LexicalismSuperfluous4
LexicalismSuperfluous4
Abstract
The Lexicalist Hypothesis, which says that the component of grammar that produces words is distinct and strictly
separate from the component that produces phrases, is both wrong and superfluous. It is wrong because (1) there
are numerous instances where phrasal syntax feeds word formation; (2) there are cases where phrasal syntax
can access sub-word parts; and (3) claims that word formation and phrasal syntax obey different principles are
not correct. The Lexicalist Hypothesis is superfluous because where there are facts that are supposed to be
accounted for by the Lexicalist Hypothesis, those facts have independent explanations. The model of grammar
that we are led to is then the most parsimonious one: there is only one combinatorial component of grammar
that puts together both words and phrases.
1 Introduction
The Lexicalist Hypothesis, usually attributed to Chomsky 1970, is a foundational hypothesis in numerous current
approaches to morphology and syntax, including Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG), Lexical Func-
tional Grammar (LFG), Simpler Syntax (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005), various versions of the Principles and
Parameters and Minimalist models, and others.1 The basic tenet of the Lexicalist Hypothesis is that the system of
grammar that assembles words is separate from the system of grammar that assembles phrases out of words. The
combinatorial system that produces words is supposed to use different principles from the system that produces
phrases. Additionally, the word system is encapsulated from the phrasal system and interacts with it only in one
direction, with the output of the word system providing the input to the phrasal system. This has the result that the
phrasal system has no access to sub-word units, and in addition, the output of the phrasal system never forms the
input to the word system.2
An alternative view dispenses with the Lexicalist Hypothesis and argues that the phrasal and word formation
systems are not distinct (Sadock 1980; Baker 1985; Sproat 1985; Lieber 1988, 1992; Hale and Keyser 1993; Halle
and Marantz 1993; Marantz 1997; Borer 2005; Bruening 2014; among others). If this view is correct, a model of
grammar does not need two separate components, but only one. This view has the virtue of simplicity: a model
of grammar with only one component is simpler than one with two, and is therefore to be preferred, assuming
that they are equivalent in their empirical coverage. In the face of this challenge, numerous recent publications
have defended the lexicalist position, arguing that the empirical facts demand the strict separation of the word and
phrasal systems (e.g., Ackema and Neeleman 2004, Williams 2007, Newmeyer 2009, Müller 2013, Müller and
Wechsler 2014).
1
This hypothesis is usually referred to as the Lexicalist Hypothesis, after Chomsky (1970). It is occasionally also referred to as the
Lexical Hypothesis (e.g., Williams 2007). The more common name seems to be the Lexicalist Hypothesis, so that is the name I will use.
The literature on this hypothesis is too vast to cite fully here. Important references include Jackendoff (1972), Aronoff (1976), Lapointe
(1980), Bresnan (1982), Kiparsky (1982b), Simpson (1983a), Mohanan (1986), Di Sciullo and Williams (1987), and Bresnan and Mchombo
(1995). Many other references can be found in the works cited throughout the text.
2
A necessary assumption of this view is that it is possible to define the word as a linguistic unit and to unambiguously identify words. As
is well-known, this assumption is false. There is no universally valid definition of a word, and even in a well-studied language like English,
there are numerous cases where it is unclear what constitutes a word. See Haspelmath (2011) for recent discussion. I will put this issue
aside in this paper, and show that, even if we grant the lexicalist assumption that it is possible to identify words, the lexicalist position is
both wrong and superfluous.
1
In this paper I make two points. First, the empirical facts indicate that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is fundamen-
tally incorrect. There are numerous instances where the output of the phrasal system feeds word formation (section
2), and there are also cases where the phrasal syntax must have access to sub-word units (section 3). These facts
are incompatible with the model of grammar posited by the Lexicalist Hypothesis. Morphology and syntax also
do not obey different principles, but instead behave alike (section 4). This removes one argument for the Lexical-
ist Hypothesis. Second, the Lexicalist Hypothesis is superfluous. Where there are facts that are supposed to be
accounted for by the Lexicalist Hypothesis, those facts have independent explanations, even within theories that
assume the Lexicalist Hypothesis. This is shown in section 5. Since the Lexicalist Hypothesis is both incorrect and
does no work, it can and should be dispensed with. We only need a single syntactic module in the grammar, one
that produces both words and phrases.
Before beginning, I should point out that different approaches that assume the Lexicalist Hypothesis vary
significantly in their implementation. Throughout this paper, I try to make points that apply to all of them. This
is not always possible, however, so where relevant I try to be clear about which specific approaches or claims
I am criticizing, and note at that point that the criticisms may not apply to certain other approaches within the
Lexicalist Hypothesis. I should also point out that there is another meaning of the word “lexicalist” as applied to
theories, where it means that that theory has information encoded in lexical entries do much of the work of the
grammar. Such approaches are referred to as “lexicalist” because they include very rich lexical entries. This paper
has absolutely nothing to say about this meaning of the term “lexicalist.” It addresses only the claim that there are
distinct word and phrase systems in the grammar.
To begin, in sections 2–4 I point out three ways in which the Lexicalist Hypothesis is mistaken in its view of
grammar.
2
(1) a. I gave her a don’t-you-dare! look.
b. She baked her fiance a sweet I-love-you cake.
In most theories, compounding must be a lexical process, since it creates elements that have the distribution (and
inflectional morphology) of words. It can also feed further derivation, as in snowboarder, pan-fryable, antibullfight-
ing, Church Slavonicism, redownload. The lexicalist literature uniformly treats compounding as a lexical process
(e.g., Kiparsky 1982b, Bresnan and Mchombo 1995). Compounds should therefore not be able to include phrases
that are put together by the phrasal syntax.
In fact, however, the phrases that constitute the first member of these compounds must be put together by the
syntax, because they have the form that the syntax requires. They can be imperatives and have the form of an
imperative, as in (1a), and they can have the form of a declarative, as in (1b). They can also be wh-questions
and exclamatives, as in the examples in (2). In all cases, if the first member of the compound violates rules and
constraints of the phrasal syntax, the result is ill-formed (3):
If these phrases were not put together by the phrasal syntax but by some other mechanism, that mechanism would
have to precisely duplicate the constraints of the phrasal syntax.
It is also not the case that the phrases that appear inside compounds are “lexicalized” units, as Bresnan and
Mchombo (1995) claimed. Using phrases in compounds is completely productive, as the examples above and at-
tested usage show (see Ackema and Neeleman 2004, Lieber and Scalise 2007, Sato 2010, and especially Hohenhaus
1998). Here are a few attested examples, pulled from the web (with the punctuation used there):
(4) a. What was your “I don’t get paid enough for this shit” moment?
(https://www.reddit.com/r/AskReddit/comments/3hiw5t/what_was_your_i_dont_get_paid_enough_for_this/)
b. How to end your “I don’t feel like it” syndrome
(http://www.prolificliving.com/i-dont-feel-like-it-syndrome/)
c. If there’s one thing I don’t need, it’s your “I don’t think that’s wise” attitude.
(http://www.gotfuturama.com/Multimedia/EpisodeSounds/2ACV02/)
d. Discovering the answer to your why can’t I sleep question is an important step to putting sleep
troubles behind you.
(http://www.holistic-mindbody-healing.com/facts-about-insomnia.html)
e. Your “Why can’t I bait newbies?” tears are glorious.
(https://forums.eveonline.com/default.aspx?g=posts&m=5798278)
f. Overcoming the I can’t afford it sales objection.
(http://www.servextra.com/overcoming-the-i-cant-afford-that-sales-objection/)
Product ads also regularly use novel phrasal compounds; here are some noticed recently:
3
c. “Growing Kids? The Yellow Pages is your oh-boy-they-need-more-shoes-and-clothes-and-we-should-
start-braces-for-their-teeth-now directory.”
Wiese (1996) argues that phrasal compounds are not a problem for the Lexicalist Hypothesis because the phrase
is a quotation. This view is supported by the fact that first and second person pronouns do not refer to the speaker
and hearer in compounds like an I-love-you cake, just as they do not inside quotations (Bresnan and Mchombo
1995). This analysis is further elaborated by Pafel (2015). I will return to this idea momentarily, after illustrating
other instances of phrases inside words.
Words can also be zero-derived from phrases, another instance of what is supposed to be banned by the Lexical-
ist Hypothesis. These phrases can include a verb plus adverb, verb plus object and particle, verb plus preposition,
modal verb plus main verb, or other elements, including functional ones that do not typically participate in word
formation (a how-to). Most of the output forms are nouns, but at least three are adjectives (see-through, lackluster,
as-is). The following are some examples that include at least three different words:
(6) a. a ne’er-do-well
b. a know-it-all
c. a wannabe (want-to-be)
d. a good-for-nothing
e. a pick-me-up
f. a hand-me-down
g. a shoot-’em-up
h. the pushmi-pullyu (push-me-pull-you)
i. a free-for-all
j. a two-by-four
k. a mother-in-law, brother-in-law, etc.; the in-laws
l. a (fine) how-do-you-do
(7) a. a has-been
b. an also-ran
c. will-call (“the tickets are waiting at will-call”)
d. the once-over
e. a do-over
f. a look-alike
g. X’s say so
h. the long ago
i. a gimme (give-me)
j. a know-nothing
k. a readme
l. a thank you
m. a how-to
n. the go-ahead (“give someone the go-ahead”)
o. a walk-through, a run-through, a drive-through, follow-through
4
One might also want to include in this list such words as pickpocket, cutthroat, and scofflaw. However, these are missing elements that
they would have to have as phrases (determiners or plural morphology, and a preposition in the case of scofflaw). In the list in the text I
include only words that are well-formed phrases.
4
p. see-through
q. lackluster
r. as-is
(8) a drive-by, a layabout, a runaway, a knock-off, a callback, a rub-down, a beat-down, a smack-down, a put-
down, a pushover, a cast-off, a castaway, a breakup, the brush-off, a let-down, a walk-up, a walkabout, a
throwback, leftovers, . . .
These verb-particle combinations contrast with ones where the particle is initial, like input, bystander, off-putting.
They therefore do not appear to have been formed by the process of compounding. Also fully productive are
adjectival passives consisting of verbs plus particles (put upon, run down, crossed out, etc.), as well as adjectival
passives derived from verbs plus full prepositional phrases (talked about, unasked for, unheard of, etc.). See
section 2.2 on these prepositional passives. There is also a productive process for forming nouns denoting food and
beverage dishes and names of products and services from phrases, primarily conjunctions of noun phrases. Some
examples include two gin and tonics, a Stoli and kiwi juice (Wechsler 2008b), a surf-n-turf, an East meets West, a
bed-and-breakfast, the wash-n-fold, a slip-n-slide, etc.
Verbs can also be created from phrases. Here are a few attested examples:
(9) a. You just Bonnie and Clyded my starting middies! (Archer season 3, episode 3)
b. The outside door opened and a knot of people, all taking down umbrellas and shaking out hats, came
in, were order-of-serviced by Colin, and went into the nave. (they were handed a card listing the
order of service; Connie Willis, The Doomsday Book)
c. Don’t you ‘wee, tim’rous beastie’ me. (New Yorker cartoon, cited by Clark and Gerrig 1990, 773,
(8a))
See also Carnie (2000) on verbs zero-derived from phrases. Besides the adjectives listed above, Ackema and
Neeleman (2004, 177, note 25) note a productive use of phrases as adjectives in certain currently popular registers:
Many words derived from phrases can feed further derivation. For instance, knowitallism and ne’er-do-well-ism
are well-attested. Clark and Gerrig (1990, 773, (8c)) cite the following example:
(11) He let it obsess him, for all the irritated now-nowing of his wife and the confusion and unease of his
children. (Martin Amis, Success)
Here now-nowing is a noun derived from a verb zero-derived from a phrase. In fact, any verb derived from a phrase
could similarly be turned into a noun with the suffix -ing (Bonnie-and-Clydeing, etc.).
The simplest analysis of all these cases is that they are phrases, put together by the phrasal syntax, and then
converted into nouns (or adjectives, or verbs).5 The ones that are nouns are clearly nouns, since they occur with
articles and/or possessors and can take plural morphology (a couple of wannabes, two has-beens, most how-tos,
three brother-in-laws). The ones that are verbs take verbal morphology (Bonnie-and-Clyded). However, in every
5
In a purely syntactic approach to word-formation, one possible analysis would be to posit a null nominal head that merges with the
phrase and turns it into a noun. An anonymous reviewer says that the purely syntactic approach to morphology necessarily adopts this kind
of syntagmatic approach to morphology and could not adopt a paradigmatic one like that advocated by Becker (1993). It remains to be
seen whether such an approach could handle all of the facts listed in Becker (1993). It is true, as the reviewer also notes, that a syntagmatic
approach will need to admit empty heads/morphemes, as just suggested, but whether this is a drawback or not seems to be entirely a matter
of opinion. It seems to me that empty elements are widespread in syntax and morphology and cannot be denied, so my own view is that
empty elements in morphology are not a drawback at all. Of course, the question will always be what analysis achieves the best empirical
coverage.
5
case the word has the form produced by the phrasal syntax, and not the form that ought to have been produced by,
say, compounding (e.g., *it-all-know, *so-say). Many of them also include non-selected adverbs (a do-over, an
also-ran), which in some Lexicalist approaches are supposed to be inaccessible to the word formation system (see
section 4.2). Some include functional elements that do not otherwise appear inside words (a how-to, a wannabe).
The noun how-to even includes apparent wh-movement of a wh-adverb, as does a fine how-do-you-do, which also
includes subject-auxiliary inversion.6 This type of zero derivation, then, like the case of phrasal compounding
above, is an instance of phrasal syntax providing the input to word formation. Again, this ordering is not supposed
to exist under the Lexicalist Hypothesis.
One could attempt to dismiss these forms as isolated exceptions. However, as can be seen from the list above,
there is a large number of them, and at least two classes are completely productive (verb-particle combinations, and
names for foods/beverages and products). Compare this with the noun-deriving affix -age, as in blockage, breakage,
cleavage, leakage, lineage, stoppage, etc. This suffix occurs with what is probably a comparable number of words
(I count 150 or so), but is far less productive (new forms are not created frequently). Yet no one views forms in
-age as isolated; they are viewed as a pattern. Zero derivation of phrases is just as common, and new forms are
created, probably more frequently (e.g., a stop-and-chat, on the TV show Curb Your Enthusiasm). Zero derivation
of words from phrases therefore constitutes a pattern of word formation that requires an account. Moreover, if the
Lexicalist Hypothesis were correct in its view of grammar, there should be no such isolated exceptions: the form
of the grammar would simply preclude their ever being created.
There are also instances of phrases combining with overt derivational morphology to derive new words. These
include do-it-yourselfer, stick-to-itiveness, unputdownable, muckupable, backupable. Some prefixes also seem
to productively attach to phrases, in particular pre-, post-, and ex-: it was pre-founding of Rome, post-digestive
disorder complications (Lieber and Scalise 2007, 11), ex-Secretary of the Interior. See Lieber and Scalise (2007,
11–12) for some discussion, and Spencer (2005, 83) on the suffix -ish. Ackema and Neeleman (2004, 149–152)
discuss the Dutch affixes -achtig and -loos, which can attach to phrases but have all the qualities of an affix. An
anonymous reviewer also notes that phrases can be suffixed with -ness in English, as in His general ok-with-
less-than-we-should-aim-for-ness makes him an undesirable candidate. The TV show Archer created the adverb
agent-in-commandingly (in the episode ‘The Papal Chase’).
Many of these cases are well-known and the general phenomenon has been discussed extensively in the litera-
ture. Despite appearances, the lexicalist literature has come to the conclusion that they are not a problem, because,
as briefly mentioned above, they are quotations (Wiese 1996). As many have noticed (e.g, Cram 1978, Bresnan
and Mchombo 1995, Postal 2004, chapter 6), quotations can include phrases from other languages, non-linguistic
sounds, gestures, and even visual symbols. These can all also appear where phrases can in word-formation (com-
pounds, zero-derivation, etc.). For instance, the following are possible utterances, where what is between angled
brackets is not spoken or written English:
(12) a. One person whistled <sequence of notes 1> and another person whistled <sequence of notes 2>.
The <sequence of notes 1>-whistler was better than the <sequence of notes 2>-whistler.
b. [One ASL interpreter to another:] I’ll <sequence of gestures> you!
One could also derive the words harumpher (‘one who makes a harumphing sound’) and vroomology (‘science of
sounds that sound like vroom’) from non-linguistic sounds, if one wished.
The claim is then that the grammar includes some mechanism for taking basically anything and using it as a
linguistic category, say Noun. Wiese (1996) and Pafel (2015) present formally explicit mechanisms for doing this.
Furthermore, this derived category (the Noun, in our example) is a single, encapsulated unit, the contents of which
are inaccessible to the morphology or the syntax it is embedded within. Now, the content of a phrase within a
word must be accessed, clearly, or sentences like An others-first attitude is clearly better than a me-first attitude
6
A reviewer suggests that zero derivation is applying not to a phrase, but to a string, based on the reviewer’s belief that examples like a
how-to do not involve a complete constituent. However, such examples are constituents, they just involve null complements. Strings that are
not constituents would never be allowed: *a gimme-the, *the push-my-pull-your. This indicates that zero derivation is applying to a phrase,
and not a string.
6
would not even make sense (nor would 12a). We also see various kinds of anaphora crossing the boundaries of the
quotation:
So, the claim must be that, within the sentence or word the phrase is embedded in, it is a single, impenetra-
ble unit, but on some parallel plane the syntax and semantics put together and interpret the phrase. Simply to be
concrete, we can use Davidson’s (1984) demonstrative theory of quotation to illustrate what this might look like.
In Davidson’s theory, a quotation is some kind of demonstrative in the sentence it is embedded in. This demon-
strative points to the content of the quotation. We might represent this with “THIS" and “THAT” indicating the
demonstrative:
The types of anaphora seen above must then be limited to the types of anaphora that work across sentences
and discourse, and for the most part they are (Partee 1973, Pafel 2011, 263–265). All of the above types of
anaphora work on this type of paraphrase (I use parentheticals because the pointing is supposed to take place
contemporaneous with the demonstrative, but parentheticals are also generally viewed as being on a separate plane
from the sentence they are embedded in):
(15) a. THIS syndrome, where THIS is “Charles and Di,” died when she did. (coreference)
b. He baked me a sweet THIS cake, where THIS is “I love you,” but I don’t think he really does. (VP
ellipsis)
c. The old THIS excuse, where THIS is “the dog ate my homework,” won’t work because I know you
don’t have one! (one anaphora)
d. You can’t use the THIS excuse, where THIS is “termites ate the walls,” because the home inspection
didn’t find any! (NP ellipsis)
e. No bag lady likes to get a THIS look from passerby, where THIS is “thank God I’m not her.” (e-type
anaphora)
So far so good, then. Where phrases can appear, non-linguistic sounds, gestures, and so on can also appear, and
the contents of the phrase seem to be encapsulated from the syntax they are embedded in.
Does this make such phrases inside words not a problem for the Lexicalist Hypothesis? Words can contain
phrases in the quotation approach. The grammar has an explicit mechanism for embedding a phrase inside a word,
namely a mechanism of the type posited by Wiese (1996) and Pafel (2015). The very existence of such a mechanism
seems, on the face of it, to be a violation of the Lexicalist Hypothesis. A proponent of the Lexicalist Hypothesis
would have to claim that these cases are exceptional, and there are other cases that the Lexicalist Hypothesis would
rule out. It is not clear what those cases could be, though. A grammar that contains a mechanism for creating a noun
stem from anything would expect anything to be able to appear anywhere a noun stem can, and this seems to be
correct. Phrases and non-linguistic sounds/gestures/symbols seem to be allowed in every case of word-formation
that is productive. As far as I can tell, they are only disallowed where affixes have some particular selectional
requirements, but these requirements rule out other types of stems, too. It is therefore not clear that the Lexicalist
Hypothesis actually rules anything out.
7
The quotation view does predict that a phrase could only be possible in a position where a non-linguistic sound
or gesture would also be possible, but again it is not clear that this prediction rules anything out. As just stated,
all of them are allowed everywhere a noun stem is. It appears that there is absolutely no content to the Lexicalist
Hypothesis’s claim that phrases cannot appear inside words in general, but are only allowed by the exceptional
mechanism of quotation.
Moreover, the claim that the derived category is encapsulated appears to be nothing more than the claim that it
behaves like any other morpheme. Word formation in general does not access the internal structure of the stem it
operates on (but see section 3 for cases where internal structure is accessed). This is the principle of strict cyclicity
in morphology (Mascaró 1976, Halle 1978). For instance, the suffix -ity does not care whether its stem has a bound
latinate root (as in nationality) or a free germanic root (as in frontality), nor could it. All it can see is the stem it
attaches to. In both cases, that stem ends in -al, which is something -ity can attach to. If I create a word based on
a sound like harumphal, then I can create harumphality. Again, the suffix -ity cannot see into the stem it attaches
to. Similarly, in a compound like oxtail, the fact that the first member takes an irregular plural is invisible at the
level of the entire compound. The plural is oxtails, not *oxtailen. The suffix -ness attached to childless necessarily
creates an abstract mass noun, not a count noun whose plural is *childlessness(r)en. The plural of the agentive
noun formed from the verb to goose is goosers, not *geeser. In every case, particularities of the internal structure
of a stem are invisible at later stages of derivation and inflection. The principle of strict cyclicity in morphology
means that a non-phrase is just as encapsulated as a phrase as the first member of a compound or as a morpheme in
a derived word.
To illustrate this further, consider words formed from names, like Reaganomics. By turning Reagan (what
would be a full noun phrase in the phrasal syntax) into a noun stem for further derivation, all the properties of the
noun phrase Reagan become inaccessible. For instance, it is no longer an R-expression for Condition C. The same
is true for the pronoun he in words like he-man: it is no longer a pronoun for Binding Principle B:
(16) a. Reagan changed his views over his eight years as president. In later years, he rejected Reaganomics.
(he=Reagan)
b. He hates he-men. (no Condition B violation)
It is not at all clear that it would be desirable to view Reagan and he as quotations in these cases of word formation.
If they are, then we might as well view every stem as a quotation in word formation, since as far as I can tell they
all have the same properties.
To further make this point, consider compounds. The stems that go into a compound act exactly like the same
stems in other cases of derivational morphology. In the examples below, the noun phrase squirrel(s) is an R-
expression in the syntax and gives rise to a Condition C violation if it is coreferential with a commanding pronoun.
The stem squirrel does not, in either a compound or a derived word:
If we want to claim that “encapsulation” follows from quotation, then every stem must be a quotation. Conversely,
if we recognize that every stem in derivational morphology is encapsulated, then there is nothing special about
phrases in morphology. Their properties just follow from the way morphology works in general.
It is also important that this same encapsulation takes place entirely within words, too. This is difficult to show
in English because of its relative paucity of morphology, but the third-person singular ending -s ought to make the
point. Consider the following example, from a newspaper:
Here we have a word, out-Trumps, which contains a stem derived from a name. The ending -s encodes a third-
person singular subject. We know from the syntactic context that this third-person singular subject is Trump
himself. Yet we see no Condition C violation within the word: it is perfectly possible for the referent of -s to be the
8
same as the individual denoted by the name that forms the root of the word. In other words, stems are encapsulated
even within words, not just across word boundaries.
What this means is that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is superfluous, as will be shown at length in section 5. That
is, the fact that phrases inside words are encapsulated follows not from the Lexicalist Hypothesis, but from the
way morphology works. To say that a phrase inside a word has no internal structure is just to locate it within
morphology in general. Crucially, word boundaries play no role; only morpheme boundaries do.
The Lexicalist Hypothesis also rules nothing out, as far as I can tell, once one admits a mechanism that can
turn any phrase into a noun stem (or adjective, or verb).7 I conclude that all of these instances of phrases occurring
inside words really do falsify the Lexicalist Hypothesis, contra assertions to the contrary.
(i) Mary said that Bill “loves himself” and he does. (Cappelen and Lepore 2007, 146, (11.10))
I find that this is also possible in phrasal compounds, if the phrase is not a complete sentence:
I also find that ‘respective’ modification is possible (cf. Davidson 1984, citing J.R. Ross):
(iv) a. Her “girls rule, boys drool” taunt applies quite well to Hillary and Donald, respectively.
b. Old Superman and New Superman are in a cool-to-tool relationship, respectively.
c. Tex and the Marshall are in a quick-and-the-dead situation, respectively.
Most accounts of ‘respective’ modification rely on mechanisms of sentential syntax; see Kubota and Levine (2016) and references there. I
will leave a complete exploration of these issues to future work. What is important here is that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is incompatible
with the existence of phrases inside words, and is not useful in explaining their properties when they do occur there.
9
(20) Adjectival Passives
a. The metal looks hammered flat.
b. The bed covers appear shaken smooth.
c. The fields have a trampled-flat look.
If prepositional passives did involve some kind of complex predicate formation, such that the object of the P
becomes equivalent to the direct object of the (complex) V, we would expect resultatives to be grammatical with
them, as well. They are not. A resultative interpretation is not possible (in some cases a depictive interpretation is):
In fact, subjects of prepositional passives pattern with objects of prepositions, which also do not permit resultative
secondary predicates. This indicates that there is no process of complex predicate formation, and the subject of a
prepositional passive does not correspond to the object of a transitive verb.
Verbal prepositional passives can even include more phrasal material, as Postal (1986) and Baltin and Postal
(1996) showed:
(23) a. The bridge was flown (both) over and under. (Postal 1986, 243, note 14)
b. The bridge was flown over and then, but only then, under. (Postal 1986, 243, note 14)
c. Fascism was fought for by Goebbels and (then) against by De Gaulle. (Baltin and Postal 1996, 30,
(9d)).
In the examples in (23), a complex predicate would have to be formed out of a verb and a conjunction of preposi-
tions, but these conjunctions are clearly phrasal.
‘Right’-type modifiers are also possible (these are based on attested examples):
(24) a. . . . no doubt that YouTube app was a trap that was walked right into!
b. I just felt that those were big details that were flown right over.
c. I pointed out that our interest was not in this program, but in doing the best possible thing for U. S.
Steel, but this was glossed right over.
One could try to claim that some of these are cases of word-part ellipsis (see section 3.1 below). This will not
help, however. For instance, Postal’s example with both in (23a) would have to be analyzed as follows, with elided
material struck through:
(25) a. The bridge was flown (both) over and under. (Postal 1986, 243, note 14)
b. = [flown both over] and [flown both under]
10
This analysis would still require a phrasal input to a word, and it would require both to appear in a position where
it is not actually allowed (pronouncing the above string is ungrammatical; both has to scope over the conjunction).
Moreover, clear instances of word-part ellipsis do not permit this: This product was hand-(*both)-made and -packed
(based on Chaves 2008, (4b); see section 3.1).
I conclude from this that prepositional passives, both verbal and adjectival, must be formed from a phrasal
input. They are formed from a V-PP phrasal combination (and the PP can consist of conjoined PPs and can contain
modifiers). This is not consistent with the Lexicalist Hypothesis. In all lexicalist accounts, adjectival passives
are formed lexically (e.g., Wasow 1977, Levin and Rappaport 1986, Horvath and Siloni 2008, Meltzer-Asscher
2011). In some lexicalist accounts, verbal passives are as well (e.g., Lieber 1980; Bresnan 1982, 1995; Levin and
Rappaport 1986; Müller 2006). In a lexical account, it should be impossible to form a passive from a V-PP phrase.
But this is exactly what seems to be going on here.
2.3 Resultatives
Word formation from a phrasal input also occurs with resultatives and caused motion constructions. As is well
known, objects can be added to verbs that do not select objects in certain constructions, for instance in resultatives:
As Müller (2006) shows, these resultatives quite regularly participate in adjectival passive formation and nom-
inalization in German. Corresponding to fish the pond empty is the nominalization Leerfischung, ‘empty fishing’
(Müller 2006, 868). Corresponding to dance her shoes bloody is the adjective in (28b):
As (28c) shows, the resultative is crucial to forming the adjectival passive, since Schuhe is not an argument of the
verb without it. This again appears to be word formation from a phrasal source.
Müller’s own analysis is a lexical one. Consider an example of a nominalization like the following:
(29) die Leerfischung der Nordsee ‘the empty-fishing of the North Sea’ (Müller 2006, 868)
The way the lexical analysis works in Müller (2006) is that a lexical rule applies to the stem fisch- (which appears
in the verb fischen, ‘to fish’). This lexical rule creates a new stem fisch2- which obligatorily takes an NP and an AP
argument (in addition to a subject). Semantically, the NP object is not the logical object of the stem, but is instead
interpreted as the subject of the AP. This permits the stem fisch2- to appear in a verbal frame like [die Nordsee leer
fischen], ‘the North.Sea empty to.fish’.
Next, a nominalization rule may apply, creating Fischung from fisch2-. Fischung inherits the arguments of the
stem, so it can now appear with the adjective leer ‘empty’ and the NP ‘the North Sea’ in (29). Hence, nominalization
in this analysis is not nominalization of a phrase, it is nominalization of a stem, which inherits the arguments of the
input stem and licenses them in the phrasal syntax.
There is an empirical problem with this sort of approach, pointed out by Williams (2011). The problem is that
arguments of nominalizations are never obligatory. This means that Fischung by itself ought to be able to mean
11
‘fish such that X enters state Y as a result’. However, according to Müller (2006), in fact Fischung can only refer
to a plank on a boat. Müller concludes from this fact that Leerfischung must be a nominalization of leer fisch-
(p. 869). His analysis does not actually capture this, however, because it applies the rule only to the stem fisch2-
and not to the phrase leer fisch-.
Of course, the lexicalist analysis could stipulate that for some reason the AP argument of the stem fisch2-
is obligatory even when it is nominalized. This would just be a stipulation, however. If we instead view the
nominalization as derived from a phrasal source, we explain why the resultative AP is obligatory: the only way to
form a nominalization with a resultative is to start from a phrase.
While this sort of case is not decisive, it is suggestive, and a phrasal analysis appears to have advantages over a
lexical one in explaining the properties of a derived word.
2.4 Summary
This section has illustrated several cases of phrasal syntax feeding word formation, in clear violation of the Lexical-
ist Hypothesis. Other examples have also been presented in the literature. For instance, Pulleyblank and Akinlabi
(1988) illustrate a case of phrasal syntax feeding word formation in Yoruba; Goddard (1988) argues for the ne-
cessity of phrasal syntax preceding morphology in the Algonquian language Fox; Rainer and Varela (1992) list
cases of prefixes attaching to phrases in Spanish; Subramanian (1988) describes phrasal syntax feeding derivation
in Tamil; Lefebvre and Muysken (1988) present such a case in Quechua; Lieber and Scalise (2007, 6–8) discuss
another in Italian; and Ackema and Neeleman (2004) present several cases in both English and Dutch.8
Part of the original motivation for the Lexicalist Hypothesis was the apparent lack of phrasal processes feeding
word formation. Since it was proposed, however, more and more instances of phrasal processes feeding word
formation have come to light. The response has often been to reassign those phrasal processes to the word formation
component, as in the example of resultatives in section 2.3.9 What this history shows, however, is that the original
motivation was incorrect. Phrasal processes can and frequently do feed word formation.
(i) a. . . . that the Black Panthers were eager to start a civil war despite its certainty to cause a bloodbath.
(blackpanthercivilrights.blogspot.com/)
b. Sadly a species’ name affects its likelihood to survive.
(https://twitter.com/meeurotaru/status/552744000651001856)
c. But in this case whether or not a man was in a committed relationship had no influence on his likelihood to sexually harass.
(https://books.google.com/books?isbn=1555536387)
Raising to object is also attested, but it is much rarer, and native speakers seem less willing to accept the examples that are attested.
Regardless, the point is that a re-evaluation of Chomsky’s original arguments for the Lexicalist Hypothesis reveals that many of them lose
all force given later lexicalist developments (and further empirical inquiry).
10
In most lexicalist approaches, this follows because the atoms of the phrasal syntax are words. See the works cited above, especially Di
Sciullo and Williams (1987). In other formulations, Lapointe (1980, 8) has a principle stating that “no syntactic rule can refer to elements
of morphological structure”; Selkirk (1982, 70) has a Word Structure Autonomy Condition that bans syntactic operations from involving
categories of both word and sentence structure.
12
3.1 Coordination/Ellipsis of Word Parts
It has long been noted that coordination of word parts is widespread (Nespor 1985, Booij 1985):
(30) a. infra e ultrasuoni (Italian, ‘infra- and ultra-sounds’; Nespor 1985, 201)
b. Freund- oder Feindschaft (German, ‘friendship or hostility’; Booij 1985, 152)
c. Pre- and post-revolutionary France were very different from each other. (Chaves 2008, 264, (10))
Chaves (2008) argues strongly that this phenomenon is actually not coordination of sub-word parts, but co-
ordination of phrases accompanied by word-part ellipsis. Among the arguments is the fact that plural agreement
is possible in (30c), as is antecedence of the reciprocal each other. The subject in (30c) must actually be Pre-
revolutionary France and post-revolutionary France, with deletion of repeated material in the first conjunct.
Regardless, ellipsis is generally regarded as a phrasal process. Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) include it in their
list of processes that cannot target sub-word units (see section 5.2). Obviously, it can. One response is to view this
type of ellipsis as different from phrasal syntax ellipsis; for instance, Chaves (2014) treats it as a process that targets
linearized strings, not syntactic phrases. Note, however, that this ellipsis process cannot break up morphemes that
are not easily segmentable, even when the same phonological string can be stranded in a different morphological
context:
In (36), for instance, we see that the strings bi- and a- can stand alone, as can the string son. But (36c) does not
work, because in these particular words bi-, ma- (similar in sound to a-), and son are not distinct morphemes. This
means that this process of ellipsis is not simply operating on phonological or prosodic strings, it must have access
to morphological structure. It does seem to be true that this type of ellipsis is sensitive to prosody (Booij 1985), but
it is also true that the constraints holding of it cannot be stated solely in terms of prosody, as just demonstrated (see
also Chaves 2008, 2014). Rather, this process of ellipsis makes crucial reference to morphology. This means that
it has access to sub-word parts.
Chaves (2008, 2014) also argues that the ellipsis process at work here is the same one that we see operating
on phrasal units in right node raising and coordinate ellipsis. Corresponding to deletion of the left member of the
second coordinate in word-part ellipsis is what is sometimes regarded as non-constituent coordination:
And corresponding to deletion of the right member of the first conjunct is right node raising:
13
(38) a. [over-application] and [under-application]
b. The break-in on Monday was a [rare breach of royal security] but [not unheard-of breach of royal
security]. (Chaves 2014, 839, (11e))
As these examples show, these two ellipsis processes can target units larger than words, namely, phrases. At
the same time, however, this process must also have access to sub-word morphemes. That is, it can see both units
larger than words and units smaller than words. This is a clear violation of the Lexicalist Hypothesis: the word
formation system is supposed to be encapsulated from everything that deals in units larger than the word. There
should be no process that can target both phrases and morphemes. Yet this type of ellipsis does exactly that.
Another example of this situation can be found in Japanese. In Japanese, it is possible for a causative morpheme
to embed a disjunction of verb phrases, as Kuroda (2003) shows:
In this example, the causative morpheme -(s)ase embeds the disjunction ‘clean the house or pay room rent’. This
is clearly a syntactic phrase. At the same time, the causative morpheme has all properties of an affix (see Manning,
Sag, and Iida 1999, Cipollone 2001). Either this is true disjunction embedded beneath a bound morpheme and is
an example of phrasal syntax feeding word formation, or it is also ellipsis and is another example of a process that
can target both phrases and sub-word units.11
3.2 Focus
It is also well-known that focus can target sub-word units (Selkirk 1984, 271, Wennerstrom 1993, Artstein 2004):
(40) a. That poet is from the POST-colonial era, not the PRE-colonial one.
b. That type of action indicates an A-moral viewpoint, not an IM-moral one.
c. That individual is TRANS-sexual, not BI-sexual.
d. Sex-IST, not sex-Y!
Since focus can also target phrases, this is again an example of a process that makes no distinction between phrasal
and sub-word units (Artstein 2004). It will not do to say that focus operates over some representation that is or-
thogonal to syntactic or morphological structure, because focus is sensitive to phrase structure and to constituency.
This is quite clear with scope, association with focus, and focus projection. I will illustrate with focus projection.
In this phenomenon, focus stress occurs on one particular phonological unit (for instance, a syllable), but what is
interpreted as being in focus can project to dominating nodes in the syntax (see, e.g., Gussenhoven 1984, Selkirk
1984). For instance, focus stress on a syllable of the direct object of a ditransitive verb can be interpreted as just
the direct object being in focus, or the whole VP or the whole IP:
It is not possible to interpret just any string of elements that includes the stressed syllable as focused:
11
Ackema (2014) attempts to defuse the problem Japanese causatives pose for the Lexicalist Hypothesis by claiming that the Japanese
causative morpheme is actually a free form, not an affix. He claims that something can be a free form syntactically but a bound form
phonologically. This appears to be the least parsimonious theory possible: there is a component of word formation for some types of
derivation; a phrasal syntax for putting together phrases out of free forms; and a phonological component that can create phonological
words out of free forms, mimicking the morphological component. In the absence of compelling evidence, any theory with one component,
or even two, should be preferred to one with three. If one believes there are good reasons to admit phonological word formation after
syntax, as in Ackema’s analysis, then one should explore the option of doing all word formation this way, getting rid of the morphological
component altogether.
14
(42) a. * The teacher gave me a PLANner yesterday, not you a painting.
b. * The teacher gave me a PLANner yesterday, not painting the day before.
Since it is sensitive to phrase structure and constituency, focus must operate on the same representation as the
syntax. This is in fact how all research on focus treats it (e.g., Rochemont 1986, Kratzer 1991, Rooth 1992, Krifka
1996).
3.3 Summary
This section has shown that there is no strict separation of the word and phrasal systems as envisaged by the
Lexicalist Hypothesis. There are at least two processes that can target both phrasal and sub-word units.
(43) John told stories about the destruction of himself. (Williams 2007, 354, (2))
In contrast, self-destruction strictly requires coreference between the destroyed and the destroyer. An example like
(44a) cannot instead relate the destroyed with the teller of stories. This means that, in contrast with (43), (44a) is
unambiguous, and must mean (44b), not (44c):
According to Williams, such facts show that “the lexical system has no delayed resolution, but the phrasal system
does” (Williams 2007, 355).
Williams is incorrect about both morphology and syntax here. In (43), of himself combines strictly with destruc-
tion to fill the internal argument role of destruction. The NP himself needs an antecedent, but, as is well-known,
inside NPs reflexives are free to find an antecedent based on perspective or other principles (Pollard and Sag 1992,
Reinhart and Reuland 1993). If himself were to occur as the object of the verb destroy, it would strictly require
covaluation between it and another argument of the verb. That is, phrasal himself, like affixal self-, generally does
not allow delayed resolution. It is only in contexts like within certain kinds of NPs that phrasal himself can take a
long-distance or even discourse antecedent.
Such a discourse antecedent is also available for some instances of affixal self-, contra Williams:
15
(45) a. Her behavior is self-serving. (the behavior does not serve itself, it serves her)
b. Most mission statements are self-aggrandizing. (the statements do not aggrandize themselves, they
aggrandize the stater)
c. Some of the funniest remarks are self-deprecating. (the remarks do not deprecate themselves, they
deprecate the remarker)
In these examples, if self-serving (for example) were to be analyzed as x serves x, then it is not clear how self-
serving could be predicated of her behavior. All of its arguments have already been saturated, and there is no role
for her behavior to fill. In other examples, the NP that is the subject of a predicate adjective with -ing must be the
external argument of the related verb:
(46) a. Her robots are self-replicating. (only: the robots replicate themselves, they cannot replicate her)
b. Those stories are self-destroying. (only: the stories destroy themselves, they cannot destroy the
storyteller)
c. These rumors are self-sustaining. (only: the rumors sustains themselves, they cannot sustain the
rumorer)
d. These tales are self-educating. (only: the tales educate themselves, they cannot educate the teller)
In (45a), then, the analysis must be that her behavior is the external argument (her behavior serves x), and we have
delayed resolution, since self- does not relate two arguments of the stem it attaches to, instead it relates the internal
argument to a non-argument. The examples in (45) are exactly analogous to Williams’s example (43) in the phrasal
system. As can be seen, morphology and syntax behave exactly the same: in general there is no delayed resolution
(46), but in some circumstances we see delayed resolution in both morphology and syntax. (At this point I do not
have any account of what those circumstances are with affixal self-.)
Examples of delayed resolution can also be found in other word-formation processes. One example occurs
in the Bantu languages discussed by Bresnan and Moshi (1990). Bantu languages are famous for their valence-
changing morphology. An applicative affix (“Appl”) can add an argument, for instance a benefactive. A reciprocal
affix (“Recip”) can reduce valence by unifying two arguments into one, interpreted as acting in a reciprocal manner.
When these two combine in the order verb-Appl-Recip in some Bantu languages, like Chichewa, the Recip can only
combine the external argument (or agent) and the argument added by the applicative affix:12
This fits Williams’s characterization of “no delayed resolution”: the reciprocal morpheme can only combine the
most local arguments, it cannot look past the applicative affix and act on an argument of the verb stem that is not
local to it.
However, in some other languages, like Kichaga, this is exactly what happens:
In (48), the theme of the verb stem ‘kill’ and the agent added by the reciprocal morpheme are interpreted as
reciprocal, skipping the benefactive argument added by the applicative morpheme in between. This is delayed
12
Bantu Abbreviations: Asp = Aspect; FV = Final Vowel; Pres = Present tense; SM = Subject Marker; numeral = noun class.
16
resolution: the argument of the verb stem is not saturated immediately, but is only combined with the agent by the
reciprocal morpheme after another morpheme has been added in between. (For an analysis, see Bruening 2006.)
It is true that in most cases, affixes are strictly local in their effects. However, this is true of most cases of the
phrasal syntax, too. It is not true that morphology and syntax are radically different in this respect. In fact, they
seem to behave exactly the same, as a theory with only one grammatical component would predict.
According to Williams, a prefix “can have scope only over the arguments of the item it adjoins to in the word
system” and not the adjuncts “because the arguments of a lexical item are represented on the item itself in some
way, but adjuncts are not” (Williams 2007, 355). In contrast, an item of the phrasal syntax like again attaches to an
entire phrase, which can include adjuncts.
Williams’s claim about affixes is not correct, as has already been shown. The passive morpheme can affect an
NP that is not an argument of the verb (section 2.2). Nominalization in German can include a resultative, also not
a selected argument of the verb (section 2.3). In Japanese, the derivational suffix -sugiro takes scope over an entire
VP, including adverbs (Sadock 1991, 125). Prefixes can attach to phrases that include adjuncts in Spanish (Rainer
and Varela 1992). In numerous languages, a causative morpheme can take scope over an adjunct that is interpreted
as modifying the caused event. I illustrate with Venda:
Other languages that permit this with morphological causatives include at least Japanese (Shibatani 1990, 313–315;
Harley 2008 and references there), Bemba (Givón 1976), Luganda (Pylkkänen 2008, 119), and Finnish (Pylkkänen
2008, 116). Note that the ability of an adverb to take sub-lexical scope is not necessarily an argument against
the Lexicalist Hypothesis. There are analyses of sublexical scope within lexicalist approaches (e.g., the analysis
of again in Dowty 1979). However, proponents of these analyses acknowledge that affixes can take scope over
adjuncts, contra Williams.
Another counterexample from English involves affixal self-, discussed in the previous subsection. The most
general use of this morpheme relates a logical external argument and a logical internal argument, as follows:
However, as noted by Bruening (2014, 418, note 32), affixal self- can also relate an external argument and an
oblique:
17
d. self-concerned = x is concerned with x
e. self-reliant = x relies on x
(53) a. a self-addressed envelope = x addresses an envelope to x
b. a self-assigned task = x assigns a task to x
c. “Mediocrity is self-inflicted, but genius is self-bestowed.” = x inflicts mediocrity upon x, x bestows
genius upon x
Most of the above examples could be considered selected oblique arguments of the base verb, but the following
examples are not amenable to such an analysis:
A for phrase can be added to any verb and is a canonical adjunct, while obliques of the type in (54g) can be added
to any verb of communication. These examples look like self- relating an argument to an adjunct.13
There are also cases where affixal self- seems to correspond to an emphatic reflexive:
Arise and rise are unaccusative verbs and only have one argument; self- must necessarily involve an adjunct with
such verbs. Emphatic reflexives are certainly adjuncts: no verb selects one as an argument. In all of these examples,
then, affixal self- is able to operate on an adjunct, or at least add one. See also Bruening (2014, 417–418), analyzing
other cases of affixal self- as operating on a raising-to-object like structure where the NP involved is not a selected
argument of the verb that self- attaches to.
Williams (2007) therefore seems to have arrived at an erroneous conclusion by looking at the wrong affix. The
prefix that he looks at, re-, is in fact more constrained than Williams characterizes it. Unlike self-, it cannot even
include selected arguments of the stem it attaches to if they have the form of an oblique rather than a direct object
(Carlson and Roeper 1980, Horn 1980, Wechsler 1990):
(56) a. * John reput the book on the shelf. (Wechsler 1990, 9, (18b))
b. John restocked the shelf.
(57) (Wechsler 1990, 12, (30))
a. * John reclimbed over the fence.
b. John reclimbed the fence.
(58) a. * Jimmy rerelied on James.
13
It is unlikely that the examples I have paraphrased with for are actually based on indirect objects. Not all of these examples permit
indirect objects (pay and enter), and the semantics of a double object construction is for many speakers obligatorily caused possession. This
is not the right semantics for most of these examples. (It is also not clear that indirect objects are selected arguments of the verb.)
18
b. * Tammy is reconcerned with her son.
This constraint does not follow from Williams’s general view of word-formation processes; it seems to be idiosyn-
cratic to re-. This particular prefix therefore cannot be used as evidence for a weaker constraint.
At the same time, the prefix re- can include a particle in its scope (Farrell 2005, Larsen 2014, 375–376):
While it is not entirely clear what the relation between a verb and a particle is, the particle is definitely not the direct
object of the verb. Note that self- does not appear to be compatible with particles at all (*self-hooking-up washers,
*a self-sworn-in governor), meaning that in this respect re- is less constrained than self-.
What this comparison between re- and self- indicates is that individual affixes must be analyzed in detail, just
like individual items in the phrasal syntax. There is no general principle like the one posited by Williams; instead
different affixes exhibit different behavior. Some affixes can include non-arguments, while others may not and
may even be more constrained. Any analysis will have to explain the behavior of individual affixes. Analyses of
many types of affixes have been proposed within purely syntactic approaches: on different causative morphemes,
see Pylkkänen 2008; on a syntactic treatment of re-, see Marantz 2009; Bruening (2014, 418) suggests an outline
of an analysis of self-, at least as it combines with adjectival passives. Simply assigning affixation to a lexical
component does not help us to understand the different properties of different affixes. Most importantly, there is no
one principle governing affixes and a different one that governs phrases.
4.3 Headedness
Williams (2007) lists two other differences that he claims hold between the word system and the phrasal system.
The most important one, the claim that the word system provides input objects to the phrasal system and not vice
versa, has already been shown to be false (section 2). The other is the claim that the word system and the phrasal
system obey different principles, so that, for instance, the word system is head-final in English, but the phrasal
system is head-initial. In fact, the driving intuition behind the syntactic approach to word formation is that this
is false: principles of word formation are ones familiar from phrasal syntax (Baker 1985, Hale and Keyser 1993,
among numerous others). As for head directionality, it is rather superficial, and there are numerous counterexamples
in both directions in English: words can be head-initial, like verbs formed with en- (e.g., enrage, enfeeble; Lieber
1988, 214), and compounds can have equal weight for their two parts (e.g., bittersweet, deaf-mute; Lieber 1988,
218). In the other direction, phrases can be head-final, like counterexamples notwithstanding and two years ago.
This difference, such as it is, is simply not significant.14
4.4 Idiosyncrasy
One of Chomsky’s (1970) original arguments for a lexical treatment of nominalizations, repeated in Newmeyer
(2009), is that they are not completely productive or semantically regular. That is, they show a great deal of
idiosyncrasy. The following list of sample semantic irregularities among derived forms (not just nominalizations)
is from Newmeyer:
19
b. ignore (‘pay no attention to’)—ignorance (‘lack of knowledge’)—ignoramus (‘very stupid person’)
c. person (‘human individual’)—personal (‘private’)—personable (‘friendly’)—personality (‘character’)—
personalize (‘tailor to the individual’)—impersonate (‘pass oneself off as’)
d. social (‘pertaining to society’; ‘interactive with others’)—socialist (‘follower of a particular political
doctrine’)—socialite (‘member of high society’)
There are also nominalizations that have no corresponding verb that they could be derived from, for instance
motion (*mote), tuition (*tuit). The same is true of other derived forms (social, *soci).
An often repeated view is that lexical processes and processes of the phrasal syntax differ in productivity,
and this is the basis for Chomsky’s argument. The claim is that operations of the phrasal syntax are completely
productive and semantically transparent, while lexical processes are not regular, often not productive, and are
frequently idiosyncratic.15
Since Chomsky (1970), however, this putative difference has been shown over and over to be false. Processes of
word formation can be productive and semantically transparent (e.g., Di Sciullo and Williams 1987). On the other
side, irregularity is not the exclusive province of the word formation system, it is pervasive in the combinatorial
system generally. There are phrasal idioms, like kick the bucket and the shit hit the fan; there are particle-verb
combinations that are interpreted idiosyncratically and are not completely productive (throw up, chew out, put up
with; see Jackendoff 2002); there are numerous fixed phrases (all of a sudden, never mind) and phrasal collocations
(concerted effort); there are obscure limitations on different types of A-bar movement (Sag 2010). Here again there
is no difference between the word system and the phrase system, and no reason to treat them differently. In fact, if
we want a uniform account of idiosyncrasy, then we have to treat them the same, otherwise we will have to have
two different ways of deriving idiosyncrasy, one for the word system and the other for the phrasal system.
Moreover, simply equating idiosyncrasy with listedness does not help to understand linguistic phenomena. As
an example, Reinhart and Siloni (2005) discuss derived reflexive verbs in various languages, and propose that in
some languages, reflexive verbs are derived in the lexicon, while in others, they are derived in the syntax. In the
syntax languages, reflexive verbs are completely productive, while in the lexicon languages, reflexive verbs are
limited to a small, apparently listed, set, typically verbs of grooming (dress, shave, wash, etc.). However, simply
saying that these are listed in the lexicon does not explain why they are limited and in what way. Anything at all can
be listed, and a listed set can be of arbitrarily large size. Why are reflexive verbs limited to a small set of particular
verbs? Why dress and shave and not tie up and choke? Why not list every single verb in the lexicon, giving the
appearance of complete productivity? In other words, appealing to listedness explains nothing by itself.16
Newmeyer (2009, 105) does ask a pertinent question: In purely syntactic theories of word formation, where
is it recorded which affixes particular roots can combine with? That is, where is it stated that the root destroy
(or destruct or whatever its base form is) combines with -ion, while grow combines with -th and criticize forms
criticism and not *criticization?
This is an important question, but it is a question to be answered, not an argument. Any theory has to answer
this question, whether it assumes the Lexicalist Hypothesis or not. The Lexicalist Hypothesis does not make giving
an answer any easier, since in a lexicalist theory, root and affix combinations are also done via rule, just as in a
purely syntactic theory. The rules just have a different name. Particular roots still have to be specified as undergoing
some rules and not others. The same has to be done in a syntactic theory. The two types of approaches are in the
same boat; the question for all of them is what lexical entries look like, and what information is stored where.
15
Personally, I suspect that the amount of idiosyncrasy in word formation has been vastly overstated. Cases like profess—professor are
few and far between, and most English speakers probably consider the two words to be unrelated. The word profession can also be used to
mean ‘the act of professing’, as in professions of faith, which is completely regular. To my knowledge, no one has actually done a systematic
analysis to back up the claim of massive idiosyncrasy, or to compare the amount of lexical idiosyncrasy to the amount of idiosyncrasy of
phrases. Jackendoff (1997, 156) and Sag et al. (2002, 2) estimate that the number of “multi-word expressions” in a speaker’s lexicon is at
least as large as the number of single-word expressions.
16
Reinhart and Siloni (2005) also claim that it is no accident that the lexicon languages do not permit reflexivization of raising to object
verbs; in their system, this follows from the operation applying in the lexicon, where only selected arguments of a verb stem can be affected.
However, it also follows from these languages limiting reflexivization to a small, listed set of verbs; no raising to object verb is on that list.
The list only consists of grooming verbs, none of which are raising to object verbs.
20
If we give up lexical rules and only have a single syntactic rule component, as I am arguing for here, then all
word formation has to be done by the same syntax that builds phrases. We need a way to capture idiosyncrasies
and lack of full productivity. There are two obvious ways:
1. All specifications are stored in the lexical entries of roots. Suppose we have a root SOCI. In the entry for this
root, it can be recorded that SOCI + -al = ‘pertaining to society’, while SOC + -al + -ist = ‘follower of the
doctrine of socialism’, and so on. (Cf. Marantz 1997.)
2. Lexical entries include syntactic structure. There is a lexical entry for socialist that includes its structure and
its meaning. There is another lexical entry for social that includes its structure and meaning (and its structure
is probably a subset of the structure of socialist). (Cf. Hale and Keyser 1993.)
On both views, combinations are memorized as they are encountered. At the same time, language users will
generalize to some extent and extract commonalities (different individuals may do this to different extents). This
is not really different from most lexicalist views; all that is different is the claim that the system that puts words
together is the same as the system that puts phrases together.
There are also other possibilities besides the two listed, and I will not commit to any one here. It is an empirical
question what the best account is. It seems to me, however, that a uniform account of idiosyncrasy at the word
level and at the phrasal level would be desirable, and this is more likely to be successful in a theory that does not
distinguish the two. (See Bruening 2010 on an approach to phrasal idioms where selection is crucial; selection
operates uniformly throughout the system. See also Sag 2007.)
21
from the Lexicalist Hypothesis. We saw in section 3 that this is incorrect in many instances, but in others it does
seem to be true.
(61) * It’s American history that they’ve been [— teachers] for years. (modified from Bresnan and Mchombo
1995, 187, (3b))
Presumably, if there were no Principle of Lexical Integrity, we would expect word parts to be accessible to extrac-
tion.
The obvious question to ask here is whether the phrasal syntax independently rules out such attempts at ex-
traction. It does, in fact. Extraction, and A-bar extraction in particular, may only target phrases, and not heads
(cf. Haspelmath 2011, 52):
Neither of these illicit instances of extraction is ruled out by the Principle of Lexical Integrity. Independently,
then, we need a constraint to the effect that A-bar extraction only targets phrases, and may not target heads.18 Once
we have this constraint, however, the inability of A-bar extraction to target sub-word units follows: they are not
phrases. There is no need to have a Principle of Lexical Integrity in addition. It is entirely superfluous.
The same constraint operates on A-extraction, too. Raising to subject and passivization may not target a head,
even in a case like the prepositional passive where a subpart of the argument of the verb—the complement of the P
complement of the V—can be extracted:
Both A- and A-bar extraction are constrained to operate on phrases, not heads; and it therefore follows that they
cannot target sub-parts of words, because those are not phrases.
Some lexicalist theories treat raising and passive lexically (e.g., Bresnan 1982, Müller 2006). As such, they
should in principle be able to target sub-parts of words, yet they cannot:
(66) a. * American history is likely [a(n) — teacher] to win Teacher of the Year.
b. * American history was hired [a(n) — teacher].
Some other principle must block this. Typically, this is done simply by the way the rule is stated: it targets an
argument. A sub-part of an argument cannot be targeted. But this by itself rules out targeting a sub-part of a word,
since a sub-part of a word is not an argument. The Principle of Lexical Integrity is thereby rendered superfluous
even within a lexicalist theory. It does no work whatsoever regarding extraction, even in a theory that assumes its
correctness.
18
There are proposals that A-bar extraction can target heads, for instance Müller’s (1996) analysis of partial VP fronting in German.
However, it is not necessary in these analyses that A-bar extraction be able to target a head. Partial VPs can also be targeted, and a verb by
itself can be a partial VP. That is, phrases can contain only one word and still be phrases.
22
Since I am going to propose below that the head-phrase distinction plays a large role in explaining other facts
that form the “residue” of the Lexicalist Hypothesis, it is important to elaborate on this distinction here. First, it is
important to make it clear that the syntactic notion of a head is not the same as a word. In X-Bar Theory, a head is
a zero-level category. Words can consist of multiple heads. Heads can also be complex, and themselves consist of
multiple heads. Conversely, it is possible that the pieces of a phonological word may not have to all be dominated
by a single X-zero node in the syntax (for instance, shouldn’t’ve might span multiple head positions; note that it
cannot front as a unit in subject-auxiliary inversion, which is commonly viewed as head movement). I will not
attempt to define the notion of a word (something that might be impossible; see note 2). As for the notion of a
head, I will simply assume that there is such a notion, and it is what is typically meant in syntactic theories that
adopt some form of X-Bar Theory. As a rough guide, most morphemes are heads, and a complex of morphemes is
a complex head (which may or may not be a word). It is not my intent to spell out a complete syntactic theory of
word formation here. An intuitive understanding of what a head is—-something that is common to most syntactic
theories—is all we need to explain the phenomena discussed in this section. What is important is that a head is not
the same as a word, and so I have not simply reintroduced the Lexicalist Hypothesis under a different guise. For
instance, the ban on extracting heads rules out extracting both words and sub-parts of words. This is very different
from the Principle of Lexical Integrity, which only bans extracting sub-parts of words.
To illustrate further with extraction, consider compounds again. We saw in section 2.1 that the first member
of a compound can be a syntactic phrase. Such phrases still cannot be extracted by A-bar movement processes,
however:
Any theory of compounds has to say that the phrase curled up on itself is turned into a noun stem, as described
in section 2.1. As also discussed in that section, the internal structure of stems in general is invisible to elements
outside that stem. As soon as the stem [N [XP curled up on itself]] is created, then, the internal structure of N
becomes invisible. This is due to strict cyclicity, the correct form of which should cover both morphology and
syntax since they are the same (but I will not attempt to spell out a theory of cyclicity here). So, the fact that there
is a phrase inside the compound is not something that can be accessed in the syntax when it goes to do extraction.
The XP inside the N head is simply invisible, as are all the phrases that it dominates. (For an analysis of phrasal
compounds that attempts to derive their inaccessibility to extraction from cyclicity, see Sato 2010.)
Note that it is not important to this explanation that the phrase is inside a word. It is important that it is inside a
head. It is also important to note once again that strict cyclicity in morphology does not follow from the Lexicalist
Hypothesis, since it holds within as well as across words. Thus, this explanation is not simply rephrasing the
Principle of Lexical Integrity, and the Lexicalist Hypothesis really can be done away with, in favor of independently
needed constraints that do not refer to words.
23
There are some indications that coordination of heads is illusory, however, and is probably always phrasal
coordination (as proposed by Kayne 1994 and Beavers and Sag 2004). For instance, coordination of demonstratives
and modals can include phrasal elements like adverbs and negation, and in coordination of verbs, and can always
be replaced by but did not:
(69) a. You can bring this but probably not that water bottle.
b. They can and probably will arrest you.
c. They shot but did not kill the suspect.
That is, any apparent instance of head coordination can include more than one word in one of the conjuncts, making
it phrasal.
Similarly, coordination of verbal heads (here nominalized) acts like coordination of word parts in permitting
plural agreement and antecedence of reciprocals (see above and Chaves 2008):
(70) a. Their shooting and killing (of) the suspect were unrelated to each other. (the suspect was wounded
by the shooting last year, and then they killed him with a knife this year)
b. Her offering and making me an espresso usually take place on different days.
It is plausible, then, that all instances of apparent head coordination are actually phrasal coordination with ellipsis,
or are instances of right node raising (as Chaves 2014 seems to analyze them).
Borsley (2005) and Abeillé (2006) argue against this view, arguing that there must be true coordination of
heads. However, their arguments do not go through. In every case where they contend that some phenomenon
distinguishes head coordination from phrasal coordination (primarily right node raising), the same fact holds with
what must be phrasal coordination (but did not). As an example, Abeillé (2006) claims that head coordination and
right node raising differ in available interpretations. According to her, head coordination in (71a) and right node
raising in (71b) differ in that in (71a), there are necessarily only two books, whereas in (71b) there could be either
two or four books:
This is true, but a variation on (71a) that is clearly phrasal (72) also obligatorily involves only two books:
(72) Paul read but did not annotate two linguistics books.
Example (72) simply cannot be analyzed as head coordination, since the second coordinate involves three different
words. The forced “single object” interpretation could therefore not be explained by the coordination being head
coordination.
The same is true of all of the differences Borsley (2005) and Abeillé (2006) point to between right node raising
and apparent head coordination: all the respective facts still hold when and is replaced with but did not. For
instance, weak pronouns are still allowed in (73b), just as they are in (73a), although they are not very good in
canonical right node raising (73c):
For further discussion of prosody in right node raising, see Chaves (2014). Prosody does not argue for the existence
of head coordination, because the same prosody of (73a) holds in examples like (73b), which is clearly phrasal.
Additionally, in all the cases from other languages cited by Abeillé (2006), the phenomena claimed to be limited
to heads also always admit “light” modification of the putative head, making it necessarily phrasal. Abeillé’s own
analysis appeals to phonological weight, and it is likely that that is the factor involved in her data, not the head-
phrase distinction.
24
I conclude that the arguments for the existence of head coordination do not go through, and there are good
reasons to think that, in fact, apparent coordination of heads is always coordination of phrases.19 If this is true,
then coordination is just one of many processes (like extraction above) that only targets phrases, and not heads.
This is a restriction in the phrasal syntax, but it has the result that the coordination of word parts is banned, with
no reference to the Lexicalist Hypothesis or the Principle of Lexical Integrity. Once again, all the work of the
Lexicalist Hypothesis is already done by the phrasal syntax.
Although coordination is limited to phrases, ellipsis clearly is not (see section 3.1). Neither is focus (section
3.2). Ellipsis and focus seem to be able to target any syntactic unit: morphemes, complex heads, phrases. (Focus
also seems to be able to cross cyclic boundaries, but in the phrasal syntax it is known to be insensitive to islands.)
In the typology of syntactic elements, then, we have ones that can only target phrases (extraction, coordination);
ones that can only target heads (some morphemes discussed below); and ones that can target anything (ellipsis,
focus). Note that this typology makes no reference to the notion of a word.
(75) a. * People who smoke like other do-so-ers. (Postal 1969, 217, (69a))
b. * We need a truck but not a one-driver. (cf. We need a truck but not a driver of one.)
It is not exactly clear how this would follow from the Principle of Lexical Integrity. According to Simpson
(1983a), coreference is part of the sentence grammar (the phrasal system), so a pronoun could not receive its
reference within a word, since the sentence grammar has no access to sub-words parts. As Ward, Sproat, and
McKoon (1991) note, this would then have nothing to say about cross-sentential anaphora, which is also ruled
out. Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) themselves explain the facts in a way that makes no reference to Lexical
Integrity: “indexical pronouns, though they do have intrinsic lexical content and can appear word-internally, lack
the appropriate lexical content to serve as morphological bases for semantic derivatives” (p192). In other words,
pronouns have very little semantic content, and that is what stops them from forming words like *himite and *do-so-
er. In attested words with pronouns like he-man and she-wolf, the pronouns are used just for their gender features,
which is the only real semantic content that they do have. If this is correct, then inbound anaphoric islands have
nothing to do with the Principle of Lexical Integrity and everything to do with the paucity of content in pro-forms.
A different explanation is offered by Sproat (1988). According to Sproat, pro-forms are always maximal
projections. Pronouns are actually NPs, do so is a full VP, and so on. Word formation processes, according to
Sproat, never operate on maximal projections. For instance, it is possible that suffixes like -ite and agentive -er
strictly select heads, and may not combine with phrases (see more on this below). This rules out formations like
*himite and *do-so-er.
Note that either of these potential explanations would permit pro-forms in compounds. In Sproat’s theory, pro-
forms should be allowed if a phrase can form the input to a word, and we know this is possible in a compound.
19
A reviewer points to examples like no man or woman as requiring coordination of noun heads, since it is not identical to no man or
no woman. However, negative indefinites are unusual in many respects, for instance in being able to take split scope (see, e.g., Abels and
Martí 2010, Penka 2012). It is possible that an elided element in the second conjunct is simply an indefinite (something like no man or any
woman). Such coordinations can also include more words, for instance even: No intellectual or even academic has the courage to speak
out about the war (COCA). This supports the contention that they are actually phrasal. On coordination of nouns below determiners in
general, Le Bruyn and de Swart (2014) argue that the second N always has a null determiner or undergoes an equivalent type shift and so is
equivalent to a full NP (a phrase).
20
Postal (1969) also discusses “outbound anaphoric islands,” but these are not considered by Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) to be evidence
for Lexical Integrity, since they were shown by Ward, Sproat, and McKoon (1991) to be regulated by pragmatics.
25
In Bresnan and Mchombo’s analysis, if a pro-form can be contentful, it should be allowed, and pro-forms can get
content in phrases like those that form the input to compounding. It is correct that phrasal compounds can include
pro-forms, including fully referential ones:
Recall that Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) claim that phrases in compounds are “lexicalized” (see above). If they
are lexicalized then they would be expected to behave like words, and be inbound anaphoric islands. Instead they
behave like phrases, and permit pro-forms.
Additionally, Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) themselves cite numerous counterexamples to the inbound anaphoric
island constraint, where in some languages a derived word form can include pronominal agreement affixes. Harris
(2006) similarly shows that Georgian word-formation processes can include fully referential pronouns. This means
that inbound anaphoric islands are not observed in some languages (or in compounds in English), a state of affairs
that should be impossible if they really follow from the putatively universal Principle of Lexical Integrity.
Inbound anaphoric islands, then, follow the pattern we have seen throughout this paper: there are numerous
counterexamples to what the Lexicalist Hypothesis requires, and where there are restrictions, they follow from
other considerations.
I turn now from the Principle of Lexical Integrity to other claims that have been made in the literature.
A derived N takes adjectives, not adverbs, and may not have sentential negation or auxiliary verbs that are possible
with the verb it is derived from. According to Chomsky and Newmeyer, these facts only follow if derived Ns enter
the syntax as unanalyzable Ns.
Chomsky (1970) originally contrasted nominalizations with gerunds, which have the external distribution of
nouns but the internal structure of VPs or even clauses:
26
According to Chomsky (1970), gerunds are derived transformationally; if nominalizations are not, we explain the
differences between them.
However, later work in lexical frameworks like LFG and HPSG has lost the ability to make such a distinction.
In these approaches, any process of word formation has to be a lexical process (Dowty 1978, 412, Bresnan 1982,
21, Müller and Wechsler 2014, 32). Since gerunds are morphologically derived forms, they must be lexical, too.
An HPSG analysis of gerunds is proposed in Malouf (2000); an LFG analysis is proposed in Bresnan and Mugane
(2006). Their properties are captured with lexical rules and constraints in these analyses.
This means that the Lexicalist Hypothesis again does no work in explaining linguistic facts: all the work is
done by the actual analysis. Nominalizations are analyzed one way, gerunds another; their differences are captured
by analyzing them differently. The Lexicalist Hypothesis plays no role whatsoever.
Moreover, the claim that Ns derived from Vs do not have phrasal properties of Vs has been argued to be false,
although the facts are disputed. Fu, Roeper, and Borer (2001) argue that Ns derived from Vs may have adverbs
following them, while underived ones may not:
This has been contested by Newmeyer (2009), but all of his examples of putatively underived nouns (p.109, ex-
amples 47a–c) are either zero-related to verbs (use, release) or can plausibly be analyzed as derived from a verbal
source that is not actually used (recourse, which is used in the “light verb” construction take recourse). The fol-
lowing contrast between a derived N and an underived one appears to me to support Fu, Roeper, and Borer’s view
over that of Newmeyer:21
However, I acknowledge that the matter requires more research to be settled. (Newmeyer’s skepticism of the do so
data also offered by Fu, Roeper, and Borer 2001 does appear to be warranted.)
Other facts have been suggested to distinguish derived from underived Ns. For example, Bruening (2013)
argues that certain PP adjuncts require verbal structure, and so they are only permitted with Ns that include verbal
structure. Instrumentals are one such. They are allowed with VPs and with derived nouns, but not with (at least
some) underived nouns (Bruening 2013, 12, (48–52)):
27
We also saw in section 2.3 that nominalizations can include resultative secondary predicates in German. If
resultative secondary predicates can only combine with VPs (something that seems to be true in English), then
these nominalizations include verbal structure.
At the same time, it is true that nominalizations differ from gerunds in having largely nominal syntax. Any
theory will have to account for this difference, whether it assumes the Lexicalist Hypthesis or not. As described
above, lexicalist theories do this by analyzing gerunds and nominalizations as both lexical, but treat them differently.
A purely syntactic theory would derive them both syntactically, but again would have to treat them differently.
Perhaps the simplest analysis would treat them differently only in size: nominalizations nominalize a fairly small
structure, say VoiceP as in Bruening 2013, 31–34, while gerunds nominalize a larger phrase, perhaps a full IP as
in Abney 1987. Producing an analysis is not important here; the important point is that lexicalist and syntactic
theories are entirely equivalent on this point. All the work is done by the actual analysis; no work is done by the
Lexicalist Hypothesis.22
In (86b), how cannot modify just the complete part of the noun completeness. The examples in (86c–d) are meant
to show that there is nothing semantically ill-formed about this question.
I will address this issue in two parts. First, we need to know why how cannot target just a sub-part of a word.
That is the topic of this subsection. Then, we need to rule out the bracketing in (86b), where the suffix -ness attaches
to a phrase. That is the topic of the next subsection.
We saw in section 3 that certain processes can target sub-word parts. In particular, ellipsis and focus can.
Apparently, a wh-phrase like how cannot. The question is whether we need the Lexicalist Hypothesis to explain
why it cannot.
The answer is no. Since at least Bresnan (1973) and Jackendoff (1977), degree elements like how and quite
have been treated as elements that are sister to a phrase (for instance, they are specifiers in X-bar theory; for a recent
HPSG treatment of how as a specifier, see Ginzburg and Sag 2000, 187–188). This by itself rules out having them
modify a sub-word unit: the only thing they can modify is the constituent X-bar (or some other phrasal constituent):
22
One argument presented against syntactic accounts of nominalizations is that they can be coordinated with underived nouns and share
arguments (Wechsler 2008a, Müller and Wechsler 2014). In section 5.2 I suggest that all apparent coordination of heads is actually co-
ordination of phrases. If this is correct, the possibility of coordination of derived and underived nouns is not problematic for any theory.
Additionally, the argument relies on the assumption that only heads with the same number and type of arguments can be coordinated, but
this is false:
This is possible even with weak pronouns (she described and then brought me it), which is supposed to rule out a right node raising analysis
(see more on this in section 5.2). The fact that derived words can be coordinated with underived words shows nothing.
28
(87) AP
Spec A
how A
complete
How cannot be the specifier of an NP (*how man, *how liberty), so it simply cannot modify the N completeness.
As a specifier, it also cannot attach directly to an A head, which might then permit further suffixation. We need
some such constraint independently, to rule out cases like the following:
As can be seen, how only combines with a full phrase, including any adverbs, and may not combine just with a
head.23 The analysis of how as a specifier captures this (assuming adverbs can only attach below the specifier). But
this analysis again rules out how combining with a sub-part of a word, with no need for the Lexicalist Hypothesis.24
Similarly, Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) say that the Lexicalist Hypothesis and their Principle of Lexical
Integrity are needed to account for the inability of adverbs and other phrases to modify sub-word parts:
All of these are supposed to be ruled out by something like the No Phrase Constraint (Botha 1981) in the
Lexicalist Hypothesis: phrases may not form the input to word-formation. (In most versions this just follows from
the hypothesized architecture of the grammar and need not be stated as a separate constraint; see note 3.)
At various points above, I have suggested that certain affixes might actually be able to combine with phrases
(importantly, phrases that have not been turned into heads as in compounding). One example was the passivizing
affix, which can apply to a V-PP phrase. Depending on how the data turn out, nominalizing affixes might be another
example. If some affixes can combine with phrases, then what rules it out in this particular case?
23
A reviewer points out that the German equivalent of how seems to have different properties. I will leave exploration of other languages
to future research, but again it is important to emphasize that we need detailed analyses of every individual morpheme, as they do not act
alike.
24
It should be noted that it is possible for how to question a sub-part of a word, but that sub-part needs to be repeated and seems to be
treated as a full phrase:
29
One type of analysis that has been proposed within a purely syntactic approach to word formation is to hypoth-
esize that morphemes select different categories to combine with. For instance, Pylkkänen (2008) proposes that
causative morphemes in the world’s languages divide into three types. One selects a full phase (in the phase theory
of Chomsky 2000), one selects a verb phrase, and one selects a bare root. The first two combine with phrases and
may include things like adverbs. The root-selecting causative morpheme combines only with a bare root, and not a
phrase.
Stating this slightly differently, and in a way consonant with the typology of linguistic elements proposed
in section 5.2, one could propose that some morphemes select only heads, and may not combine with phrases.
(Heads, unlike roots, can be complex.) The morpheme -ness would be one such morpheme. (The analysis of -ness
in Embick and Marantz 2008 seems to have this character.) In support of this sort of analysis, complements of
adjectives are generally not preserved from the adjective to the noun in -ness:
Note that the morphemes suggested to attach to phrases, the passivizing and nominalizating suffixes, do often
preserve complements:
One could argue that there is a correlation between preserving arguments of the stem and being able to combine
with phrases. If a stem must project its (internal) arguments in its minimal phrase, then any affix that combined
with a phrase rather than just a head would preserve (internal) arguments of the stem it attaches to. An affix that
attaches only to a head may or may not preserve the arguments of that head. Since the suffix -ness does not preserve
arguments, we can conclude that it does not attach to phrases.
30
If this is true, then there is an independent explanation for the inability of -ness to attach to APs with wh-phrases
and adverbs, or phrasal comparatives. We do not need the Lexicalist Hypothesis to explain this, it follows from
properties of individual affixes.
To clarify, what I am proposing is that individual affixes can differ in their selectional requirements. Some, like
the passivizing affix, can combine with a whole VP:
(99) PassP
Pass VP
V PP
Others, like -ness, can only combine with a head, although that head can be complex and need not be a word:
(100) N
A -ness
mind -ful
In the case of the passive morpheme, some mechanism is necessary to combine the morpheme with the head of its
complement. This could be movement (e.g., Baker 1988b) or it could be some other mechanism. The two could
combine phonologically and not syntactically, for instance. Or, the form of the V could be determined to be its
passive participle form because it occurs in the local context of Pass (so the actual phonological content of Pass
never occupies the Pass head). There are numerous possibilities, which I will not decide between here. What is
important is that the two types of affixes differ, and the effects of the No Phrase Constraint (where they do occur)
fall out from the difference.
A more general point to be made here is the same one that was made earlier regarding self- versus re- (section
4.2): It is necessary to analyze individual affixes or word-formation processes in detail. They differ significantly
from each other, in such a way that blanket statements like “affixes cannot attach to phrases” and “affixes may not
take scope over adverbs” are simply false: some can, and those that cannot are often even more constrained, in
peculiar ways. We do not want a model of grammar whose architecture rules out affixes combining with phrases
and affixes taking scope over adverbs, because many of them do. If some of them do not, then that is something
that is going to have to be captured in the analysis of those particular affixes, since it will not follow from general
principles. I have given one suggestion for an analysis here, but it may well be that a better analysis is available.
One can only decide this based on extensive research into the properties of the individual affixes involved.
5.7 Summary
This section has gone through several cases from the literature where some phenomenon has been claimed to
require the Lexicalist Hypothesis and its Principle of Lexical Integrity. In every case, the Lexicalist Hypothesis
is superfluous: all of the data are already accounted for by independently needed principles, even within theories
that assume the Lexicalist Hypothesis. Importantly, these principles never refer to the notion of a word. Rather,
they refer to syntactic units like ‘head’ and ‘phrase.’ Another important point is that we need detailed analyses of
particular morphemes, since they can be both more and less constrained than what the principles of the Lexicalist
Hypothesis require. The Lexicalist Hypothesis has no explanatory value in understanding any of the phenomena
discussed.
6 Conclusion
The Lexicalist Hypothesis was a reasonable hypothesis about the organization of the human language faculty. It
could have been correct that the human grammar has distinct word formation and phrasal syntax components.
However, all of the evidence reviewed here indicates that it does not. The first part of this paper showed that there
31
are numerous phenomena where phrasal syntax provides the input to word formation, and there are also phenomena
where phrasal operations have access to sub-word units. Claims that processes of word formation and processes
of phrasal syntax obey different principles were shown to be incorrect. The second part of the paper showed that
where there are facts to be explained, they follow from independent principles that make no mention of the word
as a linguistic unit. Since the Lexicalist Hypothesis refers specifically to the notion of a word, it is incapable of
explaining the facts that it was designed for.
If some hypothesis is both incorrect and does no work, the obvious action to take is to discard it. In this case,
doing so leads to the kind of theory that considerations of parsimony would also prefer: a theory where there is
only one combinatorial system for both words and phrases, not two distinct systems. As noted in the introduction, a
theory with only one component is simpler than and therefore preferable to a theory with two components, all other
things being equal. This paper has attempted to show that all other things are equal: the Lexicalist Hypothesis does
no work, and so has no empirical advantage to outweigh the parsimony consideration. In fact, it seems to be at a
disadvantage, since it gets many empirical facts wrong.
References
Abeillé, Anne (2006), “In Defense of Lexical Coordination.” In Olivier Bonami and Patricia Cabredo Hofherr, eds.,
Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 6, online publication: http://www.cssp.cnrs.fr/eiss6/, pp. 7–36.
Abels, Klaus, and Luisa Martí (2010), “A Unified Approach to Split Scope.” Natural Language Semantics 18: 435–470.
Abney, Steven Paul (1987), The English Noun Phrase in Its Sentential Aspect. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of
Technology. Distributed by MIT Working Papers in Linguistics, Cambridge, Mass.
Ackema, Peter (2014), “Japanese Causatives are not Relevant to Lexical Integrity.” Studia Linguistica 68: 169–197.
Ackema, Peter, and Ad Neeleman (2002), “Syntactic Atomicity.” Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 6:
93–128.
Ackema, Peter, and Ad Neeleman (2004), Beyond Morphology: Interface Conditions on Word Formation. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Aronoff, Mark (1976), Word Formation in Generative Grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Artstein, Ron (2004), “Focus Below the Word Level.” Natural Language Semantics 12: 1–22.
Baker, Mark (1985), “The Mirror Principle and Morphosyntactic Explanation.” Linguistic Inquiry 16: 373–415.
Baker, Mark (1988a), “Theta Theory and the Syntax of Applicatives in Chichewa.” Natural Language and Linguistic
Theory 6: 353–389.
Baker, Mark C. (1988b), Incorporation: A Theory of Grammatical Function Changing. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Baltin, Mark R., and Paul M. Postal (1996), “More on Reanalysis Hypotheses.” Linguistic Inquiry 27: 127–145.
Beavers, John, and Ivan A. Sag (2004), “Coordinate Ellipsis and Apparent Non-Constituent Coordination.” In Stefan
Müller, ed., Proceedings of the 11th International Conference on HPSG, Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications, pp.
48–69.
Becker, Thomas (1993), “Back-Formation, Cross-Formation, and ‘Bracketing Paradoxes’ in Paradigmatic Morphol-
ogy.” In Geert Booij and Jaap van Marle, eds., Yearbook of Morphology, Dordrecht: Foris, pp. 1–25.
Booij, Geert E. (1985), “Coordination Reduction in Complex Words: A Case for Prosodic Phonology.” In Harry van der
Hulst and Neil Smith, eds., Advances in Nonlinear Phonology, Dordrecht: Foris, pp. 143–160.
Borer, Hagit (2005), Structuring Sense Volume I: In Name Only. New York: Oxford University Press.
Borsley, Robert D. (2005), “Against ConjP.” Lingua 115: 461–482.
Botha, Rudolf P. (1981), “A Base Rule Theory of Afrikaans Synthetic Compounding.” In Michael Moortgat, Harry
van der Hulst, and Teun Hoekstra, eds., The Scope of Lexical Rules, Dordrecht: Foris, pp. 1–77.
Bresnan, Joan (1973), “The Syntax of the Comparative Clause Construction in English.” Linguistic Inquiry 4: 275–343.
Bresnan, Joan (1982), “The Passive in Lexical Theory.” In Joan Bresnan, ed., The Mental Representation of Grammat-
ical Relations, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 3–86.
Bresnan, Joan (1995), “Lexicality and Argument Structure.” Paper presented at the Paris Syntax and Semantics Con-
ference, 1995.
32
Bresnan, Joan, and Sam A. Mchombo (1995), “The Lexical Integrity Principle: Evidence from Bantu.” Natural Lan-
guage and Linguistic Theory 13: 181–254.
Bresnan, Joan, and Lioba Moshi (1990), “Object Asymmetries in Comparative Bantu Syntax.” Linguistic Inquiry 21:
147–185.
Bresnan, Joan, and John Mugane (2006), “Agentive Nominalizations in Gı̃kũyũ and the Theory of Mixed Categories.”
In Miriam Butt, Mary Dalrymple, and Tracy Holloway King, eds., Intelligent Linguistic Architectures: Variation
on Themes by Ronald M. Kaplan, Stanford: CSLI Publications, pp. 201–234.
Bruening, Benjamin (2006), “The Morphosyntax and Semantics of Verbal Reciprocals.” Ms., University of Delaware.
Bruening, Benjamin (2010), “Ditransitive Asymmetries and a Theory of Idiom Formation.” Linguistic Inquiry 41:
519–562.
Bruening, Benjamin (2013), “By-Phrases in Passives and Nominals.” Syntax 16: 1–41.
Bruening, Benjamin (2014), “Word Formation is Syntactic: Adjectival Passives in English.” Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 32: 363–422.
Cappelen, Herman, and Ernie Lepore (2007), Language Turned on Itself: The Semantics and Pragmatics of Metalin-
guistic Discourse. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carlson, Gregory N., and Thomas Roeper (1980), “Morphology and Subcategorization: Case and the Unmarked Com-
plex Verb.” In Teun Hoekstra, Harry van der Hulst, and Michael Moortgat, eds., Lexical Grammar, Dordrecht:
Foris, pp. 123–164.
Carnie, Andrew (2000), “On the Notions XP and X0 .” Syntax 3: 59–106.
Chaves, Rui P. (2008), “Linearization-Based Word-Part Ellipsis.” Linguistics and Philosophy 31: 261–307.
Chaves, Rui P. (2014), “On the Disunity of Right-Node Raising Phenomena: Extraposition, Ellipsis, and Deletion.”
Language 90: 834–886.
Chomsky, Noam (1970), “Remarks on Nominalization.” In R. A. Jacobs and P. S. Rosenbaum, eds., Readings in English
Transformational Grammar, Waltham, MA: Ginn, pp. 184–221.
Chomsky, Noam (2000), “Minimalist Inquiries: The Framework.” In Roger Martin, David Michaels, and Juan
Uriagereka, eds., Step by Step: Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik, Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, pp. 89–155.
Cipollone, Domenic (2001), “Morphologically Complex Predicates in Japanese and What They Tell Us About Gram-
mar Architecture.” Ohio State University Working Papers in Linguistics 56: 1–52.
Clark, Herbert H., and Richard J. Gerrig (1990), “Quotations as Demonstrations.” Language 66: 764–805.
Cram, D. F. (1978), “The Syntax of Direct Quotation.” Cahiers de Lexicologie 33: 41–52.
Culicover, Peter W., and Ray Jackendoff (2005), Simpler Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Davidson, Donald (1984), “Quotation.” In Donald Davidson, ed., Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, Oxford:
Clarendon Press, pp. 79–92.
Di Sciullo, Anna-Maria, and Edwin Williams (1987), On the Definition of Word. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
den Dikken, Marcel (1995), Particles: On the Syntax of Verb-Particle, Triadic, and Causative Constructions. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Dowty, David (1978), “Governed Transformations as Lexical Rules in a Montague Grammar.” Linguistic Inquiry 9:
393–426.
Dowty, David (1979), Word Meaning and Montague Grammar. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Dowty, David (1988), “Type Raising, Functional Composition, and Non-Constituent Conjunction.” In Richard T.
Oehrle, Emmon Bach, and Deirdre Wheeler, eds., Categorial Grammars and Natural Language Structures, Dor-
drecht: Reidel, pp. 153–197.
Embick, David (2004), “On the Structure of Resultative Participles in English.” Linguistic Inquiry 35: 355–392.
Embick, David, and Alec Marantz (2008), “Architecture and Blocking.” Linguistic Inquiry 39: 1–53.
Fabb, Nigel Alexander John (1984), Syntactic Affixation. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Farrell, Patrick (2005), “English Verb-Preposition Constructions: Constituency and Order.” Language 81: 96–137.
Fu, Jingqi, Thomas Roeper, and Hagit Borer (2001), “The VP within Process Nominals: Evidence from Adverbs and
the VP Anaphor Do So.” Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 19: 549–582.
33
Ginzburg, Jonathan, and Ivan A. Sag (2000), Interrogative Investigations: The Form, Meaning, and Use of English
Interrogatives. Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Givón, Talmy (1976), “Some Constraints on Bantu Causativization.” In Masayoshi Shibatani, ed., The Grammar of
Causative Constructions, New York: Academic Press, vol. 6 of Syntax and Semantics, pp. 325–351.
Goddard, Ives (1988), “Post-Transformational Stem Derivation in Fox.” Papers and Studies in Contrastive Linguistics
22: 59–72.
Gussenhoven, Carlos (1984), On the Grammar and Semantics of Sentence Accent. Dordrecht: Foris.
Hale, Kenneth, and Samuel Jay Keyser (1993), “On Argument Structure and the Lexical Expression of Syntactic
Relations.” In Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, eds., The View from Building 20: Essays in Linguistics in
Honor of Sylvain Bromberger, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 53–109.
Halle, Morris (1978), Formal Versus Functional Considerations in Phonology. Bloomington: Indiana University Lin-
guistics Club.
Halle, Morris, and Alec Marantz (1993), “Distributed Morphology and the Pieces of Inflection.” In Kenneth Hale
and Samuel Jay Keyser, eds., The View from Building 20: Essays in Linguistics in Honor of Sylvain Bromberger,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 111–176.
Harley, Heidi (2008), “On the Causative Construction.” In Shigeru Miyagawa and Mamoru Saito, eds., The Oxford
Handbook of Japanese Linguistics, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 20–53.
Harris, Alice C. (2006), “Revisiting Anaphoric Islands.” Language 82: 114–130.
Haspelmath, Martin (2011), “The Indeterminacy of Word Segmentation and the Nature of Morphology and Syntax.”
Folia Linguistica 45: 31–80.
Hawkins, John A., and A Cutler (1988), “Psycholinguistic Factors in Morphological Asymmetry.” In John A. Hawkins,
ed., Explaining Language Universals, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 280–317.
Hawkins, John A., and Gary Gilligan (1988), “Prefixing and Suffixing Universals in Relation to Basic Word Order.”
Lingua 74: 219–259.
Hohenhaus, Peter (1998), “Non-Lexicalizability as a Characteristic Feature of Nonce Word-Formation in English and
German.” Lexicology 4: 237–280.
Horn, Laurence R. (1980), “Affixation and the Unaccusative Hypothesis.” In Papers from the Sixteenth Regional Meet-
ing of the Chicago Linguistic Society, Chicago: University of Chicago, Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 134–146.
Horvath, Julia, and Tal Siloni (2008), “Active Lexicon: Adjectival and Verbal Passives.” In Sharon Armon-Lotem, Gabi
Danon, and Susan Rothstein, eds., Current Issues in Generative Hebrew Linguistics, Amsterdam/Philadelphia:
John Benjamins, pp. 105–134.
Jackendoff, Ray S. (1972), Semantic Interpretation in Generative Grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jackendoff, Ray S. (1977), X̄ Syntax: A Study of Phrase Structure. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jackendoff, Ray S. (1997), The Architecture of the Language Faculty. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jackendoff, Ray S. (2002), “English Particle Constructions, the Lexicon, and the Autonomy of Syntax.” In Nicole
Dehé, Ray Jackendoff, Andrew McIntyre, and Susan Urban, eds., Verb-Particle Explorations, Berlin: Mouton de
Gruyter, pp. 67–94.
Kayne, Richard (1994), The Antisymmetry of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kiparsky, Paul (1982a), “From Cyclic Phonology to Lexical Phonology.” In Harry van der Hulst and Norval Smith,
eds., The Structure of Phonological Representations (Part I), Dordrecht: Foris, pp. 131–175.
Kiparsky, Paul (1982b), “Lexical Phonology and Morphology.” In Seok Yang, ed., Linguistics in the Morning Calm,
Seoul: Hanshin, pp. 3–91.
Kratzer, Angelika (1991), “The Representation of Focus.” In Arnim von Stechow and Dieter Wunderlich, eds., Seman-
tics: An International Handbook of Contemporary Research, Berlin: de Gruyter, pp. 825–834.
Krifka, Manfred (1996), “Frameworks for the Representation of Focus.” In Geert-Jan M. Kruijff, Richard T. Oehrle,
and Glyn Morrill, eds., ESSLLI 96: Formal Grammar, Universität des Saarlandes: Department of Computational
Linguistics and Phonetics.
Kubota, Yusuke, and Robert Levine (2016), “The Syntax-Semantics Interface of ‘Respective’ Predication: A Unified
Analysis in Hybrid Type-Logical Categorial Grammar.” Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 34: 911–973.
Kuroda, S.-Y. (2003), “Complex Predicates and Predicate Raising.” Lingua 113: 447–480.
Lapointe, Steven G. (1980), A Theory of Grammatical Agreement. Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.
34
Larsen, Darrell (2014), Particles and Particle-Verb Constructions in English and Other Germanic Languages. Ph.D.
thesis, University of Delaware.
Le Bruyn, Bert, and Henriëtte de Swart (2014), “Bare Coordination: The Semantic Shift.” Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 32: 1205–1246.
Lefebvre, Claire, and Pieter Muysken (1988), Mixed Categories: Nominalizations in Quechua. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Levin, Beth, and Malka Rappaport (1986), “The Formation of Adjectival Passives.” Linguistic Inquiry 17: 623–661.
Levin, Beth, and Malka Rappaport Hovav (1995), Unaccusativity: At the Syntax-Lexical Semantics Interface. Cam-
bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lieber, Rochelle (1980), On the Organization of the Lexicon. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. Distributed by MIT Working Papers
in Linguistics.
Lieber, Rochelle (1988), “Phrasal Compounds in English and the Morphology-Syntax Interface.” In CLS 24: Papers
from the Parasession on Agreement in Grammatical Theory, Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 202–222.
Lieber, Rochelle (1992), Deconstructing Morphology: Word Formation in Syntactic Theory. Chicago and London: The
University of Chicago Press.
Lieber, Rochelle, and Sergio Scalise (2007), “The Lexical Integrity Hypothesis in a New Theoretical Universe.” In
G. Booij, L. Ducceschi, B. Fradin, E. Guevara, A. Ralli, and S. Scalise, eds., Proceedings of the Fifth Mediterranean
Morphology Meeting, on-line publication: http://mmm.lingue.unibo.it/, pp. 1–24.
Malouf, Rob (2000), “Verbal Gerunds as Mixed Categories in Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar.” In Robert D.
Borsley, ed., The Nature and Function of Syntactic Categories, San Diego: Academic Press, vol. 32 of Syntax and
Semantics, pp. 133–166.
Manning, Christopher D., Ivan A. Sag, and Masayo Iida (1999), “The Lexical Integrity of Japanese Causatives.” In
Robert D. Levine and Georgia M. Green, eds., Studies in Contemporary Phrase Structure Grammar, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 39–79.
Marantz, Alec (1997), “No Escape from Syntax: Don’t Try Morphological Analysis in the Privacy of Your Own
Lexicon.” In Alexis Dimitriadis, Laura Siegel, Clarissa Surek-Clark, and Alexander Williams, eds., Proceedings
of the 21st Annual Penn Linguistics Colloquium, no. 4:2 in Penn Working Papers in Linguistics, Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania.
Marantz, Alec (2009), “Resultatives and Re-Resultatives: Direct Objects May Construct Events by Themselves.” Paper
presented at the Penn Linguistics Colloquium.
Mascaró, Joan (1976), Catalan Phonology and the Phonological Cycle. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Tech-
nology.
Meibauer, Jörg (2007), “How Marginal are Phrasal Compounds? Generalized Insertion, Expressivity, and I/Q-
Interaction.” Morphology 17: 233–259.
Meltzer-Asscher, Aya (2011), “Adjectival Passives in Hebrew: Evidence for Parallelism between the Adjectival and
Verbal Systems.” Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 29: 815–855.
Mohanan, K.P. (1986), The Theory of Lexical Phonology. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Müller, Stefan (1996), “Yet Another Paper about Partial Verb Phrase Fronting in German.” In Jun ichi Tsuji, ed., Pro-
ceedings of COLING-96: 16th International Conference on Computational Linguistics (COLING96), Copenhagen:
Association for Computational Linguistics, pp. 800–805.
Müller, Stefan (2006), “Phrasal or Lexical Constructions?” Language 82: 850–883.
Müller, Stefan (2013), “Unifying Everything: Some Remarks on Simpler Syntax, Construction Grammar, Minimalism,
and HPSG.” Language 89: 920–950.
Müller, Stefan, and Stephen Wechsler (2014), “Lexical Approaches to Argument Structure.” Theoretical Linguistics
40: 1–76.
Nespor, Marina (1985), “The Phonological Word in Italian.” In Harry van der Hulst and Neil Smith, eds., Advances in
Nonlinear Phonology, Dordrecht: Foris, pp. 193–204.
Newmeyer, Frederick J. (2009), “Current Challenges to the Lexicalist Hypothesis: An Overview and a Critique.” In
William D. Lewis, Simin Karimi, Heidi Harley, and Scott O. Farrar, eds., Time and Again: Theoretical Perspectives
on Formal Linguistics in Honor of D. Terence Langendoen, Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 91–117.
Pafel, Jürgen (2011), “Two Dogmas on Quotation.” In Elke Brendel, Jörg Meibauer, and Markus Steinbach, eds.,
Understanding Quotation, Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 249–276.
35
Pafel, Jürgen (2015), “Phrasal Compounds are Compatible with Lexical Integrity.” Sprachtypologie und Universalien-
forschung 68: 263–280.
Partee, Barbara H. (1973), “The Syntax and Semantics of Quotation.” In Stephen R. Anderson and Paul Kiparsky, eds.,
A Festschrift for Morris Halle, New York: Holt, Reinhart and Winston, pp. 410–418.
Penka, Doris (2012), “Split Scope of Negative Indefinites.” Language and Linguistics Compass 6: 517–532.
Pesetsky, David (1987), “Wh-in-Situ: Movement and Unselective Binding.” In Eric Reuland and Alice ter Meulen,
eds., The Representation of (In)definiteness, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 98–129.
Pollard, Carl, and Ivan Sag (1992), “Anaphors in English and the Scope of the Binding Theory.” Linguistic Inquiry 23:
261–303.
Postal, Paul M. (1969), “Anaphoric Islands.” In Robert I. Binnick, Alice Davison, Georgia M. Green, and Jerry L.
Morgan, eds., Papers from the Fifth Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, Chicago: University of
Chicago, Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 205–239.
Postal, Paul M. (1986), Studies of Passive Clauses. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Postal, Paul M. (2004), Skeptical Linguistic Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pulleyblank, Douglas, and Akinbiyi Akinlabi (1988), “Phrasal Morphology in Yoruba.” Lingua 74: 141–166.
Pylkkänen, Liina (2008), Introducing Arguments. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rainer, Franz, and Soledad Varela (1992), “Compounding in Spanish.” Rivista di Linguistica 4: 117–142.
Reinhart, Tanya, and Eric Reuland (1993), “Reflexivity.” Linguistic Inquiry 24: 657–720.
Reinhart, Tanya, and Tal Siloni (2005), “The Lexicon-Syntax Parameter: Reflexivization and Other Arity Operations.”
Linguistic Inquiry 36: 389–436.
Rochemont, Michael S. (1986), Focus in Generative Grammar. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Rooth, Mats (1992), “A Theory of Focus Interpretation.” Natural Language Semantics 1: 117–121.
Sadock, Jerrold M. (1980), “Noun Incorporation in Greenlandic: A Case of Syntactic Word Formation.” Language 56:
300–319.
Sadock, Jerrold M. (1991), Autolexical Syntax: A Theory of Parallel Grammatical Representations. Chicago: Univer-
sity of Chicago Press.
Sag, Ivan A. (2007), “Remarks on Locality.” In Stefan Müller, ed., Proceedings of the 14th International Conference
on Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar, Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications, pp. 394–414.
Sag, Ivan A. (2010), “English Filler-Gap Constructions.” Language 86: 486–545.
Sag, Ivan A., Timothy Baldwin, Francis Bond, Ann Copestake, and Dan Flickinger (2002), “Mutiword Expressions: A
Pain in the Neck for NLP.” Lecture Notes in Computer Science 2276: 1–15.
Sato, Yosuke (2010), “Complex Phrase Structures within Morphological Words: Evidence from English and Indone-
sian.” Lingua 120: 379–407.
Schachter, Paul, and Fe T. Otanes (1972), Tagalog Reference Grammar. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Selkirk, Elisabeth O. (1982), The Syntax of Words. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Selkirk, Elizabeth O. (1984), Phonology and Syntax: The Relation between Sound and Structure. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Shibatani, Masayoshi (1990), The Languages of Japan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Shibatani, Masayoshi, and Taro Kageyama (1988), “Word Formation in a Modular Theory of Grammar: Postsyntactic
Compounds in Japanese.” Language 64: 451–484.
Simpson, Jane (1983a), Aspects of Warlpiri Morphology and Syntax. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technol-
ogy. Distributed by MIT Working Papers in Linguistics, Cambridge, Mass.
Simpson, Jane (1983b), “Resultatives.” In Lori Levin and Malka Rappaport, eds., Papers in Lexical-Functional Gram-
mar, Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club, pp. 143–157.
Spencer, Andrew (1988), “Bracketing Paradoxes and the English Lexicon.” Language 64: 663–682.
Spencer, Andrew (1991), Morphological Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.
Spencer, Andrew (2005), “Word-Formation and Syntax.” In Pavol Štekauer and Rochelle Lieber, eds., Handbook of
Word-Formation, Amsterdam: Springer, pp. 73–97.
Sproat, Richard (1985), On Deriving the Lexicon. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
36
Sproat, Richard (1988), “On Anaphoric Islandhood.” In Michael Hammond and Michael Noonan, eds., Theoretical
Morphology: Approaches in Modern Linguistics, Orlando: Academic Press, pp. 291–301.
Subramanian, Uma M. (1988), “Subcategorization and Derivation: Evidence from Tamil.” In D. Brentari, G. Larson,
and L. MacLeod, eds., Papers from the Twenty-fourth Annual Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society,
Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 353–361.
Ward, Gregory L., Richard Sproat, and Gail McKoon (1991), “A Pragmatic Analysis of So-Called Anaphoric Islands.”
Language 67: 439–474.
Wasow, Thomas (1977), “Transformations and the Lexicon.” In P. Culicover, A. Akmajian, and T. Wasow, eds., Formal
Syntax, New York: Academic Press, pp. 327–360.
Wechsler, Stephen (1990), “Accomplishments and the Prefix re-.” In Juli Carter and Rose-Marie Déchaine, eds., Pro-
ceedings of the North Eastern Linguistic Society XIX, Amherst, MA: GLSA, University of Massachusetts, pp.
419–434.
Wechsler, Stephen (2008a), “A Diachronic Account of English Deverbal Nominals.” In Charles B. Chang and Hannah J.
Haynie, eds., Proceedings of the 26th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, Somerville, MA: Cascadilla
Proceedings Project, pp. 498–506.
Wechsler, Stephen (2008b), “Dualist Syntax.” In Stefan Müller, ed., Proceedings of the 15th International Conference
on Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar, Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications, pp. 294–304.
Wennerstrom, Ann (1993), “Focus on the Prefix: Evidence for Word-Internal Prosodic Words.” Phonology 10: 309–
324.
Wiese, Richard (1996), “Phrasal Compounds and the Theory of Word Syntax.” Linguistic Inquiry 27: 183–193.
Williams, Alexander (2011), “Objects in Resultatives.” Natural Language and Linguistic Theory to appear: .
Williams, Edwin (2007), “Dumping Lexicalism.” In Gillian Ramchand and Charles Reiss, eds., The Oxford Handbook
of Linguistic Interfaces, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 353–381.
37