W2-OBrien-Shared Meaningedited
W2-OBrien-Shared Meaningedited
Basis of Humanness
Imagine that you have just been kicked in the knee. How do you
respond? Your immediate physical response is probably an upward
jerk of the leg. Perhaps a rush of air and a surprised gasp escapes
your lips. In a behaviorist's terms, the blow to the knee is considered
the stimulus and your direct, physical response is your jerking leg
and cry of pain. This physical response to the stimulus of being
kicked is the same for most humans.
In addition to this physiological response, you are likely to have
additional reactions that are not as predictable. How do you respond
to the person who kicked you? You may kick the person in return.
You may apologize for being in the way. You may flee. Your response
to the person who kicked you depends on how you interpret the inci
dent. Do you perceive it to be an act of aggression, an accident, a
playful joke? Your interpretation of the incident is in tum based on
the situation and the cues you pick up from the person who kicked
you. If you are in a crowded space and the kicker smiles apologeti
cally, you are likely to interpret the act as an accident and to respond
accordingly. If you have been reading quietly in an empty room and
the kicker glares at you menacingly, you are more likely to interpret
the kick as an act of aggression than as an accident.
Symbolic interactionists are interested in the process of assigning
meaning to actions and in the responses that follow. The meaning that
you assign to being kicked determines how you will respond to the
kicker and, in tum, how the kicker will respond to you. That is, how
you perceive the incident will determine how you feel about it and
your subsequent course of action. This perception will also be the
basis for how you store the event in your memory and recall it later.
A jerk of the knee and a cry of pain may be predictable, universal,
physical responses. However, there is nothing inherent in the inter
pretation that can be placed on the event. To symbolic interactionists,
the most interesting aspects of human behavior are those that take
place when we assign meaning to our own actions or interpret the
actions of others. Although it is possible to chart direct stimulus
response patterns in human behavior, symbolic interactionists main
tain that these patterns are of limited interest in understanding hu
man behavior and institutions. Most noteworthy behavior involves a
process of interpretation between stimulus and response. Thus, the
interesting question for the student of human behavior is not what
63
the objective stimulus is (for example, the blow to the knee), but
what meaning the receiver of the kick assigns to the stimulus (that is,
how the blow is perceived). It is the process of assigning meaning
that determines how people feel and act.
Symbolic interactionists claim that symbolic activity mediates
between stimulus and response. In this essay, we explore the impli
cations of being symbol-using creatures who interpret the world. We
also discuss human thought as a process of symbolic gestures
achieved through the acquisition of language. From this perspective,
social behavior is a manifestation of shared patterns of symbolic
meaning.
The philosopher Ernst Cassirer, in Reading 6, "A Clue to the Na
ture of Man," suggests that "physical reality seems to recede in pro
portion as man's symbolic activity advances." By this he means that
symbol-using creatures do not exist in a direct state of nature. To
exist in a state of nature is to be nonconscious, nonreflective, and
nonsymbolic. In such a state the organism is propelled directly by
the forces of nature, which include internal physiology and the exter
nal environment. In contrast, the symbolic creature is able to compre
hend, comment on, and organize behavior in accordance with ab
stract representations that are removed from the state of nature. This
does not imply necessarily that humans are "superior'' to animals,
nor that we do not have an animal form (biologically and physiologi
cally). The point is that most noteworthy human activity is symbolic
(abstracted from a direct state of nature). Thus the symbolic inter
actionist focuses on human behavior and culture primarily as expres
sions of meaningful symbol systems.
A comparison with elephants illustrates this point. W hen el
ephants meet, one places its trunk in the mouth of the other. Body
temperature and fluids in the mouth indicate whether each elephant
is in a state of arousal or aggression or is passive. This encounter
triggers the appropriate response----copulating, fighting, fleeing, or
traveling together. The elephants, as far as we can tell, do not think
about this encounter; they do not interpret the event and assign
meaning to it. They simply engage in a series of stimulus-response
behaviors with each other in a direct state of nature.
The difference between humans and elephants is that humans do
not respond directly to the physical environment. Rather, humans
impose symbolic interpretations on experiences and draw conclu
sions based on these interpretations. It is true that we are attuned to
odors and other physiological manifestations of our fellow humans
and that we may experience these directly rather than through a
process of interpretation. But most of our responses to others are
• Humans act toward a thing on the basis of the meaning they as
sign to the thing.
• Meanings are socially derived, which is to say that meaning is not
inherent in a state of nature. There is no absolute meaning. Mean
ing is negotiated through interaction with others.
• The perception and interpretation of social symbols are modified
by the individual's own thought processes (Blumer, 1969, p. 2).
Ralph is an elephant.
Elephants live in Africa.
Elephants have tusks.
Conclusion
Consider another illustration from Stephen Pinker (1994). The fol
lowing are real headlines he took from various newspapers:
Words are the supreme objects. They are minded things. As pure and
transcendent as any idea that ever cast a shadow into Plato's dark cave of
our perceptions. But they are also pitfalls of deceit and misperception.
Words bend our thinking to infinite paths of self-delusion, and the fact
that we spend most of our mental lives in brain mansions built of words
means that we lack the objectivity necessary to see the terrible distortion
of reality which language brings .... [Yet] here is the essence of [human
kind's] creative genius: not the edifices of civilization nor the bang-flash
weapons which can end it, but the words which fertilize new concepts ....
You see, in the beginning was the Word. And the Word was made flesh in
the weave of the human universe. Words are the only bullets in truth's
bandolier. (Simmons, 1990, pp. 190-191)
References
Barthes, R. (1967 /1964). Elements of semiology. New York: Hill & Wang.
Blumer, H. (1969). Symbolic interactionism. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-
Hall.
Brown, R. (1986). Social psychology (2nd ed.). New York: Free Press.
Charon, J. (1989). Symbolic interactionism (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Chomsky, N. (1972). I.anguage and the mind. New York: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich.
Fine, G. (1990). Symbolic interactionism in the post-Blumerian age. In G.
Ritzer (Ed.), Frontiers of social theory {pp. 117-157). New York: Columbia
University Press.
Lee, D. (Ed.). (1980). Wittgenstein's lectures, Cambridge 1930-1932. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Lindesmith, A. R., Strauss, A. L., & Denzin, N. K. (Eds.). (1988). Social psy
chology {6th ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self and society. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Pinker, S. (1994). The language instinct: How the mind creates language. New
York: Harper Perennial.