Alston TwoTypesFoundationalism 1976
Alston TwoTypesFoundationalism 1976
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of
Philosophy
I65
In other words, (A) there are foundations, and (B) they suffice to
hold up the building.
2 Only 'includes', because other requirements are also commonly imposed for
mediate justification, e.g., that the first belief be "based" on the others, and,
by some epistemologists, that the believer realize that the other beliefs do
constitute adequate grounds for the first.
belief, then that is quite compatible with our conclusion that the
latter can only be mediately justified.
(2) The conclusion should not be taken to imply that one must
perform any conscious inference to be justified in an epistemic
belief, or even that one must be explicitly aware that the lower-level
belief has an appropriate warrant-increasing property. Here as in
other areas, one's grounds can be possessed more or less implicitly.
Otherwise we would have precious little mediate knowledge.
I have already suggested that the second-level argument is not
really directed against II. To be vulnerable to this argument, a
foundationalist thesis would have to require of foundations not
only that they be immediately justified, but also that the believer
be immediately justified in believing that they are immediately
justified. A position that does require this we may call iterative
foundationalism, and we may distinguish it from the earlier form
(simple foundationalism) as follows (so far as concerns the status
of the foundations):
It would not take much historical research to show that both posi-
tions have been taken. What I want to investigate here is which of
them there is most reason to take. Since the classic support for foun-
dationalism has been the regress argument, I shall concentrate on
determining which form emerges from that line of reasoning.
II. THE REGRESS ARGUMENT
8 One should not confuse the respect in which Iterative is stronger than
Simple Foundationalism with other ways in which one version of the position
may be stronger than another. These include at least the following: (1) whether
it is required of foundations that they be infallible, indubitable, or incorrigible;
(2) whether foundations have to be self-justified, or whether some weaker form
of direct justification is sufficient; (3) how strongly the foundations support
various portions of the superstructure. I am convinced that none of these modes
of strength requires any of the others, but I will not have time to argue that
here. Note too that our version of the regress argument (to be presented in a
moment) does nothing to support the demand for foundations that are strong
in any of these respects,
lated as follows:
C. The belief that p occurs at some point (past the origin), so that the
branch forms a loop.
Of course some branches might assume one form and others another.
The argument is that the original belief will be mediately justified
only if every branch assumes form A. Positively, it is argued that on this
condition the relevant necessary condition for the original belief's being
mediately justified is satisfied, and, negatively, it is argued that if any
branch assumes any of the other forms, is not.
B. For any branch that exhibits form B, no element, even the origin, is
justified, at least by this structure. Since the terminus is not justified,
the prior element, which is justified only if the terminus is, is not
justified. And, since it is not justified, its predecessor, which is justi-
fied only if it is, is not justified either. And so on, right back to the
origin, which therefore itself fails to be justified.
proposition. But perhaps there are other versions that yield the
stronger conclusion. Indeed, in surveying the literature one will dis-
cover versions that differ from A2 is one or both of the following
respects:
13 Lest this assumption still seem obvious to some of my readers, let me take
a moment to indicate how mediate epistemic knowledge might conceivably be
derived from nonepistemic foundations. Let's begin the regress with Chisholm
and follow the line of the first ground he mentions: that I justifiably believe that
b. (To simplify this exposition I am replacing 'know' with 'justifiably believe'
throughout.) By continuing to raise the same question we will at last arrive at
a c such that I have immediate justification for believing that c. Here my
justification (for believing that I justifiably believe that c) will shift from one or
more other justified beliefs to the appropriate "warrant-increasing" property.
What is then required at the next stage is a justification for supposing the
belief that c to have this property, and for supposing that this property does
confer warrant. It is highly controversial just how claims like these are to be
justified, but, in any event, at this point we have exited from the arena of ex-
plicit claims to being justified in a certain belief; what needs justification from
here on are beliefs as to what is in fact the case, and beliefs as to what principles
of evaluation are valid, not beliefs as to my epistemic relation to these matters,
And, without attempting to go into the details, it seems plausible that, if a
foundationalist view is tenable at all, these sorts of beliefs will rest on the same
sort of foundation as other factual and evaluative beliefs.
14 I have not located a clear-cut example of a regress argument with this start-
ing point and with the conclusion in question. Nevertheless, the prospect seems
tempting enough to be worth deflating. Moreover, it forces us to raise interesting
questions concerning the concept of showing.
Just as the ambiguity of 'knowledge claim' led to versions' of the regress argu-
ment being indeterminate with respect to the earlier feature, so the process-
product ambiguity of terms like 'justification' and 'justified' often make it uncer-
tain whether a philosopher is talking about what it takes for a belief to be justi-
fied or about what it takes to justify a belief in the sense of showing it to be
justified. See, e.g., C. I. Lewis, An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation (La
Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1946), p. 187; Leonard Nelson, "The Impossibility of the
'Theory of Knowledge'," in Chisholm & Swartz, op. cit., p. 8.
might be led into this. One who accepted the previous argument
might still feel dissatisfied with simple foundationalism. "You
have shown," he might say, "that it is possible to be justified in
believing that p without having any immediately justified epistemic
belief. But are we in fact justified in believing any p? To answer
that question you will have to show, for some p, that you are justi-
fied in believing it. And the question is, what is required for that?
Is it possible to do that without immediately justified epistemic
belief?"
Now if we are to show, via a regress argument, that immediately
justified epistemic belief is necessary for showing that I am justified
in believing any p, it must be because some requirement for show-
ing sets up a regress that can only be stopped if we have such beliefs.
What could that requirement be? Let's see what is required for
showing that p. Clearly, to show that p I must adduce some other
(possibly compound) proposition, q. What restrictions must be put
on a q and my relations thereto?
This requirement clearly does give rise to a regress, viz., that al-
ready brought out in A2. We have seen that immediately justified
epistemic belief is not required to end that regress; so again we
may pass on.
Now when p is 'S knows that a', the question is whether one or
more of these conditions is satisfiable only if S has immediately justi-
fied epistemic beliefs. Let's consider the conditions in turn. As for
1, S can in fact know that a without having any directly justified
epistemic belief, even if it should be the case that one can't know
that a without knowing that one knows that a. For, as we saw in sec-
tion II, there is no reason to doubt that all justified beliefs that one
knows or is justified in believing something are themselves mediately
justified. As for 2A and 2B, there should be no temptation to sup-
pose that they depend on iterative foundationalism. Surely the
grounds I adduce for the claim to know that a can be true and
adequate without my having any immediately justified epistemic
beliefs. Even if one or more of the grounds should themselves be
claims to knowledge, the question of what is required for their
truth can be handled in the same way as requirement 1. And
adequacy, being a matter of relations between propositions, can-
not depend on what sort of justification S has for one or another
17 To be sure, this short treatment leaves open the abstract possibility that the
first such higher-level belief might be justified by some of the lower-level beliefs
among the current foundations (if indeed the rules of the game permit their use
in justification without first having been justifiably recognized as immediately
justified). But it is clear that the foundational beliefs Descartes recognizes are
radically unsuitable for this employment.
18 Descartes apparently felt that he was required not only to identify his
foundations as such before building anything on them, but also to show at that
stage that each of the foundations had the required status. And not even itera-
tive foundationalism could help him with that. In the attempt to show that he
immediately knows that, e.g., 2 plus 2 equals 4, he is inevitably and notoriously
led to make use of premises the knowledge of which needs to be shown just as
much or as little as the proposition with which he begins.
BOOK REVIEWS
19 For a position that approximates this, see Anthony Quinton, The Nature
of Things (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1973), pt. II.