Stambaugh, Joan - The Formless Self (Optimized)
Stambaugh, Joan - The Formless Self (Optimized)
t h e formless self
Joan Stambaugh
Gathering and interpreting material that is not readily available elsewhere, this book dis
cusses the thought of the Japanese Budd.hist philosophers Dagen, Hisarnatsu, and
Nishitani. Stambaugh develops ideas about the self culminating in the concept of the
Formless Self as formulated by Hisarnatsu in his book The Ful/nm ofNothingness ·and the
essay "The Characteristics of Oriental Nothingness/ and funher explicated by Nishitani in
his book R.e/igion and Nothingnm. These works show that Oriental nothingness has noth
ing to do with the nineteenth- and twentieth-century Western concept of nihilism. Instead,
it is a positive phenomenon, enabling things to be.
"I confess that this work-&om the perspective of exposition, analysis, interpretation,
application, and stimulation-is, I believe, just about as good as it gets. This book is an
unexcclled example of comparative philosophy. Starnbaugh's uses of Kant, Nietzsche,
Heid egger, Tillich, etc. to illwnine Buddhist sensibilities is discreet, even-handed, and
nuanced to a degree that comparativists seldom achieve. My greatest concern about this
book is that it might not be followed by another one from the same hand."
-David L. Hall, co-author with Roger Ames of Thinking.from the Han
"So much of contemporary Western thought is in a deep struggle to reinvent a more pro
found sense of'sel£' And Stambaugh's narrative strikes right at the core of this effort, bring
ing the most advanced thinking in East and West into a creative synthesis. She brings out
how the nondual discourse of the Selfis profoundly different from any tradition that situ
ates its hermeneutic within the dualistic patterns of Subject/Object thinking. At this point
in our evolution it is panicularly important for thinkers in the Western traditions who
struggle to reach a 'postmodern' vision ofthe Subject or Selfto have a direct encounter with
the classical powers of nondual thinking about the Self-the Formless Self."
-Ashok Gangadcan, Haverford College
Joan Stambaugh
N o part o f this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without
written permission. N o part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or
transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic
tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior
permission in writing of the publisher.
Preface ix
Introduction xi
i. DoQen i
The Question of the Self l
Activity of the Self
The Self as Illusion and Enlightenment 14
The Self as Buddha-nature 21
Temporality and Impermanence 28
2. Hisamatsu 55
Dialogues w ith Tillich 55
Oriental Nothingness 71
The Formless Self 81
"Critique of the 'Unconscious'" 92
3. Nishitani 99
The Self-Overcoming of Nihilism 99
Religion and Nothingness 101
Conclusion 165
Notes 167
Index 1 73
Property was thus appall'd
That the self was not the same;
Single nature's double name
Neither two nor one was call'd.
This study attem pts to probe into the m eaning of the self as set
forth by three Japanese Buddhist thinkers: Dogen, Hisamatsu,
and Nishitani. Dogen lived in the thirteenth century—Hisamatsu
and Nishitani in the twentieth.
Dogen's main work, Shobogenzo, Treasury of the True Dharma
Eye, has received considerable attention and may be considered
one of the most profound and challenging philosophical works of
Buddhism in any period. H isam atsu is perhaps less well known
in the West; his m ain w ork in English is Zen and the Fine Arts. In
addition, he has authored some articles available in English, most
notably "The Characteristics of Oriental Nothingness" and the di
alogues with the Protestant theologian Paul Tillich. Nishitani en
gaged in extensive studies of Western philosophy and religion;
the book Religion and Nothingness is his attem pt to put Buddhist
concepts in a form also accessible to Western thinkers.
W hat these three thinkers have in common is, among other
things, a concern w ith the problem of the self. Formulated by
H isam atsu as the Formless Self, the resultant concept of self d e
velops in a way that merges self and world w ith a total lack of ob
jectification or reification of either.
In this work, I have tried to pursue some questions raised in
my earlier book, Impermanence is Buddha-nature. That w ork cen
tered almost exclusively on Dogen and the question of time. This
IX
X Preface
study again is concerned with Dogen and then goes beyond the
thirteenth century to consider a less well-known Buddhist
thinker, Shin'ichi Hisamatsu, in his own essays as well as in dia
logues with the Protestant theologian Paul Tillich. Finally, atten
tion is focused on Keiji Nishitani, a Buddhist scholar who
devoted himself to the study of Western philosophy and theology.
Thus, the far-reaching implications of impermanence for the
question of the self are pursued in an attem pt to reach an under
standing of nonsubstantialized self that has nothing to do with a
reified ego.
This can hardly claim to be the work of a scholar of Bud
dhism. The only credentials the author can lay claim to are some
years of Sanskrit study, an all too short period of study with the
German scholar of Indology and Buddhism, Erich Frauwallner, as
well as an equally short period of study w ith Masao Abe, plus a
lifelong keen interest in the East and in Buddhism in particular.
However, the lim itations in comprehension are decidedly my
own and no one else's responsibility.
This study is an attem pt to present Eastern ideas, or at least
one Western interpretation of Eastern ideas, to Western readers in
a meaningful way. Now that philosophers have to a large extent
exhausted their fascination with substantialist metaphysics, the
opportunity to explore Buddhist thoughts may be welcome.
(w tr o d u c tio p )
One of the many Buddhist nam es for ultimate reality is the Form
less Self. The term "self" is not w ithout its problems in the context
of Buddhist thought. One of the few utterances traceable to the
Buddha himself involves the statement that all things are w ithout
self. Early Buddhism (Theravada, Hinayana) was exceedingly con
cerned w ith uprooting this firmly entrenched and m uch cher
ished view of the self that w e cling to so tenaciously. That view of
the self is inextricably bound up w ith the B uddha's tw o other
statements that all things are suffering and all things are im per
manent. We ultimately "suffer" because there is no such thing as
a perm anently enduring self. In fact, one of the lasting insights of
the Buddha is that there is no enduring self in anyone or anything
at all.
On the other hand, a perhaps even more fundam ental and
comprehensive utterance traceable to the Buddha is that we must
at all costs avoid the two extremes of permanence (sasvata) and ni
hilism (uccheda). We all w ant to be able to say either that there is a
perm anent self or an immortal soul or else that there is nothing at
all b u t physiology, nerves, ganglia, blood and so forth, destined to
rot in the ground to which they are eventually entrusted. But any
one m aking either of these two statements is, according to the
Buddha, sim ply dead wrong. So there is no neat conceptual an
swer to this suprem e existential question of the self. But there are
XI
xii Introduct ion
Perhaps the clearest access to the question of the self in Dogen lies
in the fascicle of Shobogenzo entitled "Genjo-koan." Because all is
sues are so intimately and inextricably interwoven in Dogen's
thought, it is difficult and even artificial to isolate one question
from all the rest. Yet we m ust choose the m ost direct inroad avail
able to us to the question of the self.
i
2 T h e Formless Self
m yriad dharm as verify and confirm one's activity and this al
lows body-m ind to drop off. W hen one's body-m ind drops off,
the notion of the body-mind of the other drops off as well. Drop
ping off body-m ind (Shinjin datsuraku) allows the transparency
of enlightenm ent to enter. Enlightenment leaves no trace, as this
would imply a dualism between the dropped off body-m ind and
enlightenment. This traceless enlightenment, absolutely free from
any kind of dualism whatsoever, is then free to come forth and
continue for ever and ever.
Only when the self gives way to allow the myriad dharm as to
enter, does the self become w hat it truly is. Its true function is to
become utterly transparent to the myriad things of the world, be
they other people, realities of nature, man-made things or w h at
ever. In the words of D. T. Suzuki:
should be exerted and verified are not the dharm as, but the self.
The self is to be exerted, not asserted.
A c t iv i t y o j the Self
T o ta l exertion ( c j u j i n )
It is not the case that there are two mutually exclusive states:
enlightenment and illusion. Enlightenment and illusion cannot be
separated. Dogen reinterpreted the statement in the N irvana
Sutra: "all beings have the Buddha-nature" to mean: "all beings
Dogen 15
gory, and misses the flowers and the moon in their suchness, their
as-it-is-ness. O verpainting the landscape ruins the painting. Or
one can perhaps see this as-it-is-ness in a small child before it has
become self-conscious. It just is, and that is its utter charm.
Spring has the tone of spring, and autum n has the tone of
autumn; there is no escaping it. So when you w ant spring
or autum n to be different from w hat it is, notice that it can
only be as it is. Or w hen you w ant to keep spring or au
tum n as it is, reflect that it has no unchanging nature.15
singled out the im m ortal soul as w hat is real, as w hat is the self,
and had denigrated the body to being "the prison of the soul"
(Phaedo 81 e), Dogen w ants to free one from both body and mind.
What we think of as our m ind, the mental activity and represen
tation going on more or less automatically in our heads is not
w hat w e truly are, is not the self. It, too, m ust be dropped off.
Take, for example, James Joyce's Ulysses . This enorm ous book de
scribes w hat w ent on in one m an's head during a period of
twenty-four hours. Can we therefore say that this is w hat the
man is?
Buddhas are like this. You may w onder how many life
times buddhas have been practicing. Buddhas large and
small, although they are countless, all know their own
traces. You never know a buddha's trace w hen you are
not a buddha.
You may w onder why you do not know. The reason is
that, while buddhas see these traces w ith a buddha's eye,
those w ho are not buddhas do not have a buddha's eye,
and just notice the buddha's attributes.
Dogen 21
If the student attempts to look into his mind, and this is what
he is instructed to do if he is not to search for the Buddha-nature
outside of himself, w hat he encounters is the ordinary m ind's re
actions to w hat is going on around him. In other words, in spite of
his attem pt to "turn w ithin," he is still "outside." Actually, the
very fact that he is representing an "outside" and an "inside" du-
alistically, shows that he is getting nowhere. He is trying to enter
w hat Heidegger called "the cabinet of consciousness." However,
as Heidegger showed throughout Being and Time, we are always
already "out there" (in the world). This is the meaning of ek-sis-
tence and ek-stasis. The cabinet of consciousness is a Cartesian
construct.
When asked for his name, the boy does not reply that he has a
name, but states that there is a name, that is, Buddha-nature. The
master flatly retorts that the boy has no Buddha-nature. But the
boy, instead of being rebuked or defeated by that remark, replies
that he "has" no-Buddha-nature because Buddha-nature is empti
ness. Here again "no-Buddha-nature" m ust be understood to
lie beyond the opposition of Buddha-nature versus no-Buddha
nature.
Dogen continues:
are not even fully and truly alive. H isam atsu brings out the
unique feature of Zen that seeks to overcome the view of the
holy or divine as som ething transcendental and objective com
pletely outside of hum an being. Thus, H isam atsu accepts nei
ther the view that the usual state of hum an being as such is holy
nor the view that the holy is som ething objective and transcen
dent absolutely separate from hum an being. The antidote to the
first view could be found in N ietzsche's bitterly sarcastic re
mark: "All m en godlike!" H um an being in its usual state is not
automatically som ething to be proud of. One has only to take a
look at the w orld as it is today or, for that matter, as it often has
been. On the other hand, the idea of the holy as som ething u t
terly unattainable is hardly satisfying for the religious seeker
here and now.
One should not get into long disputes about w hether Bud
dha-nature exists or does not exist, but rather ask w hat kind of
thing that could be. How can one argue w hether something exists
or not w hen one doesn't know w hat it is? Is it Mind? It is perm a
nent or impermanent? W hat does it "do?"
Near the beginning of this chapter we touched upon the ques
tion of activity, dynamism, and exertion. We now continue that
scrutiny, focusing on the question of impermanence and tem po
rality. "Temporality" indicates how dynam ism takes place or
comes about. The term "dynam ism " by itself is too general to
convey a concrete meaning.
Temporality
We turn now to the fascicle on being-time. "We set the self out
in array and make that the whole w orld."34
W hat does it m ean to set the self out in array? "Array" seems
to im ply a positioning of the self in the things of the world. This
means that the self is fundam entally "outside" of itself in the
world; it is not an encapsulated subject. This self has nothing to
do w ith an isolated subject confronting objects. The eight state
ments w ith w hich the fascicle begins articulate how the self sets
itself out in array.
The self sets itself out as various things (staff, whisk, pillar,
lantern), as various people (Chang and Li) and as earth and
heaven. Hence, this self is not psychological, but cosmological.
However, Dogen then goes on to say that all these "things" are
basically so m any different times. This completely distances
"things" (a neutral term that can include people and the cosmos)
32 T he Formless Self
This view separates the subject from the various places that
he traverses and also separates the present time in which he re
sides in a fine vermilion palace from the time w hen he crossed the
river and mountain. This common sense view is not totally
wrong, but it does not exhaust the matter.
now reside in a fine palace, the river and m ountain are separated
and far aw ay from me. They are there w ith me, too. Where I am,
time does not just pass away.
Dogen does not explicitly deny the aspect of time that passes
away or flies by. But since that aspect of time is the sole one that
everybody is aware of, he presents the abiding aspect of time,
juhoi, dwelling in a dharma-situation, in uncompromisingly para
doxical statements.
Dogen is dealing w ith time in its two aspects: the one that
everyone is aware of, coming and going, passing away, and the
one that he seems to be the first to em phasize in this way, abid
ing in a dharm a-situation. It is true that thinkers in both the West
and the East have spoken of an eternal now, b u t their conception
was prim arily that of a timeless m om ent, a mom ent lifted out of
time. Dogen's abiding in a dharm a-situation is unique in that it
does n o t lie outside of time. O n the contrary, the present m o
m ent (nikon) affirms itself while negating past and future and at
the same time negates itself w hile affirming past and future
time.
It seems logically com prehensible enough to say that w hen
the present mom ent affirms itself, it negates past and future; and
that w hen it negates itself, it affirms past and future. But we m ust
ask: W hat does it m ean existentially to say that the present m o
m ent affirms or negates itself? The mom ent is not a hum an
agency. How, then, can it affirm or negate? Obviously not by any
thing like an act of will. The pow er of affirmation or negation
m ust be structurally inherent in the mom ent itself.
Of course, Dogen does not use abstract terminology like af
firm or negate; for negation he uses " swallow dow n" and for af
firmation "spit out." This is not only concrete and pictorial
language; it is actually visceral.
Most people are preoccupied with time's rolling away into the past.
They are less aware of the fact that it unfailingly arrives in the present
again and again.
follows: He did not set out to study himself, but that is initially
w hat he finds w hen he seeks to learn about the Buddha Way. The
deeper he goes into himself, the more he fails to find anything en
during and substantial. Gradually he "forgets" his self and in this
process the things of the world confirm him.
As stated in a previous passage of this fascicle, things have to
come to us; we cannot move toward them. Suddenly body and
mind drop off, and the person is free. At the same time all others
are freed of their bodies and minds as well. W hen body and m ind
have thoroughly dropped off, he is not preoccupied w ith or at
tached to body-mind or to the dropping off of body-mind, and all
traces of enlightenm ent disappear. He then does not "have" en
lightenment, but is it. This traceless enlightenment continues on
endlessly.
The man moving along in a boat looks at the shore and mis
takenly concludes that it is moving. In reality, of course, it is he
w ho is moving along. His error is due to the fact that he doesn't
understand the impermanence and "movem ent" of his own body
and mind. If he will b u t observe attentively his daily living, he
will realize not only that he is by no means perm anent, but also
that nothing at all is.
We shall consider two further passages from "Genjo-koan,"
and then move on to other fascicles. The first concerns the ques
Dogen 39
A lthough firewood "turns to" ash, it does not turn into or be
come ash. This instance of transition is one everyone takes for
granted. Less accessible w ould be the kind of transition epito
mized in the koan about tile-polishing.39 No one would accept the
idea that polishing a tile w ould turn it into a mirror. By analogy, it
is not clear to the average person how zazen can transform some
one into a Buddha. Dogen questions every kind of transition, the
kind people take for granted and also the kind that is problem
atic, and ultim ately rejects them all. Firewood is not firewood
before and ashes afterwards. Firewood is firewood at the dharm a-
situation of firewood and is possessed of before and after which,
so to speak, keep it in that dharm a-situation from which it does
not pass. Firewood is "beyond" before and after, a highly enig
matic statement, at least in the sense that it does not pass through
them. Similarly, and far more importantly, life does not become
40 The Formless S e lf
death nor death become life. (Plato's argum ents in the Phaedo to
the effect that to the universally accepted fact that w hat is bom ,
dies, there belongs the complementary idea that w hat dies, is re-
bom , w ould not be convincing to Dógen). Most people who have
watched someone die w ould surely adm it that there is something
utterly incomprehensible involved here. Even the birth of a baby,
which is, after all, not an absolute beginning, always has some
thing astonishing and miraculous about it. On a more m undane
level, w ho has ever observed when winter became spring?
Fish swim the water, and however much they swim, there
is no end to the water. Birds fly the sky, and how ever
much they fly there is no end to the sky. Yet the fish and
the birds from the first have never left the w ater and the
sky. When their need is great there is great activity; when
their need is small there is small activity. In this way none
ever fails to exert its every ability, and nowhere does any
fail to move and turn freely. Yet if a bird leaves the sky it
quickly dies; if a fish leaves the w ater it immediately per
ishes. We can realize that w ater means life [for the fish]
and the sky means life [for the bird]. It m ust be that the
bird means life [for the sky], and the fish means life [for
the water]; that life is the bird and life is the fish. A nd it
w ould be possible to proceed further [in this way]. It is
similar to this with practice and realization, and with the
lives of the practicers. Therefore [even] were there a bird
or fish that w anted to go through the sky or the w ater
after studying it thoroughly, it could in sky or w ater make
no path, attain no place.40
Nonantbropological Perspectives
Thus, the views of all beings are not the same. You should
question this m atter now. Are there many ways to see one
thing, or is it a mistake to see many forms as one thing?
You should pursue this beyond the limit of pursuit. Ac
cordingly, endeavors in practice-realization of the way are
not limited to one or two kinds. The ultimate realm has
one thousand kinds and ten thousand ways.
W hen we think about the meaning of this, it seems
that there is w ater for various beings but there is no orig
inal w ater—there is no w ater common to all types of be
ings. (102)
You should know that even though all things are liber
ated and not tied to anything, they abide in their own
phenom enal expression. However, w hen most hum an be
ings see w ater they only see that it flows unceasingly. This
is a limited hum an view; there are actually m any kinds of
flowing. Water flows on the earth, in the sky, upw ard and
dow nw ard. It can flow around a single curve or into
m any bottomless abysses. W hen it rises it becomes
clouds. W hen it descends it forms abysses. (102-3)
I
Beginning w ith a discussion of how to find a degree of calm
ness in the m idst of a busy life, the dialogue moves to the ques
tion of w h at it is that enables us to find that calm. Hisamatsu
states that this is aw akening to the "Calm" or "True Self." This
self is at w ork, for example, w hen Tillich is busily preparing his
lectures while traveling on trains. Tillich then asks w hether this
self m ust be conscious or possess a kind of psychological aware
ness. Hisam atsu replies that this awareness is not psychological,
nor is it even a state of mind; rather, it is No-Consciousness or
No-Mind. M indful of the contemporary efforts to get beyond the
subject-object split in consciousness, Tillich asks w hether that is
55
56 The Formless Self
What can it mean to say that in pure seeing the orange juice in a
sense disappears? Beyond saying that the orange juice disappears as an
object separated from the seeing subject (no subject-object split), what
is the "positive" content of such a statement? What does it mean to
see a glass of orange juice not as an object? This can perhaps be better
illustrated by an example from the realm of hearing that by its nature
has less to do with objects; as in the case of music, for instance, it has
nothing to do with objects at all.
The example consists of listening to a bell, a gong, perhaps in a
Zendo. If one listens in a certain, that is, a "pure" and noncon-
Hisamatsu 57
ceptual way, one does not hear a bell; one hears vibrations open
ing out into space, gradually receding into silence. One knows it
is a bell, but one does not hear a bell; one hears vibrations, one
hears vibrating. This is pure hearing. One is not thinking: that is a
bell; w hat kind of bell or gong is it? This cluster of questions and
opinions that usually accompany our experience is w hat is meant
by "mind" here. Therefore, pure hearing is No-Mind or the activ
ity of the Formless Self.
Pure hearing and pure seeing are beyond the dichotomy of
hearing and not hearing, seeing and not seeing. There is a well
known precedent for this w ith regard to thinking.
Since seeing and hearing are m ore tangible and thus perhaps
more accessible than thinking, they might be able to facilitate our
concrete understanding of w hat it means to be beyond the di
chotomy of seeing and not seeing, being, and nonbeing. The dia
logue does not help us here since Hisamatsu states that there is a
consciousness beyond seeing and not seeing, and Tillich says he
understands that to a certain extent and immediately shifts back
to his existential question of how to find calm in the m idst of
busyness.
W hat could a seeing that is beyond the dualism of seeing and
not seeing be like? An initial, easy answer is that this kind of see
ing w ould not see objects. Then w hat is seen? A presence. Not a
static object, but a dynamic, vibrant presencing. This is perhaps
most evident in certain paintings or draw ings of landscapes,
Western, and Eastern. Chinese landscape draw ings hardly depict
objects. They largely present em ptiness offset by some kind of
58 The Formless Self
The logos. But this is not the formless. The logos is the form
of God, w hich is bom . The actualization is often called by
him "being bom ." The logos is being bo m in us; Christ is
again bom through us, as is Mary, symbolically speaking.
This is not the Formless Self.3
II
The second dialogue begins w ith Tillich's question to H isa
matsu: how does he couple artistic form w ith the Formless Self?
H isam atsu's initial answer is that since it is self, the Formless Self
includes self-awareness and is active in expressing or presenting
itself through artistic form. Tillich focuses his question on the con
tent of, for example, a particular painting. H isam atsu's reply is
that w hat is expressing itself in the painting is always the Form
less Self. This Formless Self can express itself in anything; thus, it
m ay be said to have boundless contents. Tillich then states that
content w ould mean, for example, the sea, the m ountain or the
landscape. Hisam atsu denies this, stating that m ountains and
rivers, or flowers and birds constitute the M oment for the Form
less Self to express itself. Zen art has nothing to do with a realistic
copying of natural phenom ena. The discussion then centers on
62 T he Formless Self
the meaning of the German word, Moment , which was crucial for
Hegel's dialectic. A Moment can be understood either temporally,
in which case its m eaning is identical w ith that of the English
w ord "m om ent," or else it can be understood structurally as a
special kind of factor or catalyst. The latter sense is prim arily in
tended here. Tillich's conception of kairos, the ripe time, is now in
troduced as being close to w hat is m eant by M om ent . One is
rem inded of Brutus' speech in Shakespeare's Julius Caesar.
We can only see the Formless Self w ithin form, since forms
are always w hat we see.
Tillich finds in H isam atsu's remarks an affinity with w hat he
calls "the depth of being" in things. For both thinkers art trans
mits something beyond itself: for Tillich this leads to God as the
ultimate source of being; for Hisamatsu it leads to m an's true or
Formless Self.
Hisamatsu 63
The discussion now leads out of the realm of art into that of
religion itself. H isam atsu finds the ground of and need for reli
gion in the fact that hum an being not only has, but is, an ultimate
antimony. The interpreter, Richard De Martino, answers for
Hisamatsu:
Tillich's own view of the ground of and need for religion, its
raison d'être, lies in the experience of belonging to the Infinite
and of being excluded from it at the same time. The goal of reli
gion is thus reunion with the Infinite. This reunion is available to
us only in a fragm entary way; total reunion can only be antici
pated. Hisamatsu replies:
Ill
The third and last dialogue begins with a brief discussion
of freedom. With regard to the painting of Dancing Pu-tai , Hisa
matsu states that the predom inant Zen quality in this work is un-
Hisamatsu 65
attached freedom. To the inquiry what it is that the figure is free from,
Hisamatsu replies freedom from everything, and De Martino explicates:
Here we see the difficulty Hisamatsu has with Tillich's Being itself.
In contrast to the Formless Self, which Hisamatsu asserts to be beyond the
opposition of form-formless, Being itself still stands in dualistic opposition
to nonbeing. Hisamatsu then states that Zen is unattached to anything,
including Buddha and especially unattachment itself. This is an important
point. First of all, "unattachment" is a better term for the more common
"detachment" which tends to be construed as having nothing to do with
something, as total indifference. Second, one can get insidiously attached
to the idea of unattachment, just as one can take great pride in being
humble or modest. If one is attached to the idea of freedom, one can
hardly be said to be free. Consequently, what is needed is a freedom that
is free of the duality of freedom-unfreedom.
Tillich comes back to the main objection he has been raising
throughout all the dialogue: that the specific form of Dancing Pu tai must
have an inner relationship to ultimate reality or the Formless Self.
Ultimate formlessness and the finite form must be related in some way.
Hisamatsu replies that in its self-concretiza tion the Formless Self can
assume innumerable forms. Tillich per
66 The Formless Self
can see itself in that thing and in any other thing that has gone
outside of itself, em ptied and negated itself.
We are now facing the limitations of these dialogues, points
on which Christianity and Buddhism cannot reach total unanim
ity. For Zen, the claim is that m an can escape the situation of fini-
tude by himself becoming Buddha or the ultimate. In spite of the
nontraditional elements in his position, as a Christian, Tillich can
not embrace this possibility. Tillich's "mysticism" remained w hat
he called it, a "nature mysticism"; the union was w ith nature, not
with God. Actually, union is a w ord that Tillich rejected, prefer
ring the more cautious term "participation."
Returning to the discussion of Hua-yen, Tillich's position re
mains on the level of riji-muge, no obstruction between universal
and particular, whereas Zen moves on to the level of jiji-muge, no
obstruction between particular and particular. The universal is
lacking. Every particular is fulfilled and every particular is com
prehended within every other.
The formulation between universal and particular no obstruc
tion generates the view of a universal apart from the particular.
For this reason Hisamatsu prefers the expression "nonparticular"
(negation of the particular) over universal. On the basis of the non
duality of any thing and its own negation rests the nonduality of
any thing and any other thing. Thus, each thing "is" and is "in"
every other thing.
The discussion now centers on the meaning of this "is," a
point touched u pon previously. For Tillich, "is" indicates partici
pation. Everything participates in and is an expression of the ulti
mate. In contrast, for Zen each thing is a Self-ex pression of
ultimacy. Tillich's reply is that speaking for himself, he would be
shy to say this. The two thinkers seem to have come as close to
each other as they are able; of necessity a final difference remains.
For Tillich the relation of the particular to the ultimate is that of
participation; for Hisamatsu it is nonduality.
Trying to grasp the Zen point of view, Tillich proffers the
statem ent that whereas a dialectical identification of the particu
70 T h e Formless Self
Oriental Nothingness
Nothing,
as
1
Empty concept w ithout object
ens rationis
2 3
Empty object of a concept Empty intuition w ithout
nihil privativum object ens imaginarius
4
Empty object w ithout concept
nihil negativum17
the body, the senses, emotions, and desires. There is nothing free
or formless about our m inds either. Formlessness means dis
carding the ordinary self, the self that has form and can still be
differentiated.
Hisam atsu places considerable emphasis on the fact that he is
not talking about the idea of a formless self, but about its existen
tial reality.
Taking up the statem ent from the Nirvana Sutra that "all sen
tient beings have the Buddha-nature, a statem ent that Dogen
am ended to read "all sentient beings are the Buddha-nature,
H isam atsu explains that this should not be understood to mean
that they are fundam entally Buddha but as yet have not realized
this. That w ould constitute a distinction between the Original and
the manifest.
86 T he Formless S elf
99
100 The Formless Self
N ishitani distances this Great D oubt not only from any kind
of Cartesian methodological doubt, b u t also from anything psy
chological at all. He is not talking about a state of mind, but about
reality.
Through the Great Doubt the self is brought to experience the
nihility or relative nothingness lying at its ground. For Nishitani
this nihility is intrinsically present in the structure of self, but has
now erupted full-blown in the West as the crisis of nihilism in
which we now live.
Basically, N ishitani w ants to get beyond consciousness and
self-consciousness that are bound up with the structure of subject-
object. That this does not constitute a descent into the psycholog
ical unconscious should be clear. He is not talking about any kind
of m ental state, b u t about reality. As long as we are dealing with
consciousness or self-consciousness we can only represent, objec
tify and substantialize reality, that is, distort it.
In an effort to convey more concretely w hat he means by
a self that is not to be equated w ith consciousness or self-
consciousness, Nishitani speaks of subjectivity and ecstasis. The
subjectivity he has in mind is not part of the duality of subject-ob-
ject, b u t lies beyond this duality and, for that matter, any possible
duality. It is not the subjectivity of the ego. How then, are w e to
think this subjectivity?
Nishitani, our moving our limbs, clouds floating in the sky, w ater
flowing, leaves falling, and blossoms scattering are all ultimately
non-Form. To adopt these forms of non-Form as the form of the
self is precisely to realize (in the double sense) the Formless Self.
We need to address N ishitani's treatm ent of reality and illu
sion that does not coincide w ith any Western conceptions of that
relation. In the chapter on "The Personal and the Impersonal,"
Nishitani states that person is an appearance w ith nothing at all
behind it to make an appearance. How are w e to think this kind
of appearance?
The term appearance is essentially ambiguous. On the one
hand, it can be equated w ith illusion. For example, He appeared to
be healthy, but was in reality quite ill. On the other hand, appear
ance can indicate something real. For example, He appeared in the
doorway. He p u t in an appearance at the meeting. In the first in
stance, appearance masks something that does not appear. In the
second, no such duality is involved. Yet in a sense something can
be said to be behind the appearance insofar as the person cannot be
entirely equated w ith his appearance in the doorw ay or at the
meeting. A principal distinction between the two instances lies in
the lack of any element of illusion or deception in the second.
Nishitani's discussion of appearance lies closer to the second
instance in that it involves no duality and no illusion in the sense
that something behind it is being concealed. A nd yet it does in
volve some kind of illusion. N ishitani speaks here of "shadow "
and "mask."
gle stone or blade of grass dem ands as much from us. The
pine dem ands that we learn of the pine, the bamboo that
we learn of bamboo. By pulling away from our ordinary
self-centered mode of being (where, in our attem pts to
grasp the self, we get caught in its grasp), and by taking
hold of things where things have a hold on themselves, so
do we revert to the "m iddle" of things themselves. (Of
course, this "m iddle" does not denote an "inside," as I
pointed out earlier on.) (140)
Here we have m oved from the field of reason, the field of tra
ditional Western philosophy, to the field of nihility, the field of ni
hilism discovered, opened up and diagnosed by Nietzsche, to the
field of iunyatd. W hen things are at one w ith em ptiness by relin
quishing their substantial m ode of being, they are in w hat Nishi
tani variously terms the m iddle m ode of being, the nonobjective
(nonobjectified) m ode of being as they are in themselves, and
samadhi-being. Nishitani distances this "m iddle" from the m iddle
as it has been conceived on the field of reason as the Aristotelian
m ean or Hegelian mediation. Nishitani's m iddle is immediate, in
his expression "at hand" and "underfoot." We are, so to speak,
standing on it.
as some of the depictions of life are, they can be pretty bleak (for
example, Beckett). But as the theologian Paul Tillich said in The
Courage To Be, the fact that these artists can express their despair
is an indication that they have in some measure transcended it.14
There is undoubtedly some truth in this, but we m ust ask: Is
this the only "transcendence" open to us, to give expression to
despair?
It is w ith problem s such as these that Nishitani is wrestling.
Following Nietzsche, he recognized the contem porary situation
of nihilism, "the uncanny guest at the door," faced it squarely and
struggled to overcome it, I believe successfully. We m ust continue
for a while longer to circle around these main "them es" of
samadhi- being, in itself (jitai ), m iddle and the logic of soku hi (is
and is not).
no distraction on the part of the senses and w hen the m ind is not
agitated, one is tranquil in one's activity. One acquires a steadi
ness that is unshakeable, imperturbable. Basho's haiku about the
frog jum ping into the pond might serve as an example. There was
complete stillness before the frog jum ped. But his jum ping does
not disturb the stillness; rather, it only points it up, offsets and
heightens it. After the plop has subsided, we really hear absolute
stillness.
Hisamatsu is careful to point out that all of these seven char
acteristics are present in a Zen art w ork or in everyday activity.
They are so close to each other as to be inseparable. They charac
terize the expression of the Formless Self, its taking on form and
working therein. Otherwise we w ould remain at the eighth stage
of the ox-herding pictures, the em pty circle. We m ust go on to the
ninth stage showing an old m an and a younger one meeting
along a roadside. Ueda Shizuteru gives an interesting interpreta
tion of the last three stages, eight, nine, and ten, as being no
longer, as in the preceding stages, a m atter of gradual progres
sion, but a kind of oscillating back and forth. The direction is re
versible, m eaning that one can move freely between nothingness,
nature, and hum an communication.
This same thing, the selfless self, is for its part only fully
real insofar as it is able to realize itself in a totally different
way in each aspect of this three-fold transformation: as ab
solute nothingness, as the simplicity of nature, and as the
double self of communication. The final three stages por
tray as it were the three-in-one character of the true self.
This means that the self is never "there" but always in the
process of transformation, always fitted to its circum
stances and likewise always proceeding from out of itself,
at one moment passing away into nothingness unhindered
and without a trace, at another, blooming in the flowers as
the selfless self, and at a third, in the encounter w ith the
other, converting that very encounter into its own self.21
i 30 T h e Formless Self
The key sentence here is the self is never "there." It never per
sists statically throughout change. Thus the prime characteristic of
the Western conception of self, its continuity of consciousness and
self-identity, is conspicuously absent. We shall return to this point
in a discussion of the length dimension, living the life of history
while transcending history, the suprahistorical living of history.
But first w e shall discuss the depth dimension. Of course,
these three "aspects" of the Formless Self are hardly separable ex
cept for purposes of analysis. There remains of necessity a certain
artificiality in discussing them in isolation. As stated before, we
have to some extent already discussed this dim ension in our dis
cussion of the dimension of width.
The whole Kyoto school takes religion extremely seriously.
Hisam atsu asks where in man is the "m om ent" which prevents
man from rem aining merely man? Put in a different way, where
in m an is the "moment" whereby he needs religion? "Moment" is
being used in the Hegelian sense of a crucial factor. Hisamatsu is
seeking a standpoint which is neither a theistic heteronomy nor
rational autonomy. In other words, he is seeking a standpoint
which is absolutely autonom ous but not based solely on reason,
although it includes the rational. The medieval type religions
based on theonomy have been replaced by the hum anism of au
tonom ous reason. While affirming the element of autonomy,
Hisam atsu sees in the "m oment" in man which prevents him
from remaining merely man the necessity to get beyond rational
humanism.
W hat is this "mom ent?" It is to be found in the ultimate an
tinomy lying at the basis of the self. Hisamatsu interprets this ul
timate antinom y in terms of sin and death, whereby "sin" must
be taken in a qualified sense since it has not always been consid
ered central in Buddhism. When Sakyamuni escaped his father's
palace, w hat he encountered and w hat became the "moment" for
his religious quest was not release from sin, but from sickness, old
age, and death. Nevertheless, we w ant to see how Hisamatsu in
terprets sin, since he includes it in his discussion.
Nishitani 13i
the Great Death. This m ust not rem ain a mere concept; it m ust
be realized existentially.
It m ight be said tentatively that w hat "precedes" the Great
Death is the Great Doubt or doubting-mass, although, strictly
speaking, there is no continuity of temporal sequence here, rather
a complete turn-about (pravrtti) and shattering of w hat went
before.
One reason there is such a break in continuity is that the way
of being of the Formless Self comes breaking through the bottom
of ultimate antinomy.
the ultim ate source of all our w orries and anxieties. This antin
omy is insoluble. It is insoluble because w hat we w ant is pure,
eternal life, and this is impossible. It is impossible because life as
w e know and live it is fundam entally life-death. When Buddhism
states that we are living and dying at every moment, this is no
mere metaphor. O ur lives are shot through with loss, disappoint
ment, failure, and the like. Of course, we also experience gain, ful
fillment, and success. But they are fundam entally temporary.
N othing lasts. N othing is achieved once and for all. This is not a
cause for regret or despair. It is simple impermanence, the im per
manence that w e are.
But that is not all. This is going on at every moment. My con
sciousness is not, so to speak, a steady stream of thoughts and
feelings, as the expression "stream of consciousness" w ould indi
cate. It arises and perishes every instant. Otherwise, how could
one explain the occurrence of a new idea or of any kind of cre
ativity. The language that the Kyoto school constantly uses to de
scribe our root source is that of bottomlessness. O ut of this
bottomlessness our awareness arises and perishes at every in
stant. We shall return to this rather fascinating question later.
It is in terms of this ultim ate antinom y that the concept of
original sin is to be understood. The "sin" lies in the ultimate an
tinomy that forms the basis of reason. This is not our fault, nor is
anyone else responsible. It is simply the w ay things are. Thus,
original sin is not a moral question, but an ontological one.
H ow do we get free of this antinomy? Since the ultimate an
tinom y forms the basis of reason, we as rational beings cannot
solve it. The solution of m ost religions, Christianity and Shin
Buddhism, for example, lies in the hope of a future redem ption
by another being, be it Christ or Amida Buddha. Hisamatsu
firmly rejects this point of view.
Negation takes place in the movem ent from the unaw akened
self to the Formless Self. W hat m ust be negated is the self based
on reason and the senses. Affirmation, however, takes place w hen
the rational self is resuscitated with the Formless Self as its source.
The fact that it is resuscitated or resurrected means that some
kind of death has taken place here, the death of the rational self.
When it reemerges from the Formless Self it freely lives the ratio
nal life while transcending reason.
We turn now to the length dim ension, that of the Suprahis-
torical. H isam atsu uses this w ord in a different sense, say, from
Nietzsche, for w hom it m eant that w hich is above time and
timeless. For Hisam atsu, on the contrary, it is the source of time
and space, that out of w hich they come. Hence it is in no w ay a
negation of time and space, nor can it sim ply be equated w ith
them.
hilistic. They are both, and this forms the contradiction at the
heart of all things.
In other words, the total being is itself the task. That the
total being, which is the task, elucidates itself in a total
manner by means of itself, is to live philosophy. (12)
The Zen Master Ma-tsu Tao-i used the term heijdshin [or
dinary mind] in its original sense in which it is contrasted
w ith shojishin (Life-and-death mind). . . . With both Ma
tsu and N an-ch'uan, heijoshin means the Ordinary Mind
awakened to its true Self and functioning in its everyday
activities—that is, w hat the author calls the creation of
Suprahistorical history. (18)
In this existential theory, the present does not follow the past
horizontally in some kind of succession. Rather, the present
flashes up vertically out of an infinite openness lying "beneath
our feet," w hat N ishitani calls the "hom e-ground of the present."
This is the dim ension Nishitani means w hen he speaks of "time
w ithout beginning or end."
Here Dasein "breaks out of" time, that is, it breaks out of the
conceptual overlay that it imposes on the sheer happening of in-
stantaneity. The present does not follow the past in continuity; it
arises out of the bottomless depth. That is w hy newness is possi
ble: new ideas, new beginnings, new experiences. Why do we
tend to get bored w ith w hat we have, w hom w e know, w hat we
are doing? Because we fail to perceive this newness. Thus, we say
that nothing lasts. Indeed nothing does last, not even for an in
stant. But we expect things to last horizontally, to persist through
out time. Even should we realize this vertical dimension of
infinite openness, we w ould still to some extent continue to expe
rience time horizontally. This is simply inevitable. Nishitani ex
presses this fact by stating that the second form of Dasein, that of
transcendence, become manifest only in unison w ith the absolute
immanence of the first form, that of immanence.
The instant occurs as a dharani gathering all pasts and all futures,
perhaps analogous to the m anner in w hich for Heidegger the
thing gathers the fourfold of earth, heaven, the godlike ones, and
Nishitani 147
You m ust see all the various things of the whole world as
so many times. These things do not get in each other's way
any more than various times get in the way of each other.40
The one direction alone in which the true way of things is not
to be found is its quality of passing away, a quality that Dogen
does not deny, b u t feels that it is all that people see in time. In ad
dition to the quality of passing by, and even that Dogen under
stands differently from w hat most people think, Dogen sees the
crucial aspect of dwelling in a dharm a-situation or a dharm a-
position.
As the time right now is all there ever is, each being-time
is w ithout exception entire time. A being-grass and being-
form are both times. Entire being, the entire world, exists
in the time of each and every now. Just reflect: right now,
is there an entire being or an entire w orld missing from
your present time, or not?48
that fire is burning, we could say that the fire is in its fire-
samadhi).49
We set the self out in array and make that the whole
world. You m ust see all the various things of the whole
w orld as so many times.65
What does it mean, to set the self out in array? The self has no
form; it is no-thing. Thus, it is intrinsically capable of ecstasis, of
i64 The Formless Self
On a Portrait of Myself
Cold lake, for thousands of yards, soaks up sky color.
Evening quiet: a fish of brocade scales reaches bottom, then goes
first this way, then that way; arrow notch splits.
Endless waters surface moonlight brilliant.67
With regard to the question in w hat sense a Formless Self can be a
self, we would in conclusion be able to reply that if selfhood is not
to be conceived egotistically as a separate self opposed and hos
tile to everything other than itself, formlessness offers an eminent
possibility of rethinking selfhood. Overcoming and abandoning
its anxious sense of itself as an encapsulated separate "I," the self
gains the w ondrous freedom and openness to emerge in joyous
compassion from the shackles of its self-imposed boundaries.
165
\N o te s
C h a p t e r 1: Dögen
1. Hee-Jin Kim, Flowers of Emptiness, (Lewiston, NY: The Edwin
Mellen Press, 1985).
2. D. T. Suzuki, The Essence of Buddhism (Kyoto: Bunko, 1948), p. 65.
3. L udw ig W ittgenstein, Traktatus Logico-Philosophicus (London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1958), p. 150.
4. Wittgenstein, Traktatus, p. 56.
5. Ibid., p. 51.
6. Ibid.
7. Dogen Kigen, Mystical Realist (Tucson: University of Arizona
Press, 1975), p. 221.
8. Kim, Flowers of Emptiness, p. 197.
9. Francis Cook, How to Raise an Ox (Los Angeles, CA: Center Pub
lications, 1978), p. 55.
10. Kim, Flowers of Emptiness, p. 201.
11. Muchu-setsumu (Dreams within Dreams), quoted in Kim, Mystical
Realist, p. 113.
12. Ibid., p. 273.
13. Ibid., p. 276.
14. Kazuaki Tanahashi, ed., Moon in a Dewdrop (San Francisco:
North Point Press, 1985), p. 162. "Only Buddha and Buddha" (Yuibutsu
Yobutsu).
15. Ibid.
16. Ibid.
17. Ibid., p. 164.
167
i68 Notes to Chapter 1
18. Ibid.
19. Ibid., p. 167.
20. Norman Waddell and Abe Masao, trans., "Buddha-nature," The
Eastern Buddhist 8, no. 2:100-1.
21. Ibid., p. 101.
22. Ibid.
23. Ibid., p. 108.
24. Ibid., pp. 111-12.
25. Philosophical Studies ofJapan, vol. Ii, 1960, p. 93.
26. Eastern Buddhist, 10, no. 1:10.
27. Ibid., p. 12.
28. "Buddha-nature/' Eastern Buddhist, 9, no. 1:90.
29. Eastern Buddhist, 7, no. 2:100.
30. Ibid., pp. 102-4.
31. Ibid., p. 105.
32. Ibid., p. 91.
33. Ibid., p. 104.
34. "Uji," Eastern Buddhist, 12, no. 1:116.
35. Kim, "Uji," in Flowers of Emptiness (see n. 1 above), p. 229.
36. Norman Waddell and Abe Masao, trans., "Genjo-koan," Eastern
Buddhist 5, no. 2:134-35.
37. Ibid., p. 125.
38. Ibid., p. 136.
39. D iscussed in "Koky," (The Primordial Mirror) (Tokyo: Naka-
yama, 1983), vol. 3, p. 45.
40. Ibid., p. 38.
41. As a college student, I w as assigned to read Levy-Bruhl. When I
read that for primitive man everything w as alive, my first thought was:
one could never be alone.
42. Tanahashi, ed., "Mountains and Waters Sutra," in Moon in a
Dewdrop, pp. 97-8.
43. Tanahashi, ed., "Only Buddha knows Buddha," in Moon in a
Dewdrop, p. 161.
44. Ibid., pp. 151-52.
45. Ibid., p. 162.
46. Wiinschbarkeiten.
47. Ibid.
Notes to Chapter 2 (69
48. Ibid.
49. Ibid., p. 167.
C h a p t e r 2: Hisamatsu
2. Ibid., p. 3.
3. Traceable back to Indian thought, m appo is the last and worst in
the series of world epochs.
4. Ibid., p. 97.
5. Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness, Jan. Van Bragt, trans. (Berke
ley: University of California, 1982), p. 4.
6. Nishitani, Nishida-Kitaro, Yanamoto Seisaka and James W.
H eisig, trans. (Berkeley: University of California, 1991), p. 112.
7. Ibid., p. 114.
8. Ennead VI, 4, Loeb Library, vol. 7, p. 317.
9. Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness (see ch. 3, n. 5), p. 154.
10. Ibid., p. 155.
11. Nishitani, Nishida Kitard, p. 102.
12. Eastern Buddhist 5, no. 2:133.
13. Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness, pp. 199-200.
14. Paul Tillich, The Courage To Be (N ew Haven: Yale University
Press), 1959.
15. Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness (see ch. 3, n. 5), p. 216.
16. Eastern Buddhist 25, no. 1:61-62.
17. Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness, p. 129.
18. Ibid., p. 130.
19. Ibid., p. 164.
20. Hisamatsu, Zen and the Fine Arts, p. 51.
21. Eastern Buddhist 15, no. 1:22.
22. Hisamatsu, "Ultimate Crisis and Resurrection," in Eastern Bud
dhist 8, no. 1:21-22.
23. Hisamatsu, "Zen: Its Meaning for M odem Civilization," in East
ern Buddhist 1, no. 1:32.
24. Eastern Buddhist 8, no. 1:14.
25. Eastern Buddhist 8, no. 2:50.
26. Eastern Buddhist 8, no. 2:52.
27. Ibid.
28. Eastern Buddhist, ibid., p. 40.
29. Eastern Buddhist 8, no. 2:14.
30. Eastern Buddhist 8, no. 2:64.
31. Eastern Buddhist 12, no. 1:4.
32. Eastern Buddhist 12, no. 1:5.
33. Eastern Buddhist 8, no. i:14.
17 2 Notes to Chapter 3
173
i 74 Index