41936
41936
https://ebooksecure.com/download/act-elite-ebook-pdf/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-the-powerscore-digital-
lsat-logical-reasoning-bible-2020th-edition/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-the-powerscore-digital-
lsat-logic-games-bible-powerscore-test-preparation-2020th-
edition/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-melvilles-taxation-
finance-act-2019-25th-edition/
https://ebooksecure.com/download/conquering-act-math-and-science-
ebook-pdf/
(eBook PDF) Taxation Finance Act 2017 by Alan Melville
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-taxation-finance-
act-2017-by-alan-melville/
https://ebooksecure.com/download/taxation-finance-act-2022-28th-
edition-ebook-pdf/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-melvilles-taxation-
finance-act-2018-by-alan-melville/
http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-working-with-the-
residential-tenancies-act-fourth-edition-4th/
https://ebooksecure.com/download/500-act-math-questions-to-know-
by-test-day-ebook-pdf/
Copyright © 2019 by McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. Except as permitted under
the United States Copyright Act of 1976, no part of this publication may be reproduced or
distributed in any form or by any means, or stored in a database or retrieval system, without
the prior written permission of the publisher.
ISBN: 978-1-26-045362-1
MHID: 1-26-045362-6
The material in this eBook also appears in the print version of this title: ISBN: 978-1-26-
045361-4, MHID: 1-26-045361-8.
All trademarks are trademarks of their respective owners. Rather than put a trademark
symbol after every occurrence of a trademarked name, we use names in an editorial fashion
only, and to the benefit of the trademark owner, with no intention of infringement of the
trademark. Where such designations appear in this book, they have been printed with initial
caps.
McGraw-Hill Education eBooks are available at special quantity discounts to use as premiums
and sales promotions or for use in corporate training programs. To contact a representative,
please visit the Contact Us page at www.mhprofessional.com.
ACT is a registered trademark of ACT, which was not involved in the production of, and does
not endorse, this product.
TERMS OF USE
This is a copyrighted work and McGraw-Hill Education and its licensors reserve all rights in
and to the work. Use of this work is subject to these terms. Except as permitted under the
Copyright Act of 1976 and the right to store and retrieve one copy of the work, you may not
decompile, disassemble, reverse engineer, reproduce, modify, create derivative works based
upon, transmit, distribute, disseminate, sell, publish or sublicense the work or any part of it
without McGraw-Hill Education’s prior consent. You may use the work for your own
noncommercial and personal use; any other use of the work is strictly prohibited. Your right to
use the work may be terminated if you fail to comply with these terms.
THE WORK IS PROVIDED “AS IS.” McGRAW-HILL EDUCATION AND ITS LICENSORS MAKE
NO GUARANTEES OR WARRANTIES AS TO THE ACCURACY, ADEQUACY OR
COMPLETENESS OF OR RESULTS TO BE OBTAINED FROM USING THE WORK,
INCLUDING ANY INFORMATION THAT CAN BE ACCESSED THROUGH THE WORK VIA
HYPERLINK OR OTHERWISE, AND EXPRESSLY DISCLAIM ANY WARRANTY, EXPRESS OR
IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO IMPLIED WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR A PARTICULAR PURPOSE. McGraw-Hill Education
and its licensors do not warrant or guarantee that the functions contained in the work will
meet your requirements or that its operation will be uninterrupted or error free. Neither
McGraw-Hill Education nor its licensors shall be liable to you or anyone else for any
inaccuracy, error or omission, regardless of cause, in the work or for any damages resulting
therefrom. McGraw-Hill Education has no responsibility for the content of any information
accessed through the work. Under no circumstances shall McGraw-Hill Education and/or its
licensors be liable for any indirect, incidental, special, punitive, consequential or similar
damages that result from the use of or inability to use the work, even if any of them has been
advised of the possibility of such damages. This limitation of liability shall apply to any claim
or cause whatsoever whether such claim or cause arises in contract, tort or otherwise.
Acknowledgments
The author would like to acknowledge the contribution of the faculty and staff of Advantage
Education. You are not only the smartest, but also the best.
Contributing authors Aishah Ali, Pamela Chamberlain, Jennifer Gensterblum, Matt Mathison,
Blair Morley, Ryan Particka, BethAnne Pontius, Andrew Sanford, Sasha Savinov, Kim So, Kyle
Sweeney, and Amanda Thatcher.
PART V APPENDIXES
Amy Dulan put her analytical skills and nurturing personality to work as an ACT coach after
receiving a Psychology degree from Michigan State University in 1991. During forays into the
corporate world over the next several years, Amy continued to tutor part-time, eventually
helping to found Advantage Education® in 1997. Since then, Amy has worked with thousands
of high school students in both private and classroom settings, helping them to maximize their
ACT scores. Her sense of humor and down-to-earth style allow Amy to connect with her
students and make learning fun.
Note from the Authors
Based on student feedback over the past few years, we’ve made some improvements for this
edition of our book.
1. Expanded Explanations. We identified questions in the content area chapters that are
particularly ripe for “teachable moments.” In our individual tutoring sessions, we’ve found
that applying our strategies to specific questions is a great help to students. So, we’ve
added several longer, more detailed explanations. They are identified in the explanations
and are easy to spot because they are in a blue box.
2. “Amy Says/Steve Says” tips. We’ve each included our favorite strategy reminders. These
are the tips that we often hear ourselves repeating to our students.
3. Index of Question Types. We know that many students reach a point where they need to
practice specific question types rather than simply doing full practice sections. We’ve
included the Index (starting on page 815) so that it will be easy to find examples of each
type of question. Repetition can really help with nailing down methods of solving
whichever type of question you are mastering at the moment.
4. 100 Extra-Challenging Questions Section. We have included difficult questions from
each of the four multiple choice test sections: English, Mathematics, Reading, and Science.
The explanations are fairly detailed in order to help you understand the best way to
approach each of these challenging question.
PART I
Getting Started
CHAPTER 1
Understanding the ACT
ACT Format
Amy Says:
One important thing about scores is that you don’t have to be perfect to get a good score
on the ACT. The truth is that you can miss a fair number of questions and still get a score
that places you in the top 1% of all test-takers. In fact, this test is so hard and the time limit
is so unrealistic for most test-takers that you can get a score that is at the national average
(about a 21) even if you get almost half of the questions wrong.
ACT SCORES
Each of the multiple-choice sections of the ACT is called a Test (English Test, Mathematics
Test, Reading Test, and Science Test). Each test is given a score on a scale of 1 to 36. These
four “scale scores” are then averaged and rounded according to normal rounding rules to
yield a Composite Score. It is this Composite Score that is most often meant when someone
refers to your ACT score.
Your actual score report will also refer to detailed results for each test section. These are
based on your performance on a subset of the questions on each of these tests. These results
will help you to determine your readiness for college-level courses.
TESTING IRREGULARITIES
A “testing irregularity” is basically an accusation of cheating. You can avoid this situation by
following all instructions and only working on the section on which you are supposed to be
working. This includes marking the answer sheets. Don’t go back to a previous section or
forward to a later section, either in the test book or on the answer sheet. Do write in the test
booklet. We are aware of one student who could have saved himself the time, inconvenience,
and expense of a testing irregularity accusation if he had merely shown some work in his test
book. If you are accused of a testing irregularity, don’t panic. You have certain due process
rights. Discuss the matter with your parents and perhaps an attorney as soon as possible so
that you can react appropriately.
This test will help you to assess your strengths and weaknesses. Take the test under realistic
conditions (preferably early in the morning in a quiet location), and allow approximately 3.5
hours for the entire test. Each of the test sections should be taken in the time indicated at the
beginning of the sections, and in the order in which they appear. Fill in the bubbles on your
answer sheet once you have made your selections.
When you have finished the entire test, check your answers against the Answer Key. Follow
the directions on how to score your test, and calculate your score using the Scoring Guide
that appears on pages 65 through 67. Then, read the Answers and Explanations, paying close
attention to the explanations for the questions that you missed.
Your scores should indicate your performance on the individual test sections, as well as
your overall performance on the Diagnostic Test. Once you have identified your areas of
strength and weakness, you should review those particular chapters in the book.
ACT DIAGNOSTIC ASSESSMENT TEST
Answer Sheet
ENGLISH
MATHEMATICS
READING
SCIENCE
You may wish to remove these sample answer document pages to respond to the practice ACT
Writing Test.
ENGLISH TEST
45 Minutes – 75 Questions
DIRECTIONS: In the passages that follow, some words and phrases are underlined and
numbered. In the answer column, you will find alternatives for the words and phrases that
are underlined. Choose the alternative that you think is best and fill in the corresponding
bubble on your answer sheet. If you think that the original version is best, choose “NO
CHANGE,” which will always be either answer choice A or F. You will also find questions
about a particular section of the passage, or about the entire passage. These questions will
be identified by either an underlined portion or by a number in a box. Look for the answer
that clearly expresses the idea, is consistent with the style and tone of the passage, and
makes the correct use of standard written English. Read the passage through once before
answering the questions. For some questions, you should read beyond the indicated portion
before you answer.
PASSAGE I
Helen Keller’s Light in the Darkness
high fever robbed her of sight and hearing just before her second birthday that her
remarkable journey started. Although the exact cause of Helen’s fever was never
determined, modern doctors believe Helen suffered from meningitis. The illness plunged
Helen into a dark silence that most people cannot even imagine . The Kellers’
unable to understand anything that she experienced. Her resulting tantrums became more
violent as she continued to grow.
from being the State Insane Asylum, the Kellers contacted the Perkins Institute in
Enter Annie Sullivan, who truly became the “miracle worker” in Helen’s life.
be Helen’s salvation. In order to work her “miracle,” Annie needed to get Helen away from
her parents’ pampering. Annie permission to take Helen to live in a little house
on the opposite side of the Kellers’ garden. Initially, Helen continued to fight
but gradually the girl began to behave. Soon, Helen’s submission gave way to trust in
Annie. Helen began to comprehend that everything she touched had a name. Her constant
darkness was suddenly illuminated by this new-found understanding, and her hunger for
knowledge became .
For the remainder of her life, Annie Sullivan continued to feed Helen’s appetite for
learning, providing a constant light in Helen’s otherwise impenetrable darkness.
1. A. NO CHANGE
B. had began
C. begins
D. began
2. F. NO CHANGE
G. happy and healthy, learning to walk and talk
H. happy, and healthy, learning to walk, and talk,
J. happy, and healthy learning to walk, and talk
3. A. NO CHANGE
B. to think about
C. or really think about
D. DELETE the underlined portion.
4. Which of the following sentences, if added here, would best introduce the new subject
of Paragraph 2?
F. Helen didn’t obey her parents.
G. The next few years were frustrating for Helen and physically and emotionally
draining for her family.
H. Annie Sullivan came to teach Helen.
J. Helen loved plants and animals, and many different kinds could be found near her
home.
5. A. NO CHANGE
B. discover and feel new sensations
C. feel new sensations about making discoveries
D. make discoveries and sense new feelings
6. F. NO CHANGE
G. impaired daughter, Helen’s parents
H. impaired daughter Helens’ parents
J. impaired daughter Helen’s, parents
7. A. NO CHANGE
B. sent to
C. sent with
D. sent for
8. F. NO CHANGE
G. Primarily a blind school,
H. Just a school for the primarily blind,
J. For the blind, primarily, this school, along with
9. A. NO CHANGE
B. Helen, only with her self-discipline, would
C. Only by including self-discipline, would Helen
D. Only Helen, with self-discipline, would
10. F. NO CHANGE
G. One’s stubbornness was
H. Her stubbornness being
J. Helen’s stubbornness was
11. A. NO CHANGE
B. channeled it
C. channeled: it
D. channeled, it
12. F. NO CHANGE
G. had gave
H. was giving
J. gave
13. A. NO CHANGE
B. Annies’ efforts
C. Annies efforts
D. Annie’s efforts,
14. F. NO CHANGE
G. excited
H. insatiable
J. unfounded
15. Suppose the writer was asked to write a brief essay about Helen Keller’s professional
accomplishments. Would this essay successfully fulfill this goal?
A. Yes, because the essay focuses on the skill of Annie Sullivan in communicating
with Helen.
B. Yes, because the essay indicates that Helen eventually stopped having tantrums
and began learning from Annie Sullivan.
C. No, because this essay mostly addresses Annie Sullivan’s accomplishments
concerning Helen.
D. No, because Helen’s disabilities prevented her from having a successful career.
PASSAGE II
The following paragraphs may or may not be in the most logical order. You may be asked
questions about the logical order of the paragraphs, as well as where to place sentences
logically within any given paragraph.
[1]
Why do the holidays make you feel like a kid again? I’m not talking about the wide-eyed
wonder of seeing the tree at Rockefeller Center No, I
mean the tantrum-filled, “I want to do it all” attitude of a two-year-old. You begin the
season with enthusiasm. You begin thinking about the Christmas season soon after Labor
[2]
minute begin your holiday shopping early. In September, you buy the perfect
gift for Aunt Susie. You compliment yourself for thinking ahead. In October, you just
the right gift for Uncle John (who collects ghost figurines). holiday shopping
is going to be a snap!
[3]
Suddenly, it’s Thanksgiving. The holiday invitations begin to arrive. As you mark the
dates on the calendar, you vow that from those in the past. You
[4]
You calmly begin writing a list that includes names of family and
checkmarks next to those whose gifts you’ve purchased. What’s this? You’ve purchased only
two gifts for fifteen relatives and twelve friends? Suddenly, the holiday season a
nightmare. You begin making frantic phone calls to obtain wish lists, but to no avail.
[5]
Now it’s November, and the radio stations are playing Christmas carols. How silly—we
have six weeks until Christmas! There is still plenty of time to find gifts for everyone on
your shopping list.
[6]
You rush from store to store. Your eyes dart among the displays for the perfect gift.
Finally, you give up and purchase 25 generic gift certificates at a department store.
They are not the most inspired gifts, but you’re done shopping! You
begin baking cookies. Immediately, your son asks, “What did you
get Miss Jones?” You into tears, realizing you forgot not only his teacher but seven
other people who somehow didn’t make your list. Your son cautiously approaches and gives
you a gentle hug. You feel a glimmer of joy return. You decide to skip the cookies and get
some sleep. As you turn out the lights, you silently vow to start your shopping earlier next
year!
16. F. NO CHANGE
G. illuminated at the initial time.
H. illuminated for the first time.
J. firstly illuminated, initially.
17. A. NO CHANGE
B. enthusiastic
C. enthusiastically
D. enthusiasm in
18. F. NO CHANGE
G. being shopping for gifts.
H. is shopping for gifts.
J. for the shopping of gifts.
19. A. NO CHANGE
B. purchases, you
C. purchases you
D. purchases; you
20. F. NO CHANGE
G. found
H. will find
J. have found
21. A. NO CHANGE
B. This year, your
C. This year: your
D. This year you’re,
22. F. NO CHANGE
G. this Christmas will be different
H. the differences this Christmas would have
J. a different Christmas it would be
23. A. NO CHANGE
B. scheduled, overlapping set of events on the schedule,
C. few overlapping events,
D. few overlapping events scheduled to occur at the same time,
24. F. NO CHANGE
G. friends. Placing
H. friends; placing
J. friends, placing
25. A. NO CHANGE
B. has become
C. becoming
D. will become
26. Which of the following sentences offers the best introduction to Paragraph 6?
F. Deciding that you must come up with your own gift ideas, you head to the mall.
G. Christmas should not be stressful.
H. Malls have a diverse selection of stores within steps of each other.
J. Most stores offer gift options for last-minute shoppers.
27. A. NO CHANGE
B. trudging home, exhausted, to
C. exhausted trudge home to
D. trudge home, exhausted, to
28. F. NO CHANGE
G. erupt
H. burst
J. jump
29. What function does Paragraph 6 serve in relation to the rest of the essay?
A. It refers back to the opening sentences of the essay, suggesting that all adults act
like toddlers.
B. It indicates that the narrator will likely succeed in next year’s goal of completing
her holiday responsibilities early.
C. It summarizes the essay’s main point that Christmas is the most relaxed holiday of
the year.
D. It indicates that, despite the narrator’s feelings of being overwhelmed, she may
eventually be able to enjoy the holiday.
30. For the sake of unity and coherence of the essay, Paragraph 5 should be placed:
F. where it is now.
G. after Paragraph 1.
H. after Paragraph 2.
J. after Paragraph 3.
PASSAGE III
Have You No Shame?
Popular opinion teaches us that guilt is a wasted emotion. Ironically, this same
teaches us “No pain, no gain.” Although we recognize that physical fitness may involve
occasional discomfort, we are unwilling to accept that may as well. Despite
what we have learned about pain, studies show that if an exercise hurts, you’re probably
doing it wrong. Similarly, if a course of action (or inaction) causes pangs of guilt,
Nature provides our bodies with pain receptors to limit injury to
ourselves—if you place your hand on a hot stove, pain prompts you to remove your hand.
into your lane. Although you could safely allow the car to merge, you instead accelerate so
as not to delay your trip another second.
As you drive by, you
recognize your neighbor behind the wheel—the one who watched your dog during your
vacation. You feel an uncomfortable twinge of guilt, and you more
Discounting guilt is akin to turning off conscience. Imagine a society in which no one
Although you may joke that I’ve just described rush-hour traffic, in fact,
regret for his actions. So how did guilt get its bad reputation? First, we hate pain, and if we
can avoid it, we do. In the case of it is difficult to escape the negativity.
Therefore, we decide the guilt itself—not the action that prompted the wrong.
Second, guilt, if improperly can lead to devastation. Guilt should not be ignored,
but it should be examined (What caused me to feel guilty?), analyzed (How can I avoid that
mistake in the future?), and then released (I move on with new wisdom). Unfortunately,
some people spend so much time on the examination that they never move to the
analysis and release. They become crippled by the guilt. The purpose of guilt is not to cause
people to withdraw from society but to become better members of it.
31. Which choice would most precisely sharpen the focus of this paragraph, in keeping
with the way the writer develops the argument in the rest of the essay?
A. NO CHANGE
B. physicality
C. improvement
D. DELETE the underlined portion.
32. F. NO CHANGE
G. societal fitness
H. societal’s fitness
J. societies fitness
33. Which choice best supports the argument that guilt serves a purpose?
A. NO CHANGE
B. you should call a psychiatrist.
C. you should ignore it.
D. you should change your course of action.
34. F. NO CHANGE
G. stop us from causing unnecessary and grievous pain to other people.
H. limit emotional injury to others.
J. limit unnecessary and emotionally grievous injury to others.
35. A. NO CHANGE
B. trying to attempt a turn
C. trying to attempt to turn
D. attempting to turn
36. F. NO CHANGE
G. The faster you are traveling, the longer it will take you to stop.
H. Vehicles today can stop faster than in the past.
J. DELETE the underlined portion.
37. A. NO CHANGE
B. find yourself, driving,
C. find yourself driving
D. find, yourselves, driving
38. F. NO CHANGE
G. acts in
H. acts as if he is in
J. performs of and for
39. A. NO CHANGE
B. penalties of a legal nature, which may include fines and/or imprisonment.
C. fines, imprisonment, or other legal penalties.
D. penalties of a legal nature.
40. F. NO CHANGE
G. I, myself, just
H. by just having,
J. I have,
41. A. NO CHANGE
B. that he is criminally insane
C. that he is not of sound mind
D. DELETE the underlined portion.
42. F. NO CHANGE
G. guilt, so,
H. guilt, then,
J. guilt, thereby,
43. A. NO CHANGE
B. guilt, is
C. guilt: is
D. guilt. Is
44. F. NO CHANGE
G. managed, which
H. managed,
J. managed, it
45. A. NO CHANGE
B. like
C. on
D. in time
PASSAGE IV
A Picture of Health
embodied the tanned, athletic image other men sought. In reality, his ‘‘tan’’ was a symptom
of Addison’s disease.
played outside.
age thirteen, he developed colitis. By 1940, he had osteoporosis and compression fractures
in his lower back, and in 1944 he had his first back surgery. In 1947, Kennedy was officially
diagnosed with Addison’s disease, He underwent two more unsuccessful back surgeries
in 1954 and 1955 and took chronic pain medication from that point until his death in 1963.
By the time Kennedy became president, he was taking ten to twelve pills every day,
including anti-spasmodics, muscle relaxants, various steroids, pain medications, and
sleeping pills. In addition,
How did Kennedy hide such significant health problems from the American people
? His best alibi was his appearance: He looked healthy. His well-being
president.
By today’s standards, Kennedy had medical problems severe enough to qualify him for
federal disability or retirement. Nevertheless, he not only survived but
46. F. NO CHANGE
G. enviable health, tall
H. enviable health, but tall
J. enviable health tall
47. A. NO CHANGE
B. He had been bedridden for much of his life. He was genuinely athletic. He was
C. Although genuinely athletic, he had been bed-ridden for much of his childhood,
D. He was a childhood athlete bedridden
48. F. NO CHANGE
G. began by
H. began for
J. began with
49. The writer would like to add more detail to help the reader to understand the
symptoms of Addison’s disease. Assuming all are true, which of the following
completions of this sentence best achieves this effect?
A. an auto-immune disorder that has numerous symptoms.
B. which is rare.
C. a rare auto-immune disorder characterized by weight loss, muscle weakness,
fatigue, low blood pressure, and darkening of the skin.
D. which causes a variety of unpleasant symptoms and can result in death, often at a
very early age.
50. F. NO CHANGE
G. in his back he received anesthetic injections up to six times a day.
H. in his back, up to six times a day, he received anesthetic injections.
J. up to six times a day in his back, he received anesthetic injections.
51. A. NO CHANGE
B. without their knowledge or noticing it
C. without noticing them
D. DELETE the underlined portion.
52. F. NO CHANGE
G. which
H. that
J. whom
53. A. NO CHANGE
B. healthy, and he
C. healthy. As he
D. healthy; by showing he
54. F. NO CHANGE
G. crippling pain from his doctors, except
H. pain, which was crippling, from all except his doctors
J. doctors from his crippling pain
55. A. NO CHANGE
B. related questions about his health;
C. health-related questions about his well-being;
D. health-related questions;
56. F. NO CHANGE
G. attributed
H. is attributing
J. was attributed
57. Which of the choices provides the most effective introductory sentence for this
paragraph?
A. NO CHANGE
B. Perhaps a better question would be whether Kennedy played football.
C. Perhaps a better question would be whether such an ill man was competent to be
president.
D. Perhaps a better question would be why Kennedy had Addison’s disease.
58. F. NO CHANGE
G. and not the drugs
H. nor the drugs
J. and either the drugs
59. A. NO CHANGE
B. at the highest level, performed.
C. highly performed at his level.
D. achieved high performance above his expected level.
60. Suppose the writer had been assigned to write a brief essay about Addison’s disease
and treatment of the disease. Would this essay successfully fulfill the assignment?
F. Yes, because the essay describes the symptoms of Addison’s disease.
G. Yes, because the essay explains that Addison’s disease is treated with steroids.
H. No, because the essay focuses on President Kennedy’s health.
J. No, because the essay does not describe any symptoms of the disease.
PASSAGE V
Warmth in the Arctic
“We’re going where?” “To the gateway to the Arctic—the Land of the Midnight Sun!
forward to going home to Southern California, to lifeguard and use my spare time
to surf. Now my friend was proposing that we spend the summer 250 miles north of the
Arctic Circle. Was he nuts? As I look back, it was the best crazy decision I ever made.
Although the weather in Tromso wasn’t hot, it wasn’t particularly cold, either. I
occasionally needed a sweater, but seldom a coat. And, though I didn’t develop my usual
summer tan, the warmth of the people of Tromso more than made up for what the climate
(1) That summer, my days weren’t spent sitting in a lifeguard chair, a whistle
pleasantly surprised that it did not. (4) I know I slept less that summer than I ever have;
yet, I didn’t feel tired.
Discovering Diverse Content Through
Random Scribd Documents
ULTIMATE QUESTIONS
XV
THE CONSEQUENCES OF MONISM
An explanation of Nature on a single principle, or, in other words, Monism,
derives from human experience all the material which it requires for the
explanation of the world. In the same way, it looks for the springs of action
also within the world of observation, i.e., in that human part of Nature
which is accessible to our self-observation, and more particularly in the
moral imagination. Monism declines to seek outside that world the ultimate
grounds of the world which we perceive and think. For Monism, the unity
which reflective observation adds to the manifold multiplicity of percepts,
is identical with the unity which the human desire for knowledge demands,
and through which this desire seeks entrance into the physical and spiritual
realms. Whoever looks for another unity behind this one, only shows that he
fails to perceive the coincidence of the results of thinking with the demands
of the instinct for knowledge. A particular human individual is not
something cut off from the universe. He is a part of the universe, and his
connection with the cosmic whole is broken, not in reality, but only for our
perception. At first we apprehend the human part of the universe as a self-
existing thing, because we are unable to perceive the cords and ropes by
which the fundamental forces of the cosmos keep turning the wheel of our
life.
All who remain at this perceptual standpoint see the part of the whole as if
it were a truly independent, self-existing thing, a monad which gains all its
knowledge of the rest of the world in some mysterious manner from
without. But Monism has shown that we can believe in this independence
only so long as thought does not gather our percepts into the network of the
conceptual world. As soon as this happens, all partial existence in the
universe, all isolated being, reveals itself as a mere appearance due to
perception. Existence as a self-contained totality can be predicated only of
the universe as a whole. Thought destroys the appearances due to
perception and assigns to our individual existence a place in the life of the
cosmos. The unity of the conceptual world which contains all objective
percepts, has room also within itself for the content of our subjective
personality. Thought gives us the true structure of reality as a self-contained
unity, whereas the multiplicity of percepts is but an appearance conditioned
by our organisation (cp. pp. 178 ff.). The recognition of the true unity of
reality, as against the appearance of multiplicity, is at all times the goal of
human thought. Science strives to apprehend our apparently disconnected
percepts as a unity by tracing their inter-relations according to natural law.
But, owing to the prejudice that an inter-relation discovered by human
thought has only a subjective validity, thinkers have sought the true ground
of unity in some object transcending the world of our experience (God, will,
absolute spirit, etc.). Further, basing themselves on this prejudice, men have
tried to gain, in addition to their knowledge of inter-relations within
experience, a second kind of knowledge transcending experience, which
should reveal the connection between empirical inter-relations and those
realities which lie beyond the limits of experience (Metaphysics). The
reason why, by logical thinking, we understand the nexus of the world, was
thought to be that an original creator has built up the world according to
logical laws, and, similarly, the ground of our actions was thought to lie in
the will of this original being. It was overlooked that thinking embraces in
one grasp the subjective and the objective, and that it communicates to us
the whole of reality in the union which it effects between percept and
concept. Only so long as we contemplate the laws which pervade and
determine all percepts, in the abstract form of concepts, do we indeed deal
only with something purely subjective. But this subjectivity does not belong
to the content of the concept which, by means of thought, is added to the
percept. This content is taken, not from the subject, but from reality. It is
that part of reality which is inaccessible to perception. It is experience, but
not the kind of experience which comes from perception. Those who cannot
understand that the concept is something real, have in mind only the
abstract form, in which we fix and isolate the concept. But in this isolation,
the concept is as much dependent solely on our organisation as is the
percept. The tree which I perceive, taken in isolation by itself, has no
existence; it exists only as a member in the immense mechanism of Nature,
and is possible only in real connection with Nature. An abstract concept,
taken by itself, has as little reality as a percept taken by itself. The percept is
that part of reality which is given objectively, the concept that part which is
given subjectively (by intuition; cp. pp. 90 ff.). Our mental organisation
breaks up reality into these two factors. The one factor is apprehended by
perception, the other by intuition. Only the union of the two, which consists
of the percept fitted according to law into its place in the universe, is reality
in its full character. If we take mere percepts by themselves, we have no
reality but only a disconnected chaos. If we take the laws which determine
percepts by themselves, we have nothing but abstract concepts. Reality is
not to be found in the abstract concept. It is revealed to the contemplative
act of thought which regards neither the concept by itself nor the percept by
itself, but the union of both.
Even the most orthodox Idealist will not deny that we live in the real world
(that, as real beings, we are rooted in it); but he will deny that our
knowledge, by means of its ideas, is able to grasp reality as we live it. As
against this view, Monism shows that thought is neither subjective nor
objective, but a principle which holds together both these sides of reality.
The contemplative act of thought is a cognitive process which belongs itself
to the sequence of real events. By thought we overcome, within the limits of
experience itself, the one-sidedness of mere perception. We are not able by
means of abstract conceptual hypotheses (purely conceptual speculation) to
puzzle out the nature of the real, but in so far as we find for our percepts the
right concepts we live in the real. Monism does not seek to supplement
experience by something unknowable (transcending experience), but finds
reality in concept and percept. It does not manufacture a metaphysical
system out of pure concepts, because it looks upon concepts as only one
side of reality, viz., the side which remains hidden from perception, but is
meaningless except in union with percepts. But Monism gives man the
conviction that he lives in the world of reality, and has no need to seek
beyond the world for a higher reality. It refuses to look for Absolute Reality
anywhere but in experience, because it recognises reality in the very content
of experience. Monism is satisfied with this reality, because it knows that
our thought points to no other. What Dualism seeks beyond the world of
experience, that Monism finds in this world itself. Monism shows that our
knowledge grasps reality in its true nature, not in a purely subjective image.
It holds the conceptual content of the world to be identical for all human
individuals (cp. pp. 84 ff.). According to Monistic principles, every human
individual regards every other as akin to himself, because it is the same
world-content which expresses itself in all. In the single conceptual world
there are not as many concepts of “lion” as there are individuals who form
the thought of “lion,” but only one. And the concept which A adds to the
percept of “lion” is identical with B’s concept except so far as, in each case,
it is apprehended by a different perceiving subject (cp. p. 85). Thought
leads all perceiving subjects back to the ideal unity in all multiplicity, which
is common to them all. There is but one ideal world, but it realises itself in
human subjects as in a multiplicity of individuals. So long as man
apprehends himself merely by self-observation, he looks upon himself as
this particular being, but so soon as he becomes conscious of the ideal
world which shines forth within him, and which embraces all particulars
within itself, he perceives that the Absolute Reality lives within him.
Dualism fixes upon the Divine Being as that which permeates all men and
lives in them all. Monism finds this universal Divine Life in Reality itself.
The ideal content of another subject is also my content, and I regard it as a
different content only so long as I perceive, but no longer when I think.
Every man embraces in his thought only a part of the total world of ideas,
and so far, individuals are distinguished one from another also by the actual
contents of their thought. But all these contents belong to a self-contained
whole, which comprises within itself the thought-contents of all men.
Hence every man, in so far as he thinks, lays hold of the universal Reality
which pervades all men. To fill one’s life with such thought-content is to
live in Reality, and at the same time to live in God. The thought of a
Beyond owes its origin to the misconception of those who believe that this
world cannot have the ground of its existence in itself. They do not
understand that, by thinking, they discover just what they demand for the
explanation of the perceptual world. This is the reason why no speculation
has ever produced any content which has not been borrowed from reality as
it is given to us. A personal God is nothing but a human being transplanted
into the Beyond. Schopenhauer’s Will is the human will made absolute.
Hartmann’s Unconscious, made up of idea and will, is but a compound of
two abstractions drawn from experience. Exactly the same is true of all
other transcendent principles.
The truth is that the human mind never transcends the reality in which it
lives. Indeed, it has no need to transcend it, seeing that this world contains
everything that is required for its own explanation. If philosophers declare
themselves finally content when they have deduced the world from
principles which they borrow from experience and then transplant into an
hypothetical Beyond, the same satisfaction ought to be possible, if these
same principles are allowed to remain in this world to which they belong
anyhow. All attempts to transcend the world are purely illusory, and the
principles transplanted into the Beyond do not explain the world any better
than the principles which are immanent in it. When thought understands
itself, it does not demand any such transcendence at all, for there is no
thought-content which does not find within the world a perceptual content,
in union with which it can form a real object. The objects of imagination,
too, are contents which have no validity, until they have been transformed
into ideas that refer to a perceptual content. Through this perceptual content
they have their place in reality. A concept the content of which is supposed
to lie beyond the world which is given to us, is an abstraction to which no
reality corresponds. Thought can discover only the concepts of reality; in
order to find reality itself, we need also perception. An Absolute Being for
which we invent a content, is a hypothesis which no thought can entertain
that understands itself. Monism does not deny ideal factors; indeed, it
refuses to recognise as fully real a perceptual content which has no ideal
counterpart, but it finds nothing within the whole range of thought that is
not immanent within this world of ours. A science which restricts itself to a
description of percepts, without advancing to their ideal complements, is,
for Monism, but a fragment. But Monism regards as equally fragmentary all
abstract concepts which do not find their complement in percepts, and
which fit nowhere into the conceptual net that embraces the whole
perceptual world. Hence it knows no ideas referring to objects lying beyond
our experience and supposed to form the content of purely hypothetical
Metaphysics. Whatever mankind has produced in the way of such ideas
Monism regards as abstractions from experience, whose origin in
experience has been overlooked by their authors.
Just as little, according to Monistic principles, are the ends of our actions
capable of being derived from the Beyond. So far as we can think them,
they must have their origin in human intuition. Man does not adopt the
purposes of an objective (transcendent) being as his own individual
purposes, but he pursues the ends which his own moral imagination sets
before him. The idea which realises itself in an action is selected by the
agent from the single ideal world and made the basis of his will.
Consequently his action is not a realisation of commands which have been
thrust into this world from the Beyond, but of human intuitions which
belong to this world. For Monism there is no ruler of the world standing
outside of us and determining the aim and direction of our actions. There is
for man no transcendent ground of existence, the counsels of which he
might discover, in order thence to learn the ends to which he ought to direct
his action. Man must rest wholly upon himself. He must himself give a
content to his action. It is in vain that he seeks outside the world in which
he lives for motives of his will. If he is to go at all beyond the satisfaction
of the natural instincts for which Mother Nature has provided, he must look
for motives in his own moral imagination, unless he finds it more
convenient to let them be determined for him by the moral imagination of
others. In other words, he must either cease acting altogether, or else act
from motives which he selects for himself from the world of his ideas, or
which others select for him from that same world. If he develops at all
beyond a life absorbed in sensuous instincts and in the execution of the
commands of others, then there is nothing that can determine him except
himself. He has to act from a motive which he gives to himself and which
nothing else can determine for him except himself. It is true that this motive
is ideally determined in the single world of ideas; but in actual fact it must
be selected by the agent from that world and translated into reality. Monism
can find the ground for the actual realisation of an idea through human
action only in the human being himself. That an idea should pass into action
must be willed by man before it can happen. Such a will consequently has
its ground only in man himself. Man, on this view, is the ultimate
determinant of his action. He is free.
1. Addition to the Revised Edition (1918).
In the second part of this book the attempt has been made to justify the
conviction that freedom is to be found in human conduct as it really is. For
this purpose it was necessary to sort out, from the whole sphere of human
conduct, those actions with respect to which unprejudiced self-observation
may appropriately speak of freedom. These are the actions which appear as
realisations of ideal intuitions. No other actions will be called free by an
unprejudiced observer. However, open-minded self-observation compels
man to regard himself as endowed with the capacity for progress on the
road towards ethical intuitions and their realisation. Yet this open-minded
observation of the ethical nature of man is, by itself, insufficient to
constitute the final court of appeal for the question of freedom. For, suppose
intuitive thinking had itself sprung from some other essence; suppose its
essence were not grounded in itself, then the consciousness of freedom,
which issues from moral conduct, would prove to be a mere illusion. But
the second part of this book finds its natural support in the first part, which
presents intuitive thinking as an inward spiritual activity which man
experiences as such. To appreciate through experience this essence of
thinking is equivalent to recognising the freedom of intuitive thinking. And
once we know that this thinking is free, we know also the sphere within
which will may be called free. We shall regard man as a free agent, if on the
basis of inner experience we may attribute to the life of intuitive thinking a
self-sustaining essence. Whoever cannot do this will be unable to discover
any wholly unassailable road to the belief in freedom. The experience to
which we here refer reveals in consciousness intuitive thinking, the reality
of which does not depend merely on our being conscious of it. Freedom,
too, is thereby revealed as the characteristic of all actions which issue from
the intuitions of consciousness.
1 The Preface and Introduction to the original edition of “Truth and Science” are printed
as Appendix III and Appendix IV at the end of this volume. ↑
I
PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS
Theory of Knowledge aims at being a scientific investigation of the very
fact which all other sciences take for granted without examination, viz.,
knowing or knowledge-getting itself. To say this is to attribute to it, from
the very start, the character of being the fundamental philosophical
discipline. For, it is only this discipline which can tell us what value and
significance belong to the insight gained by the other sciences. In this
respect it is the foundation for all scientific endeavour. But, it is clear that
the Theory of Knowledge can fulfil its task only if it works without any
presuppositions of its own, so far as that is possible in view of the nature of
human knowledge. This is probably conceded on all sides. And yet, a more
detailed examination of the better-known epistemological systems reveals
that, at the very starting-point of the inquiry, there is made a whole series of
assumptions which detract considerably from the plausibility of the rest of
the argument. In particular, it is noticeable how frequently certain hidden
assumptions are made in the very formulation of the fundamental problems
of epistemology. But, if a science begins by misstating its problems, we
must despair from the start of finding the right solution. The history of the
sciences teaches us that countless errors, from which whole epochs have
suffered, are to be traced wholly and solely to the fact that certain problems
were wrongly formulated. For illustrations there is no need to go back to
Aristotle or to the Ars Magna Lulliana. There are plenty of examples in
more recent times. The numerous questions concerning the purposes of the
rudimentary organs of certain organisms could be correctly formulated only
after the discovery of the fundamental law of biogenesis had created the
necessary conditions. As long as Biology was under the influence of
teleological concepts, it was impossible to put these problems in a form
permitting a satisfactory answer. What fantastic ideas, for example, were
current concerning the purpose of the so-called pineal gland, so long as it
was fashionable to frame biological questions in terms of “purpose.” An
answer was not achieved until the solution of the problem was sought by
the method of Comparative Anatomy, and scientists asked whether this
organ might not be merely a residual survival in man from a lower
evolutionary level. Or, to mention yet another example, consider the
modifications in certain physical problems after the discovery of the laws of
the mechanical equivalents of heat and of the conservation of energy! In
short, the success of scientific investigations depends essentially upon the
investigator’s ability to formulate his problems correctly. Even though the
Theory of Knowledge, as the presupposition of all other sciences, occupies
a position very different from theirs, we may yet expect that for it, too,
successful progress in its investigations will become possible only when the
fundamental questions have been put in the correct form.
The other objection lies in this, that we have no right, at the outset of our
epistemological investigations, to affirm that no absolutely certain
knowledge can have its source in experience. Without doubt, it is easily
conceivable that experience itself might contain a criterion guaranteeing the
certainty of all knowledge which has an empirical source.
1 l.c., p. 20. ↑
2 cf. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, Intr. to 2nd edit., Section vi. ↑
3 Prolegomena, Section v. ↑
4 Critique of Pure Reason, Intr., Section iv. ↑
5 cf. his Analyse der Wirklichkeit, Gedanken und Tatsachen. ↑
6 “Possible” here means merely conceivable. ↑
7 cf. Die Welt als Wahrnehmung und Begriff, pp. 161 ff. ↑
8 This attempt, by the way, is one which the objections of Robert Zimmermann (Über
Kant’s mathematisches Vorurteil und dessen Folgen) show to be, if not wholly mistaken, at
least highly questionable. ↑
9 Critique of Pure Reason, Intr. to 2nd edit., Section ii. ↑
10 cf. Kant’s Theorie der Erfahrung, pp. 90 ff. ↑
11 l.c., Section v. ↑
12 cf. Kant’s Theorie der Erfahrung, pp. 90 ff. ↑
13 cf. Die Grundsätze der reinen Erkenntnistheorie in der Kantischen Philosophie, p.
76. ↑
14 l.c., p. 21. ↑
15 Zur Analyse der Wirklichkeit, pp. 211 ff. ↑
16 Darstellung der Kantischen Erkenntnistheorie, p. 14. ↑
17 Vierteljahrsschrift für Wissenschaftliche Philosophie, 1877, p. 239. ↑
18 System der Logik, 3rd edit., pp. 380 ff. ↑
19 Kritische Grundlagen des Transcendentalen Realismus, pp. 142–172. ↑
20 Geschichte der Neueren Philosophie, Vol. v., p. 60. Volkelt is mistaken about Fischer
when he says (Kant’s Erkenntnistheorie, p. 198, n.) that “it is not clear from Fischer’s
account whether, in his opinion, Kant takes for granted only the psychological fact of the
occurrence of universal and necessary judgments, but also their objective validity and
truth.” For, in the passage referred to above, Fischer says that the chief difficulty of the
Critique of Pure Reason is to be found in the fact that “its fundamental positions rest on
certain presuppositions” which “have to be granted if the rest is to be valid.” These
presuppositions consist for Fischer, too, in this, that “first the fact of knowledge is
affirmed,” and then analysis reveals the cognitive faculties “by means of which that fact
itself is explained.” ↑
21 How far our own epistemological discussions conform to this method, will be shown
in Section iv, “The Starting-points of the Theory of Knowledge.” ↑
III
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE SINCE KANT
Kant’s mistaken formulation of the problem has had a greater or lesser
influence on all subsequent students of the Theory of Knowledge. For Kant,
the view that all objects which are given to us in experience are ideas in our
minds is a consequence of his theory of the a priori. For nearly all his
successors, it has become the first principle and starting-point of their
epistemological systems. It is said that the first and most immediate truth is,
simply and solely, the proposition that we know our own ideas. This has
come to be a well-nigh universal conviction among philosophers. G. E.
Schulze maintains in his Ænesidemus, as early as 1792, that all our
cognitions are mere ideas and that we can never transcend our ideas.
Schopenhauer puts forward, with all the philosophical pathos which
distinguishes him, the view that the permanent achievement of Kant’s
philosophy is the thesis that “the world is my idea.” To Eduard von
Hartmann this thesis is so incontestable, that he addresses his treatise,
Kritische Grundlegung des Transcendentalen Realismus, exclusively to
readers who have achieved critical emancipation from the naïve
identification of the world of perception with the thing-in-itself. He
demands of them that they shall have made clear to themselves the absolute
heterogeneity of the object of perception which through the act of
representation has been given as a subjective and ideal content of
consciousness, and of the thing-in-itself which is independent of the act of
representation and of the form of consciousness and which exists in its own
right. His readers are required to be thoroughly convinced that the whole of
what is immediately given to us consists of ideas.1 In his latest work on
Theory of Knowledge, Hartmann does, indeed, attempt to give reasons for
this view. What value should be attached to these reasons by an
unprejudiced Theory of Knowledge will appear in the further course of our
discussions. Otto Liebmann posits as the sacrosanct first principle of the
Theory of Knowledge the proposition, “Consciousness cannot transcend
itself.”2 Volkelt has called the proposition that the first and most immediate
truth is the limitation of all our knowledge, in the first instance, to our own
ideas exclusively, the positivistic principle of knowledge. He regards only
those theories of knowledge as “in the fullest sense critical” which “place
this principle, as the only fixed starting-point of philosophy, at the head of
their discussions and then consistently think out its consequences.”3 Other
philosophers place other propositions at the head of the Theory of
Knowledge, e.g., the proposition that its real problem concerns the relation
between Thought and Being, and the possibility of a mediation between
them;4 or that it concerns the way in which Being becomes an object of
Consciousness;5 and many others. Kirchmann starts from two
epistemological axioms, “Whatever is perceived is,” and, “Whatever is self-
contradictory, is not.”6 According to E. L. Fischer, knowledge is the science
of something actual, something real,7 and he criticises this dogma as little
as does Goering who asserts similarly, “To know means always to know
something which is. This is a fact which cannot be denied either by
scepticism or by Kant’s critical philosophy.”8 These two latter thinkers
simply lay down the law: This is what knowledge is. They do not trouble to
ask themselves with what right they do it.
The best way to convince ourselves of the truth of the assertion that this
proposition has no right to be put at the head of the Theory of Knowledge,
is to retrace the way which the human mind must follow in order to reach
this proposition, which has become almost an integral part of the whole
modern scientific consciousness. The considerations which have led to it
are systematically summarised, with approximate exhaustiveness, in Part I
of Eduard von Hartmann’s treatise, Das Grundproblem der
Erkenntnistheorie. His statement, there, may serve as a sort of guiding-
thread for us in our task of reviewing the reasons which may lead to the
acceptance of this proposition.
Physiology adds its quota to the physical arguments. Physics deals with the
phenomena which occur outside our organisms and which correspond to our
percepts. Physiology seeks to investigate the processes which go on in
man’s own body when a certain sensation is evoked in him. It teaches us
that the epidermis is wholly insensitive to the stimuli in the external world.
Thus, e.g., if external stimuli are to affect the end-organs of our touch-
nerves on the surface of our bodies, the oscillations which occur outside our
bodies have to be transmitted through the epidermis. In the case of the
senses of hearing and of sight, the external motions have, in addition, to be
modified by a number of structures in the sense-organs, before they reach
the nerves. The nerves have to conduct the effects produced in the end-
organs up to the central organ, and only then can take place the process by
means of which purely mechanical changes in the brain produce sensations.
It is clear that the stimulus which acts upon the sense-organs is so
completely changed by the transformations which it undergoes, that every
trace of resemblance between the initial impression on the sense-organs and
the final sensation in consciousness must be obliterated. Hartmann sums up
the outcome of these considerations in these words: “This content of
consciousness consists, originally, of sensations which are the reflex
responses of the soul to the molecular motions in the highest cortical
centres, but which have not the faintest resemblance to the molecular
motions by which they are elicited.”
If we think this line of argument through to the end, we must agree that,
assuming it to be correct, there survives in the content of our consciousness
not the least element of what may be called “external existence.”
Now let us ask ourselves, How do we come by such a view? The bare
skeleton of the line of thought which leads to it is as follows. Supposing an
external world exists, we do not perceive it as such but transform it through
our organisation into a world of ideas. This is a supposition which, when
consistently thought out, destroys itself. But is this reflection capable of
supporting any positive alternative? Are we justified in regarding the world,
which is given to us, as the subjective content of ideas because the
assumptions of the naïve consciousness, logically followed out, lead to this
conclusion? Our purpose is, rather, to exhibit these assumptions themselves
as untenable. Yet, so far we should have found only that it is possible for a
premise to be false and yet for the conclusion drawn from it to be true.
Granted that this may happen, yet we can never regard the conclusion as
proved by means of that premise.
It is usual to apply the title of “Naïve Realism” to the theory which accepts
as self-evident and indubitable the reality of the world-picture which is
immediately given to us. The opposite theory, which regards this world as
merely the content of our consciousness, is called “Transcendental
Idealism.” Hence, we may sum up the outcome of the above discussion by
saying, “Transcendental Idealism demonstrates its own truth, by employing
the premises of the Naïve Realism which it seeks to refute.” Transcendental
Idealism is true, if Naïve Realism is false. But the falsity of the latter is
shown only by assuming it to be true. Once we clearly realise this situation,
we have no choice but to abandon this line of argument and to try another.
But are we to trust to good luck, and experiment about until we hit by
accident upon the right line? This is Eduard von Hartmann’s view when he
believes himself to have shown the validity of his own epistemological
standpoint, on the ground that his theory explains the phenomena whereas
its rivals do not. According to his view, the several philosophical systems
are engaged in a sort of struggle for existence in which the fittest is
ultimately accepted as victor. But this method appears to us to be
unsuitable, if only for the reason that there may well be several hypotheses
which explain the phenomena equally satisfactorily. Hence, we had better
keep to the above line of thought for the refutation of Naïve Realism, and
see where precisely its deficiency lies. For, after all, Naïve Realism is the
view from which we all start out. For this reason alone it is advisable to
begin by setting it right. When we have once understood why it must be
defective, we shall be led upon the right path with far greater certainty than
if we proceed simply at haphazard.