Ecocide Environmental Harm and Framework Integration at The International Criminal Court
Ecocide Environmental Harm and Framework Integration at The International Criminal Court
Matthew Gillett
To cite this article: Matthew Gillett (26 Dec 2024): Ecocide, environmental harm and
framework integration at the International Criminal Court, The International Journal of Human
Rights, DOI: 10.1080/13642987.2024.2433660
Both international environmental law and international criminal law are booming
disciplines in their own right, but their interaction remains, apart from a few exceptions,
curiously under-explored. Mégret (2011, 201)
Introduction
Ecological destruction afflicts all areas of world (Robinson, 2022), from the Amazon1 to
Ukraine.2 Criminal accountability for the worst acts against the environment provide one
means to heighten its protection.3 The World’s first permanent International Criminal
Court (‘ICC’), which is designed as a last resort institution when domestic authorities
are unable or unwilling to act,4 is showing concerted interest in addressing environ
mental harm.5 In late 2024, the crime of Ecocide was proposed for inclusion in the
Rome Statute.6 A few months earlier, the ICC Office of the Prosecutor (‘OTP’)
announced its launch of ‘a comprehensive policy paper on Environmental Crimes’,
which has since been disseminated for public consultation.7 That builds on the OTP’s
2013 and 2016 policy papers.8 These efforts respond to calls for ecocentric regulatory
reform,9 particularly in relation to ecocide.10 Against this backdrop, it is critical to
examine the ICC’s normative framework applicable to environmental harm.
At present the ICC’s framework is overwhelmingly anthropocentric in nature (Gillett
2022a, 6). Consequently, the shift to encompass ecocentric interests creates normative chal
lenges. Adjudicating environmental crimes will require the Court to apply rules and prin
ciples extrinsic11 to the Rome Statute, including from international environmental law
(‘IEL’),12 international humanitarian law (‘IHL’) (when the charges are linked to armed
conflict), and international human rights law (‘IHRL’).13 This is particularly applicable
for the proposed crime of ecocide (Falk, 1973), which lies at the intersection of these
branches of international law.14 Consequently, examining how to emmesh these disparate
strands of international law is essential. Yet the mechanics of incorporating external
sources of law under the ICC’s normative framework remain opaque and undeveloped.
A leading doctrine for reconciling various strands of international law is that of ‘sys
temic integration’ espoused by international law scholar Martii Koskenniemi.15 Although
it is technically formulated as a method of interpretation, systemic integration has been
hailed as a means to integrate parties’ international obligations under extrinsic instru
ments.16 In relation to the ICC, Campbell McLachlan argues that, as an international tri
bunal, it must engage in systemic integration (McLachlan, 2024, p. 320). Yet there are
fundamental incongruities between systemic integration, proposed by Koskenniemi
under Article 31(3) of the VCLT, as compared to the terms of the pivotal ICC provision –
Article 21 of the Rome Statute, in both form and function. Overlooking those differences
may lead to misplaced reliance on systemic integration and undervalue the far broader
integrative potential of Article 21. The present article seeks to remedy that gap.
The study shows that more than mere interpretation is required by the ICC’s uniquely
formulated ‘sources of law’ provision. As the fulcrum provision, Article 21 requires the
Court to apply not only the Rome Statute instruments but also ‘where appropriate, appli
cable treaties and the principles and rules of international law’.17 This green light for the
application of extrinsic legal sources is consequential. It provides the normative potential
for a harmonious incorporative approach to international law.18
Despite this potential, Article 21 does not explain how extrinsic sources are to be
incorporated. Moreover, ICC jurisprudence has done little to clarify this issue.19 With
the OTP policy on environmental harm and the proposed crime of ecocide highlighting
the relevance of a range of sub-branches of international law, increasingly pressing ques
tions arise concerning how to identify the relevant external principles, assess their
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 3
‘relative normativity’,20 prioritise them, and potentially de-conflict those extrinsic legal
rules. Smooth integration is necessary to avoid exacerbating the fragmented current
state of international law,21 which is particularly evident in relation to environmental
protection.22
In keeping with the scholarly mission to develop and synthesise normative systems
(Peters, 2013), this article proposes an innovative theoretical approach for the coherent
incorporation of IEL and other sub-branches of international law before the ICC, called
‘framework integration’. Framework integration reconceptualizes systemic integration
for the purpose of ICC proceedings.23 Importantly, the analysis articulates four criteria
to facilitate framework integration, namely: adjudicative coherence, the principle of effec
tiveness (effet utile), substantive proximity, and de-fragmentation. It highlights the specific
benefits and challenges that will arise from using framework integration for environmental
harm.
Examining how to incorporate extrinsic law in environmental cases before the ICC is a
novel line of inquiry,24 which has not been analysed in detail.25 Previous works have
highlighted the relevance of IEL principles under the Rome Statute,26 and the links
between IHRL, IHL and ICL, but have not looked at how to harmoniously integrate
these sources under Article 21 of the Rome Statute.27 Separately, there has been a ‘pro
liferating critical scholarship on ecocide’ (Minkova, 2024), attacking IEL and ICL at the
broad conceptual level.28 However, some of these works omit any viable means of disen
tangling normative tensions under the current system of international criminal law
(e.g. Cusato & Jones, 2023). Typical of this approach is to advocate for a radical re-think
ing of the entire international criminal law initiative. There are even assertions that the
‘emphasis on accountability’ for Rome Statute crimes is borne of a ‘primitive urge’ to
punish (Cusato & Jones, 2023, p. 61). While these generalised debates lie outside the
purview of the present article, it must be stressed that individual criminal accountability
is justified for war crimes, crimes against humanity, genocide, and aggression, whether or
not the underlying sentiment is labelled as ‘primitive’,29 and a similar form of account
ability for ecocide should not be dismissed on this basis.
With ecocide and environmental harm prosecutions on the horizon, it is imperative to
examine the legal bases on which they can proceed at the ICC,30 The endeavour can yield
important insights for other institutions, such as Colombia’s Special Jurisdiction for
Peace, which draws on ICL, IHL, IHRL and domestic criminal law, and is actively pro
secuting environmental harm.31 More fundamentally, the approach of framework inte
gration proposed in this article provides a potent means to defragment international
law and thereby enhance its stability.32 Given the legitimacy crisis of international law
and the growing questions of identifying applicable law among multiple branches,33
the article seeks to contribute to the normative coherence and effectiveness of the inter
national legal system as a whole.34
discipline following the end of the Cold War,35 its conceptual basis was laid several cen
turies earlier. Taking notions of Statehood developed by Vitoria and others and centred
on the principle of pacta sunt servanda, Grotius articulated a ‘common law among
nations’ that was both independent of the ecclesiastical ties of those former thinkers
(so much so that his seminal work De Jure Belli ac Pacis was banned by the Catholic
Church for 275 years) (Vreeland, 1917), and a rebuke to the Machiavellianism which
had been the predominant approach to inter-State relations during the preceding
century (Scharf, 2022). Building on Grotius’s recognition of the right to punish acts
beyond their borders if they ‘enormously violate the laws of nature and nations’
(Grotius, 1925), Henri Donnedieu de Vabres advocated for a ‘system of universal juris
diction’ based on the ‘universality of the right to punish’ (Donnedieu de Vabres, 1922–
1923). Core principles laid down by these thinkers, such as aut dedere dut judicare,36
were early signs of potential systematicity.
That first phase of conceptual development precipitated a second wave of progress
ive codification of rules of IHL which predicate international criminal law, including
the 1863 Lieber code, the Hague Convention of 1899, and the Geneva Conventions
of 1949.37 However, the codification process was punctuated and irregular, with core
tenets emerging in a decentralised way, often in reaction to specific atrocities or
wars. Crimes against humanity were first mentioned as such in relation to the 1915
extirpation of the Armenians in Turkey; war crimes developed on the basis of IHL
created following Henry Dunant’s witnessing of the battlefield suffering at Solferino;
and genocide as a reaction to the Holocaust.38 Although the Nuremberg and Tokyo tri
bunals did not address genocide as such, they constituted the first major application of
the other offences now seen as constituting international criminal law. They also saw
the conceptual basis for distinguishing international from domestic crimes, with the
International Military Tribunal defining an international crime in the Hostages case
as ’an act universally recognized as criminal, which is considered a grave matter of
international concern and for some valid reason cannot be left within the exclusive jur
isdiction of the State that would have control over it under ordinary circumstances’.
Yet, the situationally-bound nature of the Nuremberg and Tokyo trials means they
cannot be equated with the full establishment of an independent domain of inter
national criminal law per se.
After the developmental hiatus during the Cold War, international criminal law truly
crystallised as a definitive branch of international law in the 1990s. The creation of the
Yugoslav, Rwandan, Sierra Leonean and other ad hoc tribunals saw international
judges produce a wealth of jurisprudence fleshing out the key concepts and
contours of international criminal law. In parallel, States successfully negotiated the
enshrinement of the core international crimes in a systemic manner in the Rome
Statute of the ICC.39 This phase cemented international criminal law’s existence as an
autonomous normative framework, and saw it infused with independent positions on
issues such as the ‘overall control’ test for State responsibility and head of State immunity
for atrocity crimes, which diverged from those of the ICJ.40 International criminal justice
also stood distinct from, though related to, domestic frameworks. Through these connec
tions at various levels, international criminal justice can be seen as a developed system of
‘multi-level jurisdiction that is organized along with principles of subsidiarity and defer
ence’ (Stahn, 2019, p. 20).
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 5
However, dissents regarding the conceptual basis for international criminal law have
persisted. These have often replicated Judge Pal’s attack on the organisational basis for
international criminal law, as set forth in his dissent in the Tokyo trial, that.
[N]o particular group of nations can claim to be the custodian of the ‘common good’. Inter
national life is not yet organized into a community under the rule of law. A community life
has not even been agreed upon yet. Such an agreement is essential before the so-called
natural law may be allowed to function in the manner suggested.41
Whereas critiques in the 1990s were narrowly and legalistically framed, such as Slobodan
Milošević’s challenge to the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia
on the basis that the UN Security Council lacked the power to establish a criminal tribu
nal (Abtahi & Dawson, 2016), recent years have seen a resurgence of questions regarding
the legitimacy and cohesiveness of the system of international criminal law as a whole,
with a focus on its ‘democratic deficit’, fragmentation, and a perceived anti-African
bias or selectivity against the global South.42 These important critiques highlight the
need to ensure that international criminal law rests on theoretically sound underpinnings
and functions as a part of the broader system of international law, in line with its foun
dational principles and secondary rules.
To this end, in recent years efforts have been made to reconcile the rules of international
criminal law back into the broader corpus of international law.43 With cross-cutting issues
arising before multiple international institutions, from the UN Security Council, to the ICJ,
to the ICC,44 and with secondary principles of international law such as the role of peremp
tory norms increasingly being raised before these bodies, there is a growing appreciation of
the risks of fragmented sub-branches of international law. Inconsistent approaches, and
potentially outcomes, for the same allegations depending on the international forum
chosen contravenes the predictability and legitimacy of international law and provides
potent fodder for those seeking its downfall (Perez-Leon-Acevedo, 2024, p. 400; Webb,
2013, p. 5; Cryer, 2009, p. 395). Ecocide epitomises this risk of divergence, as it inherently
implicates the criminal and environmental branches of international law and will typically
have ramifications for human rights and humanitarian law. Predictability is particularly
important in the environmental context, so that people seeking to engage in necessary
activities such as buildings hospitals, schools and infrastructure, can plan their behaviour
accordingly.45
However, approaches to the incorporation of external international law branches
into the applicable framework of international criminal law have varied both theoreti
cally and in practice. At the ad hoc tribunals for the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda,
IHL was a core contributory stream for the doctrinal developments (even if those devel
opments sometimes formed schisms with established interpretations of IHL).46 Yet,
beyond IHL, those tribunals did not delve into other sub-branches of international
law with any regularity. Similarly, ICC jurisprudence has heavily relied on IHL,
along with IHRL. Though it has addressed the inter-relationship with the United
Nations Charter,47 it has avoided deep engagement with the conceptual basis for
those inter-connections.
On the specific connections with extrinsic legal sources, ICC jurisprudence lacks con
sistency and coherence.48 Some chambers have shown concerted resistance to extrinsi
cally based practices,49 while others have embraced procedures with no basis in the
6 M. GILLETT
Statute.50 This jurisprudential confusion exacerbates the lack of scholarly attention paid
to the integration of the Rome Statute’s terms with broader international law.
To give an example, the Independent Expert Panel’s definition of ecocide refers to ‘damage
to the environment’ without defining what this means.57 In relation to animals, that gap
could be filled by using the Convention on International Trade in Endangered Species of
Wild Fauna and Flora (CITES) treaty to determine which acts against animals and plants
qualify as relevant forms of damage to the environment.
In this light, there is a disconnect between systemic integration’s ambitious purpose of
incorporating rules into a coherent system of international law, and its narrow framing
for interpretive purposes. More than just interpretation of the Rome Statute’s terms is
required to redress environmental harm. Instead, substantive content will need to be
integrated into the Court’s legal sources, consistently with Article 21. To do so in a coher
ent and principled way, the following section examines how systemic integration can be
reconceptualised under the Rome Statute’s normative framework.
Elements of Crimes shall assist the Court’s interpretation and application of Articles 6–
8bis. Given that the Rome Statute contains several interpretive bulwarks, it may be asked
whether there is any space for external legal sources to be applied under Article 21, par
ticularly in relation to substantive crimes.
However, when examined in detail, significant gaps in the ICC’s coverage appear, par
ticularly in relation to environmental harm. For example, to address environmental
harm the Court would typically need to determine whether acts that result in environ
mental harm were legal or illegal in nature. This may be informed, for example, by
looking at the CITES on animal trading, as set out above, or looking at the World Heri
tage Convention to determine whether a natural site had outstanding universal value to
qualify for special legal protection. External instruments may similarly be required to
discern whether any other grounds for excluding criminal responsibility could be
raised under Article 31(3) of the Rome Statute or mistake of law under Article 32 (Robin
son, 2022, pp. 342–343). These could include exceptions, such as those set out under the
Convention on the Prevention of Marine Pollution by Dumping of Wastes and Other
Matter (1972) and its 1996 Protocol and the Convention on Prevention of Pollution
from Ships (1973). Additionally, IEL principles such as the precautionary principle
could potentially impact the mens rea element, as discussed below, and external
sources such as the Convention on Environmental Modification (ENMOD) and IHL
instruments are likely to be either applied or used as aides to flesh out and interpret
the elements of widespread, long-term and severe, which are contained in the war
crime under Article 8(2)(b)(iv) as well as in leading formulations of ecocide such as
that proposed by the Independent Expert Panel (Gillett 2022, pp. 99–104).
Already, the Court’s practice has seen several procedural questions require resort to
external legal sources.68 IHL and IHRL have been drawn into the Court’s jurisprudence,
including in the context of Article 8 war crimes,69 in analyses of persecution as a crime
against humanity under Article 7, and in fair trial assessments.70 The VCLT itself has
been relied on several times, even though it is technically an extrinsic treaty of inter
national law, only applicable under Article 21(1)(b) because the Rome Statute (and
other primary instruments) do not contain a complete internal interpretive guide.71
Having examined the structure of Article 21 and its hierarchy of sources, the specific
terms of Article 21(1)(b) itself must be taken into account to assess its application to
extrinsic legal instruments. At the outset, it must be noted that the meaning of the
pivotal phrase ‘where appropriate’, regarding the circumstances in which external
materials may be applied, remains unclear (Hochmayr, 2014, pp. 664–666). This
phrase appears to be situational in nature, referring to circumstances in which there is
a gap in the primary legal sources on a germane issue. However, it could also have a
second filtering nature, controlling the types of external materials which may be relied
on under Article 21(1)(b). In this respect, claims have been made in leading texts that
Article 21(1)(b) is a narrow provision only referring only to ‘those treaties of general
application that form the basis for the definitions of crimes over which the Court has jur
isdiction, such as the Geneva Conventions, the Genocide Convention, and the Conven
tion on the Rights of the Child.’72 However, that assumption is questionable, as Article 21
includes no such explicit limitation to sources of law concerning substantive crimes.73 In
fact, its wording refers to the Court’s Rules of Procedure and Evidence, which address
matters going well beyond substantive crimes.74 Given that Article 21(1)(b) also
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 9
already includes a subordinating phrase (‘in the second place’) it would be duplicative to
also interpret ‘appropriate’ as only referring to where gaps are left by Article 21(1)(a) and
it is instead open to read ‘appropriate’ to also have a filtering character. In this way,
Article 21(1)(b) would be given a construction whereby resort should only be made to
external sources when the primary sources under Article 21(1)(a) are insufficient to
meet an aim of the Statute, and where the external sources being used are relevant to
resolving the gap in the internal regulatory framework.75
Looking to its other operational terms, Article 21 requires that the extrinsic legal
source is ‘applicable’. For treaties, this would imply that the instrument is applicable
within the relevant context (typically the territorial jurisdiction where the crimes
occurred).76 A narrower reading of Article 21 requiring parallel acceptance by States is
proposed by Pellet, whereby external treaties could only be applied where ‘two or
more States agreed to accord it some specific jurisdiction or to require the application
of particular principles’ (Pellet, 2002, pp. 1069–1070). Nonetheless, the more flexible
reading of ‘applicable’ above aligns with the broad wording of Article 21, which differs
from the more constrictive terms of Article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna Convention (referring
to extrinsic sources ‘applicable in the relations between the parties’ and thereby implying
a parallelism requirement).77
Under Article 21(1)(b)’s terms, principles of customary international law would also
be presumptively applicable.78 Such principles have been utilised for example in the
Jordan litigation surrounding its failure to arrest Al-Bashir.79 However, the rigour of
the Court’s identification of applicable customary international law has been questioned
(Schabas, 2016, p. 522). Whatever the merits of those criticisms, it is clear that there is an
absence of structured guidance as to how extrinsic materials should be identified and
applied under Article 21, which has no doubt contributed to the Court’s mixed
approaches to using customary international law. Beyond treaty and customary law,
there are so-called ‘soft law’ materials, such as declarations and UN General Assembly
Resolutions. These may be used as indicia of the principles of international law, but
could not be directly applied in a binding sense per se.
Whereas Article 21’s structure is relatively clear, it does not comprehensively specify
how to apply its terms to integrate international law. The Rules of Procedure and Evidence
note the relevance of Article 21 to national laws (Rule 63(5)) and human rights law on the
admissibility of evidence (Rule 72(2)), as well as aggravating circumstances (Rule 145) and
offences against the administration of justice (Rule 163), but provide no overarching gui
dance concerning other branches of international law. To remedy the lack of guidance, one
could look to Koskenniemi’s systemic integration via Article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna Con
vention. Yet, significant incongruities emerge when it is superimposed onto Article 21 of
the Rome Statute as set out herein. Although the Court itself has frequently referred to
Article 31 of the Vienna Convention to interpret the Rome Statute and associated internal
instruments,80 it has done so in a confused manner, sometimes not specifying the basis for
doing so,81 and generally leaving it unclear whether the Vienna Convention interpretive
approach only applies to provisions of the Rome Statute or also to provisions of external
sources of law applicable under Article 21(1)(b).82
This confusion demonstrates the Court’s conflation of two separate notions – the
Article 21 Rome Statute process for determining and prioritising the applicable law
(referred to herein as the ‘identificatory’ function) and the Article 31 Vienna Convention
10 M. GILLETT
process for interpreting provisions of international law (referred to herein as the ‘inter
pretive’ function).83 Whereas applying an extrinsic law is different to interpreting an
internal provision in light of extrinsic law,84 the conflation can be seen in examples
such as the Katanga Trial Judgment, where the Court appeared to bundle all the pro
cesses together as one extended form of interpreting the Rome Statute.85 Further con
fusion arises from Pre-Trial Chamber I’s reading of ‘interpretation and application’ to
refer only on ‘interpretation’, rather than distinguishing between the different func
tions.86 Grover observes a similar lack of precision in the jurisprudence of the ad hoc tri
bunals, ‘with judges not always specifying whether they are invoking a legal source as an
aid to interpreting a statutory provision or applying it directly to a set of facts’ (Grover,
2010, p. 549).
The merging of the identificatory and interpretive functions can also be seen in aca
demic commentary (e.g. McLachlan, 2024, pp. 310–311). Collapsing the identificatory
and interpretive functions into one process ignores the explicit distinction
between these functions within Article 21 itself (see Manley et al., 2023, p. 774).
Given that prosecuting environmental harm will require the incorporation of substan
tive provisions of extrinsic law, and given that systemic integration is narrowly conceived
as an interpretive function (as discussed above), the present study proposes a new
concept of ‘framework integration’. It contends that framework integration is a more
fitting approach than systemic integration for the process enabled of incorporating exter
nal sources via Article 21(1)(b) at the ICC. Article 21(1)(b) does not stop at interpret
ation, but potentially permits the integration of substantive sources of international
law that are extrinsic to the Rome Statute. This reconceptualised approach of framework
integration seeks to realize that promise by allowing for the identification, interpret
ation87 and application of external sources of law, consistent with Article 21 of the
Rome Statute, and thereby ensuring a systemic approach consistent with the normative
constitutional foundations of the Rome Statute system. However, the way in which
framework integration manifests under Article 21 requires exploration, as the terms of
the article itself do not provide comprehensive guidance for judges looking to utilise it.
According to the adjudicative coherence test, if any key facets essential to the Court’s
operations are inherently jeopardised by a phenomenon or procedure proposed before
the Court, then that phenomenon or procedure is incompatible with the Court’s identity
as a judicial institution. Essential Court facets include the investigation and presentation
of inculpatory and exculpatory evidence, respect for fair trial rights of the accused, the
protection of victims and witnesses, the maintenance of efficient and expeditious pro
ceedings, and the entering of a well-reasoned judgment and sentence.99 The Court’s
two overarching obligations are the need to ensure accountability for atrocity
crimes and the principle of legality, which accords with the Rome Statute drafters’
goal of listing ‘crimes within the Court’s jurisdiction exhaustively and in as detailed
and clear a manner as possible so that states and their agents could know with reasonable
certainty what the outer reaches of prohibited conduct were and what obligations they
had under the Rome Statute.’100
For the identification and prioritisation of external sources of law, adjudicative coher
ence assists to triage provisions based on their fit with the Court’s core facets.101 For
example, provisions such as Articles 9, 14, 15 of the ICCPR (and their customary
counterparts reflected in the UDHR) are inherently relevant to a judicial institution
and can complement the Court’s existing due process provisions (Grover, 2010, p.
562). Similarly, the Court can incorporate the power to stay proceedings for abuse of
process in order to avoid undermining the integrity of a trial and, more broadly, the
legitimacy of the Court.102 As a further example, if the Court were to send witnesses
back to countries in which they face a real risk of persecution,103 it could undermine
core facets of the Court’s operations, including obtaining evidence (due to the ‘chilling
effect’ this would have on other witnesses) and, arguably, the protection of witnesses.104
In these instances, adjudicative coherence would augur in favour of integrating external
legal protections, such as the principle of non-refoulement.105
In this context, it is important to note that, whilst the principle of legality is axiomatic,
it is not an excessive stricture which prevents the court from conducting its work of dis
cerning the law (Grover, 2010, p. 547). In particular, it does not bar progressive and
dynamic interpretation of ICC law.106 What this principle requires is that, at
minimum, the judicial interpretation of an offence is reasonably foreseeable at the
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 13
relevant time to an accused receiving legal assistance.107 Bearing in mind these expla
nations, the adjudicative coherence criterion is consequently a means of harmonising
international law through the application of international criminal law, while respecting
the latter’s autonomous existence and underlying mores as an anti-impunity movement
rather than a purely humanitarian one (Stahn, 2019, p. 26).
Effet utile
A further criterion proposed to form part of the framework integration approach for the
ICC is that of effet utile or ‘effectiveness’ (ut res magis valeat quam pereat).108 Although it
is closely related to the telelogical approach to interpretation signalled by Article 31(1) of
the Vienna Convention’s reference to the object and purpose of a treaty, it also draws on
Article 26’s principle of pacta sunt servanda and Article 32(b)’s direction to avoid mani
festly absurd or unreasonable results (such as the provision no longer having any prac
tical utility whatsoever). Moreover, effet utile is used in the context of framework
integration for the purpose of identifying relevant sources of law along with being an
interpretive maxim. In relation to interpretation, support for its use can be seen in the
Katanga Trial Chamber holding that ‘in interpreting a provision of the founding texts,
the bench must dismiss any solution that could result in the violation or nullity of any
of its other provisions’.109
The principle of effectiveness directs the Court to select external sources of law which
will help ensure the operability and efficacy of the internal provisions of the Rome Statute
system. For example, although the existence of a subpoena power is not explicitly
included in the Rome System instruments, the Court was able to use the importance
of obtaining witness testimony in order to rely on a mix of external materials to fulfil
internal objectives recognised in the Rome Statute.110 The ad hoc tribunals also used
the principle of effet utile to discern applicable laws, including in relation to
subpoenas.111
However, an overly teleologically framed principle of effectiveness, if prioritised above
all other considerations, can lead to abuses and even the re-writing of the Statute, to the
detriment of the principle of legality (Robinson, 2008, p. 929). For this reason, in the con
struction of criteria of framework integration, the principle of effectiveness must not be
used to override adjudicative coherence.
provision under examination; (ii) relevancy of the subject-matter of regulation; (iii) (in
the case of external treaties in particular) complete or partial overlap of Signatory
Parties with the parties to the dispute; and (iv) temporal proximity, in the sense of
being applicable at the time of the events in question. The greater the terminological
identity, subject-matter relevancy, coverage of the parties, and temporal proximity to
the provision or objective under examination, the higher the priority should be given
to the external source of law with those features.
To provide an example, when determining what law to apply to add content to the
elements of ‘severe’, ‘damage’ and ‘unlawful’ in the context of environmental harm, texts
such as CITES, ENMOD or the Paris Pact on Green House Emissions would be particularly
relevant because of their linguistic and substantive proximity to the objective of identifying
and redressing harms meeting those elements. Other principles referring to the term
‘severe’ such as the Torture Convention or ad hoc tribunals’ jurisprudence on the
meaning of torture, would be less relevant to environmental harm because of the
different conduct they address. However, unlike the lex specialis rule, the proximity test
does not displace other bodies of law. Instead, it can assist to determine the range of
bodies of external law of relevance and their relative weight when integrating diverse
strands relating to a specific issue.
too often toward the view that the Rome Statute creates something close to a self – con
tained regime, rather than a part of a system of international criminal law enforcement’
(Cryer, 2009, pp. 396–399). In operational terms, the extent to which the application of
extrinsic sources of law in ICC proceedings will assist the de-fragmentation of inter
national law can be assessed by a counter-factual review of the risk of increased legal dis
crepancies created by the Court proceeding to determine an issue without reference to
that external law. If a hermetically sealed approach is likely to increase legal fragmenta
tion, this augurs in favour of seeking means to harmoniously integrate external sources
concerning overlapping matters.
When applied in light of the preceding analysis, framework integration provides a
vehicle for effective incorporation of separate legal sources which goes beyond the her
meneutic systemic integration, which is particularly apposite in environmental cases
implicating multiple areas of law with differing foundational principles. Because it
encompasses both the selection of legal sources as well as their prioritisation, interpret
ation, and application, it can allow bodies such as the ICC to contribute to the harmo
nisation of general international law.
334). Guidance for its integration into ICL can be taken by analogy from its integration
into other branches of law. For example, in its General Comment 36 on the right to life,
the Human Rights Committee referred to several key IEL principles, including the pre
cautionary principle, access to information, sustainable use of resources, environmental
impact assessment reports, and notification to other States about emergencies.123 In
relation to IHL, the International Law Commission (International Law Commission,
2022) and the International Committee of the Red Cross (ICRC, 2020) have both
looked at how IHL can protect the environment, but neither engaged in any systematic
integration of the frameworks of IEL and IHL. Hulme and others have sought to recon
cile IEL and IHL by looking at ‘how far IEL obligations in nature conservation treaties
can bolster existing protection offered by international humanitarian law’, but without
taking the further step of systemically integrating IEL/IHL into ICL.124
In some instances, IEL instruments provide a basis for identifying unlawful conduct,
such as in the case of illegal trafficking of hazardous wastes125 and unlawful maritime pol
lution.126 These can support the listing of prohibited underlying acts of ecocide, which is
essential in order to know what ecocide encompasses in accordance with the principle of
legality.127 Sources from IEL could also assist to substantiate the meaning of the term
‘severe’,128 which is a necessary element of Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Rome Statute and
is also present in the major proposed definitions of ecocide.129 Moreover, the precaution
ary principle could impact on the interpretation and application of the mens rea element
of launching attacks with knowledge of the risk to the environment under Article
8(2)(b)(iv),130 as well as the requirement that the accused foresee harm which would
be ‘clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage
anticipated’. Most instances of severe environmental harm are likely to involve indirect
intent rather than a specific intent to harm the environment. Formulations of indirect
intent usually revolve around the knowing assumption of risks and the failure to take pre
ventive measures.131 The precautionary principle will inform the determination of
assuming the risk of harm and taking ‘available and appropriate measures’.132 In this
way, an accused who argues that it was unclear that such harm would eventuate as the
science was indeterminate (and thereby seeks to be excused from criminal culpability)
would not be successful as long as they knew of the risk that such harm would likely
occur as a result of their actions. However, a court assessing whether to integrate the pre
cautionary principle in this manner would have to determine whether it unduly
encroached into the area of redefining the crime in violation of Article 22’s requirement
of strict interpretation of substantive crimes, as set out above.
A doctrinal example from IEL is the performance of an environmental impact assess
ment when undertaking activities potentially harmful to nature, which can be relevant to
the prosecution of environmental crimes at the ICC (Gillett 2022, pp. 113–114). Along
with the ICJ, which recognised this obligation in the Pulp Mills case,133 and the
ITLOS,134 other bodies have also noted it as a requirement which should be undertaken
such as before launching military operations.135
Another IEL principle is that of sustainable development. The IEP makes sustainable
development the central consideration on which its definition of ecocide pivots
(Minkova, 2024, p. 3, 24). This principle may also be of relevance to formulating reparations
for crimes harming the environment, particularly if they involve environmental remedia
tion. Support for incorporating this principle can be found in the ICJ comment in
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 17
enumerated version of environmental crimes (Ecocide) in its recent Directive, rather than
an unenumerated version such as that proposed by the IEP, which could be seen as violat
ing the principle of nullum crimen sine lege.146 This example reinforces the need to inte
grate IHRL principles when applying ecocide and environmentally-linked charges. Based
on the foregoing, IHRL can assist the conduct of environmental proceedings under ICL to
inform the level of specificity required of the prohibitions.
Additionally, the recently recognised human right to a clean, healthy and sustainable
environment could be used as the basis for a charge of the crime against humanity of per
secution, particularly as a ‘fundamental right’, given its intersection with the right to life,
private and family life and security.147 Depriving people of this right would have dual
anthropocentric and ecocentric impacts. To support the existence of this right, the
Court would likely look to international human rights law, as elaborated by the Inter-
American Court on Human Rights, as well as the United Nations Human Rights
Council and the General Assembly. At the same time, the terms of the crime of persecu
tion cannot be unlawfully exceeded, lest human rights liberalism could undermine crim
inal law liberalism (Danner & Martinez, 2005). As Robinson notes, the Court must be
careful not to transpose a victim-focused teleological reasoning directly from human
rights law, as that regime focuses more on a ‘broad and liberal construction to maximize
protection for beneficiaries’ rather than ‘the special moral restraints which arise when
fixing guilt upon an individual actor’ (Robinson, 2008, pp. 928–929).
On a related track, for crimes involving the misappropriation and destruction of prop
erty, such as the war crimes of pillage or the destruction of enemy property, ownership is
a key element on which IHRL can provide guidance. In relation to the abuse of ownership
rights, the African Court on Human and Peoples’ Rights and the Inter-American Court
of Human Rights have issued relevant jurisprudence, including that ‘Indigenous peoples’
right to collective property over natural resources – grounded in their cosmovision –
appears particularly relevant to determine how natural resources can be used’
(Martini, 2024, p. 378). Jurisprudence on collective rights from the Inter-American
Court of Human Rights could also provide ‘pertinent guidance’ to assess reparations
for victims by the Trust Fund for Victims of the ICC.148 This may be transposed onto
environmental harm cases, particularly given that human rights courts are increasingly
finding violations based on harm to nature.149 Utilising these IHRL concepts can add
to the effet utile to the Rome Statute’s provisions by enabling them to be applied to cir
cumstances of environmental harm and to provide specific remedies therefor.
Based on the preceding analysis, it can be seen that IHRL lies at the heart of adju
dicative coherence. IHRL is also an important means to give effect to the provisions of
the Rome Statute, is in several respects proximate in formulation to the Rome Statute’s
articles, and can assist to defragment international law. As long as not used exclusively
to expand terms at the expense of due process rights, IHRL can assist to realize the
provisions of the Rome Statute in relation to the environment. At the same time,
IHRL norms indicate that any version of ecocide which the court adopts should
contain enumerated underlying offences in an equivalent form to those contained
in the formulation of other crimes under the Rome Statute (Mistura, 2018, p. 199;
Gillett, 2022). Without that specificity as to the nature of the prohibited conduct con
stituting ecocide, both internal and external IHRL protections will conflict with the
efforts of the Court to redress environmental harm.
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 19
line with the cautions set out herein. The construct of framework integration, along with
the proposed de-conflicting criteria above, provides a means to conduct that triage in a
structured and principled way, responsive to the unique character and requirements of
the ICC as an international criminal institution.
A collateral issue raised by the use of extrinsic legal sources is the potential variation
in the precise formulation and application of crimes depending on which State party’s
territory or nationals are in question. For example, if CITES is used to flesh out the
terms of ecocide or any of the existing crimes with potential applicability to the
environment, as suggested above, then the question would arise whether that covers
non-States Parties to CITES, such as Kiribati, Marshall Islands, and Nauru, all of
which are ICC States Parties. For this challenge, it should be noted that variation in
the crimes that apply to different States as a jurisdictional matter is not an insurmoun
table problem. In fact, it is envisaged in Article 121(5) of the Rome Statute in relation to
any amendments creating new substantive crimes, which only apply to those States
which adopt them.
But the variation in the elements and contours of crimes, which differ as a matter of
law depending on the States in question, would raise concerns. At the normative level, it
would beg the question of whether an individual from a State Party to the extrinsic treaty
is convicted of the same crime as the individual from the non-State Party to that external
treaty. Although differences in the interpretation of the contours of a crime over time
does not inherently mean a violation of the principle of legality,160 the concurrent exist
ence of different interpretations could raise objections by an accused subjected to a more
exacting construction of the crime.
One potential resolution is to only apply treaties that are also reflective of customary
international law.161 Limiting external sources to those reflecting customary inter
national law would assist to mitigate challenges that the Court is progressing on
different normative tracks in different cases. Adherence to custom would also accord
with the views of several key players involved in the drafting of the Rome Statute, includ
ing the Chair of the Committee of the Whole and the Court’s First President, Philippe
Kirsch.162 However, that approach to Conventions would render the word ‘treaties’ in
Article 21(1)(b) redundant, as the relevant content would have to be part of the principles
and rules of customary international law. It would also deprive the Court of considerable
normative inspiration deriving from treaties setting out standards relevant to the protec
tion of the environment. Consequently, the Court will have to pay particular attention to
applying treaties with limited subscription and closely scrutinise customary international
law whenever possible to discern a parallel basis for their application of external sources.
While challenges will arise, that emphasis on drawing multiple legal sources together,
both conventional and customary in nature, will contribute to the harmonisation of
international criminal law with other branches of international law.
At the underlying conceptual level, there is a further risk of the ICC’s anthropocentric
orientation being incompatible with a sudden and strong shift toward an environmental
focus. Framework integration of IEL and other extrinsic sources of law could be seen as
exacerbating this risk. For practical purposes, the Court is currently ill-equipped to
address environmental cases in a large-scale manner (Gillett 2022, p. 316, 335–345).
At the normative level, a homeostatic reflex may lead the Court to subsume the eco
centric facets under traditional requirements, such as individual human suffering and
standing to brings claims and assume victim status, thereby anthropocentricizing
ecocide. As a bulwark against this assimilation, the adoption of ecocide (and increase
in the prosecution of environmental harms) should be accompanied by an increase in
appropriate resources, including scientific investigators and potentially judges with
22 M. GILLETT
Final conclusions
With environmental harm on the ICC’s horizon, the Court’s ability to draw on exter
nal branches of international law faces a moment of reckoning. Just as all war crimes
cases at the court to date have made greater or lesser reference to IHL, any environ
mental crimes case will inevitably see reference made to instruments and principles of
international environmental law. The Rome Statute framework leaves rooms to assim
ilate such extrinsic sources of international law, particularly via Article 21(1)(b).
However, the latitude granted to the judges under Article 21 is not complemented
by guidance for the exercise of that power. The traditional concept of systemic inte
gration is not apposite in the Rome Statute context, as it is explicitly limited to
interpretation rather than predicate step of identifying the ‘appropriate’ laws which
can then be subjected to interpretation and application.
To remedy this gap and to ensure normative coherence, this analysis has formulated
the novel approach of ‘framework integration’. This conceptual mechanism is bespoke
for the ICC, and covers the identificatory and interpretive functions, while also
guiding the normative assessments of other courts charged with harmonising disparate
strands of international law. Framework integration provides a means of ensuring that
the integration of external sources of law is conducted in a transparent, principled,
and structured manner. It permits a dynamic legal intertwining of branches of law
while remaining faithful to the Rome Statute framework and the fundamental precepts
of international law formation.
Using framework integration to draw external sources into international law can
import significant advantages for the adjudication of environmental harm. Environ
mental law instruments and principles can inform and instantiate factors, including
the lawfulness of conduct harming the environment, as well as the ‘severe’ element
and mens rea ‘criteria’ of crimes encompassing harm to nature, along with the proposed
crime of ecocide. In this way, these external sources can provide legal reference points on
which the ICC judiciary can rely in reaching their conclusions. IHL principles provide an
additional source of legal guidance to mediate between the interests of the environment
and those of belligerents and civilians caught up in armed conflict. Spanning the conflu
ence of all provisions is IHRL, including its elaboration of due process rights and its
identification of a substantive right to a clean, healthy and sustainable environment.
Beyond environmental harm, the analysis herein has important ramifications for any
areas where the Court may need to resort to extrinsic legal sources. Prosecutions for
aggression or involving new forms of evidence such as digital materials, can find gui
dance in the approach to framework integration that this study has articulated. Norma
tively, because of Article 21’s pivotal importance for the Court’s situating of the Rome
Statute as a part of the system of international law, the criteria set out herein provide
a means of coherently achieving that integrative function, while respecting the Court’s
axiomatic principles of legality and due process.
Challenges arise from using framework integration, include exposing the Court to
allegations of acting ultra vires and binding States to treaty provisions they may not
have signed up to. Yet careful management of these risks can be achieved. Key to this
are the four complementary principles, namely, adjudicative coherence, effet utile, sub
stantive proximity, and de-fragmentation of international law. Framework integration,
24 M. GILLETT
as developed in this article, emerges from the prospect of redressing ecocentric harm via
the hitherto essentially anthropocentric ICC. Examining the fault lines produced by the
Court’s ecocentric expansion is critical for the identification of moderating criteria by
which external legal sources, particularly international environmental law, could be
meaningfully drawn into the Rome Statute framework to assist the judges’
deliberatie while respecting the Court’s core obligations. Through the innovative norma
tive approach of framework integration, the conceptual underpinnings of the ICC’s func
tioning within the broader context of international law can be strengthened, not just
systematically but also systemically, and its ability to redress grave attacks on the environ
ment can be deepened and reinforced.
Notes
1. See, e.g. Climate Counsel, Greenpeace Brasil, Observatorio do Clima (2022).
2. See, e.g. Rekrut (2024).
3. Criminal sanctions are not a panacea but part of a multi-faceted process involving inputs
from the education, economic, and scientific sectors, along with the legal system.
4. Rome Statute, Article 17(1).
5. See, for example; Kostin (2024) (noting that Ukrainian prosecutors have been working closely
with the ICC on environmental harm including the destruction of the Kakhovka Dam).
6. Business and Human Rights Resource Centre (2024).
7. See ICC (2024); https://www.icc-cpi.int/sites/default/files/2024-12/2024-12-18-OTP-Policy-
Environmental-Crime.pdf.
8. ICC: Office of the Prosecutor’s Policy Paper on Preliminary Examinations, November 2013,
para.65; ICC: Office of the Prosecutor’s Policy Paper on Case Selection and Prioritisation,
15 September 2016, para.41.
9. See, e.g., Freeland (2015).
10. See, e.g. Gillett (2022); Independent Expert Panel for the Legal Definition of Ecocide,
Commentary and Core Text, June 2021, www.stopecocide.earth/expert-drafting-panel.
11. Alain Pellet refers to Rome Statute law as ‘proper law’ and extrinsic sources as ‘external law’;
Pellet (2002).
12. See Burdon Dasbach (2024).
13. See Gillett (2023).
14. Gillett (2023) referring to Independent Expert Panel and Gillett definitions of ecocide (both
definitions draw on international environmental law, as stated in their accompanying com
mentaries). See also Burdon Dasbach (2024).
15. See below under ‘The theory of systemic integration’.
16. See Koskenniemi (2005). See further McLachlan (2005). Note that the ILC suggested that the
term ‘interpretation’ could be interpreted in a broad manner to include ‘giving content’ to a
rule; ILC, ‘Report of the Study Group on Fragmentation of International Law: Difficulties
arising from the Diversification and Expansion of International Law’ (finalized by Mr.
Martti Koskenniemi), 56th Session, Geneva 3 May-4 June 2004 and 5 July-6 August 2004,
A/CN.4/L.663/Rev.l, at para.52. However, interpretation ultimately is the attribution of
meaning to express terms rather than adding substantive content to complement the exist
ing content of a treaty.
17. Rome Statute, Article 21(1)(b). See also Maučec (2021).
18. See Hafner and Binder (2006) referring to Belgium’s declaration concerning Article 31(l)(c)
of the ICC Statute upon ratification, dated 28 June 2000, and Colombia’s declaration upon
ratification, dated 5 August 2002.
19. See Hochmayr (2014); McLachlan (2024, pp. 311–312) (providing examples where external
sources were reviewed in ICC jurisprudence without a detailed examination of Article 21’s
functioning).
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 25
20. Shelton (2003) (assessing the problems of deciding the order of priority between competing
rules which are applicable to the legal matter or dispute).
21. McLachlan (2005, p. 284) (citing Brierly – ‘the development of specialized fields of inter
national law, if progressed in isolated compartments, could lead to serious conflicts of
laws within the international legal system’); International Law Commission (2006), UN
Doc. A/CN.4/L.682 and Add.1: 85, as corrected, U.N. Doc. A/CN.4/L.682/Corr.1 (11
August 2006), para.486 (‘normative conflict is endemic to international law’); Stahn and
van den Herik (2012); Webb (2013) (arguing that there are few instances of fragmentation,
such as on the specific intent for genocide, but that the overall picture is one of genuine inte
gration in relation to genocide); Cryer (2009) (noting that the ICC Elements of Crimes
depart from customary international law on the ‘manifest pattern’ contextual factor for
genocide).
22. Bruch et al. (2021) (reviewing ‘international humanitarian law, international environmental
law, international criminal law, international human rights law, the United Nations (UN)
Charter, and so on’ and finding that ‘a fragmented and unclear legal framework protects
the environment in times of armed conflict’).
23. See below under the heading ‘Reconceptualizing systemic integration as ‘framework inte
gration’ under Article 21 of the ICC Statute’, where the analysis highlights the conflation
made in ICC jurisprudence between the identificatory and interpretive functions required
under Article 21.
24. In her study on systemic integration, Rachovitsa refers to the ICC in passing, but makes no
mention of Article 21 of the Rome Statute; Rachovitsa (2017). In his study on IHRL and ICL,
Galand refers to IHRL having a systemic effect on ICL, but does not refer to environmental
harm in any respect; Galand (2019). In her study on systemic integration and climate
change, Feria-Tinta makes no reference to international criminal law and does not question
the limited interpretive framing of systemic integration; Feria-Tinta (2024). In his study on
systemic integration, Campbell McLachlan briefly refers to Article 21 of the Rome Statute
but does not address environmental harm in this context; McLachlan (2024). Anne Peters
reviews systemic integration and mentions the ICC, but does not refer at all to Article 21
and does not examine how extrinsic materials would be applicable under the Rome
Statute; Peters (2017).
25. Several authors have commented on the application of ICL and IHL, and in some cases
IHRL, to environmental harm, without assessing how these branches of law would be
integrated under the Rome Statute. See, e.g. Rekrut (2024) (commenting on ICL and
IHL, without mentioning Article 21 of the Rome Statute or any other theory of inte
gration). Others have talked about integrating IHL and IEL, but also without addressing
integration under the Rome Statute in any detail; Hulme (2022) (looking at how IEL can
apply during armed conflict, so as to ‘mirror and reinforce IHL protections’); Bruch et al.
(2021); van Steenberghe (2022). Other views focus on the Court’s utilisation of the Vienna
Convention for interpretation without looking at other extrinsic sources of law, e.g.
Manley et al. (2023); Jain (2017); Robinson (2022, pp. 334–335) (calling for IEL to be
incorporated into ecocide but without any discussion of the means to do so and
without mentioning Article 21).
26. Gillett (2022, pp. 170–174). But see Pardy (2002).
27. See, e.g., Cryer (2022) (containing no reference to systemic integration or to Article 21 of the
Rome Statute).
28. See, e.g. Ruhl (1997); Kooijman, 2023; Cusato and Jones (2023).
29. Of course, it is not claimed that ICL is a panacea capable of resolving these threats in and of
itself; see Gillett (2022, 40).
30. See Nishimura (2022) (noting that the international community seeks a ‘system of inter
national law that should strive for coherence and consistency’). See also Grover (2010)
(‘[i]f judges invoke diametrically opposing canons of interpretation for crimes in the
Rome Statute, they may call into question the legitimacy of international criminal law, as
they may appear to be invoking a particular interpretive canon because it yields a desired
26 M. GILLETT
outcome.’). Grover also notes ‘in terms of a hierarchy of applicable sources of law for pur
poses other than protecting the rights of the accused, little or no thought was given to the
relationship between internationally recognized human rights and the Rome Statute’
… [similarly] ‘in terms of normative hierarchies, little or no thought was given to the
relationship between internationally recognised human rights and the ‘international law
of armed conflict’; Grover (2010, p. 559).
31. See, JEP: Macro Case No. 5 Decision of 1 February 2023, paras. 500, 1029–1030. On anti-
personnel mines, the JEP noted that these particularly impacted sites that are sacred to indi
genous and other special communities, including lagoons, moors, and riverbanks.
32. See Colangelo (2016); King and Thornhill (2003, pp. 52–53) (‘law’s unique social function is,
therefore, to stabilize normative expectations over time’; ‘[l]aw allows at least for the possi
bility of expectations being based on established norms so that it is possible to anticipate
whether conduct will be legal or illegal, subject to the law or not subject to the law’);
Perez-Leon-Acevedo (2024).
33. See, e.g. von der Dunk (2021).
34. See Klabbers et al. (2009, pp. 135–142); Shany (2014).
35. Although many refer to the Nuremberg trials as the emergence of international criminal law,
at that point it was still ad hoc and inherently linked to armed conflict. After the end of the
Cold War, the requirement of armed conflict was removed from crimes against humanity
and a permanent international criminal court was established.
36. See Grotius (1925, pp. 527–529).
37. Scharf (2022, pp. 25–26). Though ICL has since differentiated itself from IHL and IHRL,
though maintaining a close inter-connection, Stahn (2019) (‘International criminal law
has gradually distinguished itself from other bodies of law, such as international humanitar
ian law or human rights law’.).
38. See Bergsmo et al. (2014).
39. See Schabas (2011, pp. 1–16); Bergsmo et al. (2014).
40. See Peters (2017).
41. Tokyo Tribunal, Judgment of The Honorable Justice Pal, Member from India.
42. Simpson (1997, pp. 4–11); Sander (2015); Iommi (2020); Popovski (2012). See also
Torbisco-Casals (2021).
43. See, e.g. ICC, Prosecutor v. Ntaganda, Case No. ICC-01/04-02/06 OA5, Judgment on the
Appeal of Mr Ntaganda Against the ‘Second Decision on the Defence’s Challenge to the Jur
isdiction of the Court in Respect of Counts 6 and 9’ (Appeals Chamber), 15 June 2017, para.
53 (‘[T]he expression “the established framework of international law” in the chapeaux of
article 8(2)(b) and (2)(e) as well as in the Introduction to the Elements of Crimes for
article 8 of the Statute, when read together with article 21 of the Statute, requires the
former to be interpreted in a manner that is consistent with international law, and inter
national humanitarian law in particular’). See also McLachlan (2024, pp. 311–312).
44. Libya and Sudan constitute earlier examples, whereas Russia’s full-scale invasion of Ukraine
in 2022 and the Israel-Hamas conflict have also seen multiple jurisdictions engaged in
litigation.
45. Colangelo (2016, p. 34) (referring to ‘the “presumption of catholicity,” that is a presumption
toward using as much of the universe of international legal sources and materials available as
possible to resolve disputes. Although such rule predation may not always be purposeful, it
nonetheless places actors subject to multiple sets of laws in difficult and maybe even imposs
ible positions when it comes to compliance with “the law”’).
46. See, e.g. ICTY: Prosecutor v. Dusko Tadić, Decision on the Defence Motion for Interlocutory
Appeal on Jurisdiction, IT-94–1-AR72, 2 October 1995, para.204; Gutierrez Posse (2006).
47. ICC: Prosecutor v. Lubanga (ICC-01/04- 01/06), Judgment on the appeal of the Prosecutor
against the decision of Trial Chamber I entitled ‘Decision on the consequences of non-
disclosure of exculpatory materials covered by Article 54(3)(e) agreements and the appli
cation to stay the prosecution of the accused, together with certain other issues raised at
the Status Conference on 10 June 2008’, 21 October 2008, para. 51 (implicitly accepting
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 27
Arido against the decision of Trial Chamber III entitled ‘Decision on Sentence pursuant to Article
76 of the Statute’, 8 March 2018, ICC-01/05-01/13-2276-Red, paras 75−76 (‘The nature and type
of the concerned power, as well as of the matter to which it relates, are relevant considerations to
determine whether there are gaps justifying recourse to subsidiary sources of law or invocation of
“inherent powers”’). See also Bitti (2015, pp. 426–427); Hochmayr (2014, p. 664).
67. For example, Bitti takes a restrictive view of Article 21: ‘the external sources of law men
tioned in Article 21(1)(b) and (c) of the Statute should be of limited use before the ICC
and indeed have been of limited use apart from some very isolated jurisprudence’, Bitti
(2015, pp. 433–434).
68. See, e.g., ICC: Prosecutor v. Ruto and Sang, ‘Reasons for the Decision on Excusal from Pres
ence at Trial under Rule 134 quater, Ruto and Sang’ (ICC-01/09-01/11), Trial Chamber
V(A), 18 February 2014, paras.56–60.
69. See Hochmayr (2014, pp. 664–666).
70. Hochmayr (2014, pp. 674–675). Cassese has also recognised the need to look to extrinsic
treaties, such as in the context of assessing whether weapons are indiscriminate or cause
unnecessary suffering; Cassese (2008, p. 50).
71. See also Manley et al. (2023, p. 774).
72. See deGuzman (2022), fn 26. Dapo Akande also refers to treaties related to substantive
crimes as those of primary relevance under this provision, but allows for other treaties to
also be residually relevant; Akande (2009).
73. A footnote that would have specified that ‘international law’ means ‘public international law’
was not retained in the final version of the Rome Statute; UN Doc. A/CONF.183/C.1/
WGAL/L.2, p. 2, fn. 2; Schabas (2016, p. 519).
74. Rome Statute, Article 21(1)(a).
75. On this basis, the term ‘appropriate’ supports the proximity criterion for framework inte
gration set out below.
76. The ICTY permitted such an approach in the Tadić case, where it concluded that the Statute
allows for the application of international agreements that are binding on the parties at the
time of the offence, conditional on them not conflicting with peremptory norms; ICTY:
Tadić Jurisdictional Decision, IT-94-1-AR72, 2 October 1995, paras. 143– 144. See
further, by analogy, see Permanent Court of Arbitration (2003, paras. 93–105).
77. See Panel Report, EC – Measures Affecting the Approval and Marketing of Biotech Products,
paras. 7.49–7.95, esp. 7.75, WTO Doc. WT/DS 291–293/R (29 June 2006). See Peters (2017,
pp. 693–694).
78. Subject to any question of persistent objector status.
79. See ICC: Prosecutor v Al-Bashir, Judgment in the Jordan Referral re Al-Bashir Appeal,
Appeals Chamber, ICC Case No 02/05-01/09-3 (6 May 2019).
80. See, e.g., ICC: Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, ICC-01/04–01/06 A5, Judgment on the
appeal of Mr. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo against his conviction, 1 December 2014, para.277;
ICC: Prosecutor v. Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo, ICC-01/05–01/08–3343, Judgment pursuant
to Article 74 of the Statute, 21 March 2016, para.70; ICC: Democratic Republic of Congo,
Decision 2006, para.33.
81. See, e.g., ICC: Situation in Bangladesh/Myanmar (Decision, 14 November 2019) ICC-01/19,
para. 55.
82. See Katanga Trial Judgment, para.47 (considering that under article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna
Convention on the Law of Treaties, the interpretation of the applicable law can also be
informed by external sources providing context).
83. The distinction is mentioned in Hochmayr (2014, pp. 656–657). In addition to the identifi
catory and interpretative functions, there is also the applicative function; see Urs (2024, p.
12). Koskenniemi hints at taking his approach to systemic integration beyond interpret
ation, stating ‘although a tribunal may only have jurisdiction in regard to a particular instru
ment, it must always interpret and apply that instrument in the context of its relationship to
its normative environment – that is to say “other” international law’ (emphasis added).
However, the rest of his study shows that he did not take this approach beyond the
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 29
confines of interpretation; International Law Commission (2006, para. 423). Another use of
extrinsic legal sources may be as ‘evidence of acceptance and recognition’ of the bindingness
of a legal norm, such as a jus cogens norm; International Law Commission, 2022 Study on
Jus Cogens Principles, conclusion 8. See also Hafner and Binder (2006, p. 172); Hochmayr
(2014, p. 662).
84. Pauwelyn (2003, pp. 203–204) referring to the Lockerbie case, ICJ Reports 1992, para. 42.
85. See ICC: Katanga Trial Judgment, para.47.
86. See Bitti (2015, pp. 436–437) citing ICC: Situation in the Democratic Republic of the Congo,
Decision on the Joinder of the Cases against Germain Katanga and Mathieu Ngudjolo Chui,
Katanga, 10 March 2008, ICC-01/04-01/07-257, PTC I, ICC, 10 March 2008. But see ICC:
Appeals Chamber in Prosecutor v. Lubanga, Judgment on the Appeal of Mr. Thomas
Lubanga Dyilo against the Decision on the Defence Challenge to the Jurisdiction of the
Court pursuant to article 19(2)(a) of the Statute, ICC-01/04-01/06-772, 14 December
2006, para.37.
87. Technically, Article 31 of the VCLT could still be used to conduct the interpretive function,
insofar as it does not clash with Article 21 of the Rome Statute. Given that the Rome Statute,
including Article 21, does not exhaustively specify how to interpret its terms, this allows for
resort to Article 31 of the VCLT in accordance with the terms of Article 21(1)(b) of the
Rome Statute. Consequently, interpretive guides, such as the ‘ordinary meaning’ and
‘object and purpose’ tests remain valid under the framework integration approach.
88. See Article 52(3) of API for a corresponding presumption for protected objects.
89. See Gillett (2023).
90. See ILC 2022 Jus Cogens study, Conclusions 10–11.
91. See ILC 2022 Jus Cogens study, Conclusion 23 ‘non-exhaustive list’ referring to the prohibi
tion of aggression, the prohibition of genocide, the prohibition of CAH and the prohibition
of torture, for example.
92. See, e.g. Bitti (2015, pp. 438–439). But he also argues that there is no such basis to distinguish
between the superior status of the law in question (at 440).
93. See ICC: Lubanga Appeal Judgment, para.277. But see Maučec (2021, p. 24).
94. See Colangelo (2016, Part V) (referring to ‘precise and concrete “coherence methods” (as
opposed to conflict methods), to use in advancing international law’s systemic coherence
through decisional cross-fertilization in resolving disputes’).
95. Adjudicative coherence emanates from the institution’s identity as a Court, which is reflected
in the Preamble and Article 1 of the Rome Statute among other provisions. Effet utile emanates
from the Preamble’s requirement ‘to put an end to impunity for the perpetrators of [atrocity
crimes]’ and ensure their ‘effective prosecution’ as well as the structure of Article 21(1)(a) to (c)
which provides a cascading web of normative sources designed to avoid the Court lacking a
legal basis to act. Substantive proximity emanates from the multiple references throughout
the Statute to international law (25 references), the law of armed conflict/IHL (around 8 refer
ences), human rights law (3 references), and several more in the Elements of Crimes, demon
strating a graduated focus on these areas (if ecocide is adopted into the Rome Statute,
references to IEL will likely also be added). De-fragmentation also emanates from the multiple
references to the Court’s Statute taking account of international law.
96. Gillett (2022, pp. 49–50). For an example of an interpretive approach approximating adju
dicative coherence in the context of an international criminal trial, see STL, Judgment,
Ayyash et al. (STL-11-01/T), Trial Chamber, 18 August 2020. paras. 5917–5918. See also
Di Gianfrancesco (2021).
97. See Katanga Trial Judgment, para.50 referring to Article 22. The principle also encompasses
the notion of lex certa; ICC: Prosecutor v. Al Bashir, Case No. ICC-02/05-01/09-3, Decision
on the Prosecution’s Application for a Warrant of Arrest Against Omar Hassan Ahmad Al
Bashir, paras. 128–131. See also Grover (2010, p. 550) (the ‘principles underpinning a liberal
criminal justice system are those of personal culpability, legality, and fair labelling’); Robin
son (2008); Jacobs (2014).
98. ICC Elements of Crimes, Article 7 Crimes against humanity, Introduction: 3.
30 M. GILLETT
118. Per Verzijl P, Georges Pinson case, Franco-Mexican Commission (Verzijl, President), AD
1927-8, No. 292, para.50.
119. ICJ: Case Concerning the Gabcíkovo--Nagymaros Project (Hungary v. Slovakia), Judgment,
ICJ Reports 1997, para.140.
120. For leading formulations of ecocide, see IEP (2021) and Gillett (2022a) definitions refer
enced above.
121. Gillett (2023). See also Schabas (2003, p. 887).
122. Robinson (2008, pp. 927–928). For example, see the term ‘person’ as used in an international
criminal law context, such as Article 67 in the Rome Statute, as opposed to how the term
‘person’ is used in international trade law – https://investmentpolicy.unctad.org/
international-investment-agreements/treaty-files/2552/download.
123. HRC: General comment No. 36, Article 6: right to life, CCPR/C/GC/36, 3 September 2019,
para.62.
124. See Hulme (2022, p. 1156).
125. Basel Convention on the Control of Transboundary Movements of Hazardous Wastes and
Their Disposal, 1673 UNTS 57, 22 March 1989, Article 9.
126. Protocol of 1978 Relating to the International Convention for the Prevention of Pollution
from Ships, 1340 UNTS 61, 17 February 1978, and annexes.
127. See Gillett (2022) definition of ecocide, which links the enumerated underlying acts to exist
ing IEL conventions; Gillett (2023).
128. See Hulme (2022, pp. 1165–1166) (in the context of the corresponding IHL provisions –
Articles 35(3) and 55 of Additional Protocol I).
129. See IEP and Gillett (2022) definitions referenced above.
130. See also Hulme (2022, p. 113, 1168) (commenting on the precautionary principle’s ana
logues in IHL).
131. Gillett (2022, 348) setting out a proposed definition of Ecocide, with a mens rea element
focused on ‘Wilfulness’.
132. See Hulme (2022, p. 1167).
133. See ICJ: Pulp Mills on the River Uruguay (Argentina v. Uruguay), Judgment, ICJ Reports
2010, para.204.
134. ITLOS: Responsibilities and Obligations of States Sponsoring Persons and Entities with
Respect to Activities in the Area, Seabed Disputes Chamber of ITLOS, Advisory Opinion
of 1 February 2011, paras 145–150.
135. Report of the International Law Commission of its 66th Session, held between 5 May–6 June
and 7 July–8 August 2014, A/69/10, para.209.
136. ICJ: Gabcíkovo – Nagymaros, para.140.
137. ICJ: Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion, [1996] ICJ Reports
226, para.29.
138. On gravity, see Urs (2024).
139. See Robinson (2022, p. 325).
140. The Rome Statute has an overwhelmingly anthropocentric formulation at present; Gillett
(2022, 354).
141. ICC: The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Judgment on the Appeal of Mr. Thomas
Lubanga Dyilo against the Decision on the Defence Challenge to the Jurisdiction of the
Court pursuant to article 19(2)(a) of the Statute of 3 October 2006, Appeals Chamber,
ICC-01/04-01/06-772, para.37.
142. On ICL and IHRL, see, e.g., McDermott (2016); Galand (2019). On IHRL and IHL, see, e.g.,
Oberleitner (2015); Kolb and Gaggioli (eds.) (2013). See also Lemos (2023).
143. See above under the heading ‘Adjudicative Coherence as a Criminal Court’.
144. Feria-Tinta (2024, p. 25) citing inter alia Inter-American Court of Human Rights,
The Environment and Human Rights (Advisory Opinion, 15 November 2017) Series A
No 23.
145. Inter-American Court of Human Rights, The Environment and Human Rights Advisory
Opinion, paras. 43–45.
32 M. GILLETT
146. Mistura (2018) (‘A general definition of ‘environmental crime’ would likely breach such
principle, as it poses a high risk of vagueness and potential over-breadth of coverage.’).
See also Killean and Short (2024) ).
147. See Martini (2024); Martini et al. (2023).
148. Perez-Leon-Acevedo (2024, pp. 391–393) citing Filing on Reparations and Draft
Implementation Plan, Lubanga (ICC-01/04-01/06-3177-Red), TFV, 3 November 2015,
paras 219–35.
149. See, e.g. IACtHR: Indigenous Communities of the Lhaka Honhat Association (Our Land) v
Argentina (Merits, Reparations and Costs, Judgment) IACtHR Series C No 400 (6 February
2020) para 202; ECtHR: Verein KlimaSeniorinnen Schweiz and Others v. Switzerland.
(2024). Grand Chamber of the European Court of Human Rights, Application no. 53600/20.
150. See, e.g. Hulme (2022).
151. See, e.g. ICTY: Final Report to the Prosecutor by the Committee established to Review the
NATO Bombing Campaign against the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia (2000), paras.14–15,
90–91.
152. ICRC Customary International Humanitarian Law Study, Volume I book3 at Rules 43–45.
153. ICRC (2020). See also International Law Commission, ‘Principles on the protection of the
environment in relation to armed conflict’, now reflected in United Nations General Assem
bly resolution 77/104.
154. See Gillett (2022b).
155. See STL: Interlocutory Decision on the Applicable Law: Terrorism, Conspiracy, Homicide,
Perpetration, Cumulative Charging (Case No. STL-11-01/I), Appeals Chamber, 16 February
2011.
156. See, e.g. Rachovitsa (2017, pp. 563–564).
157. See, e.g. Special Tribunal for Lebanon: Public Redacted Version of Judgment on Appeal,
NewTV S.A.L. and Al Khayat (STL-14-05/I/CJ), Appeals Chamber, 8 March 2016 Contempt
Cases; Public Redacted Version of the Judgment, Akhbar Beirut S.A.L. and Al Amin (STL-
14-06/I/CJ), Contempt Judge, 15 July 2016.
158. See above under the heading of ‘Reconceptualizing systemic integration as ‘framework
integration’.
159. See, by analogy, ECtHR, Verein KlimaSeniorinnen Schweiz and Others v. Switzerland,
no. 53600/20, judgment (Grand Chamber), 9 April 2024, para.453–455 (referring also
to Fedotova and Others v. Russia [GC], nos. 40792/10 and 2 others, para.167, 17 January 2023).
160. See ECtHR: Jorgić v. Germany, App. No. 74613/01, §§ 89–116 (12 July 2007).
161. On the interplay of customary international law and the Rome Statute instruments, see
Cryer (2009, p. 399); Grover (2010, pp. 564–566).
162. Kirsch (2006, p. 79, 80). See also Grover (2010, pp. 568–569, 576); von Hebel and Robinson
(1999).
163. See Minkova (2024, p. 7).
164. See Minkova (2024, p. 3).
165. In this respect, see the author’s proposed definition of ecocide, which does not pivot on the
notion of sustainable development, which is only an element in relation to the final under
lying act of ecocide.
166. See Stevenson (2013) arguing that compliance with IEL can in fact lead to adverse impacts
on the environment.
167. See above under the heading ‘Implementation of framework integration for ecocide and
environmental harm’ referring to murder, torture or rape.
Acknowledgement
The views herein are those of the author alone and do not necessarily reflect those of any organ
isation he is affiliated with. Thanks go to the reviewers for their excellent comments; all errors rest
with the author.
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 33
Disclosure statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).
Notes on contributor
Dr. Matthew Gillett is a Senior Lecturer at the University of Essex and a United Nations Special
Mandate Holder (Chair Rapporteur of the United Nations Working Group on Arbitrary Deten
tion). He prosecuted cases before the international courts in The Hague for over a decade. He
has published extensively on international criminal law, human rights, and protection of the
environment.
ORCID
Matthew Gillett http://orcid.org/0000-0002-3507-0944
References
Abtahi, H., & Dawson, G. (2016). The anatomy of the Milošević trial (2001–2006). International
Journal of Humanitarian Action, 1(4), 5–6.
Akande, D. (2009). Sources of international criminal Law. In A. Cassese, et al (Ed.), The Oxford
companion to international criminal justice (vol. 41, pp. 48–49). Oxford University Press.
Bergsmo, M., Ling, C. W., & Ping, Y. I. (2014). Historical origins of international criminal law.
Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher.
Bitti, G. (2015). The ICC and its applicable law, 18 Article 21 and the hierarchy of sources of Law
before the ICC. In C. Stahn (Ed.), The Law and practice of the international criminal court (pp.
412–413). Oxford University Press.
Bruch, C., Payne, C. R., & Sjöstedt, B. (2021). Armed conflict and the environment. In L. Rajamani
& J. Peel (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of international environmental Law (2nd ed., p. 865).
online edn, Oxford Handbooks, Oxford Academic.
Business and Human Rights Resource Centre. (2024, September 9). Pacific island countries ask
ICC to recognise “ecocide” as crime allowing for prosecution of heads of state & large compa
nies for environmental destruction. https://www.business-humanrights.org/en/latest-news/
pacific-island-countries-ask-icc-to-recognise-ecocide-as-crime-allowing-for-prosecution-of-he
ads-of-state-large-companies-for-environmental-destruction/.
Caracciolo, I. (1999). Applicable Law. In F. Lattanzi & W. Schabas (Eds.), Essays on the Rome
Statute, Vol. 1 (pp. 211). il Sirente.
Cassese, A. (2008). International criminal Law (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press.
Climate Counsel, Greenpeace Brasil, Observatorio do Clima. (2022, November 9). ICC
Communication: Crimes Against Humanity in Brazil: 2011 to the Present.
Colangelo, A. J. (2016). A systems theory of fragmentation and harmonization. New York
University Journal of International Law and Politics, 49(1), 4.
Cryer, R. (2009). Royalism and the king: Article 21 of the Rome statute and the politics of sources.
New Criminal Law Review: An International and Interdisciplinary Journal, 12(3), 395–397.
Cryer, R. (2022). Chapter 26: International criminal Law, edited by F. Moeckli, et al. (Ed.),
International human rights Law (4th ed., pp. 547–548). Oxford University Press.
Cusato, E., & Jones, E. (2023). The ‘imbroglio’ of ecocide: A political economic analysis. Leiden
Journal of International Law, 37(1), 1–20.
Danner, A., & Martinez, J. (2005). Guilty associations: Joint criminal enterprise, command respon
sibility and the development of international criminal law. California Law Review, 93(1), 81–89.
Dasbach, A. B. (2024, May 1). How the ICC is using international criminal law to prosecute sus
pects of eco crimes. Legal Planet, https://legal-planet.org/2024/05/01/how-the-icc-is-using-
international-criminal-law-to-prosecute-suspects-of-eco-crimes/.
34 M. GILLETT
deGuzman, M. (2022). Article 21. In K. Ambos (Ed.), Rome Statute of the international criminal
court, article by article commentary (4th ed., p. 1129). Beck/Hart/Nomos.
Di Gianfrancesco, L. (2021). The STL still struggles with the method for interpreting its statute:
The Ayyash et al. Trial judgment departs from the tribunal’s ‘Tadić‘ on the identification of
the applicable Law. Journal of International Criminal Justice, 19(5), 1228–1229.
Djeffal, C. (2015). Static and evolutive treaty interpretation. Cambridge University Press. 3–5.
Donnedieu de Vabres, H. (1922–1923). Le système de la répression universelle: Ses origines his
toriques – Ses formes contemporaines. Revue critique de droit international privé, 18, 563–564.
Falk, R. (1973). Environmental warfare and ecocide: Facts, appraisal and proposals. Bulletin of
Peace Proposals, 4(1), 80–96. https://doi.org/10.1177/096701067300400105
Feria-Tinta, M. (2024). The master key to international law: Systemic integration in climate
change cases. Cambridge International Law Journal, 13(1), 20–40. https://doi.org/10.4337/cilj.
2024.01.02
Flynn, C. (2020). Is Article 21 of the Rome Statute an impediment to the development of senten
cing principles at the international criminal court. Florida Journal of International Law, 32(1),
51.
Freeland, S. (2015). Addressing the international destruction of the environment during warfare
under the Rome Statute of the international criminal court. Intersentia.
Galand, A. S. (2019). The systemic effect of international human rights Law on international crim
inal Law. In M. Scheinin (Ed.), Human rights norms in ‘other’ international courts (pp. 87–131).
Cambridge University Press.
Gillett, M. (2022a). Prosecuting environmental harm before the international criminal court.
Cambridge University Press.
Gillett, M. (2022b). Protected zones, edited by A. Peters, et al. (Ed.), Animals under the Law of
armed conflict, 234–263. Cambridge University Press.
Gillett, M. (2023, July 3). The Kakhovka Dam and Ecocide: A convergence of international
criminal law, international humanitarian law, international environmental law, and inter
national human rights law?. Verfassungsblog. https://verfassungsblog.de/the-kakhovka-dam-
and-ecocide/.
Goy, B. (2012). Individual criminal responsibility before the international criminal court: A com
parison with the Ad Hoc Tribunals. International Criminal Law Review, 12(1), 7.
Grotius, H. (1925). De Jure Belli ac Pacis, Book II, chapter XXI, section IV, translated by Francis
W. Kelsey. Clarendon Press.
Grover, L. (2010). A call to arms: Fundamental dilemmas confronting the interpretation of crimes
in the Rome statute of the international criminal court. European Journal of International Law,
21(3), 543–583. https://doi.org/10.1093/ejil/chq057
Gutierrez Posse, H. D. T. (2006). The relationship between international humanitarian law and the
international criminal tribunals. International Review of the Red Cross, 88(861), 73–76.
Hafner, G., & Binder, C. (2006). The interpretation of article 21(3) ICC statute opinion reviewed.
Austrian Review of International and European Law, 9(1), 167.
Hochmayr, G. (2014). Applicable law in practice and theory: Interpreting article 21 of the ICC
statute. Journal of International Criminal Justice, 12(4), 655–679. https://doi.org/10.1093/jicj/
mqu057
Hulme, K. (2022): 1155–1190 Using international environmental law to enhance biodiversity and
nature conservation during armed conflict’. Journal of International Criminal Justice, 20, 5.
ICC. (2024, February 16). Prosecutor Karim Khan, statement on environmental policy. https://
www.icc-cpi.int/news/office-prosecutor-launches-public-consultation-new-policy-initiative-ad
vance-accountability-0.
ICRC. (2020). Guidelines on the protection of the natural environment in armed conflict: Rules and
recommendations relating to the protection of the natural environment under international
humanitarian law, with commentary. International Committee of the Red Cross.
Independent Expert Panel (IEP). (2021, June). Legal Definition of Ecocide, Commentary and Core
Text. Stop Ecocide Foundation. https://www.stopecocide.earth/expert-drafting-panel.
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 35
International Law Commission. (2006, April 13). Report of the study group of the international
law commission - fragmentation of international law: Difficulties arising from the diversifica
tion and expansion of international law. finalized by Chair Mr. Martti Koskenniemi.
International Law Commission. (2022). Draft principles on the protection of the environment in
relation to armed conflict, Chapter V, A/77/10, 18 April–3 June and 4 July–5 August 2022.
Iommi, L. G. (2020). Whose justice? The ICC ‘Africa problem’. International Relations, 34(1),
105–129. https://doi.org/10.1177/0047117819842294
Jacobs, D. (2014). International criminal Law. In J. Kammerhofer & J. D’Aspremont (Eds.),
International legal positivism in a post-modern world (p. 467). Cambridge University Press.
Jain, N. (2017). Interpretive divergence. Virginia Journal of International Law, 57, 45.
Killean, R., & Short, P. D. (2024) Scoping a domestic legal framework for ecocide in Scotland.
Environmental Rights Centre for Scotland, 1–56.
King, M., & Thornhill, C. (2003). Niklas Luhmann’s theory Of politics and law. Palgrave Macmillan.
Kirsch, P. (2006). Customary international humanitarian law, its enforcement, and the role of the
international criminal court, edited by L. Maybee, & B. Chakka (Eds.), Custom as a source of
international humanitarian law: Proceedings of the conference to mark the publication of the
ICRC study ‘customary international humanitarian law’, (pp. 539–547). ICRC .
Klabbers, J., Peters, A., & Ulfstein, G. (2009). The constitutionalisation of international Law.
Oxford University Press.
Kolb, R., & Gaggioli, G. (Eds.). (2013). Research Handbook on human rights and humanitarian law.
Edward Elgar.
Kooijman, M. (2023). From Anthropos to Oikos in international criminal law: A critical-theoreti
cal exploration of ecocide as an ‘Ecocentric’ amendment to the Rome Statute. In Netherlands
yearbook of international Law 2021 (pp. 104). T.M.C. Asser Press.
Koskenniemi, M. (2005). From apology to Utopia. Cambridge University Press.
Kostin, A. (2024, April 26). Opinion: Environment: No longer a silent victim – Ukraine leads the
charge in prosecuting environmental war crimes. Kyiv Post. https://www.kyivpost.com/
opinion/31746.
Lekkas, S.-I., & Merkouris, P. (2022). Interpretation of international law: Rules, content, and evol
ution. Netherlands International Law Review, 69(2), 183–189. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40802-
022-00226-w
Lemos, M. (2023). The appeals chamber’s jurisdictional judgment in Abd-Al-Rahman and the
issue of applicable law at the international criminal court. Chinese Journal of International
Law, 22(2), 223–261. https://doi.org/10.1093/chinesejil/jmad024
Luban, D. (2010). Fairness to rightness: Jurisdiction, legality, and the legitimacy of international
criminal Law. In S. Besson & J. Tasioulas (Eds.), The philosophy of international law (p. 579).
Oxford University Press.
Manley, S., Tehrani, P. M., & Rasiah, R. (2023). Mapping interpretation by the international crim
inal court. Leiden Journal of International Law, 36(3), 771–806. https://doi.org/10.1017/
S0922156523000225
Martini, P. (2024). International criminal law and the environment: A few reflections. International
Community Law Review, 26(4), 367–380. https://doi.org/10.1163/18719732-12341505
Martini, P., Holt, J., & Sarliève, M. (2023). Mass deforestation as a crime against humanity?
International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 72(4), 1013–1046. https://doi.org/10.1017/
S0020589323000404
Maučec, G. (2021). The international criminal court and the issue of intersectionality – a concep
tual and legal framework for analysis. International Criminal Law Review, 21(1), 21–22.
McDermott, Y. (2016). Fairness in international criminal trials. Oxford University Press.
McLachlan, C. (2005). The principle of systemic integration and article 31(3)(C) of the Vienna
convention. International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 54(2), 279–320. https://doi.org/10.
1093/iclq/lei001
McLachlan, C. K. (2024). The principle of systemic integration in international law (online edn).
Oxford Academic.
36 M. GILLETT
Mégret, F. (2011). The problem of an international criminal law of the environment. Columbia
Journal of Environmental Law, 36(2), 195.
Merkouris, P. (2015). Article 31(3)(c) VCLT and the principle of systemic integration: Normative
shadows in Plato’s Cave. In Queen Mary studies in international Law, Vol. 17. Brill.
Minkova, L. (2024). Ecocide, sustainable development, and critical environmental law insights.
Journal of International Criminal Justice, 22(1), 5.
Mistura, A. (2018). Is there space for environmental crimes under international criminal law? The
impact of the office of the prosecutor policy paper on case selection and prioritization on the
current legal framework. Columbia Journal of Environmental Law, 43(1), 199.
Nishimura, L. (2022). Adaptation and anticipatory action: Integrating human rights duties into
the climate change regime. Climate Law, 12(2), 99–127. https://doi.org/10.1163/18786561-
20210001
Oberleitner, G. (2015). Human rights in armed conflict: Law, practice, policy. Cambridge
University Press.
Pardy, B. (2002). Applying the precautionary principle to private persons: Should it affect civil and
criminal liability? Les Cahiers De Droit, 43(1), 63–78. https://doi.org/10.7202/043702ar
Pauwelyn, J. (2003). Conflict of norms in public international law how WTO law relates to other
rules of international law. Cambridge University Press.
Pellet, A. (2002). Applicable Law. In A. Cassese, P. Gaeta, & J. R. W. D. Jones (Eds.), The
Rome statute of the international criminal court (Vol. II, pp. 1069–1070). Oxford University
Press.
Perez-Leon-Acevedo, J.-P. (2024). ‘Reparations in environmental cases: Should the international
criminal court consider the inter-American court of human rights’ jurisprudence?. Journal of
International Dispute Settlement, 15(3), 401.
Permanent Court of Arbitration. (2003, July 2). Dispute concerning access to information under
article 9 of the OSPAR convention: Ireland v United Kingdom final award. International Legal
Materials, 42, 1137–1138.
Peters, A. (2013). Realizing Utopia as a scholarly endeavour. European Journal of International
Law, 24(2), 533–552. https://doi.org/10.1093/ejil/cht022
Peters, A. (2017). The refinement of international law: From fragmentation to regime interaction
and politicization. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 15(3), 671–704. https://doi.org/
10.1093/icon/mox056
Popovski, V. (2012). Legality and legitimacy of international criminal tribunals, edited by R. Falk,
M. Juergensmeyer, & V. Popovski (Eds.), Legality and legitimacy in global affairs (online edn,
388–413). Oxford Academic.
Rachovitsa, A. (2017). The principle of systemic integration in human rights law. International and
Comparative Law Quarterly, 66(3), 557–588. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020589317000185
Rekrut, I. (2024). Environmental damage is a war crime: Analyzing the legal implications of the
Russian armed invasion’s environmental impact on Ukraine. The Journal of Criminal Law
and Criminology Online, 114(1), 30.
Robinson, D. (2008). The identity crisis of international criminal Law. Leiden Journal of
International Law, 21(4), 925–963. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0922156508005463
Robinson, D. (2022). Ecocide – puzzles and possibilities. Journal of International Criminal Justice,
20(2), 313–347. https://doi.org/10.1093/jicj/mqac021
Ruhl, J. B. (1997). Thinking of environmental Law as a complex adaptive system: How to clean Up
the environment by making a mess of environmental law. Houston Law Review, 34, 947.
Sander, B. (2015). International criminal justice as progress: From faith to critique. In M. Bergsmo
et al. (Ed.), (p. 784).
Schabas, W. A. (2003). Interpreting the statutes of the ad hoc tribunals. In L. C. Vohrah, et al. (Ed.),
Man’s inhumanity to man: Essays on international Law in honour of Antonio Cassese (p. 847).
Kluwer Law International.
Schabas, W. (2011). An introduction to the international criminal court (4th ed.). Cambridge
University Press.
THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS 37
Schabas, W. (2016). The international criminal court: A commentary on the Rome statute (2nd ed.).
OUP.
Scharf, M. P. (2022). Hugo grotius and the concept of grotian moments in international law. Case
Western Reserve. Journal of International Law, 54:1, 17.
Shahabuddeen, M. (2004). Does the principle of legality stand in the way of progressive develop
ment of Law? Journal of International Criminal Justice, 2(4), 1007–1017. https://doi.org/10.
1093/jicj/2.4.1007
Shany, Y. (2014). Assessing the effectiveness of international courts. Oxford University Press.
Shelton, D. (2003). International Law and ‘Relative Normativity’. In M. Evans (Ed.), International
Law (pp. 148–149). Oxford University Press.
Simpson, G. (1997). War crimes: A critical introduction. In T. L. H. MacCormack & G. J. Simpson
(Eds.), The law of war crimes: National and international approaches (pp. 1–30). The Hague.
Stahn, C. (2019). Justifying international criminal justice: Towards a relational approach.
Stahn, C., & van den Herik, L. (2012). Fragmentation, diversification and “3D” legal pluralism:
International criminal law as the jack- in- the- box? In L. van den Herik & C. Stahn (Eds.),
The diversification and fragmentation of international criminal Law (p. 21). Martinus Nijhoff.
Stevenson, H. (2013). Institutionalizing unsustainability: The paradox of global climate governance.
University of California Press.
Torbisco-Casals, N. (2021). The legitimacy of international courts: The challenge of diversity.
Journal of Social Philosophy, 52(4), 491–515. https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12452
Urs, P. (2024). Gravity at the international criminal court admissibility and prosecutorial discretion.
Oxford University Press.
Van Schaak, B. (2008). Crimen sine lege: Judicial lawmaking at the intersection of law and morals.
Georgetown Law Journal, 97, 119–192.
van Steenberghe, R. (2022). The interplay between international humanitarian law and inter
national environmental Law: Towards a comprehensive framework for a better protection of
the environment in armed conflict. Journal of International Criminal Justice, 20(5), 1123–
1154. https://doi.org/10.1093/jicj/mqac062
Verschuuren, J. (2017). The role of sustainable development and the associated principles of
environmental law and governance in the anthropocene. In L. J. Kotzé (Ed.), Environmental
Law and governance for the anthropocene (p. 19). Hart Publishing.
von der Dunk, F. G. (2021). Armed conflicts in outer space: Which law applies? International Law
Studies, 97, 190–191.
von Hebel, H., & Robinson, D. (1999). Crimes within the jurisdiction of the court. In R. S. Lee
(Ed.), The international criminal court: The making of the Rome statute (p. 122). Brill.
Vreeland, H., Jr. (1917). Hugo Grotius: The father of the modern science of international Law.
Oxford University Press.
Webb, P. (2013). International judicial integration and fragmentation. Oxford University Press.