Первый Учебник По Математическому Анализу Юктибхаша-s10781-007-9029-1
Первый Учебник По Математическому Анализу Юктибхаша-s10781-007-9029-1
DOI 10.1007/s10781-007-9029-1
P. P. Divakaran
Introduction
In 1832, Charles M. Whish, an Englishman who had worked for the East India
Company, presented to the Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain and Ireland
an account1 of the contents of four palm leaf manuscripts which he had found
in the environs of Cochin (or Kochi as it is now known) in coastal central
Kerala. One of the four is a work in Malayalam, the language of Kerala, on
mathematics and astronomy entitled Yuktibhās: ā (abbreviated to YB from now
on; the others are also mathematical/astronomical texts, by now similarly well-
known, in Sanskrit). Thus was brought to the notice of scholarly Europe,
perhaps for the first time, the text of which I speak here. Whish’s effort seems
to have made no impression on historians of mathematics till the 1940s. But
the decades since then have seen increasing attention being paid2 to the quite
astonishingly sophisticated mathematics produced by the socalled Kerala
1
Charles M. Whish (1835, p. 509).
2
As far as I can tell, Whish’s baton was first picked up by Mukunda Marar and Rajagopal (1944,
p. 65). Of the numerous subsequent publications, two are worthy of special mention: T. A. Sarasvati
Amma’s thesis (later published as a book 1979; second revised edition 1999) and George
Gheverghese Joseph (1992). The first is largely faithful to the methods actually employed by the
Kerala mathematicians. Joseph’s book has brought the story to a large readership. There are a fair
number of good websites that discuss the work of the Kerala school and there are also some which
are not fully reliable.
P. P. Divakaran (&)
Chennai Mathematical Institute, SIPCOT IT Park,
Siruseri 603 103, India
e-mail: [email protected]
123
418 P. P. Divakaran
school in a relatively brief period of 200 years or so, beginning in the second
half of the 14th century CE.
The text of YB that I use here is the one that virtually everyone interested
in the work relies on directly or indirectly, that given in the annotated Mal-
ayalam edition of Rama Varma Tampuran and A. R. Akhilesvara Ayyar,
published in 1948.3 It is based on four separate manuscripts which, according
to the editors, are largely in concordance. Tampuran belonged to a local royal
family and was a well-known scholar of Malayalam (and hence of Sanskrit)
and of the sāstra literature, and Ayyar was a schoolteacher with a master’s
degree in mathematics; in the complementarity of their domains of expertise,
a more ideal pair of collaborators is hard to imagine. The main part of the
book is 290 printed pages long of which roughly half is commentary. The
editing and the commentary are impeccably done, in the best Indian bhās: ya
tradition. Especially noteworthy are the meticulously drawn geometric figures
without which the work of those who followed them would have been made
greatly more arduous.
The edition of Tampuran and Ayyar covers only Part I of YB. Part II
contains applications to astronomy and has so far not been published, in any
language. The late K. V. Sarma, whose efforts more than of anyone else
brought the main texts of Kerala mathematics and astronomy to the attention
of the scholarly world, had completed (in association with M. D. Srinivas,
M. S. Sriram and K. Ramasubramanian) an English translation of both parts
of YB at the time of his death in January 2005, but it is yet to appear. As of
now, a faithful presentation of what YB contains, in any language other than
Malayalam (unfortunately beyond the acquaintance of most interested
scholars) does not exist. This should be a matter of regret because what it does
contain, primarily, is a very thorough account of the techniques of the infin-
itesimal calculus that the Kerala school created and developed for the study of
the geometry of the circle.
The above claim and the title of this article raise the question: what exactly
constitutes the mathematical discipline we call calculus?
The question is no easier to answer today than it has been in the past.
Contemporary mathematics almost unanimously holds the view that the
central concern of calculus is with the properties of ‘functions’. In the early
days of calculus in Europe, these were limited to real functions of a real
variable, explicitly given by formulae, of a small number of types such as
powers of low degree and functions defining the conic sections; e.g., y ¼ x2 ,
y ¼ ð1 x2 Þ1=2 . Over the next two centuries and a half, the concept of a
function was greatly broadened, culminating in a very abstract and general
definition, free of any explicit geometric or numerical connotation, as a ‘map’
from one ‘space’ to another, a ‘black box’ that takes an input from an initial
space and gives an output in a final space. In this generality, functions are not
amenable to the methods of calculus; for that to be possible, there must be a
criterion for deciding when two points are nearby in both the initial and final
3
Rama Varma (Maru) Tampuran and Akhilesvara Ayyar (1948).
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 419
spaces as well as a rule for adding (and subtracting) two nearby points.4 No
further limitations are necessary.
In its early avatars, in India or in Europe, calculus provided a set of con-
ceptual and technical tools, essentially geometric, with which to approach and
find answers to an array of questions regarding simple functions. The
remarkable fact is that these tools, suitably sharpened and broadened, are
recognisably the very same ones as are in use in today’s greatly more general
form of the discipline. An instance of this dramatic increase in generality is
provided by the invention in the middle of the last century of the theory of
distributions, inspired largely by physics. The mathematical objects called
distributions are maps only in an indirect sense; they stretch the idea of a
function to a point where some people, at least for a time, even denied them a
mathematical existence. Nevertheless, distributions are just as readily man-
ageable by the methods of calculus as the simple functions for which they were
first fashioned. It seems then fair to characterise the discipline of calculus
primarily as this collection of principles and methods formulated in essence by
the pioneers, whose ever expanding field of applicability we are far from
having fully charted. Most of the problems the creators of calculus tackled
existed from antiquity; what was new and revolutionary is their method of
solving them.
It is in this perspective that YB can be described as a book on calculus
rather than on trigonometry or infinite series. No matter how impressive or
novel in their time, these well-known results (of which the main ones I shall
write down later as the occasion arises) are only the first in a long list of
applications of calculus whose end is not in sight. Neither the Kerala math-
ematicians of the 15th–16th centuries nor the Europeans of the 17th would
have recognised a distribution if it blew up (as they are liable to do) in their
face, but they would have recognised the processes of differentiation and
integration which are used to elucidate their properties. They would also have
understood each other’s achievements and the many parallels in the way they,
vastly separated in space and time, developed the subject. There were sig-
nificant differences as well; while the early Europeans had a broader view of
the uses of calculus from the beginning, the Kerala work as presented in YB is,
though limited to the circle, more systematic and sophisticated. (Such a dec-
laration of course requires justification and I hope to take up the question
elsewhere).
The Background
Till about 700 CE or so, Kerala formed part of the Tamil linguistic landscape.
The rich cultural, especially literary, life of those days is well documented and
4
More technically, spaces on which calculus can be done have to have a topological structure
(providing a measure of nearness or locality) and, locally (with respect to the given topology), a
linear structure. I thank M. S. Narasimhan for explaining to me the modern sense of what
d’Alembert called the metaphysics of calculus.
123
420 P. P. Divakaran
5
The question of why YB was composed in Malayalam is an intriguing one, not addressed here.
6
This extremely concise sketch of the medieval history of Kerala is an inadequate summary of the
pioneering studies of Ilamkulam (or Elamkulam) P. N. Kunjan Pilla. Some aspects of his work
have recently been questioned; despite this, his research provides the one coherent overall picture
we have of the history of Kerala, especially of the time relevant to us. He wrote in Malayalam, but
there is a volume of English translations of a selection of his essays (Ilamkulam 1970). He has the
added distinction of having been the first to seriously read Śankaranārāyan: an’s commentary on
the Laghubhāskarı̄yam, thereby establishing a first direct link between astronomical activities in
Kerala and elsewhere in India.
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 421
In the chaotic aftermath of this ‘100 year war’, the Cera kingdom broke up
into a number of principalities, of which the most powerful was that ruled by
the Zamorin (samutiri) dynasty from Calicut. This period also saw a renewed
influx of brahmins and their rise to a position of social and cultural preemi-
nence. The southern part of the Zamorin’s domain became a particularly
favoured area for Namputiri settlements. It is in this region, on either bank of
the river Nila (more commonly known now as the river Bharata), that there
emerged, beginning in the second half of the 14th century, a succession of
astronomers and mathematicians of truly exceptional quality. They formed a
tight-knit group, all linked together by the traditional teacher-disciple bonds.
There was at least one father-son pair among them, Parameśvaran and
Dāmodaran. Most were Namputiris of one variey or another. According to
local tradition, three were native to one village and two taught at the same
temple school. Virtually all lived in close geographic proximity and produced
their work within a time span of roughly two centuries.
7
I have transcribed all names as they are conventionally written in Malayalam. Modern names,
place names, etc. have been exempted from diacritical markings. The marks on technical terms
follow the way they are written in Malayalam script in YB. Though the Malayalam transliteration
of Sanskrit and Sanskrit-origin words does not always conform to their original forms, the devi-
ations are minor and easily spotted. The Malayalam distinctions between the short and long e and
o as well as the two l s have been ignored.
123
422 P. P. Divakaran
The most original and creative of this brilliant lot, by the acclamation of
those who followed him, was also the first: Mādhavan, said to be of
Sangamagramam.8 Mādhavan has remained a somewhat shadowy figure. We
know nothing about his life except that it spanned the second half of the 14th
century and the first quarter of the 15th and that the great astronomer
Parameśvaran was his disciple. The few manuscript fragments that are
attributed to him are primarily astronomical, having little mathematical con-
tent of any originality, and it is through the writings of his intellectual heirs
that his achievements are known to us. Parameśvaran’s student Nı̄lakan: t:han,
in particular, quotes mathematical verses attributed to Mādhavan quite lib-
erally in his Sanskrit work Tantrasam : graha, making it clear that it is meant to
be a compendium of his teaching. The overwhelming significance of YB lies in
the fact that it contains, in chapters 6 and 7, the most thorough exposition we
have of the new mathematics that Mādhavan created and Tantrasam : graha
summarised. If only to place YB itself in context, it is useful to touch on the
highlights of Mādhavan’s legacy.
Since at least the time of Āryabhat:a, the one abiding theme of Indian
mathematics was the circle, more particularly the relationship between an arc
and the corresponding chord, and a variety of questions linked to it. This was
entirely in line with the uses to which mathematical reasoning was put in
India, first and foremost for the study of the geometry of the celestial sphere
and the motion of heavenly bodies in their epicyclical orbits. Āryabhat:a
himself famously recognised the difficulty of giving an exact number for the
ratio of the circumference of a circle to its diameter, qualifying his value
3.1416 for p as approximate, āsanna. Fundamentally, what Mādhavan did was
to push the quest for precise values for such ratios to its logical and mathe-
matical limit. (That p was understood by this time to be an irrational number
is clear from a well-known passage from Nı̄lakan: t:han’s commentary on the
Āryabhat: ı̄ya, see below). In the process, he was led, at a technical level, to
express such ratios (trigonometric functions) as appropriate power series,
infinite series of smaller and smaller terms with none exactly equal to zero.
(We know them as the ‘Gregory-Leibniz’ series for the arctangent and the
‘Newton’ series for the sine and the cosine, the quotation marks indicating a
compromise between current usage and historical accuracy). Mādhavan also
did some wonderful and practical things with these series: techniques for
accelerating their convergence; accurate estimates of the remainder as
rational functions when a series is truncated; interpolation formulae for values
of trigonometric functions at a point in terms of the values at a neighbouring
point; and so on. Most of this is described in detail in YB.
8
It is possible to make the case that Mādhavan or his family was a recent arrival from up north.
He is said to have been an Emprantiri (brahmins recently arrived from coastal Karnataka, an
established staging area on the migrant route). There is no known Sangamagramam (‘the village at
the confluence’) in Kerala, if we set aside some fanciful etymology of place names. Temples to
Sangamesvara (Siva) stand at several confluences of rivers or streams in northern Karnataka and
southern Maharashtra.
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 423
About YB
K. V. Sarma’s date for the composition of YB, around 1550–1560 CE, seems
now to be generally accepted, as also his attribution of the authorship
to Jyes: t:hadevan.9 We know a little more about Jyes: t:hadevan than about
Mādhavan: he was a disciple of Nı̄lakan: t:han and Dāmodaran, both disciples of
Mādhavan’s disciple Parameśvaran and, like Parameśvaran, was connected
with the Rama temple (or to a school attached to it) in the village of Alattiyur,
just north of the river Nila not far from its mouth. And, most importantly, we
have a whole book, extensive and intact, attributed to him.10 Alattiyur still has
memories of his name and of its past mathematical-astronomical glories, but
astrology has long since supplanted astronomy as its chief source of pride.
In the context of Indian mathematical writing, YB is singular in several
respects: (i) it is not in Sanskrit verse but in Malayalam prose (bhās: ā), (ii) it
provides detailed lines of reasoning (yukti) and, as a consequence, (iii) it is
inordinately long. It is also very ‘theoretical’; there are few worked examples
or numerical illustrations (udāharan: ams) unlike say in the work of the second
Bhāskara and, despite the strongly geometric methods of proof, no diagrams
at all. (Tampuran and Ayyar have included a profusion of them in their
commentary and these have been freely and gratefully duplicated in the
subsequent literature). It is relevant to ask why it is three-fold singular in this
particular way. Given our ignorance of the circumstances of its writing, the
answers can only be tentative at best. But, reading the text, it is difficult
9
Sarma and Hariharan (1991, p. 185). The date suggested in this article is about 1530 CE but
Sarma later tended to favour a slightly later dating. Once it is accepted that YB is an account of
Mādhavan’s mathematics, transmitted via Nı̄lakan: t:han and others, a sharp date is of little con-
sequence except to historiographers.
10
K. V. Sarma’s view (2002) that Jyes: t:hadevan also authored Dr: kkaran: am, an astronomical
chronicle datable to 1607, apparently on the basis of hearsay gathered by Whish, is difficult to
reconcile with the accepted date of YB and the dramatically different linguistic styles of the two
texts.
123
424 P. P. Divakaran
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 425
reasoning that this new knowledge is based on and, more generally, what
obstacles the reliance on such a natural style of thought and communication
places in the way of development of what is after all a highly abstract
undertaking. To enable readers to judge for themselves how well these chal-
lenges are met, I now present in translation two passages from YB, both
relating to calculus, before expressing my own views. The first describes the
computation of the surface area of a sphere (from chapter 7) and the second is
the section in which the integrals of the positive integral powers of a variable
are worked out (in chapter 6).
The translation is as literal as I can sensibly make it. The only liberties I have
taken are to provide basic punctuation and paragraph breaks, to drop the too-
frequent conversational connectives, to supply personal pronouns where
English requires them and to add a few brief explanations (not present in the
original) or comments [within square brackets]. In particular, I provide no
diagrammatic guide to the reasoning (the basic figure which I use to define
notation for my own explanation of the passage on integration of powers
should not count)—those so inclined will find it instructive, at least as a start, to
supply their own figures before looking up Tampuran and Ayyar (1948) or
Sarasvati Amma (1979). The first passage requires only a minor transformation
to make it ‘modern’; Sarasvati Amma’s version is largely faithful. The second
passage holds a few points of mathematical interest which it will be worthwhile
to return to later. It is also the part of Kerala calculus that today’s scholars,
unlike Tampuran and Ayyar, sometimes tend to handle with less than complete
fidelity, lapsing occasionally into a reliance on later western developments like
the binomial theorem for negative exponents, theorems on limits and their
interchangeability with infinite sums etc., in place of what is actually in YB. For
this reason, in the introductory remarks on this passage and in the few expla-
nations within it, I have made an effort to guard against my use of current
notation distorting in any way the material I am trying to convey.
The section headed golapr: s: :thaks: etraphalānayanam gives the proof of the for-
mula: surface area of a sphere = diameter circumference [of a great circle]. It
occurs at the very end of chapter 7 (with only the calculation of the volume of the
sphere to follow) though, with the exception of the use of one ‘package’,
the work required is much less demanding than in the proofs of the various
trigonometric series earlier in the book. It is probably the case that Mādhavan
invented the infinitesimal method first for the determination of p via the
‘Gregory-Leibniz’ series and then found it to be a powerful general tool for
settling several other interesting problems14 (also see below).
14
Bhāskara II arrived at the correct formulae for the surface area and volume of the sphere, but
by seminumerical methods which the inventor of the infinitesimal method must surely have
scoffed at.
123
426 P. P. Divakaran
Next, the method (upāyam) to know how many gaps there are and what
their lengths and width are. The radii of the circles that we have imag-
ined above [the latitudes] are half-chords (arddhajyā) of a circle whose
radius is the radius of the sphere. Hence, multiplying these half-chords
by the circumference of the sphere and dividing by the radius of the
sphere [i.e., multiplying by 2p] will result in circles [their circumferences
to be precise] having the half-chords as radii. These will be the lengths of
the rectangles if the chords are taken at the midpoints of the gaps.
Multiplying the sum of all half-chords (arddhajyāyogam) [by 2p, left
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 427
unsaid] will result in the total length of all the figures (ks: etrāyāmam)
[i.e., the sum of the lengths of all the rectangles]. The gap between two
arbitrary [the Malayalam phrase is yāva cilava = yāvat tāvat] circles [an
arbitrarily chosen pair of consecutive latitudes is meant] at the south-
north circle mentioned earlier is an arc segment (cāpakhan: d: am) of the
circumference of the sphere [i.e., of the S-N circle].
Next, the method of getting the sum of the chords (jyāyogam). Multiply
the square of the radius by khandāntarayogam [I make no attempt at an
exact translation of this ‘package’. The expression stands for the sum of
the second differentials of the half-chords with respect to the arc
(or, equivalently, the angle) and has already been treated earlier in
the chapter in connection with the series expansions of sine and cosine.
The result about to be used below is also derived there.] and divide by
the square of the full chord of the arc segment (cāpakhan: d: as-
amastajyāvarggam). The result is the sum of the half-chords. Multiply
this by the width. The width is the chord of the arc segment. The
khan: d: āntarayogam is the first chord segment. Because of smallness [of
the arc segment] these [the first chord segment and the width] are [both]
almost equal to the full chord. These are the multipliers and the square
of the full chord is the divisor. But multiplication and division are
unnecessary [the square of the full chord cancels from the numerator and
denominator]. What remains is the radius. This has to be multiplied by
the circumference and divided by the radius. Only the radius will survive.
Since we have to get the result for both halves of the sphere, double the
radius. Therefore, multiplying the diameter of the sphere by the cir-
cumference of the sphere will produce the area of the surface of the
sphere.
We have here a straightforward narration in natural spoken Malayalam,
understandable literally by any literate person but for the technical terms. By
and large, the technical nomenclature is that used in mainstream mathemat-
ical writing in Sanskrit over many centuries and is consequently unambiguous.
But these linguistic resources are now asked to be at the service of a
sophisticated novel mode of reasoning demanded by Mādhavan’s infinitesimal
mathematics, a service they were not designed to provide in full. Added to this
burden is the yoke of a foreign tongue, Malayalam, which was not sung, at
least mathematically speaking, at the cradle of the author. The strain shows.
Even in translation it is evident that, while the first part of the proof
(the geometric construction) is simply presented and easy to follow, the
transition to the ‘infinitesimal mode’ is marked by an increasing degree of
opacity. What the translation cannot show is that the Malayalam itself is, apart
from being very informally used, quite unrefined in relation to other literary
material of the period.
123
428 P. P. Divakaran
Integrals of Powers
lim meaning the limit described above. Each term within the bracket
(including the sum over j and in the limit but ignoring the minus signs) is
referred to as a sam
: kalitam which I shall translate as an integral, in anticipa-
tion.15 In addition to the integrals of even powers contributing to the arc
15
Anterior to the Kerala work, sam
: kalita is the standard Indian term for the sum of any (finite)
series. According to Datta and Singh (1993), this usage goes back at least to the (ambiguously
dated) Bakhshali manuscript.
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 429
length, YB considers those of the odd powers since the induction procedure
requires their evaluation. Thus, the kth sam
: kalitam is defined to be
Xn
rjk
Ik :¼ lim ; k ¼ 0; 1; 2; . . .
j¼1
nkþ1
the second form being the expression with which YB actually works.
In mūlasam : kalitam, the last side (bhuja) [a bhuja is the side AP of the
right triangle OAP , OP being the corresponding karn: n: am; so the last
bhuja means AB] is equal to the radius of the circle, the one below
(or before) that is one segment (khan: d: am) less and the one before that
two segments less. Suppose all the sides are equal to the radius. In that
case, if the radius is multiplied by the number of sides [i.e., n], that will be
the result of the sam : kalitam. But here only one side is equal to the radius.
Starting from this, the sides of the other smaller and smaller diagonals
(karn: n: am) are, in order, one unit (sam : khya) at a time less. Whatever is
the number of units the radius is supposed to have, imagine that the
number of segments of the side [here it means the full side AB] is the
same. That makes it easy to remember. The last but one side will be one
unit less. The next shorter one will be two less than the number of units
of the radius. The missing part (am : sam), starting with one, will increase
123
430 P. P. Divakaran
one [unit] by one [unit] progressively, the last deficit (ūnāmsam) almost
equal to the radius, just one unit less. Now if the deficits are all added,
this number (sam : khya) will eventually equal the sum [the word used for
this finite sum is sam: kalitam, as is traditional, see footnote [15]] of terms
starting with one, increasing by one and ending with the radius, less one
radius [i.e., it is the original sum minus the radius]. Therefore, multiply
the number of units in the radius by one added to the number of sides
[these two numbers are the same by assumption]. Its half is the
bhujāsam : kalitam. Bhujāsam: kalitam means the sum of the sides of all the
diagonals.
The smaller the segment, the more accurate (sūks: mam) the result.
Therefore imagine that each segment (bhujākhan: dam) [the text has
bhujāsam: khya, which is probably a result of sloppiness somewhere in the
transcription] is divided (cut) into atoms (an: u) and then carry out the
sam
: kalitam. For this, if the division is by parārddham [any very large
number will do; here, specifically, it is 1017 ], add one to the product of the
bhuja and parārddham, multiply by the radius and halve it. Also, divide
by parārddham. This is approximately half the square of the radius. To
make it a whole number, divide by parārddham. Thus, to the extent that
the segment is short, only a small part has to be added to the bhuja to
produce the sam : kalitam. [I understand this sentence to mean that the
correction to the integral due to the finite length of the segment can be
neglected in the limit]. Therefore, adding nothing to the bhuja, multi-
plying it by the radius and halving it will result in the sam : kalitam of the
extremely finely segmented bhuja. This is how half the square of the
radius is the accurate bhujākhan: d: asam
: kalitam.
The terminological imprecisions in the passage (for instance the different
senses in which the words bhuja, sam : khya and even sam : kalitam itself are
employed) are evident as is the increasing lack of clarity (the parārddham
business for example), once again, of the writing when it comes to describing
the reasoning about the passage to the limit.
After this account of the computation of the integral of x, the next sub-
section deals with x2 in some detail. The passage from x to x2 involves con-
ceptual and technical novelties which then carry over smoothly to the general
inductive step, from xk to xkþ1 . Here is how the general method of computing
the integral of an arbitrary positive power (sam
: kalitānayanasāmānyannyāyam)
is summarised:
. . ..To make integrals of higher and higher powers, multiply the partic-
ular integral by the radius and remove from it the result divided by the
number which is one greater [Ikþ1 ¼ xIk xIk =ðk þ 1Þ in our notation].
Thus divide the square of the radius by two, the cube by three, the fourth
power by four, the fifth power by five. Thus divide the consecutive
powers starting with the first (ekaikottarasamaghātam) by [the same]
consecutive numbers; the results will be the integrals of powers in
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 431
increasing order. As the simple integral comes from the square, the
integral of the square from the cube, the integral of the cube from the
fourth power and so on, the power of an unknown (rāsi) when divided by
the same number as the power will give the integral of one less power of
the unknown. This is the method of producing integrals of all powers.
There are several mathematically interesting reasons for reproducing this
brief paragraph, to which I will return shortly. But for the present, let us
overlook the familiar prolixity (perhaps it was a class of dull students, the
mandabuddhi so often addressed by Indian mathematicians when they wrote
their expositions) and note the clarity with which the theorem itself is stated.
The Language
123
432 P. P. Divakaran
Mādhavan and representing the formulae for the sines of the sum and dif-
ference of two angles (together with the proof). Unwrapping such packages is
essential for the understanding of the yukti, but they circumscribe the maxi-
mum deviation from the natural use of language that can be found in YB.
One other point about the language, or rather the general style of discourse,
merits mention. The second section of chapter 7 of YB has the heading ‘technical
terms and definitions’. A demanding reader looking here for precise charac-
terisations of the concepts and terminology necessary for the formulation and
proof of the great theorem on the ‘Newton’ series to follow is likely to be
disappointed. The section is neither systematic nor complete, but only a partial
account of some of the geometric constructions and the associated nomencla-
ture needed for the proof. In all of YB, the terminology itself does not have an
invariable significance. To give one instance, the crucially important word
sam
: kalitam is used to mean both a finite sum as in earlier writing (see footnote
[15]) and, in chapter 6, integrals of several different types. In the same chapter 6,
the term yogam never means an integral, but only a finite sum whereas in chapter
7 we have, for example, arddhajyāyogam denoting the finite sum as well as the
limiting integral. On the other hand, sam : kalitam is never used for the integrals
occurring in surface and volume computations and, elsewhere in chapter 7,
khan: d: āntarayogam and khan: d: āntarasam
: kalitam are distinguished.
Such instances can be multiplied. The question is: Is this lack of precision
related in some intrinsic way to a reluctance or an inability to transcend the
limitations of natural means of communication? Following from this: To what
extent has the use of a dominantly natural language impeded the processes of
conceptualising and developing the mathematics and then communicating it?
The answer to the first question requires a thorough acquaintance with texts
contemporary with and anterior to YB (many of them written in the not very
natural language of terse mathematical Sanskrit) and is not for me to attempt.
As for how well the mathematics was conveyed, if Tampuran and Ayyar could
read the work four centuries after it was written and still make perfectly good
sense of it—though they confess to having sometimes to guess at the author’s
train of thought—Jyes: t:hadevan clearly has not made too bad a job of it.
In concluding these scattered remarks on the language of YB, I should note
that its semi-natural style is in line with that of mathematical writing in
Sanskrit over a long period.16 We should also remember that the use of a
natural language and comprehensibility do not always go together. While
there are quite a few texts which were clearly meant to be understood by an
informed reader without the need of a detailed commentary—Śankara Vār-
iyar’s works are good examples from Kerala—there are also those, generally
terse to the point of being cryptic, whose main purpose appears to have been
the transmission of the core content of a body of knowledge and whose proper
understanding requires thorough preparation or instruction. The prime
example of such an esoteric text is of course Āryabhat: ı̄ya.
16
See Frits Staal’s (1995) wide-ranging study of scientific Sanskrit as utilised in several disciplines,
including mathematics.
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 433
The Mathematics
What, now, are the other mathematical ideas and techniques, aside from the
originality of the infinitesimal method and novel results it was used to prove,
that are conveyed to us by the imperfect vehicle that is the natural Malayalam
of YB? The order in which the various series occur in YB—first the numerical
series for p=4, then the ‘Gregory’ series for general angle and then, in a
veritable tour de force, the two ‘Newton’ series for sine and cosine—would
seem not to be a matter of chance. It is a logical way to proceed if we accept
that the motivation behind the search for a series of ever smaller terms whose
sum approaches, in the limit, the value p=4:
p 1 1
¼ 1 þ
4 3 5
tan3 h tan5 h
h ¼ tan h þ
3 5
123
434 P. P. Divakaran
17
John Kadvany (2007, this issue).
18
A ring is a set whose elements can be added and subtracted as well as multiplied. Division need
not be defined and the multiplication may be noncommutative, i.e., depend on the order of the
factors. The rings mentioned in the text are all commutative.
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 435
h3 h5
sin h ¼ h þ ...:
3! 5!
h2 h4
cos h ¼ 1 þ ...;
2! 4!
Together with the value s1 ¼ 1, also specified, repeated use of this recursion
formula leads to
s2k1 s2k3 1
s2kþ1 ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ :
2kð2k þ 1Þ ð2k 2Þð2k 1Þ2kð2k þ 1Þ 1:2:::ð2k þ 1Þ
A similar rule is given for the cosine series. It should be noted that the use of
recursion is not limited to just the statement of these formulae in an eco-
nomical form. It is an organic part of the development; the formulae for the
coefficients introduce themselves recursively, so to speak, in the very process
of their computation. There is, moreover, a unity in the way the coefficients in
all these series arise. In the ‘Gregory’ series they are definite integrals (from 0
to 1 or 0 to tan h) of even powers and in the two ‘Newton’ series they are
iterated integrals of even and odd powers respectively, with positive and
negative signs alternating. It is accurate to say that the constructive proof of
their correctness is itself recursive (though I have to add that the proof is one
of the least transparent passages in all of YB).
Perhaps the best illustration from YB of the use of recursion to establish the
validity of an infinite sequence of propositions is the short passage on the
123
436 P. P. Divakaran
calculation of the general sam : kalitam given in translation earlier together with
the two sections of YB which precede it. The untranslated (for reasons of
space) sections give a recursive proof for the correctness of the values of the
integrals of powers. First I2 is computed in terms of I1 , then I3 in terms of I2 ,
both in detail. This is followed by the statement that I4 can be computed from
I3 and, generally, Ikþ1 from Ik in the same way. It is perfectly obvious that the
recursive method cannot work if all values of k, even and odd, are not con-
sidered together, even though the series for p=4 requires Ik to be determined
only for even k. Once the first step in the recursion, I2 from I1 , is done,
generalisation is straightforward, involving as the common basic step a rec-
ognisable finite form of integration by parts. Indeed, a hint that the recursive
nature of the computation was fully understood is available in the choice of
the term mūlasam : kalitam for I1 , the root sam : kalitam from which all others are
generated.
How close does all this come to the method of mathematical induction as it is
understood today? A modern formulation of the principle of induction,
essentially deductive, will go something like: The truth of an infinite sequence
of propositions Pk ; k ¼ 1; 2; . . . is established if (i) P1 is true and if (ii) Pk is
true implies Pkþ1 is true for all k. Lacking the necessary symbolic aptitude,
Mādhavan and his followers could not possibly have expressed their compu-
tation-oriented reasoning in such abstract and elegant language. But for one
not versed in logical niceties, it is difficult to see that their use of recursion, not
only to generate an infinite sequence of true mathematical statements but also
to prove them, is in any fundamental way different, once allowance is made for
the general preference in India for constructive as opposed to deductive proofs.
From a modern perspective, there are of course other issues raised by YB’s
handling of infinite series, chief among them the question of convergence. Not
surprisingly, YB is not concerned in any serious way with this question. It is
striking however that all the series occurring in YB are convergent for the
considered range of values of the variable. In particular, the geometry of
the derivation of the ‘Gregory’ series works as it is described only for angles in
the first octant which, together with the fourth, fifth and eighth octants, is also
the range in which the series converges.
But overshadowing everything else is the pervasive presence of a new way
of addressing long-standing problems arising in the geometry of the circle and
the forging of the tools required for their successful solution—in other words,
the conceptual basis and the techniques of calculus.
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 437
risks, a temptation not easily resisted. I shall limit myself to one particular
instance of a missed turn which, in my view, clearly brings out the possible role
of the language in which the mathematics was ‘done’, as distinct from how it
was communicated, in inhibiting the requisite degree of abstraction and
generalisation.
But first a remark, not directly related to language, on an issue YB does not
concern itself with, that of the irrationality of p. At first sight this is a sur-
prising omission, given the central position occupied by the geometry of the
circle in YB’s calculus, especially if, as I have suggested above, the infinite
series expansions grew out of the search for a method of ‘controlling’ an
irrational number like p. Also as we have seen, the person who asserted this
irrationality was none other than Nı̄lakan: t:han, Jyes: t:hadevan’s teacher and the
author of Tantrasam : graha, the source book for YB. One reason for the silence
may be technical, that a yukti for the assertion was beyond the computational
methods at the command of the Kerala school—after all, it was only in 1761
that in Europe Johann Heinrich Lambert proved Nı̄lakan: t:han’s conjecture
(without of course knowing it as such). But a more likely explanation may lie
in the philosophical underpinning of Indian science as a whole throughout its
long history. Indian mathematicians, unlike the Greeks, seem never to have
come to gripspwith proofs p of the irrationality of any number, not of the far
easier case of 2 nor of 10, often used as an approximation for p at the time
of Āryabhat:a. Almost certainly, this failure has to do with the necessity of
having to use reductio ad absurdum methods in any such putative proof. For
the Greeks, proof by contradiction, involving as it does the principle of the
excluded middle, was legitimised by the authority of Aristotle. But in India
the view that P and notP are complementary and mutually exclusive was
regarded with distrust at least by some and from at least the time of the
Buddha.19 Subsequently, reasoning by contradiction (tarka, a word which has
other meanings as well) was much debated but generally not accorded full
admissibility.20 Like all scholars, mathematicians would have had a good
19
According to the Pali canon, scepticism or agnosticism about the validity and/or usefulness of
the rule of the excluded middle was expressed by the Buddha himself. The list of questions on
which the Buddha is said to have declined to take a position includes some concerning the nature
of the physical world, e.g.: Does the universe have a finite extent or not or neither or both? The
great congress (3rd century BCE) which saw the parting of the Mahasanghikas from the orthodoxy
following a ferocious debate, and whose proceedings are recorded in the Kathāvattu, not only
made references to such ‘multi-valued’ propositions, but also discussed rules of debate and dis-
putations. It appears reasonable to suppose that a degree of scepticism about the disjointness
between a property and its negation marked the early Buddhist approach to physical phenomena,
regardless of what the Buddha actually might or might not have said on the subject.
20
In Indian philosophy, the term tarka signifies ‘‘some sort of reductio ad absurdum where an
appeal to some absurdity or absurd consequence is made in order to lend an indirect support to a
positive thesis [by showing] in fact that the opposite thesis leads to absurdities’’ (Bimal Krishna
Matilal (1986, p. 79)). The widespread reluctance to accept tarka as ‘‘a means leading to a positive
piece of knowledge’’ is also discussed there.
123
438 P. P. Divakaran
grounding in other sciences (this certainly was the case in Kerala at the rel-
evant time21 ), and it is almost inconceivable that they did not know of the
reservations regarding recourse to tarka as a means of establishing a logical
truth—YB contains not a single instance of it; elsewhere in India, it is not till a
hundred years later that we come across its first hesitant and insecure use in
mathematics.22 The fact remains that this disdain denied Indian mathematics
the use of a powerful proof device. Contrast this with Newton’s free use of it in
the Principia (Book 1) whose reliance on infinitesimal geometry (but with
diagrams supplied), especially of similar triangles, is otherwise so very remi-
niscent of the Kerala techniques.
The missed turn I wish to focus on concerns the generalisation of Mādha-
van’s series expansion of sin h in powers of h with numerical coefficients
(‘around h ¼ 0’) to an expansion around some nonzero value of h, namely an
expansion of sinð/ þ hÞ in powers of h with coefficients depending on /. This
would amount to a generalisation of the Maclaurin series for the sine function
(and the cosine function) to the corresponding Taylor series. Since such
expansions of general (sufficiently ‘good’) functions f :
df y 2 d 2 f
f ðx þ yÞ ¼ f ðxÞ þ y þ þ
dx 2! dx2
21
For an examination of the epistemological roots of Kerala mathematics, from the writings of its
most thoughtful and articulate representative (Nı̄lakan: t:han), see Roddam Narasimha (2007, to
appear). It would seem that the study of the impact of philosophical systems on mathematical
thinking in the Indian context is still in its infancy. I thank Frits Staal for an elucidation of the
status of the ‘principle of non-contradiction’ in Indian thought and of the nuances one must be
sensitive to in interpreting Indian philosophical and logical writings on this issue.
22
Srinivas (2005).
23
A good starting point for following the debate regarding Mādhavan’s ‘wrong’ interpolation
formula is Kim Plofker (2005). The article is also a valuable step-by-step guide to the computation
of the interpolation formula as given in Śankara Vāriyar’s Yuktidı̄pika.
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 439
123
440 P. P. Divakaran
symmetries of the cube. With this table in hand, we know the group fully:
there is no proposition concerning such transformations, no matter how
complicated or subtle, whose truth cannot be decided by the table alone,
without reference to the cube. It follows that all groups of transformations of
any ‘physical’ entity whatever, indeed all groups not even necessarily of
transformations, are abstractly the same group if they have the same mul-
tiplication table. At the second, deeper, level, we would recognise that,
though the group of symmetries of a cube and of, say, a regular tetrahedron
are not the same, i.e., do not have the same multiplication table, not even
the same number of elements, they still share a common abstract structure,
the structure of a group. We would then proceed to elaborate the (funda-
mentally syntactic) properties that all groups must have; in short we would
make a general theory of groups. Essentially identical considerations apply to
all algebraic structures, for instance to the rings that we invoked in connec-
tion with the positional notation.
It is obvious that I could have made my point more concisely and elegantly,
in fact more powerfully, if I had taken recourse to the language that developed
to accommodate the abstract structural point of view, a language primarily
algebraic: symbols for the various groups under consideration and for their
elements, a notation for the group operations, an economical statement of the
relations, etc., the language in which theorems/‘truth’ will be presented/
expressed. Everyone now knows that group structures occur in virtually all
sciences,24 that modern physics in particular has been revolutionised by a
systematic exploitation of the formal, syntactic, understanding we have
acquired of these structures. As for mathematics, and staying with groups, I
only mention the recently completed classification of all finite simple groups
(the recursive building blocks of all finite groups) as a general illustration of the
generative power inherent in the artificial language of algebra. Without that as
a vehicle of thought and communication, it seems inconceivable that we could
have reduced mathematical reasoning and creativity to an application of ‘‘rules
without meaning’’ so successfully.
Rules without meaning but not without purpose. Decisions about what
abstract (syntactic) structures are likely to prove ‘interesting’ and even
judgements about what results are ‘deep’ or ‘beautiful’ have still to be made
semantically, by reference to the contexts in which questions arise and are
resolved. The tension between problem-solving and theory-making, the virtual
inseparability of content and language, is arguably the main source of the
extraordinarily wide scope and power of mathematics as it is practised now
(and is perhaps also the reason for the ‘‘unreasonable effectiveness of math-
ematics in the physical sciences’’). Once the creative process of discovery is
thus algebraised and put on autopilot as it were, there is no limit to what is
discoverable—algebra is truly, infinitely, generous.
Moving back from these generalities to the Kerala of the 15th and 16th
centuries, one cannot of course be dogmatic about the extent to which pro-
24
For an unusual instance from the social sciences, see A. Weil (1949).
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 441
gress towards greater abstraction and hence greater generality was inhibited
by the spurning of symbolic methods. But on the evidence of YB, it cannot be
doubted that obvious general points of view were overlooked or neglected. As
the episode of the Taylor series makes clear, an intuitive feeling for the
symmetry of the circle (the corresponding group being the group of all rota-
tions around the centre, which is not a finite group but still, structurally, a
group) did not translate into the precise understanding that this symmetry
denies a privileged role to any particular diameter, even if it is called the east-
west direction. I like to think that if only they could have been persuaded to
designate a diameter as the line AB or ab or a Malayalam equivalent thereof,
the Kerala mathematicians might have gone on eventually to a more general,
less concrete, appreciation of their own achievement.
What is puzzling in all this, at least to a non-expert, is that abstraction and
symbolic representations of objects and their relationships were not strangers
to Indian thought. Grammar (first and foremost), prosody and the classifica-
tion of meters, cosmogonic speculation, systematisation of the rules of rea-
soning and several other areas of intellectual inquiry come to mind as having
been greatly enriched by a fundamentally structural point of view. In math-
ematics, the positional notation for numbers is itself a triumph of structure
over clumsy description; as we have seen, it is pure syntax. Bhāskara the
second, who lived not more than three centuries before the efflorescence of
mathematics in Kerala and whose work was known and cherished there, was a
true algebraist; his Bı̄jagan: ita proposes the use of the names of colours to
symbolically represent variables in equations, as distinct from numerical val-
ues for them, and states the rules for manipulating them, exactly as if they
were numbers. (In a strange echo, modern physics employs the term chro-
modynamics for the interactions of quarks of different ‘colours’). Bhāskara’s
algebraic legacy seems to have been better nourished in the Arab lands than
among his own mathematical heirs in India. Perhaps, at the time and place we
are talking about, mathematics was seen as no more than a handmaiden of
astronomy, with no high intellectual standing of its own. But then, what else
but intellectual curiosity can have inspired a Nı̄lakan: t:han to cogitate on the
irrationality of p or a Mādhavan to compute it to thirteen decimal places?
Close to three hundred years after Mādhavan, Newton and Leibniz laid the
foundations of calculus as it is taught today and their 18th century followers
gave it the form and language that we still follow, more or less faithfully. That
came after the first integrations were performed in Europe, by Cavalieri,
Fermat and a host of others (perhaps only coincidentally, the integrals of
powers). The context in which this happened was vastly different from the one
in which the heroes of our narrative perfected their infinitesimal geometry of
123
442 P. P. Divakaran
the circle. Descartes had already algebraised geometry25 and both Newton
and Leibniz were well versed in the Cartesian method and philosophy. The
first ideas about a general function of a variable were taking shape and the first
correspondences between functions and the simplest curves, the conic sec-
tions, beginning to be understood. The Newton-Leibniz calculus reflects this
great opening up, especially in the willingness and ability to handle more
general functions. In the case of Newton, the Newton of the Principia in
particular, a degree of generality could not, in principle, have been avoided;
the position of a mass-particle as a function of time is a priori unknown, being
determined, in terms of a given force, only after the equations of motion are
solved. (In contrast, with the early exception of Āryabhat:a with his belief in a
spinning earth and ideas on relative motion, Indian theories of the motion of
celestial bodies were almost entirely descriptive, paying little heed to possible
underlying causes). It is in this fundamental respect, in the recognition that the
infinitesimal method is of universal applicability, that the European calculus
of the late 17th century—even while admitting that an acceptable foundation
for it was not laid till the middle of the 19th—can be seen to have gone far
beyond Mādhavan’s pathbreaking achievements. If history were different and
granted them the time, could Mādhavan’s followers have taken their own road
one day to this high ground? Going by what YB tells us, we must remain
sceptical. For one thing, there is the much-discussed difference in the Euro-
pian and Indian approaches to doing mathematics, summarised in the catch
words ‘deductive’ or ‘axiomatic’ and ‘constructive’ or ‘computational’. Our
look at (a tiny sample of) YB’s contents provides, I think, enough evidence
that a more severe obstacle was the aversion to a spare and refined language
and the consequent absence of a structural or general point of view.
But what history brought was the Portuguese incursion into Kerala, sig-
nalling another period of strife and disorder. The resistance to the invaders
was led by none other than the Zamorin who, in his other traditional role, was
overlord and protector of the temples and patron of learning. The delta of the
river Nila saw much violence and bloodshed during the very time in which,
half a day’s walk away, Nı̄lakan: t:han, Jyes: t:hadevan and others were teaching
and writing down their new mathematics in their temple villages. All the great
texts date from this turbulent 16th century and with its end mathematics in
Kerala also went into terminal decline.
25
Two and a half centuries before Descartes, Nicole Oresme (or Nicolas d’Oresme) had taken the
first step to liberate space from its Euclidean literalness and give it a more metaphorical role by
plotting on a plane the graph of a ‘function’ of a ‘variable’. I owe my acquaintance with Oresme’s
work to David Mumford, who is also responsible for the characterisation above of its significance.
The Indian view of geometry is, if anything, more down-to-earth than the Greek—compare (i) the
use of the terms bhūmi and base for the ‘horizontal’ line in a polygon in the two traditions, (ii)YB’s
instruction to ‘drop a plumbline’ with drawing (or dropping!) a perpendicular, not necessarily to a
base, and several other similar instances. Notable coincidence: Oresme and Mādhavan (if we
accept the conventional chronolgy) lived at about the same time, the former being the senior by 20
or 30 years.
123
The First Textbook of Calculus: Yuktibhās: ā 443
Acknowledgements Over the years of my involvement with YB I have frequently enjoyed the
generous hospitality of the Institute of Mathematical Sciences, Chennai, for which I express my
gratitude. My thanks go also to several friends, in particular Frits Staal, David Mumford and M. S.
Narasimhan, for encouragement and much critical stimulation and advice.
References
Datta, B., & Singh, A. N. (1993). Use of series in India. Indian Journal of History of Science,
28(2), 103.
Ilamkulam P. N. Kunjan Pilla (1970). Studies in Kerala history. Kottayam: National Book Stall.
Joseph, G. G. (1992). The crest of the peacock: Non-European roots of mathematics. London:
Penguin Books.
Kadvany, J. (2007). Positional value and linguistic recursion. Journal of Indian Philosophy, this
issue.
Matilal, B. K. (1986). Perception: An essay on classical Indian theories of knowledge (p. 79). New
Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Mukunda Marar, K., & Rajagopal, C. T. (1944). On the Hindu quadrature of the circle. Journal of
Royal Asiatic Society (Bombay branch), 20, 65.
Narasimha, R. (2007). The yukti of classical Indian astronomical science. In B. V. Sreekantan
(Ed.), Foundations of Science. PHISPC Monograph Series on History of Philosophy, Science
and Culture in India, to appear.
Plofker, K. (2005). Relations between approximations to the sine in Kerala mathematics. In
G. Emch, R. Sridharan, & M. D. Srinivas (Eds.), Contributions to the history of Indian
mathematics. New Delhi: Hindustan Book Agency.
Sarasvati Amma, T. A. (1979/1999). Thesis, Madras University. Later published as Geometry in
ancient and medieval India (1979; 2nd ed. 1999). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Sarma, K. V. (2002). Āryabhata and Āryabhatan astronomy: Antecedents, status and develop-
ment. In Proceedings of the International Seminar and Colloquium on 1500 Years of Ary-
abhateeyam. Kochi: Kerala Sastra Sahitya Parishad.
Sarma, K. V., & Hariharan, S. (1991). Yuktibhāsā of Jyesthadeva. Indian Journal of History of
Science, 26(2), 185.
Srinivas, M. D. (2005). Proofs in Indian mathematics. In G. Emch, R. Sridharan, & M. D. Srinivas
(Eds.), Contributions to the history of Indian mathematics. New Delhi: Hindustan Book
Agency.
Staal, F. (1995). The Sanskrit of science. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 23, 73.
Tampuran, Rama Varma, & Akhilesvara Ayyar, A. R. (1948). Yuktibhās: ā (Part I, General
Mathematics), with vyākhyā. Trissivaperur: Mangalodayam Ltd.
Weil, A. (1949). Sur l’étude algébrique de certains types de lois de marriage. In C. Lévi-Strauss,
Les structures élémentaires de la parenté (p. 278). Paris: Presse Universitaire de France.
Whish, C. W. (1835). On the Hindu quadrature of the circle and the infinite series of the pro-
portion of the circumference to the diameter exhibited in the four śāstras Tantrasamgraha,
Yuktibhasha, Caranapaddhati and Sadratnamala. Transactions of the Royal Asiatic Society of
Great Britain and Ireland, 3, 509.
123