PDF Lectures On Philosophy George Edward Moore Download
PDF Lectures On Philosophy George Edward Moore Download
https://ebookultra.com/download/some-main-problems-of-philosophy-
moore/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/lectures-on-mechanics-jerrold-e-
marsden/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/philosophy-in-multiple-voices-george-
yancy/
ebookultra.com
Philosophy The Power of Ideas 8th Edition Brooke Noel
Moore
https://ebookultra.com/download/philosophy-the-power-of-ideas-8th-
edition-brooke-noel-moore/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/lectures-on-the-philosophy-of-
religion-volume-iii-the-consummate-religion-consummate-
religion-v-3-g-w-f-hegel/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/lectures-on-analytic-differential-
equations-yulij-ilyashenko/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/club-law-a-comedy-1st-edition-george-
charles-moore-smith-editor/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/the-philosophy-of-enchantment-robin-
george-collingwood/
ebookultra.com
Lectures on Philosophy George Edward Moore Digital
Instant Download
Author(s): George Edward Moore
ISBN(s): 9780415295499, 0415295491
Edition: Reissue
File Details: PDF, 19.32 MB
Year: 2004
Language: english
Muirhead Library of Philosophy
LECTURES ON PHILOSOPHY
ZMuirfuad
li/franj o f
Thilofopfuj
Muirhead Library of Philosophy
2 0 T H C E N T U R Y P H IL O S O P H Y
In 22 Volumes
© 1966 Routledge
These reprints are taken from original copies of each book. In many cases
the condition of these originals is not perfect. The publisher has gone to
great lengths to ensure the quality of these reprints, but wishes to point
out that certain characteristics of the original copies will, of necessity, be
apparent in reprints thereof.
BY
GEO RG E EDW ARD MOORE
O.M.
Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge,
and Emeritus Professor of Philosophy
in the University of Cambridge
EDITED BY
C A S IM IR L E W Y
Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge,
and Sidgwick Lecturer in Moral Science
in the University of Cambridge
R Routledge
Taylor &. Francis Group
LONDON AND NEW YORK
F IR ST P U B L I S H E D I N 19 6 6
e d i t o r ’s p r e f a c e page vi ii
P A R T I. S E L E C T I O N S F R O M A COURSE OF LECTURES
GIVEN IN 1 9 2 8 - 2 9
P A R T II . S E L E C T I O N S F R O M A COURSE OF LECTURES
GIVEN IN 1 9 2 5 - 2 6
P A R T I I I . S E L E C T I O N S FR OM A COURSE OF LECTURES
GIVEN IN 1 9 3 3 - 3 4
ix
This page intentionally left blank
PART I
S E L E C T IO N S FR O M A C O U R SE OF L E C T U R E S
G IV E N IN 19 3 8 -2 9
This page intentionally left blank
I
WHAT IS M E A N T BY “ N A T U R E ” ?
in the sense in which my body has—a sense with wh. we are all
familiar, though the analysis of it is difficult & (b) continuing to
exist for a certain time, in the sense in which my body has done
so.
Starting from this, part at least of what we mean by Nature is,
I think, this thing together with all those wh. have the property
of being related to it in both the following ways:
(a) are similar to it in the z respects mentioned
(b) are also positively related to it in this respect: that they
either have been or will be, or both have been and will be, at
every moment of their existence, in the same space in which it is
or was.
The first point I want to insist on is that both these things are
necessary in order that a material thing may form part of the
material Universe or of Nature.
So far as I can see, there may be things wh. fulfil the first
without the second; & in that case they would not be parts of the
material Universe or Nature.
What I’m insisting on is that Nature does not mean merely
all those things wh. have a certain intrinsic property: but all those
things wh., besides this, stand in a certain relation to this thing.
Try to think of what you mean by all the things that are now
parts of Nature, or parts of the Material Universe.
This is, of course, only a part, because things that have been &
have ceased to exist, & things that will be (if any will be) will also
be parts of nature.
Well, one natural way of thinking of it, is, I think, certainly this.
We start from certain things we are perceiving, things in this
room, our own bodies & their parts, this desk & so on, these are
quite certainly part of Nature now: not mere sense-data: whether
these are or are not included in Nature, is to be left over.
But this does not constitute the whole of Nature now: we know
that there are, or may be, other things which are also parts of
Nature now: we know that is, of certain properties, that if there
are any things wh. have those properties they also are parts of
Nature now.
What properties?
These at least: Things wh. resemble our bodies etc. in this
respect at least, that they have size & shape in 3 dimensions, in the
familiar sense, whatever it is, in which our bodies have
WHAT IS MEANT BY “ N AT U R E ” ? 7
& also have one or other of three important relations to things
we are perceiving:
are either parts of, or in contact with, or at some distance from
them.
Part at least of what we mean by Nature now is “ Those things
& all those things that satisfy the 2 conditions (a) that they’re
extended in 3 dimensions (b) that they are in the same Space with
these.”
This may not be a//, but it is part.
But now, for the past & future.
We don’t necessarily include in Nature all the things wh. have
been or will be, which are extended in 3 dimensions.
It’s only those among them wh. fulfil a condition analagous to
(b) —have been or will be in the same Space with these.
And the trouble is that to say that A was in the same space in
which B is, can’t have the same meaning as is in the same space
in wh. B is.
And such things simply haven’t got now to any of the things
I’m perceiving now relation (b).
What they do have to those is some relation wh. can be ex
pressed by saying that they were in the same space in which these
are.
Now the analysis of this I don’t pretend to give, but I said I
thought I could give a criterion = something which is true of
all those things & those things only which were at any time in the
same Space in wh. these are now.
(1) All those things which exist now as parts of Nature & also
existed in the past, were at every moment of this past existence
in the same Space in which they now are.
(2) All those things which had at any time to one of these the
relation R were in the same Space in which these are now.
This includes a very great deal; since e.g. the earth & sun &
moon & stars exist now & have existed for a very long time in the
past: & every extended thing which has at any time had R to
any of these is then included in Nature.
(3) But even this is not enough: for Nature may have existed
(& that it may is enough) before any of the things wh. exist now
did exist, & may continue to exist in the future after they have
ceased. What do we mean by this supposition?
I think the case may be met by taking instead of R, R# \
But even this is not enough: this only gives us things in Nature;
events are also certainly in Nature, & this forms part of our
conception.
But how are we to define natural or physical events?
I think we can define them as (1) events which have happened,
are happening, or will happen to natural things or which hap
pened where certain physical things were (I’m inclined to think,
in opposition to Whitehead, that to say they happened somewhere
in physical space is to say something wh. is to be defined in terms
of this), & (2) events wh. are not mental events, i.e. not of a kind
such that any event of that kind must be an experience.
if it’s to be true that they’re not blue. Similarly it might seem that
in order not to be real, a thing must at least be.
Now as to this argument, I fully admit that there are senses of
“ real” such that “ Material objects aren’t real” is compatible
with There are material objects. But what I want to insist on is
that there is a sense in which it’s not: & why I’ve used this
argument is because it brings out that to say so involves saying
that “ Material objects aren’t real” is not of the same form as
“ Lions are not blue” . For I do think that “ Lions are not blue”
does = “ There are lions & no lion is blue” .
In support of my contention consider what is meant by:
Unicorns aren’t real; griffins aren’t real; dragons aren’t real.
It’s quite clear, I think, that in asserting these things we aren’t
asserting “ There are unicorns” , “ There are griffins” , etc.
But
(2) some people might use another argument in favour of the
view that “ material objects aren’t real” can’t possibly be properly
used = “ There are no material objects” .
They might say:
Unicorns & dragons are imaginary material objects; & since
they are, it follows that there really are imaginary things.
But if there’s a sense of “ real” such that “ There are material
objects” = “ Material objects are real” , then it follows that in
that sense “ There are imaginary material objects” must = “ Im
aginary material objects are real” . But there’s certainly no sense
whatever of “ real” in which imaginary material objects are “ real” .
(Some philosophers have drawn just the opposite conclusion
that there is a sense in which imaginary things are real.)
Or, put it in another way: if “ Material objects aren’t real”
= There are no material objects; then “ Imaginary material
objects aren’t real” should mean “ There are no imaginary material
objects” : but it certainly doesn’t, in any sense, because “ There are
no imaginary material objects” is false, whereas the other is true.
I think this argument is really puzzling, & I want to try to
say how I shall meet it.
I think the expression “ There are imaginary material objects”
is true, in a sense, & I also agree that there’s no sense whatever
in which imaginary material objects are real: and I can, therefore,
only meet the argument by saying that the way in wh. “ There are”
is used in “ There are imaginary material objects” , where this
22 LECTURES ON P HI L O S OP HY
as we can of Caliban & Ariel & Mr. Pecksniff. What on earth can
be meant by saying that we all now are just thinking of Aladdin’s
lamp—that it is an object to all of us, if there is no such thing?
Of course it’s unreal, but it has being, & it is material: & hence
from the fact that it is material, it does really follow that there is
at least one material thing.
The point here is a different one from the one I raise explicitly
in Phil. Studies, p. 2 1 7 1, when I try to explain what must be true
of me, if it’s to be true of me at a particular time that I am thinking
of a unicorn. What I say there is true so far as it goes: particularly
of course the fundamental point that “ S is thinking of a unicorn”
does not mean There is something of wh. it’s true both that it is a
unicorn & that S is thinking of it: it’s not true that the fact that S
is thinking of a unicorn proves that there is at least one unicorn:
as, if it were true that I was shooting a unicorn, it would be true
that there was: S is shooting a unicorn does = There’s something
of which it’s true both that it is a unicorn & that S is shooting it.
It’s also true, I think, so far as it goes, that in order that it may be
true that I am thinking of a unicorn, I must (1) be thinking of
some property, such that, if anything had that property, it would
be a unicorn & (2) conceiving the hypothesis that there is some
thing wh. has that property. But this though it’s necessary is
certainly not sufficient in order that it should be true that I am
thinking of a particular unicorn: for it is something wh. happens
when I am merely conceiving the hypothesis that there are unicorns,
wh. is not the same thing as thinking of a particular unicorn. But
I can do this. I can think of the unicorn in Alice Through the
Looking Glass: you & I can both think of the same particular
unicorn. What more am I doing? It is natural here to think of
Russell’s statement that “ Apollo” means “ the object having such
& such properties” 2, i.e. as he elsewhere puts it that it is “ a
definite description” : so that to conceive any hypothesis with
regard to Apollo, e.g. that he was brother of Artemis, is to conceive
with regard to some property or collection of properties, <f>9
“ There’s a thing which has </>, which alone has </>, & wh. is
brother of Artemis” . And this is actually offered by R. as an
explanation of how it can be true that Apollo isn’t real: he says
things are fictions, what we are saying is, with regard to some
property or other, that nothing has it. But ~ E ! (ix)(<f>x) does
not say with regard to <£ that nothing has it, but only that it’s not
the case that only one thing has it. Thus R. is asking us to believe
that when we say Apollo is a fiction, we’re only saying with
regard to the properties mentioned in the Classical Diet, under
Apollo, that it’s not true that only one person possessed them all,
& are leaving it perfectly open that there may have been several
who did. Or that when we say that there was no such person as
the author of Slawkenburgius on noses, we are only denying that
“ Slawkenburgius on noses” was the work of one man only, &
are leaving it a perfectly open question whether it wasn’t written
by several persons.1 I think there’s obviously something wrong
here. In all these cases we’re obviously saying of some property
or other that nothing whatever possessed it: we’re not leaving
open the possibility that, though there wasn’t only one thing
which did, yet there may have been several. And this is shewn,
I think, by the extremely careless way in wh. R. introduces his
statement. He is then talking of the prop, “ the round square
does not exist” (a prop., by the way, which nobody would think
of making; & wh. has no meaning). He says we may substitute
“ It’s false that there is an object x which is both round & square” .
This gives us there are no round squares.
But now what does actually happen when 2 people both think
of the same imaginary object? In order to answer this question,
the first thing necessary is to consider what happens when a
person tells you a fairy-tale, or any other fictitious story for the
first time. Take the simplest possible case, such as the parable of
the Good Samaritan in the N .T., or as J. takes (I. 85)2, the story
of Jack & the Beanstalk—only he tells it quite wrong: J. is talking
about the difference between what he calls the Introductory
Indef. article & the Alternative Indef. He says there’s an impor
tant difference between “ A man must have been in this room” &
“ Once upon a time there was a boy who bought a beanstalk” :
he says the first means “ Some man or other” , & the second means
“ a certain boy” (p. 85). What the difference is, he never tells us:
I don’t believe there is any. But let’s take Luke 10.30: “ A certain
man was going down from Jerusalem to Jericho; & he fell among
1 [.Principia, and ed., vol. I, p. 68.]
2 [W. E. Johnson, Logic, Part I (Cambridge, 1921).]
Discovering Diverse Content Through
Random Scribd Documents
cases have been recognized. The green and brown color of lizards
may protect them, the green color of many frogs is supposed to
conceal them as they sit amongst the plants on the edge of a stream
or pond. The gray-brown color of the toad has been described as a
resemblance to the dry ground, while the brilliant green of several
tree-frogs conceals them very effectively amongst the leaves. Many
fishes are brilliantly colored, and it has even been suggested that
those living amongst corals and sea-anemonies have acquired their
colors as a protection, but Darwin states that they appeared to him
very conspicuous even in their highly colored environment.
Amongst insects innumerable cases of adaptive coloration have
been described. In fact this is the favorite group for illustrating the
marvels of protective coloration. A few examples will here serve our
purpose. The oft-cited case of the butterfly Kallima is, apparently, a
striking instance of protective resemblance. When at rest the wings
are held together over the back, as in nearly all butterflies, so that
only the under surface is exposed. This surface has an
unquestionably close resemblance to a brown leaf. It is said on no
less authority than that of Wallace that when this butterfly alights on
a bush it is almost impossible to distinguish between it and a dead
leaf. The special point in the resemblance to which attention is most
often called is the distinct line running obliquely across the wings
which looks like the midrib of a leaf. Whether the need of such a
close resemblance to a leaf is requisite for the life of this butterfly,
we do not know, of course, and so long as we do not have this
information there is danger that the case may prove too much, for, if
it should turn out that this remarkable case is accidental the view in
regard to the resemblance may be endangered.
Amongst caterpillars there are many cases of remarkable
resemblances in color between the animal and its surroundings. The
green color of many of those forms that remain on the leaves of the
food-plant during the day will give, even to the most casual
observer, the impression that the color is for the purpose of
concealment; and that it does serve to conceal the animal there can
be no doubt. But even from the point of view of those who maintain
that this color has been acquired because of its protective value it
must be admitted that the color is insufficient, because some of
these same green caterpillars are marvellously armed with an array
of spines which are also supposed to be a protection against
enemies. Equally well protected are the brown and mottled
geometrid caterpillars. These have, moreover, the striking and
unusual habit of fixing themselves by the posterior pairs of false
legs, and standing still and rigid in an oblique position on the twigs
to which they are affixed. So close is their resemblance to a short
twig, that even when their exact position is known it is very difficult
to distinguish them.
Grasshoppers that alight on the ground are, in many cases, so
similar to the surface of the ground that unless their exact location is
known they easily escape attention, while the green color of the
katydid, a member of the same group of orthoptera, protects it from
view in the green foliage of the trees where it lives. The veinlike
wings certainly suggest a resemblance to a leaf, but whether there is
any necessity for so close an imitation may be questioned.
There can be little doubt in some of these cases that the color of
the animal may be a protection to it, but as has been hinted already,
it is another question whether it acquired these colors because of
their usefulness. Nevertheless, if the color is useful to its possessor,
it is an adaptation in our sense of the word, without regard to the
way in which it has been acquired. Even, for instance, if the
resemblance were purely the outcome of chance in the sense that
the color appeared without relation to the surroundings, it would still
be an adaptation if it were of use to the animal under the ordinary
conditions of life.
In the lower groups numerous cases in which animals resemble
their surroundings could be given. Such cases are known in
crustacea, worms, mollusks, hydroids, etc., and the possible value of
these resemblances may be admitted in many instances.
It is rather curious that so few cases of adaptive coloration have
been described for plants. No one supposes that the slate color of
the lichen is connected with the color of the rocks on which it grows,
in the sense that the resemblance is of any use to the lichen. Nor
does the color of the marine red algæ serve in any way to protect
the plants so far as is known. The green color of nearly all the higher
plants is obviously connected with the substance, chlorophyl, that is
essential for the processes of assimilation, and has no relation to
external objects. But when we come to the colors of flowers we
meet with curious cases of adaptation, at least according to the
generally accepted point of view. For it is believed by many
naturalists that the color of the corolla of flowering plants is
connected with the visits of insects to the flowers, and these visits
are in many cases essential for the cross-fertilization of the flowers.
This adaptation is one useful to the species, rather than the
individual, and belongs to another category.
The leaf of the Venus’s fly-trap, which suddenly closes together
from the sides when a fly or other light body comes to rest on it, is
certainly a remarkable adaptation. A copious secretion of a digestive
fluid is poured out on the surface of the leaf, and the products of
digestion are absorbed. There can be no question that this
contrivance is of some use to the plant. In other insectivorous
plants, the pitcher plants, the leaves are transformed into pitchers.
In Nepenthes a digestive fluid is secreted from the walls. A line of
glands secreting a sweet fluid serves to attract insects to the top of
the pitcher, whence they may wander or fall into the fluid inside, and
there being drowned, they are digested. A lidlike cover projecting
over the opening of the pitcher is supposed to be of use to keep out
the rain.
In Utricularia, a submerged water-plant, the tips of the leaves are
changed into small bladders, each having a small entrance closed by
an elastic valve opening inwards. Small snails and crustaceans can
pass into this opening, to which they are guided by small
outgrowths; but once in the cup they cannot get out again, and, in
fact, small animals are generally found in the bladders where they
die and their substance is absorbed by forked hairs projecting into
the interior of the bladder.
The cactus is a plant that is well suited to a dry climate. Its leaves
have completely disappeared, and the stem has become swollen into
a water-reservoir. “It has been estimated that the amount of water
evaporated by a melon cactus is reduced to one six-hundredth of
that given off by any equally heavy climbing-plant.”
It does not require any special study to see that there are certain
groups of animals and of plants that are more like each other than
they are like the members of any other group. It is obvious to every
one that the group known as mammals has a combination of
characters not found in any other group; such, for instance, as a
covering of hair, mammary glands that furnish milk to the young,
and a number of other less distinctive features. These and other
common characteristics lead us to put the mammals into a single
class. The birds, again, have certain common characters such as
feathers, a beak without teeth, the development of a shell around
the egg, etc., and on account of these resemblances we put them
into another class. Everywhere in the animal and plant kingdoms we
find large groups of similar forms, such as the butterflies, the
beetles, the annelidan worms, the corals, the snails, the starfishes,
etc.
Within each of these groups we find smaller groups, in each of
which there are again forms more like each other than like those of
other groups. We may call these smaller groups families. Within the
families we find smaller groups, that are more like each other than
like any other groups in the same family, and these we put into
genera. Within the genus we find smaller groups following the same
rule, and these are the species. Here we seem to have reached a
limit in many cases, for we do not always find within the species
groups of individuals more like each other than like other groups.
Although we find certain differences between the individuals of a
species, yet the differences are often inconstant in the sense that
amongst the descendants of any individual there may appear any
one of the other variations. If this were the whole truth, it would
seem that we had here reached the limits of classification, the
species being the unit. This, however, is far from being the case, for,
in many species we find smaller groups, often confined to special
localities. These groups are called varieties.
In some cases it appears, especially in plants, these smaller
groups of varieties resemble in many ways the groups of species in
other forms, since they breed true to their kind, even under changed
conditions. They have been recognized as “smaller species” by a
number of botanists.
In this connection a point must be brought up that has played an
important rôle in all discussion as to what limits can be set to a
species. As a rule it is found that two distinct species cannot be
made to cross with each other, i.e. the eggs of an individual of one
species cannot be fertilized by spermatozoa derived from individuals
of another species; or, at least, if fertilization takes place the embryo
does not develop. In some cases, however, it has been found
possible to cross-fertilize two distinct species, although the offspring
is itself more or less infertile. Even this distinction, however, does not
hold absolutely, for, in a few cases, the offspring of the cross is
fertile. It cannot be maintained, therefore, that this test of infertility
between species invariably holds, although in a negative sense the
test may apply, for if two different forms are infertile, inter se, the
result shows that they are distinct species. If they cross they may or
may not be good species, and some other test must be used to
decide their relation.
We should always keep in mind the fact that the individual is the
only reality with which we have to deal, and that the arrangement of
these into species, genera, families, etc., is only a scheme invented
by man for purposes of classification. Thus there is no such thing in
nature as a species, except as a concept of a group of forms more or
less alike. In nature there are no genera, families, orders, etc. These
are inventions of man for purposes of classification.
Having discovered that it is possible to arrange animals and plants
in groups within groups, the question arises as to the meaning of
this relation. Have these facts any other significance than that of a
classification of geometric figures, or of crystals according to the
relations of their axes, or of bodies as to whether they are solids,
liquids, or gases, or even whether they are red, white, or blue?
If we accept the transmutation view, we can offer an explanation
of the grouping of living things. According to the transmutation
theory, the grouping of living things is due to their common descent,
and the greater or less extent to which the different forms have
diverged from each other. It is the belief in this principle that makes
the classification of the biologist appear to be of a different order
from that in any other science; and it is this principle that appears to
give us an insight into a large number of phenomena.
For example, if, as assumed in the theory, a group of individuals
(species) breaks up into two groups, each of these may be supposed
to inherit a large number of common characteristics from their
ancestors. These characters are, of course, the resemblances, and
from them we conclude that the species are related and, therefore,
we put them into the same genus. The differences, as has been
said, between the species must be explained in some other way; but
the principle of classification with which we are here concerned is
based simply on the resemblances, and takes no account of the
differences between species.
In this argument it has been tacitly assumed that the
transformation of one species into another, or into more than one,
takes place by adding one or more new characters to those already
present, or by changing over a few characters without altering
others. But when we come to examine any two species whatsoever,
we find that they differ, not only in one or in a few characters, but in
a large number of points; perhaps in every single character. It is true
that sometimes the differences are so small that it is difficult to
distinguish between two forms, but even in such cases the
differences, although small, may be as numerous as when they are
more conspicuous. If, then, this is what we really find when we
carefully examine species of animals or of plants, what is meant
when we claim that our classification is based on the characters
common to all of the forms that have descended from the same
ancestor? We shall find, if we press this point that, in one sense,
there is no absolute basis of this sort for our classification, and that
we have an unreal system.
If this is admitted, does our boasted system of classification,
based as it is on the principle of descent, give us anything
fundamentally different from an artificial classification? A few
illustrations may make clearer the discussion that follows. If, for
example, we take a definition of the group of vertebrates we read:
“The group of craniate vertebrates includes those animals known as
Fishes, Amphibians, Reptiles, Birds, and Mammals; or in other
words, Vertebrates with a skull, a highly complex brain, a heart of
three or four chambers, and red blood corpuscles.” If we attempt to
analyze this definition, we find it stated that the skull is a
characteristic of all vertebrates, but if we ask what this thing is that
is called skull, we find not only that it is something different in
different groups, being cartilaginous in sharks, and composed of
bones in mammals, but that it is not even identical in any two
species of vertebrates. If we try to define it as a case of harder
material around the brain, then it is not something peculiar to the
vertebrates, since the brain of the squid is also encased in a
cartilaginous skull. What has been said of the skull may be said in
substance of the brain, of the heart, and even of the red blood
corpuscles.
If we select another group, we find that the birds present a
sharply defined class with very definite characters. The definition of
the group runs as follows: “Birds are characterized by the presence
of feathers, their fore-limbs are used for flight, the breast-bone is
large and serves for the attachment of the muscles that move the
wings; outgrowths from the lungs extend throughout the body and
even into the bones and serve as air sacs which make the body
more buoyant. Only one aortic arch is present, the right, and the
right ovary and oviduct are not developed. The eyes are large and
well developed. Teeth are absent. We have here a series of strongly
marked characteristics such as distinguish hardly any other class.
Welcome to our website – the ideal destination for book lovers and
knowledge seekers. With a mission to inspire endlessly, we offer a
vast collection of books, ranging from classic literary works to
specialized publications, self-development books, and children's
literature. Each book is a new journey of discovery, expanding
knowledge and enriching the soul of the reade
Our website is not just a platform for buying books, but a bridge
connecting readers to the timeless values of culture and wisdom. With
an elegant, user-friendly interface and an intelligent search system,
we are committed to providing a quick and convenient shopping
experience. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery
services ensure that you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
ebookultra.com