Aristotle Poetics
Aristotle Poetics
itself and ventured into the areas of storytelling and drama in its elevated tones. Written in the 4th
century BCE, it condenses the tragic elements and is an influence that makes its way into many other
forms of literature across all kinds of mediums.
Over the years the Poetics has been both praised and disparaged. Some critics object to Aristotle's
theory of poetics and regret that the work has held such sway in the history of Western literature.
One contemporary critic argues that Aristotle "reduces drama to its language," and the "language
itself to its least poetic element, the story, and then encourages insensitive readers...to subject
stories to crudely moralistic readings that reduce tragedies to the childish proportions of Aesop-
fables" (Sachs 1). Other critics have argued against such views and reclaimed the Poetics for their
own times; often these critics emphasize the importance of reading the Poetics in its historical
context - it was, after all, written an awfully long time ago - and stress that despite this historical
barrier the insights contained in the work still hold true. In appreciating what The Poetics means, an
individual must first understand the major concepts defining Poetics and then apply them to major
narratives, classical and contemporary.
The Poetics is Aristotle's attempt to explain the basic problems of art. He both defines art and offers
criteria for determining the quality of a given artwork. The Poetics stands in opposition to the theory
of art propounded by Aristotle's teacher, Plato. In his Republic, Plato argues that "poetry is a
representation of mere appearances and is thus misleading and morally suspect" (Critical, 1). In the
poetics, Aristotle, Plato's student, attempts to refute his teacher by exploring what unites all poetry:
its imitative nature and its ability to bring an audience into its specific plot while preserving a unity of
purpose and theme. The tone of the Poetics reflects its argumentative spirit as Aristotle attempts
both to explain the "anatomy" of poetry and to justify its value to human society.
Despite its broad goals, however, Aristotle's arguments are quite concrete. He is less interested in the
abstract "existence" of art than he is in looking at specific artworks by specific playwrights. Aristotle
wants to explain why effective poetry has stayed with audiences for so long. He tends to look for
"empirical evidence" - i.e. sensory proof through past observation - that art is both good and useful,
no matter how philosophers like Plato try to dismiss it.
In his Poetics, Aristotle opens with an exploration into the nature of mimesis, or imitation, which
according to him is the basis of all arts. In Aristotle's view, “art is an imitation of life”, and thus such
an experience is purging of emotions. Humans are, by nature, prone to imitation; and it is in this
process that man has learnt and delights. For Aristotle, this imitation in literature implies imitation of
human actions which will necessarily have coherence and unity. He further outlines different modes
of imitation in different genres, saying each of the epic, the tragedy, and the comedy employs a
different medium, object, and manner of imitation. Tragedy acquires, for Aristotle, the highest rank
in literary art, for it stirs in man the passions, and delivers moral knowledge. For instance: in Hamlet,
the play-within-a-play functions as a reflection of the plot in the center, amplifying the themes of
vengeance and guilt, while allowing the audience to envelop themself in some sort of self-reflection.
The definition of tragedy in Poetics occupies one of the lasting legacies of Aristotle. He defines
tragedy as “an imitation of an action that is serious, complete, and of a certain magnitude; in
language embellished with each kind of artistic ornament... in the form of action, not narrative;
with incidents arousing pity and fear, wherewith to accomplish its catharsis of such emotions.”
This definition highlights several key components of tragedy, such as seriousness, completeness, and
catharsis, which have shaped most subsequent views on dramatic or narrative art.
Aristotle identifies six elements of tragedy: plot, character, thought, diction, spectacle and song. It is
the plot that, according to him, takes precedence over all of them, serving as “the soul of a tragedy”.
The well-structured plot sets forth “a clear beginning, middle, and end”, which serves coherence
and unity within the whole while being centered around one action as is in Homer’s Iliad and
Odyssey. Within this regard, Aristotle himself spoke primarily concerning the unity of action but
critics later added to the argument that it must be time and place and that a play might represent
events occurring within the same day and in a single setting. These unities have not at all times been
observed; but they have led the great tradition of dramatic structure as observed in Jean Racine's
Phèdre. Plot also must contain elements of astonishment, reversal (peripeteia), recognition, and
suffering as is observed in Sophocles’ Oedipus Rex. In Oedipus Rex, the complication sees us all the
way through Oedipus discovering his own crimes - and from there, the denouement takes us through
his self-mutilation and redemption. Often, then, the climax takes place at the moment of key reversal
or recognition in a tragedy. The audience is gripped by the protagonist’s relentless pursuit of truth
and his ultimate realization of his own tragic flaws. The unfolding events evoke both pity for Oedipus’
plight and fear of the inexorable power of fate, culminating in a profound emotional release for the
audience
Character, the second-most important of all. Aristotle observes a difference between the protagonist
and the other characters, for the protagonists should be complex and relatable. They should show
virtues and flaws simultaneously so that pity and fear may be aroused in the audience as the drama
comes to a close. When it comes to character, Aristotle states a poet should aim for four things- “The
character will be good if the purpose is good… the second thing to aim at is propriety [manly
valor]... Thirdly, character must be true to life… the fourth point is consistency.” It is significant to
note Aristotle's delineation of the tragic hero's character. The tragic hero is not an eminently 'good'
man, or model of virtue swiftly brought down by adversity. In that, says Aristotle, there is only shock
- since we can see none of ourselves in a perfectly virtuous man, and find it arbitrary that he would
be selected for cosmic punishment. What is far more effective is if the hero possesses some 'frailty',
or flaw (like Achilles' heel), which he compensates for, hides, runs away from - but eventually catches
up with him. An 'error' of character should not be confused with an error in a character's 'action' - a
tragedy must spin on a fundamental flaw in the hero's behaviour and one that the audience can
identify with or substitute in themselves. Only through the tragic climax can he - and the audience -
find redemption. Shakespeare’s Macbeth and Othello fit the Aristotelian description of a tragic hero
whose flaws, Macbeth’s pride and Othello’s jealousy and insecurity, brings the audience to sympathy
and reflection. The audience’s pity for the tragic hero arises from his initial nobility and the
preventable nature of his downfall, while their fear stems from the recognition of how easily such a
flaw can lead to catastrophe.
Beyond plot and character, Aristotle discusses diction, thought, spectacle, and song in the framework
of tragedy. Diction pertains to the playwright’s choice of language and style while thought reflects
the themes and messages conveyed by the tragedy. For instance, the poetic language in Euripedes’
Medea not only enhances the dramatic intensity of revenge but also stresses upon the themes
explored in the play concerning betrayal and justice. Though spectacle and song are considered less
important compared to plot and character, they still contribute to the overall emotional impact of a
tragedy.
Furthermore, it is the relationship between form and content that encouraged literary critics and
theorists to examine the structural aspects of storytelling. His emphasis on the primacy of plot is
echoed in structuralist approaches to narrative, while his concern with emotional engagement
resonates with reader-response theory. The analytical tools proposed by Aristotle are still relevant
for interpreting literature, drama, and even video games, where narrative immersion and emotional
resonance play key roles in framing the experience.
Nevertheless, Poetics has suffered its share of critics despite its past and continuing significance.
Critics argue that to focus on plot and not character as Aristotle has done was to ignore the
complexities of human psychology and relationships, which many modern works have taken into
consideration. Others challenge the universality of his principles by mentioning that non-Western
literary traditions do not conform to Aristotelian models.Classical Indian dramaturgy, for example, as
found in Bharata's Natyashastra, has set different emotional experiences, or rasas, as priorities,
instead of catharsis. However, the very flexibility inherent in Aristotle's idea permits such adaptation
and reinterpretation. For example, the Natyashastra differs in its theoretical approach from the
Poetics, but shares its interest in the emotional reception of the performance by the audience.
Likewise, works of modernist and postmodernist literature tend to defy the traditional concepts of
plot unity but such works still actively contend with Aristotelian principles by either subverting or
probing the limits of the same.
(Aristotle concludes the Poetics by addressing two main criticisms that often-plagued poetry in his
time. First, there is the question of what makes for 'good' poetry or 'bad' poetry. Aristotle points out
that every work of art can be distilled to its 'essence,' meaning its purpose of imitation. Either a work
aims to reveal life exactly as it is, as people think it is, or as it ought to be. Thus, depending on which
of these three imitative purposes a poet has, his work should be considered under a separate set of
criteria. For instance, a poet who aims to show life as it 'ought to be' certainly has more relaxed
standards for the accuracy of representation than a poet who is portraying life as it is. Aristotle uses
the example of a poet who might not know that a hind does not have horns -- in the case of a poet
trying to portray life realistically, this error would ultimately be more glaring that in the case of a poet
presenting an accurate view of life, simply because his purpose leads the reader to expect
verisimilitude of detail. That said, what is also significant for the reader to understand that in neither
case does an error of detail necessarily affect the quality of the poem - unless it perverts the essence
of the piece. Only if the author makes a fundamental error in the type of imitation he is pursuing is
the final work ultimately compromised.
Aristotle ends by addressing what appears to be a long-standing debate between critics over the
primacy of tragedy or epic poetry. Critics in his time vaunted epic poetry, but Aristotle takes the
opposite view, noting that tragedy has all the same good qualities of an epic in its reading, but also
has the added dimension of being able to translate onstage into a drama of spectacle and music,
capable of being digested in one sitting.
Just as he began without much of an introduction, so too Aristotle finishes the Poetics with a
perfunctory conclusion - no summary or final thought or discussion of significance. He wraps up his
argument swiftly, content that he has addressed all the points laid out at the beginning, and
confident that he has quashed his critics' preconceptions about the poetic art form.)
Indeed, Aristotle's Poetics is the keystone of literary theory, and it is one of the foundational texts for
comprehending the principles of tragedy and narrative art. It has had its effect on the ancient
dramatists, Renaissance playwrights, and present-day storytellers. By examining the elements that
make a narrative compelling and meaningful, Aristotle provides timeless insights into the human
condition and the enduring power of storytelling. From Oedipus Rex to Macbeth to contemporary
drama, the principles set forth in Poetics still inform our understanding of art, emotion, and the
diverse feedback of human experience.
Poetics
Aristotle's Poetics is one of the earliest texts that laid down the precepts for later literary theories
itself and ventured into the areas of storytelling and drama in its elevated tones. Written in the 4th
century BCE, it condenses the tragic elements and is an influence that makes its way into many other
forms of literature across all kinds of mediums.
Poetics represents Aristotle's effort to address the fundamental questions of art. It both defines art
and sets criteria for assessing its quality. While in his Republic, Plato argues that "poetry is a
representation of mere appearances and is thus misleading and morally suspect" (Critical, 1),
Aristotle defends its value, emphasizing its imitative nature (mimesis) and its ability to engage
audiences in meaningful experiences. Poetics dissects poetry in order to justify its existence in
society. His analysis enriches our experience of the performance, enabling us to grasp its principles of
construction and the emotions it stirs in us. One contemporary critic argues that Aristotle "reduces
drama to its language," and the "language itself to its least poetic element, the story, and then
encourages insensitive readers...to subject stories to crudely moralistic readings that reduce
tragedies to the childish proportions of Aesop-fables" (Sachs 1).
While his approach does bring criticism of being too reductive by reducing drama to its language and
sometimes favoring oversimplified readings, Aristotle's argument is pretty much founded on
observation and, thus, on practical relevance. He is less interested in the abstract "existence" of art
than he is in looking at specific artworks by specific playwrights. Aristotle explains why effective
poetry has stayed with audiences for so long by looking at "empirical evidence". Thus, he counters
Plato's skeptic attitude toward poetry.
The core of Poetics is found in the concept of mimesis or imitation, which Aristotle identifies as the
basic framework for all arts. "Art is an imitation of life," and thus this imitation produces the purging
of emotions, or catharsis, for Aristotle. Humans are naturally inclined toward imitation, and through
it, they find learning and pleasure. Imitation, in literature, means representing human actions with
coherence and unity. Aristotle classifies different genres—epic, tragedy, and comedy—based on
their modes of imitation. Among these, he assigns the highest rank to tragedy for its power to stir
emotions and impart moral understanding. Shakespeare’s Hamlet exemplifies this through the play-
within-a-play, which reflects the central themes of guilt and revenge, encouraging self-reflection in
the audience.
Aristotle identifies six elements of tragedy: plot, character, thought, diction, spectacle, and song,
with plot being the paramount. Described as the "soul of a tragedy," the plot must have “a clear
beginning, middle, and end”, ensuring unity and coherence. Aristotle’s emphasis on the “unity of
action” further enhances the audience’s enjoyment of a well-constructed play. By focusing on a
single, coherent narrative, the playwright ensures that all events contribute to the main storyline.
This unity prevents distractions and maintains the audience’s engagement. This principle is evident in
Homer’s Odyssey and Iliad, where the stories revolve around a central action. Later critics expanded
this to include the unities of time and place, as observed in Racine’s Phèdre, where events unfold
within a single day and setting.
Aristotle also highlights the importance of plot elements such as reversal (peripeteia), recognition
(anagnorisis), and suffering. In Oedipus Rex, these elements converge powerfully: Oedipus’
discovery of his crimes marks a dramatic reversal, leading to his tragic downfall and redemption. The
audience experiences pity for Oedipus and fear of the inexorable power of fate, culminating in an
emotional catharsis.
Character, the second-most important element, must complement the plot. Aristotle stresses that
protagonists should be relatable, with both virtues and flaws. This complexity elicits pity and fear,
crucial for catharsis. He outlines four qualities for characters: “The character will be good if the
purpose is good… the second thing to aim at is propriety [manly valor]... Thirdly, character must be
true to life… the fourth point is consistency.” Aristotle says that a tragic hero is one who is neither a
complete villain nor he is all good. Their fall is a result of some tragic flaw-affecting with hamartia-so
that their fate becomes inevitable as well as relatable. Shakespeare’s Macbeth and Othello embody
this ideal. Macbeth’s ambition and Othello’s jealousy lead to their respective downfalls, evoking
sympathy for their initial nobility and fear of their fatal flaws.
Beyond plot and character, Aristotle examines thought, diction, spectacle, and song. Thought
reflects the themes and ideas conveyed in a tragedy, while diction pertains to the playwright's choice
of language and style. For example, Euripides’ Medea employs poetic language to heighten the
drama and stress the themes of betrayal and justice. Spectacle and song, though less important than
plot and character, enhance the emotional experience. The dramatic staging and music in operas like
Les Misérables amplify the narrative’s impact, demonstrating Aristotle's principles in action.
Poetics has influenced wider literary theory beyond its own bounds. Its emphasis on plot structure is
paralleled in contemporary narrative frameworks (such as the three-act structure used in
screenwriting). Aristotle’s focus on emotional engagement aligns with reader-response theories,
where audience perception shapes the narrative’s impact.
Despite its lasting significance, Poetics has faced criticism. Some argue that Aristotle’s prioritization
of plot over character overlooks the complexities of human psychology and relationships, which
many modern works explore in depth. Others challenge the universality of his principles, noting that
non-Western literary traditions do not conform to Aristotelian models. For instance, India’s
Natyashastra emphasizes emotional experiences (rasas) over catharsis. Nevertheless, Aristotle’s
framework is adaptable, allowing reinterpretation across cultures and genres. Even works that defy
traditional narrative structures, such as modernist and postmodernist literature, engage with
Aristotelian ideas by either subverting or reimagining them.
Aristotle concludes the Poetics by refuting two important criticisms of his times: the criteria for
"good" poetry and the relative merits of tragedy against epic poetry. He regarded imitating life as it
is, or as people think it is, or as it should be, as the aim of poetry. Regarding tragedy and epic poetry,
Aristotle contends that tragedy surpasses the epic by combining the same narrative depth with the
added dimensions of performance and music, making it more immediate and engaging.
Indeed, Aristotle’s Poetics remains a cornerstone of literary theory, shaping our understanding of
tragedy, narrative structure, and the emotional power of storytelling. Its principles have influenced
generations of writers, from ancient dramatists like Sophocles to Renaissance playwrights like
Shakespeare and contemporary creators in literature and film. By analyzing the elements that make
narratives compelling, Aristotle provides timeless insights into the human condition and the enduring
appeal of storytelling. Through his analysis, we gain a greater understanding of why certain plays
resonate with audiences, making them enduring sources of enjoyment and reflection. From Oedipus
Rex to Macbeth to modern dramas, Poetics continues to illuminate the art of narrative and its
profound impact on audiences.