Weber 2017 LogFunctions
Weber 2017 LogFunctions
Introduction
Logarithms as functions differ from logarithms as numbers (e.g. determining log 2 1024 ) or opera-
tors (e.g. using logarithms to manipulate expressions and solve equations), especially when it comes
to teaching and learning (Smith & Confrey, 1994). To make logarithms as numbers and operators
meaningful and thus more accessible to learners, some subject matter knowledge for teaching has
been developed by Weber (2016). This was achieved by combining the theoretical construct of
basic models (or ‘Grundvorstellungen’, vom Hofe & Blum, 2016) with the construct of operational-
ity and structurality (Sfard, 1991; 2008). The present paper focuses on the functional side of loga-
rithms and its teaching, namely on the sketching of logarithmic graphs. After recalling various con-
ceptualisations of logarithms and analysing some students’ difficulties in graphing logarithmic
functions, four basic models are discussed with regard to their explanatory power for graphing loga-
rithmic functions. Because of the mathematical analogy between logarithms and division (cf. We-
ber, 2016), some arguments used here are analogous to those familiar from the teaching of division
(Ball, Thames, & Phelps, 2008; Greer, 1992; vom Hofe & Blum, 2016).
Background
Various conceptualisations of the logarithmic concept
As we are interested in different ways of viewing logarithms, it is worth taking a quick look at the
history of mathematics. Several properties of logarithms have been discovered since their invention
in the early 17th century (for details, see Weber, 2016):
(P1) Napier and Bürgi conceptualised logarithms as numbers that count divisions. For example,
log 2 8 equals 3 because 8 has to be divided by 2 three times (to yield 1). In analogy to the
standard division algorithm, this interpretation can be extended to a logarithm algorithm for
the manual calculation of logarithms proceeding by repeated division down to 1 instead of re-
In: T. Dooley & G. Gueudet (Eds.) (2017), Proceedings of the Tenth Congress of the European Society for Research in
Mathematics Education CERME10 (pp. 537–544). Dublin, Ireland: DCU Institute of Education and ERME.
peated subtraction down to 0: one divides instead of subtracting, exponentiates by 10 instead
of dividing by 10, trying to yield 1 instead of 0 (ibid., pp. 79–80).
(P2) The conception found in current collections of formulas only became possible after Descartes
had invented the symbol for powers, an. This notation enabled logarithms to be seen as parti-
cular exponents, a property that Euler used in his 1765 definition log a b = x :⇔ a x = b . More-
over, the left-hand equation can be read not only arithmetically (focusing on the number x ),
but also functionally, taking “ log ” as a function of the argument b .
(P3) Another conceptualisation was provided by Cauchy in the 19th century. He proved that loga-
rithmic functions are, apart from a factor, the only continuous solutions Φ of the functional
equation Φ(x ⋅ y) = Φ(x) + Φ(y) ( x > 0 , y > 0 ). Specifying the logarithmic function in implicit
form, this conceptualisation is a purely functional one.
Each of the properties (P1) to (P3) highlights a particular aspect of logarithms. Because, from a ma-
thematical perspective, they are all equivalent, each property could serve as a definition of the con-
cept. From an epistemological perspective, however, their qualities are distinct, as discussed below.
Logarithmic functions, their graphing and some of the difficulties students face
Logarithmic functions are essential in calculus and for modelling processes, which is why they are
taught at secondary level and in undergraduate courses. As with other types of functions, there are
several challenges for students, such as when it comes to interpreting graphs verbally, or deciding
whether or not a given graph represents a certain function (e.g. Leinhardt, Zaslavsky, & Stein, 1990;
Markovits, Eylon, & Bruckheimer, 1986; 1989). For instance, one well-known student misconcep-
tions says that any function should be linear (e.g. Sfard, 2008, p. 21). An issue specific to logarith-
mic functions is the confusion of the logarithmic graph with the “combined graph” (Kastberg, 2002,
p. 129), i.e. with the exponential and the logarithmic graph merged into a single image. A similar
misconception reported is students viewing the graphs of y = 2 x and y = log 2 x as being “exactly
the same” (Williams, 2011, p. 54). Misconceptions like these might be caused by the standard in-
troduction of logarithmic functions as inverse exponential functions.
As space precludes other aspects, this paper deals with the graphing of logarithmic functions only,
i.e. with manually sketching the graph of a function in a Cartesian plane, based on its logarithmic
equation y = f (x) . To analyse some of the difficulties that can arise here, the following steps (S1)
to (S4) involved in graphing logarithmic functions are identified:
(S1) Determining and calculating an appropriate number of pairs (table of values): This step in-
volves selecting a finite series of x -values that lie within the domain of the function, which in
the case of logarithmic functions is a proper subset of the real numbers. In particular, one has
to determine a first x -value, a last x -value, and the pattern the series follows (e.g., if there is
a pattern, whether the difference or the ratio of two consecutive x -values is constant).
(S2) Drawing the axes and scales, and plotting the corresponding points (“local construction,”
Leinhardt et al., 1990, p. 13): The plotted points form the supporting points of the graph to be
drawn.
538
(S3) Connecting the supporting points with a line segment (“prediction,” ibid., p. 13): This step
involves making a conjecture based on the visual characteristics of the plotted points. It will
therefore be referred to here as “graphical interpolation”. It includes decisions regarding the
curvature and the degree of smoothness of the line (e.g. differentiable at the points).
(S4) Extending the graph to the right and left of the line segment: This is a second prediction to
make, based on a part of the graph, referred to here as “graphical extrapolation”: Does the
graph straighten out to a straight line? If not, in what way does its curvature change? Is it
bounded, does it have vertical asymptotes, intercepts with the axes, etc.?
In each of these steps, the lack of a meaningful basis for argumentation can result in difficulties:
Firstly, determining the domain in (S1) is a known issue (e.g. Markovits et al., 1986, 1989). As an
illustration, Figure 1 shows two students’ graphs of the function y = log 2 (x) − 3 . Student A’s graph
extrapolated to the left intersects the x -axis and thus exceeds the domain. Moreover, his x -values
form an arithmetic progression, which is not optimal in terms of the corresponding y -values.1
Figure 1: Students’ documents showing their tables of values for f (x) = 2 x+3 and g(x) = log 2 (x) − 3 ,
together with the corresponding graphs (left side: student A, male; right side: student B, female)
Secondly, graphs are sometimes thought of as isolated points (Leinhardt et al., 1990), or the sup-
porting points may be interpolated with a straight line (Markovits et al., 1989). Figure 1 shows that
in their third step (S3), both students chose the graphical interpolations to be a more or less straight
line, at least piecewise. And thirdly, in (S4), the graph is sometimes not extended beyond the range
of the supporting points at all, or only by a little; or there may be an extrapolation to one side which
suggests a progressive growth of the logarithmic function (cf. student B in Figure 1).
1
The two first- and second-year undergraduate students (18 and 19 years old) had attended a precalculus course held at
a public university on the east coast of the USA in spring 2016. Logarithmic functions had been introduced in the tradi-
tional way, i.e. as inverse exponential functions. The documents shown in Figure 1 are from their final examination.
The exact wording of the task was: “Consider the two functions f (x) = 2 x+3 and g(x) = log 2 (x) − 3 : a) For each func-
tion, create a table of values, choosing your x -values carefully. b) Graph both functions on the same set of axes.”
539
Students’ difficulties like these give rise to the following question: What mathematical knowledge
for teaching logarithmic functions could endow learners with a meaningful basis for argumentation
in order to potentially reduce their difficulties?
540
Basic models for logarithms as numbers and operators
To help students access and understand a certain mathematical concept, it is sometimes embedded
in a context that is realistic or, if this is not possible, in a context that is at least familiar to the stu-
dents (cf. the Dutch “realistic mathematics education”, van den Heuvel-Panhuizen, 2003). In the
German-speaking countries, basic models is a theoretical construct to capture what is meant by
making concepts accessible, or understanding them (referred to as “Grundvorstellungen”, vom Hofe
& Blum, 2016). Put simply, a basic model for a concept must have two characteristics: Firstly, it is
an interpretation of that concept in a context in which students are likely to have more experience,
and secondly, it has a certain explanatory power, that is, it is flexible enough to be applicable to dif-
ferent mathematical situations. For instance, when division is seen within the everyday context of
fair-sharing, an equation such as 30 ÷ 1 2 = 60 is difficult to follow or perform. However, within
the context of splitting-up or measuring, it can be explained as “ 1 2 fits into 30 sixty times”. Both
basic models of division, fair-sharing and splitting-up, are thus indispensable for understanding di-
vision (referred to as “partitive” and “quotative division”, Greer, 1992). For Ball and colleagues,
they constitute the specialized content knowledge for teaching division (Ball et al., 2008, p. 400).
For the teaching of logarithmic functions, no basic models are known thus far. For logarithms as
numbers and operators, however, I have previously identified four models (for details, see Weber,
2016):
(BM1) Logarithms as multiplicative measuring: The logarithm of a number b (to base a ) indicates
how often the base a fits into the number b as a factor. This interpretation derives from the
algorithm mentioned above (P1), or from the relation b / a log ab = 1 . Example: log 2 1024 can
be simplified to 10 because 2 as a factor fits into 1024 ten times. As it generates result, mul-
tiplicative measuring emphasises the operational side of logarithms most strongly.
(BM2) Logarithms as counting the number of digits: The (common) logarithm of a number b finds
the number of digits of b needed to represent b in positional notation, minus one. This in-
terpretation derives from the fact that the number of digits of any natural number n (in dec-
imal notation) is equal to ⎢⎣log10n⎥⎦ +1 . Example: The number 22000 has 603 digits when
written out in decimal notation because log10 22000 ≈ 602.06 . In describing the effect it has
on numbers and thus dealing with a specific application, this interpretation could be used to
support the operational explanation of logarithms in the case of numbers.
(BM3) Logarithms as decreasing the hierarchy level: The logarithm of an expression reduces third-
level operations (powers, roots) to second-level operations (multiplications, divisions), and it
reduces second-level operations to first-level operations (additions, subtractions). This inter-
pretation derives from property (P3). Example: The expression log cd can be expanded to
1 logc + logd ) because the taking of square roots, as a third-level operation, becomes di-
2(
viding by two, and multiplication of the variables becomes addition of their logarithms. In
describing the effect it has on expressions and thus dealing with another specific application,
this interpretation could support the operational explanation of logarithms for expressions.
541
(BM4) Logarithms as inverse exponents: The logarithm of a number (or expression) to base a is
the exponent by which the base a must be raised to yield the number (or expression). This
derives from property (P2), and is useful for solving exponential equations. Example: 40 as
a power of 2 is approximately 2 5.32 because log 2 40 ≈ 5.32 . Because this interpretation re-
lates logarithms to another object (exponents), it reflects the structural view of experts.
In the next section, this collection of operational and structural basic models will be shown to have
the potential to serve as a basis for argumentation for the graphing of logarithmic functions as well.
542
4. Growth of the graph: As we have seen above, both graphical interpolation and graphical extrapo-
lation can cause many problems (cf. (S3), (S4)). Referring to the basic model “logarithms as
counting the number of digits” (BM2), the growth of logarithms can be recognized as non-
proportional: In general, doubling a number does not double its number of digits. Furthermore, it
is strictly increasing and unbounded above because this is how the number of digits behaves.
Thus neither the interpolated nor the extrapolated graph can be a straight line, but must increase
monotonically, growing degressively.
Discussion
This work builds on my earlier paper about the basic models for logarithms as numbers and opera-
tors (Weber, 2016). There, the supposition was discussed that the standard textbook explanation
log a b = x :⇔ a x = b could be too compact or “dense” for many learners to serve as a meaningful
basis of argumentation, which may be why dealing with logarithms often turns into mere manipula-
tion of formal symbols, causing students’ difficulties (ibid., pp. 85–86). If this applies to logarith-
mic functions as well, an alternative, broader way of introducing and teaching logarithms is re-
quired. For this reason, this paper discusses some content knowledge for the teaching of logarithmic
functions. The guiding theoretical construct is that of basic models (vom Hofe & Blum, 2016),
combined with the construct of operationality and structurality (Sfard, 1991, 2008). The four basic
models, developed previously for logarithms as numbers and operators (Weber, 2016), are shown
here to have some explanatory power for logarithmic functions and their graphing, that is, that they
could potentially help to make logarithms meaningful and reduce some common difficulties that
students encounter.
This paper lays some theoretical foundations for future research. To what extent an approach with
multiple basic models can facilitate more meaningful teaching and understanding in the actual
classroom will have to be investigated carefully. There has been a first encouraging episode from
my own teaching, where a student who in general struggles with mathematics realized why loga-
rithmic functions cannot be proportional: Making use of basic model (BM2), not the standard inter-
pretation (BM4), she argued precisely as in point 4 in the previous section. A teaching experiment is
therefore planned in the near future to study the affordances and limitations of the basic models,
exploring the discourse of students who are taught not just one but four interpretations of the loga-
rithmic concept. In analogy to the teaching and learning of division with multiple models, a crucial
point will be the students’ shift from the multiple basic models proposed here to the object of loga-
rithmic functions. Or, to cite Freudenthal (1975, as quoted in van den Heuvel-Panhuizen, 2003, p.
15, italics in original): “Models of something are after-images of a piece of given reality; models for
something are pre-images for a piece of to-be-created reality”.
543
References
Ball, D., Thames, M., & Phelps, G. (2008). Content knowledge for teaching: what makes it special?
Journal of Teacher Education, 59(5), 389–407.
Berezovski, T., & Zazkis, R. (2006). Logarithms: Snapshots from two tasks. In J. Novotná, M.
Moraová, M. Krátká, & N. Stehlíková (Eds.), Proceedings of the 30th Conference of the Interna-
tional Group for the PME (vol. 2, pp. 145–152). Prague: PME.
Greer, B. (1992). Multiplication and division as models of situations. In D. A. Grouws (Ed.), Hand-
book for research on mathematics teaching and learning (pp. 276–295). New York: Macmillan.
Kastberg, (2002). Understanding mathematical concepts: the case of the logarithmic function (Un-
published doctoral thesis). Athens, GA: University of Georgia.
Lauritzen, P. (2012). Conceptual and procedural knowledge of mathematical functions. Doctoral
dissertation at the University of Eastern Finland (34), Joensuu, Finland.
Leinhardt, G., Zaslavsky, O., & Stein, M. (1990). Functions, graphs, and graphing: Tasks, learning
and teaching. Review of Educational Research, 60(1), 1–64.
Markovits, Z., Eylon, B., & Bruckheimer, M. (1986). Functions today and yesterday. For the
Learning of Mathematics, 6(2), 18–24, 28.
Markovits, Z., Eylon, B., & Bruckheimer, M. (1989). Difficulties students have with the function
concept. In A. Coxford, & A. Shulte (Eds.), The Ideas of Algebra, K–12 (pp. 43–60), Reston,
VA: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics.
Sfard, A. (1991). On the dual nature of mathematical conceptions: Reflections on processes and ob-
jects as different sides of the same coin. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 22, 1–36.
Sfard, A. (2008). Thinking as communicating: Human development, the growth of discourses and
mathematizing. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Smith, E., & Confrey, J. (1994). Multiplicative structures and the development of logarithms: what
was lost by the invention of functions? In G. Harel, & J. Confrey (Eds.), The development of
multiplicative reasoning in the learning of mathematics (pp. 331–360). Albany, NY: State Uni-
versity of New York Press.
Van den Heuvel-Panhuizen, M. (2003). The didactical use of models in realistic mathematics edu-
cation: an example from a longitudinal trajectory on percentage. Educational Studies in Mathe-
matics, 54, 9–35.
Vom Hofe, R., & Blum, W. (2016). “Grundvorstellungen” as a category of subject-matter didactics.
Journal für Mathematik-Didaktik, 37(Suppl. 1), 225–254.
Weber, C. (2016). Making logarithms accessible — operational and structural basic models for log-
arithms. Journal für Mathematik-Didaktik, 37(Suppl. 1), 69–98.
Williams, H. (2011). A conceptual framework for student understanding of logarithms (Unpub-
lished master’s thesis). Provo, UT: Brigham Young University.
544