0% found this document useful (0 votes)
13 views9 pages

Between A Game and A Story

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOC, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
13 views9 pages

Between A Game and A Story

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOC, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 9

nBetween a Game and a Story?

Ken Perlin
2004-05-01

Secondary Threads:
electropoetics
Why does a character in a book or movie seem more real to us than a
character in a computer game? And what would it take to make an interactive
character on our computer screen seem real to us the way that a character on
the page or silver screen does? In other words, is there something
intermediate between a story character and a game character? As I write this
I’m looking at my computer screen, where an interactively animated character
that I’ve created appears to be looking back at me. In what sense can that
character be considered real? Obviously it’s all relative; there’s no actual
person in my computer, any more than a character in a movie is an actual
person. We’re talking about a test of dramatic reality. But what sort of
dramatic reality?

If Iím seeing a movie and the protagonist gets hurt, I feel bad because Iíve
grown to identify with that character. The filmmakers have (with my consent)
manipulated my emotions so as to make me view the world from that
characterís point of view for 100 minutes or so. I implicitly consent to this
transference process; I ìwillingly suspend my disbelief.î As I watch the movie, I
am continually testing the protagonistís apparent inner moral choices against
my own inner moral measuring stick, looking for affirmation of higher goals
and ideals, or for betrayal of those ideals. That transference is why a character
such as Tony Soprano, for example, is so gripping: the narrative and point of
view lead us forcefully into his vulnerable inner landscape, into the way, for
example, that he finds connection with his own need for family by nurturing a
family of wild ducklings. And then we are led to scenes of him being a brutal
mob boss, hurting or maiming adversaries who get in his way. The power of
the work lies in pulling us into the point of view of a character who makes
moral choices wildly at odds with the choices that most of us would make. In
some strange sense we ìbecomeî Tony Soprano for a time, a very novel and
unsettling experience for most of us.

This transference can be effected in such a focused and powerful way only
because we agree (when we start watching) to give over our choice-making
power, and to passively allow the narrative to lead us where it will. When this
is done well, then we are drawn inside the head of one character (or in some
cases several characters). In that mode we are taken to places that we might
never reach in our actual lives.

The form I have just described, of course, arises from what I will call ìThe
Novel,î which has for some time been the dominant literary form of Western
civilization. Whether it is in the form of oral storytelling, written text, dramatic
staging, or cinema, the basic premise is the same. A trusted storyteller says to
us, ìLet me tell you a story. There was a guy (or gal), and one day the following
conflict happened, and then this other thing happened, and then...,î and by
some transference process we become that guy or gal for the duration of the
story. His conflict becomes our conflict, his choices our choices, and his
fictional changes of character seem, oddly, like a sort of personal journey for
our own souls. My focus here will be more on those variants of the novel in
which the narrative is literally played out by embodied actors, such as staged
theater, cinema and figurative animation, because those are the narrative
media with the closest connection to modern computer games.

Thereís an odd sort of alchemy at work in the way that the transference
process by which a viewer identifies with the protagonist succeeds precisely
because it is not literal. For example, imagine a novel in which countless
millions of innocent people die a senseless and brutal death, with much of the
worldís population being wiped out, yet in which the protagonists, when faced
with difficult moral choices, acquit themselves admirably and stay true to their
ideals. This will probably result in an uplifting story. (This is precisely the
recipe, for example, of the films When Worlds Collide and Independence Day.)
In such a story, the protagonist doesnít even need to survive ó as long as he
dies nobly, exiting with a suitably stirring speech on his tongue or a grim
gleam of stoic heroism in his steely eye.

On the other hand, imagine another novel in which nobody is killed or even
hurt, but in which the sympathetic protagonist betrays his inner ideals. This is
inevitably a tragic tale, and reading or viewing it will fill us with despair. The
Bicycle Thief is a classic example.
Note that there are certainly other art forms that convey personality, soul, and
character without following the paradigm of linear narrative. Figurative
sculpture, for example, does not impose a narrative on us, although it certainly
can transport us to a different emotional state or psychological point of view.
There is no fixed viewpoint from which we are expected to look at a sculpture.
There isnít even a recommended sequence of successive viewpoints. And yet
sculpture, without narrative, can powerfully convey emotions, personality,
struggle.

So, there is something very particular about the way the novel, in all its many
variants, goes about its business. By telling us a story, it asks us to set aside
our right to make choices ó our agency. Instead, the agency of a protagonist
takes over, and we are swept up in observation of his struggle, more or less
from his point of view, as though we were some invisible spirit or angel
perched upon his shoulder, watching but never interfering.

By way of contrast, look at games. A game does not force us to relinquish our
agency. In fact, the game depends on it.

When you play Tomb Raider you donít actually think of Lara Croft as a person
the same way, say, you think of Harry Potter as a person (see sidebar images).
There is a fictional construct in the backstory to the game. But while youíre
actually playing the game, the very effectiveness of the experience depends on
you becoming Lara Croft. The humanlike figure you see on your computer
screen is really a game token, and every choice she makes, whether to shoot,
to leap, to run, to change weapons, is your choice.

When you stop the game play momentarily, there is no sense that the
personality of Lara Croft is anywhere to be found. While youíre taking
inventory, changing weapons, etc., the game figure on the screen stands
impassively, and you know that the figure would stand that way forever if you
were never to reenter gameplay mode. In other words, even a bare minimum
of suspension of disbelief is not attempted. In fact, you are supposed to
ìbecomeî Lara Croft ó it is that immediacy and responsiveness that makes the
game so exciting.

So letís compare Harry Potter to Lara Croft. When I am reading one of the
Harry Potter books, and I put the book aside for a while, I can easily sustain
the pleasant fiction that there is an actual Harry Potter, with a continued set of
feelings and goals, living ìoffstageî somewhere. This is because to read Harry
Potter is to experience his agency, as he navigates the various difficult
challenges that life presents him. In contrast, when I walk away from my
computer screen, I cannot sustain the fiction that an actual Lara Croft
continues to exist offstage, because I have not actually experienced her
agency. All I have really experienced is my agency.

Of course, linear narrative forms and games are intended to serve very
different purposes. The traditional goal of a linear narrative is to take you on a
vicarious emotional journey, whereas the traditional goal of a game is to
provide you with a succession of active challenges to master. A character in a
game is traditionally merely a convenient vehicle for framing and embodying
these challenges. In this sense, a game is traditionally all about player control,
since without active control, the player cannot meet the challenges that the
game poses.

So how could the two forms, story and game, grow closer together? Well, to
start, let’s look at narrative structure. Here’s a classic story arc: in the
beginning, we are introduced to the basic characters, and some introductory
conflicts are played out in small scale. Choices are made early on by the
protagonists that have ramifications only much later in the drama
(foreshadowing). Over time, the stakes get raised; the conflict becomes
stripped to its essentials, culminating in a dramatic climax near the end. When
the dust settles, in the release of dramatic tension that inevitably follows
climax, there is a clear outcome.

Of course what I’ve just described is the basic gameplay of both Monopoly and
chess. One obvious thing that distinguishes these games from narrative
literature is that their protagonists are the players. In contrast, the conflicts in
a work of narrative literature are played out by fictional characters, and the
author’s deeper purpose in building the narrative structure is generally to take
the reader through the dynamic psychological journey of these characters. It
was once said of writing narrative fiction that: Plot is the drugged meat that
you throw over the fence to put the guard dog to sleep so you can rob the
house. In other words, story is about conveying character. To do that
interactively would require some sort of plausible psychological agency on the
part of somebody within the interactive narrative.

If we look at linear narrative and interactive game as a dialectic, how can we


really get into intermediate states along this dialectic? In other words, can we
create a form in which the wall between my agency and the agency of an entity
that seems psychologically present and real to me can be removed or blurred?

But what exactly would intermediate agency look like? A fascinating insight is
provided by Philip Pullmanís trilogy of novels His Dark Materials. These novels
take place in an alternate universe in which the soul of a person is an external,
embodied entity. In this universe your soul is neither distinctly ìselfî nor
ìother,î but rather an embodied familiar, or daemon, who always travels with
you, who helps you to wrestle with choices, and with whom you can converse.
Interestingly, the daemons of two people can converse with each other
directly. If one imagines a similar relationship between a player and a
character, this dramatic structure could plausibly lead to a form of creative
work with is intermediate between linear narrative and game, by enabling a
psychologically present entity which is somewhere in between me and other.

There has been some movement in the computer gaming world toward
something that one could call character. But these attempts have been
hindered by the fact that characters in games can’t act within an interactive
scene in any compelling way. Of particular interest are ìgod-gamesî ó those
games, such as Will Wrightís SimCity, in which the player takes a ìGodís eye
viewî of the proceedings. More recently, Wright introduced The Sims ó a
simulated suburban world in which the player nurtures simulated people, sort
of as pets (see sidebar image). The player directs these virtual people, who
have no knowledge of the existence of the player, to buy things, marry, have
children, take care of their physical and psychological needs, and so forth.

In a sense, the player is asked to take on some of the traditional role of an


author ó The Simsitself is more of a simulator toy than a game. By playing with
this simulator, the player becomes a sort of author. As in many god-games, the
player himself is expected to design much of the dramatic arc of the
experience ó it is up to him to starve or to feed his Simscharacters, to
introduce them, encourage them to acquire possessions or children. Given the
current state of technology, it would be impossible to sustain the dramatic
illusion if these characters were to attempt to speak to each other in clear
English. For this reason, Wright has made the clever design decision to have
the characters ìtalkî to each other in a sort of gibberish. This allows us to buy
into the illusion that they are engaging each other in substantive conversations
about something or other. In this way, The Sims replaces some social activity
in its simulated world with the texture of social activity.

Playing The Sims is lots of fun, but one thing conspicuously lacking from the
experience is any compelling feeling that the characters are real. Much of this
lack comes from The Sims í reliance on sequences of linear animation to
convey the behavior of its characters. For example, if the player indicates to
a Sims character that the character should feed her baby, then the character
will run a canned animation to walk over to the babyís bassinet, pick up the
baby, and make feeding movements. If the player then tells her to play with the
baby, she will put the baby down, return to a previous position, then begin the
animation to approach the bassinet, again pick up the baby, and start to play.
One result of this mechanical behavior is that there is no real possibility of
willing suspension of disbelief on the part of the player as to the reality of the
character.

The player ends up thinking of The Sims as a sort of probabilistic game, not
really as a world inhabited by feeling creatures. A player quickly realizes that
anything that happens that is not caused by his own agency is being caused by
the equivalent of a set of dice being thrown inside the software, not through
the agency of thinking, feeling characters. The Sims remains, dramatically, a
world-building game, not a psychological narrative in which one believes in the
agency of the characters.

In the gaming world, one can also see a small step in the direction of
intermediate agency in the game Black and White, a god-game in which the
player has the use of embodied daemons to do his bidding. Yet the daemons in
this game do not seem like interestingly real characters. I believe that one key
reason for this is that the key ingredients of successful narrative film are
simply not yet available for use in games.
In order to create a psychological suspension of disbelief, a visual narrative
medium requires all three of the following elements: writing, directing, and
acting. If any of these is missing, then a narrative on stage or film cannot
provide observers with the essential framework they need to suspend their
disbelief.

Of these elements, in computer games to date, acting has been conspicuously


missing. Even in the most badly executed films (e.g., the films of Ed Wood) the
essential humanity of the actors playing the characters somehow manages to
come through. We believe the actor is attempting to convey a specific
character within a specific scene, and we respond by agreeing to pretend that
the actor has become that character, responding to the psychological
challenges of the moment.

Yet imagine that film or theater did not have acting as we know it ó but that
instead all cast members were constrained to act in the most rotely mechanical
way, repeating lines of dialogue and movements without any feeling that was
specific to the scene (think of the mother putting down the baby only to pick it
up again, in The Sims).

This is precisely the situation that game designers are faced with today when
they foray into more narrative-based forms. If, as a creator, you have a
nonlinear, interactive narrative structure, but it is embodied in such a way that
acting is essentially nonexistent, then there is no way to create emotional buy-
in for that character ó the willing suspension of disbelief by the audience in
that characterís existence. Myst cleverly got around this by creating an
interactive narrative in which there were no people (they were all gone before
the observer shows up). But when the sequel Riven introduced actual fictional
characters, the results were far less compelling, because it became
immediately apparent that these were mere precanned game characters ó
windup toys ó about whom the player could not really suspend disbelief.

A number of people have been working very hard over the years on ìnonlinearî
or interactive narrative. It is my contention that these efforts cannot move
forward to merge film and games, and that we will not be able to find a way to
create an intermediate agency that will allow the viewer to find their way into
caring about characters, until we provide a way that characters can act well
enough to embody an interactive narrative.

For this reason, and to lay the groundwork for interactive media that are
intermediate in the ìagencyî dialectic, a number of us have been working on
various techniques for ìbetter interactive acting abilityî by computer-based
virtual actors. This work involves body language, facial expression, rhythm of
conversational response, varieties of ways to convey focus and attention
between actors, and various ways to convey internal emotional states and
awareness while playing a scene.

Right now, weíre all in a learning stage, trying to figure out what works to
make effective emotionally interactive actors. For example, presented here
(figure 2.1) is the control panel for an interactive applet we made at NYU that
teaches its user how to build a large vocabulary of facial expressions by
combining a small number of emotional primitives.

Fig. 2.1: NYUís Responsive Face.


You can see to the right of the face the basic elements of facial expression. Just
above those are some example ìpresetsî ó complex facial expressions that are
simply linear combinations of the lower-level primitives. Above that are some
tools to let the user string together sequences of expressions to tell an
emotional story.

Tools such as this one can help us to learn what works (or doesnít work) to
make an effective interactive actor. With any luck (and some hard work), we
will have good interactive acting on our computer screens by the time the next
edition of this book comes out. And that capability will, in turn, provide one of
the key tools needed to properly explore the space of an interactive narrative
form intermediate between story and game.

Sidebar

Sidebar images

Responses

Victoria Vesna responds

Will Wright responds

Ken Perlin responds

Reference

McCloud, Scott (1993). Understanding Comics: The Invisible Art. Lettering by


Bob Lappan. Northampton, MA: Tundra.

You might also like