Enredos Racionales
Enredos Racionales
net/publication/222476293
Rational Tangles
CITATIONS READS
70 567
2 authors, including:
Louis Kauffman
University of Illinois Chicago
684 PUBLICATIONS 14,281 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Louis Kauffman on 09 January 2019.
Rational Tangles
Jay R. Goldman
and
Louis H. Kauffman
Department of Mathematics, Uni¨ ersity of Illinois at Chicago, 851 South Morgan Street,
Chicago, Illinois 60607-7045
1. INTRODUCTION
The key concept for this section is the notion of a tangle. A tangle is
analogous to a link except that it has free ends. These ends are depicted as
strands that enter a box Žthe tangle box. within which there are no free
ends. Inside the box one may find closed loops that are knotted and linked
with the tangle strands. The strands of the tangle may themselves be
knotted and linked. Note that if you begin at one of the free ends
emanating from the tangle box and walk along it, you will enter the box,
and eventually leave the box to meet another end of strand. Thus a tangle
box must have an even number of ends. We will be concerned in this
section with tangles with four ends. Such tangles have two strands, each
302 GOLDMAN AND KAUFFMAN
FIGURE 2.1
FIG. 2.2. Twining diagonally opposite strands via twists of adjacent strands.
Ž2. For k - n.
Ži. if Ta s t a , let Bkq1 s t a q Bk or Bk q t a ,
kq 1 kq 1 kq 1 kq 1
FIGURE 2.3
FIGURE 2.4
Note. This theorem is, in general, not true for nonrational tangles. For
example, consider the tangle illustrated in Figure 2.6.1. It is not rational.
One strand has a knot in it and this strand is linked with the other strand.
This tangle is not equivalent to the tangle obtained by performing a
vertical flip because there is no way to deform the knot on one strand to
the other one, since the endpoints are fixed.
FIGURE 2.5
FIGURE 2.6
RATIONAL TANGLES 309
FIGURE 2.6.1
FIGURE 2.7
310 GOLDMAN AND KAUFFMAN
FIGURE 2.8
RATIONAL TANGLES 311
FIGURE 2.9
The reason for taking mirror images in the definition of inverses will
become clear when we discuss numerical invariants.
THEOREM 3. The c-in¨ erse and cc-in¨ erse of a rational tangle are ambient
isotopic.
Proof. We apply the flip theorem twice Ža vertical followed by a
horizontal flip as shown in Fig. 2.9.
Thus if a subtangle of a tangle is of the form 1r c b, b rational, we can
always replace it by 1rcc b and, conversely, we can replace 1rcc b by 1rc b.
We will often write 1rb if the type of the inverse does not matter.
We need a few more properties of our operations in order to describe
basic tangles algebraically.
PROPOSITION 4. Ž1. If b is a basic horizontal tangle, then 1r c b is a basic
¨ ertical tangle.
Ž2. If b is a basic ¨ ertical tangle, then 1rcc b is a basic horizontal tangle.
Ž3. tXa s 1rc t a s 1rcc t a and t a s 1rc tXa s 1rcc tXa .
Ž4. t d q tXe s t d q 1rt e .
1
Ž5. t d q9tXe s cc.
1
te q c
td
Ž6. yŽ b q c . s Žyb . q Žyc ., yŽ1rb . s 1rŽyb ., yt a s tya , and
ytXa s tya
X
.
Proof. The results follow easily from the definitions Žwe leave it to the
reader to draw these pictures..
Now we can build our basic tangles using the tangle operations q, y,
r c , rcc . For example, consider the basic tangles of Fig. 2.8. The construc-
tion of the first tangle is given by
t 3 ª t 3 q 9t 2 ª Ž t 3 q 9tX2 . q ty2
RATIONAL TANGLES 313
or
1 1
t3 ª cc ª cc q ty2
1 1
t2 q c t2 q c
t3 t3
1
; ty2 q cc
1
t2 q c
t3
or
1 1 1
ª t2 q ª cc
t3 t3 1
ty2 q c
1
t2 q
t3
In fact, we could take Ž1. and Ž2. as the definition of a basic tangle.
314 GOLDMAN AND KAUFFMAN
These forms for basic tangles suggest associating to the basic tangles Ž1.
and Ž2. the arithmetic continued fractions
1 1
an q and . Ž 3.
1 1
a ny 1 q . an q
.. 1
a ny 1 q .
1 ..
q
a1 1
q
a1
F Ž ytXa . s F Ž tya
X
. s F Ž 1rtya . s y1ra s yF Ž 1rt a . s yF Ž tXa . .
Ž4. F Žyb . s yF Ž b ..
Proof. Only Ž4. is not immediate from the definitions and Proposi-
tion 4. A formal proof of Ž4. requires induction, but we shall just illustrate
the reasoning with an example. Let
1
b s t3 q .
1
t4 q
ty5
Then, by Proposition 4,
1
yb s yt 3 y
1
t4 q
ty5
1
s yt 3 q
1
yt4 y
ty5
RATIONAL TANGLES 315
1
s yt 3 q
1
yt4 q
yty5
1
s yt 3 q .
1
yt4 q
t5
Therefore
1 1
F Ž yb . s y3 q sy 3q s yF Ž b . .
1 1
y4 q 4q
5 y5
We now have the concepts and tools to state and prove John Conway’s
fundamental theorem.
CONWAY’S THEOREM. Let T1 and T2 be basic tangles. If F ŽT1 . s F ŽT2 .,
then T1 is ambient isotopic to T2 .
Remarks. The converse is in fact true, namely, if T1 is ambient isotopic
to T2 , then F ŽT1 . s F ŽT2 .. Later we will give a different interpretation of
the fraction of a tangle, which allows us to prove this. Thus the fraction is
a complete invariant for the equivalent of basic tangles. Moreover, since
any rational tangle is ambient isotopic to a basic tangle Žby an algorithm.,
we have an algorithmic procedure for deciding the equivalence of any two
rational tangles.
Proof. Given a basic tangle T in the continued fraction form of Eq. Ž1.
with fraction prq, we will show that it is ambient isotopic to a basic tangle
T with fraction prq, whose continued fraction Ž3. satisfies a i ) 0 for
i s 1, . . . , n y 1. Such a continued fraction is called regular. Since the
regular continued fraction of prq is unique Žup to the last term which can
be written as a n y 1 q 1r1}see w5x., this means that any tangle with
fraction prq is ambient isotopic to T 9 and we will be finished.
We begin arithmetically with the continued fraction Ž3. of the fraction
F ŽT . and show how to convert it into the regular continued fraction with
the same sum. The key step is the following formula of Lagrange ŽSee
Lagrange’s Appendix to Euler’s Algebra w5x.,
1 1
ay s Ž a y 1. q , Ž 4.
b 1
1q
Ž b y 1.
which is trivial to verify.
316 GOLDMAN AND KAUFFMAN
43 1 1
s1q s1y Ž 5.
62 1 1
y3 q 3q
1 1
y4 q 4y
5 5
and move all negative signs to the numerator as shown. We find the last
appearance of a negative sign reading down the fraction Žin this case
y1r5. and apply Eq. Ž4. to 4 y 1r5 Ž a s 4, b s 5 y 1r5.. Then
1 1
4y s3q ,
5 1
1q
4
43 1
s1y , Ž 6.
62 1
3q
1
3q
1
1q
4
a continued fraction for 43r62 with one less negative sign. Now find the
last negative sign in Ž6., which is the only one, and apply Eq. Ž4. to Ž6. with
a s 1 and
1
bs3q ,
1
3q
1
1q
4
which gives
43 1 1 1
say s0q s ,
62 b 1 1
1q 1q
1 1
2q 2q
1 1
1q 1q
4 4
RATIONAL TANGLES 317
a continued fraction with all terms positive. This procedure, namely using
Lagrange’s formula to reduce the number of negative signs one step at a
time, works in general yielding a continued fraction in which a negative
sign can only appear in front of the first term.
Now we mirror this procedure topologically. Let the numbers a and b
represent rational tangles with fractions a and b respectively. Then
Fig. 2.10 shows the construction of a rational tangle with fraction 1rŽ1 q
1rŽ b y 1.., which corresponds to part of the right-hand side of Ž4..
FIGURE 2.10
318 GOLDMAN AND KAUFFMAN
In Fig. 2.11, we use the rational tangle from Fig. 2.10 to form a rational
tangle corresponding to Ž a y 1. q 1rŽ1 q 1rŽ b y 1.. and then topologi-
cally deform this tangle until it is the rational tangle for the fraction
a q 1rŽyb .. Thus we have the topological version of Lagrange’s formula.
Now we are essentially done. We start with a basic tangle T in the
continued fraction form of Eq. Ž1. with fraction prq given by the contin-
ued fraction Ž3.. We have shown how to convert the continued fraction
into a regular one, which is essentially unique. Then we showed how to
convert the original tangle to an ambient isotopic tangle corresponding to
the regular continued fraction for prq. Hence given any two tangles T1
and T2 with the same fraction prq, they are ambient isotopic to the same
tangle T 9 which corresponds to the unique regular continued fraction for
prq. Therefore T1 and T2 are ambient isotopic. Moreover, our proof
actually gives an algorithm for converting T1 to T2 .
Note that the basic tangles associated to regular continued fractions are
alternating, i.e., as we walk along a strand, the crossings alternate between
under and over crossings. So we have proved that any basic tangle is
ambient isotopic to an alternating tangle.
FIGURE 2.11
RATIONAL TANGLES 319
We have seen how to define the fraction of a rational tangle and that
tangles with the same fraction are ambient isotopic. In this section we shall
prove the converse}that if two tangles are ambient isotopic, then they
have the same fraction. This will complete our goal of showing that the
fraction of a rational tangle completely classifies its topological type.
In order to show that ambient isotopic tangles have the same fraction,
we shall build an in¨ ariant, C ŽT ., for arbitrary tangles T and then show
1. If T is ambient isotopic to S, then C ŽT . s C Ž S ..
2. If T is rational, then C ŽT . s F ŽT ., the fraction of T.
This is a case where it is actually easier to solve a more general problem
Žof finding an invariant for arbitrary tangles rather than just for rational
tangles..
We shall call the invariant C ŽT . the conductance of T, because it is the
Žgeneralized. conductance of a Žgeneralized. electrical network associated
with T. The full theory of C ŽT . is explained in our paper w7x, but here we
shall give a different and elementary development of C ŽT . that is based on
the bracket polynomial. In order to do this we will first give a quick
introduction to the bracket. Readers interested in more information on the
bracket polynomial should consult w8, 9, or 11x. The relationship between
the bracket ŽJones polynomial. and the conductance invariant is explained
in w7x.
The Bracket
The bracket invariant ² K : is defined on all knots and links K Žnot yet
on tangles. by the formulas:
Ž1.
Ž2. ² OK : s d ² K :,
² O : s 1,
320 GOLDMAN AND KAUFFMAN
Exercises in Bracketology
The following exercises provide a self-contained introduction to various
basic notions and to the bracket polynomial. Some of these results will be
used later.
FIGURE 3.2
322 GOLDMAN AND KAUFFMAN
It follows from this formula that if we take B s Ay1 and d s yA2 y Ay2 ,
then
With this specialization of the variables, the bracket is invariant under the
second Reidemeister move.
3. Show that with B s Ay1 and d s yA2 y Ay2 , the invariance of the
bracket under the second Reidemeister move implies its invariance under
the third Reidemeister move.
4. Show that ² K : changes under the first Reidemeister move via the
formulas
RATIONAL TANGLES 323
Note that in working with the bracket calculations we are not allowed to
perform type I moves on the diagrams without applying these compensat-
ing formulas.
5. Show that if K * is the mirror image of K, obtained by switching all
the crossings in the diagram for K, then ² K *:Ž A. s ² K :Ž Ay1 . where we
now use the bracket with B s Ay1 and d s yA2 y A2 . Compute the
bracket polynomial in A and Ay1 for the trefoil diagram in Fig. 3.3.
6. Let K be an oriented link diagram and define the writhe of K, w Ž K .,
by the formula w Ž K . s the sum of q1 or y1 for each crossing in K
where the q1 or y1 is the sign of the crossing.
The sign of a crossing is obtained as shown in Fig. 3.4.
Now define the normalized bracket, f K Ž A., by the formula f K Ž A. s
ŽyA3 .yw Ž K . ² K : where we take K to be oriented but forget the orienta-
tion when we compute the bracket. Show that f K Ž A. is an invariant of all
three Reidemeister moves. Show that f K * Ž A. s f K Ž Ay1 .. Use these facts
and your calculation of the trefoil diagram Žfrom Problem 4. to prove that
the trefoil knot is chiral Ži.e., inequivalent to its mirror image..
FIGURE 3.3
324 GOLDMAN AND KAUFFMAN
FIGURE 3.4
FIGURE 3.5
RATIONAL TANGLES 325
only isotopies within the tangle box are allowed. By the properties of the
bracket expansion, a ŽT . and b ŽT . are each invariant under Reidemeister
II and Reidemeister III moves of the tangle. We know that the bracket
behaves under a type-I move by multiplying by either yA3 or by yAy3 . It
is easy to see that both a ŽT . and b ŽT . are multiplied by the same factor
under a type-one move applied to the tangle. Hence the ratio R T Ž A. s
a ŽT .rb ŽT . is unchanged under the first Reidemeister move. Therefore
the ratio R T Ž A. is an invariant of the tangle T. Note that RŽT . may take
the value ‘‘infinity’’ under the circumstance that b ŽT . is zero when a ŽT .
is nonzero. This completes the proof of the theorem.
Specializing the A
Now let A s 'i Ž i 2 s y1.; hence B s 1r 'i and d s yA2 y Ay2 s
yi y 1ri s yi q i s 0. Thus the loop value is 0 for this bracket. From
now on ²T : denotes this specialization of the bracket. Let
C Ž T . s yiR T Ž 'i . .
We are now going to see that C ŽT . has just the properties that we need to
show that C ŽT . s F ŽT . for rational tangles.
It is easy to see that C Ž1rT . s Ž1rC ŽT ..*, where * denotes complex
conjugation, for
²T : s a Ž T . ² w ` x : q b Ž T . ² w 0 x :
« ²1rT : s a Ž T . *² w 0 x : q b Ž T . *² w ` x : ,
since
1r w 0 x s w ` x as tangles and Ž 1r'i . * s 'i .
Thus C Ž1rT . s b ŽT .*ri a ŽT .* s i*b ŽT .*ra ŽT .* s Ž1rC ŽT ..*.
Note that when C ŽT . is real, then C Ž1rT . s 1rC ŽT . since a real
number is conjugate to itself. We shall see shortly that the values of C ŽT .
on rational tangles are rational numbers and hence real.
Thus for rational tangles, C Ž1rT . s 1rC ŽT ..
EXAMPLE.
Hence C Žw1x. s Ž1ri .Ž'i rŽ1r 'i .. s Ž1ri .Ž ir1. s 1. In exactly the same
way, we find that C Žwy1x. s y1. Note that C Žw`x. s 0 and cŽw0x. s `,
with the convention that formally 1r0 s `.
We now see that C ŽT q S . s C ŽT . q C Ž S ..
PROPOSITION 3.2. If ²T : s a²w`x: q b ²w0x: and ² S : s c²w`x: q d²w0x:
then ²T q S : s Ž ad q bc .²w`x: q bd²w0x:. Hence C ŽT q S . s C ŽT . q
C Ž S . follows from the fact that Ž ad q bc .rbd s arb q crd.
Proof. In this proof we shall proceed by a picture-writing technique
ŽFig. 3.6.: the boxes stand for the tangles in question. We first expand on
the tangle T, replacing it by the sum of two tangles with coefficients that
corresponds to its bracket expansion. We then expand each of these
pictures on the tangle S to get the full sum that is evaluated. Thus
²T q S : s Ž ad q bc .²w`x: q bd²w0x:, completing the proof of the theo-
rem.
FIGURE 3.6
RATIONAL TANGLES 327
Our mission is complete. We have proved that the rational tangles are
classified by their fractions.
are two possibilities for such a crossing. We have called these possibilities
R and L. In Fig. 4.2 we have illustrated the concept of a site specific
recombination by drawing the DNA schematically in a single closed loop
with local arrows at these sites. In order for the recombination to occur,
the DNA must twist about to bring these two sites into proximity with the
orientations lined up.
Num Ž w 1rn x q S q S . ,
Num Ž w 1rn x q S q S q S . ,
??? .
sum of tangles is the sum of the fractions of the summands. we have the
equations
x q y s y2r3
x q 2 y s y5r3.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
It gives Lou Kauffman great pleasure to thank John Conway for numerous conversations
about tangles and square dancing and David Krebes for insightful remarks on tangles and the
bracket. We both thank DeWitt Sumners for his enthusiasm for the topology of DNA and
Steve Bleiler for helpful conversations.
REFERENCES