
pears to be on how specific others personify group norms or the standards
of reference groups. In turn, these significant others are often viewed as
deterministically linking the self-interpretations and evaluations of an
individual to either the norms of a group or the standards of a reference
group.”! With respect to the relations among the components of self, anal-
ysis appears to have followed the lead of William James” by focusing on
the connections between the self-esteem and the self-conception of an
individual.” In turn, the interaction between self-esteem and other com-
ponents of self is viewed as the result of reactions from various others
who affect the self-images of the individual. Finally, all these components
interact in complex ways to shape the individual’s overt behavior.
Thus, looking back at Figure 16-1, it is evident that only some pro-
cesses have been extensively studied. Relatively little theoretical attention
has been drawn, I feel, to the following potential connections indicated
in the figure: (a) broader social and cultural structure and specific patterns
of interaction, (b) enacted role behaviors and their effect on role-playing
capacities, (c) these role-playing capacities and self, and (d) enacted roles
and the self-assessments that occur independently of role-taking with
specific others or groups. Rather, concern has been focused on the re-
For example, see Anselm Strauss, Mirrors and Masks (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1959),
pp. 100-18; Shibutani, Society and Personality, pp. 471-596; Orville G. Brim and Stanton
Wheeler, Socialization after Childhood (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1966).
See Edwin Lemert, Social Pathology (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1951); Thomas Scheff,
“The Role of the Mentally Ill and the Dynamics of Mental Disorder: A Research Frame-
work,” Sociometry 26 (December 1963), pp. 436-53; Howard Becker, Outsiders: Studies in
the Sociology of Deviance (New York: Free Press, 1963).
*Turner, “Role-Taking, Role Standpoint”; Shibutani, Society and Personality, pp. 249-
80.
“William James, Principles of Psychology, 2 vols. (New York: Henry Holt. 1890).
*8See Shibutani, Society and Personality, pp. 433-46.
“There is much experimental literature on the impact of various types of “contrived”
role-playing on attitudes and other psychological attributes of individuals: as yet, the findings
of these studies have not been incorporated into the role-theoretic framework. For some
examples of these studies, see Bert T. Kiag and Irving L. Janis, “Comparison of the Ef-
fectiveness of Improvised versus Non-Improvised Role-Playing in Producing Opinion
Changes,” Human Relations 9 (May 1956), pp. 177-86; Irving C. Janis and Bert T. King,
“The Influence of Role Playing on Opinion Change,” Journal of Abnormal and Social
Psychology 49 (April 1954), pp. 211-18; Paul E. Breer and Edwin A. Locke. Task Experience
as a Source of Attitudes (Homewood, Ill.: Dorsey Press, 1955); Theodore Sarbin and V. L.
Allen, “Role Enactment, Audience Feedback, and Attitude Change,” Sociometry 27 (June
1964), pp. 183-94. |
PROBLEMS AND ISSUES IN BUILDING ROLE THEORY 363
lations between self and expectations as they affect, and are affected by,
enacted roles.
Constructing Propositions
To this point, I see role-theoretic concepts as providing only a means for
categorizing and classifying expectations, self, role-playing capacities, role
enactment, and relationships among these analytical units. The use of
concepts is confined primarily to classification of different phenomena,
whether attention is drawn to the forms of status networks,” types and
sources of expectations,” relations of self to expectations,”’ or the enact-
ment of roles.”8 In the future, as they begin the difficult task of building
interrelated inventories of propositions, structural role theorists, I believe,
will confront several theoretical problems.
First, they must fill in the gaps of their causal imagery. To continue
emphasizing only some causal links while ignoring others will encourage
skewed sets of theoretical statements. Particularly crucial in this context
will be the development of propositions that specify the linkages between
concepts denoting more inclusive social and cultural variables, on the one
hand, and concepts pointing to specific interaction variables, on the other.
Another problem is that the current propositions that do exist in the
literature will have to be reformulated so that they specify when certain
role processes are likely to occur. For example, in the theory of reference-
group behavior, propositions assert that the use of a particular group as
a frame of reference is likely to occur when (a) contact with members of
a reference group is likely, (6) dissatisfaction with alternative group mem-
berships exists, (c) perception of potential rewards from a group is likely,
(d) the perception of that group’s standards is possible, and (e) perception
of the availability of significant others in the group is possible.” Although
For example, see Davis, Human Society; Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure;
Benoit, “Status, Status Types”; and Biddle and Thomas, Role Theory, pp. 23-41.
*Davis, Human Society; Richard T. Morris, ‘““A Typology of Norms,” American So-
ciological Review 21 (October 1956), pp. 610-13; Alan R. Anderson and Omar K. Moore,
“The Formal Analysis of Normative Concepts,” American Sociological Review 22 (February
1957), pp. 9-16; Williams, American Society.
27Turner, “Role-Taking, Role Standpoint”; and Sarbin and Allen, “Role Enactment,
Audience Feedback.”
*Goffman, Presentation of Self; Sarbin, “Role Theory”; John H. Mann and Carola H.
Mann, “The Effect of Role-Playing Experience on Role-Playing Ability,” Sociometry 22
(March 1959), pp. 69-74; and William J. Goode, “A Theory of Role Strain,” American
Sociological Review 25 (August 1960), pp. 483-96.
*Example drawn from summary in Alvin Boskofi, The Mosaic of Sociologic al T heory
(New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1272), pp. 49-51.
364 CHAPTER 16 / STRUCTURAL ROLE THEORY
these propositions are suggestive, they offer few clues as to what forms
of contact, what levels of dissatisfaction, what types of rewards and costs,
which group standards, and what type of significant others serve as con-
ditions for use as a frame of reference by an individual. Furthermore,
many relevant variables are not included in these propositions. For in-
stance, in order to improve the theory of reference-group behavior, I think
it necessary to incorporate theoretical statements on the intensity of self-
involvement, the capacity to assume roles in a group, the nature of group
standards, and their compatibility with various facets of an individual’s
self-conception.
These are the problems that a theoretical perspective attempting to
link social-structural and individual personality variables will inevitably
encounter. When psychological variables, such as self-concept, self-es-
teem, and role-playing capacities, are seen as interacting with cultural
and structural variables, such as status, norm, reference group, and others,
the resulting inventory of theoretical statements will become complex.
Such an inventory must not only delve into the internal states of indi-
viduals but must also cut across several levels of emergent phenomena—
at a minimum, the individual, the immediate interaction situation, and
the more inclusive structural and cultural contexts within which the in-
teraction occurs. Yet, despite the difficulties involved, I think that struc-
tural role theory is crucial to resolving some of the theoretical gaps in
sociology, especially those that concern the micro versus macro debate
(see Chapter 1).
Methodological Implications
The potential utility of role theory derives from its concern with the
complex interrelations among the expectations of social structure, the
mediation of these expectations through self-conceptions and role-playing
capacities of actors in statuses, and the resulting enactment of role be-
haviors. Measurement of role enactment does not pose a major meth-
odological obstacle, since it is the most observable of the phenomena
studied by role theorists. However, to the extent that such overt behavior
reflects the impact of expectations and self-related variables, several meth-
odological problems become evident. The complexity of the interrelations
between role behavior, on the one hand, and self and expectations, on the
other, as well as the difficulty of finding indicators of these interrelations.
pose a series of methodological problems that continue to make it difficult
to construct bodies of theoretical statements on the relation between
society and the individual.
Since one of the assumed links between society and the individual
revolves around the expectations that confront individuals, it is theoret-
ically crucial that various types of expectations and the ways they affect
individuals be measurable. One method is to infer expectations from ob-
PROBLEMS AND ISSUES IN BUILDING ROLE THEORY 365
served behavior. The most obvious problem with this approach is that
expectations can only be known after the emission of the behavior they
are supposed to circumscribe. Therefore, the concept of expectations as
inferred from behavior has little theoretical utility, since it cannot be
measured independently of behavior. Hence, role behavior cannot be pre-
dicted from the content of expectations and their relationship to self. An
alternative method involves (a) the accumulation of verbal accounts of
individuals prior to a particular interaction sequence,?° (b) the inference
of what types of expectations are guiding conduct, and (c) the prediction
of how role behavior will unfold in terms of these expectations. This
method has the advantage of making predictions about the impact of
expectations, but it suffers from the fact that, much like inferences drawn
from role enactment, expectations are not measurable independently of
the individual who is to be guided by them.3! The end result of these
methodological dilemmas is for expectations to represent inferences that
are difficult to discern independently of the behavior—whether verbal
accounts or role enactment—that they are supposed to guide.
A final alternative to this methodological problem is for researchers
to become active participants in social settings and from this participation
to derive some “intuitive sense” of the kinds of expectations that are
operating on actors. From this intuitive sense it is then presumed that
more formal conceptual representation of different types of expectations
and of their varying impact on selves and behavior can be made. The
principal drawback to such an approach is that one researcher’s intuitive
sense is not another’s, and the result may be that the expectation structure
observed by different researchers in the same situation is a “negotiated”
product as researchers attempt to achieve consensus as to exactly what
this structure is to be. However, to the extent that such a negotiated
conceptualization has predictive value, it would represent an indicator of
the expectation structure that is, in part at least, derived independently
of the verbal statements and behavior of those whose conduct it is sup-
posed to guide. ;
In sum, then, I believe that studying expectations is a difficult en-
terprise. Since most bodies of sociological theory assume the existence of
an expectation structure, it is crucial that these methodological problems
be exposed because they have profound implications for theory building.
The most important of these implications concerns the possibility of
There are many ways to accumulate such accounts, ranging from informal observations
and unstructured interviews with subjects to highly structured interviews and questionnaires.
All of these have been employed by role theorists, whether in natural settings or the small-
group laboratory. |
“This dilemma anticipates the discussion of ethnomethodology to be undertaken in a
later chapter, for, as the ethnomethodologist would argue, these verbal accounts are the
“reality” that guides conduct. From this perspective, the assumption of a “really real” world,
independent of an actor’s mental construction of it, is considered to be unfounded.
366 CHAPTER 16 / STRUCTURAL ROLE THEORY
building theory with concepts that are not measurable, even in principle.
Examining either role behavior or verbal statements and then inferring
the existence of expectations tends to make specific propositions tauto-
logous, since variation in behavior is explained by variation in phenomena
inferred from such behavior. The use of participant or observational tech-
niques overcomes this problem, but it presents the equally perplexing
question of how different researchers are to replicate, and hence poten-
tially refute, each other’s findings. If conceptualization of the expectation
structure is a negotiated product, the subsequent investigation of similar
phenomena by different investigators would require renegotiation. When
the nature of phenomena that are incorporated into theoretical statements
is not explicitly defined and classified in terms of independently verifiable,
clear-cut, and agreed-upon standards but is instead the product of ne-
gotiation, then the statements are not refutable, even in principle. As
products of negotiation, they have little utility for building a scientific
body of knowledge. Ultimately, I imagine that the severity of these prob-
lems is a matter of subjective assessment. Some of these problems would
appear to be fundamental, whereas others stem from the inadequacies of
current research techniques. |
Whether problems with conceptualizing expectations are seen as either
fundamental or technical, they are compounded by the methodological
problems of measuring self-related variables. How is it possible to derive
operational indicators of self-conceptions, self-esteem, and intrapsychic
assessments of the situation? As the discussion of Blumer and Kuhn in
the last chapter stressed, verbal accounts and observational techniques
have typically been used to tap these dimensions of interaction. Although
they are technically inadequate in that their accuracy can be questioned,
verbal and observational accounts do not raise the same fundamental
questions as do expectations, since they do seem measurable in principle.
The problems arise only when attempts are made to link these self-related
variables to expectations that are presumed to have an independent ex-
istence that guides the creation and subsequent operation of self-related
processes. While the independent existence of norms, others, reference
groups, and the like is intuitively pleasing, just how these phenomena are
to be conceptualized and measured separately from the self-related pro-
cesses they are assumed to circumscribe remains a central problem of
interactionism in general.
The substantive criticisms of structural role theory revolve around
the overly circumscribed vision of human behavior, and presumably of
social organization, that it connctes. Although it can be argued that cur-
rent role theory is too diverse to be vulnerable to this line of criticism. I
think that both theory and research in this tradition portray a highly
structured view of social reality.
Structural role theory assumes the social world to be organized in
terms of status networks and corresponding clusterings of expectations.
PROBLEMS AND ISSUES IN BUILDING ROLE THEORY 367
For example, see John W. Getzels and KE. C. Guba, “Role, Role Conflict, and Effec-
tiveness,” American Sociological Review 19 (February 1954), pp. 164-75; Talcott Parsons,
Social System, pp. 280-93; Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure, pp. 369-79; and
Robert L. Kahn et al., Organizational Stress: Studies in Role Conflict and Ambiguity (New
York: John Wiley & Sons, 1974).
*Goode, “Theory of Role Strain.”
*Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure, pp. 121-51.
368 CHAPTER 16 / STRUCTURAL ROLE THEORY
leaves much of role analysis with the empty assertion that society shapes
individual conduct. If role-theoretic assumptions are to have theoretical
significance, it is essential to specify just when, where, how, and through
what processes this circumscription of role behavior occurs. In fact, in
the absence of theoretical specificity, I think that a subtle form of func-
tionalism is connoted: the needs of social structure and the individual
require that behavior be circumscribed. This functionalism is further sus-
tained by the classificatory nature of role-theoretic concepts. In denoting
the types of interrelations among society, self, and behavior without in-
dicating the conditions under which these relationships are likely to exist,
these concepts appear to denote what processes must occur without in-
dicating when, where, and how they are to occur.*
Finally, the methodological problems of measuring expectations sep-
arately from the very processes that they are supposed to circumscribe
makes even more mysterious just how and in what ways social structure
affects individual conduct. Again, the inability to measure this crucial
causal nexus leaves the role theorist with the uninteresting assertion that
society shapes and guides individual conduct.
These problems have led others to propose a more processual version
of role theory. Yet, it would be foolish, I think, to ignore this more struc-
tural orientation. Social structures do exist; they do reveal normative
expectations; they do order people’s access to reference groups; and they
do circumscribe people’s options and self-evaluations. It has become very
“trendy” in social theory to ignore these facts, especially after the effort
to kill off Parsonian functionalism. I think that the more process-oriented
theorists had a legitimate criticism but they have often overreacted and
posited a social universe in which people are interpersonal entrepreneurs
and gadflies. Nonetheless, let us now turn to the more processual approach
of Ralph H. Turner, keeping in mind that roles are often enacted in social
structures and that theoretical sociology must confront this fact. For al-
though structural role theory has very clear problems, it does attempt to
analyze an important dynamic of social reality.
Although most structural. role theorists would vehemently deny it, they have followed
Parsons’s strategy for building theory, except on a more micro level. In developing concepts
to classify and order role-related phenomena, without also developing clear-cut propositions,
they have created a conceptual order without indicating when and how the order denoted
by concepts is maintained (or broken down or reconstructed).
____._ The Process Role Theory ____
eo| LO hee oO. Turher
369
370 CHAPTER 17 / THE PROCESS ROLE THEORY OF RALPH H. TURNER
“abnormal” social processes, such as role conflict and role strain, thereby
ignoring the normal processes of human interaction. (3) Role theory is
not theory but rather a series of disjointed and unconnected propositions.
(4) Role theory has not utilized to the degree required Mead’s concept of
role-taking as its central concept.
It is criticism on the overly structural view of roles that has, I believe,
been the main impetus to Turner’s alternative approach. Indeed, he has
recently emphasized the overly structural bias in role theory, even among
those who have tried to reconcile structural and processual accounts of
roles. He attacks structural approaches with a series of questions. First,
does the structural conception of role add anything that is not covered
by the concept of normative expectation? For if roles are merely enact-
ments of expectations, why even introduce the concept of role? Second,
can the structural analysis of roles deal with roles that are not lodged in
some organizational structure? Most roles, Turner contends, are not at-
tached to a clear structure; and if conceptualization of roles requires that
we examine roles with structural positions and expectations, then analysis
is dramatically limited. Third, can structural orientations to roles deal
with situations where new roles are created or old ones changed by efforts
of people to realize certain values or beliefs? For if roles are part of
structure, how is it possible to analyze the emergence of new roles, often
in defiance of structural dictates?
These questions led Turner to posit a series of unresolved issues in
role theory, which, he claims, structural role theory cannot handle. One
issue is whether or not roles are acts of conformity to norms or creative
constructions of actors. Turner believes that roles involving normative
conformity are, in reality, exceptional cases that occur when a repressive
structure limits opportunities, when people receive few rewards from their
roles, and when people are insecure about their capabilities. But these are
relatively rare situations, and so in most social contexts, people negotiate
their respective roles.
Another issue is whether or not roles are inventories of specific be-
haviors or more general gestalts and configurations of meaning about lines
of conduct. It is rare, Turner argues, for actors to be able to list precisely
the behaviors of a role; more typically, they can communicate only general
attitudes, styles, and loosely defined behavioral options associated with
a role. Only in rigid and pathological structures are roles so clearly defined
as to constitute a list of appropriate behaviors.
Yet another issue is: Are roles fixed and predetermined, or do indi-
viduals negotiate which roles they are going to play in a situation? Even
in highly structural situations, roles are negotiated. And in most social
encounters, individuals must actively make roles for themselves and ne-
gotiate with others to their right to play a given role.
What emerges from Turner’s questions and presentation of unresolved
issues in role theory is a view of roles as general configurations of responses
that people negotiate as they form social relations. They are not mere
enactments of expectations, and they are not always tied to positions in
structures. In light of these considerations, Turner offers a conceptuali-
zation of roles that emphasizes the process of interaction over the dictates
of social structures.
*Ralph H. Turner, “The Rule and the Person,” American Journal of Sociology 84 (1978),
pp. 1-23.
Turner, “Social Roles: Sociological Aspects.” Turner has extensively analyzed this pro-
cess of self-anchorage in roles. See, for example, Ralph H. Turner, “The Real Self: From
Institution to Impulse,” American Journal of Sociology 81 (1970), pp. 989-1016; Ralph H.
Turner and Victoria Billings, “The Social Context of Self-Feeling,” working paper; Ralph
H. Turner and Steven Gordon, “The Boundaries of the Self: The Relationship of Authen-
ticity to Inauthenticity in the Self-Conception,” in Self-Concept: Advances in Theory and
Research, ed. M. D. Lynch et al. (Cambridge, Mass.: Ballinger Publishing Co., 1981).
374 CHAPTER 17 / THE PROCESS ROLE THEORY OF RALPH H. TURNER
can be the basis for assigning and verifying roles.'! And the conception
of roles as parts that people learn to play is preserved, for people are able
to denote each other’s roles by virtue of their prior socialization into a
common role repertoire.
Not only do these assumptions embrace the major points of emphasis
in prominent definitions of role, but they also help reconcile the differ-
ences between symbolic interactionism and more structural versions of
role theory. Turner’s assumptions employ the key concepts of Mead’s
synthesis, while taking cognizance of Blumer’s emphasis on the processes
that underlie patterns of joint action. These assumptions also point to
the normal processes of interaction but are sufficiently general to embrace
the possibility of conflictual and stressful interactions. And these as-
sumptions about the role-making process do not preclude the analysis of
structured interaction, since formal norms and status positions are often
the major cues for ascertaining the roles of people as well as a source of
verification for imputed roles.
Assumptions are, however, only as good as the theory that they can
generate. I think it particularly significant that Turner delineates an ex-
plicit strategy for translating these assumptions into theoretical propo-
sitions. My sense is that tne execution of this strategy will help inter-
actionism bridge the gap between suggestive assumptions and concepts,
on the one hand, and the current plethora of narrow empirical proposi-
tions, on the other. Let me now outline the basic elements of this strategy.
variables that can specify the conditions under which actors “tend to act
to alleviate role strain.” The tendency proposition thus provides an initial
set of guidelines for developing true propositions about relationships among
variables.
Furthermore, since the tendency propositions are grouped together,
as was done in the sections above, the true empirical propositions will be
organized around related tendencies. As such, the propositions are less
scattered and disparate than would be the case if the search for propo-
sitions had not begun with the delineation of certain normal tendencies.
Yet, I still find the transition from the tendency propositions to the true
empirical propositions rather vague. Nonetheless, Turner’s propositions
about the person and role can illustrate the potential of his theory-building
strategy (the last section in the tendency propositions above).'®
The person is viewed as the repertoire of roles that he or she plays.
And while “people are normally quite different actors in different roles,
and even have senses of ‘who they are,’ ”’ humans also use roles as a means
for self-identification and self-validation.'® Some roles are thus more im-
portant to individuals and resist compartmentalization, or separation,
from a person’s self-concept. Roles that arouse strong self-feelings, which
people appear to play across situations, refuse to abandon, and embellish
with associated attitudes, are likely to involve considerable merger of the
individual’s self with the role.
Thus, to generate an empirical proposition from these tendencies, we
need to know the conditions under which individuals become identified
with roles, using the role for purposes of self-identification and validation.
Tendency Propositions 24 and 26 can be dependent variables organizing
a search for the conditions under which individuals tend “to form self-
conceptions by selective identification of certain roles from their reper-
toire as more characteristically themselves than other roles” and to show
“role distance” and “a lack of personal involvement” in situations that
“contradict the self-conception.” For all the other tendency propositions
listed, a similar search could be initiated in an effort to discover the
empirical conditions that influence their rate, degree, and extent of
occurrence.!”
Turner divides his discussion of person and role into two general lines
of analysis: (1) how do others in the situation discover a merger of role
and person, and (2) how do the individuals come to lodge their selves in
|. The broader the setting in which a role is lodged, the greater the tendency for
others to identify the role with the person, and the stronger the tendency for the
actors to accept that identification for themselves.
ll. The more a role in one setting determines allocation and performance of roles
in other settings, the greater the tendency for others to identify the role with the
person, and the stronger the tendency for the actors to accept that identification
for themselves.
lll. The more conspicuous and widely recognizable the role cues, the greater the
tendency for others to identify the role with the person, and the stronger the
tendency for the actors to accept that identification for themselves.
IV. The more a role exemplifies the goals and nature of the group or organization
in which it is lodged, the greater the tendency for others to identify the role with
the person, and the stronger the tendency for the actors to accept that
identification for themselves.
V. The more that allocation to a role is understood to be temporary and the role
discontinuous in content with respect to preceding and succeeding roles, the
greater the tendency for community members not to identify the role with the
person, and the stronger the tendency for the actors not to identify role with
self.
clearly defined and distinguishable the role, the greater the tendency for
person-role merger. In Proposition III, the more that roles among person
and others are in conflict, the greater the role-person merger—andso on
for the remaining propositions. What is critical in these and other prop-
ositions is that they reveal covariance between variables and thus con-
stitute true propositions.
The social settings of actors often overlap. People see each other in
different settings, but as they interact, they seek to discover which role
is part of a person’s self-identification. The five propositions in Table 17-
2 are examples of some of the considerations that Turner views as op-
erating in multiple social settings to influence role-person merger. People
in multiple settings will be likely to identify the role with the person, and
the person will likely accept this identification when the role cuts across
many social settings (I), the role influences the other roles that a person
can play and/or how they are played (II), the role is highly conspicuous
(III), the role exemplifies, or personifies, the nature of the social unit in
which it is lodged (IV). Proposition V is an example of a condition under
which roles will not merge with the person. When a role is short-lived
and inconsistent with other roles played by a person, then the individual
will not identify with the role.
The propositions in Tables 27-1 and 17-2 address the question of
how others in situations discover a person-role merger. However, people
are rarely passive, accepting the labels of others. People actively seek to
dictate the merger of their self with a role. This fact is stressed with the
concept of role-making, thus requiring still more propositions on self and
role merger.
THE STRATEGY FOR BUILDING ROLE THEORY 383
|. The more highly evaluated a role, the greater the tendency to locate self in that
role.
ll. The more adequately a role can be performed, the greater the tendency to
locate self in that role.
Ill. The higher the evaiuation of roles among a repertoire of roles that can be
played adequately, the greater the tendency to locate self in the roles of highest
evaluation.
IV. The more visible and readily appraisable role performance, the greater the
tendency to locate self in highly evaluated roles will be modified by the tendency
to locate self in roles that can be played with high degrees of adequacy.
V. The more the scope of an individual's social world exceeds the boundaries of
the social circle of a given role, the greater the tendency to use evaluations of
the larger community rather than those of a specific social circle to locate self in
a role.
Vi. The more intrinsic (as opposed to extrinsic) the benefits derived from enacting a
role, the greater the tendency to locate self in that role.
Vil. The greater the investment of time and effort in gaining or maintaining the
opportunity to claim a role or in learning to play a role, the qreater the tendency
to locate self in that role.
Vill. The greater the sacrifice made in gaining or maintaining the opportunity to claim
a role or in learning to play a role, the greater the tendency to locate self in that
role.
IX. The more publicly a role is played and the more actors must explain and justify
a role, the greater the tendency to locate self in that role.
X. The more unresolved role strain encountered in a role has been prolonged, the
greater the tendency to locate self in that role.
expenditure of time and effort, that involve sacrifice in reaching, that are
publicly played and in need of public justification, and that involve pro-
longed role strain and effort to eliminate strain.
These propositions on the person and role listed in Tables 17-1, 17-
2, and 17-3 are only tentative. Similar empirical propositions need to be
developed for Turner’s other tendency statements. Yet, even clearly ar-
ticulated empirical propositions represent only crude groupings of state-
ments and tendencies. Such propositions are the result of speculation,
and they can, no doubt, suggest additional propositions. But these em-
pirical propositions are not organized deductively—that is, in a way that
would allow them to be deduced from a small number of abstract prop-
ositions or “axioms.” The next step in Turner’s strategy, therefore, in-
volves an effort to generate explanatory propositions.
'8Tbid.
; aecis He does this also because he feels these are perhaps the most generic dimensions
of roles.
THE STRATEGY FOR BUILDING ROLE THEORY 385
2] have phrased these differently than Turner would, but the meaning is the same. See
Turner, “Strategy.”
386 CHAPTER 17 / THE PROCESS ROLE THEORY OF RALPH H. TURNER
I think that such efforts tc- deduce the empirical propositions yield
considerable insight as to why people are willing to locate their selves in
roles. By working hard to claim and maintain a role, actors set up ex-
pectations that they should receive rewards proportionate to their in-
vestments. In other words, tenability considerations become important.
And when these become more important than functionality considera-
PROCESS ROLE THEORY: A BRIEF ASSESSMENT OF TURNER’S APPROACH 387
tions, people are more willing to locate their selves in, and identify with,
roles.
The insertion of the concept of tenability also provides, as Turner
intended, an explanation for why the independent variables in the other
person and role propositions should increase the likelihood of self-location
in roles. For example, to the extent that “role adequacy,” “role evalua-
tion,” “role visibility,” “scope of social world,” ‘intrinsic benefits,” and
the other independent variables of Turner’s empirical propositions on
“individual efforts at role merger” (see earlier listings in Table 17-3) can
be seen as specific types or forms of the tenability principle, he has pro-
vided a common explanation of why people should locate self in a role.
1See, for example, Thomas P. Wilson, “Normative and Interpretative Paradigms in So-
ciology,” in Understanding Everyday Life, ed. J. Douglas (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul, 1970).
389
390 CHAPTER 18 / THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGICAL CHALLENGE
’Paul Attewell, “Ethnomethodology Since Garfinkel,” Theory and Society 1 (1974), pp.
179-210.
‘This is not always true, especially in some of his more institutional works, such as
Asylums (Garden City, N. Y.: Anchor Books, 1961). Other representative works by Goffman
include The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life (Garden City, N. Y.: Doubleday Pub-
lishing, 1959); Interaction Ritual (Garden City, N. Y.: Anchor Books, 1967); Encounters
(Indianapolis, Ind.: Bobbs-Merrill, 1961); Stigma (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1963).
392 CHAPTER 18 / THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGICAL CHALLENGE
Metaphysics or Methodology?
Ethnomethodology has often been misunderstood. Part of the reason for
this misunderstanding stems from the vagueness of the prose of some
‘See, in particular, Alfred Schutz, Collected Papers I: The Problem of Social Reality, ed.
Maurice Natanson (The Hague, Holland: Martinus Nijhoff, 1962); Alfred Schutz, Collected
Papers II: Studies in Social Theory, ed. Arvid Broderson (The Hague, Holland: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1964); and Alfred Schutz, Collected Papers III: Studies in Phenomenological Phi-
losophy (The Hague, Holland: Martinus Nijhoff, 1966). For adaptations of these ideas to
interactionism and ethnomethodology, see Alfred Schutz and Thomas Luckmann, The
Structure of the Lifeworld (Evanston, IIl.. Northwestern University Press, 1973) as well as
Thomas Luckmann, ed., Phenomenology and Sociology (New York: Penguin Books, 1978).
See also Robert C. Freeman, “Phenomenological Sociology and Ethnomethodology,” in
Sioa Ha to the Sociologies of Everyday Life, eds. J. Douglas et al. (Boston: Allyn &
acon, .
“Augh Mehan and Houston Wood, The Reality of Ethnomethodology (New York: John
Wiley & Sons, 1975), p. 190. This is an excellent statement of the ethnomethodological
perspective.
THE NATURE OF ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 393
*For another example of this interpretation, see Walter L. Wallace. Sociological Theory
(Chicago: Aldine Publishing, 1969), pp. 34-36.
THE NATURE OF ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 395
*Tbid., p. 42.
*Tbid.
i[bid., pp. 104-15.
*Ibid., p. 110.
400 CHAPTER 18 / THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGICAL CHALLENGE
different rules had been used to construct the corpus of what really
happened.
In sum, I think that these two examples of Garfinkel’s research strat-
egy illustrate the general intent of much ethnomethodological inquiry: to
penetrate natural social settings or create social settings in which the
investigator can observe humans attempting to assert, create, maintain,
or change the rules for constructing the appearance of consensus over the
structure of the real world. By focusing on the process or methods for
constructing a reality rather than on the substance or content of the reality
itself, research from the ethnomethodological point of view can potentially
provide a more interesting and relevant answer to the question of “how
and why society is possible.” Garfinkel’s studies have stimulated a variety
of research and theoretical strategies. Several of the most prominent strat-
egies are briefly discussed below.
Aaron V. Cicourel, Method and Measurement in Sociology (New York: Free Press,
1964).
Ibid., p. 35.
*Aaron V. Cicourel, “Cross Modal Communication,” in Linguistics and Language Sct-
ence, Monograph 25, ed. R. Shuy (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1973).
*See, for example, his Cognitive Sociology and “Basic and Normative Rules in the
Negotiation of Status and Role,” in Recent Sociology No. 2, ed. H. P. Dreitzel (New York:
Macmillan, 1970).
402 CHAPTER 18 / THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGICAL CHALLENGE
*See,
I
for example, Zimmerman
:
and Pollner, “The World as a Phenomenon”: Zimmerman
’ ? - oe
and Wieder, “Ethnomethodology and the Problem of Order”: Wieder, Langtrage and Seciat
7s “e .
Reality.
NEW PARADIGM OR IMPORTANT SUPPLEMENT? 403
*8] agree with Lewis Coser on this issue. See his ““Two Methods in Search of a Substance,”
American Sociological Review 40 (1975), pp. 691-700. I also agree with him about the “other
method” discussed in this article.
*Actually, many nonethnomethodologists, such as Jurgen Habermas (see Chapter 9),
Randall Collins (see Chapter 21), and Anthony Giddens (see Chapter 22), have used the
ideas of ethnomethodologists to build interesting theory—far more interesting than that
produced by the ethnomethodologists themselves.
ae aie em
405
CHAPTER 19
it will be ev-
stimulated more modern structural theorizing.’ As I do so,
theorizing
ident that many of the basic issues that trouble sociological
ogy
become highly visible in structural theories. For example, can sociol
be a science, or is there something different and unique about human
structures? Can social structure be conceptualized independently of the
microprocesses from which it is constituted, or must it be analyzed in
terms of these microprocesses? And can the basic dimensions—both macro
and micro—of structure be isolated and analyzed by theory, or is structure
merely a reification?? As is evident, structural theorizing forces us to deal
with sociology’s more difficult questions. Let me now trace the origins of
these questions in the structural thought of sociology’s early masters.
1For one recent effort to clarify the “structuralisms” that pervade social theory, see Bruce
H. Mayhew, “Structuralism versus Individualism: Part 1, Shadowboxing in the Dark”’ and
“Structuralism versus Individualism: Part II, Ideological and Other Obfuscations,” Social
Forces 59 {2 and 3, 1981), pp. 335-75 and 627-48, respectively. See also a volume edited
by Ino Rossi, Structural Sociology (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982) for rep-
resentative analyses.
*For example, see Douglas W. Maynard and Thomas P. Wilson, “On the Reification of
Social Structure,” Current Perspectives in Social Theory 1 (1980), pp. 287-322.
‘Such is the case because I do not think that they have generated any theory, even if
we include meta-theory as part of sociological theorizing. Structuralism is, of course, a broad
intellectual movement, and its most Marxist exponent was Louis Althusser, For Marx (New
York: Penguin Books, 1969) and Politics and History (London: NLB, 1977). For an inter-
esting secondary review, see also Alison Assiter, “Althusser and Structuralism,”” The British
Journal of Sociology 35 (2, 1984), pp. 272-94.
‘See appendix for my review of Lévi-Strauss, the most prominent of these French
structuralists.
5See Karl Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (New York: In-
ternational Publishers, 1970); The Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 (New
York: International Publishers, 1964; and Capital: A Critical Analysis of Capitalist Pro
duction (New York: International Publishers, 1967).
KARL MARX AND STRUCTURAL ANALYSIS 409
‘Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto (New York: International
Publishers, 1971).
410 CHAPTER 19 / THE ORIGINS OF STRUCTURAL THEORIZING
Spencer’s Macrostructuralism
Herbert Spencer’s work is most commonly identified with functional theo-
rizing. But in actual fact, Spencer’s work is far less functional than is
commonly recognized.’ I think that a much more accurate label is ma-
crostructural, which violates, of course, our other misinterpretation of
Spencer as the staunch individualist who coined the phrase “survival of
the fittest.”” For contrary to our stereotypes, Spencer’s main theoretical
problem was the relationship among (a) the size of a population, (b) the
rates of contact and interaction among its members, (c) the level of dif-
ferentiation of activities and subgroupings in a population, and finally,
(d) the pattern of its integration. I see this emphasis as macrostructural
because there is not much concern with how individuals build and sustain
structure; rather, emphasis is on the form of structures and how they
constrain individual actions.’ Let me recapitulate Spencer’s macrostruc-
tural theory.®
For Spencer, increases in population size generate pressures for trans-
formation in the ways that activities of its members are organized. One
pressure for change comes from the fact that rates of face-to-face contact
decline with increases in size; peaple simply cannot all interact with each
other. As a result, informal social control is disrupted, forcing the elab-
Spencer’s Microstructuralism
Spencer argued that ultimately all macrostructures are built from “cer-
emonial practices’’—that is, rituals, forms of address, bodily movements,
dress, badges and emblems, and other stereotyped presentations of self
and sequences of behavior. Moreover, macrostructures are sustained
through ceremonies, or interaction rituals. He argued that too often these
more micro processes are ignored because next to the macrostructures—
the state, classes, and religion, for example—‘“‘ceremonial control” seems
“of no significance.” Yet, Spencer did emphasize that growing size and
complexity at the macrostructural level undermine the extent to which
ceremonial control can be effective. But his major concern was with how
ritualized interaction varies under conditions of inequality. His guiding
proposition is that the greater is the degree of political centralization in
a population, the greater is the level of inequality, and hence, the more
pronounced are interaction rituals and the more they will be used to mark
ranks.
Spencer’s analysis of ceremony or interaction rituals is, I think, one
of the first efforts in sociology to analyze the connection between ma-
croprocesses of size, differentiation, spatial distribution, political cen-
tralization, and class inequalities with more micro processes that produce
and reproduce these macro properties of society. His work was very much
in the spirit of contemporary structural approaches, but tragically, his
ideas have been ignored, as evidenced by Talcott Parsons’s remark in
1937, “who now reads Spencer?” Yet, as I think will be evident in the
following chapters, contemporary theorists have rediscovered many of
Spencer’s insights.
One reason for our ignorance of Spencer is our misunderstanding of
his work. Sociologists frequently equate his ideas with what is now called
a right wing ideology. Such a conclusion is too simple a portrayal and
has kept sociologists from fully appreciating Spencer’s genius. Another
reason for our misconception of Spencer is that we have allowed Emile
Durkheim’s biased evaluation of Spencer to color our view.’° Indeed.
mile Durkheim, The Division of Labor in Society (New York: Free Press, 1947).
THE STRUCTURALISM OF EMILE DURKHEIM 413
“Again, I do not think that this approach has led anywhere, and hence, I am not going
to analyze it in any detail.
“Durkheim, The Division of Labor.
’Spencer, The Principles of Sociology.
“See Jonathan H. Turner and Leonard Beeghley, The Emergence of Sociological Theory
(Homewood, Ill.: Dorsey Press, 1981), pp. 334-41 for a detailed analysis.
414 CHAPTER 19 / THE ORIGINS OF STRUCTURAL THEORIZING
‘*This is, I should stress, the basic dilemma that Adam Smith proposed much earlier in
his treatise.
‘Emile Durkheim, The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (New York: Free Press. 1947:
originally published in 1912),
"Ibid., p. 9.
'*So did some of the early linguists who borrowed from Durkheim. But modern linguistics
has turned Durkheim, and those early French thinkers who borrowed from him, “on their
heads.”
‘Indeed, at times they are embarrassingly bad. For example, see Emile Durkheim and
Marcel Mauss, Primitive Classification (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963; orig-
inally published in 1903).
THE STRUCTURALISM OF EMILE DURKHEIM 415
(New
*See essays in Kurt Wolff's edited volume on The Sociology of Georg Simmel
| Hw!
York: Free Press, 1950).
analysis of
27’This is, in reality, a more precise way of stating Spencer’s and Durkheim's
size and differentiation.
418 CHAPTER 19 / THE ORIGINS OF STRUCTURAL THEORIZING
*Georg Simmel, The Philosophy of Money (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978).
; See, for example, Erving Goffman, The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life (Garden
City, N.Y.: Doubleday Publishing, 1959); Behavior in Public Places (New York: Free Press,
1963); Forms of Talk (Boston: Blackwell Scientific Publications, Inc., 1981).
ws Herbert Mead, Mind, Self, and Society (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
“Alfred Schutz, The Phenomenology of the Social World (Evanston, Ill: Northwestern
University Press, 1967; originally published in 1932).
INTERACTIONISM AND MICROSTRUCTURALISM
419
Alfred Schutz
Microstructuralists seem to prefer Schutz’s conceptualization of stock
knowledge at hand to Mead’s notion of generalized others and to modern
conceptions of roles, values, beliefs, and norms. I assume that this pref-
erence comes from the metaphorical idea of stocks that can be used se-
lectively as the actor wants and desires. Schutz’s conception would appear
to de-emphasize explicit normative constraints and roles. But does it?
Let me quote Schutz:
Now, to the natural man all his past experiences are present as ordered
(italics in original), as knowledge or as awareness of what to expect, just as
the whole external world is present to him as ordered. Ordinarily, and unless
he is forced to solve a special kind of problem, he does not ask questions
about how this ordered world was constituted. The particular patterns of
order we are now considering are synthetic meaning—configurations of already
lived experience.
*See, for example, the “baseline approach” of Bruce H. Mayhew and various collabo-
cal
rators. In particular, consult his argument in a special issue of The Journal of Mathemati
Sociology 9 (4, 1984).
Claude Lévi-Strauss, The Elementary Structures of Kinship (Paris: University of France,
1949).
and in Anthro-
*Actually, an earlier work, “The Analysis of Structure in Linguistics
the form of Lévi-Strauss’s
pology,” Word 1 (1945), pp. 1-21, provided a better clue as to
structuralism.
422 CHAPTER 19 / THE ORIGINS OF STRUCTURAL THEORIZING
Durkheim?’ and Marcel Mauss.** There are, however, also clear departures
from Durkheim and Mauss, which signal that Lévi-Strauss was to “turn
Durkheim on his head” in much the same way that Marx was to revise
Hegel. For as Durkheim and Mauss had argued in Primitive Classification,
human cognitive categories reflect the structure of society.* In contrast,
Lévi-Strauss’s structuralism came to the opposite conclusion: the struc-
ture of society is but a surface manifestation of fundamental mental
processes.
Lévi-Strauss came to this position under the influence of structural
linguistics, as initially chartered by Ferdinand de Saussure*® and Roman
Jakobson. Ferdinand de Saussure is typically considered both the father
of structural linguistics‘! and of Lévi-Strauss’s structuralism. In reality,
as a contemporary of Durkheim, de Saussure was far more committed to
Durkheim’s vision of reality than is typically acknowledged. Yet, he made
a critical breakthrough in linguistic analysis of the 19th century: speech
is but a surface manifestation of more fundamental mental processes.”
Language is not speech nor the written word; but rather, it is a particular
way of thinking, which, in true Durkheimian fashion, de Saussure viewed
as a product of the general patterns of social and cultural organization
among people. This distinction of speech as a mere surface manifestation
of underlying mental processes was to increasingly be used as a metaphor
for Lévi-Strauss’s structuralism. Of course, this metaphor is as old as
Plato’s view of reality as a mere reflection of universal essences and as
recent as Marx’s dictum that cultural values and beliefs, as well as in-
stitutional arrangements, are reflections of an underlying substructure.
Lévi-Strauss also borrows from the early 20th-century linguist Roman
Jakobson the notion that the mental thought underlying language occurs
in terms of binary contrasts, such as good-bad, male-female, yes-no, black-
white, and human-nonhuman. Moreover, drawing from Jakobson and
others, Lévi-Strauss views the underlying mental reality of binary op-
posites as organized, or mediated, by a series of “‘innate codes” or rules
that can be used to generate many different social forms: language, art,
music, social structure, myths, values, beliefs, and so on. Thus, over the
last decades, Lévi-Strauss’s structuralism has become concerned with un-
derstanding cultural and social patterns in terms of the universal mental
processes that are rooted in the biochemistry of the human brain.“ It is
in this sense that Lévi-Strauss’s structuralism is mentalistic and reduc-
tionistic. And for this reason, I do not think that it is sociologically very
useful.* Indeed, it is more philosophy than science. Yet, since it now
generates so much intellectual interest, even in sociology, let me at least
summarize its basic line of argument.*¢
Without enumerating the full complexity (and vagueness) of his ap-
proach, I see the following as the critical steps and built-in assumptions
of Lévi-Strauss’s theoretical (philosophical) strategy:
Steps 1 and 2 are about as far as Lévi-Strauss went in the first pub-
lication of The Elementary Forms of Kinship. Subsequent work on kin-
ship and on myths has invoked at least the rhetoric of Steps 3, 4, and 5.
What makes structuralism distinctive, therefore, is the commitment to
the assumptions and strategy implied in these last steps. The major prob-
lem with this strategy is that it is untestable, for if mechanical models
are never perfectly reflected in the empirical world, how is it possible to
confirm or disconfirm the application of rules to binary opposites? As
Marshall Sahlins sarcastically remarked, ‘““What is apparent is false and
what is hidden from perception and contradicts it is true.’’47 I think that
there are more profitable ways to analyze social structure, and so, let me
now turn to them in the next three chapters.
1See Peter M. Blau, Inequality and Heterogeneity: A Primitive Theory of Social Structure
(New York: Free Press, 1977); “A Macrosociological Theory of Social Structure,” American
Journal of Sociology 83 (July 1977), pp. 26-54; see also “Contrasting Theoretical Perspec-
tives,” in The Micro-Macro Link, ed. J. C. Alexander,B.Gisen, R. Munch, and N. J. Smelser
(Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, in press).
*Indeed, he views his work on exchange as a prolegomenon—a kind of pretheory, which,
by its nature, would be unsystematic. Indeed, in Chapter 12, I had to extract the theoretical
principles.
425
426 CHAPTER 20 / THE MACROSTRUCTURALISM OF PETER M. BLAU
;
‘Ibid.
do as Blau
*Actually, as network analysis begins to deal with larger populations, they
example, Harrison C. White, Scott A. Boorman, and Ronald L. Breiger,
advocates. See, for
81 (January
“Social Structure from Multiple Networks I,” American Journal of Sociology
1976). pp. 730 80.
“Blau’s empirical work on organizations and socioeconomic status preceded his theo-
retical efforts. He has thus followed his own advice.
URlau, “Blements of Sociological Theorizing.” p. 107.
428 CHAPTER 20 / THE MACROSTRUCTURALISM OF PETER M. BLAU
ositions and then the hierarchical ordering of them. Although Blau uses
the vocabulary of axiomatic theory, his system of propositions is what I
termed formal theorizing in Chapter 1, because it does not evidence the
rigor of true axiomatic theory (for as I emphasized, very little theory in
the social sciences can meet the criteria of axiomatic theory). In Blau’s
view, the ordering of propositions involves (a) the articulation of a number
of simple assumptions as axioms and (b) the development of theorems
that apply these assumptions to generic types of social relations. For
example, Blau’s most basic assumption is that social associations are more
prevalent among persons in proximate positions than among those in
distant social positions. Thus, people at similar ranks or in the same
group are more likely to interact than those in divergent ranks or different
groups. With this and other assumptions to be discussed shortly and with
the central operator and additional concepts, Blau can then generate a
number of theorems that explain why events in the empirical world should
occur. The essence of Blau’s theory thus involves the articulation of some
simple axioms or assumptions and the incorporation of these into theo-
rems that state relations among carefully defined concepts that have em-
pirical referents.
The final element of theory construction involves “confronting the
theory with empirical data.” There are two types of data to be used n
such confrontations. One is the existing data, which can be interpreted
and understood in terms of the theory. Another is the rigorous deduction
of hypotheses from the theorems, which serve to organize the collection
of new data.'*
In sum, then, the creative act of theory construction involves (1) a
conception of what is to be explained, (2) familiarity with relevant knowl-
edge, (3) a central term or operator, (4) conceptual elaboration and clar-
ification, (5) a deductive system of propositions, and (6) confrontation of
the theory with empirical data. This vision has clearly guided the sub-
stantive formulation of Blau’s theory of macrostructure.
“Blau has attempted to do so. For example, see his and Joseph E. Schwartz's, Cross-
cutting Social Circles (Orlando, Fla.:; Academic Press, 1984).
*Tbid., p. 245.
430 CHAPTER 20 / THE MACROSTRUCTURALISM OF PETER M. BLAU
|. The more multiple parameters intersect and remain unconsolidated, the greater
is the degree of heterogeneity and the less is the level of inequality, and hence,
the more likely are social associations among people (from Axioms |, Il, and VI).
ll. The more multiple parameters intersect or consolidate, the more likely is their
effect on social associations to exceed the additive effects of the parameters
alone (from Axioms |, Ill, IV, and VIil).
lil. The more parameters intersect, the greater is the rate of mobility, and the more
likely are social associations (from Axioms |, Il, V, and VII).
IV. The greater is the size differences between two groups or status ranks
distinguished by a parameter, the more likely are social associations among
members in the smaller group or rank with members of the larger group to
exceed those of members in the larger group with those in the smaller (from
Axioms |, Il, Vi, and VIl).
whereas the larger group has more people who can have a greater number
of total relations; therefore, the same number of reciprocal relations must
represent a greater portion of the smaller than the larger groups’ total
relations.
From these four theorems, then, I believe that most other theorems
in Blau’s many “theorem sets” can be derived.'® Probably the most in-
teresting of the many examples that I could offer concern those that can
be derived from Theorem I on intersecting parameters and Theorem IV
on proportions. For example, Blau’s Theorem 26 postulates that “the
further society’s differentiation penetrates into successive subunits of its
structural components, the more it promotes the integration of groups by
increasing intergroup relations.’”® This theorem is directly derivable from
the notion of intersection versus consolidation of parameters (Theorem
I above). If a pattern of differentiation—for example, inequality of wealth—
repeats itself in every community in a society (this is successive pene-
tration), then the wealthy and not so wealthy people are more likely to
interact than if all wealthy people live in one community and all poor
people in another (this would be consolidation of wealth with community).
Since societies or any social system vary in terms of degrees of such
successive penetration, their integration will also vary.
Let me take another example. In Table 20-2, Blau’s Theorem IV
states that members of smaller groups or strata have more relations as a
proportion of their total with larger groups or strata than do members of
larger groups or strata with those in smaller groups.”? Thus, since the
distribution of people in status ranks will reveal a pyramid form, at least
from the middle ranks upward,”! high-ranking people are more likely to
have relations with lower-ranking persons than are lower-ranking with
higher-ranking persons. Such a simple artifact of mathematical propor-
tions can help explain, perhaps, the hostility of lower ranks toward higher
ranks, with whom they have little contact. Race and ethnic relations can
similarly be analyzed in this way, since majority members, who are the
larger group, are less likely to have relations with the minority than is
the minority with the majority. As a result, stereotypes and prejudice can
be more readily maintained when there is little contact by the majority,
especially when the processes described by this proportion principle are
exacerbated by the processes described in the intersection of parameters
principle (since minority status is often highly correlated with other po-
sitions that the majority does not occupy).
Blau’s basic theorems suggest many ways to analyze concrete empir-
ical cases, as Blau seeks to do throughout his work with various theorems
MACROSTRUCTURALISM: AN ASSESSMENT
Blau has isolated what he defines as two basic properties of the social
universe— heterogeneity and inequality as they are determined by the con-
solidation or intersection of parameters. He has also developed some ab-
stract principles about the dynamics inherent in these. This is, I believe,
the best way to develop theory; and as I have said elsewhere, I consider
this effort one of the most significant of this century.”* Having said this,
however, I will mention what I see as two limitations.
First, I think that the theory is too functional. In Figure 20-1, I have
diagramed Blau’s basic model to highlight this implicit functionalism. In
a subtle way, Blau assumes a functional need for integration of society
and views high rates of interactions as the way to meet this need. The
theoretical question then becomes one of determining what macrostruc-
tural forces affect rates of interaction. His answer: intersection and con-
solidation of parameters as they determine the respective levels of het-
erogeneity and inequality in a population. Many objections to this kind
of functional reasoning are immediately obviated by the fact that Blau
translates his ideas into propositions where the dependent variable is
‘social association” and “rates of interaction” without any functional
trimmings (about “needs,” “requisites,” and the like). Nonetheless, I raise
the issue because it limits the range of phenomena about which Blau is
Number and
clarity of
nominal and
graduated
parameters
Patterns of Degree to which
inequality Rates of functional need
and interaction -for social
heterogeneity integration is met
Degree of
intersection
and consolidation
of parameters
435
436 CHAPTER 21 / THE MICROSTRUCTURALISM OF RANDALL COLLINS
‘Randall Collins, Conflict Sociology: Toward an Explanatory Science (New York: Aca-
demic Press, 1975), p. 56.
*Randall Collins, “On the Micro-Foutdations of Macro-Sociology,” American Journal
of Sociology 86 (March 1981), pp. 984-1014; “Micro-translation as a Theory Building Strat-
egy,” in Advances in Social Theory and Methodology: Toward an Integration of Micro- and
Macro-Sociology, ed. K. Knorr-Cetina and A. V. Cicourel (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul, 1981); and “Interaction Ritual Chains, Power and Property: The Micro-Macro Con-
nection as an Empirically-Based Theoretical Problem,” in The Micro-Macro Problem. ed.
J. C. Alexander et al. (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, in press).
‘Collins, “Interaction Ritual Chains.”
‘Collins, “On the Micro-Foundations of Macro-Sociology.”
THE MICRO AND MACRO REALMS 437
Life-histo Genealo
MICRO “4 a
Ms
Several Fleeting encounters Small groups
persons ‘
‘. MACRO
"Ibid.
*Ibid.
440 CHAPTER 21 / THE MICROSTRUCTURALISM OF RANDALL COLLINS
topics, content, and even where people stand and what they are allowed
to say. For example, an authoritative boss in an office speaking to a
subordinate has more cultural capital—the ability, for instance, to control
pay, dictate where people work—and more emotional energy to mobilize
in the conversation (since it will be more rewarding for the superordinate
than subordinate). Thus, the boss will increase both his or her cultural
capital (affirmation of dominance) and emotional energy (feelings of con-
trol) from the conversation, whereas the employee will lose capital and
energy (memories of being told what to do and bad feelings about sub-
ordination). Such encounters will, if repeated and stretched across time,
become highl&.formal and ritualized with the subordinate expending as
little energy and capital as possible at each meeting.
Most encounters are, of course, less extreme than this example. There
is usually room for more negotiation in a conversational encounter. More-
over, most encounters are structured in terms of previous encounters, in
several senses. First, parties know what to expect in terms of their mem-
ories and previous feelings about the conversation, and hence, they can
take care to use their resources wisely and appropriate the correct amount
of emotional energy. Second, many encounters are circumscribed by the
macro system as it has been constructed from chains of past encounters.
There is usually a physical place where talk occurs; there is usually a
typical number of others in the situation; and there isa »rmal duration
for a conversation in a situation. Thus, an encounter in a grocery store,
in a school classroom, and in other well-known contexts where the ma-
crostructure delimits place, number, and duration and where people al-
ready have a sense for the right mixture of cultural capital and emotional
energy will proceed with relative ease and with a high degree of ritual
(stereotyped sequences of talk).
The repetition of such encounters—for example, each day at home,
the office, and school—is what builds and sustains structures. And as these
ritualized chains of interaction embrace increasingly larger numbers of
people and are extended in space in various configurations, they produce
and reproduce macrostructures.
There is an important methodological corollary to this line of theo-
retical argument.° If macrostructures are produced and sustained by chains
of interaction rituais among individuals using cultural capital and ex-
pending emotional energy, then one should study structure by sampling
encounters across time. By sampling encounters over time, it becomes
possible to have a sense for what people are doing—how they talk, gesture,
position themselves as well as how they feel about what is occurring. Such
a strategy for studying social structure involves what Collins calls micro
CONFLICT SOCIOLOGY
Collins’s general argument about the interactive foundations of social
structure and the effects of the macro dimensions of space, time, and size
on interaction were anticipated in earlier works. In Conflict Sociology,
Collins proposed the following steps for building social theory.” First,
examine typical real-life situations where people encounter each other.
Second, focus on the material arrangements that affect interaction—the
physical layout of situations, the means and modes of communication,
the available tools, weapons, and goods. Third, assess the relative resources
1°1t really should have been “exchange sociology,” but I guess that “conflict sociology”
sounded better and appealed more to the bias of sociology. See his Conflict Sociology.
“See, for example, Randall Collins, “Long-term Social Change and the Territorial Power
of States” in his Sociology Since Midcentury: Essays in Theory Cumulation (New York:
Academic Press, 1981).
“2Collins, Conflict Sociology, pp. 60-61.
442 CHAPTER 21 / THE MICROSTRUCTURALISM OF RANDALL COLLINS
that people bring to, use in, or extract from encounters. Fourth, entertain
the general hypotheses that those with resources press their advantage,
that those without resources seek the best deal they can get under the
circumstances, and that stability and change are to be explained in terms
of the lineups and shifts in the distribution of resources. Fifth, assume
that cultural symbols—ideas, beliefs, norms, values, and the like—are used
to represent the interests of those parties who have the resources to make
their views prevail. Sixth, look for the general and generic features of
particular cases so that more abstract propositions can be extracted from
the empirical particulars of a situation.
Thus, as with his recent work on interaction rituals, there is a concern
with the encounter, with the distribution of individuals in physical space,
with their respective capital or resources to use in exchanges, and with
inequalities in resources. As with his recent work, the respective resources
of individuals are critical: “power” is the capacity to coerce or to have
others do so on one’s behalf; “material resources” are wealth and the
control of money as well as property or the capacity to control the physical
setting and people’s place in it; and “symbolic resources” are the respective
levels of linguistic and conversational resources as well as the capacity to
use cultural ideas, such as ideologies, values, and beliefs, for one’s purposes.
A central consideration in all of Collins’s propositions is ‘“‘social den-
sity,” or the number of people co-present in a situation where an encounter
takes place. Social density is, of course, part of the macrostructure since
it is typically the result of past chains of interaction. But it can also be
a “material resource” that some individuals can use to their advantage.
Thus, the interaction in an encounter will be most affected by the par-
ticipants’ relative resources and the density or number of individuals co-
present. These variables influence the two underlying micro dynamics in
Collins’s scheme, talk, and ritual.
“Emile Durkheim, The Elementary Forms oj the Religious Life (New York: Free Press.
1948; originally published in 1912).
See, for example, The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life and other works by Erving
Goffman, including: Encounters (Indianapolis, Ind.: Bobbs- Merrill, 1961}; Interaction Ritual
oan York: Anchor Books, 1967); and Behavior in Public Places (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
See A. R. Radcliffe-Brown, The Andaman Islanders (New York: Free Press, 1948:
originally published in 1922); Bronislaw Malinowski, Magic, Science and Religion (Garden
City, N. Y.: Doubleday Publishing, 1948).
CONFLICT SOCIOLOGY 445
movement into or out of the group will be marked by rituals (ranging, for
example, from greetings of welcome to a tear-filled farewell party).
Thus, the essence of interaction is talk and ritual; and as chains of
encounters are linked together over time, conversations take on a more
personal and also a ritualized character that results from and, at the same
time, reinforces the growing sense of group solidarity among individuals.
Such is the case because the individuals have “invested” their cultural
capital (conversational resources) and have derived positive feelings from
being defined as group members. I do not think that Collins has developed
these ideas to any great extent, but we can see his intent: to view social
structure as the linking together of encounters through talk and ritual.
This basic view of the micro reality of social life pervades all of Collins’s
sociology, especially as he begins to move to the analysis of inequalities
in social life.
Class Cultures
These microprocesses of talk, ritual, deference, and demeanor explain
what are often seen as more macroprocesses in societies. One such process
"Randall Collins and Joan Annett, “A Short History of Deference and Demeanor.” in
Conflict Sociology, pp. 161-224.
'Tbid., pp. 216-19.
CONFLICT SOCIOLOGY 447
is variation in the class cultures. That is, people in different social classes
tend to exhibit diverging behaviors, outlooks, and interpersonal styles.
These differences are accountable in terms of two main variables:
1. The degree to which one possesses and uses the capacity to coerce,
to materially bestow, and to symbolically manipulate others so that
one can give orders in an encounter and have these orders followed.
2. The degree to which communication is confined to others who are
physically co-present in a situation, or conversely, the degree to
which communication is diverse, involving the use of multiple modes
of contact with many others in different situations.
Utilizing these two general classes of variables, which are part of the
macrostructure that has been built up in past chains of interaction as
well as several less central ones such as wealth and physical exertion on
the job, Collins describes the class cultures of American society. More
aad CHAPTER 21 / THE MICROSTRUCTURALISM OF RANDALL COLLINS
Sexual Stratification
The propositions in Tables 21-1 through 21-4 represent, I think, Collins’s
theoretical approach to the analysis of stratification. The propositions in
these tables provide the basic principles for the analysis of specific forms
of stratiiication, such as those created by age and sexual categories. For
as is clearly evident, stratification for Collins is a process that occurs in
types of encounters among individuals in diverse spheres of life. One such
sphere is encounters between males and females that become organized
into family relations and elaborated into kinship systems. In Table 21-
5, I have summarized some of Collins’s propositions on sexual stratifi-
cation. Deductions from these, Collins implicitly argues, can help explain
the nature of talk and ritual between the sexes as well as the structuring
of male-female encounters in kinship systems. These latter deductions
are not produced in the table, but Collins provides numerous additional
propositions”® and discursive text?! to illustrate the properties and dy-
namics of sexual stratification.
; These propositions can, in Collins’s eyes, explain the diversity in
chains of sexual encounters and the resulting structure of family systems.
For example, in societies where females perform much of the economic
,
aaa
labor and where wealth is passed through the female line (as is the case
in matrilineal kinship systems), male dominance is greatly mitigated. Or
in American society, females who enter the labor force possess resources
to counter the males’ control of the means of coercion, thereby reducing
male dominance (especially since the state rather than kin groups is the
ultimate source of coercive power in the society). Conversely, women who
do not work are often forced to counter the economic and coercive power
of males by limiting sexual encounters and by ritualizing such encounters
when they do occur. Many other specific forms of male-female stratifi-
cation can, in Collins’s view, be explained by making deductions from
these abstract propositions to specific empirical cases. But such expla-
nations do not rely upon concepts of norms, values, and roles. Rather,
they emphasize the respective resources that people have and how these
determine what happens in an encounter as well as how structures are
built up from chains of encounters among individuals with varying
resources.
Age Stratification
Another universal form of stratification is by age, which, like sexual re-
lations, involves control of resources by individuals in one age group and
efforts by individuals in subordinaie age groups to mitigate their situation
in daily encounters. I have listed several of Collins’s key propositions on
this in Table 21-6. These propositions can, I think, explain variations in
age stratification.” For example, among poor families in America, parents
often possess only physical coercion in abundance (not having money,
Organizational Processes
After examining stratification processes, Collins turns to an extensive
analysis of organizations and develops a rather long inventory of prop-
ositions on their properties and dynamics.”* These propositions overlap,
to some degree, with those on stratification, since an organization is typ-
ically a stratified system with a comparatively clear hierarchy of authority.
In Table 21-7, I have extracted only three groups of propositions from
Collins’s analysis. These revolve around processes of organizational con-
trol, the administration of control, and the general organizational struc-
ture. Other topic areas in Collins’s inventory are either incorporated into
these propositions or omitted. Moreover, I have rephrased considerably
the propositions and have also stated them at a higher level of abstraction
than in Collins’s text. By placing the propositions at a high level of ab-
straction, I think that they can explain political control in more than
complex organizations; in my view, they would seem relevant to under-
standing other patterns of social organization, such as entire societies.
Even as Collins begins to examine more macrostructures, like bu-
reaucratic organizations, it is evident that the conceptual emphasis is on
microprocesses. Organization control, its administration, and the general
structure of an organization are all created and sustained by people using
resources in encounters. As these encounters are repeated, the chains of
interactions develop a structure, whose profile depends on the respective
levels and types of resources possessed by participants.
state and economy.” A cursory look at Table 21-8 reveals, I think, few
‘eferences to individuals at the micro level. One might, as Collins would
msist, make micro translations of the processes incorporated into the
propositions, but it is clear that Collins abandons discussions of micro-
interactional ritual chains when he begins to talk about large-scale social
processes. And even his insistence that the macro is no more than size,
number, and time seems somewhat strained, although population size and
extent of territory are crucial variables in the propositions.
MICROSTRUCTURALISM: AN ASSESSMENT
I think that Collins’s work is among the most creative in social theory
today. Its great strength resides in the effort to develop abstract propo-
sitions about fundamental properties of the universe. For unlike so many
in social theory today, Collins is not so antipositivist that he must retreat
into an excessive relativism and solipsism.
A related strength in Collins’s approach is his willingness to theorize.
Meta-theoretical pontification is minimal; and he gets right down to the
business of developing propositions about the social universe. Moreover,
he is willing to theorize about a wide range of phenomena in terms of
just a few fundamental ideas. He thus achieves breadth of substantive
analysis without an overly elaborate conceptual scheme. Instead, he makes
deductions from a limited number of basic prupositions.
ically deal with (1) the respective resources of individuals, (2) the effort
to use resources to advantage and to avoid heavy costs in the process, (3)
the differentiation of individuals in terms of their respective resources,
and (4) the processes by which such differentiation is regularized, on the
one hand, and is the source of conflict and change, on the other. Collins’s
ideas on “interaction ritual chains” do this to some extent, but only in
a most imprecise and metaphorical sense. I believe that considerably more
attention should be devoted to rigorous definitions of concepts and explicit
formulation of his implicit exchange theoretic propositions. In this way,
the full potential of this microstructural approach can be realized.
CHAPTER 22
"The basic theory is presented in numerous places, but the two most comprehensive
statements are Anthony Giddens, The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of
Structuration (Oxford: Polity Press, 1984) and Central Problems in Social Theory (London:
Macmillan Press, LTD, 1979). The University of California Press also has editions of these
two books.
*See, in particular, Anthony Giddens, Profiles and Critiques in Sucial Theory (London:
Macmillan Press LTD, 1982) and New Rules of Sociological Method: A Positive Critique
of Interpretative Sociologies (London: Hutchinson Ross Publishing Co., 1976).
456
THE CRITIQUE OF SOCIAL THEORY 457
what I feel is a shortsighted view, he flatly dismisses the idea that sociology
can be like the natural sciences. For Giddens, there can be no enduring
abstract laws about social processes. In asserting this view, he echoes
Herbert Blumer’s charge that social organization is changeable by the
acts of individuals, and thus, there can be no laws about the invariant
properties of social organization.? And much like Blumer, he visualizes
“the concepts of theory . .. should for many research purposes be regarded
as sensitizing devices, nothing more.”‘ I should emphasize, however, that
the reasons for this assertion are different than those traditionally ad-
vocated by Chicago School symbolic interactionism.
First, Giddens asserts that social theorizing involves a ‘‘double her-
meneutic” that, stripped of this jargon, asserts that the concepts and
generalizations used by social scientists to understand social processes
can be employed by agents to alter these processes, thereby potentially
obviating the generalizations of “science.” We must recognize, Giddens
contends, that lay actors are also “social theorists who alter their theories
in the light of their experience and are receptive to incoming informa-
tion.’> And thus, social science theories are not often ‘“‘news”’ to lay actors,
and when they are, such theories can be used to transform the very order
they describe. For within the capacity of humans to be reflexive—that is,
to think about their situation—is the ability to change it.®
Second, social theory is by its nature social criticism. Social theory
often contradicts ‘“‘the reasons that people give for doing things”’ and is,
therefore, a critique of these reasons and the social arrangements that
people construct in the name of these reasons. Sociology does not, there-
fore, need to develop a separate body of critical theory, as others have
argued (see Chapter 9); it is critical theory by its very nature and by virtue
of the effects it can have on social processes.
The implications of these facts, Giddens believes, are profound. We
need to stop imitating the natural sciences. We must cease evaluating our
success as an intellectual activity in terms of whether or not we have
discovered “timeless laws.” We must recognize that social theory does
not exist “outside” our universe. We should accept the fact that what
sociologists and lay actors do is, in a fundamental sense, very much the
same. And, we must redirect our efforts at developing “sensitizing con-
cepts” that allow us to understand the active processes of interaction
among individuals as they produce and reproduce social structures while
being guided by these structures.
"Ibid., p. 26.
*Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory, p. 69.
THE CRITIQUE OF SOCIAL THEORY 459
That is, social structure is used by active agents; and in so using the
properties of structure, they transferm or reproduce this structure. Thus,
the process of structuration requires a conceptualization of the nature of
structure, of the agents who use structure, and of the ways that these are
mutually implicated in each other to produce varying patterns of human
organization.
FIGURE 22-1 Social Structure, Social System, and the Modalities of Connection
Allocative resources
(domination)
Reconceptualizing Institutions
For Giddens, institutions are systems of interaction in societies that en-
dure over time and that distribute people in space. Giddens uses what I
see as rather vague phrases like “deeply sedimented across time and in
space in societies” to express the idea that when rules and resources are
reproduced over long periods of time and in explicit regions of space, then
institutions can be said to exist in a society. Giddens offers a typology of
institutions in terms of the weights and combinations of rules and re-
sources that are implicated in interaction." If signification (interpretative
rules) is primary, followed respectively by domination (allocative and au-
thoritative resources) and then by legitimation (normative rules), a “sym-
bolic order” exists. If authoritative domination, signification, and legi-
timation are successively combined, political institutionalization occurs.
If allocative dominance, signification, and legitimation are ordered. eco-
‘*Central Problems in Social Theory, p. 107; and The Constitution of Society, p. 31.
THE “THEORY OF STRUCTURATION” 465
actors that gives the stabilization of relations across time and in space
its distinctive institutional character.
To his credit, Giddens is unlike many interactionists because he wants
to acknowledge the importance of analyzing stabilized social relations—
that is, institutionalization. But as with all interactionist theory, he wishes
to stress that institutionalized social relations are actively reproduced in
terms of the creative transformations of rules and resources that are em-
ployed by agents in actual interaction. Thus, one of the most important
structural features of social relations is their institutionalization in space
and across time. Such institutionalization moves along four dimensions—
law, economy, political, and symbolic—which are distinguished from each
other in terms of the relative use of various rules and resources. I am not
sure that he needed the typology in Table 22-1 to make this important
point, but it is the vehicle by which he chose to make his argument, and
so, I have discussed it here.
structural principles that separate and yet interconnect all four institu-
tional spheres, especially the economic and political.’
Structural principles are implicated in the production and reproduc-
tion of “structures” or “structural sets.”” These structural sets are rule/
resource bundles, or combinations and configurations of rules and re-
sources, which are used to produce and reproduce certain types and forms
of social relations across time and space. Giddens offers the example of
how the structural principles of class societies (differentiation and clear
separation of economy and polity) guide the use of the following structural
set: private property-money-capital-labor-contract-profit. The details of
his analysis are less important than the general idea that the general
structural principles of class societies are transformed into more specific
sets of rules and resources that agents use to mediate social relations. The
above structural set is used in capitalist societies and, as a consequence,
is reproduced. In turn, such reproduction of the structural set reaffirms
the more abstract structural principles of class societies.
As these and other structural sets are used by agents and as they are
thereby reproduced, societies develop “structural properties,” which are
““institutionalized features of social systems, stretching across time and
space.’° That is, social relations become patterned in certain typical ways.
Thus, the structural set of private property-money-capital-labor contract-
profit can mediate only certain patterns of relations; that is, if this is the
rule/resource bundle with which agents must work, then only certain
forms of relations can be produced and reproduced in the economic sphere.
Hence, the institutionalization of relations in time and space reveals a
particular form, or in Giddens’s terms, structural property.
Structural Contradiction
Giddens always wants to emphasize the inherent “transformative” po-
tential of rules and resources. Structural principles, he argues, “‘operate
in terms of one another but yet also contravene each other.’?! In other
words, they reveal contradictions that can be either primary or secondary.
A “primary contradiction” is one between structural principles that-are
formative and constitute a society, whereas a “secondary contradiction”
is one that is “brought into being by primary contradictions.”” For ex-
ample, there is a contradiction between structural principles that mediate
the institutionalization of private profits, on the one hand, and those that
mediate socialized production, on the other. If workers pool their labor
*Ibid., p. 198.
THE ‘THEORY OF STRUCTURATION”: 469
Institutionalized
patterns
(a) Regionalized contexts
(b) Routinized contexts
|
Reflexive monitoring of actions
Rationalization through
discursive consciousness
|
Interpretation through
practical consciousness
|
Unconscious pressures
|
Unconscious motives to sustain
ontological security
(achieving trust with others
and reducing anxiety)
in other words, they pay attention, note, calculate, and assess the con-
sequences of actions. Monitoring is influenced by two levels of con-
sciousness. One is “discursive consciousness,” which involves the ca-
pacity to give reasons for or rationalize what one does (and presumably
to do the same for others’ behavior). “Practical consciousness” is the
stock of knowledge that one implicitly uses to act in situations and to
interpret the actions of others. It is this knowledgeability that is con-
stantly used, but rarely articulated, to interpret events—one’s own and
those of others. Almost all acts are indexical, to use Garfinkel’s term, in
that they must be interpreted by their context; and it is this implicit stock
*Tbid., pp. 5-7; see also Central Problems in Social Theory, pp. 56-59.
*His debt to Schutz and phenomenology is evident here, but he has liberated it from
its subjectivism. See Chapter 14 on the emergence of interactionism.
470 CHAPTER 22 / THE STRUCTURATION THEORY OF ANTHONY GIDDENS
*Here Giddens is using ideas of phenomenology and ethnomethodology without all the
ontological and metaphorical rhetoric.
"The Constitution of Society, pp. 45-59.
THE ‘‘THEORY OF STRUCTURATION” 471
a1
The Constitution of Society, p. 75. Surprisingly, Giddens never really dennes “tact,”
assuming we know what it means. I had to infer this definition.
THE ‘THEORY OF STRUCTURATION” 473
un-
motivation. The result is a perspective that ties diffuse and largely
conscious needs for “ontological security” into actors’ reflexive monitor-
ing, use of ethno methods, and participation in routinized interaction.
Such are the strong points of Giddens’s theory, as I see them. He has
performed, I feel, a remarkable synthesis that demonstrates how very
diverse theoretical perspectives can be pulled together into a reasonably
coherent theoretical scheme. I do see many problems with his approach,
however. Let me now turn to these, cautioning that my perception is
guided by my theoretical bias, which Giddens and many others in soci-
ology do not share.
One major problem is that while Giddens’s writing is crisp and elo-
quent, it is also vague. There is a great deal of jargon, metaphor, and just
plain imprecision. It is often difficult to understand in more than a general
way what is being said. I sense that “‘structuration theory” is very much
like Parsonian functionalism in at least one sense: one has to “internalize”
the perspective with all its imprecision in order to use it. One must become
an intellectual convert to Giddens’s cause and, in the best tradition of
the ethnomethodologists’ et cetera principle, accept what he has to say,
even though you cannot quite understand some of it. One must feel, as
opposed to verbalize, elements of structuration theory; and this is not, I
feel, the way to build social theory.
The above is a remarkable conclusion, I admit, in light of the fact
that the theory has been articulated several times in major works, has
received considerable and deserved attention,® has always offered many
definitions of concepts and graphic portrayals of their relations, and has
even presented us with a glossary of theoretical terms in its latest incar-
nation.** Thus, it might be seriously asked: how can IJ reach the conclusion
that the theory is vague? It just is, for several reasons. First, the theory
is actually a series of definitions. The linkages among concepts are always
rather vaguely stated, despite their suggestiveness. Second, Giddens often
argues by example rather than analytically. It is extremely difficult to
interpret an analytical discussion that is presented by example. (For ex-
ample, Giddens offers the same example in several works to illustrate the
concepts of structural principles and structural sets; and yet, the defini-
tions of these ideas and the conceptual discussion of them aré decidedly
unclear.)
Another problem is that Giddens’s theory is, in reality, only a system
of concepts. It is very much like Talcott Parsons’s strategy of “analytical
realism,” although I find Giddens’s scheme far more interesting and in-
%*For recent commentaries, see the special volumes of the following journals devoted to
Giddens’s work: Theory, Culture, and Society, vol. 1 (no. 2, 1982) and Journal for the
Theory of Social Behavior, vol. 13 (no. 1, 1983). See also John B. Thompson, Studies in
the Theory of Ideology (Berkeley, Calif.; University of California Press, 1984).
*The Constitution of Society, pp. 373-77.
THE THEORY OF STRUCTURATION: A SUMMARY AND ASSESSMENT 477
*7And in Chapter 6 of ibid., he uses the scheme to re-interpret insightfully several em-
pirical studies.
478 CHAPTER 22 / THE STRUCTURATION THEORY OF ANTHONY GIDDENS
just because lay actors know about them and lock them into their dis-
cursive and practical consciousness, these properties will not change. Sec-
ond, and this is related to the above point, Giddens has a very narrow
view of what a law is. For Giddens, a law is an empirical generalization—
a statement of covariance among empirical events. If this is your vision
of law, then it is easy to assert that there are no universal laws, since
indeed empirical events change (in accord, I should add, with many of
the invariant processes in Giddens’s conceptual scheme). Third, I think
there are several examples of laws in Giddens’s scheme, and it is at just
these points where he articulates a law that the scheme takes on more
clarity and, for me at least, more interest. Here is one example of a law
that Giddens articulates but that he would deny as universal: ““The level
of anxiety experienced at the level of discursive and practical levels of
consciousness is a positive function of the degree of disruption in the
daily routines for an actor.” There is also a similar proposition about
anxiety and unconscious trust and ontological security, but I will for the
present ignore this. There are many propositions like this one in Giddens’s
scheme; and these are universal. If they were not, then his scheme would
not make any sense. And most importantly, the law is not obviated by
our knowledge of it, for an actor will not feel less anxiety if day-to-day
routines are disrupted. One might even use the law to diagnose the prob-
lem and create new, or restore the old, routines, but in the process, the
law has not been obviated. For, when one’s routines are disrupted, the
individual will experience anxiety.
I have not extracted these and many propositions from Giddens, since
it would violate the essence of his approach. But here resides the great
flaw; and I hope that others working with Giddens’s concept are not so
antipositivistic as he. For there is too much insight into the basic prop-
erties and dynamics of human action, interaction, and organization to
use the scheme as a mere “sensitizing device.” It has far more potential
than Giddens would admit for helping develop a natural science of so-
ciety—that is, for developing abstract laws of the social universe.
_ Name Index _
Abbelbaum, Richard P., 135 n Blau, Peter M., 14n, 16n, 20 n, 150 n,
Abrahamsson, Bengt, 250 n 221 n, 229, 261-86
Adorno, Theordor, 130 n, 185, 187-88 Blumer, Herbert, 6 n, 333, 337-48, 390 n,
Alexander, Jeffrey C., 9; 59 n, 102 n, 4361 457
Allen, V. L., 362 n, 363 n Boissevain, Jeremy F., 287 n
Althusser, Louis, 150 n, 408 n Boorman, Scott A., 427 n
Anderson, Alan R., 363 n Boskoff, Alvin, 363 n
Anderson, B., 255 n, 288 n, 290 n Bottomore, Tom, 109 n, 229 n, 423 n
Angel, Robert C., 180 n Boulding, Kenneth, 131 n, 242 n
Annett, Joan, 445 Braithwaite, R. B., 80n
Antonio, Robert J., 184 n, 185 n, 325n Bredemeier, Harry C., 80n
Assiter, Alison, 408 n Breer, Paul E., 362 n
Attewell, Paul, 391 Brieger, Ronald L., 427n
Brim, Orville G., 362 n
Britt, David, 131
Bales, Robert, 68 Brodbeck, M., 80 n
Barber, Bernard, 80 n, 102 n Broderson, Arvid, 392 n
Bauman, Zygmunt, 184, 324 Buck, Gary, L., 76 n
Becker, Howard, 362 n Buckley, Walter, 253 n
Beeghley, Leonard, 1 n, 42 n, 57n, 146 n, Bulmer, Martin, 334 n
226 n, 313 n, 413 n Burgess, R. L., 255 n, 288 n
Belsky, S., 225 n Burt, Ronald, 288 n
Bendix, R., 321 n Bushell, D., Jr., 255 n, 288 n
Bentham, Jeremy, 215
Berger, Peter L. 324n
Berger, J., 255 n, 288 n, 290n
Berghe, Pierre L. van de, 140 n, 163 n Cancian, Francesca, 80 n
Bergman, G., 82 n Canfield, J., 82n
Bernard, Jessie, 131 n Cardwell, J., 334 n
Biddle, Bruce J., 354 n, 355 n, 358 n, Cartwright, Darwin, 355 n
359 n, 363 n Carver, Thomas, 131 n
Bierstedt, 250 n Cicourel, A. V., 30 n, 396, 401, 436
Billings, Victoria, 373 n Cohen, Jere, 60 n
n
Blain, Robert, 248 n, 252 n, 253 n Cohen, Percy S., 47 n, 80 n, 158 n, 284
Coleman, James, 131 n, 216 n
Blalock, Herbert M., 3 n
ii NAME INDEX
Mead, George Herbert, 209, 310-18, 329, Pollner, Melvin, 4 n, 393 n, 402-3
418-20 Pollock, Friedrich, 185 n
Meeker, B. F., 251 n Pope, Whitney, 60 n
Mehan, Hugh, 392, 393 n, 395 n, 396 Popper, Karl R., 3 n, 25
Meltzer, Bernard N., 313 n, 333 n, 334 n, Price, Robert, 251 n
336, 337 n, 346 n Psathas, George, 4 n, 324n, 325 n, 393 n
Merton, Robert K., 15 n, 80 n, 87-102,
220, 356 n, 363 n, 367 n
Meyer, Max F., 226n Quarantelli, E. L., 341
Mill, John Stuart, 215 Quetelet, Adolphe, 40
Mills, C. Wright, 53 n, 79 n
Mitchell, J. Clyde, 287 n
Miyamoto, Frank, 341 n Radcliffe-Brown, A. R., 2 n, 47-50, 54, 90,
Moore, Omar K., 363 n 444
Moreno, Jacob L., 319, 354 n, 355 n Rapoport, Anatol, 131 n
Morris, C. W., 313 n Rexroat, Cynthia, 341 n
Morton, Richard T., 363 n Reynolds, Paul Davidson, 3 n, 7 n
Mulford, Harold A., 341 n Rhoads, John K., 80n
Mulkay, M. J. 236 n, 250 n, 284n Ricardo, David, 215
Mullins, Nicholas C., 3n Ritzer, George, 31 n, 325 n
Minch, Richard, 10, 11 n, 57n, 102n Rommetveit, Ragnar, 359 n
Rose, Arnold, 334 n, 335, 336, 342 n, 369 n,
390 n
Nadel, S. F., 80 n Rosenberg, Bernard G., 359 n
Naegele, K. D., 72 Rosenberg, M., 353 n
Nagel, Ernest, 80 n, 82 Rossi, Ino, 408 n
Natanson, Maurice, 324 n, 327 n
Neiman, Lionel T., 359 n
Neisser, Hans P., 324 n Sacks, Harvey, 395 n, 400-401
Newmann, Franz, 185 Sahlins, Marshall D., 424
Nisbet, Robert A., 47 n, 423 Salisbury, Winfield W., II, 341 n
Sarbin, Theodore R., 341 n, 361 n, 362 n,
363 n
Oberschall, Anthony, 131 n Saussure, Ferdinand de, 422
Oeser, Oscar A., 355 n Scheff, Thomas, 362 n
Scheffer, I., 82 n
Schegloff, Emmanuel, 400 n
Park, Robert, 318-19 Schelling, Thomas C., 131 n
Parsons, Talcott, 3 n, 10, 11 n, 52-53, 57- Schneider, David, 240-41
86, 87 n, 91, 102, 103 n, 104 n, 108, Schroyer, Trent, 130 n, 184n
114n, 120 n, 129-30, 150, 163 n, 164- Schutz, Alfred, 4 n, 209, 323-24, 327-31,
65, 181, 199, 209-10, 216, 229, 239, 391-92, 418, 469 n
240 n, 250 n, 252 n, 258 n, 262-63, Schwanenberg, Enno, 59 n
275-77, 283, 358 n, 367 n, 412, 416, Schwartz, Joseph E., 429 n
420, 463, 476-77 Scott, John Finley, 361 n
Partland, L. S., 337 n Scott, Joseph F., 57n
Patterson, John S., 131 n Seeba, G., 62 n, 416 n
Pavlov, Ivan Petrovich, 225 Sellars, W., 82 n
Petras, Jerome W., 333 n, 337 n, 346 n Shapiro, J., 191 n
Piaget, Jean, 200 n Shaw, Marvin E., 358 n, 359 n
Pitts, J. R., 72 n Shibutani, Tamotsu, 313 n, 333 n, 334 n,
Plamenatz, John, 216 n 341 n, 352 n, 356 n, 359 n, 362 n
Plato, 41 n, 422 Shils, Edward, 66 n, 68, 72 n, 163 n
Platt, Gerald M., 73 n Shosid, Norma, 387 n
NAME INDEX Vv
eta Fy,
*\% pee
mse ret = fa
ete Se al
eh .
ny 06% Pepi “off Hatibigs
‘\ weet sash pels ee At OF nnBtw ftnadtenct. wrt
eT
PLAT
WER MOET tyson cleX AOE ct OR, ‘Shug 8he Oe nt | a
rye Rae « ae . Po
eee Pd Za, te
im She Me a
. Mecegen = ul es
() i ih SeeA. or
oie, Cota RO TP mae
epi Re
Subject Index
vii
viii SUBJECT INDEX
Differentiation—Cont. Ethnomethodology—Cont.
of economic systems, 121 decision rules, 399
extended, 113-14 et cetera principle, 397
functional, 115 to expose scientific bias, 393
increases risk of dysfunction, 116 formal properties of language-in-use, 400
among individuals’ roles, 114-15 general intent of, 400
internal, 114 indexicality, 395-96, 398
material, 116 as interactionism, 389
of a political system, 118 language and reality construction, 398
segmentation, 115 lifeworld, 391-92; see also Lifeworld
social, 114 normal form, 396
stratification, 115 occasioned corpus, 402-3
symbolic effects, 117 and phenomenology, 389-90, 392
Diffuseness-specificity, 65 reciprocity of objectives, 396
Digraph notation, 296, 304 reflexive action, 395
Division of labor, 133 “sense” of reality, 393-94
Division of Labor in Society (Durkhiem), soft research methods, 393-94
45, 322 symbolic communication, 396
Double hermeneutic, 457 universal interpretive procedures, 401
Dramaturgical school of interactionism, Evolution of society, 112-17
391 and differentiation, 112-16
Dramaturgy, 459 dual process of, 211
Dualisms, versus dualities, 458-59 as increasing integration, 199
learning levels, 200
selection mechanism, 113
Economic man, 263 temporal effects, 116
Economic perspective in sociology, 37 variation mechanisms, 113
Economic systems, 121-24 Evolutionary theory, 458-59
complexity of and risk, 123 Exchange behaviorism, 240-49
deterministic social structure, 134 altered economic assumptions, 243
domination by, 149 deductive schemes within, 246-49
markets in, 121-22 discontinuity between macro and micro
money as a medium of, 122 theory, 304
and time, 121-22 elementary exchange principles, 244
tripart internal differentiation on, 123 human behavior as exchange of rewards,
Economy, governmental power in, 123 242
Economy and Society (Parsons & institutionalization, 258
Smelser), 69 institutions and human needs, 260
Economy and Society (Weber), 416 misplaced concreteness in, 252-53
The Elementary Forms of Religious Life patterns of organization, 259
(Durkheim), 322, 415, 444 propositions, 244-46
The Elementary Structures of Kinship rationality proposition, 244-45, 248
(Levi-Strauss), 222, 421, 424 reductionism in, 251-55
Emancipation, social force for, 145 relationships of parts, 252-53
Empirical generelizations as theory, 15-16, reward potential formula, 244
89, 234-35 variables, 244
abstractness and scope of, 23 Exchange network theory
and causal models, 19 actors and, 293
level of abstractness, 16 alternative sources of supply, 298
theoretical value of, 25 balancing operations, 293-93, 298-99
Ethnomethodology, 332, 389-404 basic concepts, 291
background features of interaction, 399 centrality, 301-3
breeching experiment, 398-99 coalitions, 298
common reality, 397 closed exchange relations, 299-302
SUBJECT INDEX xi
V1 999l
peel
xvi SUBJECT INDEX
i
i