Ralph Mark Rosen - Time and Temporality in The Ancient World-University of Pennsylvania Museum of Archaeology and Anthropology (2004)
Ralph Mark Rosen - Time and Temporality in The Ancient World-University of Pennsylvania Museum of Archaeology and Anthropology (2004)
Edited by
Ralph M. Rosen
Contributors ...................
243
who would have been as deeply sensitive to the cycles and temporal
markers of the natural world around them as any self-styled intellec-
tual of the day.
As this collection shows, one of the most persistent
dichotomies we find across many pre-modern societies is that
between cyclical and teleological time. The choices seem clear
enough: one considers the inevitable progression of a human life
from birth to death and concludes that time marches inexorably for-
ward toward a telos, or goal. At the same time, this apparently linear
progression of a human life span is situated within the temporal
markers of nature that seem repetitive, cyclical, and fundamentally
stable through time. As these essays make clear, over the millennia
much ingenuity has been directed at these apparently contradictory
models of time, as people variously attempted either to reconcile
them, privilege one over the other, or explain them in terms that
leave empiricism or human rationality behind.
Marc Brettler discusses precisely this tension between tele-
ological (or eschatological) and cyclical, periodically recurrent time
in the Hebrew Bible. Despite the fact that the Bible does not offer
much in the way of second-order, philosophical discourse about
time, many passages suggest a notion of cyclical time. Brettler exam-
ines the evidence of Ecclesiastes and Judges, in particular, that at
least some ancient Israelites believed that events recur through time,
although only God controls and can understand why things happen
when and as they do. Biblical scholars, however, have often contrast-
ed this notion with what they believe to be a distinct eschatological
strand elsewhere in the Bible, especially in the books of the Prophets,
which often speak of the “end of time.” As earlier scholars have point-
ed out, such prophecies for the future usually involve a return to a
past state or past conditions within Israel’s history, and Brettler
argues that it is inaccurate and misleading to refer to such periods as
“eschatological” in the sense of a telos arrived at in a linear temporal
progression. While the Bible does not explicitly address the many
questions that arise when one juxtaposes a prophetic future time
ANCIENT TIME ACROSS TIME 7
newer one that “always is” —-the Theogony recounts the process by
which the eternally present Zeus actually manipulates time by incar-
cerating the older gods (who represent past time) under the earth
while physically ingesting the potential for a future time, namely,
Zeus’s offspring. Hesiod is able to conceptualize time as something
that can be contained, whether it be in the vessel of Zeus’s body or
in a prison beneath the earth. If all this seems rather poetic and
remote from the lived reality of ancient Greece, Purves astutely dis-
cusses how in his other great poem, Works and Days—a very different
sort of effort set in the form of a didactic “farmer’s almanac’—
Hesiod can again use concrete spatial metaphors of containment
(jars, pails, granaries) to describe time, but here in the context of
agriculture and household management. While the temporal cycles
of the natural world (days, seasons) recur in a predictable, seemingly
endless, fashion, Hesiod’s farmer, like Zeus himself in the Theogony,
can intervene and exercise some control over the effects of time on
his own life.
One area in which all ancient cultures struggled to control
and organize time was in chronography, the very practical business of
keeping records, dating events, marking historical intervals, and
periodizing their own histories. Each of the cultures examined in this
collection developed idiosyncratic methods of situating themselves
relative to a past and present (and sometimes even to a future), and
each had to confront the question of how to construct chronological
reference points. Astrid Moller tells the fascinating story of how
ancient Greek chronography came to adopt the foundation of the
Olympic games as their chief chronographical reference point. The
5th century BCE sophist, Hippias of Elis, is generally credited with
attempting to synchronize historical events in relation to the
Olympic games, though the question of whether he actually fixed the
traditional foundation date of the games to what we would call 776
BCE remains unresolved, given the insufficient state of our evidence
(no parts of an actual text of Hippias’s alleged treatise on the
Olympic games survive). Despite. a scholarly tradition that takes a
ANCIENT TIME ACROSS TIME 9
lar transformation that occurred in the first half of the 2nd millenni-
um BCE in northern Europe, a period toward the middle of the
Bronze Age that witnessed various changes in agricultural organiza-
tion, including the more intensive use of land, increasing population,
and the general emergence of longer-lived nucleated settlements.
The terms structure and agency are used widely enough and in such
divergent ways that any brief employment here risks confusion.
However, these terms provide the means to avoid the pitfalls so far
identified—my argument has been that the concept of process in
archaeology has little if any explanatory value. Process is simply the
map of patterns of continuity and changes in events through time.
Attempts to extend the concept of process to incorporate genera-
tive procedures result in a reification where the appearance of mate-
rial change becomes an expression of the real force of historical
change. The failure of this reasoning is witnessed simply by the fact
that we still have so little idea about the processes behind the ori-
gins of agriculture, chiefdoms, or the state. These may be big ques-
tions, but the big answers have been slow in coming, In their place
we are presented with tautologies which simply state that for such
systems to emerge, the conditions by which they are defined have to
exist. Events and processes are ways of charting the conditions of
human existence through time and nothing more; they are descrip-
tive.
Agency on the other hand makes things happen, interven-
ing in the world by converting energy and doing work, and it makes
TEMPORALITY AND THE STUDY OF PREHISTORY 21
that these graves are normally reopened and are used for a short
sequence of inhumations, sometimes with the additions of crema-
tions. Located as single and distinctive points in the landscape, the
graves therefore mapped unique sequences of relationships between
those included in the graves and relationships of close affinity or of
difference, depending upon their location, among those assigned to
neighboring or more distant plots.
None of this material belongs to the Middle Bronze Age,
that period in which we begin to see the clearest evidence for more
intensive agricultural systems and longer-lived settlements, all of
which may represent the changes in land tenure suggested by Earle.
None of this material seems to relate directly to agricultural practice
either. My argument is that these changes in the treatment of the
dead, often analyzed as a process of changing burial rites and indica-
tive of the emergence of social hierarchies, may have had an even
more profound historical implication. These mechanisms, the dis-
placement of the dead community and the sequential linking of
funerary rites to a lineage of earlier activities, may all have been
among the local and specific strategies by which it was possible to
formulate changes in the conceptions of temporality. These were not
so much intellectual advances as the practical realization that the
past, separated from the present, was also linked to it by the lineal
flow of time. Along this trajectory some mediation between the past
and present was possible, perhaps in funerary rites, but also perhaps
in terms of the transference of rites across generations which may in
turn have allowed clearer lines of tenurial rights to have been demar-
cated. If the Middle Bronze Age required these changes to have been
put in place, then it arose not as the planned but as the unintended
consequences of the temporal practices in the centuries that preced-
ed it.”
References
one, he worked out how many minutes of life he had left and appor-
tioned his remaining time (using a nearby church clock) into several
minutes thinking about the wonder of the world, several minutes
thinking about his own life, and the last few minutes getting ready for
death. One of his thoughts in the later minutes was if he survived that
he would try to live his life at a similar level of intensity. He was
reprieved (a typical Tsarist trick which sent some people mad with
relief) and of course did not live the whole of his life with similar
intensity. Dostoyevsky’s work was a significant inspiration for the
existentialist movements of the 20th century, which focused on the
nature of human relationships with the world, especially alienation.
His, and their, point was that time contracts and dilates so that not
all minutes are equal in experience even though, by definition, each
60 seconds is the same when measured by a clock.
Dostoyevsky’s experience of time was a general human
experience of time ebbing and flowing pushed to a cruel extreme. If
all human life consists of periods of different length and impact of
experience, of hours that fly by unnoticed or minutes that creep, we
need to ask why these differences occur. Considering time more
broadly we become aware that many cultures have different means of
thinking and speaking about time: people who face the past with
their backs to the future; those who see time as moving in cycles
rather than in a linear fashion; the idea that ancestors and their
actions are both infinitely removed in time, but also present in the
contemporary world.
In a lucid and clear exposition of different conceptions of
time Gell (1992) concludes that although people represent time very
differently around the world, there is in fact only one time, which is
that of the Western physicist or time-and-motion expert, linear and
measurable. Gell’s view privileges representations and ways of talk-
ing about time, and this is valuable.
Cartographers have engaged in much useful study into the
history of map making, looking at the changing conventions used to
depict space. A similar exercise is needed charting the history of
SHAPING LIFE IN THE LATE PREHISTORIC AND ROMANO-BRITISH PERIODS 31
things are given is also vital: to return a gift too soon looks like a
refusal of the relationship; to act too late makes the relationship seem
unimportant. Judging the occasion and timing of a return gift is at
least as important to the style and impact of the transaction as decid-
ing what to give. Rivalries and attachments have their own forms of
timing. There are, of course, long-term forms of temporality. Old
sites in a landscape may be known through continuous memory of
them held in oral or written form. Their origins may be lost in the
mists of time, but invented anew through the creation of myth and
legend. Or they may be ignored altogether as irrelevant to the work-
ings of the contemporary world. Claims to land or legitimacy are
often made through links to earlier generations and the marks they
have left on the landscape. The Normans in Britain pursued the
opposite strategy, constructing large, stone churches on the sites of
smaller wooden Anglo-Saxon ones or positioning their castles for
maximum social, as well as strategic, effect.
Time has a stratigraphic element to it, ranging from deep
time embedded within the long-term use of the landscape and the
marks that previous generations have left on the landscape to the
individual stone-knapper sitting down for half an hour to make a flint
blade. Each of these forms of temporality is calibrated against the
average life span of the individual working out his or her social proj-
ects and the average life history of groups. Each social formation has
its own forms of temporality compounded of a range of times from
the everyday to the longest reach of history and myth. Different
forms of temporality may interact; daily life is partly linked to the
need to provision a longer term cycle of social exchanges and forms
of ritual, so different forms of time may flow well together or clash
discordantly. In all cases, time is not a neutral dimension of social life
but one that takes its values from a broader set of social values and is
a quality (or series of qualities) as much as a quantity.
As an example of how these rather abstract points can be
applied in practice, we may briefly examine one archaeological site
in southern Britain, occupied between the Iron Age and Romano-
34 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
British periods. The coming of the Romans has often been seen as the
imposition of foreign values on native British culture, more particu-
larly as the imposition of a Cartesian culture of rectangular buildings,
well-laid-out streets and roads, mass-produced material culture, and
a more orderly sense of time on a native consciousness less rational-
ized and regularized. This view is too simple, as there are complex
continuities as well as changes across the Iron Age-Romano-British
temporal boundary that divides prehistory from history.
“Romanization” is a contested term, but an emerging con-
sensus is that all members of the Roman Empire participated in the
construction of Roman culture, rather than having it imposed upon
them. The argument is best stated by Woolf (1998) in Becoming Roman
in Gaul, the title of the book reflecting the belief that Roman identi-
ty was a state of becoming rather than being. “Gauls were not ‘assim-
ilated’ to a pre-existing social order, but participated in the creation
of a new one” (Woolf 1997: 347).
Roman culture was an entity created anew in different parts
of the empire at different times, through the actions of all groups,
and it was not just native peoples who were being Romanized
through the expansion of empire, but also the Romans themselves. If
the Romanization of Britain concerned the use that was made of the
new cultural resources offered by the empire we should look at the
combination of existing social logics and the shape given them
through participation in the empire. Time being a vital element of
the social process as a whole provides us with a diagnostic of social
change, so the creation of time through shaping the landscape can
lead to an understanding of the novel qualities given to time after the
Roman invasion of 43 CE.
Landscapes are created through repeated human actions,
and the landscapes of prehistoric Britain were replete with signs of
human action. Ditches and pits were dug, banks and ramparts con-
structed since the Neolithic period. By the period we are examining,
which encompasses the late Bronze Age to the Romano-British peri-
od (the late Bronze Age lasts between roughly 1100 to 750 BCE, fol-
SHAPING LIFE IN THE LATE PREHISTORIC AND ROMANO-BRITISH PERIODS 35
lowed by the Iron Age which ends with the Roman invasion in 43
CE), digging and mounding were ancient traditions but were start-
ing to be deployed in new ways. Large ditch systems, so-called linear
ditches, were constructed in many areas of Britain to divide territo-
ries for reasons that we do not clearly understand. The tradition of
constructing and maintaining linears lasted some thousand years
until the Romano-British period. Ditches such as these, the longest
of which stretch some 13 km, had not only to be dug, but also
cleared regularly as water and frost eroded their sides. These features
of the landscape may have names attached to them, perhaps of ances-
tral significance, and would have been part of the temporal round of
maintaining the landscape.
Beginning in the late Bronze Age hilltops came to be
enclosed, initially by relatively small ditches and banks, some of
which were later enlarged in the Iron Age to become what we know
as hillforts, with relatively massive ramparts and ditches which often
underwent alteration. Originally seen primarily as defensive sites, as
the name hillfort implies, these are now more generally viewed as
sites which make a statement in the landscape to help assert social
claims and to support power. I would also add that the effort of con-
structing these sites, the regular forms of maintenance, and work on
the sites were as important as their final forms. In some sites, such as
the famous Maiden Castle, there seems to have been regular small
alterations to the ramparts, due to the dumping of soil in small
amounts and it seems that the activity of construction may have been
as important as the end result (Sharples 1991). The sites of late pre-
historic southern Britain are often impressive features in themselves,
which look to us to be relatively static and enduring. This should not
blind us to the fact that it was actions of construction and reconstruc-
tion that may have been as important as their final form, the sites
requiring regular and repeated work, all part of the temporality of
the landscape.
The transition from the prehistoric to the Romano-British
landscape is often seen as due to the imposition of new forms and
36 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
enclosure ditch of Alfred’s Castle, ditchV, and that its end had been
packed with chalk where it was cut, presumably to give the appear-
ance of unbroken chalk along the side of the enclosure ditch.
Ditch II ran across the southern side of the site and was
investigated through the trenches in area C, it was relatively shallow,
but of the same flat-bottomed profile as ditch I. A terminus to the
ditch was discovered at its eastern end, where it reduced its width by
half, from 2 m to 1 m, and then ended. At its western end ditch II
was cut through by the enclosure ditch, ditchV, which made use of
the line of the earlier ditch but was much more massive than it. The
linear was again packed with clean chalk where the enclosure ditch
cut it, again presumably to give an appearance of an unbroken line of
chalk along the side of the enclosure ditch, as with ditch I. Although
we have no definite evidence, ditches I and II appear to have been
converging on the southwest corner of the small enclosure of
Alfred’s Castle. The line of these ditches was made use of in con-
structing the enclosure, although the enclosure ditch, ditch V,
enlarged the existing linears. Alfred’s Castle may have been con-
structed at a point in the landscape already picked out as significant
by the meeting of two linears.
Cut partially into the fill of ditch I and slightly to one side
of it was a smaller V-shaped ditch (ditch IV), approximately 1 meter
deep and recut at least once, following the line of the linear ditch
toward the small enclosure. Ditch IV was dug after ditch I had fully
silted up and could only have formed an ephemeral mark on the
landscape. Trench 10 contained an indication of a possible ring ditch
of an earlier barrow cut by ditch IV, and it may have been that the late
Bronze Age linear (ditch I) had been aligned on an earlier barrow at
this point.
On the eastern side of the site in area A a series of trench-
es was dug to reveal two and sometimes three ditches—called col-
lectively ditch III. At some points these were separate and sometimes
they cut each other, suggesting a number of phases of cutting, silting,
and recutting of ditches. The ditches were aligned on an earlier
SHAPING LIFE IN THE LATE PREHISTORIC AND ROMANO-BRITISH PERIODS 39
here was substantially different in character and may have been only
of a single phase. It also demonstrated that the break in the rampart
was not original but had been made in the Romano-British period
with Romano-British pottery, hobnails, and other artifacts in the
upper fills of the ditch, together with substantial amounts of sarsen
stones, probably pushed down from the rampart to form a consoli-
dated surface.
Pits and postholes within the enclosure in trench 1 were also
filled with Romano-British material. This activity is related to the
building and use of a Romano-British villa house which was construct-
ed inside the small enclosure in the late 1st century CE, thus continu-
ing links to the past and extending the sequence of the site into the 3rd
century CE when the building was abandoned. Despite the name
Alfred’s Castle, there is no evidence of post-Roman activity at the site.
The main evidence of Romano-British occupation of
Alfred’s Castle is a stone building in the center of the enclosure
(Figure 2.2). This building was excavated over two seasons.
Excavations revealed the building to be relatively small and centrally
located within the enclosure and of a type which might best be
described as a “villa house” (Henig and Booth 2000:82, fig. 4.2). The
building was made up of six rooms, five of which were probably con-
structed in the late 1st or early 2nd centuries and the final one, at the
southwestern end, was a later addition, probably in the 3rd century,
not long before the building was allowed to collapse.
Walls 2005 and 2008 were constructed later than the outer
walls, to form new rooms, but probably are not much later in date.
The building lacked a corridor, although it is just possible that it was
originally an ailsed building, with internal divisions created slightly
later in its history. Two large sarsens at either ends of wall 2008
might have formed supports for the bases of posts.
Wall plaster and window glass were recovered, but there
was no trace of a mosaic pavement or a hypocaust, indicating that
although the building was a substantial stone structure, it was not
especially rich or well-appointed.
A
‘
\
1 oN
1
8 i
\
Ditch Il \
(large enclosure)
s|
Ditch | @4
(linear) tt.
+c SS
7 ing ditch
AREA A of
oo ae
aft
Ditch V
ring ditch cy, (small enclosure}
eg
Ditch IV
(large enclosure) [°s
21
0 25 50 75 100
lame ————raessssseeel-—-—-| Metres
There were a mass of Iron Age pits and other features under
the villa house, and where walls had been laid over pits their tops had
been filled with sarsen packing, indicating an awareness of the earli-
er features on the site on the part of the later inhabitants.
A number of ancillary structures was found in the area
around the house, made of sarsen and tile, some of which exhibited
evidence of craft and agricultural activities, such as a crucible found
in sarsen structure at the northern end of trench 5. The villa house
represented a local center of the agricultural economy, as well as
linking into the wider Roman world through buying a range of arti-
facts from both local and more distant parts of the Roman Empire.
In summary, the site of Alfred’s Castle provides evidence of
long-term, if discontinuous, use. From the alignment of late Bronze
linear ditches and early Iron Age V-shaped ditches on earlier Bronze
Age round barrows and the construction of the enclosure of Alfred’s
Castle along the line of two linear ditches, the creators of the site
have showed considerable awareness of the past. This awareness con-
tinued into the Romano-British period with the construction of a
substantial stone building in the middle of the enclosure, the creation
of a break through the rampart, and the filling in of the enclosure
ditch to create a new entrance. The new stone house, although mod-
est by the more general standards of Roman Britain, would have
been an obvious and visible statement on the Berkshire Downs and
we feel that it is no coincidence that this statement was made within
an earlier enclosure. Just as there was a break in time between the
construction of round barrows and the digging of the linear ditch, so
there was a gap between the early and middle Iron Age occupation of
the Alfred’s Castle enclosure and the late 1st century CE building.
This discontinuity makes the link with the past that the building sig-
nalled more intriguing rather than less.
The material world is an important source of emotions,
and the values we attach to people cannot be understood without
looking at the values deriving from the things that were important
to them. Repeated actions and links to the past through memory or
SHAPING LIFE INTHE LATE PREHISTORIC AND ROMANO-BRITISH PERIODS 43
References
foremost was Ashur, the historic religious and cultural capital of the
empire, after which its tutelary deity was named. In 879 BCE king
Ashurnasirpal II moved the political capital north to Kalhu, and just
before 700 Sennacherib relocated to Nineveh. Before these cities fell
to the Medes and the Babylonians as the empire collapsed in
614—612 BCE all three were the focus of lavish spending, particular-
ly on their temples and palaces—and on the personnel attached to
those institutions.
The Assyrian court comprised not only political and mili-
tary officials and advisers but also men of learning, ummanu, whose
fields of expertise were vast, ranging from religion to science, from
medicine to magic. These elite literati depended almost entirely, it
seems, on royal patronage to keep them in housing and employment,
creating a highly competitive atmosphere which drove intellectual
innovation as they fought among themselves for preferment. As the
rulers were particularly concerned with determining the gods’ will
by means of terrestrial and celestial omens, there were especially
strong motives to improve the predictability of key celestial events
(Leichty 1993; Brown 2000a:33—52). Lunar and solar eclipses were
particularly portentous for king and country. The scholars of celes-
tial omens held the title tupshar enuma anu ellil (“scribe of ‘When the
gods Anu and Ellil’”), after the first line of the major compilation of
omens, which ran to 70 or more tablets and is so vast that it still has
not been published in its entirety (Rochberg 2000; Hunger and
Pingree 1999:12—20, 32-50).
The sudden destruction of the scholars’ homes and work-
places has left us with their personal and official libraries of scholar-
ly works—some newly composed, some carefully copied from
ancient originals, some recast or commented upon (Pedersen
1998:132—65). They range from historical and historiographical
works to literary and mythological compositions, from hymns and
ritual instructions to medical and astronomical compendia. The
palaces have also yielded their reports to, and correspondence with,
their kingly patrons, giving unparalleled opportunities to compare
TIME IN ASSYRIA AND BaABYLONIA, C.750—250 BCE 47
allowed. The approach adopted here may appear eclectic but it sim-
ply attempts to replicate the wide-ranging interests of the ancients
themselves.
The great Epic of Creation enuma elish (“When Above”) was recited
on the fourth day of the akitu, or equinoctial festival, held on the
eleven days after the first new moon of the spring equinox at the
beginning of the year (Bidmead 2002). At the city of Uruk during
the Seleucid period it was held at the autumnal equinox, the mid-
point of the year. In Babylonia the god Marduk was both the focal
point of the festival and the hero and sole audience of the epic; in
Assyria it was Ashur. The equinoctial recital of the Epic was not only
a marker of passing time; it both described and initiated “the irrup-
tion of primordial—and hence dangerous or sacred—time in to
mundane time, an irruption that both threaten[ed] and enriche[d]
the cosmic order” (Sommer 2000:82). For on the day of the akitu
following its performance, Marduk’s temple Esangila was ritually
destroyed, purified, and rebuilt, symbolizing the abolition and
renewal of the whole cosmic order, with the person of the king at
its center, after which the king’s right to rule was reaffirmed by
Marduk (or Ashur) himself.
The Epic describes the creation of the world of the
gods, in which time passes unquantified, and the hero god’s
destruction of the forces of chaos and evil in the form of the
monstrous sea Tiamat. From her lifeless body he creates the
world in which human beings are to dwell. Thus chaos is always
immanent in the world, a constant counter-force to the orderli-
ness imposed by Marduk. In the sky he positions the heavenly
bodies and sets them in regular motion to define and structure
the year:
Figure 3.1 The god Marduk, tutelary deity of Babylon and hero of the Epic
of Creation, with his snake-dragon. The image is from the god’s own cylin-
der seal, carved from lapis lazuli and dedicated to him by a Babylonian king
of the 9th century BCE. From F H. Weissbach, Babylonische Miscellen.
Leipzig: Hinrichs, 1903, fig. 1.
TIME IN ASSYRIA AND BABYLONIA, C.750—250 BCE 51
Path of Ellil, father of the gods (to the north of Path of Anu). Each
“astrolabe” assigns a slightly different group of stars to each Path
(an example is given in Table 3.1).
Later astronomical works built upon this scheme, includ-
ing the widely attested two-tablet compilation of celestial informa-
tion now known as MUL.APIN (“Plough Star”), which reached its
final form by about 700 BCE but was still copied for centuries
after that (Hunger and Pingree 1989:271—77). We also see Marduk
closely associated with the Pole Star throughout the scholarly tra-
dition, for instance in Astrolabe B: “the red star which stands at the
rising of the south wind after the gods of the night have finished
their duties and divides the heavens: this star is the Pole Star,
Marduk” (section B, ii, 29-32; Horowitz 1998:159).
Marduk’s next act in the Epic of Creation is to create the moon,
giving it detailed instructions on how to demarcate the lunar month:
Sources: Astrolabe B, VAT 9416 (KAV 218), section B. The most recent
discussion of “astrolabes” is Hunger and Pingree (1999:50—63); see also
Horowitz (1998:154-66). For identifications of constellations and star
names, see Hunger and Pingree (1989:271—77).
Figure 3.2 A circular star map from Nineveh dividing the night sky into
eight and illustrating the most prominent constellations. From L. W. King,
Cuneiform Texts from Babylonian Tablets, &c., in the British
Museum 33. London: Trustees of the British Museum, 1912, pl. 10.
TIME IN ASSYRIA AND BABYLONIA, C.750—250 BCE 55
Only after he has set time in motion does Marduk create the natural
world itself and then mankind (Tablets V and VI; cf. Dalley
1989:255-67).
The Epic of Creation embodies two conflicting ways of mark-
ing present time: Marduk orders to the moon and the “three stars
each” to operate an ideal calendar of twelve 30-day months, making
a year of 360 days. But the real lunar calendar—in which each day
began at sunset, the start of each month was designated by the first
sighting of the new moon 29 or 30 nights since the last one, and the
year started with the new moon after the spring equinox—averages
just 354 days. And of course the solar year, at 365 1/4 days, is longer
than either. It was a major scholarly endeavor to keep the lunar cal-
endar in line with the solar year and to reconcile them both to the
ideal year that the gods had decreed. Shortfalls in the real calendar
were seen as a divine indicator of the real world’s shortcomings in
attaining godly standards of perfection. But the ideal calendar was
not only understood to have been divinely ordained by the god
Marduk: it was also administratively convenient. Temple records
from the city of Uruk in the late 4th millennium BCE are already
witness to a 360-day year of 12 30-day months, and this remained
the accounting norm throughout the 3rd millennium and beyond
(Englund 1988; 1991).
However, in reality about a half of the months of the year
were only 29 days long: in Babylonian parlance the first day of the
month was turru (turned back) instead of kunnu (firm) as it should
have been. Assyrian and Babylonian scholars expended much energy
and ingenuity in predicting month lengths, as witnessed by reports
to kings as well as collections of prediction rules (Brack-Bernsen
2002). Thirty-day months were considered much more auspicious
than their 29-day counterparts, as can be seen in the omens which
scholars to the Assyrian court typically associated with sightings of
the new moon (Beaulieu 1993). Compare the chief scribe Issar-
shumu-eresh’s upbeat assessment for a new month after 30 days: “If
the moon becomes visible on the Ist day: reliable speech; the land
56 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
will become happy,” with his more cautionary “If the moon becomes
visible on the 30th day: there will be frost, variant: rumour of the
enemy” (Hunger 1992:10—11).
Babylonian temples too needed to adjust their cultic cycle,
moving clothing ceremonies and animal sacrifices forward or back-
ward a day according to the length of the month (Beaulieu 1993;
Robbins 1996). Here, for instance, is a priest of the sun-god Shamash
in the 6th century city of Larsa writing to his superior (“father”) at
Eana in nearby Uruk: “Tablet of Shamash-idri to the administrator
my father. May Shamash and Bunene decree the well-being and
health of my father. We heard the report concerning the turning-back
of the (first) day. Shamash will be clothed on the 15th day (intead of
the 14th). May the lord send whatever (is needed) for (that) day. May
the lord (also) send a weaver and a clothes-washer” (NCBT 58;
Beaulieu 1993:77—78).
It was imperative that the temples retain the ideal calendri-
cal cycle of the gods in the face of the vagaries of real-world lunation
and that meant maintaining the rhythms of ritual whatever the pro-
fane reality.
Eleven days difference between the lunar and solar year also
required regular readjustment to keep the months in line with the
seasons and the new year in line with the spring equinox.
Intercalation, or addition of an extra month after the sixth or twelfth
month, was for most of Assyrian and Babylonian history carried out
on an ad hoc basis, by royal proclamation following scholarly advice.
Here the tupshar enuma anu ellil Balasi advises king Esarhaddon in
early 670 BCE on the need to intercalate: “Concerning the adding of
the intercalary month about which the king my lord wrote to me,
this is indeed an intercalary year. After Jupiter has become visible |
shall write again to the king my lord. I am waiting for it, but it will
take the whole month. Then we shall see how it is and when we have
to add the intercalary month” (Parpola 1993:42).
The astronomical compendium MUL.APIN contains two
simple schemes for intercalation, based on observing celestial phe-
TIME IN ASSYRIA AND BABYLONIA, C.750—250 BCE 57
April 311 BCE); year names now took the form “Year 97, Antiochus
was king (214-3 BCE)” (Hunger and Pingree 1999:xiii).The 19-year
intercalation cycle continued to be used. The units and arithmetical
models with which the scholars measured the passing of time are
well understood (Brown 2000b; Hunger 2001) even if the physical
means by which they did so are not (Brown et al. 1999-2000;
Fermor and Steele 2000).
20 Unfavorable Unfavorable
pared to 11 in the first half. Neither are the gods’ good graces spread
evenly across the months: the 3rd day of the month was favorable
only twice a year, while the Ist, 15th, and 22nd of the month were
each favorable in 9 months out of 12 (Labat 1941:20—21). These 3
days are closely linked to the ideal lunar cycle as decreed by Marduk
in the Epic of Creation. The Assyrian royal hemerology is even called
enbu bel arhi (“New Moon, Lord of the Month”).
Independent of a day’s favorable or unfavorable aspect was
its dangerous or evil character, which was unchanging from month
to month. Early hemerologies counted 9 unfavorable days a month,
but by the period we are dealing with there were just 5: the 7th,
14th, 19th, 21st, and 28th. On these days almost all activity was for-
bidden by the gods, except those relating to mourning and penitence
(Labat 1939:44). It is striking that 4 of the 5 days are multiples of 7,
and can once again be related to the key moments of the lunar cycle:
the day before the full moon, the day before disappearance, and the
2 half-way points in between. It has also been suggested that the 19th
day acquired its dangerous character from that fact that it is 7 x 7 =
49 days since the last new moon (Labat 1939:45). In the Nineveh-
Babylon hemerology mentioned above, there were no favorable yet
dangerous days in the months of Simanu (Month III) and Abu (Month
V), yet in Tashritu (Month VII) and Shabatu (Month XI) all the dan-
gerous days were considered favorable. On average two or three days
a month were both favorable and dangerous at the same time.
Although no edition of enbu bel arhi has yet been published
(see Landsberger 1915; Livingstone 1999:137), there is a contempo-
rary royal menology, or list of ominous months for kingly activity,
which bore the title igqur ipush (“He Destroyed, He Built”). It exists
in two different versions, one ordered primarily by activity, the other
taking that same material and reordering it by month (Labat 1965).
Interestingly in the light of Esarhaddon’s concern over Ashur’s tem-
ple, the first 33 sections of the first version all concern the founda-
tion and restoration of temples and cultic objects:
TIME IN ASSYRIA AND BABYLONIA, C.750—250 BCE 67
Anyway, the king, my lord, should not worry about this por-
tent. The gods Bel (Marduk) and Nabu can make a portent
pass by, and they will make it pass by the king, my lord. The
king, my lord should not be afraid. (Parpola 1993:141)
the king, my lord. It is a dark day today, so I did not include a bless-
ing. The eclipse moved from the east and settle over the entire west.
Jupiter and Venus were present during the eclipse until it cleared.
For the king my lord all is well; it is evil for Amurru. Tomorrow |
shall send the king my lord a written report on this lunar eclipse”
(Parpola 1993:75).
Because the eclipse pointed westward its influence would
be felt in Amurru, to the west of Assyria, and once more the king and
country were safe. If, however, the eclipse should unequivocally por-
tend ill for Assyria itself, fate had to be averted. A substitute king was
crowned and while the real king was ritually purified with lengthy
and complicated ritual called bit rimki (“Bath House”) (Laessoe 1955;
Borger 1967). Here the Babylonian scholar Mar-Issar reports in
Ululu (Month X) 671 BCE on the successfully averted evil of a lunar
eclipse to Esarhaddon, who underwent bit rimki at least four times in
his eleven-year reign: “The substitute king, who on the 14th sat on
the throne in Nineveh and spent the night of the 15th in the royal
palace, and on whom the eclipse took place, entered the city of
Akkad safely on the night of the 20th and sat upon the throne. I made
him recite the scribal recitations before the sun-god Shamash, he
took all the celestial and terrestrial omens on himself, and ruled all
the countries. The king, my lord, should know this” (Parpola
1993:351).
Sometimes, however, eclipses were not observed as pre-
dicted, but that did not necessarily mean that there was no danger.
Either a positive sign of temporal normality was needed, or the full
period of danger had to be endured, as Adad-shumu-usur here
explains to Esarhaddon in 669 BCE: “As regards the substitute king
about whom the king, my lord, wrote to me: ‘how many days should
he sit on the throne?’, we waited for a solar eclipse, (but) the eclipse
did not take place. Now, if the gods (i.e., sun and moon) are seen in
opposition on the 15th day, he could go to his fate on the 16th. Or if
it suits the king, my lord, better, he could (as well) sit the full 100
days” (Parpola 1993:220).
74 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
Then she gave him the Tablet of Destinies and made him
clasp it to his breast.
“Your utterance shall never be altered! Your word shall be
law!” (Tablet I, 157-58; Dalley 1989:238)
The idea is further elaborated in the Epic of'Anzu, in which the epony-
mous anti-hero, a monstrous lion-eagle, steals the Tablet of Destinies
from his godly master Ellil as he is relaxing in the bath:
The gods are powerless without the Tablet, and Anzu is in com-
plete control of the destiny of the world. Several gods refuse the
challenge of combating Anzu, until the warrior-god Ninurta rises
to the occasion. The two foes engage in a mighty cosmic battle.
Anzu, with the Tablet of Destinies in his possession, is able to
zoyinv ay1 Aq ydvsBoioyg ‘wnasnyy ysiitag ay1 ur Mou ST
pun “4g $9 9 ‘nyyoy Iw vIsnuryy fo afdaiaz ay3 UT pasoeia som a[77Dq ItUISOD aY4 fo Butasvo auojs sty]
‘sajursag fo 1ajqvy ay1 fo uotssassod sof pzInuIN] poB stosay ay1 1yBnof parg nzup ayy «9 aainBr.4
Beri” er
76 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
temple Esangila the Mushezib family and others were closely associ-
ated with one style of predictive model, now called System A, while
at the Resh temple in Uruk the Ekur-zakir and Sin-leqi-unninni fam-
ilies favored the scheme now known as System B (Neugebauer
1955). Both involved the tabulation of a mass of complex calculated
data into ephemeredes, or predictions of the lunar, solar, and plane-
tary positions for the coming year(s), computed according clearly
laid out procedures. But still the rituals to avert the evil of an eclipse
were performed. Predictable events were no less ominous; indeed it
appears that their very predictability led to the performance of more
elaborate apotropaic rituals than before, as one could now be sure
that the expense would not be wasted (Brown and Linssen 1997).
Lunar eclipse rituals from 3rd century Uruk involved massive public
spectacle with drums, wailing, and the singing of Sumerian balang
and ershema laments (Cohen 1988; Black 1991):
On the day of the lunar eclipse they will bring the bronze
halhallatu drum, the bronze manzu drum, and the bronze
kettledrum from the storehouse. . . When the lunar eclipse
begins, the kalus will put on linen garments. . . They raise
lamentations, wailing, and mourning towards the moon in
eclipse. ...
When the eclipse has cleared, they will leave the bronze
kettledrum; they will leave the magic flour circle and the
TIME IN ASSYRIA AND BABYLONIA, C.750—250 BCE 79
References
* Tam very grateful to Fran Reynolds, John Steele, and Niek Veldhuis for
their efforts in making the this chapter more accurate and readable than it would other-
wise have been.
TIME IN ASSYRIA AND BABYLONIA, C.750—250 BCE 83
Wiseman, D. J., and J. A. Black. Literary Texts from the Temple of Nabu.
Cuneiform Texts from Nimrud 4. London: British School
of Archaeology in Iraq, 1996.
CONCEPTS OF TIME IN
CLASSICAL INDIA
Ludo Rocher
Hence all figures mentioned so far are multiplied by 360: the kritayu-
ga lasts 1,728,000 years, the tretayuga 1,296,000 years, the dva-
parayuga 864,000 years, the kaliyuga 432,000 years, and the total of
the four yugas—the caturyuga or mahayuga—lasts 4,320,000 years.
Immediately after the last kaliyuga of the caturyuga, the first
dawn of a new caturyuga sets in, and this process is repeated one
thousand times, without interruption. This period of one thousand
caturyugas, i.e., 4,320,000,000 human years, is given the name of
either kalpa or “day of Brahma.”” A “day of Brahma” is naturally fol-
lowed by a “night of Brahma,” of the same duration, so that one
nychthemeron of Brahma comprises 8,640,000,000 years.
Differently from the shorter time periods (yugas and caturyugas),
which follow each other without interruption, the day of Brahma is
followed by a world destruction (pralaya), and the night of Bralima is
followed by a world creation.
Brahma does not live just nychthemeron. He lives a full life,
and, in ancient India, according to the Rigveda (1.89.9, 1.64.14.,
2.33.2), the ideal life span was considered to be one hundred years.
The life of Brahma (also called mahakalpa), therefore, corresponds to
8,640,000,000 - 360 - 100 = 311,040,000,000,000 human years.
Finally—and here exactitude gives way to speculation—
some texts go on to say that the present Brahma has been preceded
by and will be followed by numerous other Brahmas (Fleet
1911:483, n.1). Or, they say that one life of Brahma is equal to one
day, or to just one eyewink of Vishnu (Burgess and Whitney 1860:
155). Irrespective of the way in which it is justified, the point is that
cyclical time in Hinduism is eternal, without beginning or end (Jones
1788, in Marshall 1970:265).
To complete the picture of cyclical time in Hinduism, we
must note that, along with the yugas, a second system of cycles
evolves. Within each kalpa, i.e., within a period of 1,000 caturyugas,
* Even though Sanskrit words are usually cited in the stem form, I use the
masculine nominative form brahma, to distinguish the god Brahma (stem brahman) from
the neuter abstract principle brahman (nominative brahma).
CONCEPTS OF TIME IN CLASSICAL INDIA 95
(sanvarta), and (4) a kalpa in which the world remains destroyed (san-
vartavasthayin). Differently from Hinduism and from Jainism, the
duration of the mahdkalpas is asankheyya (Pali; Sanskrit asankhyeya)
(“incalculable”) literally “not to be expressed in numbers.” One
favorite description of asankheyya is as follows: “It is as if there were
a mountain consisting of a great rock, a league in length, a league in
width, a league in height, without break, cleft, or hollow, and every
hundred years a man were to come and rub it once with a silken gar-
ment; that mountain consisting of a great rock would more quickly
wear away and come to an end than a world-cycle” (Warren
1896:315,n. 1).
The fact that the incalculable mahakalpas are subdivided into
20 antarakalpas (“intermediate kalpas”) is unimportant for our pres-
ent purpose. What is important is that, within the twentieth and last
antarakalpa of the mahakalpa in which the world remains renovated,
the Buddhists insert 4 brief periods of increase and 4 equally brief
periods of decrease. And these periods are, once again, designated
with the names of the Hindu yugas: kali, dvapara, treta, and krita in an
ascending period, and krita, treta, dvapara, and kali in a descending
sequence.
In other words, even as the Jainas, the Buddhists worked
out a system of cyclical time of their own. Yet, they, too, felt obliged
to reserve a niche to incorporate the Hindu yuga system in it.
Buddhist sources, but must be much older, even though Vedic litera-
ture does not mention it (7).
The fact that world ages and cyclical time in India are old,
that they did not have to wait for the writers of the philosophical
schools to invent them or for the astronomers to borrow them from
sources outside India, is not surprising. As Eliade states, “it would be
difficult to explain why the Indo-Aryans did not also share, from the
period of their common prehistory, the conception of time held by
all primitives” (1949:115; also 1957:177). Given Indians’ propensi-
ty to quantify, it is also not surprising that they amplified the cycles
they perceived around them—day /night, seasons, years—into ever-
larger cycles and that they assigned proportionately higher numbers
to them. What makes Indians unique is the extent to which, at an
early date, they elaborated a system of cyclical time in great detail
(Eliot 1962:334; Schneider 1958:156), and the way—or ways—in
which they made similar but ever larger cycles proceed from human
time to divine time, and from divine time-——even Brahma’s life is
measured—to endless cosmic time.
References
Menninger, Karl. Zahl und Ziffer. Eine Kulturgeschichte der Zahl 2nd
ed. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1957.
Meyer, Hans. “Die Lehre von der ewigen Wiederkehr aller Dinge.”
In Albert M Koniger, ed., Beitrdge zur Geschichte des
christlichen Altertums und der Byzantinischen Literatur. Festgabe
Albert Ehrhard. [Orig. Bonn-Leipzig: Schroeder, 1922]
Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1969, 359-80.
Mill, James. The History of British India 4th ed. Notes and
Annotations by Horace H. Wilson. London: James
Madden, 1840, 1.
Marc Brettler
(1) A time (731) is set for everything, a time (MY) for every
experience under heaven: (2) A time (NY) for being born
and a time (1) for dying, a time (NY) for planting and a
time (WY) for uprooting the planted; (3) a time for slaying
and a time for healing, a time for tearing down and a time
for building up; (4) a time for weeping and a time for laugh-
ing, a time for wailing and a time for dancing; (5) a time for
throwing stones and a time for gathering stones, a time for
embracing and a time for shunning embraces; (6) a time for
seeking and a time for losing, a time for keeping and a time
CYCLICAL AND TELEOLOGICAL TIME IN THE HEBREW BIBLE 113
for discarding; (7) a time for ripping and a time for sewing,
a time for silence and a time for speaking; (8) a time for
loving and a time for hating; a time for war and a time for
peace. (Tanakh 1985, slightly modified)
sea, yet the sea is never full; to the place from which they
flow the streams flow back again. (8) All such things are
wearisome: No man can ever state them; the eye never has
enough of seeing, nor the ear enough of hearing. (9) Only
that shall happen which has happened, only that occur which
has occurred; there is nothing new beneath the sun!
(11) And the Israelites did what was offensive to the Lord.
They worshiped the Baalim (12) and forsook the Lord, the
God of their fathers, who had brought them out of the land
of Egypt. They followed other gods, from among the gods of
the peoples around them, and bowed down to them; they
provoked the Lord. (13) They forsook the Lord and wor-
shiped Baal and the Ashtaroth. (14) Then the Lord was
incensed at Israel, and He handed them over to foes who
plundered them. He surrendered them to their enemies on
all sides, and they could no longer hold their own against
their enemies. (15) In all their campaigns, the hand of the
Lord was against them to their undoing, as the Lord had
declared and as the Lord had sworn to them; and they were
in great distress. (16) Then the Lord raised up chieftains
[others “judges”] who delivered them from those who plun-
dered them. (17) But they did not heed their chieftains
either; they went astray after other gods and bowed down to
them. They were quick to turn aside from the way their
fathers had followed in obedience to the commandments of
the Lord; they did not do right. (18) When the Lord raised
up chieftains for them, the Lord would be with the chieftain
and would save them from their enemies during the chief-
tain’s lifetime; for the Lord would be moved to pity by their
moanings because of those who oppressed and crushed
them. (19) But when the chieftain died, they would again act
basely, even more than the preceding generation—following
other gods, worshiping them, and bowing down to them;
they omitted none of their practices and stubborn ways.
CYCLICAL AND TELEOLOGICAL TIME IN THE HEBREW BIBLE 117
term over a long time period, the understanding of this Day is not
stable, but in general it describes a day in which YHWH, the Israelite
God, is manifest in the world as warrior, sometimes fighting against
Israel, sometimes against Israel’s and His enemies (Paul
1991:182—184). The term appears 16 times (Saebo 1990:29). Much
more frequent is the term N17 DY “that day.” It, too, appears in a
variety of contexts, though it is favored in certain prophetic books,
especially Isaiah (Saebo 1990:16). The phrase is often used, especial-
ly in non-prophetic literature, in its plain sense, referring to a day
mentioned earlier in the narrative (but see Saebg 1990:30), but it
also has a technical, prophetic usage referring to a particular time
period. It often seems to refer to the Day of the LORD (Saebo
1990:30).
It is unlikely that these terms refer to the eschatological
period since Hebrew DY in the singular means “a day,” and is not gen-
erally delexicalized in the sense of a broader period of time. The
expected plural of 8177 OV (“that day”) is TTT /O77 OY (“those
days”). This expression is attested in the Hebrew Bible in both a plain
(Judges 21—25) and a technical sense, but the technical sense of an
ideal future period is rare and is largely confined to Jeremiah (3:16,
18; 5:18; 31:29, 33; 33:15; 50:4, 20; Joel 3:2; 4:1; Zechariah 8:6,
10, 23). Here too, none of these contexts suggests that this time is
an end, since “those days” initiate a long time-period. In other con-
texts 07/2’, “days,” without any pronoun, may also refer to the ideal
future. For example, a secondary addition (Wolff 1977:352—354;
Jeremias 1998:162) concluding the book of Amos describing
restored Israel and idealized agricultural productivity is introduced
O’xd OF” 737, “Look—days are coming.” The conclusion of Amos,
for example, suggests a long continuing period. However, there is
nothing in any of these contexts to suggest that these days were
viewed as an end.
The most familiar term that in the popular perception is
related to eschatology is the English “end of days.” This English term,
however, is an incorrect translation from the Hebrew D773" FINN,
122 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
References
Brin, Gershon, The Concept of Time in the Bible and the Dead Sea
Scrolls. Leiden: Brill, 2001.
Campbell, Antony F., and Mark A. O’Brien. Unfolding the
Deuteronomistic History: Origins, Upgrades, Present Text.
Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press, 2000.
Fox, Michael V. A Time to Tear Down and A Time to Build Up:A Rereading
of Ecclesiastes. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1999.
126 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
David W. Pankenier
first month, there have elapsed 445 jiazi days, and finally
until today one-third of the cycle [of 60].” The officiants [of
the feast] ran to the court to ask about it. Music-master
Kuang said, “It was the year when Shuzhong Hui Bo of Lu
had a meeting with Xi Chengzi in Chengkuang. In that year,
the Di invaded Lu, and Shusun Zhuangshu defeated them at
Xian, capturing their elders Qiaoru, Hui, and Pao, after all
of whom he named his sons. [Hence,] it is 73 years.” (Legge
IX:556, modified)
capable of invoking the whole tapestry. Again, it is not that the two
hexagrams are linked as cause and effect, or that one brings the other
into being. Rather, the one is simultaneously the other like the front
and back of silk brocade.
With this in mind, consider the following explanation of
dynastic prosperity and decline by the late Han scholar and icono-
clast Wang Chong: “When the mandate of heaven [tian ming] is
about to be launched, and a Sage-King is on the point of emerg-
ing, the material forces (qi), before and after the event, give proofs
which will be radiantly manifest” (Hsiao 1979:594). Compare this
with Dong Zhongshu’s view a century and a half earlier: “Your ser-
vant has heard that in heaven’s great conferring of responsibilities
on the king there is something that human powers of themselves
could not achieve, but that comes of itself. This is the sign that the
Mandate [ming] has been granted. The people of the empire with
one heart all turn to him as they would turn to their fathers and
mothers. Thus it is that heaven’s auspicious signs respond to [the
people's] sincerity and come forth.” Even in Wang Chong’s time,
the principle of causality invoked here in relation to auspicious
portents tended to be understood simplistically by “mere prognos-
ticators” in terms of cause and effect: “The errors of the School of
Prognosticators are not in acknowledging the occurrences of
calamities and auspicious happenings, but lie in their erroneous
belief that the successes and failings of government bear a cause
and effect relationship to those.”
According to Wang, however,
While the Trobriand islands are not China, one cannot help
but be struck by the anthropologist’s account of the Trobriander’s
valuation of a particular kind of reality and the homely knitting anal-
ogy. Perhaps in this description of the cultural devaluation of tempo-
EARLY CHINESE THOUGHT 145
References
Bodde, Derk. Chinese Thought, Society, and Science: The Intellectual and
Social Background of Science and Technology in Pre-modern China.
Honolulu, HI: University of Hawaii Press, 1991, 122-33.
Davies, Paul. “That Mysterious Flow.” Scientific American 287, 3
(September 2002):42.
Fagg, Lawrence W. Two Faces of Time. Wheaton, IL: Theosophical
Publishing House, 1985.
Nienhauser,
W. H., ed. The Grand Scribe’s Records 1. The Basic Annals of Pre-
Han China. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1994.
Pankenier, David W. “The Scholar’s Frustration Reconsidered:
Melancholia or Credo?” Journal of the American Oriental
Society 110, 3 (1990):440.
Sima Qian. Shiji. Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1959.
Sivin, Nathan. “Chinese Conceptions of Time.” Earlham Review 1
(1966):82-92,
Wilhelm, Richard. The I Ching or Book of Changes, rendered into
English by Cary F. Baynes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1981.
1 @e
TTOPOGRAPHIES OF TIME
IN HESIOD
Alex Purves
n the late 8th century BCE, two poems attributed to the Greek
| poet Hesiod approached the structure and order of time from
two different points of view. In the Theogony, an epic poem
describing the evolution of the cosmos, Hesiod presents time as a lin-
ear construct, plotted upon a genealogical, diachronic history that
runs from the birth of the gods to the present order of the universe.
In the Works and Days, a didactic poem that instructs the reader on the
correct way to manage a farm and a household, the poet focuses on
the circular motion of time, as it is relayed through the cyclical pat-
tern of seasons, months, and days. The two different temporalities
that these poems engage in are in large part prescribed by their
marked difference in genre; epic time will necessarily run according
to a different logic than didactic, just as historical time will flow at a
different rate to seasonal time (Strohm 2000:80—96; Koselleck
1985; Nowotny 1994). But while the temporalities of the two poems
are largely separate, they also converge to offer new insights on, and
new approaches to, the Hesiodic conception and construction of
time.
148 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
Throughout the Works and Days, Hesiod urges his audience to look
forward consistently to, and to provide for, the unforeseeable
future. There is a need, in other words, to ration out the pres-
ent—to spread it thin over the less productive seasons of the year.
The poet recommends doing this by storing up grain and wine in
large jars (called variously trifot and Gyyea), which—along with
a well-stocked granary—should only be broken open at certain
specified times (cf. Works and Days 30-32, 93, 306-307, 361-63,
368-69, 411-12, 475, 498-504, 819). During his account of the
threshing season, the poet advises the farmer to “transfer your
grain into jars, using a measuring scoop/ Then store all your
livelihood up and lock it in the house” (Works and Days 600-601),
just as, during the vintage season, he calls for the farmer to draw
wine into jars [eis Gyye’ aqvoai and preserve it for a later date
(Works and Days 613—14).
Through the simple, everyday mechanism of the jar,
Hesiod takes steps toward dividing time into the separate cate-
gories of past, present, and future. Its space thus serves as a “hold-
ing bay” for the present, or for the present-as-yet-unspent, a kind
of container of time. This is not unlike Salman Rushdie’s compar-
ison of time to chutney in Midnight’s Children (1980), whose nar-
rator cooks pickles by day and writes history by night. As he puts
it: “by day amongst the pickle-vats, by night within these sheets,
I spend my time at the great work of preserving. Memory, as well
as fruit, is being saved from the corruption of the clocks” (38).
Hesiod too, in his book about the management not of history but
of the continuous cycle of the year, comments on the practice of
“archiving”—-of preserving what in the present will soon be “past”
for a new time in the future.
In his narration of the story of Pandora, near the begin-
ning of the Works and Days, Hesiod expands upon the temporal
significance of the jar. For it is in opening the pithos given to her
by Zeus that Pandora creates a new space in time, what Hesiod
elsewhere calls the “iron age” of men:
TTOPOGRAPHIES OF TIME IN HESIOD 153
[For before that time, the race of men who lived upon the earth
Were far from evils, grievous toil,
And the baneful diseases which bring death to men.
But the woman removed the great lid of the jar with her hands,
Scattering them all. And she brought hard sorrows to mankind.
Hope alone remained there in its well-built house,
It stayed inside the jar, beneath the lip, nor did it fly outside
Before she put the lid of the jar back on,
By the plan of aegis-bearing, cloud-gathering Zeus.]
(Works and Days 90-99)
Pucci 1977:22—27; Cole 1983; Vernant 1983), in one direction, and hope
in the other, two factors that, for Hesiod, symbolize the mortal condition,
or “iron age” (Works and Days 986-87; Pucci 1977:103—105). It is hope
alone that remains for humans, trapped within the rim of Pandora’s jar.
Hesiod’s insistent reminder to preserve for the future thus
reads as a corrective to Pandora’s act, by ensuring that the lid of the
farmer’s jar is not opened before its time: “open a jar on the fourth
day” (Works and Days 819-20), “Satisfy yourself from the jar at the
beginning and end / But hold off in the middle” (368—69), “So the
ripe ears of corn may nod towards the ground/ If Olympian Zeus
should grant you such a fortunate outcome in the future/ And then
you may brush the cobwebs from your storage jars” (473—75). As
Hesiod explains it, hope is a deceptive means of providing for the
future, because it obscures the crucial difference between that which
still is (€11) and that which always is (aiet):
his reading excludes, quite forcefully, all hints of the shadow or depth
that emerge from what he calls “the darkness of the past”: “Homer
will not [let Odysseus’s scar] appear out of the darkness of an unillu-
minated past; it must be set in full light. . . Never is there a form left
fragmentary or half-illuminated, never a lacuna, never a gap, never a
glimpse of unplumbed depths” (6—7).
A similar resistance to the spatial “layering” of time can be
found in the work of the Polish Classicist Thaddaeus Zielinski,
whose treatment of plot in ancient epic is founded upon the con-
cept of events stretched out upon a single, two-dimensional plane.
In 1901, Zielinski formulated a law, still generally accepted today,
that Greek epic never presents two events as if they occurred
simultaneously. Rather than traversing the same temporal space
twice, archaic epic instead conceives of simultaneous actions con-
secutively, as if they occurred one after the other. By eliminating
the concept of “meanwhile” from the Homeric lexicon, Zielinski’s
theory refutes the possibility of epic time occupying transverse or
“horizontal” space (a conception of time that has since been
explored by scholars such as Benjamin 1968:261 and Anderson
1991:22-31). He based his findings on what he termed the eye’s
inability to apprehend multiple dimensions of time and space at
once: “So ist mein Sehn aus einem dreiplanigen plotzlich ein ein-
planiges geworden: die neu hinzugetretene Dimension der Zeit hat
die Raumdimension der Tiefe verdrangt” [Thus my vision suddenly
becomes one-dimensional from three: the newly-added dimension
of time has replaced the spatial dimension of depth] (Zielinski
1901:409).
Like Auerbach, Zielinski proposes that there is no “depth” to
time. This provides the basis for his larger claim that poetry, like aes-
thetics, cannot conceive of the simultaneous events of a plot in par-
allel space (Zielinski 1901:414). By focusing so exclusively on the
singularity of the present, Zielinski paved the way for other scholars
of his generation and after, such as Frankel (1968) and Page (1955),
who argued that in archaic epic, time had no three-dimensionality, or
158 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
[[Ouranos] would not let them come up into the light, but hid them all
Within the passages of the earth.] (Theogony 157-58)
the narrative may resolve the complexities of its own transferal from
one perception of time to another and within which it may even con-
fine these complexities, in much the same way as Zeus uses it as a
space to restrain and confine the Titans.
Located as far underground as it takes for an anvil to fall for
nine days, Tartaros is encircled by an impenetrable wall of bronze,
three layers of darkness, and the backward-flowing streams of the
river Ocean. In keeping with its circular and static geography, Hesiod
describes Tartaros in language that cycles through a series of repeti-
tions which either follow too closely upon one another (Theogony
722—S) or, atypically for the poet (Sellschopp 1967), replay without
variation (736—9 = 807-10). Both narratologically and topographi-
cally, therefore, the underworld is a place without progress or devel-
opment through time. Instead, it is bound by the laws of stasis and
repetition. In some cases, as with the exchange of Night and Day
across its threshold (Theogony 748—54), that repetition validates the
cyclical, natural patterns of time in the world above. But for those
trapped within the walls of Tartaros, there is explicitly no exit, no
“place” for time to go (Theogony 732, 772). The Underworld is thus,
in both cases, the site of repetition, but repetition without variation
(Pucci 1997), without the movement forward or out which is a nec-
essary prerequisite for all successful story-telling (Todorov
1977:233; Brooks 1984:90ff). In this way, the underworld draws
together the “archive” of the space underground, where time is held
back, with the dreadful state of repetition found at the edges of the
earth, the place where Prometheus’s liver, for example, is endlessly
replicated. In each case, these extreme locales serve to trap or hide
time at the edges of the narrative (Johnson 1999: 12-13).
In terms of the geography of plot, Tartaros thus serves as
the site to which all dead ends lead—within which the machinery of
various unfulfilled (but ever-present) story-lines winds down and is
abandoned. Although Zeus cannot destroy his immortal forebears, he
can stop their succession through narrative. By placing them within
the sequestered space of Tartaros he creates a topographical equiva-
164 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
lent of the “depths of the past” to which their mythic identity will
always be bound.
As already observed, Zeus’s actions in this case are similar
to those of the Titans before him, who sought to fix the present in
their own time by breaking the cycle of filial succession. Ouranos’s
entrapment of his children within Gaia’s womb, like Kronos’s
entrapment of his children within his own belly, is analogous to
Zeus’s suppression of those who pose a threat to the permanence of
his sovereignty and imprisonment of them within the belly of the
Underworld. For, in order to reach Tartaros, one must first. pass
through a great chasm (740) which West (1966) links with the god
Chaos, and suggests may be envisioned as a throat (116). That throat
looks back to the throat of Kronos, and forward to Zeus’s own swal-
lowing of Metis later in the poem. It also opens up a space in the nar-
rative which both West (1997:297) and Walcot (1961, 1966:61),
drawing on Near Eastern parallels, have compared to a large metal
jar.
By fashioning Tartaros as a kind of vast, makeshift jar that—
unlike the jars of the Works and Days—will never be opened, Zeus
definitively separates off the categories of the past and future from
his own all-encompassing present. In the present analysis of the jar in
the Works and Days, we saw how it worked as a kind of archive with-
in which the past could be stored for the future. But the principal
function of the archive is of course its role in preserving memory, of
saving time from the disintegration of the past. In the immortal
world of the Theogony, however, the underground storage space
becomes a refuge, a means of artificially creating a past in a syn-
chronic universe. For, if mortals use forgetfulness and hope to cate-
gorize that which is past and that which remains to take place in the
future, then the Olympians—who can instantly see through both of
these devices—are left with the problem of having nowhere to “put”
their past or at least of setting it out of sight. In this sense Tartaros
functions as an archive which binds a previous but ever-present gen-
eration of gods in an eternal state of stasis and repetition, as if
TTOPOGRAPHIES OF TIME IN HESIOD 165
References
Diels, H., and W. Kranz, eds. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Berlin:
Weidmann, 1951.
Dodds, E. R. The Greeks and the Irrational. Berkeley, CA: University
of California Press, 1951.
Faraone, Christopher. Talismans and Trojan Horses. Oxford: Oxford
University Press: 1992.
~ GREEK CHRONOGRAPHIC
TRADITIONS ABOUT THE FIRST
OLYMPIC GAMES
Astrid Moller
these dates in the first place, and it demonstrates clearly how deeply
implicated ancient chronography was in various contemporary cul-
tural and discursive traditions. It is perhaps somewhat ironic, there-
fore, as we shall see in the course of this chapter, that we have every
reason to doubt the authenticity of the traditional foundation date of
the Olympic Games, but little chance that we could ever find a bet-
ter date which would be as precise.
Ancient chronography has two meanings in the context of
classical historiography. On the one hand, it is a historiographical
genre. Felix Jacoby (1909:88) held that it began with Hellanicus of
Lesbos at the end of the 5th century BCE. During the Hellenistic
Period it took the shape of chronological tables, even though we do
not know when synchronistic tables actually started. It might have
been with Castor of Rhodes in the 1st century BCE, although there
is no direct evidence, or with Eusebius in the 4th century CE, whose
chronicle was evidently organized in parallel columns. David Asheri
(1991/92:54) argued for Timaeus of Tauromenium, who lived some-
where between 350 and 250 BCE, as the inventor of synchronistic
tables. Chronography thus describes a record of historical events
precisely dated by reference to an absolute chronological system. On
the other hand, the term “chronography” is used to refer to the
process in which precise dates were established for persons and
events not yet included in an absolute chronology (Mosshammer
1979:85). This is the situation at the beginning of historiography in
the 5th century BCE, when Greek historians started to establish
ways to date events.
In a world without documents that already contain events
dated by years of kings, magistrates, or other systems, historians had
to find ways to date events. Ancient Greek scholars created a net-
work of dates by drawing diachronic and synchronic lines, compos-
ing a temporal co-ordinate system similar to the spatial one used for
geographical maps. In 1966, the Italian historian Santo Mazzarino
argued against the schematic attribution of cyclical time perception
to the Greeks and linear time perception to Judaeo-Christian
GREEK CHRONOGRAPHIC TRADITIONS ABOUT THE FIRST OLYMPIC GAMES 171
thought (1966, 2.2: 412-61, n. 555). He held that the typical way to
set up a chronology in classical historiography was what he called the
diastematic system of dating.
The Greek word diastema means “interval,” “difference,” or
“extension,” “dimension”; diastematikos means proceeding in inter-
vals, indicating distance or having dimension. According to
Mazzarino, the backbone of classical chronology is made up by time
intervals between more or less important events. In Greek chronol-
ogy, each event had to be located in time in relation to other events
which was expressed by intervals in years or generations and in syn-
chronisms between them. Consequently, a network of synchronic
and diachronic coordinate axes was created (Daffina 1987). A major
hindrance to chronology arose from the lack of a fixed point of ref-
erence, such as for example, the birth of Christ in Western civiliza-
tion, from which point events are counted forward and backward (It
was Dionysius Exiguus in the 6th century who fixed Christ’s birth to
525 years before his own time. The calculation ante Christum natum,
however, was only introduced by Dionysius Petavius who published his
Opus de Doctrina Temporum in 1627). Instead, the Greeks had to build
their chronology from within to locate each event at a certain dis-
tance to and from another.
Synchronic lines had to be found by creating synchronisms
between persons, the foundation of cities, or famous battles. The
ability to establish that two events occurred at the same time not only
coordinated events but also provided the possibility of connecting
two different dating systems which might have been current in two
different cities.
Diachronic devices were provided to a certain extent by
genealogies (see Moller 1996 for reservations) and by lists of epony-
mous magistrates, priestesses or victors. Genealogies naturally give
only rough generations, and matters are made even more confusing
by the fact that ancient authors often have different notions of what
constitutes a “generation length” (Meyer 1892—99:151-88; Pearson
1942:9-12; Prakken 1943; den Boer 1954:5—29; van Compernolle
172 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
This means, of course, that he would have had an idea when to start
counting Olympic victors and that he made attempts to synchronize the
first Olympic games with other events. Perhaps he started counting
Olympiads by numbers, too. The use of ordinal numbers for Olympiads
is, however, attested for the first time in an inscription from the first
half of the 3rd century BCE, the so-called Olympiad chronicle from
Athens (IG II/IlI2 2326) (Ebert 1982).
Many modern scholars assume that it was Hippias of Elis who
dated the foundation of the Olympic games to a year which we trans-
late as 776 BCE. The discussion about the authenticity of the Olympic
victor list is thus essentially connected with the discussion about the
foundation date. One line of argument derives from the idea that
Hippias found a documentary list starting around 580 BCE (Ol. 50)
when some consider that Elis finally took over the sanctuary at
Olympia (cf. Moller 2003), and that he therefore had to reconstruct
the victors for the earlier games. How did he know where to start?
Mahaffy (1881) thought that Hippias determined the founda-
tion date by Iphitus, the mythical founder of the games, and that the
earlier parts of the list, i.e. before the 50th Olympiad, were construct-
ed accordingly. Cavaignac (1913—20:336-9) believed that Hippias had
found 40—50 names for the time prior to 580 BCE when the docu-
mentary list started. He assumed that till 612 BCE the games were
hold annually and calculated that the Olympic games started around
650 BCE. His clearly arbitrary arguments found immediate response
(Wade-Gery 1925:762-64). Wilamowitz (1922:481-90) equally
doubted the penteteric character of the games right from the begin-
ning and distinguished between the list which he considered authentic
and the chronology based on this list. He could therefore claim that the
date of 776 BCE was much too high (but see also Jacoby, FGrHist IIIb
comm. 152 n. 47 for criticism). These arguments were followed up by
Lenschau (1936, 1938:224-27) who took the year 580 BCE as the
beginning of penteteric games and assumed that Hippias had found 49
names of victors in the stadium race which prompted him to calculate
(49x4) + 580 = 776 = OL. 1.
GREEK CHRONOGRAPHIC TRADITIONS ABOUT THE FirRST OLYMPIC GAMES 177
From the fall of Troy until the return of the Heraclids ....... 80 years
From these until the settlement of Ionia ................ 60 years
The time thereafter until Lycurgus’ guardianship .......... 159 years
Until the year preceding the first Olympiad ............. 108 years
From this Olympiad until the invasion of Xerxes .......... 297 years
From this until the beginning of the Peloponnesian war ...... 48 years
And until the end of the war and the defeat of the Athenians. . 27 years
And until the battle of Leuktra ....0....0.....0.0..000.. 34 years
After this until Philip’s death ....................00... 35 years
Thereafter until the passing away of Alexander ............ 12 years
GREEK CHRONOGRAPHIC TRADITIONS ABOUT THE FIRST OLYMPIC GAMES 179
References
and especially the view of the Church of Rome that had been intent
on implementing a seven-day weekly cycle anchored on Sunday as a
day of worship and/or rest (Bacchiocchi 1977; Zerubavel 1985;
Rordorf 1968; Cotton 1933; Beckwith and Stott 1978).
Some scholars have wondered if Constantine, brilliant
politician that he was, was not playing both sides of the fence, choos-
ing to recognize a day—dies Solis—that was also significant for pagan
worshipers, especially those of Sol Invinctus and Mithras, of which
there were many more than Christians at the time that Constantine
passed his law (Bohmer 1931; Zockler 1912; Rordorf 1968;
Bacchiocchi 1977; Cameron and Hall 1999; de Giovanni 1977).
However we interpret Constantine’s intentions behind his Sunday
law, his actions have led Charles Pietri (1984) and others to argue
that it was the 4th century Christians who largely developed and
promulgated our modern notion of the seven-day week with its focus
on Sunday as a day of rest and worship.
But, given the evidence of the Codex Calendar of 354, with
its seven-day week illustrated by pagan astrological signs for a
Christian to use—one cannot help but wonder if the notion of the
seven-day week anchored on Sunday as promulgated by 4th century
Christian leaders and emperors was distinctly different from the
notion of the week held by pagans in the Western Roman empire.
And further, how did the imperial and Christian emphasis on and
view of Sunday contribute to developing the seven-day week in the
4th century Western Roman empire? And finally, given the multiple
weekly cycles in the Codex Calendar of 354 did the seven-day week
replace other ways of dating and organizing people’s time in the 4th
century? If not, when did the seven-day week take on these functions
in the west?
These three concerns are of more than mere antiquarian
interest, for they highlight, among other issues, the ways in which
Christians used time to shape their group identity. Indeed, some
scholars have argued that Christian leaders focused on Sunday and
the seven-day week to establish a unique identity over and against not
PAGAN AND CHRISTIAN NOTIONS OF THE WEEK 187
only Jews, who celebrated the Sabbath, but also pagans (Goldenberg
1979:442-45; Stern 2000:106-107; Zerubavel 1985:22). If, howev-
er, the seven-day week and the religious and ritual import of Sunday
were already predominant among pagans, Christian leaders do not so
much appear to be establishing a separate identity as maintaining
continuities with their pagan contemporaries. At issue is the question
of the dynamics of group formation and the conversion techniques
adopted by the post-Constantinian church.
This chapter argues three main points. First, pagan and
Christian notions of the week in the 4th century were very similar,
and, in this fluid world, pagans and Christians influenced one anoth-
er in their use of time as an organizing principle of social life, leaving
a legacy that has shaped our contemporary notions of temporality.
Second, the recognition of Sunday as a day not only of worship but
of rest was a Constantinian innovation which shows Christian influ-
ence but had no clear pagan precedents; this helps to explain why this
notion of Sunday only gradually shaped 4th century notions of the
day for pagans and Christians alike. And third, the notion of the
seven-day week with its focus on Sunday cannot be securely docu-
mented as replacing other ways of dating or organizing time in the
4th century. Rather, dating by lunar days as well as market days and
by Kalends, Nones, and Ides continued throughout this century and
well into the next. In other words, it took more than a week, indeed,
more than a century, for the effects of Constantine’s law and the
Christian notion of Sunday as the anchor to the seven-day week to
uniformly replace other ways of minding time.
torical standpoint, there are two ways of explaining why the week to
which we adhere is seven-days long, neither of which necessarily
excludes the other. One explanation relates the length of our week
to the seven-days of Creation in traditional Jewish cosmology” (6).
The biblical account of Creation explains God’s commandment to
work for six days and then rest periodically on the seventh day, which
for the Jews was the Sabbath. This divine temporal plan requires no
further explanation for a believer.
The second way to explain the seven-day cycle relates to the
seven planets of ancient astrology: “It is generally believed that the
linking of the planets to the seven gods of each day was a Babylonian,
or Chaldaean contribution, evolving around 500 BCE in conjunction
with astrological needs to cast horoscopes” (14). This linkage may go
back to earlier Babylonian beliefs in a universe that was a “sevenfold
entity governed by a fusion of seven deities” (7). It is not until the
Hellenistic Age that we see evidence for a seven-day astrological
week, evolving probably around the 2nd century BCE in Alexandria
(Maas 1902:267; Neugebauer 1963:168—69; Boll 1912).
This astrological origin, along with the Egyptian worship of
the Sun, may explain why the 2nd century CE Roman historian Dio
Cassius (37.18—19) thought that the Egyptians originated the seven-
day planetary week that spread in the Roman Empire in the 1st cen-
tury BCE. The earliest Roman reference to the gods of the week
comes from the Ist century BCE poet Tibullus, who claims to have
used as a pretext for lingering with his lover, the “sacred day of
Saturn” (1.3.18).
From this point on, the names of the planetary days of the
week can be found in a variety of Roman writers. Often, as in the
Satires of Juvenal, these references are tied to astrological predic-
tions, or to the Sabbath observance of the Jews (Sat. 7.160; 14.96 ff.
see Meinhold 1909; Boll 1912:2573—74). We hear of teachers of
rhetoric giving their lessons on a seven-day weekly basis, be it
Fridays in Juvenal’s Rome (Sat. 7.160) or Saturdays in Suetonius’s
Rhodes (Tiberius 32.4). By the 2nd century, Dio Cassius can claim
PAGAN AND CHRISTIAN NOTIONS OF THE WEEK 189
shows the gods of the week, but beginning with Sol (from right to
left) (Vermaseren CIMRM:693). Turcan explains the placement of Sol
in the Bologna relief as being tied to notions of Mithras as the god of
Time and to Pythagorean influences on the developing Mithraic cult;
according to Turcan (but with no supporting evidence), the
Pythagoreans consecrated the seventh day to Apollo, that is Sol, and
this, in conjunction with the close association of Sol Invictus with
Mithras explains the sequence of the planets beginning with Sol, not
Saturn, in the Bologna relief. Yet another reason for this placement
may be the practices of astrologers; the 2nd century astrologer
Vettius Valens, in his Anthologiarum 1.10 (Kroll 1908: 26), reckoned
birth dates using a seven-day week beginning with Sol, not Saturn.
The evidence that can be adduced for the Mithraists’ use of
the seven-day planetary week is largely iconographic; we simply do
not know how much it shaped their liturgy in the centuries before
Constantine. So, while it seems logical that Mithraists should incor-
porate the seven-day week given its planetary base and, the icono-
graphic remains from Mithraea, there is no firm evidence, as far as
we can know, that they actually did so. This is also true for the cult of
Sol Invictus, which was, as noted above, so closely linked with that
of Mithras in the popular mind that people made vows to Sol Invictus
Mithras (Vermaseren CIMRM:360—62; see Halsberghe 1972). The
most we can say is that some pagans, as well as some Christians in the
second and third centuries, used the seven-day weekly cycle to date
moments in their private lives, but they did so in conjunction with
other dating conventions.
[13.3. You [pagans] are clearly the ones who have accepted
the sun as one of the seven-days of the week and [. . .] have
selected this one day over other days as the day on which
you do not take a bath or you postpone it until the evening,
or you take care to give yourself some rest and a meal. 4.
By resorting to these customs, you are deviating from your
own rites to those of others; indeed the Jewish feasts are the
Sabbath and the “purificatory dinner” and the ceremonies of
the lamps and fasting with unleavened bread and littoral
prayers, which are very alien from your gods. 5. You who
reproach us with the sun and the day, recognize your prox-
imity: we are not far from your Saturn and your Sabbaths!]
(1.13.1-5)*
* ‘| followed the text of Andre Schneider, Le Premier Livre Ad Nationes de
Tertullien, Introduction, Texte, Traduction et Commentaire. Rome: Institut Suisse, 1968.
Schneider accepts a crux before ex diebus and reads: “et [ . . . ] ex diebus ipsorum praelegis-
tis” as evidence for Sunday celebrations.
PAGAN AND CHRISTIAN NOTIONS OF THE WEEK 197
Saturday, as a special day of the week, either because it was the first
day of the astrological week and/or in imitation of Jewish practice.
Thus Saturn was depicted first in the Codex Calendar of 354
(Salzman 1990:30—31). Moreover, if the pagan observances noted by
Tertullian on Sunday extended beyond Carthage, there has been no
trace of them identified in other texts.
In contrast, Sunday was the object of pastoral attention
among Christians, as early, some have argued, as the end of the Ist
century, when Ignatius, in Rome, wrote letters to various Churches,
in which he spoke of his Jewish converts as “no longer observing
Sabbaths, but living in accordance with the Lord’s day” (Epistle to the
Magnesians; see also Epistle to Barnabas and Teachings of the Twelve
Apostles), Clearer evidence of such practice is found in Justin who, in
the mid-2nd century, writes in his Apology to the emperor: “The day
of the Sun, we assemble, because it is the first day, on which God . .
. created the world and because on this day Jesus Christ, our Savior,
came back from the dead” (1.67.6). The association with Christ’s res-
urrection on Easter Sunday was echoed in later writers. Moreover,
according to Willy Rordorf (1968:238—73), who argued from the
textual evidence provided by Justin and Pliny, the 2nd century most
likely also saw a change from a Sunday evening worship meeting to
an early Sunday morning one, before daybreak.
The evidence from the 3rd century also indicates that
Sunday had not become the uniform day for prayer across the
empire’s Christian communities. Although Tertullian strongly advo-
cates Sunday as the only day for prayer among Christians in third cen-
tury North Africa, he also shows that some Christians there, as still
in many parts in the East, still followed the Jewish practice of special
prayers on Sabbath mornings as well as on Sunday mornings (De
Oratione 23.1). Indeed, Tertullian vehemently decries this practice
and the willingness of Christians to mark the Sabbath by fasting (De
Jejuniis 14ff.). His hostility toward Sabbath observances is echoed in
Rome by Hippolytus who, in the early third century, also preached
against this practice (Comm. In Dan. 4.20). The intent of both
PAGAN AND CHRISTIAN NOTIONS OF THE WEEK 199
ary inscriptions from Rome (70%) and Italy (30%) that mention the
days of the week. He claimed that Christians particularly noted the
days of the week, indicating Fridays (32 times) and Sundays (31)
most often, followed by Saturdays (21), Thursdays (21), Wednesdays
(19), Mondays (17), and last, Tuesdays (9). Christians preferred to
use dies Dominica (or the Greek equivalent, hemera kyriake) to dies
Solis. This body of inscriptions showed one person out of 30 referring
to a day of the week. Moreover, Pietri claimed, this number
increased over time. More than half of the inscriptions are from the
period 366—440. So, Pietri (1984) concluded, “Everything indicates
that this specifically Christian habit introduced itself into the funer-
ary formulae of the 4th century and increased noticeably thereafter”
(77). On the basis of this analysis, Pietri argued that it was the
Christians who adopted the language of the seven-day week and were
hence responsible for making it, along with Sunday as a day of wor-
ship, normative practice as early as the middle of the fourth century.
It is surprising that Pietri did no comparative work on
pagan inscriptions from Rome and Italy to make his case secure. And,
as he himself noted, his corpus of 150 Christian inscriptions was
weighted toward the most faithful, being drawn from catacombs and
churches. Thus, Pietri’s assumptions about the willingness of
Christians to adopt the seven-day week were not tested against a
comparable group of pagan inscriptions in order to say with any
degree of certainty that Christians over and above pagans adopted
the seven-day week in their funerary monuments.
There are difficulties in pursuing such a comparison of con-
temporary pagan inscriptions, not the least of which is the survival
of inscriptions from non-Christian contexts in the 4th century and
the conversion of the population at large. But given these limitations,
some comparative analysis can be undertaken. There are several col-
lections of inscriptions from the most active pagan cults in Rome and
Italy in the 4th century. I examined specific collections for four of
these cults—Mithras, Isis, Magna Mater, and Sol—as well as the use
of dating terminology in the 10,000 inscriptions from H. Dessau’s
204 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
day lunar cycles is documented for the fourth and fifth centuries.
(See the Parapegma from the Baths of Trajan in A. Degrassi
1963:299, 326, and references to lunar days by Ambrosiaster,
Quaestiones 84). The evidence for market cycles is of interest, for it
provides another important way for people to allocate commercial
and social time.
Both seven-and eight-day market cycles have a long history
in the Roman empire, and there is evidence to suggest that both
cycles coexisted into the 4th century. The eight-day market cycle was
in use first; its appearance in an official, military context in 3rd cen-
tury Dura-Europus is one indicator of how wide spread it had become
in Roman life (Snyder: 1936). The seven-day market cycle emerged
alongside the eight-day one in the first century CE in Campania
(Andreau 2000: 88-91). Interesingly, these were not the only two
cycles for organizing markets; in North Africa, markets were held on
either a 12-or 18-day cycle (Shaw 1981). Elsewhere, they could be
held on a twice-monthly basis (de Ligt 1993). These variations in
market frequency indicate that market cycles varied by region. The
effort to establish a seven-day market in the newly rebuilt town of
Aquae Iasae, Pannonia, at the time of Constantine has earlier prece-
dents, and fits easily with this emperor’s professed goal of making
Sunday and the seven day week the primary means of organizing time
in the 4th century (Andreau 2000 for earlier precedents; Shaw
1981:45). However, it is of interest that the establishment of a seven
day market cycle is at odds with the Christian and allegedly
Constantinian notion that Sunday be a day of worship and rest.
The seven-day cycle was familiar in private and, after
Constantine’s recognition of Sunday as a holiday, was becoming
increasingly important within legal and commercial contexts as well.
However, the evidence also suggests that the seven-day week was not
yet exclusively used across the empire in the 4th century. Moreover,
the habit of dating by the days of the week appeared in only a small
percentage of Christian inscriptions and did not become the norm in
the 4th century or soon thereafter. Dating by the Kalends, Nones,
PAGAN AND CHRISTIAN NOTIONS OF THE WEEK 207
and Ides remained standard and persisted as such well in the 7th cen-
tury in the west (Ware 1976).
Conclusion
On the basis of these studies, it would seem that pagans and
Christians in the 4th century were much more alike in their notions
of the week than Christian preachers were willing to admit. Both
pagans and Christians were familiar with and used a seven-day cycle;
both were familiar with the astrological associations of each day; both
used the planetary names of the days of the week. In these ways, and
in the willingness of certain Christian leaders to justify the Christian
use of the planetary names of the days of the week, we see a Christian
leadership influenced by pagan notions of the week attempting to
maintain continuities with their pagan contemporaries.
At the same time, pagans and Christians did have different
notions of Sunday; only for the Christians do we have evidence of this
day as being marked as a day of worship on a weekly basis, both before
and after Constantine. Imperial law, along with Christian preaching,
furthered this notion among pagans as well as Christians. But pagan
notions of how to celebrate a traditional Roman holiday in honor of
Sol, as begun by Constantine, did persist, as indicated by the ongoing
celebration of circus games and market days on Sundays. Sunday was
still seen by many as the day of the Sun, dies Solis—not the day of the
Lord, dies Dominica—through the end of the 4th century.
Finally, we ought not rely on funerary inscriptions or impe-
rial laws to tell us when the Christian notion of the seven-day week
revolving around Sunday as a day of religious observance and rest
came to be used exclusively to organize people’s time; the seven-day
week did not replace other ways of organizing time in the 4th centu-
ry. Thus, given how gradual was the adoption of celebrating Sunday
as a holiday, it seems likely that uniformity in using the seven-day
week to regulate people’s activities was a post-4th century phenom-
208 TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN THE ANCIENT WORLD
enon. Only in the 5th century in the West could that be said to be the
case, but by then, as the 3rd century author of the Didascalia so pre-
sciently put it, “all days belong[ed] to the Lord” (6.18.16).
References
Zerubavel, Eviatar. The Seven-Day Circle. New York: Free Press, 1985.
Zockler, O. “Siebenzahl.” In Pauly-Wissowa Real-Encyclopddie der
Classischen Altertumswissenschaft 18. Stuttgart: J. B. Metzler,
1912, 522,
e @ CONTRIBUTORS @ e