On Being at Work: The Social Construction of The Employee
On Being at Work: The Social Construction of The Employee
Nancy Harding
Gossip and Organizations
Kathryn Waddington On Being At Work
On Being At Work
The Social Construction of the Employee
The Social Construction of the Employee
Nancy Harding
Nancy Harding
www.routledge.com
This series presents innovative work grounded in new realities, addressing is-
sues crucial to an understanding of the contemporary world. This is the world
of organised societies, where boundaries between formal and informal, public
and private, local and global organizations have been displaced or have van-
ished, along with other nineteenth century dichotomies and oppositions. Man-
agement, apart from becoming a specialized profession for a growing number
of people, is an everyday activity for most members of modern societies.
Similarly, at the level of enquiry, culture and technology, and literature
and economics, can no longer be conceived as isolated intellectual fields;
conventional canons and established mainstreams are contested. Manage-
ment, Organization and Society addresses these contemporary dynamics of
transformation in a manner that transcends disciplinary boundaries, with
books that will appeal to researchers, student and practitioners alike.
Nancy Harding
First published 2013
by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Simultaneously published in the UK
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group,
an informa business
© 2013 Taylor & Francis
The right of Nancy Harding to be identified as the author of the editorial
material has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in
any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing
from the publishers.
Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or
registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation
without intent to infringe.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Harding, Nancy, 1952–
On being at work : the social construction of the employee / by Nancy
Harding.
p. cm. — (Routledge studies in management, organizations, and
society ; 21)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. Work—Social aspects—History—21st century. 2. Women professional
employees—History—21st century. 3. Women employees—History—21st
century. I. Title.
HD6955.H3527 2012
306.3’61—dc23
2012038919
Typeset in Sabon
by Apex CoVantage, LLC
This book is dedicated to my siblings:
Dawn Mary Parkes
Robert Davies
Julie Davies
Shan Stockwood
Fiona (Fifi) Wake
Adrian (Adey) Davies
Acknowledgements xi
4 Becoming Human 86
Appendix 185
Notes 187
References 189
Index 203
This page intentionally left blank
Acknowledgements
This book seeks to develop a theory of being at work in the 21st century:
what does work mean for us, what does it do to us and what sort of persons
does it allow us to become? It has three interrelated arguments. First, in
Western societies we grow up with dreams of the person we will one day be,
dreams we do not necessarily abandon as we get older. Work is one of the
major forums in which we believe we will constitute those future, dreamed-
of selves. Second, labour, or the tasks we perform in fulfilling the terms
of the employment contract, should therefore be distinguished from work,
which involves processes of self-making over and above the ‘mere’ doing
of labour. Third, the organization’s desire is that we be reduced to zombie-
machines which labour and that are less than human, and although we try
to circumvent this desire in various ways, organizations always limit the
possibilities for achieving the self I/we wish to be(come). The dreams of the
me-I-might-become through work are therefore shattered by the organiza-
tion’s compulsion that forces me to labour. In brief, the thesis of this book is
that organizations murder the me’s-that-might-have-been.
I borrow the term ‘less than human’ from the philosopher Judith Butler,
whose work provides much of the theoretical frame for the book’s argu-
ments. In ‘Butler-speak’, the questions I am seeking to answer are: what
does it mean to be a being doing paid work in/for that thing we call ‘an or-
ganization’, who is this being that is doing the doing and how is this subject
brought into being through the doing?
Although this work emerges out of both Marxist and Foucauldian labour
process theory’s hugely significant analysis of managerial control and em-
ployee resistance (Braverman, 1974; Littler and Salaman, 1982; Knights
and Willmott, 1989; Alvesson and Willmott, 1996; Cooper and Burrell,
1998), its trajectory is somewhat different in that it investigates what goes
on beyond the control/resistance binary. The control/resistance coupling
2 Introduction
ineluctably ties the working self into a relationship with management, so
that staff are management’s other and therefore can know one another only
through a managerial lens. Although that is an important aspect of what it
is to be a being at work, there are spaces and places where management is
not omnipresent, where selves are constructed not only in resistance to or
conformity with management but also beyond the purview of management.
In this book I conceive of employees, not managers, making a working place
out of the space in which work is carried out (Lefebvre, 1991). So, rather
than starting from the position of management organizing and controlling
work in ways that result in more or less resistance from employees, that is,
locating management as the powerful and the normative, I am starting from
a perspective that regards the workplace as a social sphere where life, in all
its glory, is lived by beings who are seekers after dreamed-of selves and into
which management intrudes. In this reading, a social workplace is the norm,
and management, or ‘the organization’, transgresses the norm.
Alongside Butler’s work, the inspiration for this book was a somewhat
un-nuanced reading of Marx’s theory of alienation (Marx 1988, originally
published in 1844). In that early work (which I discuss in more depth in
Chapter Six), Marx argued that the employee is alienated within capital-
ism in four ways: from the product, from the self, from the social and from
nature. Turning this on its head suggests that the non-alienated employee
is someone who is engaged meaningfully in producing a product or service
they value, who works in a social environment where they can develop a
strong sense of self and in conditions that are aesthetically pleasing (and
obviously not controlled by capitalism). In contemporary parlance, we can
envisage a utopia in which people constitute confident, fulfilled workplace
selves through the work they do and the people they do it with. This changes
the focus so that economic exploitation and the managerialist compulsion
to maximise productivity are somewhat decentred. Although these must, of
course, remain highly pertinent, there are other conditions in 21st-century
workplaces that require our attention. A brief detour through some of
Bauman’s work and his articulation of a major change between early and
late modernism will explain.
In Consuming Life (2007), Bauman proposes that we live in an era of
a society of consumers, in which the boundary between commodities and
consumers is effaced. That is, in order to have selfhood, individuals must
work on themselves, must indeed manufacture themselves, become a com-
modity that is to be ‘consumed’ by self and others. How one looks, how
one behaves and how one develops one’s skills and expertise must add up
to a package (the self) that can be ‘sold’ to an employer or be judged by
oneself and fellow citizens in much the same way as we judge objects of-
fered for sale in shop windows. In Bauman’s words (2007:12), ‘no one can
become a subject without first turning into a commodity, and no one can
keep his or her subjectness secure without perpetually resuscitating, resur-
recting and replenishing the capacities expected and required of a sellable
Introduction 3
commodity. . . . The “subjectivity” of the “subject”, and most of what that
subjectivity enables the subject to achieve, is focused on an unending effort
to itself become, and remain, a sellable commodity’. When one looks in
the mirror, one judges what one sees as if it were offered in a marketplace.
Subjects must turn themselves into commodities so as to lift themselves out
of a ‘grey and flat invisibility and insubstantiality, making themselves stand
out from the mass of indistinguishable objects’ (12). Bauman argues that
whereas, in the society of producers that previously held sway, commodity
fetishism hid from view the human substance involved in the production
of objects (Marx’s thesis), in its successor, the society of consumers, sub-
jectivity fetishism hides this new, commoditised reality. Now the emotions
are dominated by the constantly revivified abilities of wanting, desiring and
longing that have become the ‘principal propelling and operating force of
society’ (28).
In the society of producers, Bauman argues, work played the lynchpin
role in organizing society. Now, he argues, work is secondary, and con-
sumerism has become not only the lynchpin but an attribute of society: it is
consumerism that holds society together and provides the ‘specific param-
eters for effective individual life strategies’ (29). Rather than gratification
of needs, there is an ever-increasing volume and intensity of desires and a
belief, always impossible to prove, that commodities will satisfy insatiable
needs. The supreme value of such a society is happiness (44), and there is a
promise that happiness is available through the consumption of objects, but
this promise is always unfulfilled, the pursuit of yet more objects to consume
must be continuously repeated and so the promise of happiness brings only
unhappiness.
Moreover, and importantly for this book, in the society of consumers the
self becomes an object for consumption by both self and others: the self is
commoditised, has to be worked on and made into a sellable commodity.
To be ‘fully and truly human’ requires making the self into both an ideal
commodity (59 et passim) and a competent consumer (64): failure results in
exclusion and ‘Promethean shame’ (59 et passim).
Although Bauman captures extremely well the importance of working
on the self so that it becomes a commodity to be consumed by both self
and others, I diverge from his thesis on two points. The first is his sharp
distinction between work and consumerism. We do not compartmentalise
our lives so neatly, so the work we do is and indeed must be a major aspect
of the selves we constitute, as the vast literature on identities in organi-
zations testifies (see Alvesson, Ashcraft and Thomas, 2008, for a review).
Work on constituting the self, on identity-making, is another way in which
organizations may seek to control us (Alvesson and Willmott, 2002). But,
although there is increasing pressure to turn ourselves into the sort of work-
place commodity that the organization will desire to hire (Sabath, 2007),
the workplace is also a social world, so we may constitute ourselves as
commodities for consumption by ourselves and our fellow employees. This
4 Introduction
work, in which recognition is given, is productive and may (or should) be
pleasurable. Second, and relatedly, Bauman’s pessimism can be parried with
Foucault’s exploration of the ethics of working on the self, that is, ‘an exer-
cise of the self on the self by which one attempts to develop and transform
oneself, and to attain to a certain mode of being’ (Foucault, 1997a:282).
This is a ‘practice of freedom’ (not of liberation) that should be conducted
ethically (ibid.:283). In other words, whilst work on the self is in many
ways concerned with commoditisation of the self, it does not have just that
one, singularly pessimistic, interpretation. There are other explanations and
other possibilities, and Foucault’s thesis brings with it implications of an
ethical duty to constitute workplace selves that nourish other workplace
selves.
In summary, the earliest inspiration for this book’s arguments was Marx’s
theory of alienation within modern capitalism. Its more recent inspiration is
Judith Butler’s analyses of abjection in postmodern capitalism’s conditions
of subjection and subjectification. We move, it seems, from alienation to
abjection. This book takes Butler into the workplace, along with an unem-
ployed person, a boss, a manual worker, an archaeologist and two academ-
ics, so as to explore the forms that alienation and abjection may or may not
take in 21st-century working lives.
Those are the academic inspirations for the arguments in this book. There
are other, more personal reasons for needing to write it. I have been im-
mersed in ‘critical management studies’ for a quarter of a century, and what
bothers me in many of its debates is the absence of explorations of work
other than through the lens of control and resistance. Much working life
goes on despite, rather than because of, management, and there is much
about the sense of a working self that is not encapsulated within concepts of
control and resistance. The conditions of possibility that led this particular,
authorial ‘I’ to be concerned with how organizations render subjects abject,
nonhuman, beyond the reach of ethics and within the reach of only limited
definitions of justice, arise from memories of my life before I became an
academic, a life in which I took for granted my feelings of inferiority. I was
a working-class girl who was told subtly when I watched films or television
or read a novel or a newspaper that I was, in my class and gender status, in-
ferior. That inferiority penetrated the psyche. I swam in inferiority like a fish
swims in water: it was so much a part of my sense of self I hardly noticed
it, although I constantly felt it. It fuelled resentment and despair and a sense
of the impossibility of ever being good enough to pass as ‘normal’. Marx’s
theory of alienation, when I encountered it as a mature student, described
some of this experience, but I have found it explained best by postcolonial
theory, notably Said’s Orientalism (1978) and Fanon’s Black Skin, White
Masks (2008). These authors articulate in a way that theories of economic
Introduction 5
exploitation never do the subjective experience of being an abjected (infe-
rior, despised) self.
A sense of the injustices of what labouring (and thus class identity) does
to people seems, looking back on my childhood and early adulthood in a
coal-mining village, so deeply part of the mining quotidian, of the sense of a
community that defined itself as ‘not-manager’, that this need to explore the
different forms by which work oppresses us is part of my personal always-
already there, waiting only for me to gain knowledge of the language neces-
sary for the undertaking of such an exploration. On the other hand, the ‘I’
referred to throughout this text, that is, ‘I’ the author, is an academic sitting
at her desk typing, referring to texts, evading the direct gaze of a managerial
other although indirectly measured by it. There are many frustrations in this
job, but in many ways it is a dream job, one with status and self-respect.
I have become in some ways the me I dreamed of being when I made the
first, faltering inquiries about the possibilities of going to university as a
mature student. This book is therefore an attempt in some ways to under-
stand my own experiences; it is the personal become philosophical.
My aim, therefore, is to develop a theory on what it is to be at work,
that is, to be engaged in workplace activities (the doing of work) in which
the ongoing processes of the becoming of the workplace self simultaneously
take place. I will appropriate Butler’s arguments, weaving them through the
work of some other theorists and individual’s accounts of their working
lives, all the time delighting in the licence she gives to meld together different
theoretical perspectives when so doing facilitates explanation and under-
standing. There is also some optimism in Butler’s later work in which she
develops a new form of left-wing politics based on ethical relationships. It is
that optimism that I want to use in order to avoid a patriarchal pessimism
that otherwise could emerge from a study such as this one.
ESTABLISHING TERMS
Social Constructionism
This is the second book in a planned trilogy that focuses on the social con-
structions of management (2003), the employee (2013) and the organiza-
tion (as soon as possible). As in the first book, I am using the term ‘social
constructionism’ very broadly, to refer to a critical, relativist, interpretivist
position (Burrell and Morgan, 1979; Crotty, 1998) that adapts itself as new
theoretical positions become available or as authors become tired of meth-
odolatry (Janesick, 1994).
The Zombie-Machine
I am using the term ‘zombie-machine’ as shorthand to capture that form
of the self which organizations seem to prefer in their employees: devoted
6 Introduction
to the work, devoid of any objectives or pleasures save those which relate
to the organization’s purpose and little more than extensions of organiza-
tional technologies—that is, computerised machines made out of human
flesh but without any desire for agency save that which is required to fulfil
organizational objectives. This description emerges out of four decades of
antiperformative (Fournier and Grey, 2000) approaches to understanding
management and organizations, inspired notably by Braverman’s seminal
Labor and Monopoly Capital (1974), taken forward in various forms of
labour process theory (see Littler and Salaman, 1982, for a review) and in
the various antiperformative approaches more or less encapsulated in the
category ‘critical management studies’ (see Grey and Willmott, 2005, for
‘classic’ papers, and O’Doherty and Willmott, 2001, for an analysis of the
relationship between labour process theory and critical management). I will
use the phrase ‘zombie-machine’ throughout the book, relying on these four
decades of work by academics major and minor to justify its use.
In Chapter One, using the contrast between the lives of two sisters (myself
and my sister Julie) and Butler’s recent work on recognition, I argue that we
desire (paid) employment not only because it provides the means of suste-
nance but also because it is one of the primary locations where work on the
self is undertaken. I distinguish in this chapter between labour (the tasks
of doing the job) and work (the possibility of developing a self through
the doing of the job). Chapter Two explores how managers themselves, the
people who do the work of management, are as caught up in this desire
as are other staff. Using a discussion of the working life of the owner of a
small business which I read through the account of the master/slave dialectic
in Butler’s work, this chapter argues that the ‘boss’ is as controlled by the
title ‘boss’ as is staff. The argument is that the will of the manager requires,
for that person to know that s/he is a manager, that staff be reduced to the
status of zombie-machine. I therefore trace through the psyche and desires
of one manager the inscription of centuries of capitalism, colonialism, class
and hierarchy that constitute the speaking subject as ‘manager’. The para-
dox of this is explored in Chapter Three, the Bondsman’s Tale, in which
I use Butler’s Antigone’s Claim (1997) to explore the working life of a male
manual worker, Shakeel. In that chapter we, in the guise of a male manual
worker, go into the cave where Antigone was to die and see how arbitrary is
the division between management and staff. Shakeel despises managers even
as he speaks the idiom of management.
Introduction 13
Chapter Four builds further on Butler’s thesis on kinship in Antigone’s
Claim to analyse the working life of an archaeologist. This illuminates the
distinction between labour and work and argues that the friends with whom
we work provide that recognition through which we become human. Chap-
ter Four is therefore a thesis on friendship and work. Chapter Five turns to
Butler’s early work and explores organizations and gendering. It argues that
we are surprised into gender, with labour requiring a compulsory gendering
of the subject and work allowing (some of us, some of the time) to escape
from the pall that gender casts on the psyche and on selves. Chapter One
therefore articulates a desire to constitute a self through the work we aspire
to, and the succeeding four chapters explore how that desire is frustrated
by the organization’s proscriptions so that, even though self-making is un-
dertaken, circumstances limit the possibilities for being selves. Chapter Six
argues that this is a form of murder, of the me’s-I-might-have-been. Rather
than Butler’s work, which says little directly about death, I turn in this chap-
ter to Jonathon Dollimore’s book Death, Desire and Loss in Western Cul-
ture (2001). Similarly, where other chapters work with interviews with one
or two people, this chapter deviates from that modus operandi in that it
draws on a cultural product, the whodunit, to help articulate and expound
its arguments. I return to Marx’s theory of alienation in that chapter. Finally,
the book concludes, in Chapter Seven, with an exploration of the ethics of
organizational self-making.
1 What Is ‘Work’? A Tale
of Two Sisters
Figure 1.1 Five siblings (Mary, Shan, Robert, Fifi, Julie, and with apologies to Adey
who had wandered off)
What Is ‘Work’? A Tale of Two Sisters 15
In contrast, my sister Julie will have spent today much as she has spent
every day for the past 15 years. She will have walked to our father’s house
in the village a mile from where we grew up, will have lit his fire, cooked his
breakfast, done his shopping and cleaning, and gone back to her own home
to cook the midday meal for her sons before continuing with the chores
necessitated by caring for a frail elderly relative. Her day is full of what she
describes as drudgery. Is what Julie does ‘work’, and, if so, what is this thing
called ‘work’ that encompasses two such very different ways of employing
one’s time?
Here are two sisters carrying out very different forms of labour for which
the rewards are hugely different: Julie receives in return for her labours min-
imum state benefits, while I receive the salary of a senior academic, which
is extremely generous in contrast to my sister’s income. My job allows me
to travel; Julie has never been out of the UK and has not had a holiday for
15 years. My working life is adventurous, challenging, stimulating, reward-
ing, prestigious and (save for time spent in meetings) extremely interesting;
my sister’s, as we will see, is full of unremitting toil, care and responsibility
and deprives her of ‘a life’. In this chapter I am using this account of two
sisters whose destinies have diverged so greatly to develop the thesis that, in
the 21st century, labour and work are two very different, albeit conjoined,
things: labour refers to the tasks that one does as part of one’s job; work to
the aspects of one’s job through which the (working) self, that ongoing proj-
ect through which one constructs the ‘me’, is constituted. This, of course, is
only one of the forums in which the self is constructed, but my focus in this
book is on working lives and workplace selves. I introduce in this chapter
the thesis that the desire for work is a desire to construct the ‘me’ I wish to
be. I will argue in Chapter Six that these future me’s are killed, or murdered,
by organizations.
My inspiration in this chapter is what was at the time of writing Judith
Butler’s most recent book, Frames of War (FW, 2009), and the related Precarious
Lives (PL, 2004). Frames of War is Butler’s response to the violence
perpetrated on Moslem and other cultures by the US and its allies following
the 9/11 atrocities in New York. In it, she calls for a revivified left politics
based on a new ontology of the body. Her analysis focuses on how atroci-
ties may be freely committed upon some people by others because those
upon whom violence is visited are not recognised as living human beings.
This requires Butler’s development of a thesis of what is ‘a life’ and what is
‘a human being’, with the first being a condition for but not a guarantor of
the latter. In other words, the very fact of being born into the species Homo
sapiens does not necessarily allow the individual to become human. The
questions to which she pursues answers are therefore:
• What are the conditions that facilitate the recognition of some people
as human and others as less than human?
• What forms are taken by the violence enacted in and as a consequence
of the process of exclusion from the categories of the human?
16 On Being At Work
Butler’s distinction between ‘a life’ and ‘a human being’ set me wonder-
ing if such a distinction could be usefully transposed to the workplace. Criti-
cal analyses of management and organizations that focus on management’s
desire to control every aspect of working lives (see Jermier and Knights
[1994] for an overview, Thomas and Davies [2005] for an insightful discus-
sion and other recent useful analyses in Fleming and Spicer [2003; 2008])
suggest the utility of such a distinction in that it offers ways of thinking
through the effects on the person of being treated like some recalcitrant and
particularly complicated piece of machinery. This leads to the distinction
in this chapter between labour and work. My thesis is that it is ‘a life’ (or
what I am calling a zombie-machine) that labours, but ‘work’ elevates that
life to the status of the human; management1 requires that we labour (as
material objects that are alive but not human), but we, as living, breathing,
emoting human subjects, desire to work and, through so doing, constitute
a sense of self. Labour is carried out by zombie-machines who are denied
access to the human; work encompasses activities over and above labour so
that selves which are human are performatively constituted. In other words,
paraphrasing Butler, my questions are:
These questions will not be answered in this chapter alone but will
be developed as the book progresses. The book’s thesis is that organiza-
tional violence takes the form of the murder of the selves who might have
been had they been nurtured through work rather than suffocated by
labour.
Butler seeks to explore in Frames of War two problems, one epistemo-
logical and the other ontological. The epistemological problem concerns
the issue of framing, or how we develop the politically saturated ‘frames
through which we apprehend or, indeed, fail to apprehend the lives of oth-
ers as lost or injured (lose-able or injurable)’ (2009:1). The ontological issue
is: what is a life? Questions about how ‘life’ is defined and understood and
what brings into visibility those who are regarded as alive, rendering others
invisible, never having lived, arise, she argues, from operations of power.
Her thesis concerns the wars that the American state and its allies have
perpetrated since 9/11, but similar questions can be asked about organiza-
tions. I am thinking particularly of abuses in workplaces, some of which
critical theorists are very much aware of (such as the pain experienced by
many people following mergers and acquisitions ‘justified’ on the grounds
of competitiveness [Ford and Harding, 2003]) and others that are so taken
for granted they are regarded as ‘normal’ or as impediments to productivity
What Is ‘Work’? A Tale of Two Sisters 17
(for example, the relentless tedium of many jobs [George and Jett, 2003]).
What frames are used when organizing people at work, and how are the
lives of working people defined and understood?
However, in turning the lens away from war and towards organizations,
the ontological and epistemological questions I must pursue involve not
only what is life but its very necessary other: what is ‘death’? In arguing that
death takes forms other than that of biological death, as I will do in Chap-
ter Six, I would seem to be traducing Butler’s intent, while at the same time
predisposing my arguments towards an angry denunciation of workplaces.
In doing this, am I not stealing a necessary spotlight away from where it
matters, those injured and killed in wars, so as to shine it, again, on the
privileged West?
My answer to the first charge is that I am borrowing the questions posed
by Butler and asking them of my own field of interest because such an acute
thinker as Butler facilitates our reframing our thoughts and asking questions
which otherwise lie dormant, albeit waiting to be asked, at the very tips of
our tongues. And indeed Butler provides a licence for the extension of her
arguments to the field of work. She calls, in Frames of War, for a new bodily
ontology that would imply ‘the rethinking of precariousness, vulnerability,
injurability, interdependency, exposure, bodily persistence, desire, work and
the claims of language and social belonging’ (FW:2, emphasis added). She
thus calls specifically for a rethinking of work, providing a licence for the
arguments in this book. We must rethink work: what would be a rethought
bodily ontology of work in which the structure of bodies is ‘socially ecstatic’
(FW:33):
TWO SISTERS
‘we didn’t have much but there was always things going on’ . . . I knew
[emphasis on ‘knew’] we didn’t have the money other people had, we
didn’t have all the clothes and that, but when I look back I remember the
nice things like going to chapel in our new dresses, all looking the same.2
The little mining village in which we grew up, surrounded by farms, was
an idyllic place for this animal lover, and she spent as much time as possible
What Is ‘Work’? A Tale of Two Sisters 19
riding a friend’s horses and smuggling a menagerie of pets into the bedroom
we five sisters shared. (Because of these activities, I always saw her as con-
fident and outgoing: not until I used a formal interview format for our talk
did I find out that we had shared a crippling shyness.) She left school at the
first opportunity when she was 15, after having opted out of education at 13
because of that overwhelming shyness, which made her feel as if she didn’t
and couldn’t fit in. Julie’s first job was 100 miles away from home, working
at a zoo, but she left after six or nine months because she couldn’t stand the
cruelty of keeping animals in cages. Her next job was at a kennel about 40
miles from home, but she was expected to spend the nights alone in a remote
mansion, so one night she left, walked miles to the nearest bus stop and,
having missed the last bus home, waited until daylight in the women’s toilets
at the bus station. Her next job was in a local dry cleaners where she ironed
clothes all day. She remembers hating the work but loving the camaraderie
of her colleagues. She worked there for two and a half years and left to have
the first of her four sons, just before her 19th birthday. Apart from some
part-time work as a barmaid she has not been in paid employment since.
At the time of our discussion she was 52, living on an £85-a-week3 carer’s
allowance paid by the State.
I, meanwhile, left school at 16 with a clutch of G.C.E certificates, and
went to work in London as a trainee typist. I returned to Wales nine months
later and worked on the lines in a factory, making condensers for the insides
of radios, experiencing at first hand what I was to learn much later were
Taylorist principles of production. I married at 18, had my two sons within
15 months of the marriage, worked part time in the factory for a while, was
registered as unemployed for a short period, got onto a government-run
course to learn shorthand and refresh my typing skills, and then worked as a
secretary for two years, studying ‘A’ level G.C.E’s at evening class, until, at 27,
I went to university. It is at this point that our lives diverged, so that my
income is now ten times that of my sister, and the other rewards of my job
(despite its many frustrations [Willmott, 1995; Harding, Ford and Gough,
2010; Fotaki, 2011; Clarke, Knights and Jarvis, 2012]) are inestimable.
I need not describe the life of an academic, familiar to most readers. What
follows is an account of the life of a carer.
Julie’s first experience of caring was for our widowed aunt, Ethel, who
shared her house with Julie and her four sons after Julie’s marriage broke
down. As Auntie Eth grew older and more frail, Julie, who was then in her
late 30s,
had to bathe her . . . and then when she had cancer was down [the spe-
cialist hospital] everyday and then it was the worry then, cos I mean not
only is she going to die but it was was I doing everything right for her,
so er [pause] you know it was, it’s hard because you’ve got that focus,
that’s your focus, even though you’ve got the boys, you’ve got to focus
20 On Being At Work
on make sure she’s alright, as you know she was back and fore hospital,
she’d broke her hip and um and then she was in [the specialist hospital]
and it was always, got to do this, got to do that, so you forget about
yourself. . . . I worry so much if I had a chance of a night out I’d worry
about leaving her.
But eventually Auntie Eth became very confused and needed to go into a
home, where she was happy, but, Julie said,
I always feel guilty about it, and I will say I will go to my grave guilty.
A few years later our mother’s health deteriorated. Julie, now in her mid-
40s, took on more and more responsibility for her care.
I started coming up quite a few times a week, and then when she was
really ill I was up every day then, and sometimes twice, twice a day
from Aberbargoed [two miles away, up a very steep hill], walking up,
cos they would phone me, I’d come up, do what I had to do, go home,
and then they’d phone me that they didn’t have no milk, . . . so I’d have
to come all the way back up, so through all winds and weathers, every
day then.
N: That was walking?
J: That was walking, yeah.
Our mother died four years before this interview, when our father was
84, after which Julie became his carer. I asked her to describe a typical week:
A typical week apart from being boring, it’s, it’s just [coughs] it’s com-
ing over, doing his tablets, every morning and every evening, do his
lunch and cook his dinner, do his shopping for him, get his prescrip-
tions, go up [to the local town, five miles away] get his prescriptions,
um. . . . .
N: That’s on the bus?
J: Yeah, on the bus there and back, and that’s twice in a week that
is, because the prescription ends so I go up and get it. Um, do his shop-
ping, keep him company, listen to him whinging, so that’s a typical
week, and it’s always like, it’s never ending, it’s Christmas Day it doesn’t
matter. It’s 24 hours he’s on your mind and if he’s ill and if he’s at the
hospital you’re back and fore there, the same as it was with Mam, it was
always back and fore the hospital, and the same now if like oh, every-
body’s going out but I can’t go out cos I’ve got to do this for Dad, and
er that’s a typical, a typical week that is. Every day, seven days a week,
yeah, and it’s boring inasmuch as you are tied, it’s tied down, you’ve got
to be there, you’ve got to do this, to make sure he’s alright, and that’s
that’s my typical time.
What Is ‘Work’? A Tale of Two Sisters 21
Caring combined with money worries from living on such a small income
takes over her emotions and controls her mind:
If the money was better it could be fair enough, but the money is
poor . . . you’re full of worry all the time, and believe me it is when
you’ve no money and that you’re worrying from one day to the next,
you just can’t get in that frame of mind to [return to the writing for
which she showed an early talent]. . . . You just haven’t got that bit of,
it’s not get up and go, it’s the frame of mind, you’ve got to be in that
frame of mind to write and when you’ve got constant worries you just
can’t get into that frame of mind.
It’s not just physically hard, it’s mentally challenging, it does get on
top of you, and like I say when you see the other sisters and they have
their hair nice and have nice clothes and you’re in hand-me-downs, it
is hard.
Somebody said to me weeks and weeks back what will you do when
your Dad’s eyes close? And I looked at them and said ‘get a life’, and
that’s the first thing that came to my mind. Without even thinking about
it, get a life, that’s what I’m going to do.
She uses that familiar phrase, sometimes used as an insult: ‘get a life’. She
does not have to think about it; her response speaks for her before she can
think: she will ‘get a life’. ‘Life’, it seems, is somewhere out there, something
that has to be ‘got’, something she does not have at the moment. To be alive
is therefore commonly distinguished from having a life. Julie’s account is
reminiscent of zombie films—what are portrayed in films such as The Cat
and the Canary (1939), Night of the Living Dead (1968)4 and Shaun of the
Dead (2004) are living beings who do not have lives but go through their
days doing the tasks required of them by their controllers. These mindless
creatures labour but cannot think or emote or have relationships, pleasure
or fun. This is how Julie describes her existence—she does not have ‘a life’,
and thus she has few of those rights which attach to being human.
animals are divided into: (a) belonging to the Emperor, (b) embalmed,
(c) tame, (d) sucking pigs, (e) sirens, (f) fabulous, (g) stray dogs,
(h) included in the present classification, (i) frenzied, (j) innumerable,
(k) drawn with a very fine camelhair brush, (l) et cetera, (m) having just
broken the water pitcher, (n) that from a long way off look like flies.
In Frames of War, the judge that apprehends a life is the privileged West,
with its riches, its weapons of war, its power and its desire to control the
world. In other words, life is defined by those with the power to define it.
In organizations, we will see as the arguments in this book progress, that
although it may be management’s desire that staff be less than human, staff
themselves disagree and find ways of circumventing that desire.
This leads to the question of how one becomes human/not-human, a liv-
ing being that has or does not have a life.
Julie and Butler again have similar ideas, albeit couched in very different
language. Both refer to the face and the importance of recognition.
Julie said that to have a life:
I’d have to get a job but it would be nice to go and do something, have
money, have my hair cut and buy some nice clothes, and just do what
I want to do. If I want to go out for the day, get on the bus and go
somewhere I could do it. Just simple things like that.
A job is something to be deeply desired because it would give her not only
‘a life’ but the life she dreams of having. To have a life means having paid
employment that provides the money to work on one’s appearance (have my
hair cut and buy some nice clothes) and to have the freedom and resources
to do ‘simple things’. In Butler’s terms, these are not simple things at all, for
they all involve being made visible (working on one’s appearance, travelling
in the public domain) for
the norms that would allocate who is and is not human arrive in visual
form. These norms work to give face and to efface. Accordingly, our
26 On Being At Work
capacity to respond with outrage, opposition, and critique will depend
in part on how the differential norm of the human is communicated
through visual and discursive frames. (FW:77)
In Butler’s thesis, those who are invisible, who do not enter the scene of
recognition, can be trampled on, disposed of, destroyed at will, with no one
speaking on their behalf because no one (with power) is aware of their exis-
tence, and thus they cannot be recognised as human. They are apprehended,
that is, it is known that they exist, but without recognition they are not
categorised as human and so are not accorded rights to be represented and
defended. My sister says something similar: her current labours, as a carer,
render her invisible. Trudging the roads of the village each day, she is ap-
prehended (one of the many millions of carers in the UK), but she is invisible
and not marked out as human (a living, breathing, emoting being) and thus
the category ‘carer’ is overdetermining. The strong theme about freedom in
Julie’s narrative emphasises the need to be able to go out in the world. In
remembering the jobs she held in her teens, she constitutes a human self:
as an animal lover with high ethical standards (she left the zoo because of
its cruelty in caging animals); presenting a strong articulation of how staff
What Is ‘Work’? A Tale of Two Sisters 27
should be treated (not left alone miles from anywhere at dead of night); and
enjoying the pleasures of companionship (while ironing clothes). In thinking
about what paid work would allow her to do, she has a dream of that earlier
freedom: she could ‘go out for the day . . . and go somewhere’. She knows
that if she can buy clothes, have her hair done and travel out into the world,
she will be made visible and thus recognisable. That is, she could go out in
the world where, having worked on herself (new haircut and clothes), she
would be recognizable as human.
My sister’s life is similar in many ways to those of the housewives of the
East London working-class community studied by Michael Young and Peter
Willmott in 1957 (Young and Willmott, 1969). Her days revolve around
the family and the related tasks of caring and housework. Travel remains
a distant prospect, and shopping for anything other than day-to-day neces-
sities is a rare luxury. The satisfaction in being a housewife at the centre of
a family and kinship circle 50 years ago was in the doing of the activities
pertaining to that position. Times have changed: identity has shifted from
doing to being, and doing as an end in itself has switched to doing as the
means by which being may be facilitated (Butler, 1990; 1993). Julie, unlike
her predecessors, is constantly bombarded with injunctions of how to work
on the self: the television in the corner of her living room, the magazines
she leafs through at the doctor’s surgery, the conversations with sisters who
are able to participate in the project of the self—these all bring with them
instantiations of the norms of the human in a culture of consumption. That
Julie cannot participate renders her a failure in her own eyes: she is not
working on the self. Julie’s own theory is thus that work will allow her to
work on herself so that she can make herself visible and thus recognisable.
Her desire for work is therefore a desire for recognition, because through
work one attains ‘a life’ or, in Butler’s terminology, becomes human. It is a
dream of the self I wish to construct, the me I want to be.
The very paragraph with which I opened this chapter shows that I, on
the other hand, am engaged actively in this project of the self. Not only did
I show that I travel to seemingly exotic locations, I could also look at myself
in that location, comment to myself on my being there and project myself
forward (Fuery and Wagner, 2003) to the accounts I would tell family and
friends of my being there—Nancy Harding, world traveller, and therefore a
self in process. I have the photographs to prove it.
The argument so far is this: I have taken two sisters whose lives have devi-
ated in ways that could not have been foreseen in our childhoods. Each
of us works long hours, but only one of us in a job that enables working
on, constructing, the self as human and fully alive (although the manageri-
alisation of higher education threatens this [Prichard and Willmott, 1997;
28 On Being At Work
Chandler, Barry and Clark, 2002]). The sister whose labours do not facili-
tate such work on the self classifies herself as outside life. In Butler’s terms,
she is outside the human. She labours but does not work, so cannot even get
to the scene where the master and slave encounter each other to receive, or
not receive in the master’s case, recognition. She cannot therefore enter the
frame of visibility, and so she cannot enter the category of the human, for
to be human is to work actively on the self so that the self becomes visible.
When I have discussed this thesis with friends and colleagues, they have
pointed out examples of friends and family who choose not to work; how
can I, they ask, say that such people are removing themselves from the
human? This is to misread my thesis, or, rather, I have not articulated it suf-
ficiently clearly, for someone who chooses not to work will have other fora
and other activities in which they prefer to spend their time, and in which
they will be able to work on, and thus constitute, a self, because in those
places they are visible, have a face. Indeed, the majority of the population
will have spaces and places separate and apart from their labouring and
working lives in which they are able to work on the self.
What I am focusing upon here is the position in which many of us find
ourselves: we have little choice about whether or not we should be in paid
employment, and much of our time is therefore taken up in labouring, but
our labours do not allow us to participate in the construction of anything
other than an abject self. This clarifies the distinction I am drawing between
labour and work, where ‘work’ involves the possibility of working on the
self as part of the process of being engaged in a job. My sister is therefore
akin to a Weberian ‘ideal-type’; she labours but cannot work on the self. By
focusing on someone whose labour does not allow work on the self, I can
make a clear distinction between labour and work, between a life and being
alive. The body while labouring becomes that of the zombie-machine: alive
but without life, outwith the human. The body that labours is little more
than a machine for doing work, and as machine it is without recognition.
The body that works is involved in working on itself, constituting identity
or selfhood. Julie exists as the former, labouring body (as zombie-machine)
and dreams of a job that will allow her to do more than labour: to work on
the self or selves she aspires to be.
I move on now to exploring how recognition requires a face and how
labour renders labourers faceless. That is, I will pick up Julie’s discussion
about how work would give her the chance to change her appearance and
Butler’s development of Emmanuel Levinas’s thesis on ‘the face’ in Frames
of War.
We must therefore, she goes on, think seriously about modes of address
and moral authority. By the very fact of being in the world, one has a re-
sponsibility to all others who, even if we do not hear or see them, address
us and allow us our selfhood. Levinas’s value for Butler is linked to this
development of responsibility in the scene of recognition. He first provides
a way of thinking ‘about the relationship between representation and hu-
manization’, the aspect I draw on in this book, and, second, offers Butler
an ethics of Jewish nonviolence that she uses to develop her new politi-
cal theory. Levinas (in my interpretation of Butler’s interpretation) argues
that slaughter of the masses becomes possible when they are faceless, that
is, anonymised beings without identity and for whom, therefore, neither
compulsion to care nor responsibility for their flourishing is forthcoming.
That is, in seeing people’s faces we accord them recognition that they are
human, and after recognition is given different imperatives arise in regard
to what can be done with and to them. When we do not see people’s faces,
when they are anonymous crowds, they are like pebbles on the beach: we
can trample all over them because they have no humanity. I am arguing
that the labourer is faceless, that is, management feels free to use labour-
ers to churn out products and services as if they were machines because
What Is ‘Work’? A Tale of Two Sisters 31
their faces are not seen and they are therefore not accorded recognition as
being human.
Julie’s theory of the face expounds this notion from the perspective of
someone who has no recognizable face. Her understanding of herself in-
cludes a theory of being rendered faceless, and this self-understanding arises,
I suggest, from her current position of being a labourer who cannot work on
the self. Her desire to earn sufficient money to work on her appearance be-
comes a desire to have a face, for being faceless, having no face, places one
outside the human. Working on the self, constituting an identity, involves
making oneself visible to those who can grant recognition. This is Julie’s
theory of the difference between two sisters, one who has a public face and
one who doesn’t. I did not ask her a specific question on this but made a nar-
cissistic statement that stimulated her theory of why our lives are different:
I suggest that this is not a memory of an event but a theory of the present,
one in which a light is retroactively shone upon what may be an imagined
past so as to understand what is understood as the present. As Lacan ob-
serves, there is no present, only a remembering of the past and a projection
into the future:
What is realized in my history is not the past definite of what was, since
it is no more, or even the present perfect of what has been in what I am,
but the future anterior of what I shall have been for what I am in the
process of becoming. (Lacan, 1977:86; 2002:300)
FRAMING
POSTSCRIPT
But there is one further issue that needs discussion. Throughout this chap-
ter I have offered an uncritical perspective on academic work, with only
What Is ‘Work’? A Tale of Two Sisters 37
minor asides referring to some of its frustrations and the dangers some com-
mentators identify that academics are being reduced to labourers as higher
education becomes managerialised. In that way, I adopted Julie’s perspective
on my job: it is she who frames it as glamorous and exciting (which it is
in many ways). But if we reflect on academic working days (and nights),
we know that we too are often positioned as zombie-machines, albeit with
many more privileges than my sister would dream of. We are productive
paper-writing, lecture-giving, administration-doing, exam-marking, confer-
ence-attending zombie-machines. Therefore I must qualify somewhat the
allusions to the photographs of faculty that appear on websites. Although
they accord us recognition, when we look at them we see reflected back
a labourer, even though we might frame ourselves in such a way that we
refuse that aspect of the self. I see very little resistance to the denigration of
our work as it becomes a production line off which plops, spasmodically,
another paper or, more regularly, another graduate. Indeed, tomorrow I will
see my head of department for my annual performance review: have I been a
good girl this year? I will answer yes, and the evidence is there in papers ac-
cepted for publication as listed on the forms I filled in. A complex working
life is thereby reduced to a number of boxes ticked on a form.
This gives another reason, following those outlined in the Introduction,
for looking not at resistance towards management but at other ways of
being at work, because, although ‘the management’ reduces me to a series
of numbers and I seem to offer no resistance to that demand, in other ways
I evade their judgements and work on the self. This book, indeed, is a small
act of resistance (to the preference in business schools for journal papers),
but in the light of the dreams I had when I first became an academic, of the
thoughts I would think, the books I would read and those I would write, it is
a paltry souvenir of the me I had hoped to be. This book is therefore also a
work that is thinking through, tangentially and opaquely, what it is to be an
academic in the 21st century. The tension I note in my own work, of moving
between zombie-machine and human, will be evident throughout many of
the chapters of this book, save in the one which follows, in which, despite
looking actively for it, I could not find in a manager’s account of his working
life any hint that he tried to evade the imperative to be a zombie-machine.
2 The Master’s Tale
I was browsing in Leeds University’s bookshop a long time ago and picked
up a book, The Psychic Life of Power (PLP, 1997), by an author then un-
known to me, Judith Butler. The opening paragraph was enthralling:
FRANK
In his mid-50s at the time of the interview, Frank had been born in a very
tough, working-class neighbourhood in one of Britain’s industrial cities. His
father was an alcoholic who was violent to Frank’s mother. His childhood
was a repetitive cycle of his parents separating from each other and then
getting back together. His mother would refuse to put up with the violence,
take the children with her to live elsewhere, then relent and return home.
When Frank was 15 and old enough to leave school, he gave his mother the
ultimatum that it was either his violent father or him, after which his father
was evicted permanently from the family home. Frank found a job as an ap-
prentice for a national company, using his wages to help support his mother
and three siblings. He finished his apprenticeship but realised he was more
interested in management and persuaded the company to send him on its
management training course. His subsequent rise through the company was,
to use the old metaphor, meteoric. He was given his first general manager
position at 22, breaking a company rule that managers had to be at least
27 years old before becoming general managers. As a 22-year-old manager,
half the age of most staff in the branch of the organization he now managed, he
instigated performance appraisals, consultation exercises and multiskilling,
and within two years he had increased profits by 100 percent and won the
The Master’s Tale 43
title ‘manager of the year’. He moved to a bigger branch of the organization,
where, within 18 months, he won a major award for the company, after
which they asked him to take on one of their more prestigious subsidiar-
ies. His speciality became that of ‘troubleshooter’, taking over company
branches that were in difficulty and turning them around. Eventually, after
Frank went to work for a different organization that insisted on centralised
policies that would not allow him the autonomy he needed to be a successful
manager, he and his wife set up their own company. Within 10 years they
had turned a mediocre business into a very successful one.
There seems little that relates Frank to the lord and bondsman in Hegel’s
master/slave dialectic, but through introducing them to each other I aim to
establish a fruitful relationship.
What does she mean by this? Her discussion at this point revolves around
how the act of negation or repression actually constitutes that which is ne-
gated or repressed. So the act of refusing identification with a body whose
animal functions shame us actually constitutes the body as such, that is, as
a shameful animal. This is a ‘dialectical reversal’ whereby what is censored
by the law actually sustains that law (PLP, 58) and is Foucault’s repres-
sive hypothesis—that repression does not act on pre-given fields of pleasure
and desire but constitutes the fields that are to be regulated and, as such,
expands and proliferates them. In Freud, as well as in Foucault and Hegel,
‘the instrument of suppression becomes the new structure and aim of desire’
(PLP:60). But, Butler goes on to argue, the regulatory regime that produces
desire is itself produced by attachment to the rule of subjection (60). If so
(and here she returns to Hegel), then subjects will ‘attach to pain’ when
regulatory regimes ensure that it is only painful sites that are available for
attachment (61).
We therefore have a further stage in the lord/bondsman dialectic, one
that is the thesis of The Psychic Life of Power: to become a subject requires
that one absorb and enact requirements that can cause one pain. In short, if
one is to be a subject and have a liveable life, one requires recognition from
an other, including an internalised other, who not only establishes the laws
one must obey if one is to be a subject but judges one’s performance in obey-
ing those laws and often (always?) finds one wanting. Despite this ‘unhappy
consciousness’, we cling to the recognition that is offered, because without
that recognition we cannot become subjects.
To 20th- and 21st-century organization theorists, there is something
missing from this account: there is need for a manager to be inserted be-
tween lord and bondsman if the mythical scene is to hold good for ana-
lysing organizational encounters. In pursuit of understanding managerial
subjectivities, I will therefore, perhaps wildly and unwisely, reimagine the
scene, but I will insert Frank between the bondsman and the lord. In such
a position, he looks both ways, to the lord and to the bondsman. Indeed,
Butler’s observation that the lord ‘postures as a disembodied desire for self-
reflection’ who wants the bondsman to be the lord’s body (35) suggests
that for ‘lord’ we could read ‘organization’, whose metaphysical presence is
inscribed on the bodies of its managers whose task is to articulate its desires
(as if ‘it’, the organization, has an ontological reality that can have desires).
46 On Being At Work
In what follows, I will reenact each stage of the master-slave dialectic identi-
fied by Butler. This is therefore an experiment in staging a master/manager/
slave dialectic as a scene that has four acts.
ACT ONE
The bondsman, forced to produce goods for the master, eventually sees
himself reflected in the products he has created for the master, realises he
has produced the world and through this comes to self-consciousness.
The master is dependent only on the lesser form of life, the slave, for
recognition and therefore cannot attain self-consciousness.
You’re the general manager, you run the operation, um, [pause] and
we’ll have regular meetings, and providing, you know, everything is
going well that’s it.
This organization was then sold to another company, and the new owner
believed the general manager should run the [branch], as had [the first
company]. [They said] ‘If you operate it and you meet your budget you
don’t get a lot of interference’. So that was fine. That went on for a few
years.
He left the company he had worked for for most of his adult life to set
up his own business. So Frank had thought he was free, and only when that
felt freedom was taken away did he realise he had never been free. In Hegel’s
terms, he attained that freedom which leads to subjectivity only after he had
left the lord/organization that had governed the first 30 years of his working
life. However, we will see that, as Butler points out, the lord/organization is
incorporated into the psyche of the freed manager/slave, so freedom contin-
ues to be illusionary.
ACT TWO
We have seen that the manager is able to feel that s/he is free, but this is an
illusionary freedom. Frank, who here stands in for all managers, feels that
he has autonomy, but this is strictly circumscribed within limits set by the
organization: it is not therefore autonomy but the opposite, the doing of the
organization’s will.
The fear of death engendered under illusionary freedom is, I suggest,
that of the death not of the self but of the organization/lord. So long as
the manager represents the organization, so long as the organization is
inscribed on his/her body, then the manager has no identity of his/her own,
no self that can die, but only identification with an organization whose
death therefore is greatly feared (if the organization dies, the manage-
rial self dies). Indeed, the business pages of newspapers and management
journals, as well as academic texts and courses, repeat this message of
the imminent death of the organization (Grey, 2009) and how it can be
staved off only if the manager is sufficiently clever, resourceful and hard-
working. This suggests that fear of the death of the organization imposes
a dominant imperative towards maintaining the life of the organization.
The Master’s Tale 49
The manager’s task is therefore that of working as hard as possible to en-
sure that the organization does not fail. The need to work hard, cleverly,
and resourcefully and indeed to find ways of manipulating staff identi-
ties, motivations, feelings and psyches (Hochschild, 1983; Alvesson and
Willmott, 2002) means that managers must work ever harder. Hard work
therefore becomes understood to be an ethical demand, because hard
work comes to equal the staving off of (organizational) death. So we have
a curious reversal when we insert a manager into the master/slave dialec-
tic: the organization comes to have an identity that, mediated through
the manager, requires that managers and staff work as hard as possible in
order to stave off the organization’s death.
However, Frank’s working life changed very little after he had set up his
own business. Asked what was the difference between running a large com-
pany and the much smaller one that he owned, he replied:
We probably do the same job, but it’s done on a more informal basis.
Where with a large company everything has to, you know, i’s dotted and
t’s crossed, you know. A lot of what we do here. We have had various
er appraisals on the place and they say, ‘God, it’s still got the discipline
of a large business, but it’s but it’s done, you know’. I don’t think in a
place like this you can sit down with a part-time member of staff and
say, ‘right, you fill out that three-page appraisal. Tell me what you think
and then come back to me, and I’ll spend an hour going through it with
you’. Where you will sit down and say, ‘look, you are really doing well
and but however if you just look at this and look at that’, so it tends to
be done less formally, but it’s still being done.
The distinction between ‘manager’ and ‘boss’, if there ever were one,
disappears. Frank has learned one way of running a business, and he has
taken that method into his new company. There is no freedom from the
relentless hours he must work if he is to stave off the death of that organiza-
tion, which, although he owns it, is his master. Although he may think he
is free, because he has no boss to whom he must report, this freedom is the
freedom to work as hard as ever: it is still illusionary freedom, as he is the
slave of his own company.
ACT THREE
Frank is still judging himself in the same way as he did when employed by
a big corporation: he cannot take any time off because if he does, then he is
not devoting himself 100 percent to the organization. Indeed, he can justify
this on the grounds that staff are incapable of taking his place, but we must
pose the question whether any member of staff would ever be good enough:
does not Frank need them to be ‘poor’ so that he can justify to himself his
continuous presence in the organization? Again we see that the freedom the
bondsman earned is beyond his grasp: all he has is a simulacrum of freedom.
The Master’s Tale 51
But there is another twist here: note how staff are seen to ‘kinda lose the
plot’. I asked if Frank ever saw people who, at 22, showed the promise he
had shown:
Frank made few references to staff during the interview, but when I meet
him as a friend the topic of conversation always turns, almost obsessively, to
the problems he and his wife have with their staff and the idiosyncrasies of
their customers. Formally, on tape, none of those complaints were forthcom-
ing. The quotation just presented is as near as he came to voicing his thoughts
about staff. There is therefore a disjuncture here: when we talk as friends, he
gives one version of his life, but when he talked to me in the formal position
of academic researcher/interviewee, he gave another account. One aspect of
this, I have suggested, is that when I was in the formal position of ‘academic’
I was ostensibly in a position to recognise Frank as a ‘good manager’. It fol-
lows that when he discusses himself formally and on record as a manager
or business owner with someone whose formal position is that of a business
school academic and therefore supposedly with expertise in management, he
has to present himself as having ideal staff, because the ideal manager would
have only ideal staff, that is, people he has successfully developed, motivated
and rewarded and now successfully leads. In other words, Frank the zombie-
machine requires that his staff become zombie-machines if he is to be known
as ‘the boss’. That is, a sign of the success of the manager is his/her ability to
reduce staff to the status of zombie-machines.
However, there are other explanations, and one of these is to be found in
‘the plot’ that the staff are losing. They have lost the script of the play they are
supposed to be enacting, but what is this play? It would seem that it is a play
about emulating the example of the boss in working hard and that the lost
plot arises from failing to do that. Frank’s account suggests that he sees him-
self as the ideal manager: utterly devoted to the job, working very long hours,
implementing policies and practices designed to motivate staff and ensure
that everything works extremely well. His personal and family life is bound
up in the business: he and his wife work together, and many of their friends
work in the same field. In other words, Frank is a zombie-machine that eats,
sleeps and dreams the business. It is his major focus, he rarely takes time
off from it, and he is good at it. This is how he wants his staff to be, that is,
versions of himself, and these are the criteria by which he assesses them. But
they have lost the stage directions and do not, it seems, know how to do that.
52 On Being At Work
ACT FOUR
There are two constant themes throughout Frank’s theory about what
drives him; one is the need to do hard work, and the other is freedom. We
have seen that the freedom he thinks he has is illusory. First, as a manager
working in a big organization, he thought he had freedom to be an autono-
mous manager, making his own decisions. However, those decisions had
already been taken elsewhere. Second, Frank desired recognition as a suc-
cessful manager, and this required that he work very hard, efficiently and
effectively, within limits imposed by the organization/lord’s desire. Now, as
a business owner, he finds his freedom is as illusory as when he worked for
a large corporation: he is tied to the business, working just as hard as previ-
ously, but now he is his own judge, as he said himself, when asked about the
difference between being the owner and being a manager.
Eh, well, you as an owner you don’t, you you you put the pressure on
yourself. Um. If if if you think about it, if you if you work for a for a
corporate [company], you’ll have an area manager, you’ll have directors
and various specialist departments. They will dictate things like pur-
chasing policy, they will dictate things like um marketing policy, well,
when you’re an owner that’s all down to you. The only, as I always say,
the only person I have to convince once a year is the bank manager, you
know, as long as he’s happy, that’s it.
Probably, [long pause] the hours you work. You’re you’re you’re then
beginning, you’re beginning at the end of the night to feel it, you know,
you kind of say, well, wait a minute. The other thing is when you see
your friends getting ill and dying round about you. . . . I think it’s now
time we have got to think that’s it, we’ve done our, because I’ve done
40 [years] . . . and at the end of the day you want to enjoy yourself
a bit.
Note how the long hours and the hard work are seen as part of a judge-
ment: how much should people work before they can be deemed to have
made a fair contribution? His statement is redolent of a prison sentence.
In many ways, we are seeing in Frank’s account Weber’s ‘Protestant ethic’
(1930/2001), an injunction that one must work as hard as possible in order
to secure a place in heaven. The catch, however, is that one cannot know
if one is one of those chosen from the hard workers until after one’s death.
The Master’s Tale 53
The imperative is therefore to devote oneself to one’s work in the hope of
being one of the chosen ones. Frank’s closing words suggest that the work
has not been enjoyable—pleasure will come when Frank is freed from the
constant responsibilities and pressures of the manager/boss.
Therefore, becoming managerial subjects requires that people attach
themselves to an identity that causes them to suffer: they must become zom-
bie-machines, be judged as such, and judge others as such. There is a ‘dialec-
tical reversal’ (PLP:58) here in that the requirement to work very hard and
with total devotion to the business becomes something that is not imposed
but is desired. ‘The instrument of suppression becomes the new structure
and aim of desire’ (PLP:60).
• Thesis: inserted between the master and the slave, the manager thinks
s/he is free but this is an illusion of freedom;
• Anti-thesis: deludedly thinking that s/he is free, the manager works
extremely hard to achieve recognition from the lord, under the im-
perative of an ethical norm which requires that managers be utterly
devoted to their work and that they prove their worthiness as man-
agers by managing staff who they ensure work just as hard and ef-
ficiently as the managers do. The manager must therefore become
a zombie-machine that works extremely hard at turning staff into
zombie-machines;
• Synthesis: the requirement to work hard becomes a (managerial) desire
to work hard. I work hard therefore I am (a manager).
How does bad conscience (which is a turning on the self) serve the social
regulation of the subject (PLP:66)? This is the question Butler next explores
so as to better understand the formation of the subject within a manda-
tory passionate attachment to subjection, where a repeated self-beratement
functions as that person’s ‘conscience’ (67). Drawing on both Nietzsche
and Freud, she argues that conscience is self-derived, that it arises not from
external punishment but from the venting of one’s aggression internally,
that is, against oneself. From Nietzsche (72) she can argue that man is a
promising being who establishes a continuity between a statement and an
act—what he says he will do he will do. This ‘protracted will, which is self-
identical through time and which establishes its own time, constitutes the
man of conscience.’ However, there can be no ‘I’ without a moral labouring
on the self: the ‘I’ takes itself as its own object, and it is this reflexive turning
on the self that produces ‘the metaphorics of psychic life’ (76).
Bad conscience is the perverse joy taken in persecuting oneself in the ser-
vice of, in the name of, morality. This arises from a prohibition against de-
sire and that desire’s turning back upon itself. This turning back upon itself
becomes the very inception, the very action of what is rendered entitative
through the term ‘conscience’. We can imagine this as a scene. There is a de-
sire for something, but, as the desirer reaches out towards what it wants, it
realises that it is in danger of breaking the norms of its culture and therefore
of losing the love of others, so it turns back on itself reflexively and chastises
itself for wanting what it should not want. Eventually, what it desires is this
self-chastising, because, according to Freud, prohibition reproduces the pro-
hibited desire, preserves and reasserts it in the very structure of renunciation
(81). Conscience is then figured ‘as a body which takes itself as its object,
forced into a permanent posture of negative narcissism or, more precisely, a
narcissistically nourished self-beratement’ (82).
There was no talk of desire for anything when Frank recounted his
life working for big corporations, but when he discussed his current po-
sition, a desire for time away from the company, a weekend break, was
articulated, as we saw earlier. Briefly, he said that ‘it would be nice just to
go and—forget two weeks holiday—but maybe three or four weekends
away . . . and that’s ideally what we would like’. Here, the desire, the turn-
ing outwards, is for time away, to be off duty, to be someone other than
the boss. But he then represents customers as a cause that prevents his
having a short break. If he is using the (imagined) responses of customers
The Master’s Tale 55
to articulate his own concerns about being away from the business, then
we have this scene:
It is my desire to have time away from the business. But, as I reach out-
wards to fulfil that desire, I am pushed back against myself. I am a business
owner, and if I am not there then the business cannot function, or perhaps
even I myself cannot function. That could lead to the death of the business.
I therefore cannot leave it for even a short time as that would be to break the
law that the business must survive. Because I have to be physically present,
then I know that I am the boss, and I am certain in that identity.
My first proposition therefore is that the bad conscience of the boss or
the manager (this applies equally to those who work for others as managers
and those who run their own businesses) is the feeling that one is not doing
one’s duty if one is not physically there, running the business. In Freudian
terms, there must be a certain libidinal joy in this feeling—the boss both
wants to be there and does not want to be there, but his/her identifica-
tion with the business is such that s/he gets a thrill from being so attached
to something that any time away from it would be a source of guilt. This
is understood more clearly through the quote from Foucault which opens
Butler’s next chapter (p. 83): ‘My problem is essentially the definition of the
implicit systems in which we find ourselves prisoners; what I would like to
grasp is the system of limits and exclusion which we practice without know-
ing it; I would like to make the cultural unconscious apparent’. The boss, it
seems, is a prisoner within his/her own identity.
From Foucault’s Discipline and Punish, Butler writes, we get the under-
standing that we can become autonomous only by becoming subjected to
a power and thus radically dependent on that power. Foucault saw sub-
jectivation taking place through the body (and we saw with Frank how he
felt the need to be physically present in the workplace). Butler interweaves
Foucault’s ideas with those of Freud and Lacan to expand upon Foucault’s
arguments about the prison:
After about a year and a half, this is very interesting, um, [my boss]
called me into the office and said, ‘it’s time you moved on’. I said,
‘sorry’. He said, ‘it’s time you moved on’. He says, ‘If I’ve been off duty
and I come back and you’ve done everything then I worry about my
position so it’s time you moved’. [Laughter] Which I thought was a very
nice way of putting it.
• The voice of authority shouts out, ‘hey you, come into my office—it’s
time you moved on’;
• The passer-by turns round, feeling guilty. Is he being given the sack?
Will he lose his job? He asks a question that is also an apology for the
crime he is being accused of: ‘Sorry?’;
• But he is proven innocent because of his labours (he has done every-
thing the manager should do), and he is therefore equipped to be a
manager.
The final, powerful chapters of The Psychic Life of Power form ‘a certain
cultural engagement with psychoanalytical theory that belongs neither to
the fields of psychology nor to psychoanalysis, but which nevertheless seeks
to establish an intellectual relationship to those enterprises’ (138). In them
Butler develops a thesis of the melancholy induced in the psyche through
its having to give up potential sexed/gendered identities. I am not exploring
The Master’s Tale 59
sex/gender in this chapter, but Butler’s arguments provoke the question of
what is given up, what objects are lost, to the boss when s/he is under a
compulsion to work, and work, and work. I suggest (perhaps because of my
own desires) that what is given up, the opposite of hard work, is sybaritism.
The term (according to Wikipedia [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sybaris, ac-
cessed 13 July 12]) is synonymous with pleasure and luxury, and originates
in a Greek city, Sybaris, which in the sixth century BCE was so rich that it
was widely envied and admired. This contrasts markedly with Christianity’s
imperatives, as discussed by Hegel, Althusser and Weber, echoes of the last
of these resonating, I have suggested, through Frank’s account. In other
words, Christianity’s influence on Western European subjectivities is that
they emerge out of bad conscience; I am suggesting (and this is Proposition
Four) that what is suppressed by the internalised judgemental eye is the wish
for pleasure, laziness and self-indulgence.
The argument is this (and I paraphrase Butler for much of this argument).
From Freud (PLP:134) comes the thesis that the lost object haunts the ego
as one of its constitutive identifications. That is, what is given up does not
disappear but is internalised, although the regret or grief over what has been
lost means that this is a melancholic incorporation. For Butler, what is given
up is the possibility of different gendered identities and different loves. For
the boss, I am arguing that what is given up is indulgence, pleasure and en-
joyment. The memory of these, of what might be, is, however, incorporated,
and their loss is a melancholic loss.
Second, just as heterosexuality (and sexed identity) is cultivated through
prohibitions such as restrictions on whom one can love, so managerial iden-
tities are cultivated through what cannot be done (stop working and start
playing). This is because, just as becoming a man requires repudiating femi-
ninity (137), becoming a manager or a boss requires repudiating everything
that is other to the requirement for hard work. One’s secret, guilty desires,
those which one cannot allow to be articulated, are, however, projected
onto one’s other. The male knows he is male (rational, logical, transcendent)
because he is not woman (emotional, close to nature); the manager knows
s/he is manager (disciplined zombie-machine) because s/he is not worker
(undisciplined, self-indulgent, needing to be controlled). But
One of the most anxious aims of his desire will be to elaborate the differ-
ence between him and her, and he will seek to discover and install proof
of that difference. His wanting will be haunted by a dread of being what
he wants, so that his wanting will also always be a kind of dread. (137)
That is, staff become for the boss the receptacle of his/her repudiated
desires: the manager dreads giving in to his/her own desire for pleasure and
indolence, cannot articulate that dread wish to be lazy, but installs proof
of the difference between him/herself as manager and the not/manager, the
staff, by seeing in staff those repudiated aspects of him/herself. Where s/he
60 On Being At Work
is hard-working, s/he sees staff as trying to avoid work; where s/he is com-
petent, s/he sees them as incompetent; and so on. This puts the manager in
a psychic quandary. If it is the mark of the good manager to lead, develop,
train, control and motivate staff so that they work hard as zombie-machines
but the manager also needs to see staff as poorly disciplined and slothful,
then the manager is in a double bind. If his/her staff become controlled,
highly motivated and hard-working, then they will not carry his/her repudi-
ated desires and s/he will feel him/herself to be a failure for having to admit
to that desire for pleasure. But so long as staff embody (in the manager’s
eyes) those despised aspects of the managerial self, they cannot be hard-
working, and so s/he will have failed as a manager. All s/he can do to escape
from this bind is to push him/herself to work ever harder.
However, Butler’s argument is that such loss brings about a ‘disavowed
grief’ (139), resulting in a melancholia for what cannot be grieved (in our
case, freedom from the necessity of constant hard work). This melancholia,
Butler argues, becomes part of the operation of regulatory power (143),
because such a radical refusal suggests that an identification has, at some
level, taken place, but the disavowal of that identification results in the over-
determination of the identification (149). In other words, the boss recognises
him/herself at some level as someone who desires to be lazy, indulgent and
free from responsibilities, so, to disavow him/herself of that identification,
works ever harder to prove that s/he is not that which s/he, at one level,
desires to be.
Melancholia returns Butler (168) to the figure of the ‘turn’ as a founding
trope in the discourse of the psyche, that is, the turning back on oneself and
the berating of the self for its failure to achieve normative ideals. In Hegel,
turning back upon oneself comes to signify the ascetic and sceptical modes
of reflexivity that mark the unhappy consciousness; in Nietzsche, turning
back on oneself suggests a retracting of what one has said or done or a
recoiling in shame in the face of what one has done. In Althusser, the turn
that the pedestrian makes towards the voice of the law is at once reflexive
(the moment of becoming a subject whose self-consciousness is mediated by
the law) and self-subjugating. For Freud, the ego turns back upon itself once
love fails. But it is melancholia, Butler argues (191), that links the psyche
to the norms of social regulation. This is because the power that is imposed
on the self and animates its emergence as an ‘I’, that power which makes
selfhood possible, at that very instant also imposes limits upon selfhood, so
in order to be one must sacrifice possibilities for the self one could be, and
what is sacrificed is grieved (198). Thus, the discourses of a culture that
make possible ‘the boss’ or ‘the manager’ provide the motive power that
constitutes the identity of ‘the manager’, but at the same time they impose
norms of what the boss can or must do if s/he is to sustain that identity as
the boss. To be a manager requires giving up possibilities for joy, leisure,
self-indulgence, play and so on, and at the same time it requires that the
manager bar staff from sybaritic pleasures.
The Master’s Tale 61
The figure of the ‘turn’ in management thus becomes something like the
following, not quite mythical scene:
In this chapter I used the life story told me by a boss who had spent 30 years
as a manager before setting up his own business, and I have read his ac-
count with, through and alongside Butler’s The Psychic Life of Power. This
has led to an outline of Hegel’s master/slave dialectic in which I inserted
the manager in between master and slave and to the development of four
propositions designed to expand upon the stages within the dialectic. These
together lead to the following theory of the subjectivity of the boss/manager
and why the manager desires or requires that staff become zombie-machines
and less than human.
Managers think they are free, but this is an illusory freedom. Even when
they set up their own businesses, they are governed by cultural norms and
discourses that both make the identity of manager possible and place lim-
its upon what can be done if the attempt at the impossible identity of self
as manager is to be sustained. Within those cultural norms is a require-
ment that managers work, and work, and work (that is, become zombie-
machines). The person who does not work hard cannot be a manager.
Hard work is therefore an ethical norm. Any desire for a break from work
62 On Being At Work
provokes feelings of guilt (bad conscience) and fear of the failure of the
company. This drives the manager to work even harder. However, there is
a thrill of pleasure in the knowledge that the boss appears to be indispens-
able, along with an erotic thrill of power over others. These contradict the
definition of what it is to be a manager, to be called by that name, and they
induce guilt (bad conscience). Managers therefore have to prove that they
are not guilty of failing to fulfil the normative ideal of ‘the manager’, and to
do this they have to work ever harder at fulfilling their managerial duties.
However, this drive to refuse all sybaritic pleasures, to disown one’s capac-
ity for joy and pleasure in things other than work, produces the managerial
self as a zombie-machine suffering an ungrievable loss, the loss of pleasure.
Unable to indulge in pleasure at work, managers are driven to ensure that
no one else can enjoy what they cannot themselves enjoy.
To be a good manager requires that staff work very hard, efficiently and
with devotion to the business (staff must become zombie-machines): staff
who do not do this testify to the manager’s failure to motivate, lead, con-
trol or in other ways get them to perform. However, staff are receptacles
of managers’ repudiated selves, that is, their desire for sybaritic pleasures,
and so managers have to seek to drive those pleasures out of staff. They
are therefore in a double bind, because whichever of these tasks they fulfil
negates the other. The only way out is to work harder, and thereby sustain
the norm and the status quo. Management is therefore a melancholic func-
tion where the success that is desired by managerial subjects is impossible
to attain but what is lost in the striving cannot be regained. The power that
subjectifies the managerial subject, which facilities the identity of ‘manager’,
thus subjects the manager within a melancholic subject position.
In terms of the distinction between labour and work introduced in Chapter
One, there is no distinction for the manager. That is, to labour as a manager
is to work on oneself as manager, and thus to be a manager is to work on
oneself.
This is a theory of how the norms that govern managerial identities play
out in practice. It is not necessarily a description of how all managers actu-
ally behave all of the time, and indeed Butler illuminates ways in which such
normative requirements can be evaded or even fail in their enactment. There
may be misrecognition in interpellation when the name is a social category
such as ‘manager’, because it then is a signifier that can be interpreted in
a number of ways (96). The strict connection between name and identity
may also be derailed in the imaginary, which disorders and contests what
is attempted in the symbolic. Indeed, she suggests that identity always fails.
Further, Foucault’s thesis on resistance as an effect of the very power that
it is said to oppose is important (PLP:98). There is the dual possibility of
being both constituted by the law and an effect of resistance to the law. For
Foucault, the symbolic produces the possibility of its own subversions, and
these subversions are unanticipated effects of symbolic interpellations (99).
The iterability of the performativity of the subject allows a ‘nonplace’ for
The Master’s Tale 63
subversion, where the reembodying of the subjectivating norm can redirect
its normativity (99). Butler suggests (100) that the strategic question for
Foucault is: how can we work the power relations by which we are worked,
and in what direction? Finally, a failure of interpellation may mark the path
towards ‘a more open, even more ethical, kind of being, one of or for the
future’ (131). There are therefore possibilities for change.
What I have aimed to do in this chapter is not to demonise the manager
but to try to understand the imperatives that constitute managerial subject
positions and impose limitations on what managers can do if they are to
sustain that identity of manager. In Chapters Three and Four I will show
how people evade or sidestep requirements about how they should act as
zombie-machines and, in so doing, constitute the self as human. I have not
done that with the manager. Partly this is because Frank’s account is one
of relentless hard work, and numerous statistics show that he is not alone:
the length of managers’ working weeks is a cause for concern (Ford and
Collinson, 2011). But also there is within his account a sense that this person
is a good man. He rescued his mother from a violent husband, rose out of
the slums to become a successful businessman and enjoys the generosity
that comes from running a successful business. My concern is how that
person is, when in the subject position of the manager, so driven, and driven
to drive others. If we are to move towards 21st-century organizations in
which domination, exploitation, aggressive control over people’s lives and
the reduction of working selves to disposable pieces of furniture are to be
challenged, we need to find ways of including managers within the category
‘human’. Indeed, it will be impossible to change the terms within which
working lives are lived without doing so. This chapter therefore finishes
with a question that cannot be answered here: how do we change the norms
within and through which managerial identities are constituted and mana-
gerial self-making occurs?
3 The Bondsman’s Tale
In Chapter One I drew a distinction between labour and work: the former
involves undertaking the tasks required to fulfil the terms of the job and is
undertaken by a zombie-machine; the latter is concerned with constituting
selfhood in which the status of the self as human is claimed. Chapter Two
introduced the boss my sister Julie might meet if she found paid employ-
ment. I argued that bosses are melancholic subjects who, seeking recogni-
tion and identity, are driven to work themselves harder and harder and
harder. It is imperative for them, in their quest for managerial selfhood, that
staff do likewise. In this chapter I explore the encounter between manager/
lord/master and worker/bondsman/slave from the latter’s perspective. The
person whose working-life story informs this chapter is not and has never
been one of Frank’s staff, and rather than delving further into The Psychic
Life of Power I am now drawing for inspiration on Butler’s Antigone’s
Claim (2000), a book that also informs the next chapter. Antigone’s Claim
explores another mythical encounter, but it focuses in some depth on the
person who faces the lord/master rather than the lord/master him- (or in-
creasingly) herself. It is a scene in which recognition is refused and carnage
follows. The greater part of this chapter focuses on The Antigone and how
Butler’s reading can illuminate a person’s account of his/her working life; it
then returns to the scene of recognition.
Antigone’s Claim is an analysis of Sophocles’s ancient tragedy The An-
tigone. It may seem peculiar to turn to an ancient Greek tragedy to under-
stand 21st-century organizations, but I suggest that there is much to be
learned from them that management and organization theorists have not
yet touched on. Ancient Greek philosophers such as Plato and Aristotle are
referenced by management theorists, especially in discussions of business
ethics (for example, Parker, 2003; Rämo, 2004; ten Bos, 2003), but their
near-contemporaries, the dramatists Sophocles, Aeschylus and Euripides,
are rarely so. There are a few references by organizational analysts to
the gods who inform the works of these earliest playwrights, including
Cummings (1996), Handy (1995), who developed a typology based loosely
on Greek gods, and Gabriel (2003), who looked to Homer’s Odyssey for
illumination. But, apart from a tangential recourse to Oedipus by means of
The Bondsman’s Tale 65
the Oedipal complex (Stein, 2007), the tragedies remain largely unexplored
by organization researchers. In this we differ markedly from many disci-
plines, for philosophers, cultural theorists, psychoanalytical theory, feminist
theory, political science and film and theatre studies have found in ancient
Greek tragedies a fecundity of thought that, though 2,500 years old, assists
the development of important insights into contemporary issues. I therefore
start this chapter’s discussion by outlining the influence of ancient Greek
tragedy in the contemporary academy. I then introduce Shakeel, whose
story becomes the bondsman’s response to the boss’s desire that he, feck-
less being that the manager thinks he is, work and work and work, like a
zombie-machine. An outline of The Antigone is included as a short appen-
dix for those unfamiliar with the tragedy. The play has three acts, a struc-
ture mimicked in the main part of this chapter. The theory which emerges
suggests that employees do not require recognition from the manager if they
are to have selfhood, although the manager, as we have seen, requires recog-
nition from staff. Staff seek recognition elsewhere.
But first, I justify the reasons for turning to Greek tragedy for under-
standing contemporary organizations.
Anyone who has eaten popcorn and sipped a cola (or, in this grannie’s case,
drunk a cup of tea) at the cinema with young relatives watching Percy
Jackson, Lightning Thief or Clash (then Wrath) of the Titans will have seen
Greek dramas and mythologies re-presented to 21st-century audiences, so
will have witnessed the continuing circulation of these ancient stories. A
more intellectual reading was offered by Freud (1915–17/1973), who, of
course, recognised in the Oedipus tragedy an issue he thought fundamental
to the entry of every (male) child into the social world. Other psychoanalytic
theorists, of the stature of Lacan (2002) and Irigaray (1985), have followed
his lead and turned to ancient Greece for inspiration and understanding.
More recently, Mitchell (2000) drew on the Medusa to fill in a major gap in
Freudian thinking.
Philosophers turn in a major way to the Greek tragedies: Most influential
of all, perhaps, is Hegel’s interpretation of The Antigone. He draws on the
play, albeit without referring to it by its name, in the section of Phenom-
enology of Spirit (1977) entitled ‘The Ethical Order’, in a discussion entitled
‘Ethical Action. Human and Divine Knowledge. Guilt and Destiny’. His
analysis revolves around the distinction between divine and human law:
the former is that of the family, the household gods and the female; the lat-
ter that of the public realm, of rationality, objectivity and masculinity. He
writes (1977, para. 475, p. 287) that ‘Human law in its universal existence
is the community, in its activity in general is the manhood of the community,
66 On Being At Work
in its real and effective activity is the government’. This law is dependent
upon the Family, which is ‘presided over by womankind’ (1977, para. 475,
p. 288), and Antigone, it is clear, becomes his model for womankind. Wom-
ankind threatens ‘the earnest wisdom of mature age’ that is ‘indifferent to
purely private pleasures and enjoyments’ (ibid.) and thinks only of the com-
munity. The confrontation between King Creon and his niece, Antigone,
therefore marks for Hegel the emergence of the distinctive realms of the
public and private. Creon insists that his loyalty to his kin should be subor-
dinated to his loyalty to the state; if not, he takes the denigrated female po-
sition. Antigone, the female, represents the family, its role being to provide
sons who will support the state while keeping the female safely outside the
public realm (a position Antigone notably refuses). Hegel thus interpreted
Sophocles as articulating the emergence of, and the difference between, the
public realm of the state and the private realm of the family, issues that con-
tinue to perplex 21st-century societies (Stroud, 2005) and that would seem
applicable to organizations as public realms.
The Antigone proved similarly influential in the works of Fichte, Holderlin
and Kierkegaard (Steiner, 1984). In the wonderfully titled On Germans and
Other Greeks, Schmidt (2001) explores the influence of Greek tragedy in the
work not only of Hegel and Holderlin but also of Nietzsche and Heidegger.
For Schmidt (2001), the importance of the tragedies lies in the assumption,
derived from Plato and Aristotle, that tragic art informs the development of
ethical and political thought.
Feminist theorists find emancipatory potential in the tragedies. Kristeva
(1982) argued that Sophocles was representing the death of matriarchal
culture following its overthrow by patriarchy, demonstrating that the
current gender order is not immutable. Jacobs (2006), inspired by The
Oresteia, identifies in Athena’s mother, Metis, swallowed by Zeus after
he had raped her, a symbol that contributes to development of a feminist
agenda for the 21st century. Scott (2005) has a similar intention: she also
turns to the Oresteia, and specifically to the matricidal Electra, to achieve
her aim.
Butler and other feminist thinkers ask, in reference to Freud’s choice of
Oedipus rather than Antigone as his archetype for the psyche, what is fore-
closed by ‘rendering one imaginative device and narrative an authoritative
canon’ (Pollock, 2006:89) and what would be made possible using differ-
ent imaginative devices. The artist Bracha Ettinger’s response (in Pollock,
2006), arising from her interpretation of The Antigone, is a matrixial border
space, where matrix, or womb, countermands phallic imaginaries. That is,
‘the condition of being humanly generated and born is an ethical ground ab
initio, a form of linking . . . that appears transgressive to a phallic autism
when its archaic foundations are activated and invoked politically, ethi-
cally, aesthetically, symbolically as the basis for human thought and action’
(Pollock, 2006:104). In other words, rather than psychoanalytical theory’s
isolated ego, the matrixial border space emphasises the co-emergence of
The Bondsman’s Tale 67
subjectivity and thus connectedness and, it follows, a responsibility towards
the other and possibilities of a new organizational ethics.
Pointers towards such an ethics are given by Chanter (2010), who sug-
gests that tragedy can be used to bring about an epistemic shift through
identifying and registering how regimes of suffering render some forms
of pain meaningless: we need new ways of understanding what suffering
means. Sjöholm (2010) looks to The Antigone and to Sappho for an alter-
native to Foucault’s history of Eros. Her argument is that we should dis-
tinguish between active/passive, rather than male/female, and imagine an
erotics that goes beyond sex, a suggestion I drew on in the previous chapter
to argue about an erotics of power. In the same volume, Bernstein’s (2010)
sympathetic rereading of Hegel’s account of The Antigone provides a rec-
ognition of an absence in Greek ethical life not only of any concept of a
self independent of its roles but also an absence of knowledge of any self
expressing a singularizing ‘who’ through its actions. Bernstein argues that it
is the woman, Antigone, who carries for Hegel the task of instigating the ‘I’
or the ‘me’, separate from a collectivity of roles.
Through popular culture, as noted earlier, we are invited, again and
again, to explore ancient Greek myths. The focus of this chapter, The An-
tigone, has been used by dramatists such as Bertolt Brecht (1984) and Jean
Anouilh (1951/2000) to help explain the incomprehensible in the 20th cen-
tury. For artists, as the frontispiece of Seamus Heaney’s (2004) verse transla-
tion explains, the play explores how ‘language speaks truth to power, then
and now’. Theatres regularly hold performances of the plays: in the north of
England, where I live, I was able to see the Oresteia one month and in the
next watch a live transmission into cinemas of London’s National Theatre’s
staging of Phèdre.
The reasons for the continued circulation of these ancient texts have been
debated. McCarthy (2003) argues that social scientists in Europe peer at the
world through a Greek lens, whether they know it or not, for Marx, Weber
and Durkheim were all heavily influenced by their studies of the dramatists
and philosophers of ancient Greece and absorbed those ideas into their own
theories. Steiner (1984), meanwhile, suggests not only that their continuing
resonance lies in their having articulated nearly all of the major problems
that continue to bedevil Western nations but also that, in that articulation,
they entered these problems into the syntax and semantics of European lan-
guages. Foley (1995), however, is adamant that the continuing relevance
of the Greek tragedies to ways of thinking through intractable problems
of the modern, industrialised and postindustrialised world lies in the way
they break free of the linearity of writing and thought. They offer ‘multiple
codes’ that educate us in appreciating ambiguity and ‘refusal of easy closure’
(Foley, 1995:131).
Greek dramas ‘work’ because they focus on families and their members:
they propel us into identification with individuals thrown into the most ap-
palling of circumstances. Our response, if the actors are skilful, is visceral.
68 On Being At Work
After Medea has murdered her children in an act of desperate revenge on her
unfaithful husband or Queen Agavë has ripped the heart from the chest of
her son in The Bacchae, one leaves the theatre with the breath punched out of
one. Philosophers, meanwhile, or, more precisely, those rare ‘master readers’
(Steiner, 1984:291) who bring together ‘text and consciousness’ offer inspired
interpretations of the plays, casting light on current dilemmas and, in their
own way, take away the breath with the brilliance of their analyses. They
offer different, insightful ways for understanding organizations and working
lives in the 21st century. As Foucault suggested when looking at other aspects
of ancient Greek culture, they allow us to ‘think differently than one thinks,
and perceive differently than one sees’, and this is ‘absolutely necessary if one
is to go on looking and reflecting at all’ (Foucault, 1985:8).
Antigone: Would you do more than simply take and kill me?
Creon: I will have nothing more, and nothing less.
Antigone: Then why delay? To me no word of yours
Is pleasing—God forbid it should be so! –
And everything in me displeases you.
Yet what could I have done to win renown
More glorious than giving burial
To my own brother? These men too would say it,
Except that terror cows them into silence.
A king has many a privilege: the greatest,
That he can say and do all that he will.
Creon: You are the only one in Thebes to think it!
Antigone: These think as I do—but they dare not speak.
Creon: Have you no shame, not to conform with others?
Antigone: To reverence a brother is no shame.
(Sophocles, 2008, p. 18, lines 499–511)
Well, we had an extraordinarily busy week last week . . . and the man-
agers were falling [over] themselves to get the work through because,
well I think there is a tension building . . . in the workforce and the
management. Management is under pressure to cut down costs and so
they are trying to get through as maximum amount of work as pos-
sible . . . with less number of people, so they are trying to utilise . . . the
available people and they didn’t [ask for extra staff as is normal at this
time of year]. So we are under pressure to get the work through. . . . It’s
difficult because when you are receiving an extra volume of work you
aren’t gonna get through at the finishing time. So everybody is strained
and you can feel it, and . . . there is tension that is bound to build up
between the workforce and managers.
There are certain areas which become the centre of the attention of
managers, or that area takes precedence over other areas, so they will
pull people from other areas and bring them here. [This] makes it
crowded, and then people who don’t work usually with you in that area
The Bondsman’s Tale 71
they don’t know the codes of how to work or what to do . . . and you
feel like you’ve been encroached . . . we are like well, you shouldn’t do
that, and why is he throwing a package in my . . . container because
if he keeps throwing[them] in my container [then it] will be full before
I’ve checked it.
Chorus:
There was one in days of old who was imprisoned
In a chamber like a grave, within a tower;
Fair Danaë, who in darkness was held, and never saw the pure daylight,
Yet she too, O my child, was of an ancient line,
Entrusted with divine seed that had come in shower of gold.
Mysterious, overmastering, is the power of Fate.
From this, nor wealth nor force of arms
Nor strong encircling city-walls
Nor storm-tossed ship can give deliverance.
(Sophocles, 2008, p. 33, lines 944–950)
The Chorus warns that, even when entombed in a cave a person may
engage in activities unbeknownst to and so beyond the knowledge of those
who have entombed them. I turn now to Butler’s reading of the state in
Antigone’s Claim, in which she aims to bring about a crisis in its legitima-
tion (Lloyd, 2005). Using her arguments to analyse Shakeel’s description of
his working week brings about what could be called a crisis of legitimation
of management, for, as well as speaking in the idiom of management while
doing some part of his work and thus putting into crisis the question of who
is the manager, he also constitutes other spaces and places within the orga-
nization that are inaccessible to the manager/master/lord.
Butler’s reading of the State in Antigone’s Claim is located within her
demand for ‘a rearticulation of the structuralist presuppositions of psycho-
analysis and, hence, of contemporary gender and sexual theory’ (2000:19).
The state thus figures not as an overarching national organizational func-
tion represented by government, the judiciary, the police, and so on, but as
the law of the Father. In challenging psychoanalysis, Butler therefore chal-
lenges conceptions of ‘the state’. In this, her arguments echo those chal-
lenges found in poststructuralist theories of organization to any overarching
presence of ‘an organization’ (Burrell, 1988a; 1988b; Chia, 1994; 1995;
2000; Cooper and Burrell, 1988; 1989).
Butler argues that when her critics object that she is challenging the law,
their utterance that ‘It is the law’ becomes the ‘utterance that performatively
attributes the very force to the law that the law itself is said to exercise’
(2009:21). The state, and it follows for this book, organizations, can thus
also be challenged as laws that are performatively achieved. It is through ac-
knowledging their powers that we retroactively bring those very powers into
being. In doing this, theorists elevate those ‘things’ we call organizations to
‘the status of a certain order of linguistic position without which no signifi-
cation could proceed, no intelligibility could be possible’ (2009:20), and so
The Bondsman’s Tale 75
they become one of the ‘elementary structures of intelligibility’ (ibid.). I have
substituted organizations here for kinship, for Butler’s arguments on kinship
are equally applicable to organizations: we cannot, it seems, think of how to
do work without thinking of ‘organization’.
If this is so, then we must interrogate the performativity of the term ‘or-
ganization’. Poststructural theories of the becomingness of organization/
selves (Burrell and Cooper, 1988a; 1988b) dismiss the idea that organiza-
tions could either be separate from organizational subjects or enjoy a su-
perordinate position ‘over’ those who work ‘in’ them. However, the word
‘organization’ continues to circulate. In previous work, Jackie Ford and I
(2004) showed that organizations appear as only metaphysical presences for
the nonmanagerial staff who work ‘in’ them. In a reanalysis for this chapter
of a random sample of the interview transcripts from that study, I found
that eight managers used the word ‘organization’ a total of 192 times while
eight members of the nonmanagerial staff used the word only seven times
between them. Shakeel, like the nurses and doctors in that earlier study,
never uses the word ‘organization’. In a transcript that is 8,700 words long,
he uses the name of the company ten times but uses the word ‘company’
only four times, three of which are in its meaning of being in the presence of
others. The fourth use of the word ‘company’ is ambivalent. He says ‘we are
all working in the same company’, which can be read as meaning ‘the same
organization’ or ‘the company of the people brought together to work in
this place’, an ambiguity that is potentially highly productive. It thus seems
that people are introduced to the word ‘organization’ when they work in
managerial positions or study management degrees.
In light of what Butler argues, this presence in managerial narratives
and absence from staff narratives of the word ‘organization’ is significant,
for managers, it would appear, work ‘in’ organizations that become en-
dowed with a presence (the ‘rational’ organization) that is very different
from the territory occupied by nonmanagerial staff. Staff do not utter the
word ‘organization’, so for them there can be no performatively enacted
law of the organization. They would occupy spaces (not places) (Lefebvre,
1991) very different from those occupied by those who would otherwise
appear to be co-occupants, managers. In Shakeel’s account, this distinc-
tion is material as well as discursive. The place in which he works is big
and noisy, as huge machines are used to sort the mail. Managers occupy
a physically different place, and they do not seem to enter the noisy shop
floor: so invisible are they that Shakeel is not sure whether or not they
work a five-day week:
his duties will take him somewhere else, you know, so now he’s here,
now he’s not here
(a) The bondsman acquiesces because of the power of the boss. Such
a recognition can be no more than tentative, always liable to being
withdrawn should the balance of power change;
84 On Being At Work
(b) The bondsman appears to acquiesce but nurtures some resistance
within him/herself, notably a critique of the managerial abilities of
the boss and a belief that s/he can do the job of the manager far bet-
ter than can the manager him/herself, so that although the worker’s
body may appear to conform, his/her mind does not. If the master
senses this, then s/he will be engulfed in an existential crisis, not
knowing whether s/he is or is not the boss and therefore uncertain
about the extent to which s/he can demand that the worker become a
zombie-machine;
(c) The scene of recognition is a charade: the bondsman gives recognition
only grudgingly and withdraws it as soon as possible.
(d) The scene of recognition is a fantasy, borne of the managers’ or orga-
nization theorists’ theory of what exists. Just out of sight, just round
the corner, just in another construction, another scene is occurring.
And so the scene of recognition breaks down, or perhaps there never was
a scene of recognition between manager and staff member. Each party may
look elsewhere for recognition, for the achievement of selfhood.
CONCLUSION
This is the theory that is now developing: in Chapter Two I argued that the
manager is driven by hard work, which becomes an ethical norm to which
the manager must conform if s/he is to be recognised as a manager, so the
manager him/herself must become a zombie-machine. This zombie-ma-
chine is dependent for its identity as manager on staff’s conforming to the
requirement that they too labour as zombie-machines. From the master’s/
boss’s perspective, there can be no pleasure at work, nothing other than
the duty to work extremely hard, although there is a guilty, erotic pleasure
in the power over others. This chapter uses another interview, with a man-
ual worker, and another scene of encounter, that between King Creon and
his niece Antigone as interpreted by Butler. This suggests that staff do not
provide recognition to the manager, save grudgingly and tentatively. Staff
themselves do not require recognition from the manager: they achieve it
elsewhere. Rather, they go through the motions of conforming to the man-
ager’s requirements but experience the manager as a bad presence, one
that inhibits the efficient accomplishment of work. It is not that staff do
not want to work or prefer, in Taylor’s terms, to ‘soldier’; it is rather that
they have different ideas about how the work should be done, and so they
speak the idiom of managers even though they cannot be recognised as
managers. They must conform to management’s requirements about how
to do their work when the manager is present, but when the manager is
out of sight they take charge of the working space, transforming it into
a different type of space in which much more takes place than the mere
The Bondsman’s Tale 85
doing of workplace tasks. However, that which is done is always restricted
by the limitations imposed by management—there is no freedom of choice
of task or means to its accomplishment. The possibilities for being there-
fore appear very limited.
In Hegel’s outlining of the lord/bondsman dialectic, the slave eventually
achieves identity through producing the world, while the master does not
attain identity and so the roles are reversed. The theory I developed through
building on Frank’s thesis of his working life is that the manager/boss strives
for recognition through evidence of his/her extremely hard work, but in this
chapter we have seen that Shakeel, as worker, withholds recognition from
the manager. What the manager regards as extremely hard work the worker
regards as inefficient intrusion into working space. The manager must there-
fore look elsewhere for recognition, and we saw in Frank’s case that this
elsewhere is ‘the organization’ which demands that s/he work and work and
work, with the evidence of his/her abilities qua managers resting on his/her
ability to make staff into zombie-machines that work and work and work.
Shakeel has shown us that although managerial power means that staff
must appear to conform to the requirement to be a zombie-machine when
under the gaze of the manager, staff evade that identity. The worker becomes
alive, becomes human, when out of the direct control of the manager. This
does not mean that the worker can produce ‘the world’, because what can
be produced, what work on the self can be undertaken, is always limited in
some ways by what the organization deems permissible. Shakeel, for exam-
ple, must sort the mail, and even though he carries out the tasks of manage-
ment he is not recognised or recognisable as doing so. Limited in the work
s/he can do, existing in the eyes of managers only as a zombie-machine, still
the bondsman achieves recognition of the self as a living human subject. It
is in the social life of the workplace, that which Shakeel constitutes when he
evades managerial oversight, that he would appear to gain such recognition
of the self. How this occurs will become clearer in the next chapter.
4 Becoming Human
would either give you your tasks not finished off on Friday, or perhaps
explain to you the next section of work that he wants to do, um, and on
most sites you have a rough idea of what you are expecting from either
a geophysics survey done previously or a desktop study where they look
at records of what’s previously been found, so you would know perhaps
that we’re on a mediaeval site and we’re expecting to find lots of rub-
bish pits, so someone might set to and go to that section and dig out half
of it and then draw the cross-section and plan them.
She takes her equipment, including lamp, spade and drawing equipment,
to the site where she will be working. If it is a ‘large feature’, she may
Someone might call and ask your opinion over what you think, but if
you’re seen just talking the supervisor might glare at you or come across
and shout, but it’s usually the young ones who’ve just started who do
stuff like that.
The terms and conditions of employment are not good: ‘It’s standard
practice to lay people off at Christmas and the New Year’ and to be on
fixed-term contracts: ‘I know someone who had a two week contract . . .
which of course is illegal now’. Many employers, Alex thought, try to
circumvent employment laws. The longest contract she has been on was
‘11 months and 2 weeks because they laid me off a few weeks before I
got any employment rights’. This she regards as ‘typical’, but she sees no
point in protesting because ‘getting a reputation as a troublemaker would
effectively blacklist your career, that’s something you don’t tend to do’.
Further,
Earlier, when talking about why she had chosen to pursue an archaeology
degree, Alex had said, ‘I just wanted to do something more interesting and
more unusual, I didn’t want to do what everybody else expected’, so she
chose a career that she understood to be different from other careers and,
she understands (hence the raised voice when referring to a general other
that calls the job glamorous), one with a reputation for glamour.
So, Alex knows the physical reality of the job (‘very wet, cold, miser-
able’), but she also engages with a fantasy of it as ‘glamorous’. She engages
in a fantasy in which material experience is subordinated to an image of the
job. I suggested in Chapter One that fantasy is important in the distinction
between labour and work, between the doing of tasks and work on the
construction of the self who does those tasks. In this chapter we delve into a
shared fantasy, in which the camaraderie of the dig is the site of self-making,
of mutual recognition of the archaeologist self. Fantasies about work fa-
cilitate my development of the me I aspire to be; in Alex’s case, this is a me
who does glamorous, exciting work and who is therefore a glamorous and
exciting person.
There is an analogy here with The Antigone, because Alex is burying an
unpalatable issue. I do not want to stretch that analogy too far, but there
Becoming Human 91
is further inspiration to be found in the pages of Antigone’s Claim (2000).
Although I was intrigued initially by the analogy between soil and burying/
disinterring when I heard Alex’s account of her work, it was the importance
of friendships within that telling of the archaeologists’ world that first took
me back to Antigone’s Claim, whose main thesis concerns kinship, for a
more meaningful way of understanding Alex’s working life.
The important reference here is to what the job is ‘called’, that is, how
it is articulated in language. Butler (2002) draws out the distinction be-
tween Antigone’s two deeds: the doing of the act of scattering dust over
her brother’s cadaver and her use of language to claim that deed. In Alex’s
account, we have a similar distinction between the act itself (digging in the
dirt of the archaeological excavation) and her describing it to me. Butler
argues that Antigone’s description of what she has done is an act in itself,
for actions can be reported or understood only within language, so embod-
ied actions become meaningful only through language. It is when affirming
her act in language that Antigone becomes criminalised; prior to that mo-
ment she was, it could be argued, doing nothing other than performing the
92 On Being At Work
required funerary rights for a dead brother (Blundell, 1995). The same act
could be interpreted in very different ways. It is in her speaking about it and
her refusal to deny that she had done this deed that, Butler argues, renders
Antigone a criminal.
I suggest that in Alex’s account, the mechanisms are similar, but the
outcome is very different: that is, through affirming her act in language,
she transforms mundane labour into glamorous work. That is, it is the act
of talking which performatively constitutes archaeological labour as that
which is done by exciting and glamorous professional staff.
Antigone’s act can be performed only through ‘embodying the norms of
the power she opposes’ (Butler, 2000:10), for the power of her verbal acts
lies in ‘the normative operation of power that they embody without quite
becoming’ (ibid.). We saw earlier how Shakeel, a sorting-office labourer, em-
bodies managerial norms even as he appears to resist them. Alex, however,
does not oppose the power of the employer but instead uses the normative
operation of power of the professions (Friedson, 1986; McMurray, 2011)
to claim a professional identity. She refuses to acknowledge that the messy,
dirty labour is merely digging in the dirt. The scraping away of soil and the
poor working conditions are described as something that is palpably differ-
ent from how we must imagine the material reality and thus Alex, through
the words that are her deeds, can transform labour into work on the self.
In other words, Alex can speak from the position of archaeologist only
if she accedes to that prior claim that archaeology is a glamorous, exciting
profession. To be an archaeologist rather than a labourer requires that she
talk about glamour and excitement and about being a member of the profes-
sion. In her speech, she must refuse her work’s mundane everyday charac-
teristics even as she acknowledges them. Through defining the profession as
exciting and glamorous she upholds the law of the language of the profes-
sion of archaeology, a language that belies, at the same time as it redefines,
its material practices.
Alex’s words are her constitutive deeds: through speaking, she becomes
archaeologist.
The second major contradiction in Alex’s account concerned how she
was converted from hating excavations to loving the experience of them.
Analysis of this second displacement shows the importance of witnesses to
speech acts.
Students of archaeology at the university where Alex studied went on
their first excavation at the end of their first year. She hated the experience.
Looking back at it, she said, the archaeology was ‘the best archaeology I’ve
ever seen’. She ‘made some really good friends when I was there, but the
Becoming Human 93
weather was abysmal and there was a lot of very hard physical labour that
I wasn’t used to and I hated it’. She said that
we weren’t really in any way trained to dig, and so you were almost
thrown in at the deep end and that combined with . . . really poor
weather made it six weeks of hell for me.
There are many similarities between the two occasions: in each, Alex felt
underprepared for the tasks she had to do, but she reports that the archae-
ology itself was interesting at both sites. She had made really good friends
on the student dig and enjoyed the company of the people on the second
excavation. The weather was very different, but she has subsequently come
to take it for granted that the weather will generally be awful—surely one
‘golden summer’ could not have accustomed her to the physical experiences
of her many later digs? We saw earlier that Alex is able to hold comfortably
two contradictory perspectives of her profession, that it is hard, dirty work
and that it is glamorous. I will suggest that her first experience of a dig, at
the end of the first year of a degree that she thought would prepare her for
a glamorous profession, revealed its physical reality to her and shattered her
original fantasy. However, her second experience was as a graduate who
could now call herself ‘an archaeologist’, and I will argue that the experi-
ence of being an archaeologist required that the fantasy be restored. This is
because of the performativity of the identity ‘archaeologist’.
There are two scenes of encounter in Alex’s story of a neo-Damascene
conversion from hating archaeological digs to loving them. In the first, Alex
is a student in company with fellow students being taught by archaeolo-
gists; in the second, she is an archaeologist who is teaching students and
94 On Being At Work
working alongside fellow archaeologists. At this point, what is important
is the performativity of the terms ‘student’ and ‘archaeologist’, so Butler’s
development of Althusser’s theory of interpellation offers most help in ex-
ploring the scenes in which Alex is interpellated first as ‘student’ and second
as ‘archaeologist’.
Butler on Interpellation
Butler challenges ontologies: rather than there being preexisting domains,
domains are materialized through discursive, material practices. There is
thus, Butler told us in her early work (1990; 1993) no gender prior to its
citation: no male or female preexists the discursive, material practices which
bring about their masculinity or femininity. Butler (1993:7) eliminates cau-
sality: there is neither precedence nor succession, but,
The materiality of the body, its sex and gender, the ‘I’ that locates the body
as the site of its emergence, are all thus performatively achieved through a
constantly reiterated process of becoming. Applied to Alex, this means there
is not a ‘student’ or ‘archaeologist’ who precedes the identity but one that
comes into being, is constituted within and through the terms of these ap-
pellations. The ‘student’ and the ‘archaeologist’ are sites in which identities
are constituted through reiteration, reestablishment and sedimentation of
discourses, materialities, psyches and affect, with the terms themselves act-
ing in, through and upon the materiality of (performatively achieved) bodies
and, in so doing, constituting subjects and subjectivities.
Most fundamental, perhaps, the ‘I’ depends upon recognition that it is a
human subject, a recognition given through language and interaction:
I think when you start a dig it’s quite often almost there’s a sensing
out of the pecking order. . . . There’s a lot of questioning, you know,
have you worked a few years, are you friends with this person or that
person. . . . It’s quite a small profession, pretty much everyone knows
each other or they know a friend of a friend, so you might have heard
stories about the people who, or you might randomly bump into some-
one that you’ve done work with previously. Which sometimes is great
and you bump into friends, sometimes it’s dreadful when you bump
98 On Being At Work
into ex-boyfriends or, um, people that you literally cannot stand or you
think they are dreadful and they’re childish, and so those first couple of
days are always a lot of stories, setting out you know . . . who’s better
than me, who’s worse than me, is there somebody who perhaps is very
new to this and needs looking after, is there somebody who’s lazy and
needs a kick now and then, is there somebody who is a brilliant fount of
all knowledge and a really, you know, somebody that you would want
to pick their brains and learn from them.
People have to go back and forth to collect equipment and deposit re-
cords, and that takes place all the time, so quite often as they go past
you they’ll sort of stop and make a few comments or ask how your
work is going, and that’s accepted because somebody else might have a
perspective on what you’re doing. A lot of these things come down to
interpretation, to what do you think is going on, . . . so it’s quite impor-
tant to have opportunities to speak to people working in the same area.
But it is the pleasure of the company outside the actual working hours
that is very much valued:
Well, it’s great. I’ve spent hours and hours with a radio next to me and
been perfectly happy knowing that in two hours time I’m going to be
in a small metal site hut with 20 people that are all laughing and joking
and I’ll go off by myself again tomorrow.
There are many opportunities for interactions away from the dig itself
(where talking is not allowed):
You’re with people 24/7, usually away from home, you work with them,
live with them, you socialise with them.
There is time spent in the pub and time spent in the shared accommoda-
tion. Care is an important part of the time spent together:
I have REALLY good friends in my work. [They leave] cups of tea out-
side my bedroom door. I’d come home and someone would have been
to the shop and bought a chocolate bar, you know, and it’s thousands
of times, you know. . . .
of the heavier or more brutal chores, removing spoil works. . . . It’s those
little kindnesses that make the site feel like a family.
Becoming Human 99
Archaeology supervisors not only have a policing role—they inhibit talk
on site—but also are described at one point as having an emotional role, as
if they are an important part of this family: they
almost take on like an avuncular role. . . . They tend to look for the
emotional well-being of their staff or the best supervisors do, as well as
just the progress of the work.
Alex compares this with what happens in the offices she has worked in as
an administrator between digs:
when I’ve done office work, temporary, in between digs, I’ve always
been struck by how supervisors are there to concentrate on the work,
and it’s very [physically] close to people, but it’s quite isolating, you
don’t end up in personal chitchat, you don’t get to know these people,
you just work with them. . . . I get the impression that people [in offices]
go there and then they go home to their friends.
How Alex constitutes the role of the supervisor is important here. It was
only when drawing a contrast between office work (denigrated) and archaeo-
logical work (lauded) that Alex introduced the idea that archaeology supervi-
sors have an emotional (and therefore valuable) role that is absent from office
supervisors’ role, which she reduces to solely that of policing. In other words,
Alex has to do repair work to her earlier statements in order to sustain her
account of the differences between archaeological and administrative work.
I will argue later that this contrast with office work is informative: the
people Alex works with as a temporary administrator cannot give her the
recognition of herself as an archaeologist but recognize her only as an ad-
ministrator, an identity she does not want.
Why is friendship so important? What is constituted within and through
these interactions with workplace friends? I suggest that these encounters
between workplace friends are not ‘innocent’ but are constitutive of work-
place selves. It is in these moment-to-moment encounters that the self is in-
terpellated, on each temporary stage where that self meets its other. During
the interview, I was also witness to (and thus was able to re-cognise) Alex’s
constitution of herself as an archaeologist. In what follows, I will argue that
each encounter between workplace friends does a similar service, over and
over and over. It is they who give us recognition that we are human and who
therefore help us refuse the identity of zombie-machine. First, I will stage
Alex’s encounters with supervisors, fellow archaeologists and office work-
ers as scenes of recognition such as that between Creon and Antigone. This
will lead into the final part of this chapter, where I will develop a theory of
workplace friendship’s place in the recognition and thus in the elevation
of labour to work, or self-making, and in the movement from the zombie-
machine to the human.
100 On Being At Work
ALEX AND RECOGNITION
People have to go back and forth to collect equipment and deposit re-
cords, and that takes place all the time so quite often as they go past you
they’ll sort of stop and make a few comments or ask how your work is
going. . . .
Alex will therefore spend ‘hours and hours with a radio next to me’.
This first scene of encounter therefore involves supervisor/organization/
Creon, who demands that archaeologists be no more than digging/catalogu-
ing machines. Antigone disappears from this scene: she perhaps joins her
sister, Ismene, in the ‘women’s quarters’, that place reserved for those who
are not allowed participation on the public stage. There is conformity to the
tyrant’s rule, so only labour can be carried out. The work of self-making, of
becoming human, must go on elsewhere, in the spaces and places where the
acts of talking about the work are responded to by those with a different
power, that of interpellation into the human.
The Third Encounter: Self and People Who Share a Work Space
Alex’s reference to her experience of the temporary office work she carries
out between digs shows that it is not just any colleague or friend who can
accord recognition. The desired recognition can be constituted only through
interaction with others occupying the desired subject position. I will repeat
here what Alex says about temporary office work:
SUMMARY
When I was seven or eight years old, I read an Enid Blyton story in which
the Famous Five went on holiday to Wales (I think it must have been Five
Get into a Fix [1958]). I remember that the farmer’s wife who featured in
the story said ‘look you’ at the end of many of her sentences. I never used
that phrase, resulting in what I would now call an identity crisis: could I be
Welsh if I did not say ‘look you’? If I wasn’t Welsh, what, then, was I? Simi-
lar questions beset me as I read lists of the attributes of the male and female
culled from the literature cited in this chapter. The male is/must be rational,
non-emotional, strong and disembodied/close to culture, the female caring,
nurturing, emotional and embodied/close to nature. My body is biologically
female, and, after it has fallen out of bed each morning, I dress it up so that
it conforms to its biological identity (makeup, hair, nail varnish, clothes,
shoes); after 30 or 40 minutes’ labour, I turn the requisite set of arms, legs,
torso, and the rest into a semblance of a woman. Much of this work is plea-
surable; what can be painful is the outcome, which places me in a category
in which my career prospects may be limited by gender rather than capabil-
ity (Fotaki, 2011) and in which I may become invisible and silenced. When
one’s ideas are dismissed not because of their content but because of the
body that articulates them, that body flinches and shrinks as it experiences
the insult as if it were an act of physical violence.
However, it takes just a few minutes’ thought about norms to realise that
these basic distinctions between male and female/masculine and feminine
arise (in the first instance) from categorizations according to physically evi-
dent (albeit socially interpreted) characteristics: with/without breasts, vagina
and penis. To these are attached normative attributes, widely mistaken for
positive differences: rational/emotional; strong/weak; public/private; logi-
cal/caring. If one is to be a ‘real’ man, that is, if one does not have breasts or
Becoming and Not Becoming Gendered 115
a vagina but does have a penis, then one has to conform with the norms on
the left side of each slash in this list. Those with or without the other requi-
site bodily protuberances and orifices must constitute themselves according
to the appropriate set of norms. Failure to approximate sufficiently well
these normative attributes jeopardises, if not makes impossible, recognition
and therefore selfhood (Butler, 1990; 1993). This is despite their being cul-
turally variable and arbitrarily, albeit historically, allocated. When I stumble
across myself thinking or debating or working, in those times when I be-
come consciously aware of both body and mind, it strikes me that I am not
conforming neatly to gendered categories: although I am sometimes within
them, at other times I straddle both sides of those boundary lines, and I am
sometimes outside them altogether. What gender therefore is the (apparently
female) me that is rationally and unemotionally (in an apparently masculine
way) considering how it genders itself? More pertinent, what is this ‘gender’
that Butler has shown I am performatively achieving?
Much research contradicts the belief that sex/gender is a given and im-
mutable biological category, that men are born men and women, women. If
that were the case, there would be no need for a chapter on gender, unless
it was to explore the continuing inferior position of women and women’s
jobs. However, that path is very well trodden and I would add little to it.
Rather, it is the changes in occupations that intrigue me, notably in manage-
ment and the professions into which women have made many incursions so
that, at least at junior and middle levels, they are very visibly present.1 This
is very different from when I looked for my first job, at the age of 16, when
clerical posts were advertised with two pay scales for the same post, one for
men and a lower one for women.
Women today are in some ways very different from the matriarchs who
crowded in on my mining community childhood a half-century ago. How-
ever, I look round at family gatherings and see how my own sisters have in
their turn become matriarchs, provoking thoughts about the possibility of
the influx of women into management and the professions constituting an
organizational matriarchy. Such thoughts would be misplaced, because they
imply in some ways a fixity to gender identities that contradicts four decades
of feminist and gender studies that attempt to interpret what is going on ‘out
there’, outside the concrete and glass towers of modern universities, and
which try to understand what gender is. When gender theorists let down
their hair and used it to climb out through the windows of the masculine
ivory towers they had struggled so hard to enter, they escaped from huge
numbers of studies, especially those carried out by psychologists, which re-
garded, as they still do, male and female as biologically given binary oppo-
sites. These studies are blind to feminists’ counterargument that gender is a
social construction built on biological organs and to poststructural gender
theory, instigated by Butler, which argues that biology itself is not fixed
and unchangeable but apprehended only within discourse. Indeed, Foucault
shows that how we understand genitalia is itself a construction.
116 On Being At Work
How does this relate to the well-established constructionist argument
that organizations mandate gender identities, requiring that staff constitute
gendered organizational selves in conformity with that requirement (Adler,
Laney and Packer, 1993; Benn and Gaus, 1983; Benschop and Doore-
waard, 1998; Cockburn, 1990; Duncan, 1996; Gherardi, 1995; Grant and
Porter, 1996; Mills, 1992; Mills and Murgatroyd, 1991; Pateman, 1983;
Trethewey, 1999)? Many jobs are gendered, with those more concerned
with care, such as nursing, elder care and nursery teaching regarded as
‘women’s’ and those requiring, say, heavy physical labour regarded as those
of ‘men’ (Adler, Laney and Packer, 1993; Duncan, 1996; Lam, 2004; Ga-
trell and Swan, 2008). Organizations ‘themselves’ are gendered—they are
masculine (Alvesson and du Billing, 1992; Calas and Smircich, 1991, 1992;
Hearn, 1992; Collinson and Hearn, 1996). That is, they are detached,
logical, unemotional places, banning any distractions beyond the work at
hand; they are stable, powerful and authoritative (Hearn and Parkin, 1986;
Hearn, 1992; Mills and Murgatroyd, 1991; Ross-Smith and Kornberger,
2004). As such, they are not caring, emotional, subjective places close to
nature. That is, they are not feminine, not masculinity’s inferior, pollut-
ing other (Gherardi, 1995; Da Cunha and e Cunha, 2002). The approach
of these studies is constructionist. They leave unanswered the question of
what gender may be, beyond the presumption that masculinity and femi-
ninity rely on each other for definition: I am female because I am not male,
and vice versa.
To understand being at work in the 21st century, we therefore need to
understand what gender ‘is’, how it is constituted, and how it shapes the
self as zombie-machine or human. In Butlerian terms, this requires explo-
ration of the performativity of gender in organizational public spaces that
were previously the domain of men but now are occupied by both women
and men. That is the aim of this chapter: an exploration of the performativ-
ity of gender so as to seek answers to the question of what ‘is’ workplace
gender in the early 21st century. In the context of this book, the questions
I am exploring include: what is gender in today’s organizations? Does the
distinction between labour and work hold good when discussing gender?
Is the zombie-machine gendered, or the human, and where is gender in my
aspirations for the me I desire to be(come) through/in work?
I interviewed two people for this part of the study, a woman and a man.
They are academics, chosen because academia, traditionally a masculine
profession and one dominated still by men, involves male and female staff
carrying out the same tasks regardless of gender, so I anticipated that it
would be a useful forum for exploring the performativity of gender: how
do female and male academics constitute gendered identities and gendered
bodies when undertaking similar tasks—what turns one into a man, and the
other into a woman? Do they escape from these binary oppositions? But I
also explore how cultural products are reflecting back to us changing gen-
dered cultures of workplaces by discussing the hit science fiction television
Becoming and Not Becoming Gendered 117
series Battlestar Galactica. The thesis I develop is that we lapse out of gen-
dered identities but are surprised back into them. I use a vignette from the
work of Patricia Yancy Martin to illustrate how this happens. But first, the
literature review.
Butler (1990:8–9) states that there are discursive limits that both presuppose
and preempt possibilities of gender configurations save those predicated on
familiar binary structures: we have no language in which to imagine any-
thing beyond the male/female binary. This is an important observation for
this chapter, in which I will explore how an embodied gendered identity
may have little relationship to a subjective experience that is, to all intents
and purposes, outside gender. Although we will meet two people whom we
would identify, on first meeting, one as a man and the other as a woman, we
do this because of what we see before us: one is taller than the other, one has
a lighter voice and so on. Butler, however, in the opening pages of Gender
Trouble, unties sex and bodies:
One can ‘never be’ a gender because the normative assumptions of each
of the familiar genders are impossible to achieve and because the process of
becoming gendered never ends but is repeated moment after moment after
moment. That is, gender has ‘no ontological status apart from the very acts
which constitute its reality’ (1990:136). There is no female, male or other
gender identity that preexists the ‘expressions’ of gender; rather, the female
and the male are constituted through the acts that performatively achieve
gendered bodies. It is impossible to achieve fully the norms that state what a
woman or man ‘is’, but to be an ‘I’ requires that we strive to achieve them,
because the ‘I’ is ‘the historically revisable possibility of a name that pre-
cedes and exceeds me, but without which I cannot speak’ (ibid.).
Thus, as Butler summarises it (1993:2):
Her famous analogy with the drag artist does not imply that we are all
in drag: what it shows is that we are all imitating something, but what we
are imitating had no original that we can copy. Drag performs ‘the sign of
gender’, a sign that is, crucially ‘not the same as the body that it figures, but
that cannot be read without it’ (1993:237), because
120 On Being At Work
The critical potential of ‘drag’ centrally concerns a critique of a prevailing
truth-regime of ‘sex’, one that I take to be pervasively heterosexist: the
distinction between the ‘inside’ truth of femininity, considered as psychic
disposition or ego-core, and the ‘outside’ truth, considered as appear-
ance or presentation, produces a contradictory formation of gender in
which no fixed ‘truth’ can be established. Gender is neither a purely
psychic truth, conceived as ‘internal’ and ‘hidden’, nor is it reducible to
a surface appearance; on the contrary, its undecidability is to be traced
as the play between psyche and appearance (where the latter domain
includes what appears in words). (1993:233–234)
THE PROBLEM
This period in the Euro-American part of the globe, as with that time
around the industrial revolution in Britain, is a time of gender flux. Changes
that take place in epochs such as this evolve slowly, over several genera-
tions, and are not immediately visible to participants, but poststructuralist
gender theory is articulating something of what many of us perhaps sense
is happening. In other words, I am suggesting that earlier studies of how
organizations actively participate in the gendering of employees (Adler,
Laney and Packer, 1993; Benn and Gaus, 1983; Benschop and Doorewaard,
1998; Cockburn, 1990; Duncan, 1996; Gherardi, 1995; Grant and Porter,
1996; Mills and Murgatroyd, 1991; Mills, 1992; Pateman, 1983; Trethewey,
1999) may need updating to take account of the woman as a speaking
managerial or professional subject. Rather than using the constructionist
approach of the studies just cited, which argues that behaviour follows bio-
logical sex, a poststructuralist thesis such as this argues that organizational
gender discourses constitute the masculine and feminine. The exploration in
this chapter explores current changes in organizational ‘modes of existence’
(Judovitz, 2001:1) occasioned by the influx of women into professional and
managerial positions in organizations. The thesis that organizations were
male public spaces, with women contained within the private space of the
home (Pateman, 1983) has broken down. This does not mean, of course,
that there is that elusive thing called equality between the sexes or that
many occupations do not remain strictly identified as ‘women’s’ or ‘men’s’
(Lam, 2004). What it means is that women or, rather, those who occupy
the speaking positions of women (Lacan, 1998) have become highly vis-
ible co-occupants of the public spaces in which professional and manage-
rial work is undertaken. If gender is performatively constituted within a
cultural, historical and psychic field where one seeks recognition, then one
must ask whether changing gender structures of management and the pro-
fessions offer different possibilities for constituting one’s gendered organi-
zational self. This leads to the questions, noted earlier, of what therefore ‘is’
gender in today’s organizations. Does the distinction between labour and
work hold good when discussing gender? Is the zombie-machine gendered,
or the human, and where is gender in my aspirations for the me I desire to
be(come) through/in work?
The empirical analysis ponders these questions. It has three sections. The
first is a study of a science fiction drama, in which we see enacted very
124 On Being At Work
clearly and visibly the breaking down of the relationship between gendered
attributes and biological bodies. The second is based on two interviews, in
which I explore the gendering of the working self and show how one moves
between gendered identities, even into non-gendered positions, but is always
surprised back into one’s culturally required gender. The third is a reinter-
pretation of data from a paper by Martin (2006) which I reread through
the thesis developed here. This leads to the conclusion that organizations
are places where, for some people at least, one constitutes the self as poly-
morphously perverse and where there is freedom from the pains of gender.
However, this relief is temporary: one is always surprised back into gender
and into its traumas. This has somewhat contradictory implications for the
thesis of this book.
Starbuck
The time may be in the past, the future or indeed the present. Humankind
lives on 12 linked planets and has invented robot-like creatures, cylons.
Forty years previously, war between cylons and humans led to the vanquish-
ing and exile of the cylons. The cylons have evolved and now can adopt an
appearance so like that of humans that they cannot be detected, allowing the
introduction into the story of a problematic often explored in science fiction,
the question of what it means to be human. Indeed, some cylons have been
placed as ‘sleepers’ in human society but do not know they are not human.
The story opens with the cylons attacking the 12 colonies, intent on destroy-
ing the human race. The remaining humans flee into space aboard any space
ship available. The only military spaceship not destroyed is the Battlestar Ga-
lactica. It is through the eyes of the people on board Battlestar Galactica that
much of the story is told. The battlestar has a crew of fighter, or viper, pilots,
one of the more senior of whom is a woman called Kara Thrace, whose call
sign is ‘Starbuck’. All pilots dress identically in boiler-suits.
Starbuck is a hard-drinking, cigar-smoking gambler. She is ‘an accom-
plished viper pilot’, who is ‘self-reliant—and a bit of a loner’. Described
on the official programme website as tough and rebellious, she has a ‘take-
charge’ attitude and is ‘always hungry for a good fight’. She is at the core
of the combat team because of ‘her guts, her brain, and a little luck’. (All
quotations are from http://www.gateworld.net/galactica/characters/thrace.
shtml, 2 accessed May 2007.) A gifted pilot, she is also a talented military
strategist. In various episodes, she is seen to use her body in ways that could
be regarded as masculine (Young, 1990). For example, in hand-to-hand
fighting or in the boxing ring, she punches overarm, like a man. Now it may
seem at this point that Starbuck represents here a woman who has to ‘pass’
as a man in order to be accepted in a masculine profession (Marshall, 1984;
Wajcman, 1998). This is not the case, however, for Starbuck is shown often
in a ‘feminine’ light, as weak, vulnerable and emotional.
Much of this description, except for the last sentence, is equally true of
the male character called Starbuck who featured in the original series of
Battlestar Galactica, which premiered in 1978 and ran for two series, end-
ing in 1980 (see http://www.scifistream.com/battlestar-galactica/ for more
information). Further funding was not available until 2003, after which the
‘reimagined’ story proved so successful that four series were commissioned.
The show won numerous prizes, positive critical comment (except for the
last episode) and larger audiences than any other series on the Sci-Fi chan-
nel, according to Wikipedia.
126 On Being At Work
The numerous websites which discuss Starbuck do so in adulatory tones.
Only a few references describe as controversial the decision to put a woman
into what had previously been a male role. One such is an intriguing question
asked by a journalist of actor Katee Sackhoff: ‘I am somewhat concerned
about Starbuck as a woman, since the “original” character was not just a
man, but a Ladies [sic] Man with a big old phallic cigar and all that. What
about now? Does Starbuck have something to replace the cigar?’ Sackhoff
replies: ‘She still has the cigar. God, I must have smoked about 30 of the
things’ (http://scifi.about.com/cs/a/aa11203.htm, accessed 22 May 2007).
Sometimes a cigar is just a cigar, but the phallic imagery here resonates with
Butler’s proposal (1993) of a lesbian phallus; that is, contra Lacan, she ar-
gues that the phallus (the master-signifier) need not be represented by some-
thing alarmingly similar to a male organ. The phallus is central to much of
Lacan’s thinking. It is the master signifier, holding a privileged position over
all other signifiers, for it establishes the conditions for what can be signified.
The phallus therefore determines what can be knowable. Butler (1993), hav-
ing used Freud to show that bodily parts are imaginary, demonstrates that
the phallus can be attached to any body part, leading to the question of why
it should be attached to any body part. What would happen if the phallus
became a lesbian body part? Any body part or, indeed, none could thus be
the ‘master’ signifier. Following Butler’s argument, it is possible to see Star-
buck’s cigar as a female phallus that establishes the conditions for what can
be signified. As such, does it not suggest the possibility for signifying gender
as a disembodied ascription that can, to a certain extent, be refused? That
is, although my body is female, I may refuse some or many of the attributes
of its femininity, refusing to acquiesce in the requirement that morphology
becomes my destiny.
Battlestar Galactica was transmitted during a time of flux in which the
very possibilities for gender are changing. The 21st-century version of the
series, unlike its earlier incarnation, featured numerous strong female char-
acters, including the president, Laura Roslin; the cylon who destroyed the
12 colonies, Number Six; and numerous fighter pilots. Starbuck’s character
is different: these other female actors are playing strong, powerful charac-
ters, so they articulate changes in women’s lives that have occurred since
legislation promoting equal opportunity was enacted in much of the West-
ern world in the 1970s. Starbuck represents something more, because of
the polymorphous perversity of ‘her’ character (language insists we must
categorise the character as ‘he’ or ‘she’ and thus limits the possibilities for
speaking about polymorphous perversity). Writers and actor have made a
conscious attempt to replicate many of the mannerisms and characteristics
of the original male character, whilst at the same time Starbuck is shown
to be romantic, vulnerable and in other ways ‘feminine’. That such moves
are possible testifies to the major changes in the possible gender identities
that have become available in the quarter-century between the making of
Becoming and Not Becoming Gendered 127
the original and the ‘reimagined’ series. The success of the series suggests
a public quite comfortable with characters whose visual appearance sug-
gests their femininity whilst their behaviours suggest masculinity. Where
‘women’s films’ of earlier decades taught women how to desire men, thus
upholding the heterosexual matrix (Doane, 1988), such a popular television
series today seems to encourage its audience to desire and enact not a mas-
culine or a feminine but a polymorphously perverse subject position that
refuses gender categorisation.
This, importantly, is a subject position that may be desired alongside the
desire for an identity within a feminine or masculine subject position. By
this I mean that the two are not in opposition, not an either/or; rather, a per-
son can move fluidly between and, indeed, can refuse either or both of them.
This is illuminated specifically in one episode in the first of the ‘reimagined’
series, when Starbuck is portrayed off-duty and away from the spaceship.
She ‘dresses up’ as an alluring, sexually attractive woman, wearing a reveal-
ing red dress and makeup. Danger threatens, and she is a leading participant
in the ensuing fight scene. This is the most overt demonstration, in this
early episode, of how she can move easily between seemingly ‘masculine’
and ‘feminine’ subject positions. Meanwhile, the character who represents
female sexual allure and the appearance of femininity, the character known
as Number Six, is a cylon who is intent, it seems, on annihilating the human
race. This character is Butlerian theory in action: the archetypal attractive,
blonde, alluring woman is shown in the very first episode to be a creature
that becomes a woman (rather than, say, a machine) only through the per-
formativity of the feminine.
Now, the objection may be raised that what I am observing in Battlestar
Galactica is, rather than a refusal of categorisation, an elision of difference
between men and women and thus a return to an older feminism which
encouraged or required women to become as masculine as men (Hekman,
1999). One of the major differences between this and earlier arguments is
that I am neither advocating that this is what women should do nor sug-
gesting some essentialised ‘woman’ beneath the portrayal of masculinity.
Rather, I am saying this is what is happening, that new possibilities for gen-
der have emerged and are informing the constitution of gendered identities
in organizations. A second objection therefore is that I am observing a form
of masculinity being practised by those with female anatomy and thus to
some extent following Halberstam’s (1998) analysis of female masculinity.
If so, then women are conforming to organizational requirements that they
practise their gender differently. This, I submit, is one part of the case, but
I want to keep in tension the practising of both masculinity and femininity
and polymorphously perverse organizational subjects. It is not a case of
either one or the other but of both/and and, indeed, neither/nor. I develop
this argument by turning to the two people who agreed to be interviewed for
this book, Kara and Saul.
128 On Being At Work
ANALYSIS TWO: EXPERIENCING GENDER
I interviewed Kara and Saul, two academics, and also observed them giving
lectures, trying to discern the ways in which the performatively achieved
body is constituted in its moment-to-moment repetitions of stylized ges-
tures. My aim was to better understand how the gendered body interacts
with the psyche to confirm one in what seems like a stable gender identity.
I also reflected back on myself as I watched them and tried to observe myself
auto-ethnographically in the process of giving a lecture: how is the embod-
ied academic self constituted through the doing of academic activities? The
observations initially confused me: there appeared to be few, if any, differ-
ences between how Kara and Saul used their bodies, save for the obvious
differences of physical appearance. I observed other colleagues and speak-
ers at conferences, keeping notes of how female and male lecturers moved,
trying to discern those movements that are supposed to be specific to each
gender (Young, 1990). I found I could not—both men and women keep
their arms close to their bodies or use their hands a lot; some men move
around and take up a lot of space, but so do some women. Some women
take up little space, moving their bodies only in small ways, but some men
do likewise. With a few exceptions (such as Judith ‘Jack’ Halberstam), the
appearance of each speaker conformed to his or her biological sex: no man
wore a skirt or lipstick, and none of the women wore a tie. After a while, it
struck me that, beyond these superficial declarations of gendered identity,
the people I was watching while they were working were not performatively
constituting materially embodied gendered identities; there was a surface to
the body that symbolised masculinity or femininity, dress, hair and other
familiar codes, but, apart from the obvious distinguishing marks, there were
few discernible differences. Rather, I realised, I was imposing gendered iden-
tities on them. That is, my subjective body was imposing gender on what
are, to me, the objects that are their bodies (Leder, 1990).
The scene of recognition here was thus reversed: rather than their requir-
ing that I recognize them as appropriately gendered so that I could con-
firm them in their gender identity, I was imposing on them the requirement
that they appear to me as appropriately gendered. Butler alludes to this in
her work: recognition can be granted only on the condition that one ap-
proximates the norms that allow the self to be recognised; therefore there is
another party (including one’s own self looking in the mirror or reflecting
on [thinking about] its self) that judges whether one has reached the stan-
dards necessary for recognition. This implies that there is one who grants
recognition, an Other whose subjectivity we know little of. My experience
suggests something further: if I impose gender identity on an other, it means
I can place myself in relation to that person and know myself as appropri-
ately gendered and capable of recognition and therefore of being. In other
words, I require others to be appropriately gendered so that they hold up
a mirror in which I can know myself: in looking in that mirror I can see
Becoming and Not Becoming Gendered 129
myself as ‘like’ them (we share the same sex) or the opposite of them (we
do not share the same sex), and therefore I can know who I am. This must
also apply when the other is the reflection of my own body in the mirror, a
body that is outside of and separate to whatever it is I call ‘me’, but when
I see a body reflected back at me on which I can put the label ‘woman’ I
can know my gender. If I cannot place the other in an appropriate category,
then my own position is confused. This perhaps explains what happened to
Kara at the end of the semester, after her last tutorial, an incident (discussed
below) which suggests repair work is necessary for organizational partici-
pants when a person does not conform to that imposed gender identity and
is, in many ways, polymorphously perverse: we/they insist on regendering
that person, surprising them back into gender.
Kara was 31 and Saul 32 at the time of the study. They both work in busi-
ness schools in British universities. Saul was born and grew up in Britain,
while Kara, although educated in Europe, grew up elsewhere. In order to
maintain their confidentiality I will give no more than these few sketchy
details. Kara is short and slim and has her own, unique, clothes style. When
I watched her give a lecture, she moved about the stage little and used what
I would call ‘professional’ body language, in that her movements related
largely to the PowerPoint presentation and other visual aids, but her pres-
ence commanded attention as she spoke slowly and clearly in a voice that
could be described as in the range of an alto singer. Saul is tall and slim,
dresses conservatively in trousers and open-necked shirt and gives the ap-
pearance when lecturing of rigidly controlling his bodily movements.
Our discussion followed the timetable of a lecture: preparation, walking to
the lecture theatre, setting up, beginning to speak, delivering the lecture and
finishing. I will start with Kara’s account of walking to the lecture theatre.
The extended discussion of high-heeled shoes was startling, but its in-
clusion, as well as the length of the reference, suggests that Kara herself
is here working with an as-yet unformulated theory of herself as lecturer.
She shows that these shoes not only inhibit freedom of movement but are
dangerous—if she falls her credibility as a lecturer is at stake because she
would be put in the position of the frail woman needing to be rescued. Fur-
thermore, as she discusses these shoes she talks about herself as invisible—it
is only when she gets to the lectern that she feels safe from falling and able
to silence the students with a few words spoken in a loud voice. What Kara
is articulating here is, I suggest, a transition between what I will call for the
moment the feminine and masculine speaking subject positions. The shoes
make her vulnerable and perhaps in need of rescue, but they also symbol-
ize, in their instability, the frailty of the gender she must sustain if she is to
be recognized as a woman. However, when she gets to the desk or lectern,
Becoming and Not Becoming Gendered 131
the signifier of the lecturer, she shifts rapidly from a vulnerable ‘feminine’
subject position to a dominant, ‘masculine’ one.
Copjec (2003), as outlined earlier, argues that woman constitutes herself
as an object for the desiring gaze of others; Kara, when talking about her-
self as an academic, seems to be saying that she fails at this. Using a female
signifier (high heels) makes her invisible (the students are all taller than she
is, even though she is wearing high heels). To me, what Kara is articulating
here is, first, the precarity of gender as symbolised by the feminine shoes: it
is something that may fail us and so undo us, unravelling all the work neces-
sitated in sustaining a sense of self. Second, she is espousing a theory about
the impossibility of being a female speaking subject in academia: we lose
our female gender identity (fall off the shoes) when we occupy the masculine
speaking position of ‘the academic’: that is, we must move out of the posi-
tion of female speaking subject and in some ways regender ourselves. To be
academics we must abandon the normative construction of the female self:
we fall off our heels and become logical, rational, non-emotional, power-
ful and in command; we do not exist to be looked at. We are ‘safe’ when
we reach the lectern, which acts similarly to Lacan’s famous toilet door in
allowing us to claim the appropriate gendered position: we line up behind
it and can assume the position of male speaking subjects. I have previously
argued that the manager’s suit is a form of control over male managers
(Harding, 2002) and have often been asked how that account applies to
women managers who dress very differently. Kara gives an answer to that
question: women working in what have traditionally been masculine profes-
sions are in drag, masculine minds in feminine attire perhaps, if we briefly
use a Cartesian binary. As such, female professionals are controlled in ways
very different from their male counterparts. Dominant representations of
women in European cultures are of embodied creatures: semi-naked female
bodies stare out at us from magazines, adverts and billboards. The woman
remains tied to its body (de Beauvoir, 1949/1997); she is always-already
naked, a nudity covered over by clothes. For men, the professional suit elim-
inates the body. If the woman who works in a professional career is in drag,
then she is controllable through the threat to tear off the dress to reveal her
as a woman, to make her conform to the archetypal female position.
Saul wears smart trousers and sharply ironed shirts to work. He does not
use the phallolinear mark that is the tie, but his clothes otherwise, in their
severity and lack of adornment, bespeak the rationality and non-emotionality
signified by the manager’s suit (Harding, 2002). For him, the walk to the
lecture theatre passes without hindrance:
N: Walking to the lecture theatre and going into the room—what goes
through your mind, what do you do in those moments?
S: Umm. It depends actually, not a lot actually, if I’m going in on my
own, I tend not to have anything in my mind. Partly because you’re
in that social environment and you might be seeing people you
132 On Being At Work
know and typically before I’ve gone to the class I know what I’m
going to talk about so it isn’t in the front of my mind.
He had talked earlier of feeling so anxious about lecturing that his body
temperature rises. Here we see first a need to take control, to be in charge,
to prevent chaos ensuing if anything goes wrong. This is a masculine subject
position. But note also two statements: things become a bit of a blur when
he is ‘live’ and his references to being gazed at.
With regard to ‘when I’m live’, the metaphor of ‘live’ refers both to an
electrical charge flowing through a cable and to television or radio appear-
ances where, rather than being prerecorded, speakers are heard by listeners
as they talk and there is no opportunity to make corrections. Saul is speak-
ing here of a major transition, from a quiet, introspective and invisible per-
son who is about to become a lecturer to an active performer (lecturer) who
is able to carry out tasks without conscious thought (‘it’s a bit of a blur’).
When Saul goes ‘live’, when the electrical charge courses through him and
brings him to life (Frankenstein’s monster?), he stops refusing the students’
gaze (‘I don’t have to stare looking at the students’) and actively invites it:
Now all eyes have to be on him, in this swift change of subject position.
In other words, he, like Kara, moves from being invisible to being visible, to
inviting the gaze of the other, a gaze that desires the other’s desire, which, as
Copjec argues, is the place of the feminine. However, we will see next that
how Kara and Saul respond to that desired gaze differs and positions them
in unpredictable ways: Saul, the male speaking subject, responds to the gaze
in what we may regard as a ‘female’ way, whereas Kara responds in what
is commonly regarded as a ‘masculine’ way. For now though, the conclu-
sion at this point is that the transition from office to lecture hall is one in
which Kara, a female speaking subject, experiences that speaking subject’s
self from a female position, while Saul, a male speaking subject, experiences
that speaking subject’s self from the unmarked male position. This changes
when they begin lecturing.
Giving a Lecture
To be the subject of a gaze has powerful resonance for academics who, by
definition, must be looked at, as can be seen in Saul’s return to a question
he could not answer until the issue of being looked at was raised. Early in
the discussion, in response to something Saul had said, I had asked him,
‘So who are you then?’ His reply had been very bland, if not evasive. When
asked what it is like to have ‘all those faces’ looking at him as he lectured, he
suddenly returned to that earlier question, signalling the turn in the discus-
sion with an emphatic ‘So’:
At that moment. I feel quite sexy actually [laughs]. There’s there’s defi-
nitely, cos there’s always there’s always this part in lecturing—is it per-
formance, although I don’t. I mean. Prior to this interview I was kind
of thinking about that. Is it, you know, talking about the body of a
lecturer, is lecturing a performance or whatever? I mean, I, it definitely
is, right now, it’s definitely a performance . . . and I know I’m gonna
give give a give a good one, cos I know I’m good at it.
When Kara gives a lecture on a subject she likes, she talks about feeling
sexy, about giving a good performance—she will ‘give a good one’. Some-
times, it seems, the seduction fails, but this is on the occasions when she
does not feel sexy. This is the only time in the discussion that she men-
tions a philosopher’s name, a male philosopher who, it seems, takes over
the position of the seducer but who gets it wrong and insists on dry sex, sex
as duty, not sex as pleasure. Obviously, the man is not up to the job of se-
duction: it needs a powerful woman in a masculine speaking position—she
laughs in the place where the word ‘orgasm’ might have appeared, but then
changes her tone to show that she ‘does’ very few that are so unproductive
of excitement:
Saul Kara
I am 5’11, I am [pause] 13 stone 9 I am 31 and, er, I am about a 160, er,
normally, give or take a couple no, yes, 160 centimetres high and
of pounds, target weight is 13 weight about 60 kilos.
7 [laughs] and, in terms of my N. Why do you go belly dancing?
philosophy about looking after Er, just because it’s fantastic, the fun,
myself, I suppose physically I go to um, we have a nice troupe of people,
the gym at least three times a week, there’s my teacher and two other
not just for weight training which girls, we do dancing in my teacher’s
is something I do a lot less of now living room and all four of us go
that I am getting a bit older and absolutely crazy. We do things like
don’t see much point in having lots impersonating trolls [laughter]. And
of muscles to sit at a desk and do it’s just an enormously relaxing
a sedentary job. I might do some activity. We do the dancing, we just
cross-training or running or some socialise, we eat cake all the time, so
resistance training, circuit training, every session starts with cake and tea
and that’s what I do physically, [laughs], and we watch films, and we
I suppose, I play football once a do performances for charity and so
week. it’s just, I don’t know, I just like it. I
like it for the dancing, it puts you in
touch with your body really. I can
feel it, I enjoy my body, it’s really, it’s
a beautiful feeling when you can
make your body do interesting sort
of things and make it look good and
there’s a giant mirror, you know,
in the room where we can admire
ourselves, so it’s. Dress up in sequins
and skirts and scarves, so it’s like
whee it’s brilliant, yes.
Becoming and Not Becoming Gendered 137
Outside work, she is immanent to her body (de Beauvoir, 1949/1997), and
she enjoys that sensation of being embodied. This is in sharp contrast to
her relationship with it when at work, where it is something that has to be
covered up rather than enhanced.
Hi Nancy,
I thought I’d add one more little vignette on bodily interactions with
the student body. It happened just now:
After the XXX tutorial that I conducted, I was left in a room with
three of my mail [sic] students. One of them (Student 1) was asking me
a coursework question, another (Student 2) was just hanging around
and the third (Student 3) one wanted to take a photo with me. After
Student 3 asked me for a photo and I said ok, Student 1 said he wanted
one too. I said all right. When the photo was taken he stood quite close
to me—not too close, but probably closer than I would have liked.
When the photo with Student 3 was taken, Student 3 (who is quite a
bit taller than I am) put his arm around my shoulder, but very lightly,
barely touching me. After this happened, Student 1 said he would really
love another photo, and in this 2nd photo put his arm around me too
(somewhat more firmly than Student 3).
I sense that something is going on here with all these arms. I think
Student 1, seeing that Student 3 got away with putting his arm around
Becoming and Not Becoming Gendered 139
me, also decided to give it a go. I did not awfully mind, but I was not
very comfortable and still (I am writing about 20 minutes after the in-
cident) do not feel very comfortable. I felt very small and fragile with
these big arms around me, and this is not how I see myself as a lecturer.
As a lecturer, I am big, strong and authoritative. If there are arms being
put around things, they are my arms, as opposed to other arms being
put around me. It also makes me quite uneasy knowing that while all
these students are very polite (I even got a bow from Student 1), some
of them are wanting to put their arms around me.
So here we go. Now I am thinking about how to avoid arms in the
future. (or should I? . . . is this an expression of my insecurity?)
Picture the scene. Kara has just finished giving a lecture in which she has
occupied an active, ‘male’ speaking position, one of authority, dominance
and control. The students who approached her and put their arms around
her returned her immediately to a passive, ‘female’ speaking position, one
in which she is inferior and where she exists to buttress the frail mascu-
line ego (Brennan, 1993). Kara is switched from being the superior to the
subordinate, from the powerful to the powerless, from the active to the
passive, and in that moment she becomes subject to the inferiority that is
the heritage of women in the West. From being unaware of her body, from
having an absent body, she is made aware again that her body is small,
weak and leaky (Shildrick, 1997). Kara is therefore surprised back into
gender.
I want to suggest that this is not an unusual event but one that happens
repeatedly. Sitting here typing this account, my body recedes from my con-
scious knowledge, as does my awareness of my gendered identity. A glance
at the nail varnish on my fingers reminds me swiftly and sometimes brutally
that I am a woman. Every time we catch sight of our reflection in a mirror
or are positioned as male or female in the eyes of another person, we see
the visible signifier of our gendered position so, having lapsed out of it, we
are always surprised back into it. There is a violence for women in being
surprised back into what we know consciously as an inferior, subordinate
identity and for men and women alike in what we know unconsciously is
a baleful, depressing position requiring much work in the maintenance of
something we really do not want to maintain. We thus continually taste the
freedom from gender and have it snatched away, taste it again and have it
snatched away again. To be forced back into gender is traumatic, at both
the conscious and the unconscious levels. Consciously, norms of how we
should behave as men or as women can be oppressive and overdemand-
ing, and we are always subject to failure. We may be judged on our gender
rather than on our achievements, categorised and forced into uncomfortable
boxes. Copjec’s analysis shows how gender in the psyche is a torment. This
becomes clearer through re-reading an incident reported in Martin’s (2006)
research.
140 On Being At Work
ANALYSIS 3: SURPRISED INTO GENDER
Paula was the only woman manager present at a meeting where an inci-
dent occurred that was so upsetting that it led her to leave the company
six months later. She recounted to Martin (2006) what had happened. At a
meeting, a new member of the managerial staff, Bob, had just been intro-
duced. He ‘pulled a pair of bikini undies [from his coat pocket] and tossed
them on the table and said, “I’m always ready”. Only one of the men pres-
ent did not burst into laughter, and this man, Jeff, walked out of the room
with Paula. Paula made numerous formal and informal complaints, but
Bob’s only punishment was the withdrawing of some promised perks. Paula
left and established her own ‘flourishing financial services firm’.
Martin (2006) uses this and other examples to argue that men in organi-
zations are insufficiently reflexive about how they practise their masculinity
and the effect this has on women’s continued subordination. I fully support
her in her conclusion but suggest the incident says something more about
organizational gendering.
Paula has been cursed by psychoanalytical theory’s buttressing of West-
ern culture, so she has no option but to construct herself as female and thus
subordinate. She evades those demands by constituting herself within an
active, managerial speaking position. Martin indeed argues that gender is
a tacit, liminal practice that may be largely subconscious. Paula thus may
‘forget’ she is a woman and join with the men in the meeting as an equal.
She, like them, may be ‘agendered’, or non-gendered, or have all sorts of
possible gendered identities potentially available as, in the company of the
men with whom she works, she forgets about culture’s requirement that
she be female. However, the throwing of the women’s underwear onto the
table surprises her back into gender, for if Bob had tossed onto the table,
say, a handkerchief, the incident would have been meaningless. Underwear,
in an office, is ‘matter out of place’ and thus has disruptive, performa-
tive power (Douglas, 1966). A garment that clothes the genital area, it has
sexual associations. Its sudden appearance, I suggest, reminds Paula that
she is a woman, with all the connotations of inferiority, subordination and
powerlessness that are the heritage of women in the West. She is surprised
back into gender.
Further, women’s underwear symbolises that supposed fear of castration
which Freud argues results in the male child aligning himself with the mas-
culine. So the ‘uproarious’ laughter of the men in the room may have been
less about humour and more the result of shock at their being surprised
back into gender as well. They are reliving that earlier trauma, that earlier
imagined threat of castration, through what Freud termed nachträglichkeist,
most commonly interpreted as “deferred action” or “retroaction”. By this
term is meant memory traces that are given new meaning as a result of being
‘relived’ in specific situations in the present. In other words, an episode that
occurred in infancy will return again and again, to be reconstructed and
Becoming and Not Becoming Gendered 141
reexperienced in the present (Barzilai, 1999). Lacan (1977) proposed that
human subjects live nachträglich perpetually, not extraordinarily, and, in so
living, they encompass three temporal stations: past, present and an antici-
patory dimension.
The sudden appearance of a symbol of symbolic castration therefore
would plunge all parties present back into the trauma of becoming gen-
dered. The men’s laughter is thus less laughter than a rictus response which
may have had little to do with humour and much to do with the return of
the repressed.
In this reading, Paula the manager, polymorphously perverse and confi-
dent in her non- or agendered identity, is reminded that she cannot evade
the powerless position of the woman. She is sentenced to entombment in a
symbolic cave, that of gender, the trouble and confusion of which is appar-
ent in Brewis’s (2005) painful exploration of the subjectified identity of the
female academic.
In this chapter I have explored the fluidity of gender identities in jobs that
women now share with men. Gender is in flux in these jobs: it is perhaps
more appropriate to talk about organizational speaking subjects, untied
from the descriptors ‘male’ and ‘female’, than about men and women. These
positions have no more than tentative connections with biological sexes,
and ‘male’ and ‘female’ are active and passive positions through which in-
dividuals move. The person whose genitalia are female may practise itself
as rational, logical, avoiding of intimacy, active, all those things regarded
as ‘masculine’. The person whose genitalia are male may practise itself as
caring, emotional, passive, all those things regarded as ‘feminine’. These
descriptive categories are arbitrary but normative. We are trapped by lan-
guage when trying to capture some of what is going on today, because we
are inevitably returned to ‘she’ and ‘he’ when we are surprised into gender.
It may be more appropriate to talk about, say, active and passive subject
positions, but even here we return to the grammar of ‘he’ and ‘she’, and we
cannot escape the centuries-long view of activity as masculine, and passivity
as its female other.
Furthermore, I have suggested that for much of the time we are, to our-
selves, ungendered or outside gender, but others impose gender upon us,
require that we be gendered so that they are confirmed in their own gender
identity. Repair work may be taken by those others if we do not conform to
their requirements of how we should be gendered, and indeed we may shock
ourselves when we see our reflections in mirrors—we return to embodied
movements that confirm us in our culturally mandated gendered identities.
We are therefore regularly surprised into gender, returned to the traumatic
142 On Being At Work
identity whose norms are unattainable and whose practices may render us
abject or put into painful and untenable positions. Then we lapse back out
of gender, only to be returned to it; then we lapse back into that comfortable
position in which the requirements of our gender are forgotten as more im-
mediate tasks and activities take precedence. But only for a while.
In attempting to move beyond the no-longer-tenable distinctions between
organizational masculinities and femininities, there is the possibility of sub-
jectivities that are about being. Rather than there being a ‘he’ and a ‘she’,
there will just be an ‘is’. Ending that sentence with a copula, not linking the
verb ‘to be’ to anything, signifies the meaning of that sentence. It is about
not being male, not being female, not being gendered, but just being a sub-
ject. Indeed, Foucault’s The Order of Things (1970) should have led us to
ask why traits have been organized into two lists of ‘male’ and ‘female’. Are
they not, as Foucault suggests, fundamental codes of a culture which allow
the ordering of things and disallow other possibilities? Does it not behoove
us therefore to challenge them rather than to continue listing them?
In terms of the argument of this book, organizations here have a poten-
tially emancipatory stance: they offer the possibility, perhaps to only some
of the people and only some of the time, of freeing the self from the dire con-
trols of gender. There is a cultural requirement to be identifiable according
to gender in order to be capable of recognition (Butler, 1990; 1993), but or-
ganizations may be illuminating ways in which it is possible to escape from
such a requirement. To be able to absorb one’s self in one’s task or to work
with others in a position of mutual respect about the self as a person, with
no judgements being made on the basis of whether one is fulfilling the norms
of masculinity or femininity—that is the possible future of organizational
(un)gender. Organizations currently show us a promised land, even though
we are currently allowed to enter for only sufficient time to know what it
must be like to become a citizen. The self that is outside gender is a self we
might hardly know we desire to be, because gender appears as natural and
as inescapable as the air that is breathed. However, having experienced the
freedom of being non-gendered, I may feel a visceral knowledge that the me
I wish to be would be freed from the constraints of gender.
I will therefore posit the notion that, when working on the self as an
organizational subject, we work on a self that will be outside gender,
freed from its constraints. But, when we labour, then, we labour as men
or women, with no freedom from gender’s constraints. The human is or
should be treated very differently. The terms of the question I posed earlier
about whether the distinction between labour and work holds when we are
discussing gender are turned on their head. The question should have been:
what can gender tell us about the distinction between labour and work? The
arguments in this chapter suggest that gender should be equated in some
ways with imprisonment and in other ways with freedom. There can be
pleasure in performatively constituting a gendered self, but also the terms of
gendering may be imposed in such a way that we become incarcerated in a
Becoming and Not Becoming Gendered 143
traumatic prisonhouse of a body/identity. If this is the case, then labouring
as a gendered person, with the terms of that gender imposed by the organi-
zation, means that labour equates to fixed gender categories. On the other
hand, through work, we may (sometimes) escape from that prison and be-
come outside gender for a while. So work equates to constituting a self freed
from gender’s constraints.
The next question was: is the zombie-machine and/or the human gen-
dered? The answer would appear to be that the zombie-machine is clearly
marked as sexed and judged accordingly. It may be channelled into jobs
that are the domain of its requisite gender (such as nursing or caring jobs
for women, hard manual labour for men). The zombie-machine becomes
judged on how it upholds its ostensible (fixed) gender identity. The human,
on the other hand, may move in and out of gendered identities, choosing
how to constitute itself as female or male and refusing to be judged accord-
ing to the norms of either category.
These are tentative conclusions, but they point to a somewhat unexpected
observation in a critical text. This is that organizations may, in some ways,
offer some people some of the time a revolutionary potential for becoming
free of the constraints of gender.
6 A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in
Drag: Organizations and the Murder
of the Me’s-I-Might-Have-Been
DOLLIMORE ON DEATH
This is the thesis I disinter from Dollimore’s (2001) book. Death and desire
have been mutually informative throughout the entire history of Western
European cultures. Fear of death, of dissolution of the self, is so great that
the only release from it is death itself. Temporary, fleeting release can be
found in disessentializing the self through activities in which one loses one’s
subjectivity and the I, or the ego, dissolves. In such evanescent moments,
there is no ‘I’ that can fear its own demise. (Where Dollimore finds possibili-
ties for such momentary transcendence of the self in the anonymous sexual
encounter, I will later use Marx’s theory of alienation to posit another scene
in which the self may disappear.)
Dollimore traces (sexual) desire’s embedment in Western Europe’s con-
ceptualisation of death to the scraps remaining of the writings of the first
Greek philosophers and tracks the continuing marriage of death and desire
through millennia of Western European thought. Western Europeans are in-
dividuated, that is, ‘separate, differentiated, alone’ (xx); self-consciousness
of individuality is formed through a knowledge of the end of one’s life
and informed by a feeling that the only release is death (xxi), that is
‘oblivion, . . . the cessation of desire, the still point of the turning world’
(10). There is thus embedded in the European psyche a desire for death, one
that is intensified, thwarted, deflected and exploited by theology. Freud’s
theory of the death drive brilliantly reworks and challenges theology’s grip
on death (xx).
Death and desire are connected, Dollimore argues, because of ‘mutability—
the sense that all being is governed by a ceaseless process of change insepa-
rable from an inconsolable sense of loss somehow always in excess of the
loss of anything in particular’ (xiii, emphasis in original). Over millennia,
A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in Drag 151
mutability becomes internalised as the inner dynamic of desire. ‘Fragmented,
unstable and death-ridden’ (83), the human subject is driven forward reluc-
tantly by that very ‘deeply regressive desire for oblivion’ (83): the desire
for death is what propels us towards a life in which the knowledge of our
own death foments ‘a restless, agonized energy’ towards the sustenance of
life. The Western European subject is therefore always ‘a subject in crisis’,
obsessed with control and expansion so as to deal with that crisis but insti-
gating forms of control that always exceed and break down the very order
that is restlessly quested (92–93).
Hegel, whose work informs the ideas of so many thinkers in the 20th and
21st centuries, understood this. Dollimore writes that Hegel, in analysing
how ‘we live stretched across a fierce dialectic in which identity is dependent
upon otherness or difference—dependent, that is, upon what it is not’ (154),
on an other that can never be kept other because part of what I am is that I
am not that, so that what I am not is not only alongside and independent of
what I am, but is also interior to what I am. However, for Hegel, being pre-
supposes not being, and vice versa. In order to be, everything must undergo
a dialectic sublation or negation by, in or as its opposite, so the negation of
death is not exterior but intrinsic to the subject. Thus, Kojève, interpreting
Hegel, could write that ‘the human being itself is no other thing than . . .
(a) death that lives a human life’; ‘Man [sic] is not only mortal, he is death
incarnate; he is his own death’; Man not only knows that he will die, ‘he is
the consciousness of his death’ (164).
Freud, Dollimore writes, evolved a new language, almost a new mythol-
ogy, to articulate the absolute interiority of death to life. Freud’s ‘ancient,
shocking vision’ was that death is not the termination of life (that ‘mystify-
ing banality by which we live’ [192]) but life’s animating and driving force.
Thanatos, or the death drive, arises from a desire for the complete calm of
the grave, free from the troubles of life. Life is merely ‘an enforced substitute
for death, a movement in the only direction available, which is forward and
one always undertaken against the more fundamental desire to regress, to
die (186–187).
In the 20th century, Dollimore argues, death was not so much repressed
as ‘resignified in new, complex and productive ways which then legitimate
a never-ending analysis of it’ (126). One of these is the marking upon ho-
mosexuality of death. Homosexuality becomes a ‘symbolic focus for cul-
tural preoccupations which far exceed it’. Homosexuality, defined by desire,
comes to figure death. (Another of these figures of death, I will argue
later, is the whodunit—by reading novels or watching films or television
programmes about murders and the search for the murderer, we immerse
ourselves in analysis of and fantasies about death. Thus we will return to
organizations.)
Now we come to what is most shockingly productive in Dollimore’s
thesis. The only freedom from knowledge of death that we have in that
time between cradle and grave is when we become ‘disessentialized’ (325),
152 On Being At Work
that is, when we so forget the ego or the I that we are lost to ourselves.
Postmodernism’s anti-essentialism, he writes, ‘as a merely theoretical state-
ment about identity is misleading to the point of being useless’ and ‘what
needs to be recovered is the experiential dimension of anti-essentialism’
(325). Dollimore finds this in homoerotic writing and in the anonymous
homosexual encounter, in which the self is ‘disidentified’ as ‘the divide
between reality and fantasy momentarily shifts and even dissolves, as do
other divisions too, including those between public and private, self and
other’ (327). In the momentary suspension of individuality, of the individu-
ated self, there is a temporary release from Thanatos, from the compulsion
towards death.
This would seem to take us a long way from much that goes on in organi-
zations, but there is a link to be made via Marx’s theory of alienation. I will
return to this argument in the conclusion to this chapter. For now, however,
I turn to the detective novel to explore how death informs working lives.
Just as the homosexual, in Dollimore’s thesis, is a symbolic focus for
Western Europeans’ fear of death, I suggest that the detective story offers a
cultural focus through which we put ourselves face to face with death. It has
been pointed out that there are strong similarities between the work of fic-
tional detectives and that of academics—each is concerned with discovery,
with finding out and with resolving dilemmas (Nicolson, 1946, Porter, 1981,
both in Hühn, 1987); further, fictional detectives are a useful proxy for sci-
entists and academics more generally (Czarniawska, 1999). Czarniawska
(1999) explores in depth the complementarity between detective fiction
and academic writing, while Salzer-Morling (1998) mimics the hard-boiled
detective novel to explore the relationship between academic papers and
organizational life, but there are no papers which analyse the detective
story’s performative relationship between reader, text and organizations.
That is, there is no exploration of how the detective story constitutes the
author/reader/viewer, who, we have seen, is long argued to be a creature
not only endowed with the fearful knowledge of its own finitude but in
many ways driven towards its own ending. I will use film and literary
theorists to show that our delight in observing, over and over, the fic-
tional portrayal of death arises from our attraction to a genre that says,
on our behalf, albeit elliptically and through symbols, metaphors and im-
ages, something which we cannot put into words. This is, we know we
are going to die, so we know how precious is the time available to us. In
that time, we wish to constitute selves that will have made our lives worth
living. Organizations, as the previous chapters and much research in la-
bour process theory and critical management studies have shown, severely
restrict the possibilities for constituting selves because they require that
we spend much of our time in work needlessly made boring and aimless.
That organizations thus limit our potential and stifle the selves we could
be is a form of murder—the murder of our dreams of who we could and
might have been.
A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in Drag 153
THE DETECTIVE THRILLER AS ARTICULATION OF AN EPOCH’S
UNSPEAKABLE TRAUMA
The detective:
Wallander rushed down into the mud. He stumbled into the ditch and
scrambled up the other side. When he saw Hoglund [a fellow detective]
on her back in the mud he thought she was dead. . . . And it was all his
fault. For a split second he saw no way out but to shoot himself. Right
where he stood, a few metres from her. Then he saw her moving feebly.
He fell to his knees by her side. She was deathly pale and stared at him
with fear in her eyes. ‘It’ll be all right,’ he said, ‘It will be all right’. . . .
Wallander could feel the tears running down his face. He called for an
ambulance. Later he would remember that while he waited, he had
steadily murmured a confused prayer to a god he didn’t really believe
in. In a haze he was aware that [two colleagues] Svedberg and Hamren
had arrived. Ann-Britt was carried away on a stretcher. Wallander
was sitting in the mud. They couldn’t get him to stand up. (Mankell,
2009:557)
In this section I outline the history of the detective story and its relevance
for understanding organizations. The detective story, with its focus predom-
inantly upon violent death, is hugely popular. To take one week at random,
beginning 25 April 2010, British television’s five terrestrial channels offered
each evening a minimum of two programmes (including films) that featured
violent crimes and their resolution. Satellite television channels offered nu-
merous offerings on the same theme. The terrestrial channels’ programmes
included reconstructions of actual crimes; a drama in which a police officer
has been transported back to the police force of the 1980s; ‘reality’ pro-
grammes in which police officers are accompanied by camera crews; a film
about a fictional 18th-century detective; a futuristic series in which the whole
of the human race is at risk; and numerous episodes of North American
crime dramas. The top ten paperback titles in terms of sales that week
included seven crime novels, two historical novels and one book combining
both genres through its exploration of an unexplained crime from the
15th century (the murder of the princes in the Tower of London). There was
little difference in the proportion of television programmes, films and books
devoted to crime and its detection in August 2010 and in March 2011. In the
US, six of the ten highest-selling books in 2008 (the latest year for which sta-
tistics were available at the time of writing) dealt with violent death and its
detection. 1Many of these books are translated into numerous languages, so
their stories are known internationally. For example, two Swedish authors
whose books are read worldwide are Stieg Larsson, whose Millenium Trilogy
has sold more than 40 million copies, and Henning Mankell, whose Wal-
lander series, featuring the eponymous detective, has sold 25 million copies.
154 On Being At Work
The BBC television films of the Wallander novels were watched by more
than 20 percent of the viewing audience on their first airing in the UK, that
is, by between 5.2 and 6.3 million people, 10 percent of the entire popula-
tion2. Many more will have watched the programmes via other formats.
Television programmes based on Ian Rankin’s Rebus detective novels have
achieved viewing figures of up to 8.4 million people.3 Crime dramas, nota-
bly those concerning murder and attempts to discover the murderers, are
therefore the entertainment of choice of many millions of people. When
six million people sit down to watch Wallander, they sit down to watch a
portrayal of murder.
Detective fiction appeared in the mid-19th century alongside an emergent
scientific interest in deductive logic and, indeed, manufactories. A newly liter-
ate reading public which was experiencing the cultural upheavals of industri-
alisation, the move from rural to city living, mass literacy and secularisation,
found in detective fiction some sort of ontological security (van Dover, 2005).
Edgar Allan Poe’s two short stories The Murders in the Rue Morgue (1841)
and The Purloined Letter (1844) established the ‘twin fountainheads’ (Rz-
epka, 2005:74) of detective fiction: ‘whodunit?’ and ‘how is the criminal to be
discovered and captured?’ As the scientific method developed, so also did the
focus in the crime novel on deduction through a careful accumulation of facts:
the amazingly insightful detective could emerge. It was Sir Arthur Conan
Doyle’s Sherlock Holmes books that institutionalised the format, which was
to continue for a century and more: the somewhat troubled but brilliant and
astute loner, dependent on a good friend, who has powers of observation far
beyond those of the average person (Rzepka, 2005; van Dover, 2005). The
detectives featured in the classic detective novels (and, later, the films and
television programmes) offer, in the scientific age, the assurance that someone
knows infallibly what has happened to us and knows the mysteries that sur-
round the beginning and the ending of our lives (van Dover, 2005). There is
nothing in this first incarnation of the detective genre to relate it to organiza-
tions: the detective operated independently, demonstrating a sparkling intel-
ligence far in advance of that of the police officers, whose role was that of the
inferior other to this superior form of being.
Classic detective fiction revolves around two stories: the story of the crime
and the story of its solving, often recounted by a companion to the hero-
detective. Its successor, American hard-boiled detective fiction, emerged
in the first half of the 20th century: now the companion disappears and
the detective becomes the narrator. Dashiell Hammett’s Sam Spade, who
appeared in The Maltese Falcon in 1930, and Raymond Chandler’s Philip
Marlowe, who featured in a series of novels beginning with The Big Sleep
(1939), typify the hard-boiled detective. Whereas previously there were
two overlapping stories—the committing of a crime and its solving—now
the two stories merge, and through the very process of searching for the
criminal the detective causes the criminal to commit more crimes. Often the
A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in Drag 155
hard-boiled detective has to battle against not only the devious criminal but
also the corrupt organizations that employ them. The heroic detective of
the classical novel is replaced in the hard-boiled novels by a detective who
is damaged, disillusioned, and ‘in a paralyzed state of profound weariness
and melancholy’ (Hühn, 1987:461) but who can, like the heroic detective,
‘reintegrat[e] the aberrant event, [and so] the narrative reconstruction re-
stores the disrupted social order and reaffirms the validity of the system
of norms’ (425). It can be seen that, as with the classic detective story, the
hard-boiled detective story does something far more than entertain, because
it addresses the traumas of an age. However, there is again little about orga-
nizations in this period: the detective is a solo operator, and any organiza-
tions encountered are shadowy, criminal and dangerous, symbolic perhaps
of the world wars of the 20th century and the West’s fear of Soviet commu-
nism but not of workplaces.
Classic and hard-boiled detectives have been challenged by the post-
modern detective story. Whereas literary theorists have argued that this
generation of whodunits is one, typically, in which each person’s story of
the crime is just another version of what happened, with little possibility
of discovering ‘the truth’, I suggest that the distinction between the post-
modern detective story and its predecessors is the importance of organiza-
tions to the analysis, because today’s detective works for an organization,
usually a police force, and often deals with murderers who work for other
organizations. Like that of the hard-boiled detective, this detective’s read-
ing of the story changes the story itself, and the detective, battered and
bruised, is left to suffer the consequences of a damaged ego. However,
this detective is not so much disillusioned as traumatised at being unable
to control everything going on around him/her (Czarniawska, 1999), and
much of what goes on around the detective is organizational life. Although
one story—the teleological journey towards discovery of perpetrators of
the crime—continues, alongside this runs another story in which teleol-
ogy is defeated and all around is chaos and uncertainty. This is signified
in material (organizational) objects such as the furniture in the detectives’
offices. Where the aesthete Holmes has a comfortable study and his body
remains barely touched by his encounters with criminals, Philip Marlowe
is the possessor of a modest office consisting of two rooms (one for his
secretary, one for himself) that is sometimes ransacked. Marlowe himself
is often beaten up, captured, threatened or bruised, and his body aches as
he pursues the perpetrators. The postmodern detective shares a cramped
office with other officers, in an organization upon which s/he depends for
his/her livelihood and is often engaged in finding murderers who work in
other organizations or who commit crimes on behalf of those organiza-
tions. As the level of privacy and comfort in the detectives’ offices diminish
and the detectives’ engagement with organizations increases, the detective
becomes more vulnerable.
156 On Being At Work
Today’s detectives are flawed, fallible people, just like their readers.
Where Marlowe suffered no more than a hangover from drinking his fa-
vourite bourbon, his successors now suffer the problems of alcohol abuse;
their bodies ache from lack of exercise and poor diets. Mankell’s Wallander
worries about his weight and has to take a day off work when he has flu,
he is too cold if he has not worn the right jumper, is often aware that he
needs a shower, has trouble finding the time to do his washing, shopping or
cleaning, and is eventually diagnosed with diabetes and, later, Alzheimer’s
disease. Rankin’s insomniac Inspector Rebus is increasingly unfit and can-
not keep up when chasing criminals, while Billingham’s Detective Inspector
Thorne stares in his mirror at his bloodshot eyes and, like Rebus, is racked
with guilt and haunted by past cases, and, unlike Rebus but like Wallander,
has a nervous breakdown. Larsson’s Blomqvist, the journalist who acts as
detective in the Girl with the Dragon Tattoo trilogy, is put into the position
of the female (he almost dies at the hands of a mass murderer of women)
and, emasculated, is rescued by a woman. Jo Nesbo’s Finnish detective
Harry Hole is an emaciated alcoholic. These detectives often are seeking
love but unable to find it. Again it is organizations that are responsible for
this failure in the detectives’ lives—they are unlovable because of the jobs
they do. Those detectives with friends and families find their relationships
damaged, and often organizations, work and family intrude into one an-
other’s sphere in ways that endanger not only family life but the life and
health of family members. Rebus’s daughter is disabled as a direct result of
his job; Wallander’s daughter is, in several of the novels, held at knifepoint
by deranged murderers, and D.I. Thorne’s only friend, a pathologist (it is
notable that pathologists often have a major role in these stories), is targeted
by a murderer because of their friendship. Everything around these detec-
tives that relates to organizations appears unreliable or dysfunctional. They
drive cars that seem always on the point of breaking down. Wallander’s
office contains a rickety chair which is perpetually in danger of collapse, a
chair that seems symbolic of both the organization in which he works and
of Wallander himself. Rebus and D.I. Thorne loathe the buildings in which
they work, and Thorne constantly hurts himself on the corner of his desk.
All are worn down by their jobs and the organizations against which they
struggle.
Not only do organizations feature prominently in the postmodern who-
dunit, but also their integrity is often challenged. Blomqvist is editor of a
magazine that is put under severe threat, a scenario which instigates his
exploration of another organization which perpetrates utterly vile acts.
Harry Hole works with totally corrupt police officers; while Donna Leon’s
Venetian Commissario Brunetti is, unusually, happily married but oppressed
by corrupt governmental and private organizations. Brunetti’s private hap-
piness contrasts with public despair: the crime is solved, but the criminal
often goes unpunished because of influence from ‘higher-ups’. Postmodern
A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in Drag 157
detectives have no respect for those more senior than they in the organiza-
tional hierarchy, and indeed it is almost a hallmark of these detectives that
they despise their managers.
Where the brain of the classical detective solved crimes and brain com-
bines with brawn in the hard-boiled detective novels, the postmodern detec-
tive relies on the stolid work of the team, on the brilliance and intuition of
the bruised and battered detective and also on luck. These detectives are in-
escapably embroiled in organizations: those they work for (and rail against)
and those they battle, pursue and attempt to bring to justice.
This history is important because detective fiction reflects dominant so-
cietal discourses in any epoch and also explores the unsayable at any par-
ticular time (Rzepka, 2005). The classic detective novel, written during the
certainties of imperialism and the uncertainties of industrialisation, could
articulate the fears of a collapse of social order and could promise its resto-
ration. Readers of the hard-boiled detective story lived through two world
wars and were threatened with nuclear armageddon: the hard-boiled detec-
tive signalled, through his isolation and his vulnerability, the loss of cer-
tainty and the fear that social order would always be tentative (Rzepka,
2005). The postmodern detective is a flawed, suffering and fallible human
being who works for one organization while often battling the crimes com-
mitted by other organizations or criminal employees. What does this detec-
tive articulate about the current epoch that is otherwise unsayable?
I suggest that in an era when the self is a project to be worked on, an
achievement that is always ongoing, always in process and offered to the
self for its own consumption (Foucault, 1979; 1986; 1992), the who-
dunit articulates issues around the project of the self. Technologies of the
self ‘permit individuals to effect by their own means, or with the help of
others, a certain number of operations on their own bodies and souls,
thoughts, conduct, and way of being, so as to transform themselves’ (Fou-
cault, 1997b:225). The liberatory potential articulated here by Foucault
is quashed by organizations: work, for many, remains a place where the
self cannot be transformed. The body of literature on identity in MOS
is too big to summarise here (see Alvesson, Ashcraft and Thomas, 2008,
for a statement on the state of the field), but the detective story, given the
size of the reading and viewing audience, must constitute one of the dis-
courses or technologies of the self that makes available ways of being and
identity within postmodern Western organizations. It articulates attitudes
and feelings that have a performative potential, informing work on the self
through the circulation of interpretations that are invested in the becoming
of the self. I next explore how the taken-for-granted presence of organiza-
tions in today’s detective stories alerts us to the unsayable that these stories
articulate for us, albeit through a glass darkly, and which become part of
the ongoing working self. The unspeakable secret is that organizations are
imbricated with death.
158 On Being At Work
IMMERSION WITHIN (POPULAR) CULTURES OF DEATH
The victim:
I turn now to outlining how and why all this watching of fictional death,
portrayals of something that is so awful it is supposedly sequestered, denied
or repressed, is not a passive occupation but one in which the watcher/
reader is actively engaged in becoming through this immersion in the who-
dunit. This attraction towards portrayals of death, notably portrayals that
are imbricated within and through representations of organizations, does
something far more than entertain us: it articulates a relationship between
the self, death and organizations.
The thesis that fear of death is suppressed or repressed seems to me to
ignore technological developments which, over the course of the second half
of the 20th century, turned Western cultures into image-saturated cultures
(Jameson, 1991), where the self is constituted through and within omnipres-
ent visual images, both static and moving. In the arts, media and culture,
‘high’ and ‘low’, death is prodded at, poked, interrogated, analysed, pon-
dered, laughed at, analysed and inserted into plot lines, newsreels, poetry,
plays, films, novels, short stories, photographs, paintings and sculpture, so
that images and representations of death, real or imaginary, are inserted
willy-nilly into our lives whenever we turn on the television, read a newspa-
per or glance at a billboard. We are immersed in a mediatised and visualised
culture that is saturated with images of death.
Literary and film theory shows that all this watching and reading is far
from being passive and is, rather, performative of the self (Bal, 2000). In
Western ‘looking cultures’ (Denzin, 1991), subjects possess a visual literacy
which, Denzin argues, has displaced literacy based on orality and print. It
is through looking that we construct our ‘postmodern selves’, which have
become signs of themselves, where media representations and everyday life
interact in ‘a double dramaturgical reflection’: our understanding of films
A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in Drag 159
and other visual images thus bleeds into our ‘everyday lives’. Literary the-
ory, brushing aside Denzin’s observation regarding the displacement of the
written text, explores how interactions between reader and text involve a
reader who writes the text as she reads and how she too is ‘written’ through
engagement with the story (Lodge, 2000; Iser, 2000). Denzin’s thesis sug-
gests that readers interpret written texts in a manner informed by their en-
gagement with the visual media, and so readers and lookers constitute a
sense of self through engagement with both types of texts. Similarly, Mieke
Bal (2000) suggests that narrative modes which combine visual images with
the thought processes of the viewer instigate a subjective recall of things
suppressed and one’s own life narrative, so that there is within ‘the mind’
no distinction between imagery and the spoken—they so intertwine and in-
terweave that an appreciation of a work of art may be felt viscerally and ar-
ticulated to the self-as-viewer through the media of both words and images.
Film theory draws from Lacan (1977) the perspective that we want the
gaze of the text to see us so that we know of our own presence. Thus, the
relationship with the text involves a two-way flow, and our subjectivity be-
comes ‘a text for the text’, where readers and texts are caught up in each
other and where, through suture, readers enter into or project themselves
into the text whilst simultaneously operating from the place of the gaze
(Silverman, 1988; 1996).4 It goes further: it examines how we do not sit pas-
sively in the cinema seat or on the living-room settee but project ourselves
into the screen, locating ourselves on the camera’s lens and entering our-
selves into the characters portrayed on the screen. When we watch or read
a whodunit, we can therefore identify with detective, murderer and corpse.
Our engagement with film and novel is performative: through interaction
with images and words, we construct a sense of self and learn how to be in
the world (Doane, 1988).
Living in image-saturated cultures (Jameson, 1991) in which we actively
invite dramatisations of mortality into our leisure hours, read avidly about
them and view images that bring them to life, we are therefore ourselves
produced as subjects who are cognisant of and interact with death. For
example, in the opening shots of the filmed version of Mankell’s Faceless
Killers, we see two elderly people, husband and wife, eating their supper,
laughing and talking. We firstly observe them through a window, from the
vantage point of their murderers; the camera then locates our vision within
the noose the murderer is carrying, and we see Mrs. Lovgren’s terrified face
as she sees the intruder. From our vantage point, we too are intruders. We
know what is to happen, and our bodies react viscerally (Marks, 2000).
The scene changes—we are taken into a restaurant where the detective,
Wallander, is having dinner with his daughter, and we relax with him but
struggle as he tries not to damage his family relationships. The next time we
see Mrs. Lovgren is as she dies in Wallander’s arms. We are both Wallander
holding her and Mrs. Lovgren as she dies. We breathe a breath that mimics
her last breath and feel the despair of the detective.
160 On Being At Work
However, the deaths we consume while sitting on our settees or cinema
seats or in bed before going to sleep are fictionalised deaths. In filmed ver-
sions of the novels, we see bodies lying on the floor, soon to be outlined
in chalk marks by crime officers (we have become schooled in such police
procedures), but these are the bodies, we know, of actors who picked them-
selves up, wiped off the fake blood and got on with the rest of their lives
after the camera stopped rolling. They are people, just like us, doing a job
of work. We can watch dramatisations of the murder of hundreds, if not
thousands, of fictional people and know that each body we see laid out will
get up and resume daily life. In reading the novels, we enter into the selves
of the victims, but we turn the page and are resuscitated back to life after
the imaginary death we have momentarily experienced. What the detective
genre therefore does is educate us into an experience of death followed by
life followed by death followed by life, over and over, until we finally stop
reading or viewing.
So, in absorbing the stories of violent deaths, we experience being the vic-
tim, the murderer and the detective, and we experience being the observer—
the eye of the camera observing everything except the vital clues that have
been deliberately withheld from us. This experiencing is not intellectual but
is comprehended and felt ‘with our entire bodily being, informed by the full
history and carnal knowledge of our acculturated sensorium’ (Sobchack,
2004:63). We move among the positions of the terrified victim, the calculat-
ing murderer and the confused but ultimately successful, albeit damaged,
detective. So, as viewer or reader of detective stories, we experience the
possibility of our own deaths. The untimeliness of a violent death portrayed
in detective stories, Sobchak (2004:240) writes, can thus be appreciated as
potentially mine. But, in knowing that we have survived the murderer’s at-
tack—indeed, in knowing that the actor who played the victim got up, took
off the ‘blood’ and had dinner—we know that death is put off until another
day. Some of our understanding of death is therefore Lazarus-like: we can
be killed and we can rise up again, immediately, to be killed again the next
time we open the novel or turn on the television.
In such ways, through processes of projection and introjection of the sto-
ries in which we immerse ourselves, we experience death and put it behind
us until, that is, the next programme or the next chapter of the novel. At the
same time that we have experienced the situation of the corpse, we have pro-
jected ourselves into the position of the detective searching for the murderer
and often, especially in novels, into the place (mind) of the murderer. In
the quotation that opened this section, we find ourselves inside the terrified
mind of someone who is about to be murdered, and in the quotation that
follows below we are taken into the mind of the murderer. Very shortly after
this account, Mankell takes us into the mind of the detective, and with that
we are plummeted back into the world of organization and work. Through
the power of the image or the written word, we imagine that we know
something of what it is to take life and to be dead and the frustrations of the
A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in Drag 161
work that results from those twinned acts. Always, in the postmodern de-
tective story, we are located within organizations—they are an omnipresent
although hardly noticed aspect of the stories. Their taken-for-grantedness
is perhaps what makes the import of the whodunit so powerful: the images
work on our conscious minds while we remain hardly aware that they are
doing so. When we watch the detective film or read the book, we are not
escaping from the daily grind of the workplace but are taken back into it,
albeit while hardly noticing because we are more concerned with whodunit.
In that workplace, then, we experience our own murder, then rise back up
from it, to experience it again. It is through culture and its articulation in
the imagination that organization and death become imbricated. I turn now
to film and literary theory to develop the thesis that this experience articu-
lates that which is otherwise unspeakable: that organizations murder the
me-who-might-have-been.
The murderer:
In an hour her guests would arrive. Before then she would have to give
the man in the oven his food. He had been there for five days. Soon he
would be so weak that he wouldn’t be able to put up any resistance. . . .
She had not yet decided how she was going to kill him. There were
several possibilities, but she still had plenty of time. She would think
about what he had done and then resolve how he was supposed to die.
(Mankell, 2009:54–55)
This chapter has used the whodunit to explore our fascination with fictional
portrayals of death. I have argued that the location in organizations of the
postmodern detective illuminates the whodunit’s articulation of thoughts
and ideas that can be expressed only tangentially, through artefacts or prod-
ucts that symbolise what it is we cannot put into words. The thesis of this
chapter has been that the organization in demanding that we labour as zom-
bie-machines so limits opportunities for working on the project of the self
that it murders the selves who might have been. A regretful looking back at
one’s teens, with all their promises, hopes, aspirations and dreams, perhaps
comes closest to saying this unsayable thing, because we speak about death
only in terms of the biological ending of the body. However, there is so
much individuals could do, so many people they could be, if they were not
required, every working day, to constrain themselves within the straitjacket
of the particular function, task or identity required by the organization,
so there must be another form of death, one which is not biological but is
organizational. Organizational death is that murdering of the me’s-who-
might-have-been, selves perhaps with greater capacity for joy, wonder and
achievement, and of the production of things of beauty and of the mainte-
nance of family and community than can be expressed in bureaucratised,
clock-watching, rule-bound, profit-oriented production processes.
Now it might be objected that the form of the self I am outlining here lim-
its the possibilities of the self to those available within post- or late modern
capitalism. Work on the self is therefore limited to that which fulfils capital-
ism’s needs (Bauman, 2007). There is that possibility, of course, although
Foucault’s perspective is very different. He advocates a politics of pleasure,
one in which work on the self (as a work of art) is an end in itself. I will
return to his arguments, along with Butler’s more recent theorising about
166 On Being At Work
recognition, in the concluding chapter. For now, I will preface that discus-
sion by returning to Dollimore’s (2001) analysis of how death and desire
have been interwoven into the Western European psyche and to his argu-
ments concerning the disessentializing of the self as the only means by which
the dread fear of death can be put aside, if only for a short while. I will
suggest here that his advocacy of means of dissolving the ego can illuminate
further the distinction between zombie-machine and human.
• With the left hand, place the ends of the plastic and metal ribbons
around the end of a spinner, and then press a button on the footboard
with the left foot to spin the ribbons around the spinner until they
catch;
• With the right hand, lift a piece of wire, place it on the metal ribbon
(which is much narrower than the plastic ribbon which will eventually
encase it), lower an arm of the machine, and double-click with right
foot so that an electrical current seals the wire to the plastic ribbon;
• Repeat with a piece of wire to the left;
• Click left-foot button to roll further ribbon around the spool, holding
it with the left hand to ensure that it takes shape properly;
• Almost immediately, lift the red-hot sealer with the right hand, taking
care to move the left hand just in time to avoid burning your thumb
instead of sealing the wires;
• With the right arm, move another arm of the machine across to free the
new capacitor so that it slides down into an awaiting tray, and at the
same time click a counter with the left hand;
• Repeat 2,400 times a day for five days so as to earn £12 for the week’s
wages.
With practice, you could establish a rhythm: move right arm, move right
foot, move left arm, move right foot, and so on and so on. One of the fas-
cinating things was that, despite the noise and the always-present danger
of burning one’s thumb (the smell was very similar to roasting pork), we
could somehow, sometimes become absent from our bodies, and time would
pass without our having any awareness of it. The evidence for this was the
counter: we watched them anxiously to check we were keeping up sufficient
speed to earn a living wage, and sometimes a few hundred suddenly seemed
to have been added to the count. The clock would show that 20, 30 or more
minutes had passed without our having any conscious awareness of having
been there, as an embodied person making those components.
This is one aspect of what I think Dollimore is referring to when he
uses the term ‘disessentializing’. One is alive but is absent to one’s self; the
ego disappears, and in its place there is the calm of the grave, all fear of
168 On Being At Work
death forgotten because the ego that experienced that fear has ceased, for a
short time, to exist. However, that this absence from the self was instigated
through becoming the ultimate zombie-machine, where the dexterity of the
human animal melded with the machine so that maximum efficiency was
obtained, suggests that Dollimore’s thesis will help flesh out the distinc-
tion between zombie-machine and human. Marx’s thesis on alienation, read
through the lens Dollimore offers, will assist in this exploration.
I was introduced to Marx’s theory of alienation as an undergraduate
a few years after working in this factory, and it seemed to me to capture
that experience of making capacitors, where forgetting the self for a short
while was a bonus because it meant not having been consciously aware of
the passing of the 20, 30 or 40 minutes of tedium in the noise and dirt of
the factory. This is a thesis outlined by the young Karl Marx (1988) who,
in his 26th year, wrote the scraps that remain of the 1844 Manuscripts.
He outlined a theory of a subject alienated by, from and within work, one
whose mirror image is the self that could and should emerge through work.
Work should be productive of a radiant self constituted through crafting of
objects within an aesthetically pleasing physical location and a strong social
network. In 1911 the then-55-year-old Frederic Winslow Taylor published
The Principles of Scientific Management, which put what seems to have
been the final nail in the coffin of the implicit dream in the 1844 Manu-
scripts. Marx’s thesis on alienation haunts the text you are reading now. It
is time to acknowledge it openly.
Marx wrote that the human is alienated from the product s/he makes, from
him/herself, from his/her ‘species being’ and from his/her fellow (wo)men.
I will start with Marx’s exploration of alienation from ‘species being’,
which is in many ways the most difficult part of his discussion but which
is easier to understand if one thinks of a cow chewing the cud or grazing
in the field all day. The cow exists only to exist; it labours only to con-
tinue being alive. It has no consciousness (so far as we are aware) over and
above the need to continue chewing and grazing. It has no ‘conscious life-
activity’ (Marx, 1988:76). The human, in contrast, is a species being that
is conscious of its own existence: a human can ponder itself as if it were an
object and so is a ‘Conscious Being’ (76). (Wo)Man does not exist in isola-
tion from other people but is an active participant in the species that is the
human animal (77) and so contributes to the sustenance of humankind as
a whole (77). S/he goes beyond his/her own immediate physical needs so as
to contribute to the greater good, producing ‘the whole of nature’ (77). S/he
‘forms things in accordance with the laws of beauty’ (77). However, under
capitalism, (wo)man’s life activity is reduced to a means to staying alive and
no more—s/he becomes like the cow, working only to sustain physical exis-
tence. S/he moves but does not think or create. S/he exists only to exist and
so, rather than contributing to mankind or community, focuses only on the
means for his/her own immediate sustenance. S/he is thus estranged from
his/her species being.
A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in Drag 169
Further, under capitalist conditions, workers are alienated both from the
products they produce and from themselves as producers of that product.
The products they make are whipped away from them to be sold elsewhere.
The worker also ‘must sell himself and his human identity’ (1988:25) in
order to survive. Workers thus ‘sink . . . to the level of a commodity’ (69), a
commodity that they themselves produce through their labour and which
is itself sold. This commoditised self, like any other commodity produced
through labour, is ‘the objectification of labor’ (71); that is, the object in which
work is ‘congealed’ or in which immaterial practices become material—real,
physical objects. In the factory, blindly producing capacitors, we were not
allowed to talk to each other and had to have permission to go to the toilet.
We were thus infantilised but, more than this as Marx explains, we existed
only as extensions of machines that made meaningless products. We moved
our hands, arms and feet, but our minds were disengaged, and the capacitors
that rolled down into the collecting trays were taken away—alien objects
that belonged to the employer. Our ‘inner worlds’ were impoverished, as
the work required no thought, skill or imagination, and yet we were so
busily occupied in such very mundane activity that we could not produce
anything that seemed meaningful or that would contribute to the good of
the community. Yet we could not stop producing the capacitors, one after
the other, 2,400 each day, 12,000 each week. The machine governed all our
movements, with those damned capacitors dictating how we sat, thought
and behaved. They ‘exist[ed] outside [me], independently, as something alien
to [me]’ and became ‘a power on its own confronting [me]’ (72). Each of
us had ‘become . . . a slave of his object’ (72). This could occur because the
only means of earning a living, of maintaining ourselves as physical subjects,
was through paid employment of this kind, but it was only through being
physical subjects that we could be workers: to be a subject, I must labour; to
be a labourer I must be a subject who can labour (73).
Further, in the act of doing the work itself, workers estrange themselves
from themselves. First, because the worker is him/herself one of the products
that s/he makes and all products s/he makes are owned by someone else, s/he
is estranged from herself. Second, because labour is external to the worker, a
form of activity that is imposed upon him/her and which makes him/her feel
‘outside himself’, the I becomes an object just doing the mundane activities
it has been told to do. ‘The worker therefore only feels himself outside his
work, and in his work feels outside himself’ (74). The body sitting at the
machine making capacitors had no separate existence from the machine:
it was a labouring body sans mind, sans motivation, sans a sense of being
human. There was no me but a body to which I ‘returned’ at the end of the
day. However, what or who was this me to which I returned? In Marx’s
words (1988:74), ‘man (the worker) no longer feels himself to be freely
active in any but his animal functions—eating, drinking, procreating, or
at most in his dwelling and in dressing-up, etc; and in his human functions
he no longer feels himself to be anything but an animal. What is animal
170 On Being At Work
becomes human and what is human becomes animal’ (74). That is, eat-
ing, drinking and procreating become the acts of animals because they are
undertaken only to sustain the self as a labourer. This is self-estrangement,
because capitalism takes over the life-world of the worker.
Finally, it follows that (wo)man is estranged from (wo)man. The people
with whom one works become no more than fellow cogs in the machine.
As people are reduced to working only so as to sustain the physical body,
Marx argued that work becomes something to be shunned ‘like the plague’
(74) when we do not have to do it. Sitting at the machine, churning out
capacitors, we counted out the hours and minutes before we were free to
leave for the day. Those odd moments when we were absent to ourselves,
when ego had ceased to exist and the body performed the required duties
as an extension of the machine, were times of blessed relief. In the terms of
the arguments in this book, we were pure zombie-machines, with no invest-
ment in the products we were making, no opportunity to work on the self
as anything other than an extension of the machine; no interaction with
others save for supervisors who treated us like schoolchildren; and no sense
of making a contribution to the good of humankind. We worked solely to
earn money to pay the rent, buy food and clothing, pay for heating, raise
our children and, if there was anything left over, go out one or two evenings
a week in search of entertainment. There were no dreams of the me’s we
might become: the future stretched out in front of us, as attachments to
machines who laboured to contribute to the household budget.
However, the zombie-machine is not disessentialized, in Dollimore’s
terms, because, although it escapes temporarily from its mundane existence
as it forgets its own existence, it is a self whose humanity has been stripped
away.
There is an alternative possibility for disessentializing the self through
one’s work, but this requires that work be undertaken differently (that is, as
work rather than labour). Marx regarded work as ‘satisfaction of a need’
(74), a need which goes far beyond the mere sustenance of the physical
body. This need is that of expressing one’s self through one’s work, of con-
tributing to the community and living as a social being. This is alienated
work turned on its head; it is a model of what our jobs should be like. It in-
volves work in which we can invest ourselves with pride: the objects that we
make attest to who we are, and we invest ourselves in them. When I look at
this book, for example, whatever others may say about it, I will be proud to
have written a book—I will have invested myself in it, and I am happy to see
that self looking back at me. We therefore can constitute ourselves as human
in the making of products and services that allow us to use our talents and
skills in the best possible way, in a social environment in which the human
can flourish. Engagement with our colleagues, friends, customers, clients
and managers, recognition from them of our skills in making bread, grow-
ing crops, devising art works, caring for children, cleaning toilets, not under
the watchful eye of managers but in a shared endeavour in which each gives
A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in Drag 171
what s/he can—that is the sort of utopian work space Marx seemed to envis-
age. Through such labour, we would contribute to culture, society and the
welfare of all. Conscious of ourselves as humans, we would also be aware of
and recognize all the frailties that accompany membership in such a species.
Another form of disessentializing of the self would be possible here. It
is one that people sometimes talk of when they discuss their hobbies or lei-
sure pursuits, that is, the things they want to do and in which they develop
skills different from those they must use in their paid jobs. They talk of, say,
painting and ‘not noticing the time go by’ or ‘forgetting about everything
because I got so absorbed’. This form of forgetting is another way in which
one becomes disessentialized, if only for a fleeting time. If it were to occur
in the (utopian) workplace because of the pleasure in making the object or
delivering the service, then the disappearance of the ego would not be of
the sort that reduces one to a zombie-machine, allowing one to forget not
only the immanence of one’s mortality but also the dire circumstances of life
itself. It would be one in which the dread knowledge of one’s own mortality
ceased for a while as the ego dissolved, and the product or service in which
one was absorbed could be all the better for that forgetting, because one’s
talents would be set free. As Pirsig argued, in Zen and the Art of Motorcycle
Maintenance (1999), rather than a rider driving a motor bike on which he
had painstakingly worked, rider and machine become one—motor bike in
motion.
It does not seem likely that many people would say that they dream of
jobs in which they become so absorbed in their work that they forget them-
selves; we articulate our desires in other ways, perhaps because this sort
of language is not easily available to us. So, we can say that we dream of
being an astronaut or a chef or a cake baker, and with those aspirations we
dream of the people we would be while working in those jobs. We cannot
say, ‘I want a job where I can forget myself for hours at a time’. However, I
suggest that this form of forgetting the self is an aspect of being human, of
being freed to work on the self through a job that allows one’s expression
of one’s skills and talents. When the zombie-machine forgets itself while,
say, making capacitors, it escapes not only from the awful knowledge of its
own inevitable demise but also from a working life that presses down on the
self. On the other hand, when the human forgets itself through its work, it
escapes only from the awfulness of the ego; its return to its ‘self’, to being
essentialized, is to a place where pleasure accompanies the self who works.
To conclude: this chapter has focused on death and has used the who-
dunit to argue that our fascination with death articulates a knowledge that
we cannot otherwise put into words: that organizations murder our dreams,
all the me’s-I-might-have-been. Jonathon Dollimore’s thesis on death al-
lowed me to bring in the young Marx’s theory of alienation, which haunts
this book. I have argued that the zombie-machine can sometimes become
disessentialized and escape from the terrible knowledge of its own mortality
but that dissolution of the ego reduces it to a machine that must return to a
172 On Being At Work
consciousness of itself as a zombie-machine. The human, however, would be
working in a job that not only allowed work on the self, on the constitution
of a desired identity, but also would allow the self to become unaware of
itself and so forget its inevitable demise because of the sheer pleasure taken
in its tasks. That is, work should be enjoyable and should give a sense of
achievement. The ‘work of art’ that Foucault spoke of, that which we are
ideally forever constituting, could thus be one that is achieved through one’s
work.
There are some (to my mind) crass arguments in contemporary leadership
studies which recommend that leaders become ‘servant leaders’, devoted
to ensuring that staff can contribute their best efforts to the organization.
There are perhaps elements of what I am arguing for in this chapter in that
body of work. However, the difference is the context. Servant leaders work
in organizations whose aims are those of maximising return for sharehold-
ers or, in public-sector organizations, the government or community. Ser-
vant leadership, in such a context, remains exploitative, another attempt at
securing more wholehearted commitment (and thus hard work) from staff.
What I am imagining is a very different organizational context, in which
other objectives are subordinate to the major priority of the flourishing of
staff.
Can death be used as a metaphor for what is not biological death? Patrick
Reedy and Mark Learmonth’s (2011) Heideggerian reading of death and or-
ganizations suggest it should not be: I may take away its full horror and let
organizations off the hook of their ethical responsibilities, while at the same
time so exaggerating my arguments that they lose their force. To answer
this question, I return to Butler’s (1997) reference to the need sometimes for
‘hyperbolic theory’, one that overstates its case for a reason. Organizations
have certainly been complicit in atrocities which caused death and suffering
for millions of human beings (Bauman, 1989), and the sort of suffering I am
exploring in this book is nowhere akin to the depths of barbarity of which
organizations are capable. However, the identity politics of the past 40 years
has shown that forms of suffering exist that were not recognised until a
language emerged that allowed labels to be put to them and thus an activist
politics to develop. I am attempting in this book to identify another form
of suffering for which we currently lack labels. Feminism, queer theory,
postcolonial and crip theories are all testament to the power of language
to inform politics, change the symbolic order and thus have real, positive
impacts on people’s lives. An earlier politics based on class and grounded
in Marxist theory focused on working lives but eventually came to little
in the West, perhaps because, as Lacan (2007) observed, it would have
done no more than replace one master with another. Feminism challenged
A Hyperbolic Theory, a Theory in Drag 173
patriarchy, queer theory heteronormativity, and postcolonial theory empire,
and it seems to me that we need a new language, beyond that of control and
resistance, that allows us to challenge what organizations do to the people
who work in/for them, including those of the relatively privileged people
of ‘the West’. I have used the terms ‘murder’ and ‘death’ because of their
power to arrest attention. I have used the detective because s/he combines
in the same symbol both organization (the employer) and death (detectives’
job is to deal with death and find murderers), and so the whodunit provides
a bridge that links death and organizations. Furthermore, this bridge is a
person who is ground down by unnecessary organizational limitations that
add to the burdens of the messiness of everyday life. I am not arguing for
the possibilities of a Utopia where all suffering disappears, only for a means
of reducing the strains upon lives that will always be in many ways less than
perfect.
This page intentionally left blank
Conclusion: From Poverty of
Aspiration to a Politicised, Ethical
Me-I-Might-Become?
The thesis of this book is that in late capitalist or postmodern cultures where
the self has become a project to be worked on, we look to our jobs as a
means of constituting the selves we aspire to be. Organizations, however,
so limit the possibilities for being that the most many of us can achieve is a
shade of the selves that might have been, a ghost of a life that has never been
lived. Organizations therefore murder the selves that might have been. This
is a hyperbolic theory, a thesis in drag, as Butler would have it, which uses
the language of violent death as a political manoeuvre.
I have used a sociocultural philosophical approach that analyses the
working-life stories of individuals through the lens of Judith Butler’s theo-
retical perspective, treating the life stories as if they were lay philosophies of
work (Introduction). The argument can be summarised as follows. Organi-
zations desire staff who are zombie-machines, that is, intelligent machines
totally focused on achieving organizational aims and objectives and thus
lacking any agency beyond that required in contributing to organizational
goals (Introduction). Such staff would be somewhat less than human and,
it follows, would be and are devoid of certain rights that attach to being
human. Julie showed us in Chapter One that individuals, unsurprisingly,
approach work with aims and desires different from those of their employ-
ers. Among the outcomes we desire from our work is the constitution of
a desired self or selves, selves we could become through our jobs. Inher-
ent in aspirations for opportunities to work on the self is a theory of the
self as human. Julie’s ideas, illustrated further by Alex’s working life story
(Chapter Four), suggest that labour and work should be distinguished from
each other. Labour involves doing the tasks required by management but,
as it excludes anything that serves in the constitution of the self, labour is
what is undertaken by zombie-machines. Work involves those activities,
often over and above the tasks required of the zombie-machine, that facili-
tate constitution of selves that are fully human. Alex illuminated how the
friends and colleagues with whom we work, rather than management or the
organization, contribute that recognition which is vital in the constitution
of selves.
176 Conclusion
Frank, the boss, demonstrated (in Chapter Two) the difficulty for man-
agers of granting recognition to employees as anything other than zom-
bie-machines, because his thesis is of a selfhood that is so intertwined
with the organization that the self is no more than a constantly labour-
ing, managerial zombie-machine. Just as the lord, in Hegel’s dialectic,
does not seek recognition from the bondsman, so Frank does not look
to staff for recognition, although he requires that staff labour as zombie-
machines in order that he can demonstrate to himself and others that he
is a manager. At the same time, if his staff are perfect zombie-machines
then Frank’s psyche is challenged. The manager is on the horns of an
impossible psychic dilemma. Shakeel (Chapter Three) blurs the bound-
ary between managers and staff, because he shows how staff speak in the
idiom of management, have firm ideas of how work should be carried
out and are frustrated by managers who are seen as inefficient intruders
into working space. Staff therefore cannot grant recognition to managers
because they do not recognise managers as anything but imposters who
disrupt the efficient flow of work. Although staff of necessity give the
impression that they are working like zombie-machines (and thus, in their
own perception, inefficiently), the impression is superficial, unstable and
abandoned whenever possible. Managerial and staff ‘realities’ are so dif-
ferent that they cannot be said to occupy the same space. An implication
of Shakeel’s account is that he, like Alex, turns to colleagues and friends
for recognition of the self as human. Such a recognition is impossible
outside the terms of gender; gender is compulsory but also debilitating.
Kara and Saul (Chapter Five) showed how fluid are gendered identities
and how the self that is lost in the doing of its work escapes from the
prisonhouse of gendered identity. Reparative organizational work is then
undertaken, in this case not by management but by students (‘customers’),
to line up gendered subjects with biological bodies. This causes shock and
trauma to organizational subjects freed, for a time, from the constraints
of gender, but time and again they are surprised back into them. I sug-
gested that the labouring zombie-machine has to conform to traditional
gender categories, whereas work on the self incorporates opportunities for
freedom from the trauma of gender. These explorations of the limitations
imposed on constituting aspired-to working selves were brought together
in Chapter Six, where theories of death, the detective novel, and Marx’s
theory of alienation were used to argue that organizations murder the
me’s-that-might-have-been.
In summary, in late or postmodern capitalism, we look to our work for
a means of constituting an ideal(ised), aspired-to self, but organizations ne-
gate that aspiration. Staff find ways of escaping from organizations’ most
dire demand that they be reduced to less than human zombie-machines and
thus discover ways of constituting a sense of a workplace self that is human,
albeit one whose potential for being is so constrained that it is only a
shadow of the dreamed-of, aspired-to self. Organizations therefore murder
the me’s-that-might-have-been.
Conclusion 177
What I have not yet explored is who that desired, dreamed-of self might be.
Julie (Chapter One) suggested that her aspiration is to be freed through work:
work would give her a face to show to the world, and she would then be able
to go out and explore that world. Frank waits for a retirement from work that
will give him the time to do those things he has put aside so as to devote him-
self totally to his managerial labours. Shakeel has aspirations to be a writer
and become politically active, but labour gobbles up so much of his time that
those aspirations are left to wither on the vine of his dreams. Alex comes
closest to constituting the desired self of the glamorous, exciting professional
archaeologist, but the conditions of employment (short-term, temporary as-
signments without many employment rights) means she has to live much of
her life exasperated by administrative jobs that she loathes. As to Kara and
Saul, as academics they work in a profession whose members love their work
but are constantly frustrated by creeping managerialism, increasing admin-
istration and the impossibility of working on the aspired-to academic self
(Harding, Ford and Gough, 2010; Clarke, Knights and Jarvis, 2012).
But there is something narcissistic in our dreamed-of selves, and indeed
late or postmodern culture would appear to provide the terms in which our
dreams are focused on the ‘me’. Bauman (2007), as we saw in the Preface,
is perturbed that work on the self is devoted to constituting nothing but a
commodity to be sold to the highest bidder (see also Sennett, 2006). The
self that is constituted is also a product for one’s own consumption (in front
of the mirror, I ask myself do I look gorgeous/good enough?) and that of
others (have I constituted a self that my peers will value and which they can
use in positioning themselves—am I academic enough for students, manage-
rial enough for workers?) (Falk, 1994). This commodity that is the self is a
work-in-progress which staves off death—if I work hard enough to make my
body immune to illness and dying, I may live for a thousand years (Shilling,
1993). Although self-absorbed, this is a self that is positioned within nor-
mative requirements of how one should be, and so failure to constitute a
desired self can reduce one to a position of abjection. There is little of that
ecstatic, ek-static self that Marx dreamed of, whose self is caught up in giv-
ing to its society and taking from it only what it needs.
This is perhaps therefore another form of the murder-of-the-me’s that
might have been: that is, in late or postmodern capitalism, we have impover-
ished, deracinated aspirations of who we can be or what we might become.
Can we aspire to be something more? Foucault’s late work and Butler’s
recent work points to alternative possible selves.
Can we constitute workplace selves that are ethically alive and alert to a pol-
itics of microrevolutionary change that, while it would not challenge capi-
talism per se, could change the norms that govern workplace identities and
thus contribute to the flourishing of working selves? Marx (1988) hinted at
178 Conclusion
this self, as discussed in Chapter Six. For Marx, the communist workplace
should be a welcoming place that would facilitate workers’ contribution
to the greater good while they made aesthetically pleasing products. Those
objects would reflect an investment of a self that flourished through its la-
bours. Foucault’s question concerning why we should not turn ourselves
into works of art is redolent in some ways of Marx’s conception of a non-
alienated worker, although it is a question framed for the conditions of late
or postmodern capitalism rather than of Marx’s industrial capitalism. Both
theorists help us understand that one of the objects produced through work
is the self.
Where Marx conceived of persons with what we would now define as
homogeneous identities, Foucault distinguished between the subject and the
self, observing different forms of the subject emerging in different places:
‘The subject is not a substance but a form’, one that is
not primarily or always identical to itself. You do not have the same
type of relationship to yourself when you constitute yourself as a politi-
cal subject who goes to vote or speaks at a meeting and when you are
seeking to fulfil your desires in a sexual relationship. . . . In each case
one plays, one establishes a different type of relationship to oneself. And
it is precisely the historical constitution of these various forms of the
subject in relation to the games of truth which interests me. (Foucault,
1997a:290–291)
Marx could not conceive of a self that was not, within capitalism, itself
a commodity, but we have seen in this book how workplace subjects can
have a number of different relationships to themselves, in Foucault’s terms,
in that they can be at one time a less-than-human zombie-machine and at
another time lay claim to their humanity. Workplace selves (with the excep-
tion, it would seem, of the manager) can thus move between (more or less)
alienated and (more or less) non-alienated subject positions, or what I have
called the zombie-machine and the human. The question thus becomes one
of exploring how to expand the space of the latter. There has been limited
but promising work in management and organization studies drawing on
Foucault’s later work on aesthetics of existence, which offers ‘a movement
of hope, giving fresh meaning to political ideals that occupy a vital position
in contemporary political discourse and a way out from the confinements
of the new knowledge based enterprise’ (Barratt, 2008:525). Butler’s recent
work on ethics adds insights to Foucault’s thesis on constituting one’s self as
an ethical subject. Both thinkers work within the constraints of a capitalism
that is unlikely to be overturned by direct, revolutionary challenges. Their
work on ethics, when combined, can suggest how each one of us could
become a microrevolutionary (Gibson-Graham, 1996), doing what we can
within the conditions of possibility of capitalist workplaces to change those
conditions of possibility.
Conclusion 179
FOUCAULT AND AN AESTHETICS OF THE SELF
Those in power frame our understanding such that war becomes regarded
as justifiable on the grounds of national protection and the citizens of those
countries against which war is waged become understood as nonhuman.
Capitalism has so long framed our expectations of how organizations func-
tion that the capillary form of violence I have analysed in this book, the
murder of the me’s-that-might-have-been, is regarded as an everyday neces-
sity rather than the violence that it is.
Where Butler can work, in Frames of War, with visual images that proj-
ect very directly and without qualification the inhumanity of which she is
speaking, organization theorists have to work with words spoken from
within a discourse that has no language for the form of oppression I am
exploring in this book. If ‘framing presupposes decisions or practices that
leave substantial losses outside the frame’ (Butler, 2009:75), then we must
explore what is or cannot be said. The ways in which labour and work are
currently conceived do not allow everyday articulation of the possibilities
for a being at work that is positioned ‘outside the frame’. In other words,
I am extrapolating from Butler’s thesis to argue in favour of contesting the
182 Conclusion
‘ontological given’ of what being at work means and thus, like many authors
working in what we loosely call ‘critical management studies’, challenging
the normative framework in which governance of 21st-century organiza-
tions is located. It follows that the argument also involves a desire for a
language that allows articulation of the currently inarticulable. Hence the
hyperbolic choice of the terms ‘death’ and ‘murder’.
Unsurprisingly, given the influence of Foucault on Butler’s work, we see
here similarities in his arguments and hers: we need firstly to identify how
our thinking and talking are constrained to what is available within domi-
nant discourses, so as, secondly, to break free of the chains in which they
have bound our thoughts and speech.
Where Butler differs markedly from Foucault is in the final chapter of
Frames of War, when she explores the challenge of nonviolence. Butler’s
argument throughout that book follows a neo-Buddhist path: we are all ek-
statically constituted in relation with others and so are inextricably bound
up with others; we cannot exist and cannot have an identity without oth-
ers, so that the harm I do to another is harm done to myself. We inhabit
‘animated fields of differences’ wherein the social ontology of the subject is
one that affects and is affected by another, such that ‘ “the subject” ’ is less a
discrete substance than an active and transitive set of interrelations’ (147).
Our ontological interrelation with others is prior to any calculation of how
that interrelation should work.
From this flows an ethical stance towards the other.
However, Butler cautions against any easy presumption of a moral self
that can be turned towards the other. We are, each of us, ‘mired in violence’,
that is, in the violence that formed us and a violence that inhabits us. First,
we are all at least partially formed through violence, because against our
will we must conform to norms that confer intelligibility or recognisability
(167). Although we are born within a matrix of power, the repetition inher-
ent within performativity means that we do not have to repeat the violence
of our formation, even though we continue to be assaulted by relations we
never chose and that ‘are impingements that are injurious, acting forcibly
on the body in ways that provoke rage’ (171). Indeed, we must ‘assume
responsibility for living a life that contests the determining power of that
production’ (170) because we are ‘mired in violence’. Just as Foucault ar-
gues that we must recognise our fascist desires, Butler, drawing on Levinas
and Melanie Klein, advises the need to recognise that to be a subject is to
acknowledge that one is ‘injured, rageful, disposed to violent retribution
and nevertheless struggles against that action’ (171). We must acknowledge
that we are, even those of us who are ostensibly peaceable, pervaded by ag-
gression. We must recognise the injuries that we ourselves cause others and
engage in an active struggle against our own aggression, because
To say that we have ‘needs’ is thus to say that who we ‘are’ involves an
invariable and reiterated struggle of dependency and separation, and
Conclusion 183
does not merely designate a stage of childhood to be surmounted. It is
not just ‘one’s own’ struggle or the apparent struggle of ‘another’ but
precisely the dehiscence at the basis of the ‘we’, the condition under
which we are passionately bound together: ragefully, desirously, mur-
derously, lovingly. (183)
Moral responsibility thus includes protection of the other from one’s own
aggression. This involves the fallible practice of trying to attend to the pre-
cariousness of life (177) and being wary of moral sadism, which is a form of
persecution that passes itself off as virtue (177).
Although Butler is here referring to a political stance that preaches the
necessity of war in order to secure peace, I suggest that ‘moral sadism’ can
be applied to understanding organizations. Where Butler is concerned with
living and dying, I am concerned with how we define ‘life’ in organizations
and how that life is denied when subjects are reduced to zombie-machines.
The attempt to understand ‘the boss’ in Chapter Two shows how manag-
ers are so caught up in dominant organizational discourses of the need to
devote oneself singularly and wholeheartedly to the organization that they
cannot separate themselves from ‘the organization’. I have argued previ-
ously (Harding, 2003) that management textbooks and thus management
degrees are complicit in constituting such a managerial subject position. In
the language that Butler now provides us with, one must charge business
schools, management textbooks and the discourses of managerialism that
circulate more broadly as a form of moral sadism. That is, they preach the
virtue of profits and duty to shareholders and subordinate all other claims
beneath those overarching impositions, arguing that we will all benefit if we
serve the needs of profit making.
If so, then we work within conditions of moral sadism. How does one
care for one’s self and others in such a context? The art of caring for the
self, in Foucault’s terms, would involve, in Butler’s terms, ‘an understand-
ing of the possibility of one’s own violent actions in relation to those lives
to which one is bound, including those whom one never chose and never
knew’ (179). As with Foucault, this involves being alive to understanding
the ways in which we have been educated to see the world, that is, how our
understanding of it has been framed. This requires the hugely difficult task
of challenging the very terms through which we have learned to think and to
act. We must educate ourselves so that we can challenge the frames through
which representations are given to us.
CONCILIATION
Foucault and Butler combined lead us to ethical practices in which we (i) identify
how we are subjected and subjectified by dominant moral discourses and
how our responses are framed so that the breadth of our thinking and
184 Conclusion
understanding is constrained within narrow limits; (ii) find ways of moving
beyond those discourses into more ethical positions; (iii) work on the self
to identify and acknowledge the meanness and nastiness within the self and
to find ways of limiting its effect on others but abjuring any claim to have
rid the self of its dark side; (iv) work on the self to change the terms within
which one works and acts and so to reach out to others ethically.
These are ethical practices of the individual who is always given over to
others. To practice such techniques of the self would be to constitute selves
that perhaps surpass those of which we had previously dreamed. It is a
political action because such a self refuses the terms within which organiza-
tions seek to subjectify us and insists on the right to constitute selves that are
nourished and can flourish through our work.
This is where I struggle. In this chapter, I have singled out Frank, the
boss, to illuminate the absence of ethics in management. If the overall aim
is to develop an ethics of organizations in which each person can flour-
ish, constituting selves that perhaps surpass those of which they/we had
dreamed, then the most obvious target for change would be managers, and
perhaps we could reach them through our teaching and our writing. But
how would a Shakeel, a Julie, an Alex, a Kara and a Saul respond to these
ideas, and how could or would they work on themselves? Would they be
able, given the presumptions of hierarchy and the pressures on them to be
zombie-machines, to educate their managers? I must include myself in this
list: how do I challenge those discourses of the moral codes to which I cling
and move towards more ethical practices of the self? How could I sustain
them when I feel tired and grumpy and want to escape from the world and
back into my books?
For now, perhaps our focus should be on the first two of the steps out-
lined here, that is, identifying and changing or moving beyond the orga-
nizational discourses that inhibit our flourishing. That is what this book
has aimed to do: to develop a hyperbolic theory that uses the language of
murder and death to introduce different ways of articulating the harm that
organizations do when they inhibit the flourishing of their staff.
Appendix
Many versions of the stories of Oedipus and his family would have circu-
lated in Athens, passed on by word of mouth and woven into presentations
for the theatre. The version with which we are most familiar is that given by
Sophocles,1 who presents the story in three plays written many years apart.
Oedipus is the son of Laius and Jocasta, king and queen of Thebes. Follow-
ing a prophecy that the boy will kill his father, the parents charge a shepherd
with the killing of their infant son. The shepherd cannot go through with the
deed and passes the child to another shepherd, who takes him to Corinth,
where the childless king and queen adopt him. Told by the Oracle at Delphi
that he, Oedipus, now a grown man, will kill his father and marry his
mother, Oedipus decides he will avoid the curse that is on him by never re-
turning to Corinth. At a narrow pass on a mountain range, there is a violent
dispute over who has right of passage, and Oedipus kills the man who has
obstructed him. He later encounters the Sphinx. This monster is oppressing
the citizens of Thebes and will stop its tyranny only when someone answers
its riddle correctly. She asks Oedipus, as she has asked many others: what
is it that goes on four feet, three feet and two feet and is most feeble when
it walks on four? Oedipus’s answer is ‘man’: on all fours as a baby, on two
feet when grown, and on three (with the aid of a walking stick) in old age.2
The Sphinx throws herself to her death, and Oedipus’s reward is marriage to
Jocasta, the widowed queen. She and Oedipus rule happily for many years,
producing a family of two daughters, Antigone and Ismene, and two sons,
Eteocles and Polyneices. Eventually the fate that has been awaiting him all
along intercedes, and Oedipus discovers that the man he slew at the moun-
tain pass was his father and that he is married to his own mother. Jocasta
hangs herself, and Oedipus takes the long pins from her robe, puts out his
eyes and goes into exile with his daughters. Jocasta’s brother, Creon, as-
sumes the throne until his two nephews come of age, at which time there is
an agreement that the brothers, now under a curse from Oedipus, will share
the throne. Eteocles, taking his turn first, refuses to give up the throne to
his brother at the due time, and Polyneices summons an army from another
186 Appendix
city-state and sets out to attack Thebes. Oedipus’s curse is fulfilled because
in the ensuing battle the brothers kill each other.
It is at this point that The Antigone begins. Creon, returning to the throne,
dictates that Polyneices’s body shall not be buried. Antigone refuses to obey
this edict and twice sets out to scatter earth over the carcass. Discovered, ar-
rested and taken to Creon, she refuses to obey his law, and he condemns her
to the slow death of entombment in a cave. Creon’s son, Haemon, betrothed
to Antigone and heartbroken, begs for her freedom, and eventually Creon
cedes to his son’s wishes. He has delayed too long, for when they get to the
cave they find the body of Antigone swinging from the cloth she has used
to hang herself. Haemon, the wretched lover, kills himself, and, hearing the
news, so does his mother, Creon’s wife. Creon is himself soon to die.
Notes
1. See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Publishers_Weekly_list_of_bestselling_
novels_in_the_United_States_in_the_2000s#2008.5B4.5D (accessed 10 August
2010).
2. See http://www.yellowbird.se/index.php?option=com_seyret&task=videodire
ctlink&id=219&Itemid=4 (accessed 10 August 2010)
3. See http://www.dailyrecord.co.uk/news/uk-world-news/2007/06/03/rebus-
rebuff-78057-19237980/. (accessed 10 August 2010).
4. ‘Suture’ refers to procedures whereby cultural texts confer subjectivity upon
their viewers or readers (Silverman, 1988:195).
APPENDIX
1. I have used the version introduced by Knox and translated by Fagles (1982).
2. I cannot resist quoting from Muriel Rukeyser, ‘Myth’ (in Cavarero, 2005:49):
Long after, Oedipus, old and blinded, walked the roads. He smelled a fa-
miliar smell. It was the Sphinx.
Oedipus said, ‘I want to ask one question. Why didn’t I recognize my
mother?’
‘You gave the wrong answer,’ said the Sphinx.
‘But that was what made everything possible’, said Oedipus.
‘No’, she said, ‘When I asked, What walks on four legs in the morning, two
at noon, and three in the evening, you answered, Man. You didn’t say
anything about woman’.
‘When you say Man’, said Oedipus, ‘you include women too. Everyone
knows that’.
She said, ‘That’s what you think’.
References
Adler, S., Laney, J. and Packer, M. (1993) Managing women. Buckingham: Oxford
University Press.
Alvesson, M. (2003) Beyond neopositivists, romantics, and localists: A reflexive ap-
proach to interviews in organizational research. Academy of Management Re-
view, 28:1, 13–33.
Alvesson, M., Ashcraft, K. and Thomas, R. (2008) Identity matters. Organization,
15:1, 5–28.
Alvesson, M. and du Billing, Y. (1992) Gender and organization: Towards a differ-
entiated understanding. Organization Studies, 13:1, 73–103.
Alvesson, M. and Skoldberg, K. (2009) Reflexive methodology. London: Sage.
Alvesson, M. and Willmott, H. (1996) Making sense of management: A critical in-
troduction. London: Sage.
Alvesson, M. and Willmott, H. (2002) Identity regulation as organizational con-
trol: Producing the appropriate individual. Journal of Management Studies, 39:5,
619–644.
Anderson, B. (2010) Migration, immigration controls and the fashioning of precari-
ous workers. Work, Employment and Society, 24:2, 300–317.
Anderson-Gough, F., Grey, C. and Robson, K. (2000) In the name of the client:
The service ethic in two professional services firms. Human Relations, 53:9,
1151–1174.
Andrew, A. and Montague, J. (1998) Women’s friendship at work. Women’s Studies
International Forum, 21:4, 355–361.
Anouilh, J. 1951/2000. Antigone. London: Methuen.
Bal, M. (2000) Visual narrativity. In G. Coulter-Smith (Ed.), The visual-narrative matrix:
Interdisciplinary collisions and collusions, 7–16. Southampton: Southampton
Institute.
Barratt, E. (2008) The later Foucault in organization and management studies.
Human Relations, 61:4, 515–537.
Barry, J., Berg, E. and Chandler, J. (2006) Academic shape shifting: Gender, manage-
ment and identities in Sweden and England. Organization, 13:2, 275–298.
Barzilai, S. (1999) Lacan and the matter of origins. Stanford, CA: Stanford Univer-
sity Press.
Bass, B.M. and Steidlmeier, P. (1999) Ethics, character and authentic transforma-
tional leadership behavior. Leadership Quarterly, 10:2, 181–217.
Baudrillard, J. (1976/1993) Symbolic exchange and death. London: Sage.
Bauman, Z. (1989) Modernity and the Holocaust. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bauman, Z. (1992) Mortality, immortality and other life strategies. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Bauman, Z. (2007) Consuming life. Cambridge: Polity Press.
190 References
Bell, E. (2008) Reading management and organization in film. Basingstoke: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Benjamin, J. (1988) The bonds of love: Psychoanalysis, feminism and the problem of
domination. New York: Pantheon.
Benjamin, J. (1995) Like subjects, love objects: Essays on recognition and sexual
difference. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Benjamin, J. (1998) Shadow of the other: Intersubjectivity and gender in psycho-
analysis. London: Routledge.
Benn, S.I. and Gaus, G.F. (1983) The public and the private: Concepts and action.
In S.I. Benn and G.F. Gaus (Eds.), Public and private in social life, 3–30. London:
Croom Helm.
Benschop, Y. and Doorewaard, H. (1998) Covered by equality: The gendered sub-
text of organizations. Organization Studies, 19:5, 787–805.
Bernauer, J. and Mahon, J. (1994) The ethics of Michel Foucault. In G. Gutting
(Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Foucault, 141–158. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Bernstein, J.M. (2010) ‘The celestial Antigone, the most resplendent figure ever to
have appeared on earth’: Hegel’s feminism. In F. Söderbäck (Ed.), Feminist read-
ings of Antigone, 111–132. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Blundell, S. (1995) Women in ancient Greece. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Bollas, C. (1989) The shadow of the object: Psychoanalysis of the unthought known.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Bollas, C. (1993) Being a character: Psychoanalysis and self experience. London:
Routledge.
Bollas, C. (1995) Cracking up: The work of unconscious experience. London:
Routledge.
Borneman, J. (1996) Until death do us part: Marriage/death in anthropological dis-
course. American Ethnologist, 23:2, 215–235.
Bowring, M.A. (2004) Resistance is not futile: Liberating Captain Janeway from the
masculine-feminine dualism of leadership. Gender, Work and Organization, 11,
381–405.
Braverman, H. (1974) Labor and monopoly capital. The degradation of work in the
twentieth century. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Brecht, B. (1984) Antigone. In a version by Bertolt Brecht. Trans. J. Malina. New
York: Applause Theatre and Cinema Books.
Brennan, T. (1993) History after Lacan. London: Routledge.
Brewis, J. (2005) Signing my life away? Researching sex and organization. Organi-
zation, 12:4, 493–510.
Brewis, J., Hampton, M.P. and Linstead, S. (1997) Unpacking Priscilla: Subjectivity
and identity in the organization of gendered appearance. Human Relations, 50,
1275–1304.
Brocklehurst, M., Grey, C. and Sturdy, A. (2009) Management: The work that dares
not speak its name. Management Learning, 41:1, 7–19.
Browder, G. (2003) Perpetrator character and motivation: An emerging consensus.
Holocaust and Genocide Studies, 17:3, 480–497.
Budgeon, S. and Roseneil, S. (2004) Editors’ Introduction: Beyond the conventional
family. Current Sociology, 52:2, 127–134.
Burrell, G. (1984) Sex and organizational analysis. Organization Studies, 5, 97–118.
Burrell, G. (1988a) Modernism, postmodernism and organizational analysis 2: The
contribution of Michel Foucault. Organization Studies, 9, 221–235.
Burrell, G. (1988b) Modernism, postmodernism and organizational analysis: The
contribution of Michel Foucault. In A. McKinlay and K.E. Starkey (Eds.),
Foucault, Management and Organization Theory, 14–28. London: Sage.
References 191
Burrell, G. (1997) Pandemonium: Towards a retro-organization theory. London: Sage.
Burrell, G. and Morgan, G. (1979) Sociological paradigms and organizational anal-
ysis. London: Heinemann.
Butler, J. (1990) Gender trouble. London: Routledge, Chapman and Hall.
Butler, J. (1993) Bodies that matter. New York: Routledge.
Butler, J. (1997) The psychic life of power. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Butler, J. (2000) Antigone’s claim. New York: Columbia University Press.
Butler, J. (2002) Capacity. In S.M. Barber and D.L. Clark (Eds.), Regarding Sedgwick,
109–120. London: Routledge.
Butler, J. (2004) Precarious lives. New York: Verso.
Butler, J. (2004) Undoing gender. New York: Routledge.
Butler, J. (2005) Giving an account of oneself. New York: Fordham University Press.
Butler, J. (2009) Frames of war. New York: Verso.
Cabantous, L. and Gond, J-P. (2011) Rational decision making as performa-
tive praxis: Explaining rationality’s éternel retour. Organization Science, 22:3,
573–586.
Cabantous, L., Gond, J.-P. and Johnson-Cramer, M. (2010) Decision theory as
practice: Crafting rationality in organizations. Organization Studies, 31:11,
1531–1566.
Calas, M.B. and Smircich, L. (1991) Voicing seduction to silence leadership. Orga-
nization Studies, 12:4, 567–602.
Calas, M.B. and Smircich, L. (1992) Re-writing gender into organizational theoriz-
ing: Directions from feminist perspectives. In M. Reed and M. Hughes (Eds.),
Rethinking organization: New directions in organization theory and analysis,
227–253. London:Sage.
Carr, A. and Lapp, C. (2005) Wanted for breaking and entering organizational sys-
tems in complexity: Eros and Thanatos. Emergence: Complexity and Organiza-
tion, 7:3–4, 43–52.
Carr, A. and Lapp, C. (2006) Leadership is a matter of life and death. London:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Cavarero, A. (2005) For more than one voice. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Chadwick, O. (1990) The secularisation of the European mind in the nineteenth
century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chambers, D. (2006) New social ties. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Chandler, J., Barry, J. and Clark, H. (2002) Stressing academe: The wear and tear of
the New Public Management. Human Relations, 55:9, 1051–1069.
Chanter, T. (2010) The performative politics and rebirth of Antigone in ancient
Greece and modern South Africa. In F. Söderbäck (Ed.), Feminist readings of
Antigone, 83–98. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Chia, R. (1994) Decision: A deconstructive analysis. Journal of Management Stud-
ies, 31, 781–806.
Chia, R. (1995) From modern to postmodern organizational analysis. Organization
Studies, 16, 579–604.
Chia, R. (2000) Discourse analysis as organizational analysis. Organization, 7,
513–518.
Clark, D. (1993) The sociology of death: Theory, culture, practice. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Clarke, C., Knights, D. and Jarvis, C. (2012) A labour of love? Academics in busi-
ness schools. Scandinavian Journal of Management, 28:1, 5–15.
Clarke, C.A., Brown, A.D. and Hailey, V.H. (2009) Working identities? Antagonistic
discursive resources and managerial identity. Human Relations, 62:3, 323–352.
Clegg, S., Kornberger, M. and Rhodes, C. (2007) Business ethics as practice. British
Journal of Management, 18, 107–122.
192 References
Cockburn, C. (1990) Men’s power in organizations: ‘Equal opportunities’ inter-
venes. In J. Hearn and D.H.J. Morgan (Eds.), Men, masculinity and social theory.
London: Unwin Hyman.
Cole, A. (2004) What Hegel’s master/slave dialectic really means. Journal of Medieval
and Early Modern Studies, 34:3, 577–610.
Collinson, D. and Hearn, J. (1996) ‘Men’ at work’: Multiple masculinities/multiple
workplaces. In M. Mac an Ghaill (Ed.), Understanding masculinities: Social rela-
tions and cultural arenas, 61–76. Buckingham: Open University Press.
Conard, M.T. (Ed.) (2007) The philosophy of film noir. Lexington: University Press
of Kentucky.
Connolly, W. (1998) Beyond good and evil: The ethical sensibility of Michel Foucault.
In J. Moss (Ed.), The later Foucault, 108–128. London: Sage.
Cooper, R. and Burrell, G. (1988) Modernism, postmodernism and organizational
analysis: An introduction. Organization Studies, 9:1, 91–112.
Cooper, R. and Burrell, G. (1989) Modernism, postmodernism and organizational
analysis 3: The contribution of Jacques Derrida. Organization Studies, 10,
479–502.
Copjec, J. (2004) Imagine there’s no woman: Ethics and sublimation. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Costas, J. (2012, forthcoming) ‘We are all friends here’: Reinforcing paradoxes of
normative control in a culture of friendship. Journal of Management Inquiry.
Courtenay, W.H. (2000) Constructions of masculinity and their influence on men’s
well-being: A theory of gender and health. Social Science and Medicine, 50,
1385–1401.
Critchley, S. (2012) The faith of the faithless. London: Verso.
Crotty, M.J. (1998) The foundations of social research. London: Sage.
Cummings, S. (1996) Back to the oracle: Postmodern organization theory as a resur-
facing of premodern wisdom. Organization, 3:2, 249–266.
Czarniawska, B. (1999) Management she wrote: Organization studies and detective
stories. Culture and Organization, 5:1, 13–41.
Da Cunha, J.V. and e Cunha, M.P. (2002) Reading between the lines: Unveiling
masculinity in feminine management practices. Women in Management Review,
17:1, 5–11.
De Beauvoir, S. (1953/1997) The second sex. London: Vintage.
De Lauretis, T. (2008) Freud’s drive: Psychoanalysis, literature and film. Basing-
stoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. (1977) Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and schizophrenia.
Trans. R. Hurley et al. New York: Viking.
Delmestri, G. and Walgenbach, P. (2012) Mastering techniques or brokering knowl-
edge? Middle managers in Germany, Great Britain and Italy. Organization Stud-
ies, 26:2, 197–220.
Denzin, N.K. (1991) Images of postmodern society: Social theory and contemporary
cinema. London: Sage.
Denzin, N.K. and Lincoln, Y.S. (Eds.) (2002) The qualitative inquiry reader. Thou-
sands Oaks, CA: Sage.
Dick, P.K. (2007/1962) Do androids dream of electric sheep? London: Gollanz.
Dickie, C. (2009) Exploring workplace friendships in business: Cultural variations
of employee behaviour. Research and Practice in Human Resource Management,
17:1, n.p.
Doane, M.A. (1988) The desire to desire: The woman’s film of the 1940’s. Basing-
stoke: Macmillan.
Dollimore, J. (1991) Sexual dissidence: Augustine to Wilde, Freud to Foucault.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
References 193
Dollimore, J. (2001) Death, desire and loss in Western culture. New York: Routledge.
Douglas, M. (1966) Purity and danger. London: Routledge.
Douglas, M. (1997) Deciphering a meal. In C. Counihan and P.V. Esterik (Eds.),
Food and culture: A reader, 36–55. London: Routledge.
Duncan, N. (1996) Renegotiating gender and sexuality in public and private spaces.
In N. Duncan (Ed.), Body space, 127–145. London: Routledge.
Elfring, T. and Hulsink, W. (2007) Networks in entrepreneurship: The case of high-
technology firms. Small Business Economics, 21:4, 409–422.
Ellis, C. and Bochner, A. (2000) Autoethnography, personal narrative, reflexivity:
Researcher as subject. In N. Denzin and Y. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualita-
tive research, 733–768. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Elsesser, K. and Peplau, L.A. (2006) The glass partition: Obstacles to cross-sex
friendships at work. Human Relations, 59:8, 1077–1100.
Ely, R.J. and Meyerson, D.E. (2000) Advancing gender equity in organizations: The
challenge and importance of maintaining a gender narrative. Organization; 7:4,
589–608.
Equal Opportunities Commission (2006) Facts about women and men in Great
Britain. http://www.unece.org/fileadmin/DAM/stats/gender/publications/UK/Facts_
about_W&M_GB_2006.pdf, accessed 13 November 2012.
Essers, C. (2009) Reflections on the narrative approach: Dilemmas of power, emo-
tions and social location while constructing life-stories. Organization, 16:2,
163–181.
Falk, P. (1994) The consuming body. London: Sage.
Fanon, F. (2008) Black skin, white masks. New York: Grove Press.
Feldman, S.P. (2004) The professional conscience: A psychoanalytic study of moral
character in Tolstoy’s ‘The Death of Ivan Ilych’. Journal of Business Ethics, 49,
311–328.
Fleming, P. (2005) Workers’ playtime? Boundaries and cynicism in a ‘culture of fun’
program. Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, 41:3, 285–303.
Fleming, P. and Spicer, A. (2003) Working at a cynical distance: Implications for
power, subjectivity and resistance. Organization, 10:1, 157–179.
Fleming, P. and Spicer, A. (2008) Beyond power and resistance: New approaches to
organizational politics. Management Communication Quarterly, 21:3, 301–309.
Fletcher, A.J. (1995) Gender, sex and subordination: England 1500–1800. London:
Yale University Press.
Foley, H. (1995) Tragedy and democratic ideology: The case of Sophocles’ Antigone.
In B. Goff (Ed.), History, tragedy, theory, 131–150. Austin: University of Texas
Press.
Ford, J. and Collinson, D. (2011) In search of the perfect manager? Work-life bal-
ance and managerial work. Work, Employment and Society, 25:2, 257–273.
Ford, J. and Harding, N. (2003) Invoking Satan or the ethics of the employment
contract. Journal of Management Studies, 40:5, 1131–1150.
Ford, J. and Harding, N. (2004) We went looking for an organization but could find
only the metaphysics of its presence. Sociology, 38:4, 815–830.
Fotaki, M. (2005) Choice is yours: A psychodynamic explanation of health policy-
making and its consequences for the English National Health Service. Human
Relations, 59:12, 1711–1744.
Fotaki, M. (2011) The sublime object of desire (for knowledge): Sexuality at work
in business and management schools in England. British Journal of Management,
22:1, 42–53.
Fotaki, M. and Harding, N. (2012) Lacan and sexual difference in organization and
management theory: Towards a hysterical academy? Organization, http://org.
sagepub.com/content/early/2012/02/05/1350508411435280.abstract.
194 References
Foucault, M. (1966) The order of things: Archaeology of the human sciences.
London: Routledge.
Foucault, M. (1977) Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison. Harmond-
sworth: Penguin.
Foucault, M. (1979) The history of sexuality, Vol. 1. London: Allen Lane.
Foucault, M. (1982) Afterword: The subject and power. In H.L. Dreyfus and
P. Rabinow (Eds.), Michel Foucault: Beyond structuralism and hermeneutics,
229–252. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Foucault, M. (1985) The use of pleasure. Trans. R. Hurley. New York: Pantheon.
Foucault, M. (1986) The history of sexuality, Vol. 2. Harmondsworth: Viking.
Foucault, M. (1992) The history of sexuality, Vol. 3. London: Penguin.
Foucault, M. (1994) Theatrum Philosophicum. In J. Faubion (Ed.), Michel Foucault:
Aesthetics: The essential works 2, 343–368. Trans. Robert Hurley et al. London:
Penguin Books.
Foucault, M. (1997a) Ethics: The essential works 1. Ed. P. Rabinow. Trans. R. Hurley
et al. London: Penguin.
Foucault, M. (1997b) Technologies of the self. In P. Rabinow (Ed.), Michel Foucault:
Ethics, subjectivity and truth. New York: New Press.
Fournier, V. and Grey, C. (2000) At the critical moment: Conditions and prospects
for critical management studies. Human Relations, 53:1, 7–32.
Freud, S. (1914/2009) Beyond the pleasure principle. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Freud, S. (1915–17/1973) Volume One: Introductory lectures on psychoanalysis.
London: Penguin.
Friedson, E. (1986) Professional powers. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Fuery, P. and Fuery, K. (2003) Visual cultures and critical theory. London: Bloomsbury
Academic.
Gabriel, Y. (2003) Your home, my exile: Boundaries and ‘otherness’ in antiquity and
now. Organization Studies, 24, 619–632.
Gatrell, C. and Swan, E. (2008) Gender and diversity in management. London: Sage.
George, J.M. and Jett, Q.R. (2003) Work interrupted: A closer look at the role
of interruptions in organizational life. Academy of Management Review, 28:3,
494–507.
Gherardi, Sylvia (1995) Gender, symbolism and organizational cultures. London:
Sage.
Gibson-Graham, J.K. (1996) The end of capitalism (as we knew it): A feminist cri-
tique of political economy. Oxford: Blackwell.
Giddens, A. (1991) Modernity and self identity. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Gilley, A. Gilley, J.W., McConnell, C.W. and Veliquette, A. (2010) The competen-
cies used by effective managers to build teams: An empirical study. Advances in
Developing Human Resources, 12:1, 29–45.
Glaser, B. and Strauss, A. (1968) Time for dying. Chicago: Aldine.
Godfrey, R., Lilley, S. and Brewis, J. (2012) Biceps, bitches and borgs: Reading Jarhead’s
representation of the construction of the (masculine) military body. Organization
Studies, 33:4, 541–562.
Grant, J. and Porter, P. (1996) Women managers: The construction of gender in the
workplace. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Sociology, 30:2, 149–164.
Grey, C. (2009) A very short, fairly interesting and reasonably cheap book about
studying organizations. London: Sage.
Grey, C. and French, R. (1966) Rethinking management education: An introduc-
tion. In R. French and C. Grey (Eds.), Rethinking management education, 1–16.
London: Sage.
Grey, C. and Sturdy, A. (2007) Friendship and organizational analysis: Toward a
research agenda. Journal of Management Inquiry, 16:2, 157–172.
References 195
Grey, C. and Willmott, H. (2005) Critical management studies: A reader. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Gurevitch, Z. (2001) Dialectical dialogue: The struggle for speech, repressive silence,
and the shift to multiplicity. British Journal of Sociology, 52:1, 87–104.
Halberstam, J. (1998) Female masculinity. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Hales, C. (1999) Why do managers do what they do? Reconciling evidence and
theory in accounts of managerial work. British Journal of Management, 10,
335–350.
Hancock, P. (2008) Fear and (self)loathing in Coleridge Close: Management in crisis
in the 1970s sitcom. Organization, 15:5, 685–703.
Handy, C. (1995) Gods of management: The changing work of organizations.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Haraway, D. (1985) A manifesto for cyborgs: Science, technology and socialist femi-
nism in the 1980s. Socialist Review, 15:2, 65–107.
Harding, N. (2002) On the manager’s body as an aesthetics of control. Tamara:
Journal of Critical Postmodern Organization Science, 2:2, 63–77.
Harding, N. (2003) The social construction of management: Texts and identities.
London: Routledge.
Harding, N. (2007) On Lacan and the ‘becoming-ness’ of organizations/selves. Or-
ganization Studies, 28:11, 1761–1773.
Harding, N. (2008) The ‘I’, the ‘me’ and the ‘you know’: Identifying identities in
organisations. Qualitative Research in Organizations and Management, 3:1,
42–58.
Harding, N., Ford, J. and Gough, B. (2010) Accounting for ourselves: Are academics
exploited workers? Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 21:2, 159–168.
Harding, N., Lee, H., Ford, J. and Learmonth, M. (2011) Leadership and charisma:
A desire that cannot speak its name? Human Relations, 64:7, 927–950.
Harrison, W.C. and Hood-Williams, J. (2002) Beyond sex and gender. London:
Sage.
Hassard, J. and Holliday, R. (Eds.) (1998) Organization-representation: Work and
organizations in popular culture. London: Sage.
Hawkins, B. (2008) Double agents: Gendered organizational control and resistance.
Sociology, 42:3, 418–435.
Haythornthwaite, C. and Wellman, B. (1998) Work, friendship and media use for
information exchange in a networked organization. Journal of the American So-
ciety for Information Science, 49:12, 1101–1114.
Heaney, S. (2004) The burial at Thebes: Sophocles’ Antigone. London: Faber and
Faber.
Hearn, J. (1992) Men in the public eye. London:Routledge.
Hearn, J. and Parkin, W. (1986) ‘Sex’ at ‘work’: The power and paradox of organi-
zation sexuality. Brighton: Wheatsheaf.
Hegel, G.W.F. (1977) Phenomenology of spirit. Trans. A.V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Heidegger, M. (1926/1962) Being and time. New York: Harper and Brothers.
Hekman, S.J. (1999) The future of differences: Truth and method in feminist theory.
Oxford: Polity Press.
Hester, J.D. (2004) Intersexes and the end of gender corporeal ethics and postgender
bodies. Journal of Gender Studies, 13:3, 215–225.
Hird, M. (2003) Considerations for a psychoanalytical theory of gender identity
and sexual desire: The case of intersex. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and
Society, 28, 1068–1092.
Hochschild, A.R. (1983) The managed heart: Commercialization of human feeling.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
196 References
Hochschild, A.R. (1997) The time bind: When work becomes home and home be-
comes work. New York: Owl Books.
Hochwarter, W.A. and Thompson, K.W. (2012) Mirror, mirror on my boss’s wall:
Engaged enactment’s moderating role on the relationship between perceived nar-
cissistic supervision and work outcomes. Human Relations, 63:3, 335–366.
Hook, D. (2009) Restoring universality to the subject: Lacan’s Kantian logic of sexu-
ation. Annual Review of Critical Psychology, 7, 151–167.
Hühn, P. (1987) The detective as reader: Narrativity and reading concepts in detec-
tive fiction. Modern Fiction Studies, 33:3, 451–466.
Iedemam R., Degeling, P., Braithwaite, J. and White, L. (2003) ‘It’s an interesting
conversation I’m hearing’: The doctor as manager. Organization Studies, 25:1,
15–33.
Irigaray, L. (1985) Speculum of the other woman. Trans. G. Gill. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Iser, W. (Ed.) (2000) The reading process: A phenomenological approach. In
D. Lodge (Ed.), Modern criticism and theory: A reader, 189–205. Harlow: Longman.
Jacobs, A. (2006) On matricide: Myths, psychoanalysis and the law of the mother.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Jameson, F. (1991) Postmodernism, or, the cultural logic of late capitalism. London:
Verso.
Janesick, V.M. (1994) The dance of qualitative research design: Metaphor, meth-
odolatry, and meaning. In N.K. Denzin and Y.S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of
Qualitative Research, 209–219. New York: Sage.
Jermier, J.M. and Knights, D. (Eds.) (1994) Resistance and power in organizations:
Critical perspectives on work and organizations. London: Routledge.
Jovanovic, G. (2011) Toward a social history of qualitative research. History of the
Human Sciences, 24:2, 1–27.
Judovitz, D. (2001) The culture of the body: Genealogies of modernity. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
Kark, R. and Weismel-Manor, R. (2005) Organizational citizenship behaviour:
What’s gender got to do with it? Organization, 12:6, 889–917.
Kikjuit, B. and Ende, J.C.M. van den (2010) With a little help from our colleagues:
A longitudinal study of social networks for innovation. Organization Studies,
31:4, 451–479.
Knights, D. (1997) Organization theory in the age of deconstruction: Dualism, gen-
der and postmodernism revisited. Organization Studies, 18, 1–19.
Knights, D. and Kerfoot, D. (2004) Between representations and subjectivity: Gen-
der binaries and the politics of organizational transformation. Gender, Work and
Organization, 11:4, 430–454.
Knights, D. and Willmott, H. (1989) Power and subjectivity at work: From degrada-
tion to subjugation in social relations. Sociology, 23:4, 535–558.
Knights, D. and Willmott, H. (1999) Management lives: Power and identity in work
organizations. London: Sage.
Kociatkiewicz, J. and Kostera, M. (2012) The good manager: An archetypical quest
for morally sustainable leadership. Organization Studies, 33:7, 861–878.
Korczynski, M. (2011) The dialectical sense of humour: Routine joking in a
Taylorized factory. Organization Studies, 32:10, 1420–1440.
Korczynski, M. and Ott, U. (2005) Sales work under marketization: The social rela-
tions of the cash nexus? Organization Studies, 26:5, 707–728.
Kotter, J. (1990) A force for change: How leadership differs from management. New
York: Free Press.
Kram, K.E. and Isabella, L.A. (1985) Mentoring alternatives: The role of peer re-
lationships in career development. Academy of Management Journal, 28:1,
110–132.
References 197
Kristeva, J. (1982) Powers of horror: An essay on abjection. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Lacan, J. (1977) Ecrits: A selection. London: Routledge.
Lacan, J. (1982) Feminine sexuality. In J. Mitchell and J. Rose (Eds.), Feminine sexu-
ality: Jacques Lacan and the école freudienne, 27–57. Trans. J. Rose. London:
Norton.
Lacan, J. (1998) On feminine sexuality, the limits of love and knowledge, 1972–
1973. Encore. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan. Book XX. Ed. J.-A. Miller. Trans.
B. Fink. New York: Norton.
Lacan, J. (2002) Écrits: The first complete edition in English. Trans. B. Fink. New
York: Norton.
Lacan, J. (2007) Seminar XVII: The other side of psychoanalysis. Ed. J.-A. Miller.
Trans. R. Grigg. New York: Norton.
Lacqueur, T. (1990) Making sex: Body and gender from the Greeks to Freud.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Lam, M. (2004) The perception of inequalities: A gender case study. Sociology,
38:1, 5–23.
Larkin, P. (2003) Collected poems by Philip Larkin and Anthony Thwaite. London:
Faber and Faber.
Law, J. (2004) After method: Mess in social science research. London: Routledge.
Law, J. (2006) Making a mess with method. Version of 19th January 2006. http://
www.heterogeneities.net/publications/Law2006MakingaMesswithMethod.pdf,
accessed 3 March 2012.
Leder, D. (1990) The absent body. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lee, G.H. (2005) Queer(y)ing health promotion: A critical analysis. Unpublished
doctoral dissertation, University of Leeds.
Lefebvre, H. (1991) The production of space. Trans. D. Nicholson-Smith. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Lincoln, J.R. and Miller, J. (1979) Work and friendship ties in organizations: A
comparative analysis of relational networks. Administrative Science Quarterly,
24, 181–199.
Linkman, A. (2011) Photography and death. London: Reaktion.
Linstead, S. (2000) Ashes and madness: The play of negativity and the poetics of
organization. In S. Linstead and H. Höpfl (Eds.), The aesthetics of organization,
61–92. London: Sage.
Littler, C. and Salaman, G. (1982) Bravermania and beyond—recent theories of the
labour process. Sociology, 16:2, 251–269.
Lloyd, M.B. (2005) Antigone and the state. Political Theory, 4, 451–468.
Lodge, D. (2000) Wolfang Iser—introductory note. In D. Lodge and N. Wood (Eds.),
Modern criticism and theory: A reader, 188–189. Harlow: Pearson Education.
MacKenzie, R. and Forde, C. (2009) Rhetoric of the ‘good worker’ versus the reali-
ties of employers’ use and the experiences of migrant workers. Work, Employ-
ment and Society, 23:1, 142–159.
Mankell, H. (2009) The man who smiled. London: Vintage Books.
Marks, L.U. (2000) The skin of the film. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Marks, S.R. (1994) Intimacy in the public realm: The case of co-workers. Social
Forces, 72:3, 843–858.
Marshall, J. (1984) Women managers: Travellers in a male world. Chichester: Wiley.
Martin, J. (1990) Deconstructing organizational taboos: The suppression of gender
conflict in organizations. Organization Science, 1, 339–359.
Martin, P.Y. (2006) Practising gender at work: Further thoughts on reflexivity.
Gender, Work and Organization, 13:3, 254–276.
Marx, K. (1988) Economic and philosophic manuscripts of 1844. New York:
Prometheus Books.
198 References
McCarthy, G.E. (2003) Classical horizons: The origins of sociology in ancient
Greece. Albany: State University of New York Press.
McGregor, D. (1989) The human side of enterprise. In H. Leavitt, L. Pondy and
D. Boje (Eds.), Readings in managerial psychology, 314–324. New York:
McGraw-Hill.
McMurray, R. (2011) The struggle to professionalize: An ethnographic account of
the occupational position of advanced nurse practitioners. Human Relations,
64:6, 801–822.
Menzies, I. (1960) A case-study in the functioning of social systems as a defence
against anxiety. Human Relations, 13, 95–121.
Meriläinen, S., Tienari, J., Thomas, R. and Davies, A. (2004) Management con-
sultant talk: A cross-cultural analysis of normalising discourse and resistance.
Organization, 11:4, 539–564.
Mills, A.J. (1992) Organization, gender, and culture. In A.J. Mills and P. Tancred
(Eds.), Gendering organizational analysis, 93–111. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Mills, A.J. and Murgatroyd, S.J. (1991) Organizational rules. Milton Keynes: Open
University Press.
Mintzberg, H. (1973) The nature of managerial work. London: Prentice Hall.
Mitchell, J. (2000) Mad men and Medusas. New York: Basic Books.
Mitsuhashi, H. (2003) Effects of the social origins of alliances on alliance perfor-
mance. Organization Studies, 24:2, 321–339.
Mulkay, M. (1993) Social death in Britain. In D. Clark (Ed.), The sociology of death:
Theory, culture, practice, 31–49. Sociological Review Monographs. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Neilson, I.K., Jex, S.M. and Adams, G.A. (2000) Development and validationof
scores on a two-dimensional workplace friendship scale. Educational and Psy-
chological Measurement, 60:4, 628–643.
Nietzsche, F. (1882/2001) The gay science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
O’Doherty, D. and Willmott, H. (2001) Debating labour process theory: The issue
of subjectivity and the relevance of poststructuralism. Sociology, 35, 457–476.
Ogbonna, E. and Wilkinson, B. (2003) The false promise of organizational culture
change: A case study of middle managers in grocery retailing. Journal of Manage-
ment Studies, 40:5, 1151–1178.
O’Leary, T. (2002) Foucault: The art of ethics. London: Continuum.
Pahl, R. and Spencer, L. (2004) Personal communities: Not simply families of ‘fate’
or ‘choice’. Current Sociology, 52:2, 199–221.
Parker, M. (1998) Judgement day: Cyborganization, humanism and postmodern
ethics. Organization, 5:4, 503–518.
Parker, M. (2002) Against management. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Parker, M. (2003) Introduction: Ethics, politics and organizing. Organization, 10,
187–203.
Parker, M. (2008) Eating with the Mafia: Belonging and violence. Human Relations,
61:7, 989–1006.
Parker, M. (2009) Pirates, merchants and anarchists: Representations of interna-
tional business. Management and Organizational History, 4:2, 167–185.
Parker, M. (2011) Alternative business: Outlaws, crime and culture. London:
Routledge.
Parker, M. and Cooper, R. (1998) Cyborganization: Cinema as nervous system. In
J. Hassard and R. Holliday (Eds.), Organization-representation: Work and organi-
zations in popular culture, 201–228. London: Sage.
Pateman, C. (1983) Feminist critiques of the public/private dichotomy. In S.I. Benn and
G.F. Gaus (Eds.), Public and private in social life, 281–303. London: Croom Helm.
Patient, D., Lawrence, T.B. and Maitlis, S. (2003) Understanding workplace envy
through narrative fiction. Organization Studies, 24:7, 1015–1044.
References 199
Patterson, O. (1982) Slavery and social death: A comparative study. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Peirano-Vejo, M.E. and Stablein, R.E. (2009) Constituting change and stability:
Sense-making stories in a farming organization. Organization, 16:3, 443–462.
Pendleton, A. (2003) Does privatization create a ‘new breed’ of managers? A study
of the UK railway industry. Human Relations, 56:1, 85–111.
Pettinger, L. (2005) Friends, relations and colleagues: The blurred boundaries of
the workplace. Sociological Review Monograph Series, 53, Issue Supplement s2,
37–55.
Pirsig, R. (1999) Zen and the art of motorcycle maintenance. London: Vintage.
Pollock, G. (2006) Beyond Oedipus: Feminist thought, psychoanalysis, and mythical
figurations of the feminine. In V. Zajko and M. Leonard (Eds.), Laughing with
Medusa, 67–120. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Prichard, C. and Willmott, H. (1997) Just how managed is the McUniversity? Orga-
nization Studies, 18:2, 287–316.
Rabin, J. (1999) Organizational downsizing: An introduction. M@n@gement, 203,
39–43.
Ramo, H. (2004) Spatio-temporal notions and organized environmental issues: An
axiology of action. Organization, 11:6, 849–872.
Rawlins, W.K. (1992) Friendship matters: Communication, dialectics, and the life
course. Edison, NJ: Transaction.
Redman, T., Wilkinson, A. and Snape, E. (1997) Stuck in the middle? Managers in
building societies. Work, Employment and Society, 11:1, 101–114.
Reed, M.I. (1989) The sociology of management. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Reed, M.I. (1992) Rethinking organization. London: Sage.
Reed, M.I. (2012) Masters of the universe: Power and elites in organization studies.
Organization Studies, 33:2, 203–221.
Reedy, P. and Learmonth, M. (2011) Death and organization: Heidegger’s thought
on death and life in organizations. Organization Studies, 32:1, 117–131.
Rhodes, C. (2007) Critical representations of work and organizations in popular
culture. London: Routledge.
Rhodes, C. and Brown, A.D. (2005) Writing responsibly: Narrative fiction and or-
ganization studies. Organization Studies, 12:4, 467–491.
Riordan, C.M. and Griffeth, R.W. (1995) The opportunity for friendship in the
workplace: An underexplored construct. Journal of Business and Psychology,
10:2, 141–154.
Roan, A. and Rooney, D. (2006) Shadowing experiences and the extension of com-
munities of practice: A case study of women education managers. Management
Learning, 37:4, 433–454.
Ronai, C.R. (1999) The next night sous rature: Wrestling with Derrida’s mimesis.
Qualitative Inquiry, 5, 114–129.
Rose, J. (1982) Introduction 2. In J. Mitchell and J. Rose (Eds.), Feminine sexuality:
Jacques Lacan and the école freudienne, 27–57. London: Norton.
Roseneil, S. and Budgeon, S. (2004) Cultures of intimacy and care beyond ‘the fam-
ily’: Personal life and social change in the early 21st century. Current Sociology,
52:2, 135–159.
Ross-Smith, A. and Kornberger, M. (2004) Gendered rationality? A genealogical
exploration of the philosophical and sociological conceptions of rationality, mas-
culinity and organization. Gender, Work and Organization, 11:3, 280–305.
Rowlands, L. and Handy, J. (2012) An addictive environment: New Zealand film
production workers’ subjective experiences of project-based labour. Human Re-
lations, 65:5, 657–680.
Rumens, N. (2008) Working at intimacy: Gay men’s workplace friendships. Gender,
Work and Organization, 15:1, 8–30.
200 References
Rumens, N. (2010) Firm friends: Exploring the supportive components in gay men’s
workplace friendships. Sociological Review, 58:1, 135–155.
Rumens, N. and Kerfoot, D. (2009) Gay men at work: (Re)constructing the self as
professional. Human Relations, 62:5, 763–786.
Rzepka, C.J.(2005) Detective fiction. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Sabath, A-M. (2007) Beyond business casual. What to wear to work if you want to
get ahead. Lincoln, NE: ASJA Press.
Said, E.W. (1978) Orientalism. London: Penguin.
Salih, Sara (2004) The Judith Butler reader. Oxford: Blackwell.
Salzer-Morling, M. (1998) Murderous ink: A case of rhetorical killing. Studies in
Culture, Organization and Society, 4, 125–145.
Scarbrough, H. and Burrell, G. (1996) The axeman cometh. In S. Clegg and G. Paler
(Eds.), The politics of management knowledge, 173–189. London: Sage.
Scarry, E. (1988) The body in pain: The making and unmaking of the world. Oxford:
Oxford Paperbacks.
Schmidt, D.J. (2001) On Germans and other Greeks: Tragedy and ethical life.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Schneider, D. (1984) A critique of the study of kinship. Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press.
Schwartz, H. (1987) On the psychodynamics of organizational totalitarianism. Jour-
nal of Management, 13:1, 41–54.
Scott, J. (2005) Electra after Freud: Myth and culture. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univer-
sity Press.
Sedgwick, E.K. (1991) Epistemology of the closet. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Sedgwick, E.K. (2003) Touching feeling: Affect, pedagogy, performativity. Durham,
NC: Duke University Press.
Seidler, V.J. (1994) Unreasonable men: Masculinity and social theory. London:
Routledge.
Sennett, R. (2006) The culture of the new capitalism. New Haven, CT: Yale Univer-
sity Press.
Shildrick, M. (1997) Leaky bodies and boundaries: Feminism, postmodernism and
(bio)ethics. London: Routledge.
Shilling, C. (1993) The body and social theory. London: Sage.
Sievers, B. (1994) Work, death and life itself. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
Siltanen, J. and Stanworth, M. (1984) The politics of private woman and public
man. Theory and Society, 13:1, 91–118.
Silver, A. (1990) Friendship in commercial society: Eighteenth-century social theory
and modern sociology. American Journal of Sociology, 95:6, 1474–1504.
Silverman, K. (1988) The acoustic mirror: The female voice in psychoanalysis and
cinema. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Silverman, K. (1996) The threshold of the visible world. New York: Routledge.
Simmel, G. (1910/2007) The metaphysics of death. Theory, Culture and Society,
24:7–8, 72–77.
Sims, D. (2008) Managerial identity formation in a public sector professional: An
autobiographical account. International Journal of Public Administration, 31,
1–15.
Sinclair, A. (2009) Seducing leadership: Stories of leadership development. Gender,
Work and Organization, 16, 265–284.
Sinfield, A. (2004) On sexuality and power. New York: Columbia University Press.
Singh, D. (2006) Emotional intelligence at work: A professional guide. New Delhi:
Sage.
Sinha, P.N., Inkson, K. and Baraker, J.R. (2012) Committed to a failing strategy:
Celebrity CEO, intermediaries, media and stakeholders in a co-created drama.
Organization Studies, 33:2, 233–245.
References 201
Sjöholm, C. (2010) Beyond pleasure: The other history of sexuality. In F. Söderbäck
(Ed.), Feminist readings of Antigone, 173–194. Albany: State University of New
York Press.
Skultans, V. (1999) Narratives of the body and history: Illness in judgement of the
Soviet past. Sociology of Health and Illness, 21, 310–328.
Smart, C., Davies, K., Heaphy, B. and Mason, J. (2012) Difficult friendships and
ontological security. Sociological Review, 60:1, 91–109.
Smith, W. (2006) Organizing death: Remembrance and re-collection. Organization,
13:2, 225–244.
Sobchack, V. (2004) Carnal thoughts: Embodiment and moving image culture.
Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Sophocles (1982) The three Theban plays: Antigone, Oedipus the King, Oedipus at
Colonus. Trans. R. Fagles. London: Penguin.
Sophocles (1988) Oedipus the King, Oedipus at Colonus, Antigone. Trans. D. Taylor.
London: Methuen.
Sophocles (2008) Antigone, Oedipus the King and Electra. Trans. H.D.F. Kitto.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Spee, A.P. and Jarzabkowski, P. (2011) Strategic planning as communicative process.
Organization Studies, 32:9, 1217–1245.
Speer, S.A. (2005) The interactional organization of the gender attribution process.
Sociology, 39:1, 67–87.
Spencer, L. and Pahl, R. (2004) Personal communities: Not simply families of ‘fate’
or ‘choice’. Current Sociology, 52:2, 199–221.
Spencer, L. and Pahl, R. (2006) Rethinking friendship: Hidden solidarities today.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Stein, M. (2007) Oedipus Rex at Enron: Leadership, Oedipal struggles, and organi-
zational collapse. Human Relations, 60, 1387–1410.
Steiner, G. (1986) Antigones. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stenport, A.W. (2007) Bodies under assault: Nation and immigration in Henning
Mankell’s Faceless Killers. Scandinavian Studies, 79:1, 1–24.
Stewart, R. (1967) Managers and their jobs: A study of the similarities and differ-
ences in the ways managers spend their time. New York: Macmillan.
Strathern, M. (2005) Kinship, law and the unexpected: Relatives are always a sur-
prise. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stroud, L. (2005) MMR—public policy in crisis: Whose tragedy? Journal of Health
Organization and Management, 19:3, 252–260.
Sveningsson, S. and Alvesson, M. (2003) Managing managerial identities: Organiza-
tional fragmentation, discourse and identity struggle. Human Relations, 56:10,
1163–1193.
Taylor, C. (1992) Sources of the self: The making of modern identity. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, F.W. (1911/2003) The principles of scientific management. Abingdon:
Routledge.
Ten Bos, R. (2003) Business ethics, accounting and the fear of melancholy. Organi-
zation, 10, 267–285.
Thomas, R. and Davies, A. (2005) Theorizing the micro-politics of resistance: New
public management and managerial identities in the UK public services. Organi-
zation Studies, 26:5, 683–706.
Thomas, R. and Linstead, A. (2002) Losing the plot? Middle managers and identity.
Organization, 9:1, 71–93.
Townley, B. (2008) Reason’s neglect: Rationality and organizing. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Trethewey, Angela. (1999) Disciplined bodies: Women’s embodied identities at
work. Organization Studies, 20:3, 423–450.
202 References
Turner, B.S. (2008) The body and society. London: Sage.
Valsiner, J. (2006) Dangerous curves in knowledge construction within psychology.
Theory and Psychology, 16:5, 587–595.
Van Dover, J.K. (2005) We must have certainty: Four essays on the detective story.
Selinsgrove, PA: Susquehanna University Press.
Vogl, G. (2009) Work as community: Narratives of solidarity and teamwork in
the contemporary workplace, who owns them? Sociological Research Online,
14:(4)4. http://www.socresonline.org.uk/14/4/4.html, accessed June 2012.
Wajcman, J. (1998) Managing like a man: Women and men in corporate manage-
ment. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Wartenberg, T. (2007) Thinking on screen: Film as philosophy. London: Routledge.
Watson, T.J. (2008) Managing identity: Identity work, personal predicaments and
structural circumstances. Organization, 15:1, 121–143.
Watson, T.J. (2009) Narrative, life story and manager identity: A case study in auto-
biographical identity work. Human Relations, 62:3, 425–452.
Webb, J. and Byrnand, S. (2008) Some kind of virus: The zombie as body and as
trope. Body and Society, 14, 83–98.
Weber, M. (1930/2001) The Protestant ethic and the spirit of capitalism. London:
Routledge.
Willmott, H. (1995) Managing the academics: Commodification and control in
the development of university education in the UK. Human Relations, 48:9,
993–1027.
Willmott, H. (2000) Death: So what? Sociology, sequestration and emancipation.
Sociological Review, 48:4, 649–665.
Wolfram Cox, J. (1997) Manufacturing the past: Loss and absence in organizational
change. Organization Studies, 18:4, 623–654.
Young, I.M. (1990) Throwing like a girl and other essays in feminist philosophy and
social theory. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Young, J. (2003) The death of God and the meaning of life. London: Routledge.
Young, M. and Willmott, P. (1969) Family and kinship in East London. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Zald, M.N. and Lounsbury, M. (2010) The wizards of Oz: Towards an institutional
approach to elites, expertise and command posts. Organization Studies, 31,
963–996.
Index