Courtney D. Fugate (Editor), John Hymers (Editor) - Baumgarten and Kant On The Foundations of Practical Philosophy-Oxford University Press (2024)
Courtney D. Fugate (Editor), John Hymers (Editor) - Baumgarten and Kant On The Foundations of Practical Philosophy-Oxford University Press (2024)
https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192873538.001.0001
Published: 2024 Online ISBN: 9780191976162 Print ISBN: 9780192873538
FRONT MATTER
Copyright Page
https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192873538.002.0003 Page iv
Published: June 2024
United Kingdom
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above
Data available
ISBN 978–0–19–287353–8
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.001.0001
Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and
for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials
https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192873538.001.0001
Published: 2024 Online ISBN: 9780191976162 Print ISBN: 9780192873538
FRONT MATTER
Acknowledgments
Published: June 2024
The editors would like to thank all the contributors for their hard work on this volume and for their
considerable patience; Peter Momtchilo at Oxford University Press for his promotion of the study of
eighteenth-century German philosophy; and Micah Summers for help with the bibliography and editing of
the volume. The editors are also grateful to Dolarine Sonia Fonceca for diligently shepherding this book
through production.
Courtney D. Fugate would also like to thank Florida State University for its support. Most of all, he would like
to dedicate this very small work to the memory of his dear parents, Gary and Marlene: always and forever on
my mind.
John Hymers would like to thank La Salle University for its support, Matthew Connolly for assistance, and
his wife Yvette for her undeserved understanding. John would also like to dedicate this book to the memory
p. vi of his parents, Lawrence and Anna Marie.
Abbreviations
Apart from the Critique of Pure Reason, which is cited by the A and B edition paginations,
the writings of Immanuel Kant are cited either by an abbreviation specific to the work or
else by the general abbreviation AA, followed by the appropriate volume and page number
of the Akademie-Ausgabe of his collected writings. Unless otherwise noted, all translations of
Kant are from the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant and all translations of
Baumgarten’s Metaphysics and Elements of First Practical Philosophy are from the recent
English translations by Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers (Baumgarten 2013, 2020).
Other multi-volume editions are cited in a similar manner with the volume followed by a
colon. Unless preceded by a section mark (§), all references are to chapter, volume, or page
numbers. Superscripts after dates indicate edition numbers and the dates outside of square
brackets indicate the primary edition used for the citation.
Wolff ’s Works
WAN Ausführliche Nachricht von seinen eigenen Schrifften die er in deutscher
Sprache von den verschiedenen Theilen der Welt-Weißheit
herausgegeben, auf Verlangen ans Licht gestellet ([1726¹] 1733²)
WDL Vernünfftige Gedancken von den Kräften des menschlichen Verstandes
(Wolff [1712–13¹] 1754¹⁴)
WDM Vernünfftige Gedancken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des
Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt (Wolff [1720¹] 1751¹¹)
WDP Discursus praeliminaris de philosophia in genere (Prefixed to Wolff
1740)
WGNV Grundsätze des Natur- und Völckerrechts (Wolff 1754)
WIN Ius naturae methodo scientifica pertractatum (Wolff 1740–8)
WO Philosophia prima seu ontologia methodo scientifica pertractata (Wolff
[1730¹] 1736²)
WPE Psychologica empirica, methodo scientifica pertractata (Wolff [1732¹]
1738²)
WPM Philosophia moralis, sive ethica, methodo scientifica pertractata (Wolff
1750–3)
WPPU Philosophia practica universalis, methodo scientifica pertractata (Wolff
1738–9)
WRP Ratio praelectionum wolfianarum in mathesin et philosophiam
universam (Wolff [1718¹] 1735⁴)
WTL Vernünfftige Gedancken von der Menschen Thun und Lassen (Wolff
[1720] 1733²)
Baumgarten’s Works
BA Aesthetica (Baumgarten 1750–8)
BAL Acroasis logica (Baumgarten 1761)
x
https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192873538.001.0001
Published: 2024 Online ISBN: 9780191976162 Print ISBN: 9780192873538
FRONT MATTER
Contributors
Published: June 2024
Alexander Aichele
, Martin Luther University Halle-Wittenberg
Stefano Bacin
, Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of Milan
Stefanie Buchenau
, Professor of German and European History of Ideas, University Paris 8 Saint-Denis
Courtney D. Fugate
, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Florida State University
Paul Guyer
, Jonathan Nelson Professor Emeritus of Humanities and Philosophy, Brown University
John Hymers
, Associate Professor of Philosophy, La Salle University
Heiner F. Klemme
, Professor of Philosophy, Martin Luther University Halle-Wittenberg
Gualtiero Lorini
, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Catholic University of Milan
Frederick Rauscher
, Professor of Philosophy, Michigan State University
Sonja Schierbaum
, Principal Investigator of the Emmy Noether Group Practical Grounds, University of Würzburg
Clemens Schwaiger
, Professor of Philosophy, Katholische Stiftungshochschule (Benediktbeuern)
Fiorella Tomassini
, Postdoctoral Researcher, University of Groningen
Michael Walschots
, Postdoctoral Fellow, Johannes Gutenberg University Mainz
Allen Wood
p. xii , Ruth Norman Halls Professor, Indiana University
Introduction
Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers
¹ Ursula Niggli (Baumgarten 1999) translated the three difficult and dense prefaces to Baumgarten’s
Metaphysica found in the first four editions (Baumgarten 1739¹, 1743², 1750³, 1757⁴), and Günter
Gawlick and Lothar Kreimendahl were the first to translate the entire book into German (Baumgarten
2011), whose work was then followed by Fugate and Hymers (Baumgarten 2013), and most recently by
Luc Langlois and Émilie-Jade Poliquin (Baumgarten 2019b). Jean-Yves Pranchère translated
Meditationes philosophicae de nonnullis ad poema pertinentibus (Baumgarten 1735) as L’invention de
l’esthétique—Méditations philosophiques sur quelques sujets se rapportant au poème (Baumgarten
2017a; an earlier German translation is Baumgarten 1983a). The University of California Press has
recently dusted off Karl Aschenbrenner and William B. Holther’s 1954 English translation of the
Meditationes and reprinted the Reflections on Poetry (Baumgarten 2022) under their Voices Revived
series. The Initia philosophiae practicae primae (Baumgarten 1760) was translated into French by
Langlois, Mathieu Robitaille and Poliquin as Principes de la philosophie pratique première (in Kant
2015). Alexander Aichele also translated the same work as Anfangsgründe der praktischen Metaphysik
(Baumgarten 2019a), as did Fugate and Hymers under the title Elements of First Practical Philosophy
(Baumgarten 2020). The Aesthetica, first translated by Matsuo Hiroshi into Japanese (Baumgarten
1983b; revised edition 2016), has since been translated into German by Dagmar Mirbach (Baumgarten
2007) and, in an annotated edition, into Italian by Francesco Piselli (Baumgarten 2017b); Mirbach’s
Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Introduction In: Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy.
Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press. © Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers 2024.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0001
2 .
volume also contains many passages from the Metaphysica and Ethica philosophica. Hymers’s trans-
lation of the Ethica philosophica (Baumgarten 1740¹, 1751², 1763³), has just appeared with Bloomsbury
(Baumgarten 2024).
² AA mistakenly labels this as the 4th edition (19:7).
³ Notable examples of the latter include the distinction between the contradiction-in-conception
and contradiction-in-willing tests (Refl 6741, 19:146), the universal natural law formula of the
3
categorical imperative, the concept of the highest good as the heterogeneous combination of virtue and
happiness, and Kant’s understanding and criticism of alternative moral theories (perfectionism,
Epicureanism, Stoicism, etc.).
⁴ See Chapter 1 below. Bacin, following Schwaiger, further argues that Kant’s choice was personal,
grounded in his philosophical appreciation of Baumgarten. Cf. Bacin (2015, 17–19) for a closely argued
account of Kant’s interest in Baumgarten.
⁵ See Chapter 1 below. Schwaiger argues that although Baumgarten borrows the term “obligation”
from Wolff, Baumgarten not only deviates from Wolff in making it the central theme of his ethics
(following Köhler) but also substantially refines the concept.
⁶ The Rousseauean root of this can be seen, e.g. in Refl 6667, 19:128.
⁷ Which is a point that reemerges in the second Critique (KpV 5:37).
4 .
⁸ For more on this, see Guyer (2007) and (2016a) as well as the chapters by Guyer and Fugate in this
volume.
⁹ Another basic concept Kant modifies in a decisive way is that of what it means to consider
something “in itself,” “absolutely,” or “unconditionally,” which has obvious implications for the
concepts of unconditional obligation, unconditional good, and so forth. For more on this see, BM
30–2 and ch. 10 below.
5
fundamental principles for all practical philosophy as such. This is then stressed
directly in the definition: its principles are the “firsts” that constitute any piece of
philosophy a piece of practical philosophy, and so therefore belong essentially to
(are “proper” to) each practical discipline as such. And so it is because first
practical philosophy’s principles are proper to each practical discipline, that they
are also “common” to them all.
In this Baumgarten goes beyond Wolff by providing the ground for the
discipline’s universality, while at the same time strengthening the analogy with
metaphysics and opening the way for a “metaphysics of morals.”¹⁰ But he also
makes fundamental changes when spelling out the implications of this definition;
for by the “practical disciplines,” Baumgarten here intends those contained in “the
science of the obligations of a person that are to be known without faith”
(BIP §1),¹¹ which are therefore “to be deduced by an apodictic method through
principles that are certain and not through testimonies, divine or human autho-
rities, or accounts” (BIP §2). Thus, whereas Wolff had placed the defining feature
of the practical disciplines in their “affective” role in determining the will’s free
actions, Baumgarten places it in their demonstration of the laws of such and the
elucidation of the manner in which these laws make certain actions morally
necessary; that is, he places it in rationally articulating the concept of “obligation”
and all its essential features and implications. What is more, to the extent that
Baumgarten defines philosophy in general as what can be known “without faith,”
practical philosophy for him must be restricted to the demonstration of those laws
that can be known in such a way, that is, to natural laws, as well as to the concepts
required for understanding how these can come to determine our actions natu-
rally (see BIP §69; also, BM §430, 470–3, 482).
This priority of the natural over the supernatural in morality, although also
present in Wolff, receives indeed a radically new foundation in two considerations
that are distinctive to Baumgarten’s thought more generally and so are worth
mentioning here. The first is his theory about how we are to decide which should
be the first principle or principles for any science, including practical philosophy;
these, he explains, are to be selected based on a “wise” judgment, which chooses its
¹⁰ The same point is made in Schwaiger’s chapter in this volume (Chapter 1). BIP §7: “Just as
metaphysics is related to all the rest of the disciplines, so too is first practical philosophy related to the
rest of the practical disciplines (§6, BM §1).” It is interesting that Kant himself reverts—despite his use
of Baumgarten’s textbook—to the title of “allgemeinen” practical philosophy when discussing the
discipline (GMS 4:390). This possibly reflects Kant’s critical reevaluation of Baumgarten’s (compara-
tive) conception of “first” principles, which the former regards as grounding at most a comparative
generality, not strict universality (see Fugate 2015, esp. 74f.). Thus, the emphasis in the Groundwork is
on the mere generality of Wolff ’s theory of willing.
¹¹ The emphasis on obligation in the very definition of the practical disciplines at least complicates
Schwaiger’s suggestion that Baumgarten’s moral philosophy only appears to be centered on this
concept—a fact decisive in relation to Kant—because he failed to publish an entire overview of first
practical philosophy, but rather only its elements, i.e. the BIP. Cf. Schwaiger’s chapter below
(Chapter 1).
6 .
principles in view of their being the best suited to the realization of the ends and
perfections of the science among the greatest number of human beings (BIP §89).
Thus, since the “natural” is, by definition, what can be known directly through our
experience of things and their own internal principles or natures, it follows that if
there is a natural and relatively most self-evident principle of practical philosophy,
then it will also be the best first principle and so will be the one chosen as such by
the best practical philosopher. Indeed, this priority of the natural with respect to
human beings seems to be the root motivation for Baumgarten’s inclusion of the
condition “without faith” in his definitions of all philosophical disciplines includ-
ing first practical philosophy (BIP §90); for dependence on faith, rather than on
our direct experience of nature, already indicates an absence of self-evidence and
thus a deficiency in the power to directly convince and motivate by naturally
available means. The second consideration that lends priority to the natural—and
this really underwrites the previous one from a metaphysical point of view—lies in
Baumgarten’s argument that God himself prioritizes natural over supernatural
order in all his choices, and thus also in the choice of moral laws (BIP §69; BM
§495, 497, 498). Together, these two considerations can be seen as providing a
large part of the philosophical grounding for Baumgarten’s closer adherence,
when compared with Wolff, to traditional accounts of natural law.
Finally, much has been made of Baumgarten’s “softening” of Wolff ’s rational-
ism with respect to practical philosophy.¹² And this is surely an important insight
into Baumgarten’s motivations in the Elements; for it is hard to deny that Wolff ’s
formulation of perfectionism fails to fully capture the complexity of moral moti-
vation and tends toward a sort of elitism, two features that Baumgarten worked
hard to remedy in line with his Pietist leanings.¹³ But it bears emphasizing that this
points us to only one aspect of Baumgarten’s originality with respect to Wolff ’s
practical philosophy, the greater part of which has yet to be explored, or perhaps
even noticed (further points are mentioned particularly in Schwaiger’s chapter
below, but can also be found throughout the others). To take just one instance: As
central as the concept of the “good” must be to any moral philosophy, it has yet to
be emphasized that (let alone explained why) Baumgarten radically departs from
Wolff ’s definition of it. For Wolff, “good” is a concept first arising within and so
belonging properly to empirical psychology, where it is defined as “what perfects
us and our own state” (WDM §422; WPE §554). It is thus essentially human-
This Volume
¹⁴ E.g. it allows Baumgarten to defend the Scholastic convertibility of being and goodness (BM
§100), something Wolff only mentions in passing and in principle cannot accept according to his
definitions (WO §503).
¹⁵ For more on this, see Chapters 5 and 10 in this volume.
¹⁶ Schwaiger (2011a) being the first.
8 .
rational ones; he limits ethics to the possible, hence identifying and eliminating
any “chimerical ethics” that would demand the impossible; he develops the concept
of “moral egoism” (a term which the tradition has largely ascribed to Kant) to
overcome Francke’s complaint that Wolffian ethics is inherently solipsistic; and
finally he distinguishes moving from living cognition, refining the latter into one
of the chief perfections demanded by practical philosophy, thereby psychologizing
ethics. Kant, argues Schwaiger, is terminologically dependent on Baumgarten,
and his own terminological precision is often owing to his confrontation with
Baumgarten. Kant also developed the idea of a metaphysics of morality precisely
from Baumgarten’s concept of a first practical philosophy, although the two
approaches are quite disparate qua content. For example, Baumgarten gave Kant
his focus on duty. Moreover, Baumgarten is the first to use the term “imperative”
morally, which Kant goes on to sharpen, whitling away any idea that a moral
imperative could belong to the sensory or psychological. Finally, and fatefully,
Baumgarten detached happiness from ethics, and sees religion as playing a key
role in the latter. Thus, Schwaiger argues that it would be hard to account for
Kant’s interest in Baumgarten were the latter simply an orthodox Wolffian whose
strength is found merely in mastering and taming the vast output of his school-
master. Rather, the twin but opposing poles of rationalism and Pietism gave
Baumgarten a unique framework for developing the thought of Wolff, and in
the process, incalculably influencing Kant.
Stefanie Buchenau’s chapter (“Mathematizing Morality”) provides a different
perspective on the developmental story told in Schwaiger’s work by framing it
from two related vantage points. The first lies in Wolff ’s original intention to
reform moral philosophy into a genuine and well-articulated science by realizing
the dream of earlier philosophers to treat it according to the mathematical method
or mathesis universalis; the second in his aim to do so in a way that would also be
eminently useful to all of humanity as such, and thus to develop a method that is
both popular and maximally suited to fostering moral improvement. Against this
background, Buchenau argues, we should see Baumgarten’s Elements as a radical
criticism of Wolff ’s view that these two aims are in fact consistent when understood
in relation to the actual, finite nature of the human beings that such a mathesis is
supposed to improve. In effect, Baumgarten’s “softening” of Wolffian practical
rationalism—which Schwaiger shows also has Pietist roots—can equally be viewed
as aiming to fulfill Wolff ’s own popular project by drawing on resources from
outside of the Wolffian practical mathesis, particularly in the realm of practical
psychology and aesthetics. On this basis, Buchenau then argues that Kant’s moral
philosophy can be interpreted, in a certain respect, as a return to the Wolffian
scheme, which explains his (qualified) praise for Wolff ’s universal practical philos-
ophy and his attempt to positively relate his work to it. For, just like Wolff, Kant aims
to establish a foundation for moral philosophy—containing a “mathematically”
systematic account of basic moral principles—that is capable in turn of supporting
9
a truly popular doctrine, one thus aimed at moral improvement. Taken together,
the first two chapters of this volume demonstrate the complexity involved in
situating Baumgarten in relation to the two dominant philosophical tendencies of
the day, namely, Pietism and Wolffianism, and consequently of understanding his
mediating role between Wolff and Kant.
In the next chapter (“Obligation as Moral Necessitation and Nötigung”), Heiner
F. Klemme casts a critical eye on the standard claim that Baumgarten’s innovative
use of the term “Nötigung” (Lat. “necessitatio,” practical necessitation) and Kant’s
adoption of it indicates a closeness of their philosophical positions. While not
denying Kant’s dependence on Baumgarten’s terminology or other possible effects
this might have had on Kant’s thought, Klemme advances the debate in two
important ways. First, by situating Baumgarten’s usage within the larger termi-
nological tradition (particularly with reference to Leibniz’s French writings), he
shows that Kant’s usage can be seen as indicative of a philosophically motivated
distancing of his views from Leibniz’s position according to which obligation is
never a matter of necessitation. This, Klemme notes, brings Kant in fact closer to
Baumgarten in one respect, since the latter uses Nötigung precisely to further
develop the space for understanding a tension within willing according to which
one aspect of the will constrains another. Second, Klemme drives home the point
that, in another and deeper sense, the way such a space is conceptualized in the
two thinkers is completely distinct, and so in this respect there simply can be no
question of influence or of borrowing. Baumgarten conceptualizes this space
deterministically and causally, thus developing a psychological cum metaphysical
picture of this tension. Kant, on the other hand, rejects any such approach to
moral motivation, insisting instead on what Klemme characterizes as a “norma-
tive” account of this space and the tension that fills it between what one does and
what one ought to do in view of one’s moral necessitation. In this way, Klemme
brings the debate to a new stage; the question is no longer whether and to what
extent Kant directly borrows from Baumgarten, but rather—given the sharpness
in the fundamental shift from Baumgarten’s psychological cum metaphysical
approach to a normative¹⁷ one—what is the deeper basis for such an influence
at all? Moreover, by what logic was Kant able to redeploy Baumgarten’s concepts,
with their various modifications, on this utterly distinct normative footing?
Sonja Schierbaum and Michael Walschots’s contribution to our volume
(“Necessitation, Constraint, and Reluctant Action”) confirms, but also qualifies
and extends, a thesis mentioned by Klemme in his chapter, namely, that Leibniz
and thinkers closer to him see obligation as inconsistent with constraint, that Kant
differs by seeing obligation as involving it essentially, and that Baumgarten’s
¹⁷ One might already here start to wonder if this characterization is sufficiently precise to frame the
question; for Baumgarten would surely have regarded his account as normative as well, though not, to
be sure, in the same sense as Klemme ascribes to Kant.
10 .
theory of moral necessitation forms the intermediate bridge between the two
positions. Schierbaum and Walschots begin by carefully presenting the textual
and philosophical basis for the claim that Wolff holds obligation and constraint to
be incompatible, the central reason being that he equates free action with action
done gladly, which he holds to be the direct opposite of acting under constraint.
The only exception is when we must choose the lesser of two evils; here alone can
we act with displeasure, but only so as to avoid an even greater displeasure.
According to the authors, Baumgarten departs from Wolff ’s language and theory
in several crucial ways, which allow him to regard a special sort of constraint as
compatible with, though not required for, genuine obligation. The main point is
that Baumgarten develops a model of choice and motivation wherein it makes
sense to speak of deliberating in a state of conflict with ourselves, but also then
producing the grounds that turn choice decisively in the direction of our obliga-
tion. It is the condition that such grounds be produced by us or internally, in a way
that essentially presupposes freedom, that makes such constraint both moral and
compatible with natural obligation. Nevertheless, Baumgarten holds it as at least
possible for one to act without constraint, although only in the sense that the
preponderance of motives to fulfill our obligations is so overwhelming that it
doesn’t make sense to speak of it as reluctant and hence constrained.¹⁸ Turning
then to Kant, Schierbaum and Walschots echo Klemme’s claims by emphasizing
the difference between Baumgarten’s psychological approach and Kant’s norma-
tive approach to moral necessitation. But despite this difference, they argue, Kant
can be seen in one very important respect as radicalizing Baumgarten’s view by
holding constraint to be not only consistent with obligation but even equivalent to
it when understood normatively. On such an interpretation, we can see that the
sort of psychological model of interiority developed by Baumgarten—wherein a
dual self must produce (at least in part) the grounds that are to necessitate it
morally—bears a striking structural analogy with Kant’s normative account of
self-constraint and perhaps also of autonomy.
Moving beyond a consideration of the concept of obligation alone, the next
chapter compares the accounts of its grounds and status in the two philosophers.
Here Stefano Bacin argues that in §37 of the Elements, Baumgarten provides
important qualifications to the controversial notion of “objective morality,”
which had long been at the center of the dispute between moral realists like
of reason necessary for the possibility of a happiness that will be the product of
divine distributive justice for those worthy of such.
The next two chapters focus on problems related to the theory of moral
imputation, that is, the philosophical account of the grounds and procedures
involved in determining and judging whether a morally relevant action has been
performed by an agent and whether this has been performed in accordance with a
law, and more particularly which law. In “Baumgarten and Kant on Conscience,”
Allen Wood uncovers and compares the shared juridical and forensic models of
moral conscience in Baumgarten and Kant. As he shows, both see obligation of
every sort as involving, essentially, a judgment pronounced by a court or forum
that renders verdicts on actions and agents. Moral conscience, in particular, is
viewed by both as an internal capacity, structured analogously to an external court
of law, for making certain kinds of judgments about one’s own actions. And like
all courts, a central function of this capacity is deciding the imputation of both
deed and law. For Baumgarten, in fact, Wood shows that the primary judgment of
conscience is one of imputation. Baumgarten thus sees such judgments as inter-
preting the meaning of actions and as applying moral obligation more or less
wisely and accurately. For this reason, a key moral principle in his Elements is that
we should strive to act according to our “best” conscience. Kant, by contrast,
distinguishes judgments about which actions we are to perform or avoid from the
judgment specific to conscience itself. Like Baumgarten, he thinks we should of
course follow our best judgment, but with the awareness that it is always fallible.
Yet, in order to act with moral decisiveness, Kant also thinks what we need is a
distinct sort of judgment on the question: Are we guilty or innocent before our
own judgment when it comes to doing our best to determine what we ought to do,
and in assessing our actions from the standpoint of morality and not mere
legality? Kant holds that conscience, properly understood in this way, judges us
primarily in relation to this last question. And here the judgment of conscience is
infallible—not in the sense that it cannot be objectively mistaken in what we do—
but rather in the sense in which a court of last instance is procedurally infallible: it
has the final say about each particular decision.
Turning from the topic of imputation in general, Alexander Aichele—author of
the only full-length study of Baumgarten’s practical philosophy (2017) and
German translator of the Elements (Baumgarten 2019a)—points to a fundamental
problem in Kant’s specific theory of imputation, namely, that of how it is actually
to be applied in regard to real agents and in concrete circumstances. As Aichele
stresses, one of Kant’s central innovations is to articulate an absolutely pure, a
priori principle for moral judgment. This has the great advantage over previous
theories, such as Baumgarten’s, that it perfectly simplifies—or at least promises to
simplify—the judgment of action types and thus of maxims drawn up for possible
actions. By virtue of this move, moral judgment for Kant is rendered independent
from any empirical elements and becomes purely a matter of the logical
13
consistency of the proposed maxim with itself and with the a priori conditions of
willing. But the cost of this simplification is a total opacity regarding whether an
agent actually, in retrospect, acted on a certain maxim or not when they per-
formed a physical act. In other words, the purity of the law brings with it the non-
empirical character of the act of determination by such a law such that it now
becomes difficult to understand how empirical behavior—the only kind there is,
after all—can be assessed for its morality. And while this does, indeed, simplify the
judgment of action types on the one side, on the other it therefore creates
perhaps insuperable problems for the practice of moral imputation, which is
the retrospective judgment that an agent actually performed (and so freely) an
empirical act (physical imputation) and that this empirical action exemplifies a
type of action mentioned in a law (imputation of law). As Aichele notes,
Kant does not provide a theory of imputation in his published writings, but
instead in the Metaphysics of Morals, simply gestures toward the sort of theory
fully worked out and explained by Baumgarten as a major part of his Elements.
The problem here, however, is that such a theory can be so robust only because
it was designed to deal with a naturalistic, and thus empirically informed,
conception of freedom and agency. Hence, it is doubtful that Kant can make
use of Baumgarten’s philosophy as he seems to want to do, at least not without
providing a much deeper explanation of how this would work. In this way,
Aichele’s chapter (“Imputation: Applying Practical Norms in Kant and
Baumgarten”) demonstrates a key instance in which the essential difference
between Kant’s and Baumgarten’s approaches yields both advantages and dis-
advantages for each side.
Until very recently, Kant’s moral philosophy has been viewed—as he clearly at
points intended it to be—as a principled rejection of the sort of moral perfection-
ism found in the writings of Wolff and especially Baumgarten. The next two
chapters, however, not only question the adequacy of this view but argue indeed
that when seen through the lens of its development, Kant’s philosophy can and
should be thought of as a new form of moral perfectionism. In “Perfection and
Self-Perfection in Baumgarten and Kant,” Paul Guyer revisits and extends his
previous work on Kant’s relation to the perfectionist moral tradition, focusing
more specifically on Baumgarten’s role in that relationship. In the first part of
his chapter, Guyer takes a closer look at Kant’s criticisms of perfectionism—its
supposed vagueness and emptiness as a moral principle—noting that these are
neither entirely fair to Baumgarten’s version, nor do they rule out perfectionism
per se. Indeed, he argues that Kant’s own moral philosophy can and should be,
and in fact sometimes is by Kant himself, understood to be a new form of
perfectionism, one however that aims at the perfection of the human will qua
transcendentally free, rather than at the perfection of human nature in any
other, naturalistic sense. In the second and third parts of the chapter, Guyer
then digs into the consequences this has for understanding Kant’s adoption and
14 .
redrawing of the lines between what is regarded as internal and external in various
domains. For example, what is “internal” psychologically in Baumgarten is often
regarded by Kant as “external” in respect to freedom (or in respect to what is
normative, one might be tempted to say). But as Rauscher shows through his
exhaustive examination of the texts, and especially of Kant’s reflections on
Baumgarten’s textbook, the story is not as simple in all cases, particularly those
involving the division between internal and external freedom itself. Here Rauscher
advances the thesis that Kant’s relationship to Baumgarten is far more complex
than previously thought and that examining it in detail shows how the seemingly
clean distinction between the domains of virtue and right in Kant’s published
writings masks a deeper complexity that allows for other divisions cutting across
our duties in different and important ways.
Fiorella Tomassini’s comparative study (“Three Models of Natural Right:
Baumgarten, Achenwall, and Kant”) evaluates the relationship between Kant’s
published Doctrine of Right and the natural right tradition as represented
by Baumgarten and Gottfried Achenwall. In her careful analysis, Tomassini
identifies one fundamental goal shared by all three—namely, that of establishing
a systematic doctrine of right based in reason alone—as well as three ways
in which Kant distances himself from their approaches. These latter consist
in his: (1) distinguishing laws of right, as based on freedom, from laws of
nature; (2) rejecting any attempt to found such laws in an end imposed on
human beings, replacing this instead by a self-imposed end; and (3) rejecting the
idea that laws of right must have their origin in the will of a superior, divine will.
A key point Tomassini establishes is that Kant’s division between ethics and
right, which places the distinguishing mark in the latter’s connection to coer-
cion, has no basis in Baumgarten’s Elements, but is instead borrowed from
Achenwall’s Natural Right.
We close the volume with John Hymers’ historical-comparative account of the
genesis of Baumgarten’s doctrine of just war within the framework of the right of
nature, and his influence on Kant’s philosophy of peace (“War, Violence, and
Punishment in Baumgarten’s Philosophy of Right”). With his explicit cosmopol-
itanism, Kant has often been considered the philosophical father of the United
Nations and the role of his work, but especially of Perpetual Peace, within
contemporary theories of just war has been greatly celebrated. Indeed, the very
UN Charter itself takes up a number of Kantian principles, even if imperfectly
elaborated, and among these we find the strict principle of defensive war. By
looking at the breadth of Baumgarten’s philosophy of right, i.e. the Initia, the
Ethica philosophica, Ius naturae, as well as the Sciagraphia encyclopaediae philo-
sophicae, Hymers analyzes Baumgarten’s own position on just war, showing
how it developed from the thought of Hugo Grotius and Christian Wolff ’s
emendations thereto. However, along with his fellow Young Wolves Köhler and
Achenwall, Baumgarten departed at times in a striking manner from the tradition,
16 .
even while retaining the natural right-basis for a just war theory. Among his
innovations we find a three-fold temporality of defense against harm, the restric-
tion that a just war is limited strictly to defense against harm to oneself, a strict
distinction between force and violence, and, fatefully, a prohibition against puni-
tive war. Especially the doctrine of defensive war and its corollary excluding
punitive war, will show up in Kant. Thus, Baumgarten played a not unimportant
role in establishing the UN’s position on war.
1
The Inventor of the Practical Imperative
A Portrait of Baumgarten’s Ethics between
Wolff and Kant
Clemens Schwaiger
* Translator’s note: Translated by John Hymers from chapters 7 and 8 (§§37–46) of Alexander
Gottlieb Baumgarten—ein intellektuelles Porträt. Studien zur Metaphysik und Ethik von Kants Leitautor
(Schwaiger 2011a, 115–43). All notes below are from Schwaiger’s text, unless clearly indicated
otherwise.
¹ Editors’ note: For how the situation has changed since 2011, when this piece was published, see the
Introduction to this volume. In respect to monographs, see Aichele (2017).
Clemens Schwaiger, The Inventor of the Practical Imperative: A Portrait of Baumgarten’s Ethics between Wolff and Kant
In: Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers,
Oxford University Press. © Clemens Schwaiger 2024. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0002
18
first and then Kant; there is hardly any mention of all that lies in between. The
distinction between the old wolf and the young wolves—if you can excuse this
pun—usually falls by the wayside. From this perspective, Baumgarten may at best
be seen as a pioneer who broke new ground in aesthetics, the field which, as is well
known, he named. His idea of an independent science of sensuous knowledge
could be considered as an original supplement to the Wolffian system. However,
with respect to the rest of the disciplines, did he not himself openly make clear
his deep debt of gratitude to Wolff?² Indeed, it can hardly be denied that
Baumgarten’s autodidactic study of Wolff ’s writings deeply influenced the entire
development of his own thought. By adopting Wolffianism, he overcame the anti-
philosophical tendencies of the Pietist tradition in which he primarily grew up.
Nevertheless, a number of objections emerge when considering his life and
work that, even with regard to morality <in moralibus>, contradict the common
classification of Baumgarten as an undoubted disciple of Wolff. First, the suspi-
cion arises that his upbringing in the spiritual home of Pietism—the effects of
which would surely be difficult to overcome—somehow impacted the shape
of his ethics. For his entire life Baumgarten had a double identity, belonging
both to Pietism and the Enlightenment.³ Furthermore, there is the question of
whether the independence and increased valuation of sensibility, which is docu-
mented in his invention of a new science created for this purpose, did not have
tangible repercussions on his moral philosophy. In the case of a thinker who, like
Baumgarten, was so consistent in developing his basic aesthetic intuitions, there is
not only a very close link between aesthetics and logic, but also corresponding
interactions between metaphysics and ethics.
It is no coincidence that Baumgarten himself emphatically resisted being
generically labeled a Wolffian. In no field of philosophy did he see himself as a
mere imitator or mechanical parrot of Christian Wolff.⁴ At any rate, it was not
actually possible for him to be slavishly faithful to the master in the domain of
practical philosophy in the middle of the 1730s, when Baumgarten commenced
his academic teaching.⁵ For, the relevant Latin writings of Wolff were only to
appear afterwards: the Philosophia practica universalis at the end of the 1730s, the
Ius naturae in the 1740s, and the Philosophia moralis sive ethica only at the
beginning of the 1750s.⁶ So Baumgarten decided to make a virtue out of necessity;
² Cf. Baumgarten, Metaphysics, preface to the first edition (BM 92; AA 17:6); Philosophical Ethics,
preface to the first edition (BEP 30; AA 27:737); BPB (1st correspondence, 4).
³ Niggli correctly demonstrates this in her introduction to Die Vorreden zur Metaphysik
(Baumgarten 1999, xxix), which also offers a very helpful bibliography regarding Baumgarten
(Baumgarten 1999, 217–50).
⁴ Cf. Baumgarten, BPB (1st correspondence, 4); Scriptis quae moderator conflictus academici
disputavit §13 (1743, 22*).
⁵ Translator’s note: Baumgarten began teaching after his successful dissertation of 1735.
⁶ For an extensive presentation and evaluation of Wolff ’s complete moral-philosophical works,
please see my dissertation, Das Problem des Glücks im Denken Christian Wolffs (Schwaiger 1995).
19
for want of a usable textbook on ethics, he quickly wrote his own, the Philosophical
Ethics, which was first published in 1740. He found the textbook situation
somewhat better with regard to the general foundation of practical philosophy,
that is, the discipline of a general practical philosophy, which was programmat-
ically required by Wolff. For this, Baumgarten drew on the Exercitationes
iuris naturalis that Wolff ’s student Heinrich Köhler had published a few years
earlier.⁷ Driven by his hunger for education, Baumgarten had become personally
acquainted with this important natural-right scholar on trips to study at the
Wolffian center of Jena, although he never attended a lecture of the great master
Wolff himself. Later in 1760, two years before his death, Baumgarten published
the Elements of First Practical Philosophy as a result of his continued study of this
subject. Both the Ethics and the Elements offered, so to say, the staple diet on
which Kant would nourish his lectures on moral philosophy well into the 1790s.
The fact that Baumgarten laid the foundation of his practical philosophy with
Köhler’s help instead of Wolff ’s was extremely momentous for his approach. His
ethical project obtained its very strong juridical character from this origin. Thus, he
became accustomed to joining general practical philosophy with natural right,⁸
whereas Wolff treated both disciplines as systematically separate. This tendency
toward such a fusion was soon encouraged when Baumgarten, as of 1740, started
teaching at Frankfurt on the Oder, which was a university shaped by jurisprudence.⁹
The most obvious legacy of Köhler is the fact that the concept of obligation
<Verbindlichkeit>—and no longer, as in Wolff, that of perfection—became the
linchpin of his entire moral philosophy. Köhler had dedicated his own treatise to
the key term obligatio; in it he ambitiously attempted to reconcile Wolff ’s and
Thomasius’s diverging views of moral obligation <Verpflichtung>.¹⁰ In general, the
Thomasian school exerted an important influence upon Köhler’s natural right,
although the professor from Jena strongly depended on Wolff for a metaphysical
foundation. That he, for instance, particularly emphasized the difference between
constrained and unconstrained duties, which is how the Thomasians consummated
the distinction between right and morality, was then further passed on to Baumgarten.
II
⁷ Cf. Heinrich Köhler, Exercitationes juris naturalis, eiusque cumprimis cogentis, methodo system-
atica propositi (1729); see also Baumgarten’s unfinished commentary to the same, Ius naturae (1763),
which was only published posthumously. Illuminating for Baumgarten’s own philosophical beginnings
is his assessment of the situation in BDO §§22f (1748, 21–3).
⁸ Cf. BEP, preface to the first edition (XXX; AA 27:737). ⁹ Cf. Heinrich (1983, 80).
¹⁰ Cf. Köhler (1723, esp. § 47 (9), and § 90 (14)).
20
¹¹ Cf. BDO §17; BEP §§1–2; BVEEP §1; Baumgarten (1746, §2; 1750, §29); BIP §1, AA 19:9: “practical
philosophy . . . is the science of the obligations of a person that are to be known without faith <Philosophia
[ . . . ] practica est scientia obligationum hominis sine fide cognoscendarum>” (BIN §2).
¹² Cf. e.g. WDP §62: “practical philosophy [is] the science of directing the appetitive faculty to
choosing the good and fleeing the bad <philosophia practica [est] scientia dirigendi facultatem appeti-
tivam in eligendo bono & fugiendo malo>.”
¹³ Cf. the respective table of contents in WPPU 1:593 and WPPU 2:809, and the synopsis in BIP *xi
(AA 19:8f.). That in Baumgarten’s Philosophia generalis, §149, aretologia, eudemonologia, and anthro-
pognosia universalis are also listed as components of philosophia practica universalis alongside nomo-
logia, has only more of the character of one of Wolff ’s long-since stalled but unredeemed programs.
¹⁴ Cf. Kant UDG A96.
¹⁵ On the origin and significance of this distinction, which was developed in the seventeenth- and
eighteenth-century universal-right literature, see Joachim Hruschka, Strafe und Strafrecht bei
Achenwall—Zu einer Wurzel von Feuerbachs pyschologischer Zwangstheorie (1987, 161).
21
¹⁶ Cf. WPPU I, §118 “the moral necessity of acting or not acting is called passive obligation
<Necessitas moralis agendi vel non agendi dicitur obligatio passiva>.”
¹⁷ Cf. BM §723 (AA 17:137): “moral necessitation is obligation.” In the illuminating reference work of
Aso, Kurosaki, Otabe and Yamauchi (1989), Onomasticon philosophicum latinoteutonicum et teutonico-
latinum, which charts the bilingual term-indices of over one hundred Enlightenment textbooks and lexica,
Baumgarten’s Metaphysica §701 (AA 17:131) is given at any rate as the first evidence for necessitatio, i.e.
necessitation <Nöthigung>. Hruschka (1995, 740–2) exhaustively clarifies the juridical-historical back-
ground for the emergence of the concept of necessitation in the middle of the eighteenth century.
¹⁸ Cf. Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (GMS BA36-39).
¹⁹ Cf. Wolff ’s German Ethics (WTL §8): “to bind somebody to do something, or not to do something,
is nothing other than to connect a motivation or volition or nolition with that thing <Einen verbinden
etwas zu thun, oder zu lassen, ist nichts anders als einen Bewegungs-Grund des Wollens oder nicht Wollens
damit verknüpffen>”; WPPU 1:§118: “the connection of a motive with an action, either positive or
privative, is called an active obligation <Connexio autem motivi cum actione, sive positiva, sive privativa
obligatio activa appellatur>.” In express connection with Wolff, Köhler also determines obligatio moralis
as “a connection of motives with actions <connexio motivorum cum actionibus>” (1729, §300).
²⁰ Cf. the letter to Wolff of Feb. 21, 1705, in Briefwechsel zwischen Leibniz und Christian Wolff:
“I hold that there is obligation even without a superior . . . Therefore, I do not wish that obligation is to
be sought only from fear of punishment or hope of reward, since there is some non-remunerative desire
22
of acting correctly <Putem esse etiam sine superiore obligationem . . . Nolim igitur obligationem unice a
metu poenae et spe praemii peti, cum sit aliquod non mercenarium recte faciendi studium>” (Leibniz
1971, 19).
²¹ Cf. Baumgarten’s BIP §15 (AA 19:1335–7): “Obligation . . . can be defined through the
connection . . . of overriding impelling causes with free determinations <Obligatio . . . potest definiri
per connexionem . . . causarum impulsivarum potiorum cum libera determination>” (emphasis added
by author); “partial impelling causes, or even more correctly, the total impelling cause, beget no
obligation unless they will be overriding <Causae impulsivae partiales, immo totalis etiam, nisi
potiores fuerint, obligationem nullam pariunt>” (BIP §19; AA 19:14; repeated in BIN §7). This
tightening up of the obligatory character of moral necessitation in contrast to Wolff, as far as I can
see, has remained hidden in the secondary literature. For instance, Max Küenburg writes that
Baumgarten, without differentiating here, saw obligation “according to the stipulation of his teacher
Christian Wolff, in connection of overriding motives with action” (1925, 51; emphasis added by
author).
²² Cf. Wolff, WPE §890: “motives are a distinct representation of good and bad <Motiva sunt
repraesentatio boni ac mali distincta>.” Wolff clearly appears to have undergone a development in this
regard, for in the German writings motives can also be thoroughly non-distinct; cf. the German
Metaphysics (WDM §502) and the German Ethics (WTL §165).
²³ This is the reason why the expression motiva was replaced by causae impulsivae in the definition
above. For the former, as the generic term, also encompasses sensitive impulses (stimuli) alongside
rationally determined motives; cf. BM §342 (AA 17:101), BM §669 (AA 15:46), BM §677 (AA 15:49);
Gedancken vom vernünfftigen Beyfall auf Academien (BG §5).
23
III
demands. Yet for him the alternative is clearly not to counter by renouncing all
moral claims. Rather, one of the main uses of moral philosophy is to facilitate,
through an emendation of moral insight, the exercise of true and not merely
imaginary duties. Perhaps when cognition of the structures of human impulse is
deepened, motivation for moral action can also be strengthened.²⁹ At this point,
moral theory immediately turns into moral psychology, without Baumgarten ever
sharply distinguishing them.
The latter, for its part, rapidly takes up a religious hue and thereby leads to the
affirmation of morality through religion. This is because Baumgarten holds that
cognition of God, at least ideally, increases the motives for all other duties and
thus likewise facilitates their exercise. Religion is capable of producing an effect
that strengthens motivation only insofar as it leads to a living cognition (i.e.
cognition that has a practical effect) of duties. As a concrete means to achieving
such living cognition, Baumgarten mentions for instance the practice of edifica-
tion <Erbauung>, as he says while employing a key Pietist concept.³⁰ One would
scarcely err in suspecting the continual effect of Pietist influences on Baumgarten’s
emphasis on the liveliness of direct moral cognition. Apart from that, the enduring
dependence on Pietism is also the reason why he, in contrast to Wolff, intention-
ally places the duties toward God ahead of the duties to oneself.³¹ In the theocen-
tric orientation of morality, the powerful Pietist undercurrent of his thinking
becomes quite noticeable.³²
Wolff had in fact already used the expression “living cognition” in opposition to
“dead cognition” as an ethical term of art. Cognition is living if it renders a motive
for willing something, but dead when this is not the case. Wolff was also certainly
aware of the theological origin of this pair of concepts. As belief without works
would be dead, so too would be cognition without consequence for action.³³
²⁹ Cf. BEP §3 (AA 17:873); BIP §3 (AA 19:9) and §26 (AA 19:16).
³⁰ Cf. BEP §§69–70 (AA 27:886f.). Baumgarten’s consistently quite loyal interpreter Meier, in
Metaphysik III, §669, also cites conversion and being born again as paragons for living knowledge.
An evident Pietist influence lingered on in this central point for him, as for his philosophical teacher;
after all, August Hermann Francke had incessantly propagated the revival of a living faith as the chief
goal of at his Waisenhaus (i.e. orphanage) in Halle (see Wiebecke 1967, esp. 25–32; in this unfortu-
nately still unpublished dissertation, a secularization of Pietist ideas is made responsible, with good
grounds, for the “loosening” of Wolffian rationalism in Baumgarten and Meier).
³¹ Cf. Preface to the first edition of the BEP (AA 27:737), and BEP §21 (AA 27:876); Baumgarten
1750, §29.
³² Cf. Poppe 1907, 32–4; Feiereis 1965, 70: “Baumgarten’s attempt to determine the concept of
religion, elaborated by means of philosophy, as the departure point for ethics must be regarded as a
significant innovation in the German Enlightenment. There is no template for this, even in Wolff.” It
is only to be remarked in passing that Baumgarten’s new relationship between morality and religion
was of a consequence with regard to the formation of Kant’s ethico-theology that may scarcely be
overestimated.
³³ Cf. Wolff ’s German Logic (WDL Ch. 1, §15); Ratio praelectionum (WRP Sect. II, Ch. 6, §30); the
German Ethics (WTL §169); and WPPU II, §244: “Living cognition is called that which brings about a
motive for willing or not willing. But on the contrary called dead is that cognition which does not bring
about a motive for willing or not willing.” Hans Böhm (1926, 215) overlooks the biblical origin; in
contrast, he suspects that the term originates solely in rhetoric.
25
However, in Baumgarten the doctrine of cognitio viva and mortua carries a much
greater weight. Liveliness is for him generally one of the chief perfections of
cognition but is especially demanded by practical philosophy.³⁴ Due to its foun-
dational importance, this theme is also from now on anchored in empirical
psychology, whereas Wolff first discusses it in the practical part of universal
practical philosophy. Further, according to Baumgarten, and again in conse-
quence of his efforts to increase the value of sensibility, not only rational motives
but sensuous impulses too can enliven cognition. Each cognition, insofar as it only
contains incentives, would be living, no matter whether this was sensuous or
rational.³⁵ On the contrary, Wolff had only wished to speak about living cognition
when there is rationally grounded conviction. Consequently, for him the certainty
of cognition is the necessary yet, at the same time, really the sufficient condition of
its liveliness.³⁶
However, against this narrow, indeed automatic connection of certain cogni-
tion and correct action, Baumgarten expresses reservations based on experience.
One could have at one’s disposal distinct moral cognition that has progressed to
conviction and proof and yet by no means already be a moral beacon. Despite
possessing knowledge of virtue, the path to virtue can still at any given moment be
too steep for someone. Conversely, there are many good people for whom
indistinct cognition of morality already suffices for the most difficult of actions.³⁷
To mark his distance from Wolff more clearly, Baumgarten soon finds a termi-
nological specification necessary for his original word choice: there can only be
talk of living cognition in the strict sense insofar as the cognition actually suffices
for action; when it, on the other hand, is insufficient for the action demanded, it is
properly to be called dead.³⁸ The cognition that indeed contains motivations for
desiring or averting, yet without these inevitably effecting the corresponding
action, are better called moving cognition (cognitio movens), and their opposite
³⁴ Cf. BG (1740, §5); BPB (3rd correspondence, 12); Scriptis quae moderator conflictus academici
disputavit (1743, § 15); BA I, § 22; BIP §4 (AA 19:10); BAL § 6.
³⁵ Cf. BM, first edition §669 (BM 438, variant 234): “cognition, insofar as it contains the incentives
of the mind, is called living insofar as it is not dead <cognitio quatenus elateres animi continet, viva
quatenus minus mortua dicitur” [trans.: translation of BM slightly modified]; see also Meier’s
Anfangsgründe aller schönen Wissenschaften (1754, I § 178), which specifically differentiates between
the “rational” and the “sensuous life” of cognition.
³⁶ Cf. WPPU II, §§245–9.
³⁷ Cf. BEP §444 (AA 27:1001); BVEEP §§10 and 25; Meier (1744, §55) is also illuminating here, and
above all the disputation held under the chairmanship of Meier with the significantly anti-Wolffian
title, “Philosophical meditations concerning the life of cognition, not necessarily depending on its
clarity, truth, and certitude <Meditationes philosophicae de vita cognitionis, ab eius claritate, veritate et
certitudine non necessario pendente>” (Meier and Plitt 1747).
³⁸ Cf. BM §671 (AA 15:47): “Cognition . . . is living (more strictly . . . sufficient for acting). Cognition . . .
is dead (more strictly . . . insufficient for acting) <Cognitio . . . est viva (strictius . . . sufficiens ad agendum).
Cognitio . . . est mortua (strictius . . . insufficiens ad agendum)>” [trans.: translation of BM slightly mod-
ified]; BVEEP §10.
26
lifeless cognition (cognitio iners).³⁹ With this newly formed distinction between
living and moving cognition, discrepancies between cognizing and acting
can be more easily explained. Whereas Wolff in this regard leans toward intellec-
tualism and finds the moral panacea in the enlightenment of the understanding,
Baumgarten is able to make phenomena such as the impotence of cognition or
action against better knowledge more comprehensible.⁴⁰ In fact, in his view, all
human cognition is moving to a certain degree, even if this power is still very small.⁴¹
Nevertheless, even a very true cognition is by no means always living enough to
guarantee an action corresponding to it. The path from the original consternation to
a consequential action usually still leads through many dry periods.
Baumgarten takes up yet another significant distinction in this connection.
The liveliness of cognition may no longer be confused with the vividness of
perception, even though the designations (cognitio) viva and (perceptio) vivida
sound beguilingly alike and therefore this error often creeps up. For, vividness
can in fact contribute to liveliness, but knowledge often only shines without it
becoming a burning issue. Conversely, extremely effective cognitions are often not
very vivid.⁴² Under the vividness of a representation Baumgarten understands
that clarity that comes from a multitude of characteristics, thus the so-called
extensive clarity that he developed.⁴³ Aesthetics concerns itself with the laws of
vivid cognition, since sensitive cognition, as its specific object, is especially char-
acterized by a variegated wealth of individual characteristics and consequently
through extensive clarity.⁴⁴
³⁹ Cf. BM §669 (AA 15:46); BVEEP §3. The changes referred to between the first and later editions
of the Metaphysica are a perfect example of Baumgarten’s having thoroughly undertaken to radically
re-work his magnum opus in specific points. The catalyst for such was, in this case, the dissertation of
December 1741 (i.e. BVEE), which has earned even less attention in previous research. Thereby,
Baumgarten himself gives a tip in the preface to the second edition of the BEP: the concise brevity of
his textbooks, if necessary, is made up for through the greater elaborateness of corresponding
dissertations (BEP XXX; AA 27:741).
⁴⁰ Cf. BVEEP §12, and §39, where we are reminded of the famous and then oft-cited passage of
Ovid: “I see and approve the best, but I follow the worse <Video meliora proboque, deteriora sequor>”
(also in Meier and Plitt 1747, §29); on this, see also Schwaiger 2011a, chapter 5. [Translator’s note: this
chapter is translated in our companion Oxford volume, Baumgarten and Kant on Metaphysics
(Schwaiger 2018a, 55–60).]
⁴¹ Cf. BVEEP §16; BIP §204 (AA 19:90).
⁴² Cf. BG §9; BVEEP §13. This warning notwithstanding, the equation of both concepts is to be
found throughout the Baumgarten literature, as it is, for example, in Pimpinella 1993, 35f. for whom
however it does not escape notice that Wolff ’s cognitio viva and Baumgarten’s perceptio vivida belong
indeed to different spheres of thought.
⁴³ Cf. BM §531 (AA 15:12): “clarity due to the multitude of notes can be called extensively greater
clarity. An extensively clearer perception is lively <Claritas . . . multitudine notarum extensive maior dici
potest. Extensive clarior perceptio est vivida>”; BG §6; BEP §40 (AA 27:881); Baumgarten 1735, §112:
“we call vivid that in which is given many different things, be they simultaneous or successive, to
apperceive <Vividum dicimus, in quo plura varia, seu simultanea fuerint seu successiva, appercipere
datur>.” That Baumgarten assigns the attribute “vivid” chiefly to “discourse <Vortrag>” points in
this case to a rhetorical origin of the term.
⁴⁴ Cf. Baumgarten, BPB (2nd correspondence, 7); see also BEP §43 (AA 27:881). The head of the
Jena Wolffians Johann Peter Reusch, to whom Baumgarten must owe, as one of his authoritative
27
IV
teachers, crucial suggestions for his later doctrine of claritas and especially for his fundamental
distinction between extensive and intensive clarity (see Schwaiger 2011a, §53), already stresses the
advantage of the greater vividness of sensitive representations (cf. Reusch 1734, §§102 and 250).
⁴⁵ Cf. Förster 1765, §1. ⁴⁶ Cf. Praktische Philosophie Herder (AA 27:16).
28
⁴⁷ For a detailed attempt to present, by means of all available materials and assistance, the here only
hastily sketched importance of Baumgarten for the long and rocky course of Kant’s ethics, I refer to my
habilitation thesis Kategorische und andere Imperative (Schwaiger 1999).
29
⁴⁸ In contrast, Steffen W. Groß for instance simply refuses to place Baumgarten on the line leading
to Kant. Rather, the perspective of the at-best moderately significant precursor to Kant hinders the
perception of the specific significance of Baumgarten (cf. Groß 2001, 280).
⁴⁹ Praktische Philosophie Herder (AA 27:16).
⁵⁰ On this, cf. the excursus in Schwaiger (1999, 34–8).
⁵¹ In this regard, very illuminating is Oberhausen and Pozzo’s effort in combing through the
Königsberg University source material (Oberhausen and Pozzo 1999).
30
Not only is the situation no better within Baumgarten studies itself concerning
the treatment of his practical philosophy, but in fact it’s even worse. It’s been
decades since we were told that “a study of Baumgarten’s ethics is urgently to be
desired.”⁵² The neglect of this sort of work has contributed greatly to the fact that
Baumgarten has been so often misunderstood.⁵³ However, despite the long-
standing reprints, this field is still largely terra incognita. Until very recently
there has not been a single study dedicated specifically to Baumgarten’s moral
philosophy.
II
the basis for his own introductory lectures in this subject. From Köhler he
assumed the habit, in the treatment of the right of nature, of proceeding from
the basic concepts and principles of practical philosophy in general.⁵⁸ However, in
so doing, his grounding of ethics also conversely preserved a stronger juridical
template than was otherwise usually the case.
At that time, the designation philosophia practica universalis had become
customary for the philosophical foundation not only of the right of nature but
also of all practical disciplines, overwhelmingly because Wolff had published
under this title a large two-volume work at the end of the 1730s. Based on his
first published work of the same title, which appeared in 1703, Wolff could himself
take credit for having in general been the inventor and founder of this new
fundamental discipline.⁵⁹
Baumgarten, in contrast, preferred the designation philosophia practica prima,⁶⁰
through which he inconspicuously added his own emphasis. For, through this
little alteration he draws an immediate parallel with theoretical philosophy: Just as
metaphysics, as “first philosophy,” prefaces the other philosophical fields (and
again, within it, ontology precedes all the rest of the sub-disciplines of metaphysics
as the basic science), so too first practical philosophy should provide the founda-
tion for the rest of the moral disciplines.⁶¹ This is also expressed in the definition
(altered from Wolff): First practical philosophy is that first science that contains
the principles that are proper and overwhelmingly common to the rest of the
practical disciplines.⁶² While Baumgarten can claim a certain originality for the
title first practical philosophy, building such an analogy with metaphysics is not at
all unusual in the Wolffianism of the time, but instead thoroughly common. The
idea of a sort of “moral metaphysics” leads the way for Kant’s later “metaphysics of
morals,” at least terminologically, even though his project is completely different
qua content.⁶³
A final, weighty observation in connection with these considerations regarding
philosophical architectonics is still to be made: Baumgarten never completely
finished his first practical philosophy (at least in book form), but rather merely
⁵⁸ See BDO §17, and Förster’s preface to the Sciagraphia (Baumgarten 1769, 32*). Alexander
Aichele has recently investigated Baumgarten’s detailed yet in no way uncritical reception of Köhler
(Aichele 2004b and 2005). For the philosophico-historical placement of Köhler between the poles of
Leibniz and Wolff, the detailed study of Lamarra, Palaia, and Pimpinella 2001 is indispensable.
⁵⁹ Cf. Schwaiger 2005. Baumgarten (cf. BIP vi*) and Meier (cf. 1764, §30 and elsewhere) also
recognize Wolff ’s justification for his achievement in this area. However, Köhler still seems to have
foregone the discipline’s name, which was surprisingly never used in Wolff ’s German Ethics.
⁶⁰ Cf. Baumgarten 1743, §5; Baumgarten 1746, §2; BIP §6; BAL §7.
⁶¹ Cf. Baumgarten 1740, §9; BIP §7.
⁶² Cf. BIP §6: “first (universal) practical philosophy is the science containing the first principles that
are proper but also common to the rest of the practical disciplines”; BIN §3; Baumgarten 1769, §160.
In contrast, Wolff ’s definition more strongly emphasises the practical value of his new invention:
“practical universal philosophy is the practically effective science of directing free actions according to
the most general rules” (WPPU I, §3).
⁶³ For this, see Schwaiger 2001.
32
composed its elements (initia). The titling of his later work of 1760 (Initia
philosophiae practicae primae) does not merely emerge from a trace of modesty,
as is probably the case with Kant’s Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten of 1785.
Rather, in it is reflected a painful limitation, because, conceptually, this science
actually aimed at something much more comprehensive. Next to the doctrine of
obligation <Verbindlichkeit>, which alone was actually executed, it should have
also contained a doctrine of virtue, a doctrine of happiness, and indeed, actually, a
doctrine of general anthropognosia, or the art of cognizing the moral state of other
people.⁶⁴ The factual limitation to the theory of obligation, dictated not least by
the requirements of the juridical training, was supremely momentous in view of
Kant’s reception: with this depletion of content, quite conspicuous vis-à-vis
Wolff ’s thematic breadth, Baumgarten unintentionally but decisively laid the
groundwork for the focus on duty, the forgetfulness of virtue, and the abstinence
from happiness found in later Kantian ethics.
III
⁶⁴ For the entire plan of Baumgarten’s universal practical philosophy, see BDO §22; Baumgarten
1769, §§161–4; Baumgarten 1770, §149.
⁶⁵ Cf. the Dissertatio prolusoria to the Exercitationes juris naturalis (KE §CXXXII), as well as §300 in
the same.
⁶⁶ Cf. BIP §1: “practical philosophy is the science of the obligations of a person that are to be known
without faith <philosophia . . . practica est scientia obligationum hominis sine fide cognoscendarum>.”
See also Baumgarten 1746, §2, as well as BIN §2.
⁶⁷ Cf. BEP §1: “ethics is the science of the internal obligations of the person in the natural state
<Ethica . . . est scientia obligationum hominis internarum in statu naturali>.” See also BDO §17; BVEEP
§1; Baumgarten 1750, §29.
⁶⁸ Cf. BVEEP §1; MPS I, §5.
33
⁶⁹ Cf. WDP §62: “practical philosophy [is] the science of directing the appetitive faculty in choosing
the good and fleeing the bad <philosophia practica [est] scientia dirigendi facultatem appetitivam in
eligendo bono & fugiendo malo>”; WDP §64; WPM I §1.
⁷⁰ Cf. WPPU I §118: “the connection of a motive with an action is called active obligation
<Connexio . . . motivi cum actione . . . obligatio activa appellatur>”; KE §300: “moral obligation in
general is the connection of motives with actions <Obligatio moralis in genere est connexio moti-
vorum cum actionibus>.”
⁷¹ Cf. BIP §15: “obligation . . . can be defined through the connection . . . of impelling causes with a
free determination <Obligatio . . . potest definiri per connexionem . . . caussarum impulsivarum cum
libera determinatione>;” BIN §7. For an extensive analysis of this at first invisible however important
process of transformation within the context of the early modern debate on obligation, please see
Schwaiger 2011a, chapter 9.
⁷² Cf. BM §723: “moral necessitation is obligation <Necessitatio moralis est obligatio>”; WPPU
I §118: “the necessity of morally acting or not acting is called passive obligation <Necessitas moralis
agendi vel non agendi dicitur obligatio passiva>.”
⁷³ Cf. BIP §39: “The imperatives in the practical disciplines indicate that a human being is obliged.”
⁷⁴ On this critique, see also Hüning 2004a, 102, and Hüning 2004b, 146 and 158.
34
IV
⁷⁵ Cf. BIP §27. The concept obligatio falsa may be borrowed from Köhler (cf. KE §304), but it, as far
as I can see, plays no role in Wolff.
⁷⁶ Cf. BEP §7: “an ethics of erroneous obligations is deceptive (chimerical) <Ethica obligationum
erronearum deceptrix est (chimaerica)>”; BVEEP §38; MPS I, §24. The polemic against ethica
deceptrix is the apex of a more comprehensive typology of deficient forms of ethics, which
Baumgarten manifestly first developed (cf. BEP §§4–7). The parallel remarks by Meier are exceptionally
helpful for the historical contextualization of the here controverted mistaken forms (MPS I §§19–24).
⁷⁷ BIP §§11 and 43 (AA 19:12 and 24–25); BPB (3rd correspondence, 9); BIN §11. The cited
axiom of right, which has meaning for the doctrine of imputation, is likewise already mentioned by
Köhler in this connection (cf. KE §306).
⁷⁸ Cf. MPS I, §25.
⁷⁹ Translator’s note: see Schwaiger’s more recent “Zwischen Laxismus und Rigorismus.
Möglichkeiten und Grenzen philosophischer Ethik nach Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten” (Schwaiger
2016b) for further discussion of this theme.
⁸⁰ Cf. BIN §85.
35
⁸¹ Cf. the preface to the first edition of the Ethica Philosophica (BEP XXX; AA 27:737): “As is right,
I have brought forth a first principle understood according to, restricted to, and credited to the
illustrious Wolff, to whom I owe so much in philosophizing”; preface to the second edition of the
Metaphysics (BM 87); KE §340. On this point, see chapter 10 of Schwaiger 2011a.
⁸² Wolff, the German Ethics (WTL §12, original in bold); WPPU I §152: “The law of nature obligates
us to commit actions that as such tend to our perfection and that of our condition, and to omit actions
that as such tend to our imperfection and that of our condition” (original in italics).
⁸³ BEP §10 (AA 27:874, italics in original); BIP §43; BIN §30. For instance, briefer than Wolff,
however still somewhat more cumbersome than Baumgarten, is Köhler’s formulation: “Live more
appropriately to your perfections . . . and those of others <Vive convenienter perfectionibus tuis . . . et
aliorum>” (KE §704).
⁸⁴ Cf. BEP §10 (AA 27:874f.); BIP §§46 and 48 (AA 19:26).
⁸⁵ Cf. Lange 1724, 367–9; Lange 1726, 151; Lange 1734, 19: “the principle of the new ethics proposes
under the name perfection actually nothing other than a perverted self-love, and personal interest.”
⁸⁶ Cf. especially KE §§699f.
⁸⁷ Vgl. Cf. BEP §10 (AA 27:874); BIP §43 (AA 19:25). – Meier’s broader discussion of this two-fold
perfection unmistakably clarifies that the distinction between perfecting as an aim, on the one hand,
and as a means, on the other, should be read as a reply to the charge of self-interest against Wolff
(Meier 2007, I, §32; II, §504; Meier 1764, §§105 and 200).
36
⁸⁸ The German Metaphysics (WDM §449); WPE §633: “Love is the disposition of the soul to perceive
pleasure from the happiness of another <Amor est dispositio animae ad percipiendam voluptatem ex
alterius felicitate>”; WPE §649. Wolff thereby falls in line with the core of the Leibnizian definition in
the preface to the Codex iuris gentium diplomaticus of 1693: “To love . . . or to hold dear is to delight in
the happiness of another” (GP III, 387). On the background for the emergence of this famous
formulation, see Busche 1991.
⁸⁹ Cf. BM §684 (AA 15:50): “Joy based on the perfection of somebody is love <Gaudium ex alicuius
perfectione est amor>” (translation of BM slightly modified). Köhler assumes a certain middle
position: “Love is the disposition for taking pleasure from the happiness of somebody <Amor est
dispositio capiendi voluptatem ex alicuius felicitate>” (KE §689). The substitution of alterius for alicuius
makes a reference to oneself possible; yet, the retention of felicitas instead of Baumgarten’s perfectio still
always implies reference to a person. [[translator’s note: alterius always means “another of two,” so in
this case somebody else. Alicuius has a range of meanings, including “somebody,” “something,” and
even “some other.” In BM we translated alicuius as “of another,” but Schwaiger here shows that
translation is perhaps too interpretative, even if it so readily suggests itself.]]
⁹⁰ Cf. BEP §191 (AA 27:920): “rejoice in your perfections having averted your imperfections . . . by
means of sensitive and rational heautophilia (philautia), i.e. love of self <gaude perfectionibus tuis
aversatus imperfectiones tuas [ . . . ] sensitiva et rationali heautophilia (philautia) amore tui ipsius>.”
Similarly, Köhler had already written “pleasure drawn from our own happiness is called love of ourself
or philautia <voluptas hausta ex felicitate nostra dicitur amor nostri seu philautia>.” In contrast, for
Wolff there is no defining determination of self-love in either the German Ethics or the WPE. Only the
older Wolff who returned to Halle attempts make up lost ground (cf. WIN I, §606; WPM 4, §51), but
this late development can be disregarded in the present context.
37
to the universal laws of our perfection, and the second opposes these. Self-love
may not be blind, but rather must have sight, so to speak, i.e. it must rest on a
correct estimation of one’s self.⁹¹ Anyone who evinces an excessive attachment to
themselves, indeed surpassing love for God, apotheosizes themself and makes
themselves guilty of an idolatrous self-love.⁹² With the harsh syntagma of a
“philautia idololatrica,” which is probably his own newly coined locution,
Baumgarten is presumably reacting to the already-mentioned attack of Joachim
Lange, according to which the Wolffian principle of perfection would lead people
to idolatry and self-apotheosis.⁹³ The objectionable phrase is taken up, but at the
same time disarmed, through its assimilation into his own conceptual system.
While this figure of speech remained basically a chance expression limited to
the situation in which it arose, there was one turn of phrase that was much more
consequential. To condemn an excessive selfishness as immoral, Baumgarten
speaks in general—as probably the first author in the history of philosophy to
do so—of a “moral egoism.”⁹⁴ Certainly, the word “egoism <Egoismus>” (and
accordingly “egoist <Egoist>”), in particular through Wolff, had already long since
found entry into the eighteenth-century philosophical lexicon. However, with this
term Wolff still strictly signified a radical epistemological position, which one
would today call solipsism, namely the denial of the existence of an external or
social world independent of consciousness.⁹⁵ Now, however, it is questionable
whether any thinker has ever earnestly advocated such an extreme view, which
⁹¹ Cf. BEP §194 (AA 27:921): “ordered self-love conforms to the common laws of our perfection, and
the disordered is unfitting for the same. Love that follows a just assessment of the beloved possesses
vision; that which does not is blind <Philautia ordinata est legibus perfectionis nostrae communibus
conformis, iisdem disconveniens inordinata est . . . Amor iustum amati aestimium sequens est oculatus
illud non sequens, coecus est>.” Köhler had already modeled blind and vision-possessing (self-)love
(1729, §698). With an unmistakable anti-Pietist line of attack, Meier also stresses that self-love did
not inevitably indicate “a disorderly and debauched inclination to oneself” (MPS II, §501), but rather
that orderly self-love must be distinguished from the disorderly (MPS II, §502).
⁹² Cf. BEP §§81 and 195 (AA 27:889 and 921). ⁹³ Cf. Lange 1734, 19.
⁹⁴ Cf. BEP §300 (AA 27:957): “Pay attention to internal honourableness . . . , observing moral
moderation in duties towards you yourself . . . , both avoiding excess in yourself, for instance when
perfecting the end, along with the proficiency of being excessive, i.e. moral egoism <Da operam
honestati internae . . . , in officiis erga te ipsum observans mediocritatem . . . , vitans excessus in te, ut
fine perficiendo, cum habitu excedendi s. egoismo morali>”; MPS III, §772. Aso et al. (1989, 115) cite
the aforementioned Baumgarten passage as the first usage. Johann Gustav Wilhelm Hesse’s dissertation
De egoismo morali provides still considerably stronger evidence for the novelty of the word pairing,
with the author expressly declaring: “Concerning the composite term [moral egoism], I don’t remember
seeing it anywhere except in the celebrated Ethics of Baumgarten <Quod ad terminum compositum
[= egoismus moralis] attinet, illum me legere non memini, nisi in Celeb. Baumgartenii Ethica” (Hesse
1757, §17, scholion 1). Hesse then immediately defends the application of the still unusual and strange-
sounding neologism with the justification that it is thoroughly suitable for signifying the intended
mistaken disposition clearly and concisely (1757, §17, scholion 2). Also, Silvano Sportelli’s study into
the reception of the concept arrives at the same result: “the substantive egoism accompanied by the
adjective moral is first found . . . in Latin in the Ethica Philosophica, written in 1740 by A.G. Baumgarten
<Il sostantivo,egoismo‘ accompagnato dall’aggettivo,morale‘ si trova [ . . . ] per la prima volta, in latino,
nell’Ethica philosophica, scritta nel 1740, di A. G. Baumgarten>” (Sportelli 2003, 170).
⁹⁵ Cf. Halbfaß (1968, 200–27). Baumgarten also acknowledges this original gnoseological mean-
ing of the concept (cf. BM §392; AA 17:109).
38
⁹⁶ Cf. Hesse (1757, §17, scholion 1), who mentions the distinction between theoretical and practical
atheism as an analogous example for an equivocal, i.e. speculative as well as existential, usage of the
concept.
⁹⁷ Cf. “Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view” §2 (in Kant 2007); PrHer 27:53; MoC 27:359.
⁹⁸ Cf. the article “Egoismus” (Reiner and Halbfaß 1972). ⁹⁹ Cf. KrV A129.
¹⁰⁰ Cf. Fuchs’s article “Egotismus, Egoismus, Egomismus” (1972), and Gabriel’s “Solipsismus”
(1995), both in the Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie.
¹⁰¹ Cf. BEP §195 (AA 27:921); BIN §31.
¹⁰² Cf. e.g. MoC 27:359–60; see also “Observations on the feeling of the beautiful and the sublime”
(in Kant 2007; AA 20:145 and 169).
39
VI
¹⁰³ This has indeed already occasionally been remarked in the literature; however, it has scarcely
been investigated closely; cf. e.g. Poppe 1907, 32.
¹⁰⁴ In contrast, Wolff had consciously placed the officia erga se ipsum first ahead of the officia erga
Deum so as to make it clear that the glorification of God also still constitutes an integral part of one’s
own perfection (cf. Wolff 1735, sect. II, ch. 6, §§26f.).
¹⁰⁵ Cf. Preface to the first edition of BEP (BEP XXX; AA 27:737) and §21 (AA 27:876–77);
Baumgarten 1750, §29.
¹⁰⁶ Cf. BEP §§11–21 (AA 27:875–77); BM §947 (AA 17:194): “the glory of God and his celebration
are religion <Gloria dei et illustratio eius sunt religio>.” With this close connection of religion and
ethics and, accordingly, with this foundation of ethics in a philosophical concept of religion,
Baumgarten is pioneering for the late German Enlightenment (cf. Feiereis 1965, 70–2). First, Kant’s
ethico-theology turned Baumgarten’s founding relation completely on its head: And now, through
morality is access to the question of God first of all opened; a proper class of duties with respect to God
has become seen as superfluous.
¹⁰⁷ Cf. BEP §§27 and 31 (AA 27:878).
40
in truth, clarity, certainty, and liveliness of the cognition of God is termed, with a
key Pietest concept, “edification” (aedificatio).¹⁰⁸
The goal and culmination of all striving after religious perfecting thereby forms
for Baumgarten the living cognition of God (viva dei cognitio).¹⁰⁹ At this point, the
Pietist influence is once again palpable. For, a living, practically effective cognition
of the divine word in contrast to dead biblical scholarship and stiff theological
speculation was indeed the very program of Pietism, and the impetus of all its
pedagogical efforts. Baumgarten, stamped by his education at Francke’s institute,
thoroughly made this fundamental Pietist concern his own, but then attempted to
secure it philosophically.¹¹⁰ A cognition that is the most living as possible forms,
not only in religious practice but also in every domain of philosophy, an ideal
worth striving for.¹¹¹ Therefore, the vita cognitionis is counted from the beginning
among the chief perfections of cognition. It is no coincidence that it is always
stressed at the end in Baumgarten’s canon of formal perfections of human
cognition.¹¹² Baumgarten, however, defined this concept more precisely as his
thinking developed. In the first edition of the Metaphysics (1739), he still con-
sidered cognition as living insofar as it contained mental incentives; in later
editions of this work, cognition is considered properly living only when it actually
suffices for bringing forth the desired object.¹¹³ This conceptual precision corre-
sponds to Baumgarten’s newly defined concept of obligation, according to which
there can only be talk of obligation <Verpflichtung> when overriding impelling
grounds are present.
A continuous subliminal effect of Pietist thought can however be established in
Baumgarten’s moral philosophy not only in the treatment of the duties to God but
also in the discussion of the duties to oneself. Such a crypto-Pietism is noticeable
for instance in the strong accentuation of the duty for self-cognition and likewise
¹⁰⁸ Cf. BEP §69 (AA 27:886). On the role of these programmatic words among the founding fathers
of Pietism, cf. Haizmann 1997, esp. 56–9, and Breuer 2005.
¹⁰⁹ Cf. BEP §70 (AA 27:886f.).
¹¹⁰ In the introduction to Die Vorreden zur Metaphysik, Ursula Niggli takes a similar view, according
to which both Baumgartens, Alexander Gottlieb and his brother Siegmund Jacob, despite all their
“open-mindedness for modern philosophy, never abandoned [their] strict and devout Pietist character”
(Baumgarten 1999, xxix).
¹¹¹ Wiebecke has already worked out in detail how Baumgarten here “secularizes” a key term of
Pietist devoutness through generalization, so to speak (Wiebecke 1967, 30).
¹¹² Cf. BEP §202 (AA 27:923f.); BG §5; Baumgarten 1743, §15; BA I, §22 (for commentary, see the
Ästhetik-Nachschrift, Baumgarten 1907, §22); BIP §4 (AA 19:10); BAL §412. Baumgarten’s famous
doctrine of initially only four, but soon six, cardinales perfectiones cognitionis was due one day for a
more comprehensive analysis of its developmental history. The first schematic attempt to do so takes
place in Strube 2000, 33f.
¹¹³ Compare the first edition of BM §669: “cognition insofar as it contains the incentives of the mind
is called living <cognitio quatenus elateres animi continet, viva . . . dicitur>” with §671 of the fourth
edition (AA 15:47): “cognition that moves effective desires or aversions, and its motive power, is living
(more strictly . . . sufficient for acting) <Cognitio movens appetitiones aversationesve efficientes et vis
eius motrix . . . est viva (strictius, [ . . . ] sufficiens ad agendum)>”; BIP §204 (AA 19:90). On the
practico-theoretical importance of this terminological refinement and in general on the ethical signif-
icance of cognitio viva, see above pp. 23–27 for a fuller account.
41
Stefanie Buchenau, Mathematizing Morality: Wolff, Baumgarten, and Kant on the Philosophia practica universalis
In: Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers,
Oxford University Press. © Stefanie Buchenau 2024. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0003
43
the three projects one by one to show their respective particularities and adjust-
ments and to give a clearer account of the philosophia practica universalis project,
its philosophical aims and difficulties, and its evolution.
“Not the Same Old Story”: Cartesian mathesis universalis and Wolff ’s philosophia
practica universalis. The philosophia practica universalis project has received
surprisingly little attention in Wolffian and Kantian scholarship, indicating a
general perplexity among current readers.¹ While it still makes sense for us
today to ascribe a positive function to reason, knowledge, and judgment a positive
function in matters of morality, we find it harder to establish a connection
between mathematics and morals. What can it possibly mean to mathematize
morality? Isn’t the moral domain marked by a contingency that makes any
mathematization, demonstration, and quantification impossible? And aren’t
human agents in their essence characterized by a freedom that distinguishes
them from physical objects? Furthermore, doesn’t morality involve human qua-
lities other than mathematical and methodical reason? These are possible ques-
tions and objections that seem to explain a broader attitude of incomprehension
and disinterest toward philosophia practica universalis, some of them already
formulated by Enlightenment thinkers themselves.²
And yet, despite our resistance today, the project of mathematizing morality
exerted a tremendous attraction among early modern philosophers, around the
time of—and even before—Wolff, who comments on this in retrospect, in a note
to his 1728 Preliminary discourse, in which he outlines the nature and ambition of
his philosophia practica universalis project:
¹ The linguistic barrier must also have played a role. While a series of fundamental treatises by
Baumgarten have recently been translated into German, English, French, and Italian, Wolff ’s two
philosophia practica universalis treatises have not yet been translated from their original Latin, except
for a partial translation of the first treatise into French (Buchenau and Rey 2000). A few articles have
been devoted to this subject. See in particular Allison (2011); see also Bacin (2015), Klemme (2020),
Lenders (1979), Schwaiger (2005).
² On these objections, see the highly interesting preface to Meier (1764).
44
the general principles of Arithmetic and Geometry; I still find solid traditions
in it, as I have now meditated more deeply on the theory of its use, and
scrutinized its reasons more closely. Universal practical philosophy is of greatest
utility where one wishes to treat the whole of practical philosophy according to a
demonstrative method. I have defined it as an affective science, because it bends
<flectit> the will to desire and aversion: I have defined it as practical, because it
teaches to determine the faculty of locomotion for the execution of internal
actions. (WDP §70)³
By affirming that he wrote this treatise “in imitation of the more recent
Mathematicians, who in the Mathesis universalis generally convey the common
principles of Arithmetic and Geometry,” Wolff emphasizes his own early math-
ematical ambitions and establishes a direct link between his philosophia practica
universalis project and the Cartesian mathesis universalis. At a closer glance, his
project even seems connected with several earlier projects. These include the
mathesis universalis drafted by Descartes himself as well as various attempts to
revise this original project and transform morals into a demonstrative science, as
outlined by Locke, Leibniz, Caspar Neumann,⁴ and Ehrenfried Walther von
Tschirnhaus,⁵ all of whom Wolff explicitly acknowledges among his influences.⁶
Of course, most of these projects, including Descartes’s and Locke’s projects, have
remained incomplete and sketchy: Descartes himself, for instance, seems to have
remained entangled in some contradictions. In his early Rules for the Direction of
the Mind, he famously set up an all-encompassing philosophical system based on
a set of mathematical, axiom-like, fundamental, evident, and certain principles
and mathematical tools produced by the human mind. And yet, it was only late in
his life that he came to affirm morals’ central place in the system after having
conceived in his Discourse on Method no more than a provisional morality serving
as a temporary moral guide.⁷ Nonetheless, Wolff ’s predecessors seem to have
formulated a few fundamental intuitions which remain valid and inspirational for
Wolff. This applies particularly to Locke and Leibniz,⁸ whom Wolff mentions
explicitly:⁹ Wolff seems to have taken up Locke’s claim expounded in several
places in his Essay concerning Human Understanding that “morality is capable of
Demonstration, as well as mathematics” and that moral rules are knowable with
the same degree of certainty as “any Demonstration in Euclid.”¹⁰
This transformation of moral philosophy into a mathematical and demonstra-
tive science seemed to be possible because of certain resemblances between
mathematics and moral philosophy. First of all, they share a concern with ideal
notions that are independent of experience. Just as it is possible to construct a
geometrical triangle and deduce new properties in the mind without depending on
the existence of such geometrical figures in the external world, it seems possible to
take moral principles such as “justice” as mental objects of reasoning, without
reference to an extramental and empirical existence.
Second, moral deliberation and choice seem to require recourse to solid and
unquestionable principles (“justice”) and rules (“live honorably”, “don’t steal”),
similar to mathematical reasoning. It furthermore seems to presuppose an
ethical rigor and a consistency of one’s actions with these principles, as already
claimed in former philosophical traditions such as the ancient and modern
Stoic tradition; from this viewpoint, practical deliberation resembled a syllogistic
exercise and logical (rather than strictly mathematical) analysis allowing one
to deduce whether an action is right or wrong, permissible or not, obligatory or
not as a logical consequence from a higher and more general principle. This
general principle was supposed to offer some methodical norm and guide
against which human actions, behavior, and moral character could be compared
and judged. Consistency and consensus in turn represented a positive aim in
morals. By ‘morals’ I understand the highest and most perfect moral system, which presupposes a
complete knowledge of the other sciences and is the ultimate level of wisdom”. Descartes adds that this
ultimate part accounts for philosophy’s greatest benefit: “Now just as it is not the roots or the trunk of a
tree from which one gathers the fruit, but only the ends of the branches, so the principal benefit of
philosophy depends on those parts of it which can only be learnt last of all” (AT IXB:14; Descartes
1985, 1:186).
⁸ See also Leibniz (1765, 4.3.18): “The mere consideration of the goods of this life already serves to
establish important consequences for the regulation of human societies. One can judge what is just and
what is unjust as unquestionably <incontestablement> as in mathematics; for example, this proposition:
There can be no injustice where there is no property, is as certain as any demonstration in Euclid;
property being the right to <droit à> a certain thing, and injustice the violation of a right. The same is
true of the proposition: No government grants absolute freedom. For government is an establishment of
certain laws.”
⁹ WPPU, preface: “Indeed, there was not a lack of those who acknowledged that the theory of
human actions could be subjected to the laws of demonstration, among whom I will name Locke and
Leibniz.”
¹⁰ “I am bold to think, that Morality is capable of Demonstration, as well as Mathematicks: since the
precise real Essence of the things moral Words stand for, may be perfectly known; and so the
Congruity, or Incongruity of the Things themselves, be certainly discovered, in which consists perfect
knowledge” (Locke 1975, 3.11.16); see also Sheridan (2020).
46
¹¹ In his Essay, Locke himself illustrates this idea by analyzing several moral propositions such as
“No Government allows absolute Liberty” (1975, 4.3.18). The definition of government already contains
a reference to the law, it is easy to demonstrate its incompatibility with absolute liberty (allowing
anyone to do as they please). See also Leibniz’s (1765, 4.3.18).
¹² See in particular Leibniz (1667) and (1671–2).
¹³ In his review of a collection of letters by Locke in 1711 (Acta eruditorum, October 1711, 474–80),
Wolff asserts that Locke seems to have accepted that he will not realize his mathematization of morals
project when he locates the heart of moral doctrine in the New Testament (p. 477). See also Schwaiger
(2005).
47
methodo mathematica, and that I did not remain with the old pattern <ich
auch nicht bey der alten Leyer verblieb>, but sought to go further, he asked
me whether I had studied mathesin, since his intention was to employ me in
the Actis. (Wolff 1980 133)¹⁴
According to Wolff, Mencke¹⁵ (who later sent the treatise to Leibniz¹⁶) had
already realized that Wolff was not sticking to the “same old story” and that his
Philosophia practica universalis was not a standard mathesis universalis, nor did
his more geometrico apply in a standard way to any mathematical method.
The early 1703 Philosophia practica universalis already contains a few indica-
tions of Wolff ’s originality. First, while he opts for a classical mathematical mode
of presentation and resorts to definitions, scholia, problems or tasks, and proposi-
tions or theorems, a shift of emphasis from theory to practice is immediately
obvious. Philosophia practica universalis reaches beyond the original Cartesian
mathesis aimed at refuting a theoretical skepticism and/or establishing God’s
existence: it is a practical world-wisdom (Weltweisheit), beneficial for all
humans insofar as it is meant to direct their free actions and educate their will.
As Wolff puts it in his preface, “[w]hen we set out to treat universal philosophy
by a demonstrative method; it is ours, too, to devote the same effort to practical
philosophy, which is by far the most useful to the human race.”¹⁷ Second, one
notes here a distinction between theoremata (Lehrsätze) and problemata
(Aufgaben),¹⁸ with an original emphasis on the latter. This distinction would be
further developed in the bipartite structure of Wolff ’s later treatise, which is
divided into a theoretical and a practical part. In the latter part, Wolff invites
his student to solve a set of practical problems of common relevance, such as how
to wisely direct all of one’s actions throughout life.
The 1738/39 version of the treatise elaborates on the same division. Whereas
the first part contains chapters on: (1) first principles and notions, the difference
between human actions; (2) obligation and the moral law; (3) God, as the author
of the natural law, distributing rewards and punishments; (4) virtue and vice, bliss
and happiness of man; (5) moral conscience; and (6) moral imputation, the
second part is concerned with: (1) moral problems and rules; (2) the most general
direction of human action; (3) the path to be followed toward the highest good
¹⁴ Wolff emphasizes his originality again in the Ratio Praelectionem: “The name of a universal
practical philosophy has so far been unheard of among the philosophers, and perhaps the thing
understood by it has also been unknown” (WRP sect. 2, cap. 6, §2, 191). See Schwaiger (2005, 222).
¹⁵ Otto Mencke, the editor of Acta eruditorum and a friend of Leibniz, who according to Wolff sent
the manuscript to Leibniz, also particularly praises Wolff ’s mathematical skills, describing him in his
letter as a “charming person <hübscher Mensch>” “well versed in omni parte Matheseos, also in
Algebraicis.”
¹⁶ In his autobiography, Wolff mentions Leibniz’s favorable response. On the wider context and the
divergences between Wolff ’s and Ludovici’s accounts, see also Gerhard (1860) and Klemme (2020).
¹⁷ See Wolff (1703, Preface). ¹⁸ Schwaiger (2005, 230).
48
and terrestrial happiness; and (4) how to acquire a guarding conscience and avoid
moral guilt. A third innovation, intrinsically linked to the changes just mentioned,
concerns Wolff ’s assertion of the parallelism or connubium between reason and
experience, which is already reflected in the 1703 treatise. After a first chapter
containing a set of preliminary definitions and a second chapter on axioms, Wolff
in the third chapter presents a set of a posteriori observations.
These shifts allow us to infer the twofold challenge that Wolff faced when
attempting to establish a mathematical moral philosophy: he had to address
both mathematics and practical philosophy, and thus show that mathematics
can be practical and that, conversely, practical philosophy can be mathematical.
The first challenge was to develop a view of mathematical reasoning that
was sufficiently broad to ensure its applicability to practical philosophy. For
Wolff, this meant, first of all, treating mathematics as a form of logic and analytical
reasoning and relativizing mathematics’ exemplary value for philosophy: “The
proofs or demonstrations of the Mathematicorum are nothing else than a bunch
<Hauffen> of inferences <Schlüsse> put together according to the rules of logic
<Vernunftkunst>.”¹⁹
Second, it was important to adopt a view on mathematical analysis that was
broad enough to include all forms of practical and theoretical problem-solving,
and so comprising exercises in both doing and thinking that would be accessible to
philosophers and non-philosophers alike.²⁰ Wolff first laid out these ideas in his
early treatises on mathematics, the Anfangsgründe (first published in 1710),²¹
which already covered both “pure” (arithmetic, algebra, and trigonometry) and
“applied” branches of mathematics (architecture, hydraulics, hydrostatics, optics,
and astronomy). Beyond strictly mathematical and geometrical tasks such as
adding numbers or tracing a triangle from three given lines, these include
more practical and technical tasks such as making bricks (which requires a
rudimentary knowledge of physics and chemistry to protect the bricks from
excessive exposure to cold temperatures and humidity) or drawing a perspectival
plan for a building.²² Tasks (Aufgaben) here offer the basis for conducting proofs,
and they can be transformed into theorems (Lehrsätze).
Far from restricting his classes to an esoteric audience of future mathematicians
and philosophers, Wolff systematically sought to include a broader public, i.e. all
those students who attended mathematics classes as part of the program offered
by the philosophy faculties, or as a general propaedeutics to the studies of the
¹⁹ Wolff 1763, Kurzer Unterricht §45. See also WDP §139, on the identity between the philosophical
and mathematical method. Wolff here takes Leibniz’s side, against Descartes.
²⁰ From 1702 onwards, on coming to Leipzig to teach mathesin and finding this field “lay idle,”
Wolff put considerable effort into the elaboration of this mathematical method of teaching or Lehrart
(Wolff 1980, 129).
²¹ This work of four, sometimes six, volumes was greatly expanded in later editions throughout the
1730s.
²² See Beiser (2009, 50ff.) and Buchenau (2013, 15–52).
49
“higher” faculties, or even just as a preparation for life and travel. In order to adapt
to these different types of audience, Wolff developed two alternative teaching
programs in parallel, the first one offering a more thorough initiation for “who-
ever wants to go back to the proofs” and the second one a more rudimentary
teaching program intended “for life and the traveler.”²³ These changes indicate
more than Wolff ’s strong pedagogical ambition as a teacher of mathematics, as
contemporary accounts suggest²⁴; they expressed Wolff ’s original assimilation of
what was then called the “order of invention” to the “order of teaching,” and his
original notions of method, logic, and systematicity—which in turn explain his
shift of focus to issues of teaching.²⁵
After having begun to clarify these mathematical and methodical premises,
Wolff turned to ethics. He set out his main ideas in the German Ethics before
developing them in more detail in the Latin Philosophia practica universalis and
other treatises. In his view, a methodical arrangement of ethics, far from resulting
from an external and retrospective philosophical ordering, must already be incip-
ient in ordinary moral reasoning. For whoever strives to do the good (which, in his
view, corresponds to a particular task or problem), seeks wisdom, consistency, and
an orderly life (ordentlicher Lebenswandel).²⁶ Such an orderly life, in turn, can be
defined as “the arrangement of one’s actions and omissions in such a way that a
particular intention is always a means to the perfection of our inner and outer
state” (see WPPU 1:§81 and WTL §142). This depends on the agent’s capacity and
habituation for systematizing her duties in such a way that she does nothing
without intention, and indeed composes a “system” in which “each intention is a
means of another and all together a means to the main intention <alle insgesammt
ein Mittel zur Haupt-Absicht>.” In other words, human wisdom and virtue
correspond to a state of perfection (WTL §144), consistency, or concordance of
the manifold (Übereinstimmung des Mannigfaltigen) where everything in the
agent’s actions “is in mutual harmony, and nothing hinders anything else”
(WTL §144). Such wisdom allows us to correct errors of judgment wherein we
mistake an apparent good for the real good, and to establish clear priorities where
there are multiple duties and goods, avoiding conflict between duties.²⁷ This
²³ Wolff develops a similar twofold, esoteric and exoteric, method of teaching in other domains,
such as in his writings on natural law.
²⁴ Ludovici’s article on Wolff in the Zedler encyclopedia particularly underscores the originality of
its method of teaching (Lehrart).
²⁵ On systematicity, see “De differentia intellectus systematici & non systematici,” in Wolff (2019).
²⁶ See also Meier (1764, §7, p. 55): “It is therefore quite natural that such a systematic, profound
and thorough mind as that of the Freyherr von Wolf should have had the idea of systematically and
thoroughly investigating the nature of a duty and of all moral things that are connected with it.
And from this arose the science that is called the universal practical philosophy. It can be explained by
that practical knowledge of the world which contains the first principles that belong either to all or to
several moral disciplines.”
²⁷ Note that this view denies the existence of tragic situations marked by conflicts between equally
valid duties.
50
²⁸ On the directive (or guiding) and fruitful notions in philosophia practica universalis, see also the
interesting preface of the second part on moral practice and WAN §137: “Ich habe einen allgemeinen
Begriff von der Verbindlichkeit gegeben, dergleichen man bisher nicht gehabt (da er) wie alle wahre und
deutliche Begriffe fruchtbar ist.” For a discussion of these terms, see Wolff ’s articles De notionibus
directricibus et genuino uso philosophiae primae (On directing notions and the genuine use of first
philosophy), De notionibus foecundis (On fruitful notions), in Wolff (1729–31, 1:310–50 and 2:105–65).
According to Wolff ’s definition, a directive notion is a notion or concept indicating the direction in
which one needs to think in order to succeed in one’s search.
51
the footsteps of Euclid, who took the laws of true logic very strictly into account,
and accordingly assigned a complete explanation to all words, determined each
and every proposition sufficiently, and arranged the explanations as well as the
propositions in such a way that the following ones could be understood from the
preceding ones and their truth could be elucidated.
The aim of such a mathematical presentation is “to kindle a light for the entire
domain of jurisprudence <der gantzen Rechtsgelehrsamkeit ein Licht angezündet>”
and to prove “what Cicero very skillfully said,³¹ that jurisprudence is not to be
drawn from the Twelve Tables, nor from the orders of the praetors, but from the
innermost part of philosophy <aus dem innersten der Philosophie>.”³² Such a
mathematization, of course, still builds on existing systems and bodies of law,
such as the Roman law;³³ for these provide a set of empirical rules and even a
rudimentary rational system of rules, to be refined by philosophical investigation.
To sum up, since ordinary moral and legal reasoning is already systematic and
scientific in nature, the philosophical and retrospective systematization does not
differ substantially from common practical reasoning, contrary to what Wolff ’s
Cartesian predecessors had claimed.
From this follows a novel proximity between teachers and students of moral
philosophy. Of course, the philosopher remains superior, morally speaking. For
morality, self-mastery and freedom depend on a clear and distinct moral knowl-
edge of the good, and on the intellectual skills of analysis and systematization that
²⁹ Wolff ’s intention of making theology compatible with rational morals is manifest from 1703
onwards. This specifically engages the notion of God as a legislator, introducing a positive obligation
through the very nature of things and distributing rewards and punishments in accordance with
principles of reason and justice.
³⁰ For this reversal of the Cartesian model, see Buchenau (2011).
³¹ Cicero, De Legibus, I, 17. ³² WGNV Preface.
³³ See also Meier (1764, 83): “If one claims that the Freyherr von Wolf is the inventor of the general
practical knowledge of the world, then one is very far from claiming that he invented everything that
this science contains. Cicero in his books De Officiis and De Legibus, Socrates and Seneca, the Roman
civil jurists, the divine scholars, and all moral writers, especially the teachers of the law of nature, have
already taught most of what must be counted as this science. Only the Freyherr von Wolf, in his
Philosophia practica universali, in quarto, has combined all these scattered considerations into a single
system.”
52
allow the individual moral agent to avoid moral errors, resist mistaken judgments
about the good, acquire new moral insights, and free themselves from the slavery
of the senses. And yet, the philosopher can also teach these skills to a broader
public. Far from preaching incomprehensive precepts, she can contribute to the
formation of moral skills, moral character, and true freedom, and thus bears a
particular responsibility to serve the human community and lead the human race
to happiness.
II
³⁴ See Thümmig (1726–7), Canz (1739), Meier (1764), Sutor (1774), and the discussion in Lenders
(1979, 845ff.).
53
In a free determination and its opposite, the are
those ascribed to that free determination for which there are more when these are
summed up for each (BM §697). If someone wishes to excite a greater preference
in some determination rather than in its opposite, then the overriding impelling
causes must be connected with it (BM §§712, 342). (BIP §12)
³⁷ BPB 11, letter 3: “If diligence in philosophy takes away the power of historical and probable
knowledge, of faith, of mathematical insight or knowledge, along with other actions to which I am
obliged, then I do too much in philosophy.” See also BPG and, again, Meier (1764, 59ff.).
³⁸ See Baumgarten (1740).
³⁹ See Meier (1764, 56): “The greater and more varied the light by which it brightens and enlightens
<helle macht und erleuchtet> the doctrine of natural duties, the more perfect is practical philosophy.
Consequently, the clearer, livelier, and clearer is the knowledge it gives us of our natural duties, the
more definite are the concepts of our duties, the more precisely it describes and explains everything,
and the more comprehensible <verständlicher> and easier is its whole exposition <Vortrag>: the greater
is its perfection.”
55
III
Let it not be thought, however, that what is here called for already exists in the
celebrated Wolff ’s propaedeutic to his moral philosophy, namely in what he
called universal practical philosophy, and that we do not therefore have to break
new ground <ein ganz neues Feld einschlagen>.
In the subsequent lines, Kant points out several insufficiencies in the Wolffian
project, which he here qualifies as a propaedeutics to morals and as a theory of
general volition. In his view, Wolff has failed to distinguish the sources of our
moral notions. This accounts for his confusion between pure and empirical,
practical and pathological, forms of willing and motivation, and for his illegitimate
introduction of moral psychology into moral philosophy, as well as for Wolff ’s
flawed definitions of moral obligation and necessity.
⁴⁰ See WPPU 1:§§ 250–323. The reconstruction of Baumgarten’s argument requires consideration of
these two dimensions of his thought which, paradoxically, commentators tend to dissociate, focusing
either on aesthetics or, more recently, on practical philosophy. Such compartmentalization, perhaps
due to the mediocre quality of some of the older Baumgarten scholarship on aesthetics, ignores the
significance of Baumgarten’s aesthetics as emerging from a critique of philosophy and as an attempt to
redefine its boundaries. It therefore engages epistemology and all branches of philosophy, including
practical philosophy.
56
And yet, this statement is contradicted by others that, on the contrary, suggest
Kant’s high esteem of Wolff and the Wolffians and his will to continue, improve,
and defend the same project and its underlying intuitions. In particular, he
appears to seek a better a priori foundation and methodical principle for practical
philosophy than what the Wolffians had to offer, and to seek a solution to the deep
complications introduced by Baumgarten.
Kant’s desire to establish a continuity between philosophia practica universalis
and his own project is manifest in a series of titles: his lectures on moral
philosophy, given twenty-eight times between 1756 and 1794, are often presented
as treating universal practical philosophy and ethics. A course from 1793/94, for
instance, bears the title: “Metaphysics of Morals or Universal Practical Philosophy
along with Ethics according to Baumgarten.”⁴¹ It is also well-known that he
employed Baumgarten’s Initia philosophiae practicae primae as his textbook
from the winter semester of 1759/60 onwards.⁴² Before devoting a detailed
comment to it in the Groundwork and the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant discusses
the value of the mathematical method in philosophy in his 1764 treatise Inquiry
concerning the distinctness of the principles of natural theology and morality.⁴³
And it is striking that Kant, in his Groundwork and the Metaphysics of Morals,
sets himself the same task as Wolff. Affirming the existence of a metaphysics of
nature and of morals, he not only borrows from Wolff his division of the
philosophical system into logic, ethics, and physics where ethics and physics
denote territories determined by two types of law, i.e. moral and natural laws;
he also takes over the very project of locating a priori principles that offer a certain
methodical guidance in the realm of practical philosophy. Similar to Wolff and his
predecessors, Kant emphasizes the practical advantage of such a method, beyond
its speculative interest. Such philosophy helps to fight moral corruption (GMS
4:390) and tendencies toward sterile rationalization (Vernünfteln), providing a
⁴¹ For Kant’s debt to universal practical philosophy, see also the excellent discussion in Allison
(2011, esp. 37–52) and Bacin (2015). Allison opposes Wolff ’s Schulphilosophie to Garve’s
Popularphilosophie and assigns Wolff a rather negative role for the genesis of Kantian thought.
While agreeing with him on Garve’s popular stance and positive influence on Kant, I tend to view
Wolff as being more ambivalent and philosophically richer.
⁴² Kant held Baumgarten in high esteem, and he particularly appreciated the Elements, stating that it
was the “richest in content and perhaps his best book” (PrHer 27:16). On his relation to Baumgarten,
see also the editors’ preface to the English translation of BIP.
⁴³ In UDG, Kant’s emphasis lies on the differences between the mathematical and philosophical
method. In philosophy, the abstractedness and impossible exhaustive analysis of metaphysics’s first
notions constitute obstacles to attaining “the highest degree of philosophical certainty in the funda-
mental principles of morality.” He nonetheless does not lose sight of this aim, i.e. a mathematical
certainty for philosophy. He simply notes that it would require a more reliable definition of the
fundamental concept of obligation and adds that this requires further clarifications “for it has yet to
be determined whether it is merely the faculty of cognition, or whether it is feeling (the first inner
ground of the faculty of desire) which provides <entscheide> its first principles.” On this writing, see
Tonnelli (1959) and the revue Asterion (9/2011).
57
IV
Conclusion. Wolff was the first to succeed in elaborating the ambitious project
with which his early modern predecessors had all been struggling, i.e., the math-
ematization of morals or philosophia practica universalis. Contrary to conven-
tional wisdom, this project already contained a twofold, scholarly, and popular
or “wordly” dimension to the extent that it was built on a wide conception of
moral reasoning and wisdom and addressed philosophers and non-philosophers
alike. From this perspective, it was the birthplace of moral universalism and
popular philosophy—and of aesthetics as an early form and variant of popular
philosophy—as Baumgarten’s critical revision in his Elements shows.
These developments in turn shed interesting light on Kant and his debt to
Wolffian philosophia practica universalis and the ideals of “popular” philosophy—
a philosophy engaging the whole of humanity, not just its philosophical elite.
While his criticism “breaks new ground,” it mainly concerns insufficiencies in the
application of the mathematical method. Despite the claimed distance, Kant is far
from abandoning the earlier project of a mathematical philosophy à la Wolff. On
the contrary, he remains deeply committed to it, attempting to save it from
Baumgarten’s attack and to respond at least to a some of his challenges. His
critical philosophy is meant to offer a more radical and “mathematical” solution,
remedying previous insufficiencies and providing stable foundations. But to fully
appreciate and critically discuss Kant’s move, it is necessary to begin by recon-
structing this very project and by acknowledging its philosophical audacity.
In the Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant asserts that the good will is
the “highest good” (GMS 4:396) of volition.¹ In contrast to a pure rational being,
human beings do not have a “holy” (“absolutely good”) will, whose maxims
“necessarily harmonize with the laws of autonomy” (GMS 4:439). Instead we
are dependent on the principle of autonomy: we can have a good will only if we
determine ourselves to act out of respect for the moral law. Kant calls this
dependence obligation. At the same time, he speaks of “moral necessitation”
(moralische Nötigung) in this context (GMS 4:439). Because we are dependent
on, i.e. necessitated by, the principle of autonomy, there is an “objective necessity”
to perform or omit certain actions. Kant calls this objective necessity to perform
an action “from obligation” (aus Verbindlichkeit) duty:
A will whose maxims necessarily harmonize with the laws of autonomy is a holy,
absolutely good will. The dependence upon the principle of autonomy of a will
that is not absolutely good (moral necessitation) <die moralische Nötigung> is
obligation. This, accordingly, cannot be attributed to a holy will. The objective
necessity of an action from obligation <aus Verbindlichkeit> is called duty.
(GMS 4:439)
¹ The work on this chapter has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research
and innovation program under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie grant agreement No 777786. I thank John
Walsh for discussions on this topic during our stay at CONICET in Buenos Aires.
² MT §523. The whole translation reads: “Die sittliche Nöthigung ist die Verpflichtung (obligatio),
und die Verpflichtung zu einer Handlung die ungerne gethan wird, ist der sittliche Zwang (coactio
Heiner F. Klemme, Obligation as Moral Necessitation and Nötigung: From Leibniz via Baumgarten to Kant In: Baumgarten
and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press.
© Heiner F. Klemme 2024. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0004
60 .
moralis).” Baumgarten greatly expanded his Metaphysica in the second edition and added German
translations to some terms in the fourth. However, he does not translate the expression “necessitatio
moralis.”
³ See, for instance, Schwaiger (2009, 70), Schwaiger (2000, 251), Bacin (2015), and Langlois (2018,
43–4).
⁴ Bacin even claims that there is, in general, no “continuity between their views” (2015, 32).
⁵ Baumgarten, BIP §1. On the definition of ethics as a practical science see BEP §1–3.
⁶ There is a short section on “Preliminary Concepts of the Metaphysics of Morals” in the Preface to
the Metaphysics of Morals, which contains the subtitle “Philosophica Practica Universalis” (MoM
6:221–8). In it he defines concepts like obligation and duty in a way that makes clear that the whole
section is an alternative to the tradition of this discipline.
⁷ However, it is not possible to discuss here the position of Christian August Crusius, who develops
his philosophy in explicit opposition to Wolff ’s psychological interpretation of obligation. For discus-
sions of the debate on obligation in this period, see Hüning (2004a, b), Schwaiger (2000, 2009), Klemme
(2019, 2020), and the contributions by Hüning (2019), Langlois (2019), and Rivero (2019b) in Rivero
(2019a). On the relation between Crusius and Kant see Klemme (2016) and Rivero (2021).
̈ 61
⁸ I am not sure that, for Wolff, the question of the “weight” of a motive is “quite irrelevant.” After all,
he argues that distinct concepts are our strongest motives. In any case, before Baumgarten, the Wolffian
Johann Christoph Gottsched emphasizes the importance of the strength of the motive in his version of
universal practical philosophy, first published in 1733: “For we know that nothing but good and evil, in
so far as they can be distinctly cognized by the intellect, can give a powerful motive <einen kräftigen
Bewegungsgrund> to direct the will [ . . . ]. It is therefore not possible to recognize one action as
absolutely good, and yet to detest it; or to hold another to be thoroughly evil, and yet to will it.
Rather, if this seems to happen, it must be due to the imperfect knowledge of the mind, which does not
quite distinctly represent the good and evil of an action” (Gottsched 1736, §23; edition of 1777, §29).
⁹ See Kant’s answer in the Groundwork to the question posed by Johann Georg Sulzer as to why our
moral concepts are often so ineffective in motivating us (AA 4:411n). For discussion, see Klemme
(2011).
62 .
Necessity and Necessitation: Wolff und Baumgarten. The central role of motivation
in universal practical philosophy is clear from Wolff ’s conception of obligation,
understood in terms of the will’s relation to its motives: “To obligate a will to do
something or not to do something, is nothing other than to connect a motive of
volition or nolition with it” (WTL §8). Our motives are based either on rational
insight into the law of nature or on constraint (or coercion). Rational human
beings need only natural obligation to see the “nature of free actions” (WTL §21)
and to act virtuously.¹¹ For Wolff, reason is the “teacher of the law of nature”
(WTL §23), and through reason the human being is “a law unto himself” (WTL
§24). On this conception of obligation, motives are representations of good and
evil that determine the will. Here Wolff assumes that distinct cognition of good
and evil is, as it were, motivationally irresistible. Distinct cognition is the strongest
motive we can have. The mind judges good and evil, and the will necessarily
follows this judgment (WDM §373). The more distinct our cognition of the law of
nature is, the freer we become. Accordingly, cognition of the law of nature is the
key to insight into the necessity of one’s own actions. Whoever has this insight acts
according to it.
The human will is not “absolutely” rational, but rational only under the
condition that the human being recognizes his natural obligation. Wolff has no
specific term for the transition from a merely possible to a necessary determina-
tion of the will by its motives. If the human being cognizes the good and evil
determined by the law of nature, then it makes no sense, on Wolff ’s view, to speak
of a determination of the will in the sense of a necessitation (Nötigung). If a human
being does what he wills because he has cognized something as good, he is
not forced in the sense of nötigen; he simply acts as he wills to act. He performs
a free action.
Wolff ’s view is implicitly disputed by Baumgarten, who conceives of all
kinds of obligation as necessitation. Accordingly, Baumgarten’s amplification
of Wolff ’s moral psychology entails interpreting all motivation as a psychological
act of coercion. In fact, the German word nötigen—Meier’s translation of
necessitatio—implies that the agent is reluctant to perform the action to which
he is obligated.¹² Yet, if necessitatio just means that a person is incited by a new
motive to act in a certain way, then it is not clear why Wolff could not have used
this expression as well.
Let us examine Baumgarten’s concept of obligation more closely. He addresses
this concept in §723 of the Psychologia empirica of his Metaphysica, in the section
on freedom. Free determinations are moral determinations that express either a
possibility, an impossibility, or a necessity. Morally possible in the broad sense is
“that which can only be done through freedom, or in a free substance as such”
(BM §723). Morally possible (or permissible) in the narrow sense is “that which
can only be done through freedom determined in conformity with moral laws”
(BM §723). Morally impossible in the broad sense is “that which cannot be done
solely on account of the freedom in a free substance,” and in the narrow sense is
that which is impossible “through the freedom that must be determined in
conformity with moral laws” (BM §723). Morally necessary in the broad sense is
“that whose opposite is only impossible through freedom, or in a substance insofar
as it is free,” and in the narrower sense it is “that whose opposite is impermissible.”
The concept of moral necessity in the narrow sense thus indicates that an
expression of freedom possible in itself may not be carried out because it is not
permitted. It is precisely at this point that Baumgarten introduces the definition of
obligation already cited: “Moral necessitation is . The obligation to
perform an act reluctantly will be ” (BM §723).
The concept of obligation relates to that of moral necessity in its entirety. Just as
moral necessity presupposes freedom, so does moral necessitation. Not only does
freedom not contradict moral necessitation, it is a characteristic of the latter (BM
§724). The purpose of moral necessitation is to make an act necessary for a free
¹² The German word nötigen expresses this maybe more clearly than the Latin neologism necessi-
tatio coined by Baumgarten. See also the entry Nötigen in Zedler, Universal-Lexicon, where nötigen (to
necessitate) is “to seek to bring one to do that which, by himself, he otherwise would not have any
particular desire to do. Such necessitation can happen in two ways: either by an irresistible force, or by a
powerful representation” (Zedler 1732–54, Vol. 24, Sp. 1166).
64 .
will. Through obligation, a merely possible act becomes necessary. A special form
of obligation is moral constraint (or coercion).¹³ Baumgarten defines moral
constraint as that by virtue of which an action is performed reluctantly; this
suggests that there is also obligation that we gladly perform, without constraint.
(In this case, however, Meier’s translation of necessitatio with “nötigen” might be
questionable.)
As we have seen, the concept of freedom contradicts neither moral necessity
nor, consequently, moral necessitation. First, a person’s freedom is enhanced
when he distinctly cognizes the reasons that make an action necessary. We can
speak here of freedom as insight into the moral necessity of an action:
Second, God’s actions are not absolutely necessary, “since the opposite of these is
possible in itself ” (BM §902). God is not only free, he is “supremely free” (BM
§902). God has the omnipotence to be able to realize the opposite of all free
actions. However, God is not only supremely free; he also acts supremely “right-
eously” (BM §902). For this reason, his actions are not absolutely, but morally
necessary: “Since [ . . . ] God’s supreme freedom always determines itself most
righteously (§901), all of the actions are also morally necessary while they are
morally the holiest (§§723, 724)” (BM §902). Baumgarten’s justification for the
claim that God always wills the good, is noteworthy: God does not will the good
because he cognizes the good through his reason, as Wolff claims; rather, God’s
will is determined by his love for human beings. God is love and truthfulness (BM
§§903–5). He acts in a way that is morally necessary out of the goodness of his will.
If God did not have a benevolent will, then he would be necessitated by his reason
to do what is necessary. But this is precisely not the case. God necessarily wills the
good, but he is not necessitated.
So, it is clear why Baumgarten uses the term “necessitation”: he simply wants to
distinguish God’s freedom from that of human beings. Baumgarten seeks to avoid
Wolff ’s position, according to which there is in principle no difference between us
and God concerning the way we are determined to free actions by our under-
standing. As Wolff sees it, if we have distinct representations of good and evil,
then we are not necessitated to act freely at all. In this case, we—like God—simply
do what we will. Baumgarten, instead, wants to stress the difference between us
and God in this regard.
¹³ Kant already argues in his lectures on moral philosophy from the 1770s that coercion does not
create obligation (see Kant 2004, 50).
̈ 65
II
¹⁴ “My definition agrees perfectly with the general way of thinking of all human beings” (Meier
1764, §66).
66 .
III
Inclined to, but not Necessitated: Leibniz. In the Theodicy,¹⁵ Leibniz aims to show
that the theory of liberty of indifference advocated by Luis de Molina is just as false
Thomas Hobbes’s view that the human will is determined by physical influence.
The rational monad has a choice because, according to the principle of contra-
diction, it could have acted otherwise.¹⁶ For our purposes, it is important to note
that, for Leibniz, God or a rational monad is not necessitated (necessiter) but
merely inclined (incliné) to choose in a certain way. This is because Leibniz
identifies necessiter with metaphysical necessity. By contrast, the inclination of a
rational will to choose what is best expresses a moral necessity. In the German
translations (Leibniz 1720), l’incline à agir is translated as “antreiben” (to drive)
and obligé as “gehalten sein” (to be required to). The word necessiter, on the other
hand, is translated as “necessitiren.”¹⁷ Gottsched translates necessiter as “nöthigen.”¹⁸
However, he also uses nöthigen to translate the French “obligé,” which, like incliné,
expresses a moral necessity. According to Leibniz, moral necessity consists in the
obligation to choose the best.¹⁹ It is the choice of a being who wills the chosen action
itself. The sage wills the best with moral necessity. His choice is an expression of his
own nature. For this reason, Leibniz calls moral necessity a “happy necessity” (une
heureuse nécessité).²⁰
According to Leibniz, God is also obligated, i.e. necessitated or genötigt (in the
sense of obligé, not necessiter), to act according to his own nature. Gottsched
translates “obligé” here as “gehalten.” God is obligated (obligé) to choose what is
best because this choice corresponds to his nature. His nature consists in his
reason. He is not necessitated (necessiter) but inclined (incliné) to do so. Yet, based
on Gottsched’s translation of “oblige” as “genötigt,” we can also say that God is
necessitated (genötigt) by his own nature to choose the best.
Two further claims by Leibniz deserve our attention. First, the will is deter-
mined (déterminé) by “distinct cognition of the best” (Leibniz 1952, §310).
¹⁵ Baumgarten owned a copy of this work. See the note by Günter Gawlick and Lothar Kreimendahl
in their edition of Baumgarten’s Metaphysica (XVI, note 37).
¹⁶ On Leibniz’s conception of freedom, see Jorati (2017, ch. 5).
¹⁷ “God is prompted to all good; the good, and even the best, inclines him to act; but it does not
compel him, for his choice creates no impossibility in that which is distinct from the best” (Leibniz
1952, §230).
¹⁸ On the impact of Leibniz’s distinction between inclining and necessitating on early eighteenth-
century discussions of obligation, see Schwaiger (2009, 70; 2020, 251). However, Schwaiger does not
consider the possibility that necessitatio is the Latinized version of Leibniz’s nécessitation.
¹⁹ “[ . . . ] between metaphysical necessity, which admits of no choice, presenting only one single
object as possible, and moral necessity, which constrains the wisest to choose the best” (Leibniz 1952,
§367).
²⁰ “This so-called fatum, which binds [obligates; verbindet, ed. Gottsched] even the Divinity, is
nothing but God’s own nature, his own understanding, which furnishes the rules for his wisdom and
his goodness; it is a happy necessity, without which he would be neither good nor wise” (Leibniz 1952,
§191; see also §175).
̈ 67
²¹ “God is prompted to all good; the good, and even the best, inclines him to act; but it does not
compel him, for his choice creates no impossibility in that which is distinct from the best; it causes no
implication of contradiction in that which God refrains from doing. There is therefore in God a
freedom that is exempt not only from constraint but also from necessity. I mean this in respect of
metaphysical necessity; for it is a moral necessity that the wisest should be bound to choose the best”
(Leibniz 1952, §230).
²² See Leibniz (1744, §309). Gottsched also uses lenken in his definition of obligation (Gottsched
1736, §8).
²³ See WTL, Vorrede zu der andern Auflage. ²⁴ On this see Wunderlich (2021).
68 .
IV
Necessity, Necessitation and Nötigen: From Leibniz to Kant. We have seen that
Leibniz, Wolff, Baumgarten, Meier, and Kant often use the same terms but attach
different meanings to them. One of the difficulties in fully grasping the meaning of
their terms arises from the fact that they are parts of complex theories that reach
deep into the realms of logic and metaphysics. A comprehensive understanding of
Baumgarten’s or Kant’s concept of moral obligation would require extensive
reflection on numerous areas of their thought. However, this could not be
accomplished in the present contribution. Nevertheless, we have seen that
Leibniz conceives of a rational being as obligated (obligé) to act according to its
own nature. For a rational being, there is a moral, but not a metaphysical,
necessity to act freely. Meier expresses this moral necessity by the word “must,”
thereby giving it a strong individual psychological imprint in the wake of his
teacher Baumgarten. To obligate—or direct—a person’s will, according to Meier,
is to give him a motive that he cannot resist because it is so strong.
To be sure, Kant takes up Leibniz’s idea that a purely rational being is bound by
its own nature to perform free actions. However, Kant does not use the concept of
obligation to indicate this. According to Kant, neither a relation of dependence
nor of necessitation (Nötigung) is present in a pure rational being (God). For Kant,
God is not inclined (incliné) to choose the best; rather, a holy will follows the
moral law with necessity. It has no choice.
Why Kant does not adopt Leibniz’s language is largely explained by Kant’s
dualism. He believes that the human will is determined by its desires and inclina-
tions (sensibility) as well as by pure reason. Whereas, for Leibniz, God’s will is
determined (directed) by his full knowledge, for Kant, the human will is deter-
mined (directed) by both his sensibility and his pure rational nature. Because of
the specificity of his conception of the (good) will, Kant uses a terminology that
allows him to conceive of the human will as being under a tension that does not
exist in Leibniz and that brings him somewhat nearer to Baumgarten.
It makes sense that Kant employs the concept of moralische Nötigung.
However, this does not mean that he is interested in a motivational-psychological
interpretation of obligation. In particular, it does not mean that Kant proceeds in
the Groundwork “linguistically as well as factually [ . . . ] entirely along the trajec-
tory laid out by Baumgarten” (Schwaiger 2020, 251). The considerations of
obligation addressed by numerous authors in the context of universal practical
philosophy fall within the realm of empirical psychology and concern all of our
expressions of freedom. These authors seek to contribute to the question of how
̈ 69
we can concretely direct the will of people so that they do the good and refrain
from evil. Kant, however, is concerned with a very different question. He wants to
understand how a good will is possible, even though the human will is always also
affected by sensibility. He answers this question by referring to the principle of
autonomy, on which we depend insofar as we could not acquire a good will
without it. For Kant, dependence on the principle of autonomy is the key to
understanding our independence from our desires and inclinations.²⁵ This is in
essence not a psychological relation, for Kant, but a normative one in which we as
human beings stand to ourselves as purely rational beings. Dependence is at the
same time a moral necessitation insofar as the will, which is not absolutely good,
considers itself necessitated to determine itself according to the principle of
autonomy. The act of necessitation does not take place at a particular time, and
it does not entail that the human being is actually determined to act according to
the principle of autonomy. Thus, it does not function as a motive in the sense
employed by Wolff or Baumgarten.
Contrary to the entire tradition of universal practical philosophy, Kant holds
that pure reason itself is the source of a priori concepts and becomes practical
through them. Pure reason becomes practical only if its supreme principle is
represented distinctly enough. (In this respect, Kant’s analyses of the validity of
the categorical imperative also have a motivational relevance.) At the same time, it
becomes clear that Kant no longer regards the concept of obligation as a concept
of a general theory of action; rather, it becomes a basic concept particular to “pure
moral philosophy” (GMS 4: 389). Thus, the concept of obligation can no longer be
applied to the realm of (what Kant calls) hypothetical imperatives. The transfor-
mation of obligation from a moral-psychological to a pure normative concept
involves a narrowing of its meaning.²⁶
In the Critique of Practical Reason, Kant makes clear that the heteronomy of
choice, as we find it in hypothetical imperatives, opposes the principle of obliga-
tion. Heteronomy of choice, as we find it in the universal practical philosophy, is
outside the domain of obligation:
Autonomy of the will is the sole principle of all moral laws and of duties in
keeping with them; heteronomy of choice, on the other hand, not only does not
ground any obligation at all but is instead opposed to the principle of obligation
and to the morality of the will. (KpV 5:33)
²⁵ “This is to say, the sole principle of morality consists in independence from all matter of the law
(namely, from a desired object) and at the same time in the determination of choice through the mere
form of giving universal law that a maxim must be capable of. That independence, however, is freedom
in the negative sense, whereas this lawgiving of its own on the part of pure and, as such, practical reason
is freedom in the positive sense” (KpV 5:33).
²⁶ See Klemme (2019, 27).
70 .
Moral necessitation explains why people feel respect for the moral law but are not
subjectively determined to follow it. The ought expressed by the categorical
imperative is not a must. Human beings are prepared by their feeling of respect
for the moral law to follow it. However, because they are also inclined (to use
Leibniz’s phrase) to follow their desires and inclinations, they have a real choice.
They should act according to the moral law, but they are not determined with
metaphysical necessity to do so. Ultimately, we cannot explain why we do not
follow the law. Our volition remains a mystery to us.²⁷ Perhaps this is the most
obvious point of disagreement between Kant and the tradition of universal moral
philosophy: that tradition accepts the principle of sufficient reason in explaining
why people act a certain way. Kant does not.
²⁷ Kant is clear about this in his Metaphysics of Morals AA 6: 226–7. On this passage see Klemme
(2013).
4
Necessitation, Constraint, and
Reluctant Action
Obligation in Wolff, Baumgarten, and Kant
Sonja Schierbaum and Michael Walschots
¹ Sections I and II of this paper are the result of our equal collective efforts. Michael Walschots was
primarily responsible for section III. Our names are listed alphabetically.
² See esp. MS 6:379 and section 3 below where we reference many of these passages. In the
Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, necessitation (Nöthigung) and constraint
(Zwang) are inconsistently translated, such that Nöthigung, for instance, is sometimes rendered as
“constraint” (see Kant 1996a, 377n.). In this chapter, we consistently translate Nöthigung and Zwang
and their variants as “necessitation” and “constraint” respectively.
³ See Schwaiger (1999, 166–7). Since Schwaiger and others have already investigated the historical
roots of Kant’s language of imperatives, we do not engage with this topic in this chapter.
⁴ In addition to Baumgarten’s Initia philosophiae practicae primae acroamatice (Elements of First
Practical Philosophy) and his Ethica philosophica (Philosophical Ethics), both of which Kant used in his
lectures on moral philosophy, Kant also used parts of Baumgarten’s Metaphysics as the foundation for
his lectures on metaphysics, natural theology, and anthropology. See Naragon (2006) and Bacin (2015).
Sonja Schierbaum and Michael Walschots, Necessitation, Constraint, and Reluctant Action: Obligation in Wolff,
Baumgarten, and Kant In: Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by:
Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press. © Sonja Schierbaum and Michael Walschots 2024.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0005
72
it need not have this character, Kant argues that obligation necessarily involves
constraint to reluctant action.⁵ Not only this, but by conceiving of natural
obligation as compatible with constraint, Baumgarten himself departed in a
subtle but significant way from his most important predecessor, Christian
Wolff, for whom constraint is incompatible with natural obligation. Although
work has already been done to better understand Kant’s conception of obligation
within its historical context,⁶ thus far little attention has been paid to how Kant
and his predecessors understand the relationship between obligation, necessita-
tion, and constraint to reluctant action.⁷ Accordingly, our aim in this chapter is
to sketch the distinct ways in which Wolff, Baumgarten, and Kant understand
the relationship between these concepts in an effort to illustrate the subtle ways
in which their conceptions of obligation differ from each another.
The chapter proceeds in three sections. In section I, we sketch Wolff ’s theory of
obligation, according to which obligating a person involves connecting a motive to
an action. We then illustrate that although Wolff sees constraint as incompatible
with natural obligation, he nonetheless says that it is compatible with a certain
sort of divine or human obligation. In particular, we show that Wolff believes
that obligation is compatible with constraint only when obligation involves the
threat of punishment, and that, in this case, we act without pleasure or reluctantly.
In section II, we argue that Baumgarten makes both some small, mostly termino-
logical changes to Wolff ’s theory of choice, as well as some more significant
changes to Wolff ’s concepts of constraint and reluctant action: for Baumgarten,
acting reluctantly is to act in one way while simultaneously being impelled to act
in opposing directions. We illustrate how this enables Baumgarten to say that
constraint and reluctant action are compatible with natural obligation as well. At
the same time, we emphasize that Baumgarten only believes that natural obli-
gation occasionally takes on the form of constraint, and thus that it sometimes
does not have this character. Finally, in section III, we illustrate that although
Kant preserves much of Baumgarten’s terminology, such as the language of
necessitation, Kant departs from Baumgarten by conceiving of obligation as
⁵ As we go on to show below, Baumgarten and Wolff distinguish between natural, divine, and
human obligation, where natural obligation is equivalent to moral obligation. Indeed, in this chapter we
take natural and moral obligation to be equivalent for Wolff and Baumgarten. Although it is not a focus
of ours in this chapter, Kant distinguishes between moral and legal obligation, i.e., the obligation of
virtue and right respectively. With respect to Kant’s position, our focus is more general, namely to
illustrate that obligation most generally considered, and therefore both moral and legal obligation,
involves constraint to action we perform only reluctantly.
⁶ See e.g. Klemme (2018) and Schwaiger (2009).
⁷ For instance, in the scholarship on Wolff ’s conception of obligation, such as Hüning (2004a, 2004b,
2015); Klemme (2007); and Poser (1980), there is no discussion of reluctant action in relation to
constraint and obligation. The literature on Baumgarten’s ethics is rather small and focuses on very
specific topics. Aichele (2005), for instance, focuses on Baumgarten’s “juridical” conception of conscience,
whereas Osawa (2018) focuses on the role of God. For some discussion of Kant’s conception of obligation
as involving constraint, see Alexy (2015); Baxley (2010, ch. 3; 2015); Sensen (2015); and Villiez (2015).
, , 73
Christian Wolff. Wolff presents his theory of obligation as based on two other
more fundamental positions he holds: (1) his theory of the good, and (2) his
theory of the will.⁸ First, according to Wolff ’s theory of the good, actions and
omissions⁹ are good or evil in themselves and by nature, and not by virtue of the
decision of a human or divine will (WTL §5). More specifically, Wolff argues that
actions are good or evil by virtue of their naturally occurring consequences,
that is, based on whether they make what he calls the internal and external
states of human beings (both one’s own and those of others) more perfect
or more imperfect (WTL §2–5).¹⁰ For Wolff, all actions are either good or
evil in this way, and no action is morally indifferent (WTL §3).¹¹ Second,
according to Wolff ’s theory of the will, when we represent an object as good,
our soul becomes inclined (geneigt) toward or wills the object (WDM §492).
Representing an object as good therefore functions as what Wolff calls a reason
or motive (Bewegungsgrund) (WDM §496)¹² for willing an action and representing
an object as evil is a motive for “nilling” an action, i.e. being disinclined toward an
object (WDM §493).¹³ Indeed, Wolff argues that willing or nilling an action
requires that we represent an object as either good or evil; thus if we performed
⁸ In the Preface to the first edition of the German Ethics (see WTL, Vorrede, unpaginated), for
instance, Wolff clarifies that he proceeds in line with the mathematical method, according to which
everything that comes later is grounded on what comes before, and the first chapter of part one proceeds
by first discussing his theory of the good (§2–5) and theory of the will (§6–7) before moving to his theory
of obligation (§8–11). For a discussion of the more general aspects of how Wolff ’s psychology fits into
his metaphysics, see Goubet (2021).
⁹ For the sake of simplicity, we focus overwhelmingly on action in this chapter.
¹⁰ We cannot discuss the central notion of perfection in the context of our chapter. See Bacin (2017),
Schwaiger (2011a, 155–65), and Schwaiger (2018b) for a discussion.
¹¹ See Favaretti (2024) for the argument that Wolff revised this position in his later Latin works.
¹² In the first index to the German Metaphysics (WDM, Das erste Register, unpaginated), Wolff
states explicitly that Bewegungsgrund is his German term for the Latin motivum. We therefore adopt
“motive” as a translation for this term.
¹³ As we discuss in more detail shortly, Wolff distinguishes between “nilling” (nicht wollen) an
action, i.e., being disinclined toward an object, and omitting (lassen) an action, i.e., neither willing nor
nilling an object (WDM §494).
74
an action in the past, for example, then we must have represented something as
good (WTL §6–7).¹⁴
Strictly speaking, to represent an object as good is merely to will and be inclined
toward the object, whereas choice, i.e. making a decision and acting, requires
representing an object as best, i.e. as the greatest good on balance with other
possible options (see WPPU 2:§335). Wolff makes this point clear with the
analogy of the scale (Wage): when I represent something as not only good but
as the greatest good on balance with other possible options, I act; when I represent
something as the greatest evil, I have an aversion toward or “nill” the object; and
when I represent an object as neither good nor evil or as equally good and evil,
I omit acting altogether¹⁵ (see WDM §509–10). The distinction between mere
willing and choice corresponds to what Wolff refers to as the “ancient” distinction
between the antecedent (vorhergehend) and consequent (nachfolgend) will (DM
§504); the antecedent will is “incomplete” in the sense that it does not yet
possess sufficient reasons for choice, whereas the consequent will is “complete”
because it does possess sufficient reasons (WDM §504; see also WPE §919–20).
Put differently, the antecedent will does not yet have enough motives to
represent something as the greatest good or evil, and thus cannot yet act or
make a decision, whereas the consequent will possesses sufficient motives to
represent something as the greatest good or evil and thus makes a decision,
chooses, or acts (see WPE §919–20).
As mentioned, Wolff presents his theory of obligation as depending upon his
theory of the good and of the will and defines obligation in terms of connecting a
motive with an action: “Obligating someone to do, or omit, something is nothing
other than connecting a motive of willing or nilling to it” (WTL §10).¹⁶ Wolff
offers the example of the sovereign obligating subjects not to steal by connecting
the punishment of hanging to the action of stealing (WTL §8). In this example,
obligation takes place by means of the sovereign connecting evil (the punishment
of hanging) to an action (stealing), such that if a subject were to properly cognize
the evil connected to this action,¹⁷ they would have an aversion to or nill stealing.
In the first instance, however, Wolff argues that it is nature that obligates us to
perform actions that are good and to omit those that are evil, because, as already
¹⁴ Things are a little more complicated than this in that in his early, German writings, Wolff applies
“motive” (Bewegungsgrund) to both distinct representations of the intellect as well as to confused
representations of the senses, but in the later Latin writings he reserves motivum for reasons for action
that are distinct representations only (see WPE §890 and 670). We cannot discuss the distinction
between distinct and confused cognition in detail here. For discussion, see McQuillan (2017) and
Schierbaum (2022).
¹⁵ To be sure, nilling an object does not necessarily require the active avoidance of an object; it can
result in omission as well.
¹⁶ For discussion of Wolff ’s conception of natural obligation and its cognitive and other require-
ments, see Hüning (2021).
¹⁷ Indeed, Wolff ’s theory of obligation accords an important role to our knowledge of good and evil.
For a discussion see Walschots (2024).
, , 75
mentioned, actions have good and evil consequences connected to them by nature
(WTL §9). More generally, however, he argues that we can distinguish between
different kinds of obligation based on the source of the connection between a
motive and a reason for acting: if nature is the source of this connection, then we
are talking about natural obligation; if the source is God, then divine obligation;
and if human beings, then human obligation (WTL §18).
An important, but implicit, aspect of Wolff ’s theory of obligation, which will be
important once we turn to Baumgarten, is that there is a sense in which obligation
can be described in terms of “making an action necessary”: if obligation amounts
to connecting a motive to an action, and human beings necessarily act in accord-
ance with what they represent to be best, then obligation involves making it
morally necessary that a person act in a certain way.¹⁸ Indeed, in the German
Metaphysics Wolff admits that there is a sense in which human beings act in
accordance with what they represent as best with necessity (WDM §521); for
whatever we represent as best determines that we act accordingly. Put differently,
if we represent an object as not only good but the best among the possible options
available to us, then unless something better comes along, we necessarily choose
that object. At the same time, and similar to Leibniz’s defense of freedom in the
Theodicy (see e.g. Leibniz 1952, 63), Wolff argues that the necessity involved in
choosing the best, and thus the necessity involved in obligation as well, is
compatible with freedom because alternative actions are still absolutely possible
in the sense that there is nothing logically contradictory about us choosing
another course of action (WDM §515–16). Thus, Wolff argues that it is merely
certain (gewiss) (WDM §517) or hypothetically necessary that we act in accord-
ance with what we represent as best, but not absolutely necessary in the sense that
alternative courses of action are absolutely impossible.¹⁹ Accordingly, Wolff
defines freedom in terms of the capacity (Vermögen) of the soul “to choose
from two equally possible things that which pleases it the most” (WDM §519),
as well as in terms of a certain kind of self-determination (WDM §519), namely
where the soul is determined to action by its internal representations of the good
rather than by anything external to the soul (WDM §518–19).
Although freedom is compatible with a certain kind of necessity, Wolff argues
that free action is antithetical to constraint (Zwang). As Wolff states in the
¹⁸ Admittedly, things are much more complicated than this. In order for obligation to work, a
number of further conditions must be met. As Wolff himself makes clear in his example of stealing, for
example (WTL §8), the good or evil connected to an action must follow with the same kind of
necessity possessed by naturally occurring consequences. Furthermore, the motive connected to an
action presumably must be of a sufficient strength, otherwise it would have insufficient influence
on our choice (this is a point Baumgarten stresses, as we discuss below). Finally, and as already
mentioned, human beings must be aware of the good or evil connected to an action in order for
such a connection to influence their choice. See Walsh (2024) for a recent discussion of Wolff ’s account
of obligation.
¹⁹ See WDM §575 where Wolff distinguishes between these two kinds of necessity.
76
Vorbericht to the third edition of the German Ethics: “My entire moral science
<Moral> is built on the nature of the free will and knows of no constraint
<Zwange>” (WTL, Vorbericht, §10). When discussing the analogy of the scale,
for instance, Wolff addresses the objection that the analogy implies that choice is
necessary (WDM §510). He replies by clarifying that motives do not “necessitate
<nöthigen>” or compel the soul to choose: “For the question is not whether
motives are a constraint <ein Zwang>, but whether one of them is stronger than
the other” (WDM §510). Wolff goes even further and argues that the will cannot
be constrained, “because we can will nothing except that which we hold to be
good, and we can nill nothing, except that which we regard as evil (§506), but the
understanding cannot be constrained <gezwungen> in its representations; so it is
in no way possible to constrain <zwingen> the will” (WDM §522). Wolff primarily
has what he calls “external” (äusserlich) constraint in mind here, that is, constraint
by a force external to the soul (see WPPU 1:§579). This sort of constraint takes
place either when we are constrained by something external to the soul but
nonetheless internal to the human being (such as when bodily processes force
us to twitch), or when we are constrained by something external to the human
being entirely (such as when another person forces one’s hand to do something)
(WDM §519, 987; see also WGNV §4 and WPPU 1:§580). Wolff also claims that it
makes no sense to conceive of acting freely in terms of “internal” (innerlich)
constraint either (WDM §987), because by determining ourselves to act when we
act according to our representation of the best, we are acting voluntarily
(willkührlich) (WTL §518) and thus are not constrained to act.
A main reason why Wolff conceives of action in accordance with our repre-
sentation of the best as antithetical to constraint is that he conceives of constraint
as the exact opposite of acting gladly (gerne). For Wolff, representing the good is
connected to the experience of pleasure (Lust) (WDM §404), which means that
when we act based on the representation of the best, we seemingly always act
gladly (gerne) or with pleasure (WDM §987). Since freedom simply means
choosing what pleases us the most (DM §519), as noted above, Wolff argues
that it makes no sense to conceive of acting in accordance with the representation
of the best, i.e. freely, as being constrained; for “who would want to say that they
are constrained to that which they do gladly?” (DM §987). This means, of course,
that constraint can only take place if we act ungladly, without pleasure, or
reluctantly (as ungern is often translated). Wolff argues that this only happens
in a very specific case, namely when we prefer a lesser to a greater evil. More
specifically, Wolff argues that when we prefer a lesser to a greater evil, we
intentionally regard a lesser evil as good “in so far as one regards it as a means
to avoid greater evil, even if one does not hold it to be good in itself ” (WDM §507).
In such cases, what we regard as “best” we take to be evil in itself but we
nonetheless represent it as good only because it is both a lesser evil and a means
to avoid an even greater evil. Although we still act in accordance with our
, , 77
representation of the best in such instances, we do not act gladly because we think
that what we recognize as “good” or “best” is not good in itself; thus we do not
simultaneously experience the pleasure that would occur if we thought the object
was good in itself. Accordingly, when we choose a lesser evil to avoid a greater one,
this is the only case where, on Wolff ’s view, we voluntarily choose the best but we
act ungladly, without pleasure, or reluctantly.
In line with the above, Wolff argues that only one specific kind of obligation is
compatible with constraint, namely the kind that involves choosing a lesser evil to
avoid a greater one. As Wolff explains in the preface to the second edition of the
German Ethics: “With this obligation [natural obligation], the human being is
entirely free in its actions and it is never freer than when it acts in accordance with
it: on the other hand, with all remaining obligation we encounter a kind of
constraint” (WTL, Vorrede zu der andern Auflage, unpaginated; see also WTL
§946). Later on in the German Ethics, Wolff clarifies that he conceives of the fear
of punishment as a variety of external constraint (WTL §1023), and thus that both
human and divine obligation can involve constraint insofar as they involve the
fear of punishment. Indeed, if fear of punishment is our primary motive for nilling
an action, for example, then we find ourselves in precisely the unique scenario
described above, namely that of regarding an action we take to be evil (such as not
stealing, if we mistakenly think that stealing is good) as good only in order to
avoid a greater evil (being hanged, i.e. the punishment for stealing) (see WGNV §5
and WPPU 1:§581). As mentioned, however, because we believe that the action we
recognize as good is not good in itself, we do not experience the associated
pleasure and thus do not act gladly. Insofar as we do not act gladly in this scenario,
it is compatible with constraint, since constraint is just the opposite of acting
gladly (WDM §987). As perplexing as it may sound, an important consequence of
this picture is that there is a sense in which performing these obligations is less free
(minus libera) (WPPU 1:§589) than others: if freedom is defined as choosing that
which pleases us the most, and in cases where we act on threat of punishment we
act ungladly, without pleasure, or reluctantly, then these cases are less free. Indeed,
Wolff is explicit that it is less than ideal for obligation to involve constraint
because it treats human beings like cattle (WTL, Vorrede zu der andern Auflage,
unpaginated), and thus does nothing to perfect the will (see WPM 2:§138).
Accordingly, it is only via natural obligation that human beings can achieve true
virtue rather than the mere external habit of goodness (WPPU 1:§321).²⁰
In summary, Wolff conceives of obligation as compatible with constraint and
reluctant action in a very specific case, namely where we choose a lesser evil to
avoid an even greater one, which takes place when we are obligated by means of
the threat of punishment. For Wolff, natural obligation, where we are obligated by
²⁰ This is why natural obligation is moral obligation, namely because only this kind of obligation
perfects the will.
78
nature and are determined by our own representation of the good, is antithetical
to constraint, for we always perform these obligations with pleasure or gladly. In
the next section, we illustrate that Baumgarten makes a subtle but significant
change to Wolff ’s view: he understands reluctant action more broadly than Wolff
and argues that a specific kind of constraint is compatible with natural obligation
as well. This is an important change, we suggest, among other reasons because it is
Baumgarten’s broader understanding of reluctant action that Kant will adopt, as
will be discussed in section III.
II
²¹ See Schwaiger’s landmark discussion of some of these most relevant differences in Schwaiger
(2011a, 118–21, 151–4).
, , 79
Whoever desires or averts intends the production of some perception. Hence, the
perceptions containing the ground of this sort of intention are the impelling
causes of desire and aversion, and thus they are called the
< >. (BM §669; see also §342)
²² According to Schwaiger (2011a, 120fn.343), the notion of “impelling causes” is broader than
Wolff ’s notion of “motive” in that the former comprises rational and sensitive motives alike, whereas
the latter, strictly speaking, only comprises rational motives. See also Carboncini (2021, 205–7) and
Dyck (2018) for a discussion of Baumgarten’s reception and development of Wolff ’s psychology. For a
more in-depth discussion of Baumgarten’s conception of impelling causes and its influence on Kant,
see Walschots (forthcoming).
²³ For an illuminating discussion of Baumgarten’s commitment to and specific take on the principle
of sufficient reason, also in relation to both Wolff and Kant, see Fugate (2014).
²⁴ For a more in-depth discussion, see Schwaiger (2011a, 75–7) and Pimpinella (2001).
²⁵ See BM §669, 671, 675, and 695. In BM §675 Baumgarten distinguishes between three senses of
efficacious and inefficacious willing. We are only referring to the third sort here, because only it
corresponds to the distinction between mere willing and choice.
80
with the impelling causes that speak for alternative courses of action. Thus,
although his terminology is somewhat different, Baumgarten offers a model of
choice that is quite similar to Wolff ’s, according to which choice is “determined
according to preference” (BM §726, our emphasis), i.e. we necessarily choose what
we judge to be best or what we prefer.
This slightly modified account of choice helps explain Baumgarten’s concep-
tion of obligation, which, again, is as follows: “One who connects the overriding
impelling causes with a free determination renders its opposite morally impossi-
ble, and therefore renders the former free determination morally necessary, and
indeed, obligates it” (BIP §13). Baumgarten is therefore clear that to obligate
someone involves not only connecting a motive or impelling cause to an action
or free determination but connecting “overriding” impelling causes, that is,
impelling causes that are sufficiently strong such that, so long as they are correctly
cognized, they would produce “preference” and cause a person to choose and act
accordingly (BIP §12). Indeed, Baumgarten is much more explicit than Wolff in
saying that obligation involves making an action necessary: “One who obligates
renders a free determination morally necessary” (BIP §12). It is even likely that
Baumgarten coined a new Latin word, namely necessitation (necessitatio),²⁶ to
capture the fact that obligation involves rendering an action morally necessary. To
be sure, and as is the case for Wolff, a role for freedom is preserved here in that
choice only follows the judgment of what is best with hypothetical necessity
(see BM §724), not absolute necessity, since the opposite of what I necessarily
choose according to my judgment of the best is still absolutely or logically possible
(see BM §102). Baumgarten therefore defines freedom as desiring or willing
“according to one’s own preference” (BM §719).
The aspect of Baumgarten’s theory of obligation that we wish to focus on for
our purposes in this chapter is the relationship between obligation and constraint
to reluctant action. Generally speaking, Baumgarten defines both necessitation
(necessitatio, Nöthigung) and constraint (coactio, Zwang) as “the alteration of
something from contingent to necessary” (BM §701).²⁷ He quickly clarifies,
however, that absolute necessitation or constraint, whereby “something contin-
gent in itself would alter into something absolutely necessary” is impossible, thus
“nothing can be altered into something absolutely necessary,” including human
action (BM §702). What is possible, in the first instance, is “external” necessitation
or constraint, i.e. “constraint from without” (BM §707). If this amounts to what
Baumgarten calls “unqualified” external constraint, such as when one human
being is pushed by another, then the substance (the human being who is pushed)
“suffers” something and does not itself act. As such, both absolute and unqualified
external constraint are incompatible with action, which Baumgarten defines as a
substance acting “through its own power” (BM §210), rather than by means of
something external to it. When action takes place “through the nature of a
substance” (BM §710) itself, such as when a plant’s leaves face the Sun or the
human body pumps blood, this is “internal necessitation” or “internal physical
constraint” (BM §710). However, while internal necessitation is compatible with
action, it is incompatible with free action because internal necessitation implies
that an action is “physically necessary” (BM §710).
In the Elements, Baumgarten argues that only a very specific kind of constraint is
compatible with free action, and therefore obligation as well. Indeed, Baumgarten’s
discussion of constraint in the Elements begins where the Metaphysics ends, namely
by clarifying that both absolute and unqualified external constraint “do not belong
to free actions” and thus they cannot be called “moral constraints,” nor are they
“obligations” (BIP §50). He argues that only “ , in
which a person is said to constrain himself ” (BIP §51) is compatible with obligation
because only this kind of constraint is both compatible with and presupposes
freedom (BIP §51). Internal moral constraint “occurs whenever we connect over-
riding impelling causes with a certain one of our free determinations” (BIP §52).
The idea is that, distinct from internal physical constraint, internal moral constraint
involves a substance (such as a human being) acting according to preference, i.e.
“freely” as opposed to “physically.” Essential here is that we produce this preference
ourselves: “ . . . occurs whenever we connect overrid-
ing impelling causes with a certain one of our free determinations” (BIP §51).
Baumgarten’s point, of course, is not that we can create obligations at our own
discretion, but rather that we can come to see what our obligations are ourselves.
We come to realize what is best and thereby ascertain what we prefer by counting or
“weighing” the impelling causes in favor of or against various actions, which
Baumgarten calls “” (BM §697).²⁸
A key point to stress about this picture is that internal moral constraint is
compatible with natural obligation as well. Recall that natural obligation occurs
when we ourselves recognize the objective goodness or evil of an action grounded
in its natural implications or consequences. Thus, when we come to realize what is
best by nature, there is a sense in which we ourselves produce the preference
that determines choice and therefore that we constrain ourselves to perform a
certain action. To be sure, moral constraint can also be “external,” namely when
one person constrains another by means of “”, i.e. enticements or
²⁸ Baumgarten offers a fascinating account of deliberation and proceeds to list twelve questions that
one can ask oneself to assist in the process of determining what is best, such as: “how much good can
come about from a given action and its opposite?” and “how much effort is required to make these
options actual?” (BM §696).
82
persuasion, or “”, i.e. threats or dissuasion (BIP §52). Baumgarten calls this
“qualified” external moral constraint and explains that in such cases my action is
both “produced by something else outside of me” and “I am said to
” (BM §714). In both cases, however, namely in both internal moral
constraint and in qualified external moral constraint, a connection is made
between overriding impelling causes and a certain free determination, such that
a preference is produced in the person constrained and they are thereby necessi-
tated. Not only this, but both internal moral constraint and external qualified
constraint are free because, in the case of external qualified constraint, although
the overriding impelling cause is given to us from without, we ourselves none-
theless recognize it and act according to preference (BIP §52), and thus we can be
said to constrain ourselves in this case as well.
In conceiving of natural obligation as compatible with constraint, Baumgarten
departs from Wolff in a significant way. A major reason enabling Baumgarten to
do so concerns his understanding of reluctant action. Baumgarten defines con-
straint (coactio) in relation to free action, which he calls “
,” in terms of “the production of a reluctant <invitae> action” (BM
§714). What is significant about Baumgarten’s view is that he understands reluc-
tant action more broadly than Wolff. According to Baumgarten: “I desire or avert
<invitus> (ungladly <illubenter>, against one’s will <contra lubi-
tum>) when the preponderance is not very great towards preference, or when
many and likewise great things seem to impel me to the opposite of that which
I desire or avert” (BM §713, translation modified). In this definition, Baumgarten
does not restrict acting reluctantly to the case where one acts ungladly or without
pleasure (illubenter) but expands it to refer to any case where we act in one way
but are also impelled in opposing directions. This is a small but significant move
because it means that a broader category of action can be described as “reluctant”
action. According to Baumgarten’s model of choice, a single impelling cause or
incentive is just one reason among many that speaks for or grounds a desire such
that, on its own, a single impelling cause merely impels or encourages a person to
act in the way it suggests but does not determine choice. Thus, although one
would necessarily choose option A, for example, if the total impelling causes
speaking in its favor were greater than those that speak for, say, opposing alter-
natives B and C, I nonetheless remain impelled by the impelling causes that speak
for alternatives B and C when choosing A. Put differently, if I choose A, I not only
recognize the grounds speaking in favor of alternative options B and C, but these
cognitive grounds continue to be moving and exert an impelling force on me
even if I choose A. Thus, while I might necessarily choose A if it has the most
cognitive reasons speaking in its favor on balance with other, alternative options,
Baumgarten’s conception of reluctant action implies that I would perform
A reluctantly if I were to be simultaneously impelled by strong cognitive grounds
that speak for alternative options B and C. This is a much broader category of
, , 83
action than the one Wolff described, where reluctant action, or action performed
ungladly or without pleasure, was limited to the case of choosing the lesser evil to
avoid a greater one. While Baumgarten defines those cases as reluctant as well (see
BM §713), because they involve being impelled by opposing alternatives too, he
expands the definition of reluctant action to cover all the cases where we act in one
way but we simultaneously will alternative courses of action or are impelled in an
opposite direction. This is noteworthy because it means that any instance of
obligation, including natural obligation, that involves a person simultaneously
willing an opposing course of action counts as acting reluctantly. Not only this, but
these cases are also instances of constraint since constraint simply means “the
production of a reluctant action” (BM §714). Baumgarten’s broader sense of
reluctant action therefore makes it possible for him to say that natural obligation
is compatible with constraint and reluctant action as well.
By way of conclusion to this section, it should be noted that while Baumgarten
conceives of obligation as compatible with constraint, he is clear that not all
instances of obligation take the form of constraint. As he states toward the end
of the section on moral constraint: “Sometimes all obligation is called constraint,
but only very broadly and unsuitably” (BIP §55). Indeed, not all action involves
being simultaneously pulled in opposite directions, thus not every action is
reluctant. On the contrary, Baumgarten discusses that it is possible for a person
to act with “pure pleasure” or “sheer displeasure” (BM §713; see also §661), such
that one only possesses impelling causes to either desire or avert a particular
action, i.e. where one possesses no impelling causes simultaneously pulling one in
opposed directions. He also says that it makes no sense to say that one is
simultaneously impelled in an alternative direction, and thus acts reluctantly, in
cases where there exists “a remarkable preponderance” (BM §713) of impelling
causes. As such, when we are obligated to an action by means of impelling causes
that only add to the impelling causes we already possess that speak in favor of a
particular action, for example, such that we only experience pure pleasure or a
large preponderance in relation to one option only, and where we have either none
or very few and insignificant impelling causes that speak in favor of opposing
alternatives, then we are obligated but not constrained. At the same time, the point
of Baumgarten including a chapter on moral constraint in his discussion of
obligation is to explain how some cases of obligation, indeed perhaps many, can
be conceived in terms of constraint, that is, the production of reluctant action,
and that natural obligation is compatible with constraint and reluctant action
as well. This marks an important difference between his theory of obligation
and Wolff ’s.²⁹
²⁹ It should be noted here that, strictly speaking, Wolff ’s philosophy also has the resources to explain
being “impelled” toward opposing courses of action at the time of choosing a particular course of
84
III
Immanuel Kant. One of the most fundamental ways in which Kant departs from
both Wolff and Baumgarten concerns the concepts of freedom and choice. Indeed,
Kant likely had both figures in mind when he refers, in the Critique of Practical
Reason, to the “otherwise acute” men who believe that there is a difference between
choice being determined by representations that originate in the senses as opposed
to the understanding, when in fact both sorts of representation determine choice in
exactly the same way, namely by means of the degree of pleasure involved, thus
leaving no room for the possibility of pure practical reason. Thus, Kant not only
ridicules the psychologically determinist conception of choice common to both
Wolff and Baumgarten by calling it “the freedom of a turnspit” (KpV 5:97), but he
also proposes a substantially different theory of the good, according to which the
goodness inherent to pleasure, which Kant calls “the agreeable,” is different in kind
from moral good, or “the good” proper (see e.g. KpV 5:58).
Kant’s rejection of psychological determinism is significant because it implies
that he rejects understanding obligation in terms of connecting a motive or
impelling cause to an action. Put differently, Kant’s rejection of psychological
determinism implies that he rejects conceiving of obligation in terms of necessita-
tion, if by necessitation we mean making it necessary that a human being act in a
certain way by giving them a motive that determines their choice, so long as they
sufficiently cognize it. Nonetheless, and as mentioned at the beginning of this
chapter, Kant continues to understand obligation in terms of necessitation, so he
must understand necessitation in a substantially revised way.
Consider the following passage from the Groundwork, which immediately
precedes his definition of an imperative quoted at the beginning of this chapter:
If, however, reason all by itself does not sufficiently determine the will, if it is also
subject to subjective conditions (to certain incentives) that are not always in
agreement with the objective ones; in a word, if the will does not in itself completely
conform with reason (as is actually the case with human beings), then actions
objectively recognized as necessary are subjectively contingent, and the determi-
nation of such a will, in conformity with objective laws, is necessitation; i.e. the
relation of objective laws to a will not altogether good is represented as the
determination of the will of a rational being by grounds of reason, to which this
will is not, however, according to its nature necessarily obedient. (GMS 4:412–13)
action: while I might necessarily choose according to what I judge to be best, for Wolff, representing
something as good is not only to will it, but also to be inclined toward it, as we have seen in section I.
Thus, Wolff too might say that I could choose A while simultaneously being inclined toward B and C.
The point, however, is that Wolff describes the scenario where one chooses A but remains inclined
toward B and C as neither constraint nor reluctant action, and that he reserves those terms exclusively for
the scenario discussed above, namely where we prefer a lesser to a greater evil.
, , 85
³⁰ See Stern (2012, 41–99). The difference between the human and divine will for Wolff and
Baumgarten is that whereas human beings necessarily act in accordance with what appears good,
even if they might be mistaken, the divine will is only capable of distinct cognition and thus is never
mistaken about what is good (see WDM §984 and BM §863ff. and 890ff.)
³¹ Reminiscent of Baumgarten, Kant goes on to draw a distinction between two types of constraint
to distinguish between the kind of obligation belonging to right, on the one hand, and to virtue on the
other: constraint, he says, “may be an external constraint or a self-constraint” (MS 6:379, see also MS
6:381–3).
86
following passage from the Metaphysics of Morals which brings all these concepts
together:
In this passage, Kant repeats the point made above, namely that the necessitation
involved in obligation is a function of the human being as both a rational and a
natural being with inclinations that can oppose the moral law. What he adds in
this passage is that necessitation of this sort is to be understood as constraint, and
that constraint “properly” consists in acting reluctantly. Not only this, but Kant
also clarifies in the above passage that acting reluctantly is to act “in the face of
opposition.” Kant reportedly expands on the nature of reluctant action in the
Vigilantius lecture notes on moral philosophy, where it is said that constraint
“consists in the necessitation to an action that one undertakes with reluctance . . .
A thing is done reluctantly by a free being, insofar as (1) there is present in it an
inclination to the opposite of what it wills to do and (2) he nevertheless does what
he wills as a free being” (MSVig 27:519). In the Mrongovius II lecture notes as
well, we are told that Kant believes that constraint “takes place when we have an
inclination to the opposite of an action” and that “constraint always presupposes a
hindrance in the will” (MoM 29:616).³² Understanding constraint and reluctant
action in this way is significant, because it implies that Kant does not have
Wolff ’s narrow definition of reluctant action in mind, but Baumgarten’s broader
definition, according to which we act reluctantly when we act in one way but are
simultaneously impelled to act in opposing ways.
A central feature of Kant’s view, in comparison with Wolff and Baumgarten, is
that Kant stresses that all obligation involves constraint and reluctant action. In
addition to the passages from his published works cited in the previous paragraph,
the lecture notes report that Kant claims that “[a]ll obligation is a kind of
constraint” (MoC 27:269, translation modified) and that “every obligation is
forthwith associated with a moral constraint” (MSVig 27:490). This aspect of
³² Thanks to Jens Timmermann for giving us access to his translation of the Mrongovius II lecture
notes.
, , 87
Kant’s theory of obligation is borne out in detail via his response to Schiller’s
famous objection to Kant’s moral theory. In On Grace and Dignity, Schiller argues
as follows: “In Kant’s moral philosophy, the idea of duty is presented with a
severity that repels all graces and might tempt a weak intellect to seek moral
perfection by taking the path of a somber and monkish asceticism” (Curran and
Fricker 2005, 150). To put the objection more succinctly, Schiller’s primary
problem with Kant’s moral theory is that duty necessarily involves constraint.
Schiller believes, by contrast, that duty involves what he calls “grace,” that is,
“harmony” (2005, 147) with the entirety of the human being as both a natural and
rational being, such that the human being would ideally always do its duty not
reluctantly but “with pleasure” and from inclination.³³ Kant’s official reply to
Schiller in the Religion confirms that the disagreement, or misunderstanding,
between the two authors does indeed concern the proper meaning of obligation
(see Rel 6:23n.). While Kant clarifies there that he should not be misinterpreted as
saying human beings should hate the moral law, for this would lead to them
shirking as many opportunities to be virtuous as possible (see also Rel 6:484–5), he
is also clear that he disagrees with Schiller that obligation “also has a certain charm
(grace) about it” (MSVig 27:490). More specifically, Kant argues that “it is
contrary to the nature of duty to enjoy having duties incumbent upon one; it is
necessary, rather, that man’s impulses should make him disinclined to fulfill the
moral laws” (MSVig 27:490, our emphasis). Indeed, Kant argues that doing duty
from impulse and enjoying duty would destroy obligation entirely. As he explains
in the Vorarbeiten to the Religion:
If all human beings were to follow the moral law gladly <gern> and willingly
<willig>, just as is contained in reason and the rule, then there would be no duty,
just as one cannot conceive of this law, which determined the divine will, as
obligating him. Thus, if there are duties, if the moral principle in us is a
command for us (a categorical imperative), then we must be regarded as neces-
sitated to it, even without pleasure and our inclination. To do duty gladly <gern>
and from inclination is a contradiction. (AA 23:100)
Given the discussion above, it is clear why Kant makes this claim: obligation
necessarily involves constraint and reluctant action, that is, being obligated to act
in one way but always being pulled to act in opposing ways, because necessitation
is made possible by the fact that human beings are both rational and natural, i.e. by
the fact that we possess natural inclinations that can oppose the rational moral
law.³⁴ Thus, as Kant says in the Metaphysics of Morals, “when they [human
³³ See Baxley (2010, ch. 3) for an excellent discussion of Schiller’s objection and Kant’s reply.
³⁴ To be sure, we agree with Baxley, (2010, 110–15), who suggests that Kant’s conception of
obligation in terms of constraint is not a phenomenological claim about what it is like to experience
88
beings] do obey the law, they do it reluctantly” (MS 6:379).³⁵ Vigilantius contains a
nice summary of Kant’s view:
Kant therefore departs in a significant way from both Baumgarten and Wolff: by
conceiving of necessitation as expressing the tension between the sensible and
rational nature of human beings, Kant conceives of obligation as necessarily
involving constraint and reluctant action. Indeed, compared to Wolff and
Baumgarten, Kant’s position is somewhat radical in that, for Kant, there can be
no obligation without constraint and reluctant action.
IV
Conclusion. Our aim in this chapter has been to sketch the distinct ways in which
Wolff, Baumgarten, and Kant conceive of the relation between obligation, neces-
sitation, and constraint to reluctant action. As we have seen, Wolff argues that
natural obligation is incompatible with constraint and that only cases where we
prefer the lesser to the greater evil, such as when we are obligated by the threat of
punishment, are compatible with constraint and reluctant action. We have argued
that Baumgarten makes a subtle but significant change to this view: Baumgarten’s
broader conception of reluctant action, according to which we act reluctantly
when we are simultaneously impelled in opposite directions, allows him to say
that natural obligation is compatible with a certain kind of constraint as well,
namely internal moral constraint where agents themselves bring about a prepon-
derance of impelling causes and therefore constrain themselves. Whereas
Baumgarten argues that moral obligation is compatible with constraint, but it
need not have this character, in the final section we illustrated that Kant conceives
obligation in every instance but is rather a metaphysical claim about the nature of obligation given the
kinds of beings that we are. Thus, even for Kant we may not necessarily experience obligation as
constraint and acting reluctantly in every instance, but only when our inclinations oppose the moral
law. Kant’s point, however, is rather that, as natural and rational beings, we can never be rid of the
possibility that our inclinations might oppose the moral law, and for this reason obligation must always
be represented as being inextricably linked with constraint and acting reluctantly.
³⁵ In fact, Kant adds in a footnote here (MS 6:380n) that his view implies that disobeying the law
involves reluctance as well: no human being is so unholy as to no longer be a moral being, thus from the
point of view of the inclinations, the moral law always opposes their pull as well, so disobeying the
moral law involves constraint and reluctant action for the human being as well.
, , 89
³⁶ For a discussion of Kant’s account of freedom in relation to Wolff, Leibniz, and Crusius,
see Allison (2006).
5
Morality as Both Objective and
Subjective
Baumgarten’s Way to Moral Realism and
Its Impact on Kant
Stefano Bacin
Stefano Bacin, Morality as Both Objective and Subjective: Baumgarten’s Way to Moral Realism and Its Impact on Kant
In: Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers,
Oxford University Press. © Stefano Bacin 2024. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0006
91
makes that delicate transition possible, as it explains how the objective moral
worth of actions can go together with, in fact even requires, their being connected
to the imposition of a superior will.⁵ In this respect, too, the brief but incisive
treatment of objective morality represents a distinctive aspect of Baumgarten’s
account of the foundations of practical philosophy.
These three features of §37 provide the main reasons for devoting closer
attention to that transition in the Elements. To properly appraise its significance,
in the following I shall examine how Baumgarten construes his view of morality in
§§36–8 with a specific focus on the central §37. I shall first consider how he
understands and argues for the key notion of “objective morality.” Then I will
analyze the last, and arguably most surprising of the implications that he draws
per negativum from the main claim, namely that affirming objective morality does
not amount to a rejection of what Baumgarten calls “subjective morality.” Finally,
I will briefly examine how Baumgarten’s distinctive way of taking sides in the
Wolffian camp reverberates through the close dialogue with the Elements in
Kant’s private notes and lectures, thereby deeply impacting the development of
the latter’s own views in practical philosophy.
⁵ Despite their importance, those sections of the Elements have not attracted much attention, to the
best of my knowledge. Schwaiger (2021, 61–3) has considered them with a specific focus on the
meaning of the notion of “morality.” While Grote has convincingly shown how Baumgarten embraces
a few points made by Wolff ’s critics such as J.L. Zimmermann and J.G. Walch (see Grote 2017, ch. 4),
he has not given consideration to how Baumgarten understands the central idea of objective morality,
nor to how he introduces subjective morality.
93
In the second part of §37, Baumgarten suggests that defending the view that
actions have moral worth as such, prior to any command, even independently
from God’s will (hereafter, the “Objective Morality Claim,” for the sake of brevity),
does not have the implications the opponents of that view usually point at. More
precisely, Baumgarten suggests in §37 that the rationalist view does not amount to
holding that the morality of actions lies in, or has its foundations, in their specific
intrinsic properties, although the talk of perseitas and good or evil actions per se
could very well give that impression. The first four of the five points making up the
second part of §37 articulate that general idea.⁶
The first clarification that Baumgarten considers necessary to avoid misconstr-
ual of the “Scholastic” view he defends, is that the Objective Morality Claim does
not imply “that actions external to every nexus, even the nexus with perfection
and their own implications, are already considered good or evil” (BIP §37). If
we maintain that actions are good or evil per se, prior to any possible command,
the thought that goodness and badness are features that can be attributed to
them considered in isolation seems to suggest itself. Goodness and badness
would then be construed as (something like) intrinsic properties. This way of
understanding the Objective Morality Claim would motivate one of the
main objections of its opponents, that is, that “good” and “evil,” as non-reducible
properties, become obscure words, as goodness and badness seem to be presented
as qualitates occultae of sorts.⁷ However, to Baumgarten’s eyes, that is but a
misunderstanding of the Objective Morality Claim, as follows from the definitions
given in §33 and §36: actions are good and evil prior to any command, but
nevertheless only by virtue of their connection to perfection.⁸ In fact, the elucida-
tions in §37 unfold a notion already advanced in §36, where morality is defined
precisely in relational terms, namely as the “relation and convenience <respectus et
habitudo> of a free action to perfection” (BIP §36; compare §82 and BIN §54).⁹
⁶ I shall comment on the first two points here, on the following two in the next section, and on the
fifth in §4. Similarly, Meier (1764) presents the first four remarks in §54 and the equivalent to
Baumgarten’s fifth remark in BIP §56.
⁷ See Walch (1733, 1842): “the Scholastic doctrine is very obscure, as it delivers empty words
without real concepts.”
⁸ On Baumgarten’s understanding of perfection, which I cannot examine here, see Schwaiger
(2011a, 162–5).
⁹ Here I do not follow Fugate and Hymers’s translation of the Elements, which renders respectus et
habitudo with “the respect and habituation”. Aware of the terminological difficulty, Fugate and Hymers
add the remark that “[b]y habituation, Baumgarten clearly means that one’s morality (i.e. morality,
subjectively considered) is one’s condition or character with respect to perfection” (BIP 51n.88;
compare BIP 7: “Morality is the habituation towards perfection in action”). That does not seem to
match the specific context of Baumgarten’s definition, though. The topic at issue is not an agent’s
conscious attitude or consistency in a certain way of conduct, which yield a habit, but the moral quality
of token actions. In fact, the meaning of habitudo in Scholastic Latin is not anything like “habit”
(habitus), but very close to “relation”, more specifically a relation of purposiveness or suitability (see e.g.
Penner 2013, 3), which I try to render here with “convenience”. Thus, unlike a habit, a habitudo can be
ascribed to things, while habits are ascribed to agents. Baumgarten’s phrasing clearly shows that the
94
term is understood in that meaning: “respectus sive habitudo” is virtually a hendiadys, which puts an
emphasis on the purposive character of the relation. Note that also Baumgarten’s Metaphysics gives
clear indication in that sense. There he provides the following definition: “The respective determina-
tions of possible things are respects [respectus] (habituations <habitudines>, ta pros ti, relations in a
broad sense, either external or internal)” (*. § 37). “Habitudo” is thus to be taken as roughly
synonymous with “relation”. Accordingly, Meier, whose work closely follows the Elements* of his
teacher Baumgarten, defines morality (Sittlichkeit) of actions as “their relation <Beziehung> to the
perfection or imperfection of the human being” (Meier 1764, §50, 102). Aichele’s rendering of habitudo
with Beziehung can thus better convey the proper meaning of the term (see Baumgarten 2019a, 55).
Quite the same holds true for §82 of the Elements, to which Fugate and Hymers appropriately refer in
their annotation to §36.
¹⁰ See BIP §36: “Good free actions are related to perfection as means.”
¹¹ See BM §62: “A non-being (negative, cf. §54) would be something possible but not determinable
with regard to existence (§61). But this is impossible, and if it appears to be a being, it is a fictional being
(a being of reasoning reason).”
¹² In this regard, Meier invokes the risk of a sort of moral idealism implied by that misunderstanding
of objective morality (or internal morality, in his vocabulary): “For, if one would maintain that, should
no rational beings represent themselves a free action as morally good or evil, then no action would be
good or evil, then one could just as well conclude that nothing would be actual if there were no thinking
beings who represent something to themselves. Consequently, one could just as well infer that
everything exists in thoughts” (Meier 1764, §54, 109f.).
95
(or intrinsic) morality’ (innere Sittlichkeit, moralitas intrinseca), which they take to
be synonymous with “objective morality”.¹³ A few years later, Baumgarten’s pupil
Meier would have done the same as well (Meier 1764, §§51ff.). It is remarkable
that, while Baumgarten often suggests conceptual and terminological connections,
adding to many terms further corresponding concepts in brackets, he conspicu-
ously does not do so with regard to objective morality. We should thus assume
that he does not consider the term as properly equivalent to “internal morality”
(moralitas interna) as opposed to “external morality.” In fact, the label “external”
would denote a relational determination, while “internal” would not include
relations.¹⁴ But Baumgarten’s main point is, on the contrary, that morality is to
be articulated in terms of relations. Thus the label “internal” would be misleading
at best. It is precisely because objective morality is commonly conceived of as
“internal” that we need to focus on its profoundly relational character.
II
Objective Morality and God’s Will. The insistence on the relational character of
objective morality leads to Baumgarten’s third point in §37: the Objective Morality
Claim is compatible with the thought that “the existence of morality in deeds <in
factis>” cannot have “a sufficient ground outside the will of God” (BIP §37). In
fact, the Objective Morality Claim is not merely compatible with it, but requires
support from that idea, as Baumgarten’s reference to §933 of his Metaphysics
makes clear. There he had argued that the world goes back to God’s perfect will.¹⁵
Although the objective moral quality of an action is independent of any prior
command, even imposed by God’s will, that quality is rooted, through relations, in
the fabric of the world that has in God its ultimate sufficient ground. If the
goodness and badness of actions lies in their relation to perfection, it can exist—
that is, actions can actually be good or bad—if and only if those relations hold.¹⁶
This, in turn, depends on the overall order of the world, which has its ultimate
ground in God.¹⁷ Thus, in Baumgarten’s view, the Objective Morality Claim not
only does not rule out, but in fact requires backing by the thought that God’s will
¹³ See e.g. Thümmig (1726–7, 1:§12): “Actions are either good as such, or evil as such. And the
intrinsic morality of free actions consists in that <actiones aliae per se sunt bonae, aliae per se malae.
Atque in eo consistit intrinseca actionum liberarum moralitas>.” See also KE §327.
¹⁴ Baumgarten had equated objective with internal and subjective with external in BIP §29, with
regard to obligation. He never does so with regard to morality.
¹⁵ See BM §933: “God created this world most freely (§932). Therefore, he willed to create it (§893).
He willed it efficiently (§671) and hence completely, because he is infallible (§879), and consequently
from complete motives.”
¹⁶ On Baumgarten’s conception of existence see BM §55. See also Fugate (2018).
¹⁷ Analogously, Meier distinguishes between “next and immediate sufficient ground,” which lies in
human nature and the internal quality of its actions, and “the first sufficient ground of everything that is
actual in the world,” which lies in God’s choice (1764, §53, 107).
96
is the ultimate sufficient ground of the world. With his third point, Baumgarten
rejects what might be called “independent moral realism,” that is, the view that
objective morality exists necessarily, independent from any act of God’s will,
which it in fact governs.¹⁸ On the contrary, Baumgarten argues, God’s will is
indispensable to the existence of objective morality, because objective morality
exists necessarily in relations grounded on God’s will.
At this point it has become clear that Baumgarten is willing to grant to the
atheist only a narrowly limited ability to cognize morality.¹⁹ His view on the
matter is phrased, from a different angle, also in the fourth point of §37. Other
Wolffians are prepared to emphasize that, since the morality of actions is directly
related to the features of human nature, even one who is not prepared to
acknowledge the divine order of the world can grasp the essential moral properties
of actions, that is, their “internal morality,” and can thus become a virtuous
person.²⁰ That is precisely what the fourth of Baumgarten’s points in §37 refrains
from conceding. He stresses that the Objective Morality Claim does not entail
“that all implications of free actions are determined through the nature of the
action or agent alone (§33, BM §408)” (BIP §37; emphasis added). Baumgarten
thus insists that referring to the features of human nature cannot be enough,
because objective morality is to be properly grasped only with regard to the system
of relations it is rooted in, which in turn cannot leave out the ultimate ground of
that system, namely God. He supports his view by referring back to the section of
the Elements in which Baumgarten had defined that the moral worth of action
depends on the implications, or consequences (consectaria), of that action. What
matters, now, is that Baumgarten holds that those consequences can be both
natural and “chosen <arbitraria>,” that is, depending on “the free choice <arbitrium>
of someone” (BIP §33). The connection of an action to its consequences, therefore,
cannot be exhausted by considering only the features of human nature, without
referring to God’s will. Moreover, those connections are in fact part of a larger
system, as the reference to Metaphysics §408 suggests, where Baumgarten
argues that all elements of the world are interconnected.²¹ Combined with the
claim made per negativum in the third point of §37, Baumgarten’s fourth point
about objective morality is that actions are good and evil by virtue of the network
of connections with their consequences that is arranged by God’s will.²²
In this light, even the first sentence of §37 does not grant so much to the atheist
as it might appear at first glance. It rather puts a demand on him: “Objective
morality must be attributed <tribuenda est> to free determinations by the theo-
retical atheists themselves” (§37). Somehow reversing the more conciliatory view
that the atheist can grasp features of the world that allow him to reach a certain
grade of apprehension of morality, Baumgarten remarks that, properly speaking,
objective morality pushes the atheist beyond the limits of his untenable position. If
morality, as objective, is rooted in relations that bring together the overall order of
the world, someone who is not prepared to recognize God as its ultimate ground
cannot cognize objective morality as such either. An atheist can maybe appreciate
some connections of certain actions to the perfection of some traits of human
nature, but that is only scratching the surface of objective morality, which remains
unattainable to him in its entirety. Objective morality “must be attributed” to
actions even by the atheist, who however would thus be committed to give up his
atheism. In accordance with this take on the issue, Baumgarten, unlike Wolff,
never refers approvingly to Grotius’s “impossible hypothesis” that morality would
hold even if there were no God (see e.g. WTL §5, p. 7, and WAN §395).
Thus Baumgarten has a viable response to a further objection of Wolff ’s
adversaries, namely, that only the theological voluntarist who holds a divine
command theory can properly account for the morality of actions, without ending
up in a regress, since he can point at a first cause that has made some actions good
and some bad (see Walch 1733, col. 1841). On his part, Baumgarten intends to
provide such an account, without making morality dependent on anything else
and thereby contingent, that is, without giving up genuine objective morality. In
his view, the ultimate cause of morality is the same as nature’s, that is, God’s will.
It is God’s will which sustains the features of human nature and its perfection, in
relation to which the morality of actions is determined.
Thus the compressed argument sketched in the remarks 1 to 4 of §37, sup-
ported by the important sections of the Metaphysics that Baumgarten refers to,
points out that the objective morality of actions should not be construed as an
intrinsic property, or with regard to intrinsic properties, of actions, although that
²² Note that this entails that Baumgarten cannot actually endorse the talk of perseitas, although he
employs that term in brackets after introducing the notion of objective morality, as I have mentioned
earlier: “morality is attributed as objective to actions either insofar as they are seen as good or evil per se
(perseity before the will of God, etc.)” (BIP §36). “Perseitas” would denote what is purely self-standing and
can be considered independently from any relation at all. But that would counter Baumgarten’s idea of
universal connection, as put forward in BM §408. The fact that the term “perseitas” never occurs in
Baumgarten’s Metaphysics strongly suggests that he uses it in the Initia only to make reference to the debate
on the foundations of morality, without actually endorsing its traditional meaning. On Baumgarten’s use of
“per se,” however, compare BM §15. (Thanks to Courtney Fugate for pressing me on this.)
98
would appear to be the most natural way for actions to be recognized as good or
bad per se. Rather, Baumgarten argues, morality lies in relations, primarily to
human nature, and mediately to the entire order of the world as sustained by the
action of God’s will. That result brings Baumgarten to the fifth and most surpris-
ing of the claims in §37, namely that objective morality does not rule out subjective
morality. I shall thus turn to that last point.
III
Subjective Morality: The Prescriptive Character of Morality. The last of the five
crucial elucidations given in §37 formulates the outcome of the revision of
the Objective Morality Claim articulated in the first four points. At the end of
his reworking of the implications of that claim, Baumgarten simply observes that,
since holding that there is an objective morality does not entail any of the
consequences examined up to that point, then (“hence”) it does not amount to
maintain “that there is no subjective morality” either (BIP §37). In the previous
section, he had distinguished between the morality that is to be attributed to actions
“insofar as they are seen as good or evil per se” and the morality attributed to them
“insofar as they are good or evil because of someone’s free will” (BIP §36). If, as
I have noted above, Baumgarten’s choice to focus on the notion of objective
morality, instead of the more common talk of “internal morality,” is already
unusual, it was even more so to maintain that the two can go together. In fact,
however, Baumgarten argues for more than the mere possibility of that connection.
The very laconic phrasing of the fifth point in §37 (only four words in the
original Latin) requires clarification. That remark would prima facie seem to mean
that subjective morality must not be ruled out. Analogously, the first sentence of
§38 reads that “subjective morality, through the positing of objective morality, is
not denied even in actions that are good or evil per se, and it does not deny
objective morality” (BIP §38; my emphasis). The carefully phrased sentence would
seem merely to allow that attributing objective morality to actions does not deny
that there is room for subjective morality too. The reference to §36 and the
previous four points, though, make clear that Baumgarten argues for a stronger
and more meaningful view. Once the elucidations in §37 have explained that
objective morality does not rule out, in fact requires, that the moral worth of the
same actions be related back to God’s will, then it becomes apparent that the
distinction in §36 does not differentiate between cases, but between perspectives
from which genuine moral worth is attributed to actions.²³ Crucially, though,
those perspectives are not optional, but both apply to all actions, even to those that
²³ A similar view seems to be suggested by Baumgarten’s teacher Köhler. See KE §411: “We shall
note a double source of morality, springing from a different way to consider. For the morality of actions
99
are per se good or bad. Besides §37, the relevant background for that conclusion is
provided by an elusive statement in §33, which is bound to remain rather obscure
in its original context, before the further development of the argument. There
Baumgarten had remarked that the implications of actions are natural, as they are
“more closely and adequately connected with a free determination through its
nature and that of the subject to whom it belongs, and are natural” or “chosen,” if
they are connected with the action “through the free choice of someone.”
However, since the implications can be “connected through both,” “it is wrong
to conclude that if the implication is natural, it for that reason is utterly not
chosen, and that if it is chosen, then for that reason it is utterly not natural” (BIP
§33). God’s will, thus, gives a teleological order to the elements of the world that
make the morality of actions both objective and subjective.
In Baumgarten’s actual, stronger view, thus, the Objective Morality Claim
entails that subjective morality must be attributed to actions as well, that is, that
their objective morality must be connected with their subjective morality: they are
good or bad per se just in view of the fact that “they are good or evil because of
someone’s free will” (§36), namely God’s. Recall that the third remark in §37 has
established that the existence of morality (where “morality” was appropriately not
qualified) requires a connection to God’s will. In the terms that we have now
reached, therefore, that means that morality exists—that is, actions actually have
moral worth (or must be recognized as having such)—only as both objective and
subjective, that is, as both belonging to the very nature of things (primarily human
nature) and sustained by God’s own will.²⁴
The epistemological implications of that claim are made explicit in §38. If
morality has those two faces, it can be properly cognized from both sides: “it is
valid to conclude with certainty, due to the choice <arbitrium> of God, from a
subjective morality known from elsewhere to a similar objective morality,” as
much as “it is valid to conclude with certainty, in regard to the choice of God, from
an objective morality known from elsewhere to a subjective one” (BIP §38).²⁵
Importantly, the path from nature (that provides evidence of objective morality)
brings us beyond the domain of nature, that is, to our equation of it with the
subjective morality of the relevant actions with regard to God’s will. The cognition
of morality through natural relations ultimately leads to the domain of natural
theology. Notably, this does not contrast with Baumgarten’s initial definition of
is referred either to their implications or to a law that represents their implications <Annotemus
duplicem fontem moralitatis, ex diverso modo considerandi oriundum. Moralitas enim actionum vel
refertur ad consectaria earum, vel ad legem, consectaria repraesentantem>.”
²⁴ A similar claim had been already defended by Baumgarten about obligation: “Since some
obligations can likewise be more closely and adequately known from nature and choice, the obligation
to one and the same thing can be simultaneously objective and subjective, or natural and chosen”
(BIP §30).
²⁵ Baumgarten makes the same point again later on in BIP §82 in terms of natural laws and divine
positive laws.
100
actions as well, if only by virtue of the connection to God’s will. Thus Baumgarten
argues not only that morality might appropriately yield concrete norms,²⁶ nor
does he suggest, as Kant would later, that the prescriptive character of moral
norms depends on the limits of the faculties of finite beings like humans. Rather,
on Baumgarten’s view, morality is essentially prescriptive, that is, it must be
spelled out in norms because it is at the same time both objective and subjective.
Baumgarten’s distinctive emphasis on obligation from the outset of the
Elements entails a modified understanding of objective morality that goes beyond
the Wolffian view.²⁷ Drawing on Wolffian materials, Baumgarten adds with the
claims of §§36–8 an important argumentative step to the common Wolffian view.
If we consider how Wolff ’s view unfolds both in the German Ethics and the later
Philosophia practica universalis, we notice that he starts with an account of the
features of free actions, arguing then that they are good or bad in themselves
because of their natural features. That natural morality is presented as the source
of obligation and the content of the law of nature.²⁸ Baumgarten’s careful treat-
ment of objective morality finds no direct correspondence in the steps of Wolff ’s
argumentative path, not to mention the notion of subjective morality. Unlike
the (other) Wolffians, Baumgarten begins with examining the notion of obliga-
tion, which determines the overall outlook of the entire Elements.²⁹ Only after
having established how obligation is to be conceived of in its different compo-
nents, he considers how the goodness and badness of actions can be construed
in that light (§§32–5). Then, unlike the (other) Wolffians, Baumgarten needs to
show where proper obligation has its foundations and why in turn those founda-
tions yield prescriptions. This is achieved with the thesis that the Objective
Morality Claim involves that subjective morality must be attributed to all actions
as well.
Thus the conclusion that morality is to be spelled out in norms justifies the
role that the sections on (objective and subjective) morality (BIP §§36–8) play
in the overall argument of the first chapter of Baumgarten’s Elements. Only once
he has established the claims that I have examined so far, can Baumgarten
introduce the main imperatives in which morality is spelled out: “do the good,”
“seek perfection,” “do what is the best for you to do,” “live according to nature.” These
fundamental prescriptions are the main focus of the last sections of the foundational
chapter of his entire practical philosophy (BIP §§39–49). There he simply
²⁶ Something of the sort seems to be suggested by Schwaiger’s remark on this point: “With this
expansion of Wolff ’s doctrine, Baumgarten takes into account the fact that morality is always reflected
in the personal attitude to concrete historical and social moral norms.” (2021, 62f.).
²⁷ Schwaiger (2021, 62f.) sees here an “extension of Wolff ’s doctrine” on Baumgarten’s part.
²⁸ See WTL §§1–20, WPPU 1: chs 1–2 (§§9–114 and §§115–270). See also the compact survey in
WAN §137. Compare, e.g. Thümmig (1726–7, 1: chs 1–2); Gottsched (1736, chs 1–2, §§14–29).
²⁹ See Schwaiger (2011a); Bacin (2015, 19–24).
102
observes that “the imperatives in the practical disciplines indicate that the human
being is under an obligation <significant, hominem obligari>” (BIP §39; transla-
tion modified).³⁰ They express the fact that the “human being is obligated to
commit the good, and hence to omit evil.” That requirement, however, does not
merely follow from the fact that human beings are subjected to a specific com-
manding authority. That demand primarily articulates the existence of morality as
sustained by God’s will, that is, as both objective and subjective.
IV
³⁰ On Baumgarten’s notion of imperatives and its impact on Kant see Schwaiger (1999, 165ff.).
³¹ On the main features of that dialogue, with references to further literature, see Bacin (2015) and
the introduction and the materials collected in Fugate and Hymers’s translation of the Elements.
103
³² In one peculiar case, Kant experiments with employing the distinction between objective and
subjective morality to distinguish “degrees of the practical worth of actions”: see AA 19:301f.
³³ For the new critical edition of the Moral Mrongovius II and the English translation, see Kant
(forthcoming). See there the notes to 29:616 with further comments on those remarks.
³⁴ On this see Bacin (2018a, 55–7).
³⁵ On Kant’s appraisal of prior rationalist accounts of morality, see Bacin (2018a).
104
account for both the foundations of moral normativity (or evaluative properties)
and its (their) constitutive prescriptive force. In this respect, Baumgarten’s
Elements could provide Kant with an example of a view that aimed at overcoming
the weaknesses affecting traditional rationalist views, that is, primarily the inabil-
ity to account for the bindingness of morality.
Now, if Baumgarten’s view could have been of help in identifying the central
issue and the shortcomings of the previous discussion, for Kant it did not provide
a viable solution, as we gather from his comments. Thus the account of morality
that Kant developed did not follow the lines suggested by Baumgarten’s. Most
significantly, Kant was not prepared to endorse the strongly teleological view of
nature that is integral to Baumgarten’s account, which centers on the order
sustained by God’s will. If anything, Kant moved in the opposite direction.
While Baumgarten aimed to suggest a more convincing way to regard normative
properties as rooted in the nature of things, Kant eventually argued that what is
morally relevant cannot have its foundations within nature, precisely because that
would rule out the objectivity of morality (i.e. its necessity and immutability).
Accordingly, one of Kant’s notes to §36 stresses, against Baumgarten: “Goodness
is either moral or physical” (AA 19:21). Kant endorses the Objective Morality
Claim, but construes it not in terms of properties or natural relations, but of laws:
the moral worth of actions is necessary and immutable because of their (non-
natural) relation to the moral law.³⁶
Concluding Remarks. A closer look at §§36–8 of the Elements thus reveals impor-
tant aspects of Baumgarten’s distinctive way of embracing the moral realism of
Wolffian rationalism. Baumgarten aims to defend the view advocated by prior
Wolffians, but he does so in original terms. Instead of suggesting that actions are
per se good or evil simply because of some essential attributes, he proposes to
construe their moral worth in relational terms. This view opens up a broader
perspective, in which the morality of actions is determined only within the larger
context of the teleological structure of reality. This in turn leads to understanding
their worth as belonging to the overall order of the world supported by God’s will.
Thus, he argues, objective morality must be regarded, at the same time, as
subjective. Because of that dual character, morality is at the same time necessary
and immediately prescriptive.
Baumgarten thereby moves between independent moral realism and divine
command theory. In his view, God is the metaphysical ground of moral properties,
³⁶ On how Kant’s account unfolds from the aim of presenting a hybrid view along these lines,
see Bacin 2018b.
105
but indirectly, namely in a way that depends upon the overall structure of the
world. Thus moral properties can indeed be considered per se, but only when the
focus is only on their relations with the connected implications in nature. That
cannot but remain a partial and superficial consideration, though, as it misses the
proper ground of the normative importance of those connections. The atheist—
whom we might probably also call the “naturalist,” as he only accepts natural
explanations—cannot but fail to account for the emergence of normative properties.
In his account, Baumgarten tries to combine a Wolffian position with elements of a
quasi-voluntarist account in order to explain the fundamental bindingness of
morality. On his view, neither horn of the Euthyphro dilemma is sufficient. Its
solution is to find the proper way to combine both horns.
This proposal is presented in the Elements as an attempt to make a case for a
Wolffian view, defending the Objective Morality Claim. Yet, because of its dis-
tinctive features, it can be seen as an attempt to move beyond the original terms of
the debate. Four decades after the publication of Wolff ’s German Ethics, the
ensuing discussion was worn out enough that merely taking a stance in one or
the other camp was hardly reasonable or appropriate. Re-affirming one view or
the other in their traditional terms could by then sound like nothing else than
a verbal dispute.³⁷ Contributing to the debate required a new perspective on the
issue, accommodating the desiderata of both factions. The hybrid, conciliatory
character of Baumgarten’s take is also a reaction to the state that the debate had
reached by then. Also because of that character, Baumgarten’s distinctive treat-
ment of objective morality could provide Kant with a thoughtful attempt at
pursuing an integrative strategy in accounting for its most fundamental features,
namely its necessity and bindingness.
³⁷ See e.g. Ahlwardt (1752, §765): “The whole quarrel as to whether morality depend on God’s will
or there is a moralitas objectiva is, in our view, a mere, useless battle of words.”
6
“At tu nomen inane es”
Baumgarten and Kant on the Legislator:
Moral Theology and Justice
Gualtiero Lorini
First, we must clarify, in a preliminary way, the meaning of the quotation placed at
the beginning of the title of this chapter. It comes from a tragedy by Dio Cassius and
had much fortune thanks to its retrieval by Francis Bacon (Bacon 2001, 189). In this
tragedy, Brutus, on the point of death, complains that all his life he had revered
virtue by esteeming it a concrete thing (ut rem), but has now painfully realized that
it would be nothing but an empty name (nomen inane). This quotation expresses
indeed a paradoxical and, in some ways, provocative outcome, to which Kantian
ethics risks exposing itself if one focuses on the assumptions that lead it to part ways
with a conception of ethics that assigns a foundational role to moral theology, such
as that of Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten. The framework of this possible reading is
what we shall try to elucidate in the present chapter.
¹ See Announcement of the Program of his Lectures for the Winter Semester 1765–1766, AA 2:308,
tr. 1992:295; KrV A21/B35, tr. 1998:156; Letter to Herz, November 24, 1776, AA 10:198, tr. 1999:159.
Gualtiero Lorini, “At tu nomen inane es” Baumgarten and Kant on the Legislator: Moral Theology and Justice.
In: Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers,
Oxford University Press. © Gualtiero Lorini 2024. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0007
“ ” 107
² I say “as well” with regard to moral philosophy since many studies have by now pointed out the
peculiarities of Baumgarten’s metaphysics within Wolffianism: see e.g. Casula 1973; Fugate and
Hymers 2018; Lorini 2022.
³ For an overview of Baumgarten’s plan for a universal practical philosophy see BDO §22; BSEP
§161–3; BPG §149. In this latter work Baumgarten presents a plan, later disregarded in the printed
writings, which actually included a doctrine of virtue and happiness as well (see Bacin 2015, 20;
Schwaiger 2008, 223 n.19).
108
⁴ See Köhler: “moral obligation in general is the connection of motives with actions” (KE §300).
Bacin (2015: 19) highlights that through his emphasis on obligation “Baumgarten departs from Wolff ’s
pattern, whose treatment of universal practical philosophy begins, in the first German version, with a
chapter on the fundamental rule of actions (see WTL §1–71).”
“ ” 109
⁵ Wolff, WPE §636. Schwaiger (2011a, 106ff., 152) is exhaustive on the role of happiness in
Baumgarten’s ethics.
⁶ Wolff WPM I, §8; see also WTL §44–57.
⁷ For the few occurrences of this topic see BIP §98; BEP §10, 13.
110
you can,” he explicitly refers to the “degree of strength of which you are capable”
(BIP §43). In this framework, clearly rooted in metaphysical-ontological assump-
tions, we deal again with the concept of a “determining ground [ . . . ] of the
perfection that you will be able to seek,” defined as the “reality that must be posited
in you yourself, or in another (§141). The former will be your perfection as an end;
the latter, yours as a means (§341)” (BIP §43). It follows that the moral imperative
can be formulated as: “seek your perfection by which you become either a more
perfect end, or a more perfect means. Omit, as much as you can, those things
that render you more imperfect either as an end, or as a means, or in either respect
(§31)” (BIP §43).
We can now begin to glimpse the terms and limits of Baumgarten’s influence
on Kant. Not surprisingly, the relevance attributed to obligation and its formal-
ization in an imperative met with Kant’s approval. Equally interesting for Kant is
the non-eudaimonist turn that distinguishes Baumgarten within the framework
of the general Leibnizian-Wolffian rejection of voluntarism. However, while
through the decoupling of perfection from happiness Baumgarten breaks away
from orthodox Wolffianism, Kant already in his lectures attacks Baumgarten’s
very treatment of perfection.
As early as the Praktische Philosophie-Herder (1763–64) Kant disputes the
extension of Baumgarten’s imperative to the means of perfection, believing that
this makes the principle too general and, therefore, empty (PrHer 27:16). In
Moral-Mrongovius II (1784/85) Kant defines the principle of perfection—
expressly referring to Wolff and Baumgarten—as neither contrary to nor useful
for morality: “an empty husk <leere Nuß>” (MoM 29:626). In the same lectures,
Kant also argues that pursuing perfection as an end is tautological, while pursuing
it as a means would be pragmatic and not moral (MoM 29:626–7). In the
Moralphilosophie-Collins (1774–75), Kant also considers Baumgarten’s definition
of perfection, which can apply as much to things as to human beings, to be too
vague and argues for the need to distinguish it from “moral goodness <moralische
Bonitaet>” so as to be understood as the perfection of the will and not, generically,
of the faculties (MoC 27:265–6; see also Osawa 2018, 114–5).
The aforementioned lecture notes show that on Kant’s account, Baumgarten’s
concept of perfection is insufficiently determinate to be a moral principle. Indeed,
Baumgarten’s moral subject, who seeks his own possible perfection, is structurally
entangled in a metaphysical system that accounts as much for his inwardness,
with the psychological-empirical evaluation of the compelling cause that prevails
in obligation, as for his placement in an ontological order:
When the existence of this world is posited, the supreme perfection that there can
be in a world is posited (§187, 934). The most perfect world is that world in
which the supreme perfection that is possible in a world is posited (§185).
Therefore, this world is the most perfect of all possible worlds. (BM §935)
“ ” 111
Furthermore, “the end of God in creating the world was the perfection of
creatures” (BM §945). For such a subject, duty in ethics is ultimately delineated
by that part of metaphysics dealing with the rational knowledge of God, that is,
natural theology—another point that distinguishes Baumgarten from Wolff.⁸ In
the part of Ethics devoted to Religion, Baumgarten argues that the moral agent
must pursue her or his own perfection by resembling God as closely as possible
(BEP §92), on the grounds that God is knowable in his perfections according
to a “true,” “clear,” “certain,” and “living” knowledge. The Ethics (BEP §27, 30–1)
attests that moral obligation is connected with the search for divine perfections,
whose types one can know. The fundamental part of this obligation is directed
toward the “glory of God,” which in the Metaphysics, together with its celebration,
constitutes precisely religion (BM §947). Therefore, religion expresses a mixture
of objective knowledge (of divine perfections) and subjective motivation (their
celebration) (cf. BM §942, 947; Osawa 2018, 111). Thus, the application of
the knowledge of God obtained in natural theology to “Internal Worship”
(BEP, section VI) actually constitutes moral theology, as is made clear in the
Elements (BIP §98).
The output of Kant’s persistent didactic confrontation with Baumgarten
regarding practical philosophy and consequently ethics cannot, however, be
reduced to the rejection of the theological component of Baumgarten’s ethics,
which itself oscillates greatly, as we shall see. Actually, while rejecting this
approach, Kant will have to provide a convincing alternative, the elaboration of
which, on the one hand, will present him with no small number of problems and,
on the other hand, will cause him to retain, with changed functions, a reference to
God in ethics.
II
⁸ Cf. WRP §26–7, where duties to oneself come before duties to God; WTL §59. For Baumgarten,
happiness too, albeit from a different perspective than perfection, is related to the divine dimension and
is discussed in Rational Psychology concerning The State After Death (BM §787–91).
⁹ More broadly, Baumgarten frequently defines philosophy as a form of knowledge independent
from any indication dictated by faith. See e.g. BG §12; BAL §1; BPG §21. For a detailed list, see
Schwaiger 2011b, 217 n.15.
112
as “the science of the obligations of a person that are to be known without faith”
(BIP §1) is further developed:
If, however, an inquiry concerning divine positive right would infer either
(1) whether God at any time will issue laws that a person could not know from
anywhere else except through revelation strictly considered, and which will
nevertheless obligate the entire human species: such does not pertain to philos-
ophy (§1); or (2) whether there are such divine universal positive laws that have
no sufficient ground at all in the nature of the action and the agent: such is denied
(§69). (BIP §74)
God is the author of obligations, and indeed of the natural laws (BM §940, 317).
Since he has the supreme right concerning the giving of laws (BM §972), he is the
legislator of natural law and the whole of the right of nature broadly considered.
D , and are those things that have God as author
and legislator. (BIP §100).¹¹
¹⁰ The figure of the “theoretical atheist” returns often in the Elements: he must admit the cogency of
the moral law as the law of nature “ independently of his own error” (BIP §101, tr. 2020: 85; see also
§35, 71, 110, 119), at the same time “no small defect is uncovered in the right of nature or practical
philosophy belonging to the atheist” (§111, tr. 2020: 90, see also §120, tr. 2020: 94–5).
¹¹ At §104 (tr. 2020: 86) Baumgarten writes that “There is no true antinomy among the strictly, and
most strictly, revealed positive divine laws and those revealed by the right of nature (§85, BM §991),”
but the conditions he invites to be checked in this paragraph are meant only to ensure harmony
between the two perspectives. Although sometimes—like at §69 of the Elements—Baumgarten seems to
reject, with Wolff (1724, §134, and §422), the theory of divine command (see also BIP §36, 102), a
passage such as §100 seems an excellent example of his concessions to Pietism (or at any rate to moral
theology) beyond what Wolffian rationalism is willing to do.
114
Baumgarten refers then to the degrees of revelation through which “the right of
nature as well as each of the natural laws and obligations” (BIP §100) can be
known, thereby reaffirming the core role of theological premises in his practical
philosophy and the consequent heteronomy of his ethics.
It is thus apparent how Baumgarten’s conception of God as author of the law
and lawgiver represents the fundamental target of the Kantian critique. From the
time of the Inquiry—almost coeval with the aforementioned lecture notes of
Herder—Kant in fact strives to provide a “secular” foundation for this obligation.
In this sense, he distinguishes the sphere of moral obligation from the pursuit
of happiness insofar as the former is characterized by necessitas legalis (UDG,
298; Kant 1992, 272).¹² In doing so, he grasps and signals the pivotal role of the
concept of obligation in the moral domain and complains about the lack of
clarity surrounding it (UDG, 298; Kant 1992, 272). While Kant certainly refers
to Baumgarten and Crusius when claiming the necessity of the end linked with
actions characterized by moral obligation (UDG 298; Kant 1992, 272), he refers to
the English tradition of moral feeling, and expressly to Hutcheson (UDG, 300;
Kant 1992, 274), not to defend the core role of obligation, but rather the idea that
the morally good has an absolute value, a value which moral feeling discloses to us
(Langlois 2018, 38–9).¹³
Yet, “at least until 1785” (Bacin 2015, 28) Kant does continue to grant a role to
God concerning moral legislation. It seems that, having acknowledged the cen-
trality of obligation, Kant was looking for a way to secularize this concept and,
having not yet found it, was treading a middle path between Baumgarten and the
tenets of his own mature ethics. This is quite evident with regard to a distinction
through which Kant criticizes the statement in §100 of the Elements, i.e. that God
is as much the author of natural law as he is the lawgiver (as author of the
obligation linked to this law). Both the Reflexionen and the lecture notes of the
1760s, 1770s, and early 1780s show Kant’s insistence on the distinction between
author of the law and lawgiver (Gesetzgeber).
The underlying assumption is that “there are arbitrary <willkürliche>, there are
natural laws. The former have an author, the latter a legislator” (R 6680, AA
19:131; see also R 6769, AA 19:156; R 7090, AA 19:247). In the case of the moral
law Kant does not allow for authorship by God because that would make the
law positive, and therefore arbitrary and contingent, whereas it should be
possible to consider it as natural, namely uncreated (PrPow 27:145; MoM
29:635; MSVig 27: 544–5; 1997:302), just like the properties of a geometric figure
(e.g. MoC 27:283; 1997:76; PPP 27:137; MoM 29:634). However, in these years
¹² Note in a passage like this an early inclination toward a legal lexicon, in which Baumgarten’s
influence is likely playing a part.
¹³ We cannot here go into more detail concerning Crusius’ position, in which the moral dimension
depends upon the theological one more clearly and sharply than in Baumgarten, see Langlois 2018, 40.
“ ” 115
Kant repeatedly admits that God can be considered the author of the obligation
connected with the moral law, and in this sense as a “lawgiver.”¹⁴ For instance, in
the Moralphilosophie Collins we read that “any moral law is an order, and they
may be commands of the divine will, but they do not flow from such a command”
(MoC 27:277; 1997:68). The reference to God’s will is certainly in line with
Baumgarten’s position, on which Kant is commenting here. Kant then immedi-
ately refers to those aforementioned hints, in which Baumgarten seemed to
consider God as playing only the role of a lawgiver—i.e. as the one who makes
the obligation effective—with respect to a law whose morality is independent of
him: “God has commanded it because it is a moral law, and His will coincides with
the moral law. It also seems that all obligation has a relation to one who obliges,
and thus God appears to be the obligator of human laws” (MoC 27:277; 1997:68).
Yet, as we have seen, Baumgarten silenced these hints in §100 of the Elements,
where God is peremptorily defined as the author of both the moral law and its
obligation. Kant is thus willing to follow Baumgarten only in granting God the
role of author of the obligation: “God is the lawgiver but not the creator of moral
laws” (PPP 27:147).¹⁵
This concession is in line with a problem that occupies Kant at this stage of his
reflection and that not surprisingly emerges from the very pages of these courses,
namely, the shift from the “decision-question <qvaestio diiudicationis>: what is
good?” to the “execution [question]: why should I do this good?” (R 6972, AA
19:217). This is basically the problem of motivation: what motivates the subject
actually to implement the maxim recognized as good? In other words: what makes
the obligation effective?
Of course, the central point is to understand the nature of this “knowledge of God”
and how it can determine our moral action, assuming that such a determination
is possible based on this knowledge. In the light of the foregoing, it is apparent
¹⁴ On Kant’s use of the distinction between “author of the law” and “lawgiver” against Baumgarten,
see Bacin 2015, 27–8; Irwin 2004, 150–3, and Irwin 2009, 156–7; Kain 2004, 281–5; Reath 2006, 145–6.
¹⁵ See also PrHer 27:10; 1997: 6; Kant 2004, 61, 79; Pädagogik AA 9:494.
¹⁶ See also Kaehler, 55–6, 62.
116
that much of the distance separating Kant from Baumgarten concerning the
foundation of practical philosophy is played out in this passage. Although having
grasped early on the impossibility of considering the moral law as created, and
thus positive and arbitrary, Kant has the problem of explaining how the self-
legislation that the moral subject recognizes as grounded in his practical reason
has an actual capacity to obligate, that is, how it can constitute a concrete
motivation to act morally.
Still, in the Canon of Pure Reason Kant had essentially argued that the main
motives in the performance of moral duty should be identified with hope in
rewards or fear of otherworldly punishment (KrV, A 811–12/B 839–40; 1998,
680–1). This was part of a conception of the highest good that would be signif-
icantly revised in the second Critique. As mentioned above, an important
watershed in the evolution of Kant’s position on these issues is represented by
1785 with the publication of the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. As is
well known, at the core of this text Kant places the autonomy of the will, by
virtue of which he makes a clean sweep of any residue of heteronomy, beginning
with any reference to God, in the foundation of morality. In so doing, he also
refuses to ascribe to God the role—albeit residual with respect to Baumgarten—
that he still seemed to accord to him in the earlier notes and lectures, namely
that of a “legislator” who is the “author of obligation.” In the second section
of the Groundwork, he nonetheless recognizes an author of the moral law, which
is not God but the will:
Hence the will is not merely subject to the law but subject to it in such a way
that it must be viewed as also giving the law to itself and just because of this as
first subject to the law (of which it can regard itself as the author). (GMS 4:431;
1996a, 81)
It has been argued that in this passage Kant refers to the will as the “author” of the
law just as he employed the word “legislator” to indicate the author of the
obligation in the previous notes and lectures (Bacin 2013, 64; Kain 2004, 285).
In other words, autonomy is accomplished only at the moment when the legisla-
tion of practical reason, expressed by the moral law, is freely and concretely
chosen by the will. The will thereby makes this law its necessarily binding
maxim,¹⁷ and thus gives a law to itself, i.e. realizes self-legislation.
In a note likely coeval with the Groundwork, Kant argues these issues in terms
that are interestingly reminiscent of Baumgarten:
¹⁷ Kant recognizes the centrality of obligation as soon as the Preface of GMS: “The dependence upon
the principle of autonomy of a will that is not absolutely good (moral necessitation) is obligation” (GMS
4:439; 1996a, 88; see also NRFey 27:1326).
“ ” 117
However, the position expressed in these lines is quite different from Baumgarten,
because Kant uses the term “necessitation” to emphasize the insufficiency of
merely knowing the law for the effectiveness of the obligation. What is indeed
further needed is an assent (Einstimmung) on the part of the will with respect to
the universal validity of this obligation. In Baumgarten, obligation flowed directly
from the knowledge of a motive at the very moment that this motive prevailed in
the moral agent—even sensibly—over weaker ones. Furthermore, this gnoseolo-
gical criterion was placed within an ontological hierarchy that had God at its top,
so that the obligation was ultimately toward the “glory of God.”
Thus, in Baumgarten the necessity by which obligation is concretely effective as
motivation has a theological root and a psychological nature so that the prevailing
motivating factor is immediately effective as a motivation. For Kant, instead,
the difference in our good or bad will is not explained through degrees of our
knowledge, but through the act of our practical self-determination. The question
concerning the foundation of our obligation is certainly akin to the question
concerning our subjective disposition to obey the moral law, but it is not
identical to it. Indeed, I must first be clear about how morality is possible as
autonomous self-legislation, and then ask myself whether I want to act morally
(Klemme 2014, 67–8).
By defending autonomy against an ultimately theological foundation of ethics,
Kant defines a self-legislation that takes place in two stages: one connected with
the knowledge of the moral law and another connected with the free assent
granted to it on the basis of the recognition of its universality and necessity.
Only in this way does it make sense for Kant to speak of “necessitation.” The
problem with the Groundwork emerges precisely at this point. Although in the
second section, on the basis of the formulations of the categorical imperative,¹⁸
Kant goes so far as to admit “a world of rational beings (mundus intelligibilis) as a
kingdom of ends,” whose members are lawgivers “through the giving of their own
laws by all persons as members” (GMS 4:438; 1996a, 87), a crucial question is left
open. We need to explain how the will, in rational beings, can be endowed with its
own autonomous causality enabling it to give laws to itself and oblige itself to
follow them. That is, we must provide a deduction of the moral law, which implies
a definition of freedom and its peculiar causality.
¹⁸ Decisive in this regard are the references to humanity as an end in itself (GMS 4:429; 1996a, 80)
and to “the will of every rational being as a will giving universal law” (GMS 4:431; 1996a, 81).
118
In the third section, Kant tries to define freedom by equating it with autonomy.
From a practical point of view, being able to think of freedom already means being
free, but this is not an ontological property of rational beings. Indeed, although
“we have finally traced the determinate concept of morality back to the idea of
freedom” (GMS 4:448; 1996a, 96), “we could not even prove the latter as some-
thing real in ourselves and in human nature” (GMS 4:448; 1996a, 96). We still
need to explain how it is possible to acquire that “interest” of practical reason that
sensibly motivates us to act morally and which consists in making ourselves
worthy of happiness “even without the motive of participating in this happiness”
(GMS 4:450; 1996a, 97).¹⁹ It is a matter of that particular satisfaction possible only
on the basis of free adherence to the moral law (GMS 4:396; 1996a, 52), a “feeling
of pleasure or of delight in the fulfillment of duty,” whose origin cannot be made
“comprehensible a priori” “for a sensibly affected rational being” (GMS 4:460;
1996a, 52).
As is well-known, Kant’s solution relies on the acknowledgment of two natures
coexisting in the human being: the phenomenal and the noumenal. It is by virtue
of the latter, that is, by belonging to an intelligible world, that the unconditionality
of freedom can be conceived. Removing the contradiction between these two
dimensions is the business of speculative reason, which thereby makes room for
practical reason (GMS 4:456–7; 1996a, 102–3),²⁰ but without this removal allow-
ing us “to comprehend how freedom is possible” (GMS 4:456; 1996a, 102). The
conclusion of the Groundwork is actually aporetic: “freedom, however, is a mere
idea, the objective reality of which can in no way be presented in accordance with
laws of nature and so too cannot be presented in any possible experience; [ . . . ] It
holds only as a necessary presupposition of reason in a being that believes itself
to be conscious of a will” (GMS 4:459; 1996a, 105). “How this presupposition
itself is possible”—although it is not only possible but also necessary for the
validity of the categorical imperative—“can never be seen by any human reason”
(GMS 4:461; 1996a, 106).
In the argumentative structure of the Groundwork, reference to the divine plays
almost no role. When Kant refers to it, as the highest (original) good, he specifies
that we have this concept “solely from the idea of moral perfection that reason
frames a priori and connects inseparably with the concept of a free will” (GMS
4:408–9; 1996a, 63). Nevertheless, in the Dialectic of the KpV the existence of
God—and the immortality of the soul—plays a decisive role as a postulate of
practical reason with regard to the attainment of the highest (derived) good, that
is, the union of virtue and the happiness proportionate to morality. Of course,
before getting to this point, in the Analytic Kant must overcome the impasse of the
Groundwork by famously reversing the terms in which the problem was presented
¹⁹ See also the letter to M. Herz, end 1773, AA 10:145; 1999: 140.
²⁰ See also KrV BXXV; 1998: 114–15.
“ ” 119
there is not the least ground in the moral law for a necessary connection
between the morality and the proportionate happiness of a being belonging to
the world as part of it and hence dependent upon it, who for that reason cannot
by his will be a cause of this nature and, as far as his happiness is concerned,
cannot by his own powers make it harmonize thoroughly with his practical
principles. (KpV, 5:124–5; 1996a, 240)
divine will, as Baumgarten already had and who in this sense had departed from
the theological rationalism of his time.
Practical reason, therefore, has both a need (Bedürfniß) and a warrant
(Befugniß) (KpV 5:125; 1996a, 241) to postulate the existence of God because
this serves to fulfill the duty, imposed on us by the moral law, to achieve the
highest good (Gallois 2008, 134). However, while working toward the promotion
of the highest (derived) good is a moral duty, postulating the existence of God (as
the highest original good) answers a subjective need, dictated by the limitation of
human reason (KpV 5:125; 1996a, 241). Thus, the subjective necessity of this
postulate cannot ground morality, on pain of loss of autonomy, and this stands in
stark contrast to Baumgarten.
At the same time, while Kant rejects God as the foundation of practical
philosophy and obligation, which arises within the section of the Elements on
the Legislator, he also develops, and in some ways radicalizes, those passages of the
Elements in which Baumgarten alludes to “a supplement” to the right of nature
“subjectively considered” in the form of “divine positive right and revealed moral
theology” (BIP §98). At stake here is a particular sense of the concept of “justice”
not explicitly thematized by Kant but deducible from his glosses to Baumgarten.
Where in fact Baumgarten formulated “the law of nature” as “commit whatever
promises the most and greatest rewards, and omit its opposite (§70, 110)” (BIP
§111), Kant replaces “promises <spondet>” with “merits <meretur>” (R 6523, AA
19:54). Apart from references to rewards—to which we will have to return—the
centrality of merit must be emphasized here. It is practical reason itself that
demands that those who are worthy of happiness should obtain it and that this
happiness should be proportionate to morality. A lack in only one of these two
desiderata would generate an injustice that would itself be at odds with morality.
The sense of Kant’s recourse to the postulate of God’s existence in this frame-
work is well captured by the concept of a “pure practical rational belief <reiner
praktischer Vernunftglaube>” (KpV 5:144; 1996a, 255), which allows us to analyze
how the notion of “justice” outlined above can be either misleading or fruitful
depending on whether it is applied to the theological idea of God, thus encroach-
ing on theodicy, or to religion as a heuristic horizon of morality.
III
Theodicy and Religion: What Remains of Moral Theology. Baum has rightly
observed that the methodological reversal of the GMS by the KpV overcomes
but actually does not resolve the aporia that emerged in 1785. In light of what we
can positively claim about the intelligible world, the results of the “deduction of
the supreme principle of morality” (GMS 4:463; 1996a, 108) are the same as those
emerging from the second Critique: reason “cannot make comprehensible as
“ ” 121
regards its absolute necessity an unconditional practical law (such as the catego-
rical imperative must be)” (GMS 4:463; 1996a, 108; Baum 2014, 222).
In any case, in the KpV Kant openly claims that he does not see this as a
limitation because his approach does not suppose the gnoseological necessity of
knowing the causa noumenon, that is, a theoretical-speculative access to the
supersensible dimension. Accordingly, in this context, practical reason uses cau-
sality “for none other than a practical purpose; and thus it can transfer the
determining ground of the will into the intelligible order of things inasmuch as
it readily admits at the same time that it does not understand how the concept of
cause might be determined for cognition of these things” (KpV 5:49; 1996a,
179–80). Indeed, “as for the concept which it makes of its own causality as
noumenon,” practical reason “need not determine it theoretically with a view to
cognition of its supersensible existence and so need not be able to give it signif-
icance in this way [ . . . ] For, the concept receives significance apart from this—
though only for practical use—namely, through the moral law” (KpV 5:49–50;
1996a, 180).
Likewise, in practical use we can refer to God as the guarantor of justice as
expressed by the highest derived good because it is clear that at the practical level a
theoretical-speculative knowledge of God, such as that to which natural theology
strives, is not required. By contrast, in Baumgarten the obligation is ultimately
oriented by the possibility of knowing God as ontologically determined. Kant’s
distinction between theoretical and practical use of reason thus allows us to
understand the limits of reference to God in the moral sphere, especially when
it comes to divine justice. In the lecture-note of the 1780s, we read: “through
morality we recognize God as a holy lawgiver <heiliger Gesetzgeber>, a benevolent
sustainer of the world <gütiger Weltversorger>, and a just judge <gerechter
Richter>” (AA 28:1073; 1996b, 408; emphasis in original).²¹
The unity of these three characteristics is complex. Here justice seems in a sense
to act as a mediator between holiness and goodness as “a negative perfection,
because it limits [God’s] goodness in the measure that we have not made ourselves
worthy of it” (Philosophische Religionslehre Pölitz, AA 28:1076; 1996a, 410²²). The
notes are even more explicit, stating that although “God’s justice is usually divided
into justitiam remunerativam et punitivam; according as God punishes evil and
rewards good,” “the rewards God bestows on us proceed not from his justice but
from his benevolence. For if they came to us from justice, then there would be no
praemia gratuita; but rather we would have to possess some right to demand
them, and God would have to be bound to give them to us” (AA 28:1085; 1996a, 417).
Quite to the contrary, “Justice gives nothing gratuitously; it gives to each only the
merited reward. But even if we unceasingly observe all moral laws, we can never
do more than is our duty; hence we can never expect rewards from God’s justice”
(AA 28:1085; 1996a, 417).
Here the employment of Baumgarten’s legal vocabulary is balanced by a clear
rejection of his consideration of the possibility of God granting gratuitous
rewards. On this view, for God there would be no difference between distributive
and retributive justice “since to distribute desert according to worth, at least to
such creatures as we are, is to directly distribute retribution” (Friedman 2022, 15).
On Friedman’s account, it is, therefore, necessary to identify a “permissive space”
in which God, considering the imperfection of human beings, can grant them
rewards that would be undeserved in terms of “nomic justice,” but in the terms of a
“philic justice” are nevertheless not unjust. In this way, while justice defends God’s
holiness against an excess of goodness, his goodness, which is also one of his
perfections, is defended against the severity of his holiness (Friedman 2022, 12–16).
Friedman’s refined analysis deserves a separate discussion, but for our purposes
it is interesting because it identifies two levels in God’s justice. One is closely
related to God’s rigorous justice, which is not theoretically accessible by human
understanding and against which all human effort is immeasurable. On the other
level, justice is taken less strictly, but without contradicting the concept of God,
whose perfections include goodness. In the latter case, we can conceive in practical
terms a relationship between virtue and happiness governed by a concept of
justice understandable and acceptable in human terms. It is apparent that in
this scenario God’s role with respect to morality is not foundational, but rather
heuristic.
When one unduly claims to base a moral evaluation of God and his justice on
the theoretical-speculative understanding of his essence, one falls into the errors
described by On the Miscarriage of all Philosophical Trials in Theodicy (1791).
From the very first lines of this short text Kant claims that even “the defending of
God’s cause,” through trying to give reason to what seems to contrast to his
wisdom, is in reality no more than the cause “of our presumptuous reason failing
to recognize its limitations” (AA 8:255; 1996b, 24). In the first note, Kant states
that “none other than a moral proof” (AA 8:256; 1996b, 25) for God’s existence
could be valid for reason, since we can deduce the existence of such a being neither
from experience nor from the simple transcendental concept of this being. “Divine
wisdom judges” what humans take as violations of divine wisdom in the world
“according to totally different rules, incomprehensible to us, where, what we with
right find reprehensible with reference to our practical reason and its determina-
tion might yet perhaps be in relation to the divine ends and the highest wisdom
precisely the most fitting means to our particular welfare and the greatest good of
the world as well” (AA 8:258; 1996b, 27). Therefore, the pretended philosophical
defenses against what in the world seems to be at odds with God’s attributes,
“ ” 123
namely holiness, goodness and justice, clash with the formula sunt superis sua iura.
Indeed, any reference to the unfathomable divine wisdom to justify “evil proper
<das eigentliche Böse (Sünde)>” as sin, “ill <Übel>” as pain and the “disproportion
<Mißverhältniß> between crimes and penalties in the world” “cut the knot” but
cannot untie it, “which is what theodicy claims to be capable of accomplishing”
(AA 8:260; 1996b, 28).
At the beginning of the final note of the Miscarriage Kant significantly employs
the word Unvermögen to claim that the best expression of authentic theodicy
consists in admitting the “impotence of our reason, and our honesty in not
distorting our thoughts in what we say, however pious our intention” (AA 8:267;
1996a, 34; Lorini 2016, 122).
However, a few years later, in the Religion, Kant addresses the relationship
between religion and morality in a positive sense. Here, Kant does not aim to
define a religion deduced from mere reason, but rather to define a religion
placed within these limits, as appears as soon as the Preface to the first edition of
the text:
So far as morality is based on the conception of the human being as one who is
free but who also, just because of that, binds himself through his reason to
unconditional laws, it is in need neither of the idea of another being above him
in order that he recognizes his duty, nor, that he observe it, of an incentive other
than the law itself [ . . . ] Hence on its own behalf morality in no way needs
religion [ . . . ] but is rather self-sufficient by virtue of pure practical reason.
(Rel 6:3; 1996b, 57)
IV
²³ Analogy is not meant here in the technical sense, as Kant defines it in Logic, AA 9:132; 1992: 626,
and employs it, e.g. in the KU, 5:463–5, 2000: 327–9.
²⁴ See the preliminary notes to the second edition of Rel, 23: 91, 93–6.
“ ” 125
concerns “what lies entirely beyond the limits of our experience but whose
possibility is met with in our ideas, for example, the idea of God” (MS 6:443;
1996a, 564). With a clear echo of the Religion this duty consists in “recognizing
all our duties as (instar) divine commands” (MS 6:443; 1996a, 564). Yet Kant
adds that “this is not consciousness of a duty to God,” since “in this (practical)
sense [ . . . ] to have religion is a duty of the human being to himself ” (MS 6:443–4;
1996a, 564), thereby reaffirming an unbridgeable distance from Baumgarten’s
theologically grounded ethics, at the basis of which are duties to God (BEP,
Pref. 1751; AA 27:737, §21–2).
However, this “duty of religion” that requires the admission of God’s existence
seems to be in partial tension with the second Critique, where the existence of God
as a postulate of practical reason met a merely subjective need, since “pure
practical rational belief ” could not be imposed as a duty. Yet in the Metaphysics
of Morals, the admission of God’s existence acquires a heuristic function, which
justifies the duty to admit God as the supreme moral lawgiver and as the object of
a religion (understood in the sense clarified in the Religion).
This point is crucial since it allows the relationship between morality and
religion to be clearly fixed with respect to all the key notions analyzed so far,
namely (self-)legislation, obligation, motivation, and justice. Religion brings with
it a possible reference to a transcendent dimension, with respect to which,
negatively, reason can only try not to stand in contradiction. Positively, reason’s
appropriation of religion takes place on the practical level to the extent that
practical reason draws from religion the elements that serve to ensure the accom-
plishment of morality. This results in a particular form of justice, which is attained
if we achieve happiness by fulfilling what makes us worthy of it.
For this to be attained it must be possible to appeal, under the conditions
defined in the previous paragraph, to the distributive justice of God as a supreme
moral lawgiver.²⁵ However, this appeal, though enforceable as a duty by a rational-
moral religion, can at best be translated into a hypothetical imperative, in the
service of a categorical one (Campagna 2013, 204). In this regard, in the
Metaphysics of Morals Kant reverts to a terminological issue concerning which
he had already criticized Baumgarten:
²⁵ Brandt (1993, 28) argues that when ethics designates as the object of duty that by which we make
ourselves worthy of happiness it is appealing to God’s distributive justice. As examples of this he brings:
KrV A804–19; KpV 5:107–48; KU 5:469–74.
126
Here Kant sticks to the distinction settled at the very beginning of his commentary
on the Elements, namely that between the “author of the law” and the “author of
the obligation in accordance with the law.” Interestingly, after not even being
hinted at in the GMS and KpV, here the distinction re-emerges in the text that
offers the most complete version of Kantian morality through the integration into
a single framework of law and ethics, which are differentiated not on the basis of
the content they prescribe, but precisely on the basis of the diverse obligation-type:
external for law and internal for ethics.
Kant goes further and seems to even open to a voluntarist vision:
A law that binds us a priori and unconditionally by our own reason can
also be expressed as proceeding from the will of a supreme lawgiver,
that is, one who has only rights and no duties (hence from the divine will).
(MS 6:227; 2006, 381)
instances, he rejects the metaphysical claim of theology, that is, the claim to attain
a knowledge of God such that it can exert a direct influence on the faculties of the
subject in terms of indicating the moral duty.
The Doctrine of the Methods of Ethics expresses with almost schematic
clarity this state of affairs. Ethical Didactics claims the need for a Moral
Catechism, which “must precede a religious catechism,” and “cannot be inter-
woven, merely as an interpolation, in the teachings of religion but must rather be
presented separately, as a self-subsistent whole” (MS 6:478; 1996a, 592). Indeed,
“it is only by pure moral principles that a transition from the doctrine of virtue
to religion can be made, since otherwise the professions of religion would be
impure” (MS 6:478; 1996a, 592).
Coming then concretely to a Fragment of this Catechism, in the Remark
connected with this paragraph, Kant argues that in it “the greatest care must be
taken to base the command of duty not on the advantages or disadvantages that
follow from observing it, whether for the one it is to put under obligation or even
for others, but quite purely on the moral principle” (MS 6:482; 1996a, 595).
Through this “cultivation of reason <Cultur der Vernunft>,” “the pupil is drawn
without noticing it to an interest in morality <Interesse der Sittlichkeit>” (MS
6:484; 1996a, 596). This answers—in terms of an open pedagogical project and not
without anthropological implications—the question before which the GMS
stopped and which the KpV in fact did not resolve.
Beyond these last developments within Kant’s ethical reflection, the elements
acquired so far can only produce the outcome summarized in the title of the
conclusion of MS, which is directed against Baumgarten’s idea of ethics: Religion
as the doctrine of duties to God lies beyond the bounds of pure moral philosophy
(MS 6:486; 1996a, 598).
The meaning of the quotation placed in the title of this chapter is perhaps now
clearer. Taking up the words that Dio Cassius puts into the mouth of Brutus,
Bacon wants to emphasize that, without a divine foundation, Stoic ethics turns out
to be built on sand and not “upon the rock” (Bacon 2001, 189). Kant’s reference to
God’s existence in ethics critically transposes this issue because he does not make
it a ground for a theological foundation of ethics. Rather, he places this reference
to God in a religious framework, but at the same time means by religion a heuristic
horizon to which morality points so as to consolidate itself. Underneath this
crucial methodological turn, there is a deep anthropological issue, which we
cannot delve into here.
Without God to ground ethics, the obligation of the moral law is based on human
reason alone and struggles to establish itself as the exclusive motivation in the realm
of moral action. Thus, when we pursue a “cultivation of morality in us,” and try to
trace action back to its motivation, we face an insurmountable problem: “a human
being cannot see into the depths of his own heart so as to be quite certain, in even a
128
single action, of the purity of his moral intention and the sincerity of his disposition,
even when he has no doubt about the legality of the action” (MS 6:392; 1996a, 523;
see also GMS 4:407; 1996a, 61–2).
This is the price, expensive but acceptable, of an ethic built upon the autonomy
of a subject conceived of as a Selbstdenker.
7
Baumgarten and Kant on Conscience
Allen Wood
The texts for most of Kant’s lectures—on metaphysics, natural theology, ethics,
even anthropology and empirical psychology—were the Latin textbooks written
by Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten. Kant did make use of other authors in
teaching: Georg Friedrich Meier in logic, Johann August Eberhard in natural
theology, and Gottfried Achenwall in the philosophy of law. But we can never-
theless say that Baumgarten is the single author whose texts had the greatest
influence on Kant’s lectures. In lecturing on Baumgarten, Kant never hesitates to
disagree with him. But even the structure of the Critique of Pure Reason recog-
nizably follows the structure of Baumgarten’s Metaphysics.
Throughout Kant’s philosophy, we are struck by his use of legalistic and
forensic metaphors and parallels. Although the title Critique was drawn from
the writings on literary criticism of Henry Home, Lord Kames, Kant tells us that it
refers metaphorically to a legal forum before which the claims of metaphysics are
to be adjudicated. And the principle of morality for Kant is conceived as a law we
legislate for ourselves and for all rational beings thought of as a realm or com-
monwealth of ends just as a legislature gives civil and criminal laws for a
community. Many of Kant’s readers have been put off by the apparent “legalism”
of his conception of ethics, worrying that it entails a set of strict and inflexible
commands, or inferring (as Schopenhauer did) that it represents merely a deplor-
able legacy or relic of a divine command morality. It is true that Baumgarten was a
divine command moral theorist. But Kant was not. And those who have not seen
past the above negative thoughts have been misled when Kant’s use of legal
concepts has hidden from them the role of ends (duties of virtue and the highest
good) in his moral philosophy, as well as the fact that his ethics itself is conceived
as a Doctrine of Virtue. The thought that Kantian ethics is “legalistic” has also
given many the utterly false impression that its spirit is cold and hostile to human
emotions, whereas in fact Kantian ethics is above all an ethics of caring, for which
a good heart—love and respect, kept in balance—is the chief value.
It was indeed chiefly from Baumgarten (though also to an extent from
Achenwall) that Kant inherited the emphasis on law as the framework within
which he placed many of his ethical concepts. But the use of legal concepts by both
Baumgarten and Kant has much to be said for it. For both philosophers, the
idealized image of a legal process was a guiding idea when it comes to thinking
Allen Wood, Baumgarten and Kant on Conscience In: Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy.
Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press. © Allen Wood 2024.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0008
130
about ethics. Its appeal to both would seem to rest on the thought that a fair
legal proceeding is a suitable image for the way reason can be the guide and
the standard in human affairs. Contrasting or competing claims and considera-
tions can be brought before an impartial authority that weighs them and renders a
fair verdict, giving all parties to any controversy a chance to present their case
and yielding a fair result which all should find acceptable and none may reason-
ably reject.
There are interesting connections but also differences between Baumgarten and
Kant regarding the concepts of obligation, imputation, deed, and conscience. We
can see them if we compare Baumgarten’s Elements of First Practical Philosophy
(1760) with Kant’s in Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason (1794) and
the Metaphysics of Morals, especially the Doctrine of Virtue (1798). It is from
Baumgarten that Kant gets the thesis that the fundamental concept of ethics is
obligation (BIP §3, 10, MS 6:222). Both philosophers, moreover, see obligation in
judicial or forensic terms. What they see this way is not only legal obligation but
even moral obligation, or in religious contexts, the obligation to obey God—as a
matter of the judgment pronounced by a court or forum that renders verdicts on
actions and agents. For Baumgarten, moral obligation is seen theologically as our
obligation to obey God’s will. For Kant, moral obligation falls under a rational
principle, valid in itself, but it can be regarded as authored and legislated by our
own autonomous will. But for Kant even if the source of moral obligation is not
God, our duties can nevertheless be thought of as divine commands, because we
symbolize God as a morally perfect will and therefore think of all duties as willed
by him. The thought that God wills us to perform our moral duties and apportions
happiness according to worthiness enables us to consider divine volition as the
command of a legislator. For Kant, to be religious is to recognize all duties as
divine commands. A morally good person need not be religious in this sense, but
Kant thinks morality gives us practical grounds for belief in God and therefore for
thinking of our duties religiously.
Both for Baumgarten and for Kant, therefore, it holds that for an agent to be
judged, whether legally, morally, or religiously, the agent must be a person (BIP
§10; MS 6:223), that is, a being susceptible of having deeds imputed to it. For this
to be the case, the being must be the author (BIP §149–58; MS 6:223–4) of some
imputable deed (BIP §125; MS 6:227–8), an action falling under a law of some
kind. This makes the concept of imputation fundamental to Baumgarten’s ethics
as well as his philosophy of law and justice, and this is prominent in Baumgarten’s
presentation. Imputation is also an important concept in Kant, but its importance
has often not been properly appreciated by Kant’s followers and interpreters.
Misunderstandings of Kant’s views about imputation have led to some of the
commonest errors about Kant’s views on important ethical topics, such as con-
flicts of obligation, the scope of moral responsibility, the relation of moral judg-
ments to chance circumstances, and the role of conscience in the moral life. This
131
last is the main topic of the present chapter, but it will help if we take a somewhat
broader perspective on the role of imputation in Kant’s ethics.
in this way broader (or deeper) than Kant’s, which deals only with the question
whether a deed is judged right, wrong, or meritorious (in some degree) as falling
under a specific duty or duties (MS 6:227–8). In relation to conscience,
Baumgarten’s conception of imputation can therefore play the role in foro interno
of the agent’s conscience, regarded broadly as a faculty of moral judgment.
Imputatio facti for Baumgarten concerns not only whether an agent has per-
formed deeds falling under some moral concept, such as being obligatory, pro-
hibited, or meritorious; it can also play a role in moral decisions, determining with
greater or lesser perfection, wisdom, maturity, honesty, virtue, and moral effec-
tiveness which deeds ought to be done.
Thus for Baumgarten, conscience—simply as the capacity to impute deeds to
oneself—includes the agent’s judgment about what should be done (BIP §200).
Such judgments are always fallible, and Baumgarten understands them as admit-
ting of different degrees of validity or perfection: consequently, some judgments of
conscience can be better than others. This makes sense if we think of judgments of
imputation as responding better or worse to the circumstances and applying the
obligation or law to them more or less wisely. Thus Baumgarten says we should act
according to our “best conscience” (BIP §200, 201–5). For Kant, however, there is
no best, better, or worse conscience. There is simply a verdict of guilt or innocence
pronounced, prospectively or retrospectively, on oneself for a deed. Kant ascribes
fallibility to our understanding in making moral judgments; but he denies that
conscience is fallible or that it can err. This last claim, however, is puzzling,
paradoxical, and easily misunderstood. It is not the claim that our capacity to
judge the rightness or wrongness of actions in relation to the moral law is ever
infallible or immune to error. We will return later to the question how best to
understand it.
For Baumgarten, a deed is an existence of some kind imputable to a free
substance, or person (BIP §10). In order to be imputable to an agent, it must
meet certain conditions of responsibility. Ignorance and error, where not culpable,
preclude imputation of a deed (BIP §128). Nothing that is absolutely necessary or
inevitable can be imputed; neither can what is impossible, or what is merely
natural; nor what is constrained either externally or internally or what the agent
is powerless to effect (BIP §131); nor what is merely fortuitous. Baumgarten
explicitly rejects the concept of a “crime of fortune” (BIP §132).
II
consequences) can be imputed to us. This is true even if we did not anticipate or
could not have anticipated these consequences and they occurred merely through
good or bad fortune; analogously, all the good consequences of a meritorious deed
are imputable, but none of the bad ones (MS 6:223). Kant therefore quite explicitly
and deliberately departs from Baumgarten in allowing for what some have called
“moral luck.” For Kant good or bad luck cannot change a wrong action into a right
one, or the reverse; but a deed that is contrary to duty can incur far greater blame if
its consequences are worse, and an act fulfilling a meritorious duty is deserving of
greater praise if its consequences are better. It does not matter whether the good or
bad consequences were intended, foreseen, or even foreseeable by the agent.
Many moral philosophers and critics of Kant—notably, Bernard Williams
(1981)—have thought that Kant fundamentally rejects the possibility of moral
luck and have even taken this to be the foundation of Kant’s entire moral outlook.
No doubt Williams and others drew their erroneous conclusion from the fact that
Kant says early in the Groundwork that the good will retains its unlimited
goodness even when it is powerless to achieve the outcomes which are its ends
(GMS 4:394). Kant does hold such views about goodness of will; but not every
moral evaluation of actions for Kant is a matter of the agent’s good will. To think
that would decontextualize actions and their moral assessment in ways that are
plainly erroneous—errors with which Kant’s critics often falsely charge him. The
right conclusions, however, would be first, that moral merit for Kant is equivalent
neither to goodness of will nor to the moral worth that actions have only when
they are done from duty. A second conclusion is that you cannot understand
everything about Kant’s ethics just from reading (or worse yet, misreading) only
the first dozen pages of the Groundwork.
A second significant departure from Baumgarten is Kant’s view concerning
conflicts of duty. Some philosophers think there can be genuine moral dilemmas:
cases where every one of your options violates some duty and exposes you to moral
blame. Baumgarten’s theory of imputation would seem to make such cases impos-
sible, since for Baumgarten what is inevitable or impossible for an agent to do cannot
be imputed; and in the case of a genuine moral dilemma, it would be impossible for
the agent to avoid blame. Further, Baumgarten appears to analyze obligation in terms
of the motivation to fulfill it. Thus every obligation consists in “overriding impelling
causes” (BIP §16) that make the action morally necessary. Obligations can be
stronger or weaker, and there can be different or even competing “impelling causes”
of an action. But any obligation consists in impelling causes that are overriding and
make the action morally necessary and its contrary morally impossible (BIP §17).
Unless the impelling causes for an obligation are overriding, there is no obligation
(BIP §20). This too would make genuine moral dilemmas impossible.
Kant has quite often been thought to reject the possibility of genuine moral
dilemmas because he denies there can be a “conflict of duties (collisio officiorum
s. obligationum)” (MS 6:224). This consorts well with the caricature of Kant as a
134
III
IV
The question about what conscience is then depends on what (3) consists in.
What is (3) about? Is it about what you should do, and if not, how is it related to
the judgment that you should do A? We must answer these questions in such a
way that (3) is distinct from both (1) and (2) and that (3) is in some sense infallible
or immune to error, although I can never be certain of the correctness of (1) and
I can still act wrongly in (2) even in the presence of the infallible judgment (3)
(MSVig 27:619).
The difference seems to be that while (1) is a judgment about what to do, or
better yet, about what we ought to do, and (2) is the choice to do it, (3) is a
judgment (prospective or retrospective) about myself as the agent who might do,
or else who has done, the deed. Conscience is about how I have behaved in arriving
at my judgment (1) and, if the deed is already done, about the way I made the
choice (2). Kant calls conscience my faculty of moral judgment passing judgment
on itself (Rel 6:186). In making the judgment (3) I am deciding not only whether
I should do (or should have done) this action A but also whether I have
considered and have chosen the action in the right way—for instance, by moral
standards, not prudential ones. I am passing judgment not on my action but
on myself. Kant holds that if I do pass this judgment, and am found not guilty
before the inner court, then I can then be certain that I have done everything
that morality could require of me (MS 6:401). This is the sense in which
conscience is infallible. Kant holds it to be infallible even in cases where my
judgment (1) is mistaken and hence cases in which the action I have chosen (2) is
objectively wrong.
judgment would not be a moral agent at all. But we can fail to heed the judgment
of conscience, and that is why we can still do wrong (2) even when there has been
a judgment of conscience. We can also deceive ourselves about the judgment of
conscience, substituting another judgment for it. This can be a judgment confus-
ing imprudence with moral wrongfulness (MSVig 27:576)—as when I tell myself
that conscience has declared me not guilty because I experience relief at the
fact that my action will incur no consequences harmful to me. That is how Kant
would describe many of the cases in which people might say their conscience
has erred.
Kant is more emphatic about this when the judgment we substitute is too
lenient, perhaps because such cases are those in which we do wrong while telling
ourselves we have done right. But Kant is also aware of the possibility of a
“morbid” or “tyrannical” conscience (MoC 27:356–7). The judgment can also be
hairsplitting, micrological (MSVig 27:576; MS 6:440), or involve “fanatical self-
contempt” (MS 6:441). These kinds of errors, Kant says, can become habitual, in
the way someone becomes habituated (addicted) to tobacco smoke (MoC 27:356).
Kant even speaks in this context of erring conscience (MoC 27:354–5), but in
these comparatively early lectures seems not to mean what he later does. There
can be errors of fact and errors of law. The action may then be defective, he says,
but cannot be imputed to the agent as crime. Here erring conscience seems to refer
only to innocent errors of judgment for which the agent cannot be blamed.
Kant explicitly rejects Baumgarten’s identification of conscience with the fac-
ulty of moral judgment (MSVig 27:616). Or in the terms explained above, he
explicitly denies that (3) is the same as (1). He claims that imputatio facti is a
function not of conscience but of practical reason (MSVig 27:616). Likewise, Kant
rejects Baumgarten’s distinction between natural and artificial conscience (MSVig
27:617). For these are two ways of making the (always fallible) intellectual
judgment (1) about what we ought to do.
VI
Conscience as the Inner Court of Last Instance. The court of conscience is “inner”
in the sense Kant regularly uses that term. That is, it is between an individual
moral agent and himself or herself. For Kant, inner sense is the awareness of my
own states, and inner moral worth is worth as measured not by comparison with
others but only with my own self- legislated moral law and my idea of virtue (GMS
4:394, 397). In the inner court of conscience, I play all the judicial roles: I am at
once accused, prosecutor, defense attorney, witness and judge (MS 6:438–40;
MSVig 27:618). Kant at times suggests that I may look upon the judge as an
external person: God, but this is a person I create for myself; it provides no
evidence for God’s existence (MS 6:438–9; MSVig 27:574).
139
The judgment of conscience and its infallibility are best understood, I believe,
by pursuing the thought that conscience is like the verdict of a court, if we add
the further thought that for the individual moral agent, conscience is to be seen
as the court of last instance, that is: for this specific action, which I propose to do
(or have done) here and now, the verdict is final and beyond which it is not subject
to further appeal. The verdict is not only about whether I have done my best to
judge the action right or wrong (1) but about myself, my disposition, my way of
considering the action and the purity of the source of the action in myself. This is
why conscience involves being honest with myself and demands “descent into the
hell of self-cognition” (MS 6:441).
In what sense, if any, does following the verdict of your conscience make it
possible to be certain you are doing the right thing? A court of last instance is
infallible in the sense that procedurally, there is no appeal beyond it; there is
nothing in the legal sense that can rightfully correct it. We know that in our legal
system, a court of last instance can sometimes make terrible errors and do
monstrous things. The US Supreme Court for instances, furnishes many horrify-
ing instances of this, and it is now certain to furnish many more with the recent
deliberate appointment to the bench of a supermajority consisting of vile and
corrupt political party hacks for the express purpose of depriving citizens of their
basic rights (such as minorities of their right to vote and women of their right over
their own bodies). But for each of this court’s decisions—Dred Scott, Plessy vs
Ferguson, Citizens United, Dobbs vs Jackson, or the terrible declaration that the
Second Amendment provides for an individual right to threaten the lives of others
through the private possession of firearms with no supervision by a well-regulated
state militia—the criminally wrong verdicts of this highest court are final, and in
that sense infallible. As a matter of law, they must be followed; it would be wrong
(illegal) not to follow them. This remains so even if, as we must hope, such
monstrous decisions are overturned for future cases by legislation or by later
decisions that set new precedents.
The question posed for Kant’s theory of conscience is this: Suppose I judge an
act to be right (1), perform it (2), and at the time I perform it, my conscience
acquits me of any wrongdoing, so that (as Kant says) regarding that particular act,
nothing more can be required of me (MS 6:401). But then suppose that subse-
quently I come to realize that my understanding was mistaken in its judgment (1):
that objectively considered, my act was after all morally wrong, and further that it
has had many harmful consequences. What does Kant’s account of conscience
require me, and thus also allow me, to say, and to do, about this situation?
Kant is committed to say unconditionally that I should not have acted against
my conscience, and that I cannot be blamed for following it. But clearly this is a
case where moral regret is in order. Certainly also, if possible, actions are required
to repair the evil and the harm I have done. We might worry that Kant’s
commitment to the position that I should not have acted against my conscience
140
and have done all that morality requires of me also prevents him from saying that
any moral regret whatever is in order. That would be a position few of us could
find acceptable. Kant’s theory of imputation, however, does give him a way out. If
we say that following my conscience is all that morality can ask of me, then there is
one sense in which my action cannot be judged wrong. But if I later come to see
that the act was objectively wrong, then there is another sense in which the act and
its consequences can be imputed to me. This is a case like a moral dilemma, in
which conflicting judgments of my action are in order.
I must not blame myself for following my conscience, but I can still blame myself
for doing something objectively wrong, and I can (and even must) also impute to
myself the bad consequences of my objectively wrong deed. Kant seems to confirm
this last point when he discusses morsus conscientiae, the “bite of conscience,” and
how we should experience it and respond to it. Cases covered by this bite certainly
include those where I am aware of having failed to heed my conscience and have
acted against its verdict—doing what the inner judge has condemned as wrong.
But I think it also covers cases where I have heeded my conscience but later come
to see that my action was, objectively considered, wrong.
8
Imputation
Applying Practical Norms in Kant
and Baumgarten
Alexander Aichele
If practical philosophy makes sense at all it must not be limited to the rational
foundation of more or less general, universal, or particular moral norms. To be
sure, this inevitable, indeed fundamental, task has to be dealt with. However, even
having done so successfully is not enough. For simply quoting a moral norm, even
one that is rather universal and fundamental, and perhaps adding its reasons, does
not and cannot answer the question practical philosophy is bound to answer:
What shall I do—right here, right now?
Obviously, the answer I long for will and must entail a practical norm, namely
the right one which applies to the single situation I am in, allowing me to act
morally good. Furthermore, I have to know how to act according to that norm
under the circumstances given; that is, how to apply the moral norm I am obliged
to follow. This modest wish, however, already poses a problem that admits of no
clean and definite solution. One may call it the practical sister of the time-honored
problem of the incommensurability of universal concepts and singular things,
which latter should however be grasped truly through the former without being
themselves possible parts of extensional logics or simply things of the right,
conceptual kind.
The issue recurs in the practical field: to know which practical norm is to be
applied, I have to know which kind of action it is I am intending to execute—or
which action it was that I have (or someone else has) done willingly. Even from a
less subjective, more Aristotelian point of view, the problem does not change
much: to know which practical norm is to be applied, the agent has to have
definite and unambiguous knowledge of the situation he is (or was) in and that
demands his action. Indeed, the formal problem remains very much the same.
There is a single, mental or physical, event or a single state of the world demand-
ing or allowing free action. Such action is open to moral judgment; even more,
rational beings like humans are under obligation to judge their actions morally, i.e.
to apply practical norms to their actions. These actions are, first and foremost
from a theoretical point of view, singular events, changes brought about or to be
Alexander Aichele, Imputation: Applying Practical Norms in Kant and Baumgarten In: Baumgarten and Kant on the
Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press.
© Alexander Aichele 2024. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0009
142
¹ Famously, by physically pumping water there is a vast range of things a person may do:
replenishing the water supplies of the house nearby, poisoning the inhabitants of the same house,
beating up a jolly rhythm and so on, all of which can be viewed as falling under some distinct universal
concept which will at times be of moral significance, at others not.
143
² I won’t quote, in general, parallel passages of the Groundwork and the Critique of Practical Reason
for reasons of space.
144
II
A maxim is the subjective principle of acting, and must be distinguished from the
objective principle, namely the practical law. The former contains the practical
rule determined by reason conformably with the conditions of the subject (often
his ignorance or also his inclinations), and it is therefore the principle in
accordance with which the subject acts; but the law is the objective principle
valid for every rational being, and the principle in accordance with which he
ought to act, i.e., an imperative. (GMS 4:421n.; emphasis in original)
Further, a subject of not only the morally but even of the epistemically faltering
kind may represent, by their maxims, any practical law correctly or inadequately,
or even incorrectly. Thus, not only an imperative commanding to do some good is
needed but also a corrective filtering out of the right sort of good. The categorical
imperative is supposed to do both: it commands a possibly unreasonably willing
subject both to scrutinize whether their maxims are not just good somehow, e.g.
for satisfying their selfish desires, but of the right, moral sort of good, and to act in
accordance with the result, that is, to commit or to omit an action, namely the one
represented by an objective practical principle, which in turn is represented by the
maxim examined.
Now, such a representation of an action does not give exactly the one, singular
action which shall be done here and now (or has been done). It prescribes just the
kind of action that ought to be done (or ought to have been done). Even if future
singular actions, obviously, are representable by merely general concepts, the
subject, who is always under pressure to act under contingent and infinitely
complex circumstances, is left without guidance from Kant with regards to
actually doing the right thing. This is because such guidance does not matter for
moral judgment:
It is here a question only of the determination of the will and of the determining
ground of its maxims as a free will, not of its result. For, provided that the will
conforms to the law of pure reason, then its power in execution may be as it may,
and a nature may or may not actually rise in accordance with these maxims of
giving law for a possible nature. (KpV 5:45–6)
For moral judgment or moral action, it simply does not matter what happens
in the material or “empirical” world, i.e. what changes in it; it only matters
what an acting subject wills to do, i.e. what kind of action he ought to
execute when he acts. So, singular actions are excluded from moral judgment,
and, therefore, they are not what Kant means when he talks about actions—
which he does all the time. This exclusion follows, according to Kant’s
distinction between things-in-themselves and phenomena, from the phenom-
enal nature of singular actions—we do not want and do not need to go
there!—and should work just fine as an impenetrable armor against all sorts
of application-aporias. But, as we shall see right away, it does not and it
cannot do so.
Before we turn to that, however, we have to readjust, at least for the moment,
our innocent everyday concept of action. Although Kant often gives the impres-
sion that he shares it, inserting it into his theory of moral judgment would make
no sense; for such a concept of action is incompatible with the moral law itself for
the reason that morality can be found in volitions only insofar as they are
expressed by maxims. This is, first and foremost, a requirement of logic: Since
147
the moral law is a universal proposition, which just happens to be made into a
categorical imperative for wills that are not holy, it can only apply to other
general—formally particular, but on no account singular—propositions, that is,
maxims. Otherwise, moral judgment will be trapped in the aporia of application
and will never result in a definite, objective verdict on moral worth or lack thereof.
Therefore, the categorical imperative’s objects must be universals expressing
simply the kind of action a subject intends. There is no need to read more into
Kant’s talk of “subjective principles of action” as if these had to be of some special
or fundamental significance (e.g. that they must be chosen and held on to for the
whole of life). Rather, each and every action, as long as it is framed by a universal
concept, can be made the object of a maxim and, thus, judged morally. In short: an
act for Kant is not a single, manmade event in the material world—action naively
considered—but a general proposition formulating the intention to execute an
action of this or that kind under this or that kind of circumstances, that is to say, a
maxim expressing a volition. And as Kant talks constantly about moral judgment
of actions by applying the categorical imperative, we have to concede that Kantian
“action” indicates just the act of will choosing or forming a maxim. Put in
scholastic terms, moral judgment according to Kant exclusively relates to actus
immanentes, intentional modifications of the mind, conceived by understanding
and judged by reason, but never to actus transientes, modifications of the world by
causal, corporeal activity.³
Such a venerable sense of “action” has its merits. On the one hand, it excludes
worldly events from moral judgment, which would be categorically impossible
anyway and focuses moral judgment, at the same time, on its single-most object,
the acting subject’s will. On the other hand, as the subject’s will is conceived here
propositionally by the understanding, using necessarily universal concepts, and
judged by reason, using the most universal propositional principle, it seems to
presuppose that there is a way to come to definite and objective moral verdicts by
purely logical means—even if it is not really clear what, exactly, the contradiction
of a “self-contradicting will” (GMS 4:424) or “self-destruction” (GMS 4:407) of
maxims contradicting the categorical imperative would mean. It is easy to see that
the only being—except, of course, an all-knowing being—in position to judge
actions morally in this case is the acting subject himself. But, after all, locking up
morals into the subject’s mind is not a problem; rather it solves the notorious
application problem by brute force.
Or so it seems. But the issue is not concluded. For testing maxims against the
categorical imperative does not deliver a fully fledged moral judgment—not by far.
This is because such a result just tells the subject what one’s duty is and sets aside
the question whether it is a possible or actual one. However, knowing one’s duty
and even willing or acting “in conformity with” it, is not enough, since only an
action “done from duty [ . . . ] has moral worth” (GMS 4:406). For an epistemically
limited subject, unfortunately, such knowledge about the purity of one’s own
moral grounds is unattainable, as Kant emphasizes:
It is indeed sometimes the case that with the keenest self-examination we find
nothing besides the moral ground of duty that could have been powerful enough
to move us to this or that good action and to so great a sacrifice; but from this it
cannot be inferred with certainty that no covert impulse of self-love, under the
mere pretence of that idea, was not actually the real determining cause of the will;
or we like to flatter ourselves by falsely attributing to ourselves a nobler motive,
whereas in fact we can never, even by the most strenuous self-examination, get
entirely behind our covert incentives, since, when moral worth is at issue, what
counts is not actions, which one sees, but those inner principles of actions that
one does not see. (GMS 4:407)
Behind our honest conscience in acting by choosing a maxim purely from duty
there always lurks the possibility of doing just the same thing in truth on an
egoistic, contingent, purely “subjective ground of desire” (GMS 4:427), thereby
contradicting moral duty and falsifying the agent’s own conscience. This is
perfectly possible if the action of choosing a maxim consists in a singular imma-
nent act. For in that case, the subject is not able to know for sure whether this act
of choice corresponds to the maxim, consciously represented, or to another one
which may determine the choice but is, while choosing, not represented con-
sciously. Therefore, the subject can always be mistaken about which maxim, in
truth, is actually determining his will. And this uncertainty can never be lifted
since it is impossible to subsume a singular act or event under a universal
proposition or rule with objective certainty, that is, without the possibility of
getting it wrong. One and the same action may be explained with infinitely
diverse, even contradictory maxims. This is the point, as we might remember, of
the aporia of application. There is simply no way to objective conceptual certainty
if it is a singular—be it a transcendent or an immanent act—which is to be grasped
universally.
All a subject is capable of knowing is whether the maxim he believes to
determine his own will is in conformity with duty or not. However, this is no
moral judgment in the full sense. Hence, a subject’s practical judgment is
restricted to the conformity of their own apparent maxims. This is not very
satisfying, especially bearing in mind the enormous effort Kant applied in seeking
to establish a revolutionary foundation for morals with respect to moral judgment.
Setting aside the question of his success, at any rate, a gap yawns between practical
norms and singular actions. Here, Kant’s new foundation changes nothing for the
better, perhaps, even to the contrary, and the same goes for his somewhat weak
149
III
Moral Imputation: The Road to Singular Actions? The aporia of application does
not go away if one tries to circumvent it with metaphysical subtlety or if one
simply ignores it. Whether or not Kant has explicitly realized the significance of at
least some conceptual reflections on the application of norms for a practicable
practical philosophy is not important. Looking at the remarkably practically
oriented, virtually down-to-earth Metaphysics of Morals, chances are that he
has; although, even there, he only gives some hints—or better: exactly one
hint—at something as a theory of application.
There exists a well-known passage concerning the philosophy of law that is
regularly misunderstood or, more precisely, mostly tacitly understood⁵ as if Kant
had also written what in fact he has left unwritten and is found, in great detail, in
Baumgarten. We will get to that soon. First, let us read at length this very
condensed passage from the Introduction to the Metaphysics of Morals:
⁴ The upshot of Kant’s confidence in this naturally evolving excellence would be a quite elitist circle
of judging practical judgment itself: Only people possessing such outstanding capacity could be
competent to judge practical judgment and, especially, whether another subject has a similar capacity.
The hoi polloi are just bound to believe in their higher contemporaries, though. Such elitism is
defended in Enskat (2007).
⁵ For an example of this doubtful practice, see Aichele (2004a, 247–62).
150
keeping with what is owed has no rightful effect at all. – Kindly recompense
(remuneratio s. respensio) stands in no rightful relation to a deed.
The good or bad results of an action that is owed, like the results of omitting a
meritorious action, cannot be imputed to the subject (modus imputationis tollens).
The good results of a meritorious action, like the bad results of a wrongful
action, can be imputed to the subject (modus imputationis ponens).
Subjectively, the degree to which an action can be imputed (imputabilitas) has to
be assessed by the magnitude of the obstacles that had to be overcome. – The greater
the natural obstacles (of sensibility) and the less the moral obstacle (of duty), so
much the more merit is to be accounted for a good deed, as when, for example, at
considerable self-sacrifice I rescue a complete stranger from great distress.
On the other hand, the less the natural obstacles and the greater the obstacle
from grounds of duty, so much the more is a transgression to be imputed
(as culpable). – Hence the state of mind of the subject, whether he committed
the deed in a state of agitation or with cool deliberation, makes a difference in
imputation, which has results. (MS 6:227ff.)
The punctual insertions of classical Latin terminology alone clarify that what Kant
says here, of course, is closely related to the tradition of general moral philosophy
and natural law. He even selects Wolff ’s specially coined name for his newly
invented discipline of Philosophia practica universalis, much criticized in the
Groundwork (cf. GMS 4:390), for the chapter title from which this passage of the
introduction is taken, although Kant’s main source is indubitably Baumgarten’s
Elements of First Practical Philosophy.⁶ But that is not the point, here.
The point is, rather, that in this passage Kant introduces, more or less by
quotation, a concept, namely imputation, which is suitable and, in fact, invented
for applying practical norms to singular actions, thereby reviving the natural
understanding of action. He does so tacitly as, even here, he gives no explicit
definition of action in general. The meaning Kant intends, however, is clear enough
since he talks not only about (free) causes but also about results of actions, which are
morally judged by people other than the agent himself. So, physical events, changes
of the world brought about by free beings indeed become objects of moral judgment
through imputation. The same is affirmed by Kant’s definition of “deed”:
An action is called a deed insofar as it comes under obligatory laws and hence
insofar as the subject, in doing it, is considered in terms of the freedom of his
choice. By such an action the agent is regarded as the author of its effect, and this,
together with the action itself, can be imputed to him, if one is previously acquainted
with the law by virtue of which an obligation rests on these. (MS 6:223)
⁶ Cf. my introduction to Baumgarten (2019a, vii–lxviii); see also Schwaiger (2011a) and Schwaiger
(1999).
151
From this it is clear that singular actions can be judged morally only by imputation
and if and only if these are deeds, that is, if they can be subsumed under some
moral, that is, a juridical or ethical, law and if they are done by a rational and,
therefore, free agent. Notice that moral judgment has to be taken in the universal
sense holding for ethics and law as well, since the concepts Kant defines in his
universal practical philosophy “are common to both parts of The Metaphysics of
Morals” (MS 6:222). In short, deeds can be done only by persons and singular
actions are only morally imputable to persons: “A person is a subject whose
actions can be imputed to him. Moral personality is therefore nothing other
than the freedom of a rational being under moral laws [ . . . ]. A thing is that to
which nothing can be imputed. Any object of free choice which itself lacks
freedom is therefore called a thing (res corporalis)” (MS 6:224).
Obviously, the restriction of practical judgment to deciding the conformity of an
action with duty is no longer, in this context, to be regarded as insufficient for
qualifying it as moral. For, what kind of judgment if not a moral one would a
“moral imputation” be? And, indeed, moral imputation establishes precisely the
conformity or disconformity of an action with duty and the degree of the agent’s
culpability or praiseworthiness in accord with the circumstances of one’s actual
deed. To do that, no special, or even objective insight into the subject’s mental
processes or into their maxim-based decision making seems to be needed. Rather,
it appears to be taken for granted by Kant that a singular action, if done by a
person and not in conformity with duty, must be based on a morally wrong
maxim. Which maxim, exactly, the subject has chosen wrongly and why he has
done so is of no relevance; the sole question to be decided is whether it would have
been possible, under the given circumstances, to act in conformity with duty. In
this way, the subject’s state of mind is of interest only insofar as it is counted
among the given circumstances and does not constitute the exclusive, essential
object of moral judgment.
All this sounds very lucid, and, as far as it goes, it is a quite faithful rendering of
the concept of imputation developed by natural law,⁷ elaborated in great detail by
Baumgarten, and, credit where credit is due, completed by Kant with a new
universal principle of possible obligation, that is, the categorical imperative (see
MS 6:225; Kant 1996a 379). However, Kant gives just a skeleton, and even that
only by half. For he never explains how a judgment of imputation is, in fact,
passed on an action, e.g. how a deed, being done, or a person, having performed a
deed, or the law, which has to applied, can be identified, and so on. And, further,
Kant omits any discussion of such a judgment’s first part, which is called “physical
imputation” (imputatio physica). By doing so, he deprives the imputational
process from its empirical foundation, as if a moral imputation could be made
⁷ For a short but concise historical overview, cf. Hruschka (2004, 17–27).
152
without a long, hard, and perhaps even scientific look at the event that is first to be
declared an action, and then a deed, and, in the end, sanctioned with reward or
punishment.
That’s why Kant’s concept of imputation could be used in practice only with
some speculative fantasy or historical or legal knowledge. Possible reasons for that
remarkable omission are easy to invent: Perhaps Kant was worried about system-
atic unity, because there seems to be no place for such a thing as imputation in his
critical foundation of practical philosophy, or, possibly, he took it simply for
granted that a well-informed reader would tacitly supply the rest of a fairly well-
known theory—which would indicate that, somehow, at the level of application,
practical philosophy could be treated quite independently from its foundational
level and, in spite of moral philosophy’s critical revolution, every day’s moral
business could go on as usual. Maybe we get a little wiser by having a look at
Baumgarten.
IV
IVa
the judging subject himself can be completely certain, that is, they can be passed
without any fear of erring. On that basis, conceptual, empirical judgments are
grounded in reality external to the human mind and may, therefore, be regarded
as grasping this reality as truthfully as is possible for imperfect minds and even
held to be true if the appropriate theory of epistemic probability is observed (cf.
Aichele 2017, 167–224). So, to Baumgarten “a certain uncertainty” (BAL §424)
must be involved necessarily in all of our possible conceptual judgments on
contingent beings, and yet this does not justify any form of universal skepticism.
Baumgarten condenses and specifies his theory in Elements §28. It is too long to
be quoted here, so I will only outline the parts relevant to my present argument.
Baumgarten first makes the elementary distinction between certainty and uncer-
tainty, the former of which consists in a judgment sufficient for identifying
one singular thing among all possible things. Compared to this, any other kind
of judgment must be uncertain, that is, any judgment referring to a thing in
universal empirical terms, Baumgarten’s “aestheticological cognition,” is uncer-
tain. However, from such certain uncertainty about singular identity follows
neither sheer ignorance nor the necessary falsity of each universal judgment
relating to a singular. Even a limited mind is able to identify a bird among a
multitude of things; and a duck among many birds; and a teal among many ducks;
and even Harold and Hester, both of them teals, among many teals—unless all
possible things, birds, ducks, teals are congregating in your backyard. In short:
A judgment that is uncertain need not be untrue.
Deciding on a judgment’s truth or falseness, that is, affirming or negating it,
requires reasons. As we are dealing with “incomplete” or subjective certainty, a
contingent state of the mind of a finite subject of cognition (BM §531), only those
reasons which are factually recognized count. Baumgarten’s method seems to be
simple, and, albeit complex when filled out with qualitative and quantitative
content (cf. Aichele 2019, 275–9), amounts basically to this, formally speaking:
Count or calculate the reasons, weigh them against each other, and decide in
accord with the outcome according to the subjective truth value given. The
relevant epistemic qualities are three: A judgment is probable (probabile), if
more (and weightier) reasons are recognized for affirmation than negation; it is
dubious (dubium), if there are as many reasons for both; and it is improbable
(improbabile), if there are more known reasons for negation than affirmation.
Common to all such judgments is that they are similar to truth (verisimile) in that
they are of propositional form and there always exist some reasons indicating
truth even if these do not suffice for affirmation.
Against pure probabilism, judgments can be reduced to the pair of objective
truth values (BAL §464): Someone considering a judgment probable may be
uncertain about its objective truth but he does not doubt it, even less takes it to
be improbable; rather he takes it to be true, at the same time recognizing the
possibility that it could be false. The same goes, the other way around, with
154
IVb
Imputation. Evidently, any moral judgment must bear such objective uncertainty.
However, this need not hinder everyday application of practical norms, since it
can be supplemented by a rational theory of subjective certainty.
As has been hinted, deciding about future actions or kinds of actions is, in fact,
the lesser issue, at least from the point of view of application. Both Kant and
Baumgarten claim (and rightly so) that possible future actions can be given or
represented solely by universal concepts and propositions appropriate to the
extensional reasoning of a finite mind. So, it might happen that the kind of action
chosen with respect to volition and the singular action factually done conflict as to
how they are determined conceptually or judged morally. But it is also clear that
both volitions and singular actions are objects of different kinds of moral judg-
ment, one prospective and another retrospective. Both deal with different material.
The first, as far as the purely practical side is concerned, deals right from the
beginning only with universals—even though, at least, Baumgarten takes into his
philosophical and methodical account the singularity of the deciding agent’s
situation. The second has somehow to mediate between universal practical
norms and singular physical events of possible moral relevance by transforming
the latter, in the process, into universals. Baumgarten neatly distinguishes between
prospective and retrospective moral judgment, in his own terms deliberatio
(deliberating). This includes both connumeratio (adding up reasons), for the
former, and imputation, for the latter, and develops different methods for treating
each, even though, in some way, the latter also involves the former thereby making
imputation an even more complicated affair (cf. Aichele 2019, 279f.). Since both
Baumgarten and Kant allocate moral judgment to singular or physical action, and
155
happened at all, so that a deed might possible have been done; second, whether the
assumed cause was a person at the time of causal action; and, third, whether she
has freely caused that event in the world, so that it was truly a deed (BIP §127).
All these elements investigated in physical imputation are both contingent and
singular. So, at best, the resulting judgment will be of subjective certainty and each
partial judgment forming it can be, at best, probable. However, should any partial
judgment that is not probable but dubious or improbable enter the frame, then
physical imputation is not permissible (BIP §144). If the judgment is subjectively
certain though, it will have this form: “Person P has done deed D.”
This proposition constitutes the second premise of the syllogism of subsump-
tion whose conclusion makes up moral imputation. This form of reasoning is still
known under the banner of a “legal syllogism” or “legal deduction.” Wolff
officially explained and introduced it in his Jus Naturae on the occasion of proving
a title of ownership (cf. Aichele 2011b, esp. 498–502). Its demonstrative force
stems from its logical form, the modus ponendo ponens.
Baumgarten uses the same form but calls it “syllogismus imputatorius” (BIP
§171). Since all retrospective moral judgments must be imputational judgments
and all imputational judgments must be of that form, Baumgarten, by identifying
this logical process with the imputational syllogism, expands its validity to the
whole sphere of morals. According to this model, the first premise is a law and the
second premise is a deed (BIP §171). To be more exact: The first premise is a
conditional quoting the practical norm whose applicability is to be judged, while
the second premise presents the essential features, the “momenta” (BIP §128), of
the deed suspected to be subsumable under the norm, so that it can be declared a
case of the norm or not. If the deed in the second premise corresponds to the
antecedent of the conditional in the first premise, then its consequent is affirmed
by the conclusion. In the simplest form:
Premise 1 (norm): If person P has done the deed D, then P will be punished (or
rewarded) with so and so.
Premise 2 (physical imputation): Now, P has done D.
Conclusion (moral imputation): Therefore, P is to be punished (or rewarded), etc.
Of Clean and Dirty Hands. It is not all too difficult to see now why Kant does not
dwell on physical imputation, turning, in fact, a blind eye to it. As pure, sublime
even, as his revolutionary foundation of morals may be, it seems to preclude
application here below in everyday life, because it does not offer, let alone show, a
way, intelligible or not, to morally judge singular actions performed by real people.
Even if Kant in the generally more practically oriented Metaphysics of Morals,
references the traditional concept of imputation, he omits precisely the part
focusing on singulars, that is, physical imputation, mentioning solely the part
based exclusively on universals, that is, moral imputation, which, however, does
not get airborne without the physical. Conceding that he simply overlooked the
problem would be implausible in the extreme. Perhaps, as suggested above, he had
hoped that the reader would tacitly fill in the gap, well-known as the concept of
imputation was, and proceed further on his own devices. Or, maybe, Kant did
not want to cloud his theory by considering the sorts of details that necessarily
arise in the application of philosophical theories to real-life situations, especially
in moral theory.
Baumgarten, on the other hand, does not fear getting his hands dirty. He
entertains no illusions about the objectivity of moral judgments, or really of any
judgment about contingents, as far as they are passed by human and thus finite
minds. And, consistently, he does not require objectivity, but instead makes do
with subjective certainty without, however, condemning us to skepticism. So, with
dirty hands, he is able to establish a functioning moral philosophy, including a
method for the application of practical norms. It goes without saying that such
practical philosophy must remain provisional, that is, it has to stay open to
improvement or revision, something which was not, it seems, Kant’s cup of tea.
But, to repeat, Baumgarten’s careful analysis of imputation accomplishes some-
thing that everybody expects, and rightly so, from practical philosophy, namely
showing, as precisely as possible, the means for its application in everyday life.
Whether it is somehow possible to have the best of both worlds, a theory with one
hand clean and the other one dirty, remains open to discussion.
9
Perfection and Self-Perfection in
Baumgarten and Kant
Paul Guyer
¹ Bacin (2015) argues for the close connection between Kant’s account of the duties of virtue and
Baumgarten’s ethics, but does not interpret Kant’s overall approach to moral philosophy as perfec-
tionist in the way that I do. For the relation between Kant’s doctrine of right and Achenwall’s Ius
naturae, see my introduction to Achenwall (2020a).
Paul Guyer, Perfection and Self-Perfection in Baumgarten and Kant In: Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical
Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press. © Paul Guyer 2024.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0010
160
The Foundational Level. Kant heaps scorn on Baumgarten’s attempt to cast the
fundamental principle of morality in perfectionist terms. His criticism is not fair
to Baumgarten and obscures the fact that his own approach may also be con-
sidered a form of perfectionism, indeed that Kant himself sometimes presents his
own view in such terms.
Kant presents his criticism of perfectionism as early as the prize essay,
the Inquiry concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology
and Morality, submitted to the Berlin Academy of Sciences in 1762 and pub-
lished by the Academy in 1764 as the runner-up to Moses Mendelssohn’s prize-
winning essay, Evidence in Metaphysical Sciences (1764; 1997, 251–306). Here
Kant writes:
The rule: perform the most perfect action in your power, is the first formal
ground of all obligation to act. Likewise, the proposition: abstain from doing that
which will hinder the realization of the greatest possible perfection, is the first
formal ground of the duty to abstain from acting. And just as, in the absence of
any material first principles, nothing flowed from the first formal principles of
- 161
² Baumgarten’s Initia has recently been translated into English by Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers,
as Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, Baumgarten’s Elements of First Practical Philosophy: A Critical
Translation with Kant’s Reflections on Moral Philosophy, and into German, by Alexander Aichele, as
Anfangsgründe der praktischen Metaphysik. At the time of writing, Baumgarten’s Ethica philosophica
remained available only in Latin but Hymers’ translation has since appeared with Bloomsbury in 2024.
³ Clemens Schwaiger has argued that Baumgarten innovated and provided a model for Kant in
starting his moral philosophy from the concept of obligations, expressed through imperatives;
Schwaiger (2009), in German in Schwaiger (2011a, 144–54); in that volume see also “Baumgartens
Anssatz einer philosophischer Ethikbegründung” (128–43).
162
explicitly says about Wolff in the lectures: there he argues that the fundamental
principle of morality must be purely “intellectual,” but that it cannot “again be
tautological, and consist in the tautology of pure reason, like that put forward by
Baron Wolff: Fac bonum et omitte malum, which . . . is empty and unphilosophical”
(MoC 27:276).⁴
Now this criticism is unfair to Baumgarten, and no doubt to Wolff as well. For
Baumgarten continues that:
And then in the Ethica Baumgarten explains at length what comprises the
perfection of one’s soul, one’s body, and one’s external state or resources and
how one is to perfect them. So he certainly did not think that he was offering a
mere tautology; to use Kant’s terms, he clearly intended to be offering the first
material principle or principles of ethics to complement his first formal principle
of morality.
So Kant’s charge that Baumgarten’s perfectionism is an empty formalism—an
ironic charge, of course, because that was precisely the charge that would be
brought against Kant’s own categorical imperative (see Guyer 2021)—is hardly
fair to Baumgarten’s intentions. A second criticism that Kant makes might seem
to come closer to the mark, but is still unfair to Baumgarten. This is also in the
lectures, and here Kant uses the same formulation of the moral principle that he
ascribes to Wolff, but this time ascribes it to “our author,” that is, to the author of
the textbook for the lectures, i.e. Baumgarten:
The first moral law of our author is: Fac bonum et omitte malum. The express
meaning of the phrase is: Fac bonum. The good must be distinguished from the
pleasant; the pleasant refers to sensibility, the good to the understanding. The
concept of the good is a thing that satisfies everyone, and hence it can be judged
⁴ The same words are found in Kant (2004, 60), which is based on the transcription of Kant’s
lectures by Johann Friedrich Kaehler dated summer semester 1777. The Kaehler notes prove that the
Collins notes actually represent Kant’s lectures as given in the 1770s, thus that although they are in
Collins’s own hand he must have copied them from an older transcription.
- 163
Here at least Kant seems to concede that Baumgarten was trying to supply a
material as well as formal principle, or presupposing one. But any insinuation that
Baumgarten was trying to derive his material principle from what is pleasant to
the senses, which would be doomed because people are ineliminably idiosyncratic
in that regard, would still be off the mark. Baumgarten did not take pleasure as the
immediate aim of morality; like Wolff, he thought that pleasure was only the
perception of perfection, so morality must aim at perfection, although the reali-
zation of perfection will manifest itself in the feeling of pleasure. But Baumgarten
surely thought that the status of one’s mind, body, and external state as the proper
objects for our perfection was given by human nature in general (for him a proper
subject of metaphysics), not by personal, variable preference. Taking the perfec-
tion of one’s mind, body, and external state as one’s fundamental moral goal is not
like preferring chocolate to rum raisin ice cream.
Kant’s deepest criticism of Baumgartenian perfectionism would thus have to
be what he says in the Critique of Practical Reason. Here Kant presents his
criticism of what he takes to be the fourfold possibilities for “material determining
grounds in the principle of morality” that have hitherto been recognized,
namely the projects of founding morality in (i) subjective external grounds,
either of education “according to Montaigne” or “civil government” “according
to Mandeville”; (ii) subjective internal grounds, either of “physical feeling”
“according to Epicurus” or “moral feeling” “according to Hutcheson”; (iii) objec-
tive internal grounds, namely “of perfection” “according to Wolff and the Stoics”;
or (iv) objective external grounds, namely “the will of God” “according to Crusius
and other theological moralists” (KpV 5:40). His specific objection to perfection-
ism, although here associated with Wolff, is then that “if an end as an object which
must precede the determination of the will by a practical rule and contain the
ground of the possibility of such a determination—hence as the matter of the will
taken as its determining ground—is always empirical; then it can serve as the
Epicurean principle of the doctrine of happiness but never as the pure rational
principle of the doctrine of morals and of duty (so too, talents and their develop-
ment only because they contribute to the advantages of life . . . )” (KpV 5:41).
Perhaps Baumgarten did not intend the nature and needs of one’s mind, body, and
external state as the proper objects of perfection in the name of morality to be only
empirically known, but in Kant’s view they are, and in that case, we might take
him to be saying, the Baumgartenian theory of perfection is no better off than the
164
⁵ After all this time, the most extensive studies of this material remain Schilpp (1938) and
Schmucker (1961), with a briefer treatment in Ward (1972). Both Schilpp and Schmucker observe
Kant’s focus on the consistent exercise of freedom as a “law to itself” as the basis of morality in these
materials (e.g. Schilpp 1938, 131–2; Schmucker 1961, 317), although both characterize Kant’s position
in these materials and in his mature moral philosophy as “formalism” rather than “perfectionism,” in
Schilpp’s case as “procedural formalism.” Of course what one means by any term ending in “-ism”
always has to be made precise, and I would not object if what I call Kant’s perfectionism were also
considered a form of formalism, properly defined. Schilpp’s interpretation of Kant’s freedom-based
theory is limited, however, by his focus on a negative conception of freedom, in which the use of a
formal requirement of consistency in the use of freedom frees us from domination by inclination—a
part, of course, of Kant’s view—to the almost complete exclusion of a positive conception of freedom,
our freedom to set our own ends, which I regard as the heart of Kant’s view. Thus Schilpp writes “All
this lends force to our contention that by ‘freedom’ Kant means freedom or aloofness from de facto
drives and desires.” He only hints at what I regard as the necessary complement to Kant’s conception of
freedom when he continues that when Kant states “that ‘freedom is a power for acting or refraining to
act independently of empirical grounds’ ” (in what Schilpp refers to paragraph 23 of the fragment from
1775, i.e. Reflection 7202, originally Loses Blatt Duisburg 6, AA 19:276–82, at 19:281–2) “he means the
capacity to withhold assent to a particular drive in order that the drive and its objective may be
reflectively interpreted and the final objective may be determined in the light of such reflective
interpretation and construction” (Schilpp 1938, 136). Schilpp’s “the final objective may be determined”
does hint at the ability to set our own ends as the essence of Kantian freedom.
- 165
⁶ Schmucker (1961, 326–7) also cites R 6802 and 6854, as well as R 6978 and 7197, which I cite in a
few lines.
⁷ Ward’s brief discussion of the role of the 1770s lectures on ethics in The Development of Kant’s
View of Ethics points in the direction of my interpretation when he says that what the “consistency” in
the use of freedom that requires “is not just a lack of self-contradiction”; “It is more like a coherence in
once’s own conduct or with a harmonious social system of purposes.” This accurately reflects the fact
that Kant requires both intra- and interpersonal consistency in the use of freedom. But whereas on my
interpretation what Kant requires is the “greatest possible use of freedom” for all to set their own ends,
166
Ward seems to regard human ends as given by human nature and circumstances: “The moral rules . . .
provide a method for systematizing the given empirical ends of our nature so as to make them
‘universally valid,’ and thus harmonious and consistent” (Ward 1972, 53). This seems to me to get
Kant exactly wrong: freedom for Kant is the freedom to set our own ends, although consistently with
our freedom to set our own ends on other occasions and the freedom of others to set their own ends,
and precisely not in merely harmonizing given ends.
- 167
enforceable correct action). Kant’s “reciprocally” makes it clear that what morality
requires is maximal equal freedom.
This conception of the foundation of morality is radically different from what
we find in Baumgarten, who begins with the obvious point that morality (obliga-
tion) concerns only free rather than involuntary actions (BIP, §10), but does not
make freedom or its intra- and interpersonal maximization the goal or “essential
end” of morality. What remains to be shown, however, is that Kant’s account can
be regarded as a form of perfectionism, and that indeed he himself sometimes
regarded it as such. One piece of evidence that implies that Kant’s principle is itself
a form of perfectionism is the version of the fourfold classification of possible
foundations for morality that we find in the lectures on ethics from the 1770s, thus
from the period in which Kant is working out his basic idea. Whereas in the
Critique of Practical Reason all four approaches, including the “objective internal”
or rationalist approach of perfectionism, are to be rejected in favor of Kant’s own
approach, which thus stands outside of the scheme, in the lectures he puts nothing
other than his own principle in the position of the “intellectual” yet internal
foundation for morality. Thus after he rejects the internal empirical theories of
self-love (Epicurus, Helvétius, Mandeville) and moral feeling (Shaftesbury and
Hutcheson) and the external empirical theories of education and government
(here Montaigne rather than Mandeville, and Hobbes), all of which could yield
only contingent principles, what he presents as the internal intellectual foundation
for morality is nothing other than his own theory: if morality rests “on a principle
that resides in the understanding, then [its] injunction is absolute. [For example]
You are not to lie, whatever the circumstances may be. If I consider my free choice,
it is a conformity of free choice with itself and others. It is thus a necessary law of
free choice” (MoC 27:253–4). The position of perfectionism in Kant’s scheme is
here occupied by the principle that the use of free choice is always to be consistent
with free choice itself, or with the greatest possible use of freedom. This suggests
that the maximization of freedom in this way is its perfection. But Kant also says
this explicitly. In the crucial period 1769–70, when the great light dawned in
Kant’s practical as well as theoretical philosophy, he wrote:
There is a free power of choice which does not have its own happiness as an aim
but rather presupposes it. The essential perfection of a freely acting being
depends on whether this freedom [crossed out: of the power of choice] is not
subject to inclination or in general would not be the subject of any foreign cause
at all. The chief rule of externally good actions is not that they conform with the
happiness of others, but with their power of choice, and in the same way the
perfection of a subject does not depend on whether he is happy but on whether
his condition is subordinated to freedom: so also the universally valid perfection,
that the actions must stand under universal laws of freedom. (Refl 6605,
19:105–6; BIP 150)
168
And the presumably later reflection 7197, the first part of which was previously
quoted, continues:
This perfection of freedom is the condition under which the [crossed out: good]
perfection of all others and the happiness of a rational being must be universally
satisfying (worthiness), and is all that remains if the object of our current
inclination have all become indifferent to us. (Refl 19:270–1; BIP 280)
It would take more room than I have here to fully explicate these passages, but
they contain the gist of Kant’s mature moral philosophy, if not in the language
with which we are familiar from the Groundwork and the second Critique, and
present it as a form of perfectionism. The goal of morality is that each of one’s free
actions be compatible with maximal freedom for oneself as long as that is
compatible with maximal freedom for others, thus with maximally equal freedom
for all, and this is the perfection of freedom; happiness either for oneself or others
is not the direct or immediate object of morality, but morality constitutes the
condition of worthiness to be happy. Happiness is “presupposed” in the sense that
it is a natural goal of all, and, although Kant does not suggest this in these passages,
the perfection of freedom or greatest freedom possible in the world would in fact
produce the greatest happiness possible in the world. The last claim will have to be
left dangling here (although for Kant’s first stab at it, see the Critique of Pure
Reason, A 809–10/B 837–8).
The foundation of Kant’s moral philosophy is thus perfection, but the perfec-
tion of freedom rather than the perfection of the human mind, body, and external
state. However, Kant hardly completely rejects Baumgarten’s ethics, as opposed to
his elements or foundation, because those more concrete objects of perfection are
the basis of Kant’s catalogue of the particular duties of virtue of human beings.
That is, although Kant has radically revised Baumgarten’s foundation for moral
philosophy, the superstructure of his own ethics is largely Baumgartenian. But
before we turn to that, we need to briefly consider some revisions that Kant makes
at the level between the most general principle of morality on the one hand and
the particular duties of human beings on the other. These revisions must be
understood in order to understand the difference in organization between
Baumgarten’s Ethica and Kant’s Doctrine of Virtue in spite of their similarity in
content at the most concrete level of our duties, especially our duties to ourselves.
II
The Intermediate Level: Kant’s Classes of Duties. In this section I make two points.
First, while Baumgarten’s catalogue of duties is organized around a simple dis-
tinction between perfect and imperfect duties, Kant’s is organized around two
- 169
distinctions, that between perfect and imperfect duties and that between duties of
right and ethical duties. Kant’s two distinctions are not co-extensive and lead to a
more complex division of duties than is found in Baumgarten. Second, Kant’s
division of duties is also illuminated by a distinction that is not found in
Baumgarten and in fact is not explicit in Kant’s Doctrine of Virtue itself, that
between duties founded in the right of humanity in our own person and that of
others and those founded in the end of humanity in ourselves and others. This
distinction emerges rather in Kant’s final and most detailed engagement with
Baumgarten’s moral philosophy, recorded in the notes on Kant’s course on the
metaphysics of morals taken by his lawyer Johann Friedrich Vigilantius in 1793–4.
But it does illuminate Kant’s organization of the Doctrine of Virtue in the
Metaphysics of Morals, finally published in 1797.
Baumgarten follows the tradition, going back at least to Hugo Grotius and
Samuel Pufendorf, according to which duties (or correlative rights) are divided
into two classes, perfect and imperfect.⁸ Perfect duties are those that may be
coercively enforced by those to whom the obligations are owed, or by agents
acting for them, such as a state, while imperfect duties are those that do not permit
such enforcement. He also calls perfect duties “external,” since their coercive
enforcement will be executed by an agent other than the one who has the duty,
while imperfect duties are “internal,” since they can be motivated, or perhaps
metaphorically enforced, only by the one who has the duty.
Seeing that someone can be obligated to something such that another human
being, however, cannot extort <extorquere> it, whether absolutely or physically
or morally, and, nevertheless, someone can also be obligated such that another
human being can absolutely, physically, or morally extort from him that to which
he is bound: morally possible extortion granted to another is sometimes an
impelling cause, which, through obligation, is connected with a certain free
determination, and sometimes is not. An to some free determina-
tion through the extortion permitted to another human being is
(complete, perfect), and the rest are (incomplete, imper-
fect). Therefore, we are if and insofar as a
is represented by us as
⁸ Grotius distinguishes between “Right properly, and strictly taken,” such as that of a lord over a
slave, which obviously includes permission to coercively enforce it, and “imperfect” property, as well as
between “a Rule of Moral Actions, obliging us to that which is good and commendable,” as opposed to
an unenforceable “counsel” (Grotius 2005, Book I, chapter I, paragraph V, 138–9; paragraph IX,
148–9). Pufendorf distinguishes between “perfect law,” which has two parts, one the precept “whereby
it is directed what is to be done or omitted,” the other the sanction “wherein it is declared what
Punishment he shall incur, who neglects to do what is commanded,” and imperfect duties, “such as
could not have been extorted by Force or Law,” for they “are not absolutely necessary for the
Preservation of Mankind, and for the Support of Human Society in general, although they serve to
embellish it, and render it more commodious” (Pufendorf 2003, chapter I, paragraph VII, 46;
paragraph XIV, 50n, from Barbeyrac’s note).
170
, i.e., such that its extortion is morally possible or permitted to another
human being. However, we are if and insofar as a free
determination to which we are obligated is not represented by us as that which
ought to be extorted. (BIP §56)⁹
⁹ Even though “extort” is the dictionary translation of extorquere, it seems misleading insofar as
in contemporary common usage “extort” suggests obtaining something by the impermissible use of
force—extortion is a crime—whereas Baumgarten is referring to the permissible use of force. For that
reason “coercion” would be better. But Alexander Aichele’s recent German translation of the Initia is
in the same vein, using abpressen, the dictionary translation of which is “extortion,” rather than the
possibly more neutral zwingen. See Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, Anfangsgründe der praktischen
Metaphysik, trans. Alexander Aichele (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2019) Baumgarten 2019a, §56,
pp. 86–9).
¹⁰ Schmucker also recognizes that Kant distinguishes perfect duties from the (narrower) class of
coercible duties (Schmucker 1961, 297), but, since his book concerns only Kant’s early ethics, he does
not go on to explain the importance of Kant’s distinction for the structure of the Doctrine of Virtue,
which I will do.
- 171
of one’s parents)” (MS 6:390). This is why it is not right to say that perfect duties
are duties of strict obligation while imperfect duties are not, and why Kant may
say that fulfillment of imperfect duties is meritorious but does not call them
supererogatory in the modern sense:¹¹ it takes judgment to decide whether on a
particular occasion helping one’s parents should take precedence over some
other form of beneficence, or whether on such an occasion cultivating one’s
talents should take precedence over any form of beneficence, but that does not
mean that it is just arbitrary which one does, or whether one fulfills any
imperfect duty at all, and if one cannot fulfill an imperfect duty, e.g. of benef-
icence, on one occasion in one way, one may still have a residual obligation to
fulfill it on another occasion in another way, whether toward the same benefi-
ciary or another.¹²
But, although Kant only explains the difference between perfect and imperfect
duty in the Introduction to the Doctrine of Virtue, the second half of the
Metaphysics of Morals, the crucial point here is that it is presupposed by his
distinction between juridical and ethical duties, which is made in the Introduction
to the book as a whole and which structures its division into the two halves of the
Doctrine of Right and of Virtue. Baumgarten had equated the distinction between
juridical and ethical duty with the distinction between perfect and imperfect duty,
but for Kant the distinction between perfect and imperfect duty must precede the
distinction between juridical and ethical duty: for Kant, as for Baumgarten,
juridical duty is that which may and indeed must be coercively enforced (see
Guyer 2016d), or “extorted,” but only a subset of perfect duties may be coercively
enforced, namely, those the violation of which would hinder the freedom of others,
who obtain the right to attempt to hinder such hindrance of their freedom by, as
Kant puts it, the law of non-contradiction, in light of which the hindrance to a
hindrance to freedom is supposed to be equivalent to the preservation of freedom
(MS 6:231)—the first goal of morality in general, as a necessary condition of its
greatest possible use. Kant does not fully spell out the premises for his restriction
of juridical right to this subset of perfect duty, but although he does not say so the
specificity of perfect duty is clearly a necessary condition for its coercive enforce-
ment, while why coercive hindrance to the hindrance of the freedom of others
should be permitted and required but coercive intervention to prevent hindrances
to agents’ own freedom—to prevent suicide or self-mutilation, for example—
should not be could certainly use explanation. Be that as it may, Kant’s revision
of Baumgarten’s simple distinction is important, and explains why his category of
ethical duty, that is, non-coercively enforceable duty, is and must be broader than
his category of duties of virtue proper, the imperfect or wide duties to adopt
certain ends and their associated maxims, specifically the two ends that are also
duties of one’s own perfection and the happiness of others (MS 6:385–8). Ethical
duty must include perfect duties that, for whatever reason, specified or not, are not
candidates for coercive enforcement, such as the duties to oneself not to commit
suicide, self-mutilation, and self-abuse, and the duties of respect to others not to be
arrogant toward them or defame or ridicule them. These duties are part of what it
is to treat oneself and others as ends in themselves, not as mere means, to be sure,
but they are not duties to adopt more specific ends such as self-perfection or the
happiness of others. They are thus not duties of virtue, but they must be classified
as ethical duties because they are not coercively enforceable. Baumgarten’s scheme
did not allow for this distinction.
Kant makes the distinction between ethical duty in general and duties of virtue
in particular tolerably clear in the Introduction to the Doctrine of Virtue: “to every
ethical obligation there corresponds the concept of virtue, but not all ethical duties
are thereby duties of virtue” (MS 6:383); that is, wherever there is no room for
coercive enforcement, then the fulfillment of duty requires virtue in the sense of
“the strength of a human being’s maxims in fulfilling his duty,” a “self-constraint
in accordance with a principle of inner freedom, and so through the mere
representation of one’s duty in accordance with its formal law” (MS 6:394). But
in much of the Introduction to the Doctrine of Virtue Kant places so much
emphasis on duties of virtue as ends that are also duties that it is easy to lose
sight of this distinction. However, a distinction that he makes in the Vigilantius
lectures but does not repeat in the Metaphysics of Morals, although it has not
drawn much attention, can help clarify what is going on. This distinction, which is
clearly Kant’s addition to Baumgarten rather than his comment on anything in the
textbook, is between the right of humanity in one’s own person and that of other
persons and the end of humanity in one’s own person and that of others (MSVig
27:543–4). This distinction presupposes Kant’s conception of humanity as includ-
ing, at least, the freedom of each human being to set her own ends (MS 6:387,
392), and can be understood as equating the right of humanity with the require-
ment to preserve the existence of this freedom and not to undermine it, and the
end of humanity as the requirement to promote or expand this capacity. Then the
ends that are also duties, self-perfection, and the happiness of others, are actually
the ways to expand rather than contract the freedom of each to set their own ends,
since one cannot rationally set ends for which one does not reasonably believe
oneself to have adequate means, and self-perfection and assistance to others are
actually ways to expand the range of means and therefore of ends available to
oneself and others.¹³ What Kant means by the “right of humanity” is that the
freedom of oneself and others is not to be destroyed or compromised, although of
course each individual exercise of freedom must be constrained by the condition
¹³ I here compress into two sentences the argument of Guyer (2016c) and (2019).
- 173
This passage clearly explains the organization of the Metaphysics of Morals, and in
a way that displays the foundational role of humanity, in turn understood as
freedom of choice and action, more clearly and consistently than does Kant’s
published text, where that only occasionally breaks through to the surface, like a
geological substratum mostly covered with topsoil and vegetation. All duties are
duties to preserve or promote humanity, understood as the capacity of agents to
set their own ends. The right of humanity is that the freedom to set our own ends
not be destroyed or impaired, but this right can be coercively enforced only
in some interpersonal cases—those where hindrance to the hindrance by one
person of the freedom of another is, as Baumgarten would say, both physically and
morally possible, and where, as Kant would add, morally necessary. Juridical duty
is thus a subset of a subset of the duties flowing from the right of humanity. All
other duties, thus all perfect duty flowing from the right of humanity in oneself,
such as the duty not to commit suicide, some perfect duty flowing from the right
of humanity in others, namely the duties of respect, and all imperfect duty,
whether to oneself or to others, flowing from the end of humanity, namely self-
perfection and the happiness of others, are not coercively enforceable, and thus are
ethical duties, self-enforceable only by the constraint of respect for the moral law.
But only the non-coercively enforceable imperfect duties to self and others are
duties of virtue proper. This is in fact the framework on which Kant’s Metaphysics
of Morals is constructed, although he does not always make it clear.
Kant reconstructs Baumgarten’s catalogue of particular duties to self and others
on top of this framework. At that level, there are significant overlaps between the
two accounts, although also some subtle differences that I will mention in the next
section. But before I turn to that, let me emphasize the key difference. For
Baumgarten, the essence of human nature consists in mind, body, and depend-
ence upon external conditions, and the moral task is straightforward: perfect these
in yourself, insofar as you can, and then use your own perfection to promote the
happiness of others as well. For Kant, the essence of rational agency and of human
nature insofar as we are rational agents is the freedom to set our own ends, or
humanity, and our fundamental moral task is to preserve and perfect that
freedom. In our own case, as this passage makes clear, the perfection of our
natural abilities is the means to the perfection of our freedom, not an end in its
own right, and the perfection of our moral nature can be understood as part of the
perfection of our freedom. In the case of duty to others, Kant makes it clear in this
passage that the perfection of our own natural abilities is a means to the end of
promoting their happiness, but not so clear that the end of their happiness is also
only a means to something even more fundamental, namely their fullest possible
freedom to set their own ends. There is no room here to spell out how that
argument should go (again, see Guyer 2016c and 2019). The remainder of this
chapter will focus on the comparison between Kant’s and Baumgarten’s treat-
ments of the particular duties of self-perfection.
- 175
III
the duty to submit one’s conceptions of good and evil (bonitas vel pravitas) to the
moral law and to examine one’s free decisions about action (liberas tuas determi-
nationes) in light of the moral law (BEP §175), whether these actions have been
done or are being contemplated prospectively, thus by means of conscientia
consequens or conscientia antecedens (BEP §184). The duty to love oneself, finally,
is certainly not a duty to favor one’s own happiness over that of others, as its name
might suggest; it is the duty to be “ardent” (ardentissime) in the exercise of self-
knowledge, self-evaluation, and conscience (BEP §191). Precisely because of the
danger of confusing this conception of self-love (philautia or heautophilia) with
the ordinary conception and Kant’s constant polemic against any foundational
role for such self-love in morality (see above all Rel 6:35–6), we may conjecture,
Kant does not include Baumgarten’s concept of self-love in his own conception of
moral self-perfection, although we may also conjecture that his emphasis on our
duty to cultivate and strengthen our naturally occurring predispositions to moral
feeling, conscience, love of human beings, and (self-)respect in the Introduction
to the Doctrine of Virtue (MS 6:399–403) is actually his version of this
Baumgartenian duty. Otherwise, Kant simply collapses Baumgarten’s first three
“general” duties to oneself into two. First, he combines the duties of self-judgment
and conscience into “the Human Being’s Duty to Himself as His Own Innate
Judge” (MS 6:437), the duty to cultivate and respect the verdict of the “scrutinizer
of hearts” set up as a “court . . . within the human being” and which, as in
Baumgarten, is divided into “conscience as warning . . . <praemonens>” and,
“when the deed has been done,” conscience as either “acquitting or condemning
[one] with rightful force” (MS 6:439–40). Then, he takes over Baumgarten’s duty
to self-knowledge as the “command to ‘know (scrutinize, fathom) yourself,’ not in
terms of your natural perfection (your fitness or unfitness for all sorts of discre-
tionary or even commanded ends) but rather in terms of your moral perfection
in relation to your duty” (MS 6:441). Baumgarten had placed this duty first on
his list, while Kant lists it after his version of the duty to self-judgment
and conscience—but he also entitles it “the First Command of All Duties to
Oneself,” suggesting that whatever its order in his exposition, it is logically prior
to or presupposed by the duty of conscience: you cannot accurately judge yourself,
or your past or proposed deeds, except on the basis of accurate self-knowledge. So
that is the “first command” of moral self-perfection, and there is no departure
from Baumgarten here.
However, Kant’s revised scheme, on which ethical duty is not all imperfect duty
but does include some perfect duty, does allow him to make one subtle refinement
to Baumgarten’s approach: the duty to develop moral self-knowledge and con-
science is not an ordinary imperfect duty, allowing for some latitude or judgment
as to when and how to fulfill it, but is an unremitting duty, something that we
must take every opportunity to perfect. Or more precisely, Kant’s scheme allows
him to refine Baumgarten’s usual qualification that we must perfect ourselves
- 177
quantum potes, “as far as we can.” What Kant says is that “a human being’s duty to
increase his moral perfection, that is, for a moral purpose only,” a heading that
now subsumes the two parts of conscience and self-knowledge, “is a narrow and
perfect [duty] in terms of its quality; but it is wide and imperfect in terms of its
degree, because of the frailty <fragilitas> of human nature”; thus “It is a human
being’s duty to strive for this perfection, but not to reach it (in this life), and his
compliance with this duty can, accordingly, consist only in continual progress”
(MS 6:446). This duty is perfect in the sense that it is unremitting and leaves no
room for latitude, at least if that is understood as allowing that attention to this
duty may ever be set aside for any reason, but imperfect in the sense that it cannot
be fully perfected in the natural lifespan of human beings.¹⁴ Or, even more
precisely, Kant refines Baumgarten’s “quantum potes” by supplementing his
own distinction between perfect and imperfect duty with the further distinction
between quality and quantity, or kind and degree: the duty of moral-self perfection
is unremitting and perfect in kind, but can only ever be satisfied to some degree;
our duty with regard to it is to satisfy it to the greatest degree that is possible for us,
although there is nothing that would count as an absolute completion or maxi-
mum satisfaction of this duty. This refinement is made possible by Kant’s dis-
tinction between the perfect-imperfect and juridical-ethical distinctions, which
Baumgarten had collapsed.
Kant also brings his use of the distinction between perfect and imperfect duty
within the sphere of the ethical to his adaptation of Baumgarten’s account of the
“special” duties to self, which Kant presents as our duties regarding our natural
rather than moral self. Again, Baumgarten’s initial list in the Elements is just mind,
body, and external state. In the Ethica, he first lists the duty to perfect our
analogon rationis and then the duty to perfect the intellectus proper; the former
includes such capacities as experience, memory, imagination, and invention
(BEP §§203–20), the latter starts with the “obligation to take care of <curandae>
attention, abstraction, reflection, comparison” (BEP §221), or the abilities
involved in reasoning narrowly construed. Kant does not adopt Baumgarten’s
characteristic term analogon rationis (also central in Baumgarten’s aesthetics), but
he might be thought to take over the substance of Baumgarten’s distinction in his
own terms as the distinction between “powers of spirit” as “those whose exercise is
possible only through reason . . . derived a priori from principles” and “powers of
soul,” “those which are at the disposal of understanding and the rule it uses to
¹⁴ Here Kant seems to be reverting to the position he took in the treatment of the postulate of
immortality in the Critique of Practical Reason, that we need immortality to perfect our virtue (KpV
5:122), rather than adopting the position that he developed in the Religion, namely that we can
complete the “change of heart” from evil to good at any time (or “time,” since this is supposed to
happen in the noumenal will) even if we can never tell from our actions in experience that the
change of heart has in fact been completed (see Rel 6:66–7). For discussion, see Guyer (2016b) or
Guyer (2020, ch. 4).
178
fulfill whatever purposes one might have,” including “memory, imagination, and
the like” (MS 6:445): Kant’s powers of spirit would be Baumgarten’s intellectus,
while Kant’s powers of soul would be Baumgarten’s analogon rationis. Be this as it
may, Kant clearly regards the duty to cultivate these powers as imperfect, as is
implicit in Baumgarten’s classification of them as ethical: they allow for latitude, in
the proper sense that one may have to judge whether any particular occasion is
right for effort to satisfy them (in Baumgarten’s term, “cura”), or whether there is
some other duty that must on that occasion take priority; they may also allow for
latitude in the sense that one must judge what is the best way or method to
cultivate these powers, when what is best for oneself might not be the same for
others; and they are also imperfect in the sense (in their quantity) that there is
nothing that can count as a maximum or completion in the perfection of these
abilities, but one always can and must make further progress in their perfection.
But Kant does bring his distinction between perfect and imperfect duties within
the sphere of ethics to bear on Baumgarten’s account of our duties regarding our
bodies, or our bodily existence. Baumgarten simply lists as among our duties the
“care <cura> of our appetitive faculty” (BEP §235), although this duty actually
straddles a line between the mental and the physical, since we would not have the
kinds of appetites that we have if we did not have the kinds of bodies that we have;
then the “care of the body” proper, which includes our duty to preserve our body
from danger, to care for our members or limbs in particular, to take care of our
diet and health generally, and to practice temperance and sobriety (BEP §250–61).
He then lists the duty to “care for our occupation and leisure,” the duty to remain
busy but to allow ourselves the leisure necessary to recuperate and remain effective
(BEP §267–71); the duty to care for “chastity,” thus to avoid “impurity” and
“sexual intercourse external to matrimony” (BEP §272–5); and the duty to care
properly for the “necessities and commodities of life,” those external goods and
circumstances that are necessary for life on the one hand or make it more pleasant
on the other—temperance with regard to such things is prescribed (BEP §276–80).
Kant largely takes this list over, but divides it into perfect and imperfect duties. On
the one hand, the duties to avoid suicide, self-mutilation, and unchastity, whether
in the form of self-abuse, extra-marital sex, concubinage and morganatic mar-
riage, etc., are perfect: these things are simply to be avoided (although Kant
transfers the proscription of violations of heterosexual, monogamous marriage
to the Doctrine of Right (MS 6:277–80), since in his view these are properly
regulated by public law). There are no occasions on which these proscriptions can
be set aside, not even in favor of some other duty, and there is no question of
degree: they are just not to be done. On the other hand, the duty to develop or
perfect the “powers of the body,” like those of the powers of spirit and soul, is
clearly imperfect: one has to use judgment how to best realize this goal, when to
best realize it and when it must be deferred in favor of other duties, and there
is nothing that can count as complete realization of this goal, although there is
- 179
certainly something that can count as complete compliance with the perfect duties
to avoid suicide, self-mutilation or self-damage, and unchastity. In Kant’s words,
[w]hich of these natural perfections should take precedence, and in what pro-
portion one against the other it may be a human being’s duty to himself to make
these natural perfections his end, are matters left for him to choose in accordance
with his own rational reflection about what sort of life he would like to lead and
whether he has the powers necessary for it (e.g. whether it should be a trade,
commerce, or a learned profession). (MS 6:445)
Now the want of morality here does not properly lie in the failure to employ these
means for any purpose—that he deprives himself of all amusements, and shares
nothing thereof with others, for their pleasure or use or necessity; it lies, rather, in
the principle he has adopted, of retaining in his possession the means for using,
while renouncing any such use. He becomes a mere custodian of his money or
other property, without attaching the smallest use or purpose thereto. He
becomes, therefore, an instrument, a mere means to no end, like a watchdog,
180
and this is a maxim to him. Now since a man, in and for himself, is supposed to
be an end for his humanity, the miser assuredly violates humanity in his own
person, in that he puts out of sight the end prescribed to him, and looks upon the
mere means given for that purpose as though he himself were a means in that
regard. (MSVig 6:659)
¹ A similarly positive account of Kant’s relation to perfectionism is found in Guyer (2007) and
(2016a).
Courtney D. Fugate, Perfectionism from Wolff to Kant In: Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy.
Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press. © Courtney D. Fugate 2024.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0011
182 .
Three Striking Features of Kant’s Moral Philosophy. The first of the striking
features of Kant’s moral philosophy I would like to highlight here concerns its
internal unity. On his account, the moral law is not only more unified than what
you will discover in earlier authors, but its very principle consists in the self-
imposed requirement that free action itself take on a special sort of systematic
unity. The late scholastic philosopher Francisco Suárez, for instance, argues that
the natural law is supremely one, but not for the reason given by Kant, namely,
because all moral principles ultimately stem from one ultimate principle or
formula, but rather because all primitive moral principles are grasped by the
same innate rational capacity, synteresis, and tend toward the same general end,
namely, the perfection of the human being’s various capacities (Suárez 2015, II:
VIII:243–50). Natural law is then one, not in formula or derivation, but rather in
regard to the psychological origin from which our knowledge of it arises and in
terms of the general end it fulfils. Something similar seems to be the view of Locke
and others, who also defend the unity of the first ground of all moral principles,
but fail in practice to provide a truly unified account of the actual content of moral
judgment. On Kant’s reading, all such principles fail and must fail in this way
because, as much as their principles may take on a general or abstract form, this
generality can only be specified empirically, and so contingently, and is thus
different in kind from genuine universality, which always contains necessity and
so must be specified a priori.²
Stoicism, which served in many ways as an inspiration for Wolff, Baumgarten
and also Kant, perhaps comes closer to such unity through the doctrine of
homologia (see e.g. Cicero 1931, III:xxi). In this we find that the genuine good
consists not only in all action being subject to one single account or logos but more
specifically in this logos’s serving as the chosen principle within us for the selection
of all further action. In this way, Stoicism does indeed place the intention to act in
a consistent and harmonious way at the very basis of the good. However, upon
closer inspection, it turns out that the content of this intention is also so closely
tied to the empirically given dispositions of human nature and traditional religion
² Perhaps the best explanation of this distinction is found in Kant’s contrasting of analytical and
synthetical universality in the Critique of the Power of Judgment (AA 5:407–8). That Kant ascribes
synthetical universality to our moral cognition is confirmed in his Lectures on the Philosophical
Doctrine of Religion (AA 28:1057).
183
that the unity of the Stoic account remains, in practice, a mere promissory note,
which disappoints as soon as the discussion turns to specific duties.³
In Kant, by contrast, we find that the moral law itself is not only absolutely one,
such that all other moral principles are supposed to be derivable from it, but also
that it admits of various, closely related formulations from which specific duties
are supposed to follow in a unified, rationally transparent way—namely, the
formula of the law of nature, the formula of humanity as an end in itself and
the formula of a kingdom of ends—each of which in turn aims in its own manner at
rendering human freedom supremely and systematically unified. It is notable,
moreover, that these formulas also, in themselves, are supposed to constitute a
special system according to the a priori moments of form, matter, and complete
determination, which, Kant claims in the Groundwork, follow from “the categories
of the unity of the form of the will (its universality), the plurality of the matter (of
objects, i.e. of ends), and the allness or totality of the system of these” (GMM 4:436).
Here, the Stoic homologia in action is thought as only possible based upon the unity
that the pure understanding and reason directly—and so not only with intention but
even with insight into its derivation from one ground—apply in the selection of the
maxims from which all actions are to follow. I would observe here again that we find
nothing of this kind in any previous system of moral philosophy.
This first striking feature of Kant’s moral theory prompts us to ask: From
whence did this conception of virtue arise? Did Kant just invent, out of thin air,
the idea that our duties themselves constitute a scientific system under one
supreme formula and that morality itself consists in seeking the determining
ground of all our willing in that very idea of unity? Or is there, if not an historical
precedent, then at least an historical root for this both ambitious and radical moral
ideal?
If we look a bit more closely at Kant’s various formulations of the moral
law itself, we find a second striking feature. A casual perusal of Kant’s texts
shows that he never tires of contrasting the realm of nature with that of freedom.
However, in explaining the purpose and origin of the three further formulations of
the moral law just mentioned, he also indicates that all of them are based on what
in the Groundwork he calls “a certain analogy” (GMS 4:436). It is easy to verify
that this analogy is precisely one with “nature” in the most general, or formal
sense (GMS 4:437), or with what Kant in the first Critique and Prolegomena terms
“natura formaliter spectata” or nature viewed formally (see e.g. Rel 8:333n.;
B165; A419/B447n.).⁴
³ In this respect, it is a common failing of traditional natural law theories that, despite their supposedly
rational origin, the specific duties this is held to ground usually consists in little more than a loose list of
traditional religious and civic duties. See e.g. the discussion in Cicero, De legibus, II. A fine comparison
between periods of the natural law tradition in this respect is found in Scattola (2003).
⁴ I drew attention to this concept of nature in Kant, its moral function, and its roots in Baumgarten’s
cosmology in BM 25–9.
184 .
Since the universality of law in accordance with which effects take place con-
stitutes what is properly called nature in the most general sense (as regards its
form)—that is, the existence of things insofar as it is determined in accordance
with universal laws—the universal imperative can also go as follows: act as if
the maxim of your action were to become by your will a universal law of nature.
(GMS 4:421)
In the case of the formula of humanity as an end in itself, the use of the analogy is
admittedly not quite so obvious, but Kant still states that it consists in considering
the rational being as an “end by its nature” (GMS 4:436). Kant also begins his
derivation of the ends formula with the premise: “Rational nature is distinguished
from the rest of nature by this, that it sets itself an end” (GMS 4:437; emphasis
added), thereby basing it not on transcendental freedom, but on the rational agent
as a special kind of natural being. And in one passage he indirectly confirms this
by explain with regard to all the formulas: “Imperatives as they were represented
above – namely in terms of the conformity of actions with universal laws similar
to a natural order or of the universal supremacy as ends of rational beings in
themselves [ . . . ]” (GMS 4:431).
As for the last formula, Kant clearly states in summary right after its derivation:
“A kingdom of ends is thus possible only by analogy with a kingdom of nature”
(GMS 4:438; emphasis added). And just before this, in stating it as following from
the need for a principle of the complete determination of our maxims, he says that
it amounts to judging “all maxims by means of the formula, namely, that all
maxims from one’s own lawgiving are to harmonize with a possible kingdom of
ends as with a kingdom of nature” (GMS 4:436).
Finally, in one footnote, Kant says even more broadly:
In this passage, all of morals is ascribed the general inverse function of teleology;
instead of thinking nature as a possible realm of ends, it thinks of moral ends as if
they were to form a system of nature. I could present more evidence from other
texts for this analogy with nature taken formally but will not belabor the point
presently. I will only mention that Kant takes this analogy so seriously, that in the
second Critique he feels comfortable adopting as his standard title for the intel-
ligible world simply “supersensible nature.” What is more, at several points in the
185
II
Wolff ’s Empirical Perfectionism. The tale starts with Christian Wolff ’s moral theory,
which has fittingly been called a type of moral perfectionism.⁷ Considered gener-
ally, Wolff ’s moral thought clearly stands within the broader tradition of natural
law ethics and, in particular, within the intellectualist rather than the voluntarist
strain of it. Pretty much all natural law ethicists, of either kind, hold the following
views: namely, that all human beings possess the natural capacity to grasp the
distinction between good and evil; that this capacity consists in recognizing some
certain end or ends that are good; that the moral quality of an action derives from
its fitness or unfitness for realizing this end or ends; that, more specifically, this
end or these ends are the core of what constitutes human nature; and so, finally,
that the moral quality of an action derives in particular from its agreement or
harmony with human nature.
It is easy to verify that Wolff accepts each of these claims under some inter-
pretation. Indeed, he often tells us such in direct or indirect reference to previous
authors on natural law. However, despite this broad agreement, Wolff ’s concep-
tion of the moral law and of moral science radically departs from both the
meaning and the intention found in most if not all of those authors, and it does
so according to a common underlying project aimed at revolutionizing moral
theory on the model of modern natural science.
This project of moral enlightenment, which broadly falls under his general aim
to create a sacred marriage between reason and experience, is grounded in the
German Ethics, but is most fully explained in a Latin essay entitled “On Moral
Experience” (“De experientia morali,” 1731). In this work, Wolff explains that the
familiar scientific methods, including those of empirical research, are perhaps
even more crucial to developing a proper moral science, and to a human being’s
becoming moral, than they are to the elaboration of physical science. He intro-
duces and defends this claim on several different grounds, which I have discussed
elsewhere,⁸ but the most fundamental surely lies in his specific conception of the
law of nature itself, or better, of the nature of the natural law. This law, he explains,
makes it our duty to perform the best action available to us (even if we are not
presently aware what that might be), where goodness is defined in terms of
⁷ Wolff ’s perfectionism is treated, among other places, in Klemme (2007) and Schwaiger (2018b).
The following is a compressed summary of the argument in Fugate (2024).
⁸ The following is a summary of the findings in Fugate (2024).
187
simply: “the human being ought to do what brings about the perfection of the world,
and omit what destroys it” (WAN §137; emphasis in original). For this reason, we
find Wolff fully and explicitly endorsing the Stoic view that ethics ultimately
comes down to living in agreement with nature (WTL §28). However, by “nature”
he means not Stoicism’s teleological conception of a cosmos guided by intrinsic
purposes and knowable to us through tradition and rational reflection on our
natural instincts, but rather nature as the object of modern, experimental science
as Wolff understood it. For my purposes, the important point to stress here is this
Wolffian claim of the convertibility between the moral and natural perfection of
an action, along with its implications, because I think such is both the focal point
of the agreement and the disagreement between Wolff and Baumgarten.
Stepping back from the details of Wolff ’s system for a moment, and bracketing
its other laudable qualities, it is helpful to consider the cost of holding such a
theory from the traditional standpoint of theories of natural law—a cost that
I think Baumgarten, and later Kant, were unwilling to pay. Recall that perhaps the
central reason for the invention and continuation of the long tradition of natural
law theory rested in its promise to articulate what was supposed to be a universally
and easily recognized set of laws for human conduct, one which could be common
to everyone regardless of religion, rank, or level of education. Wolff ’s specific
brand of natural law ethics, by contrast, is founded on the idea that nothing less
than a sophisticated moral science, itself resting on the other philosophical
disciplines, is required for providing new insights and overturning received, but
erroneous views about right and wrong, just as modern observational astronomy
(resting on sophisticated mathematics) was required to do with respect to com-
mon, but erroneous views of the cosmos, such as that the earth does not move or
that the Sun is only a palm in width. What is more, in his writings Wolff places
such emphasis on the value of acting from such scientific moral knowledge—
stating many times that those who do so are alone masters of themselves and are
virtuous, while others at most only appear virtuous and are more like slaves, or
children or animals (see WTL §38, 81)—that it is hard to see how his theory would
not create an elite class of philosophers alongside the rest of “childlike” human-
kind. But this is the natural consequence of taking the Stoic emphasis placed on
knowingly acting from the logos that animates nature and pairing it with a
modern, scientific conception of that logos and hence also of the methods required
for its discovery.
III
The second key Leibnizian doctrine that Baumgarten extends and places at the
heart of his philosophical system is that the actual world is the best of all possible
worlds. Wolff does in fact endorse this Leibnizian doctrine but gives it relatively
little scope. Baumgarten, again, provides a clear defense and elaboration of the
best-world doctrine, while transforming it into a foundational principle of
metaphysics where it is used to prove universal preestablished harmony and to
explain the relationship between the natural and the supernatural orders, and the
hierarchical priority of different sorts of law, among other things. As far as its
elaboration, Baumgarten articulates several principles thought to govern how the
natural perfection of a world is structured, anticipated, and measured.
As I have treated these matters in detail elsewhere, I will recall only those
elements relevant to my argument here (see Fugate 2023). The first point to note is
that philosophy, on Baumgarten’s understanding of it, is something that belongs
to both God and human beings. However, the divine “archetypal” philosophy
stands in a complex relationship to its human “ectype,” or philosophy insofar as it
is developed by finite, human beings like ourselves. In God, all things are known to
flow from all things, such that there is no intrinsic priority between cause and
caused, principle and principled, etc. In human knowledge, by contrast, some
things can only be known through others, and indeed certain truths ought to be
given priority in science because, for beings like us, it happens to be easier to grasp
and demonstrate other truths from them, and since, moreover, it is a duty of wise
judgment that the scholar conform philosophy to the needs of regular human
beings. That is to say, although these truths are not intrinsically fundamental or
first, they will be chosen to serve in this role by the philosopher who recognizes
that they are rather first or simplest relative to us and is cognizant of and strives to
realize the perfections of human knowledge in the wisest manner.
The two sciences that build upon such wisely chosen first principles are
metaphysics, or “the science of the first principles in human knowledge” (BM §1;
emphasis added), and first practical philosophy, or “the science containing the
first principles that are proper but also common to the rest of the practical
disciplines” (BIP §6). In the former, Baumgarten defines perfection in terms of
conformity of several things with a single determining ground or focus, and
its magnitude in terms of the degree of such conformity. Now, a norm or law
is a “proposition that expresses a determination in conformity with a ground”
(BM §83). So in the best or most perfect world as “that in which the greatest of the
most parts and the most of the greatest parts that are compossible in a world agree
in as great a being as is possible in a world,” there is the “greatest universal nexus,
harmony, and agreement that is possible in a world” (BM §441). Consequently,
there are the most universal laws (BM §444). And, indeed, the supreme law of this
world is that “[t]he best of all compossibles are joined together with the best” such
that there will be the greatest unity of the greatest multiplicity under the greatest
number of universal laws (BM §482; emphasis in original).
191
But the philosopher, who studies only what can be known without faith, has no
access to God’s archetypal knowledge of things and so knows things only insofar
as they are derived from metaphysics and experience. Together, these allow us to
know only laws of things that flow from the latter’s persistent, internal properties,
which we are aware of through experience. And as the collection of all these
internal properties is called the “nature” of the thing and what follows from such
according to laws is said to be “natural” (BM §430, 470–3), human philosophical
knowledge is restricted to the knowledge of natural laws. Thus, while admitting
other, supernatural laws are possible in the best world, Baumgarten believes that
our philosophical knowledge is restricted to those that are natural. This is,
however, not much of a handicap, because although supernatural laws are hypo-
thetically possible, the principle of the best itself places a priority on natural over
supernatural order, such that the law immediately subordinated to the law of the
best is “the law of the best in nature: the best of all natural things in the most perfect
world are joined together with the best” (BM §482; emphasis in original). The
upshot is the general law that supernatural events will occur if and only if it is the
case that the same perfection cannot be achieved according to the ordinary laws of
nature. Thus, while possible, supernatural order will be as minimal and natural
order will be as maximal as possible in the best of all possible worlds, and so in the
actual world. Hence, the philosopher will expect the laws in the actual world to
conform as much as possible to the form of a most-perfect system of natural law.¹¹
This metaphysical conception of the connection between perfection, law, and
nature in the broadest sense—of which I have provided the barest possible
outline—is of paramount importance for understanding Baumgarten’s practical
philosophy, which is founded upon it.¹² First practical philosophy has the function
of wisely choosing the best and simplest principles according to which we can
come to know one specific domain of the natural laws that obtain in the best of all
possible worlds and so also in this world, namely, those pertaining to the free
determinations under the control of the human will (BM §472; BIP §60).
Consequently, the practical philosopher—in the absence of any supernatural
signs to the contrary—will take the system of moral laws to constitute a most-
perfect system of propositions obligating us to conform our own actions to the
realization of the greatest possible natural perfection in the world. It is on this
basis that Baumgarten writes:
In any case, there can be positive law in human laws, and even in divine laws, that
is not natural, the sufficient ground of which we cannot know from the nature of
the action and the agent. But seeing that the will of God, or his most free choice
(BM §898), follows most perfectly upon supreme knowledge (BM §893), all his
positive laws have likewise a sufficient ground in the nature of the action and the
agent, or are likewise natural (§63). And since God wishes every good (BM §899),
all the natural laws (§39) are also divinely chosen. From the natural law, one may
validly infer the will of God concerning the free determinations of people, and
from the will of God concerning the free determinations of people, one may
validly infer the natural law. (BIP §69)
The propositions of moral philosophy will thus form the best possible system of
natural norms or laws. Furthermore, as actual nature, encompassing both the laws
of physical and free nature, is for him the best possible, we can now see why
Baumgarten so readily embraces the Stoic principle to live according to nature
(BIP §45); for one who does so brings their free actions under the universal laws of
the best possible world, thereby knowingly and intentionally uniting them into the
most perfect system with all other free actions and with all of physical nature as
well. This is therefore just the same as the duty to “seek perfection” (BIP §43).
As can be seen from this, Baumgarten not only extends Leibniz’s theory of the
best possible world but indeed makes it into a fundamental component of his
theory of the systematic structure of philosophical knowledge in general. For this
reason, it is able to provide the formal structure—what Kant would call a “regu-
lative principle” or “idea”—to guide the discovery and construction of the systems
of both physical and moral laws, as well as the single system comprising both.
However, it does so only under the regulative but philosophically justified guide-
line that these laws are all, or at least for the most part, consonant with our innate
conception of natural perfection.
(2) The second main difference between Wolff and Baumgarten concerns the
latter’s development of a key set of doctrines, which he brings together in a special
chapter of his Metaphysics entitled “The First Principles of the Mathematics of
Intensive Quantities.”¹³ Baumgarten introduces under this title a new branch of
ontology that has the aim of providing a mathematically precise account of the
scales or degrees of various kinds of perfections. This mathematics is referenced
and employed throughout his works and plays an essential role in his natural
theology and even in his conception of the nature of philosophy. As Baumgarten
says in the introduction to his Metaphysics, the mathematics of intensive quan-
tities opens up “a new sphere of mediation” for the philosopher and allows us to
“conceive what is the greatest of that which is real and positive and thus discover
God and the divine” (BM 90). Among other things, in practical philosophy it
proves essential to understanding the degrees of our own perfections, one lesson
of which is that owing to the mirroring doctrine, we should not underestimate the
extent to which just the analogue of reason is already far on the better side of
representing the perfection of things and so also what is good. Since the analogue
of reason is already capable of providing a relatively perfect, if not rationally pure,
grasp of the perfection of the world, it can be considered a relatively good
source of judgment about right and wrong, if properly formed. Moral instincts
and common moral views are thus not necessarily to be despised or regarded as
intrinsically vulgar, slavish, or incorrect. In rather sharp contrast with Wolff ’s
ethical intellectualism, then, one might see this as part of Baumgarten’s acceptance
and defense of the “mediocre,” which is something we find mentioned in several
passages in his writings.¹⁴
(3) The third main difference lies in Baumgarten’s view that knowledge is an
intrinsic good because it is a perfection in itself. Both Wolff and Baumgarten agree
that naturally good and evil actions are such per se, intrinsically or in themselves.
This is what makes them moral intellectualists rather than voluntarists like
Pufendorf. But for Wolff, this doesn’t mean that actions are good or evil when
taken entirely in isolation from the rest of nature. It means rather that they are
such because of how they are connected by natural laws with the rest of things. In
fact, Wolff constantly reminds us that the way to determine the moral quality of
an action is by looking to its natural effect, either by experience or by knowing
this in advance through science. A good action is such because it causes perfection,
while an evil action is such because it causes imperfection. This conception
of intrinsic goodness is expressed in the following passage from Wolff ’s German
Ethics:
While the free actions of human beings become good or evil through their
consequence, that is, through whatever alterable thing follows in the internal or
external state of the human being, but whatever follows from free actions must
do so necessarily and cannot refrain from happening (Met. §575); they [i.e. free
actions] are good by and in themselves, and are not first made such through
God’s will. (WTL §5; emphasis added)
¹⁴ By speaking of the “mediocre” here Baumgarten surely intends to draw on the ancient doctrine of
the mean (BIP §107, 244, 248; BA §269), yet in a way deeply rooted in his metaphysics of finitude
(BM §249) and framed to instill a respect for the average human being and the “lower” cognitive
faculties (BPB 12).
194 .
between things—in this case between an action and its consequence and so also
between the former and its own goodness—possess a kind of hypothetical neces-
sity depending on the actual order of nature. To give an example: Brushing your
teeth would be good, according to Wolff, because it improves or maintains one’s
bodily perfection. But there is a possible world in which the natural laws would
make it such that brushing would decrease one’s perfection (say by eroding one’s
enamel) and so would be bad. This explains why, in one sense, Wolff is able to
maintain, in opposition to moral voluntarists, that actions are intrinsically or
objectively good or evil (WAN §137), while, in another sense, Kant can be correct
in saying that Wolff ’s view implies that actions are not intrinsically good or evil at
all. This is because, for Wolff, lying, or breaking one’s promise, or whatever, is not
good or evil all by itself and in virtue of certain features of the very maxim that
internally defines it as the kind of act that it is, as is the case for Kant, but only
when seen from within the actual, though still hypothetical nexus of natural laws.
In short, two different senses of “intrinsic” are operative here; one employed by
Wolff, meaning within the context of natural laws and so of the nature of the act
understood accordingly, and another, employed by Kant, meaning internal to the
maxim defining the act itself irrespective of the actual laws of nature.
Now, Baumgarten fundamentally alters this Wolffian theory in an essential
way, which I don’t think has been noticed previously. Instead of defining goodness
in terms of an action’s effect or consequence, he writes:
The essential determinations of each being agree with its essence (§63, 40) and its
attributes. Therefore, every being is transcendentally perfect. [. . .] Something is
good if, when it is posited, a perfection is also posited. Therefore, every being is
transcendentally good (§99). (BM §99–100)
The third sentence in this passage is key. It does not say something is good when it
causes perfection or when perfection is its real consequence, but only that it is good
if, when the thing is posited, a perfection is posited.¹⁵ This means there are now
two possibilities: Something can be good if, when it itself is posited, perfection is
posited (namely its own); or something can be good if, when it is posited,
something else is posited (say caused) that contains perfection. The significance
of this change can be seen from the rest of the passage. To prove a being is
transcendentally good here, Baumgarten does not show that every being causes
some other perfection according to natural laws, but only that its being as such
is in itself already a perfection. The logic he employs is as simple as it is
¹⁶ This can also be seen from BM §147: “When the realities of a being are posited, its perfection is
posited (§141). Hence, realities are good (§100), and indeed absolutely necessary realities are a
METAPHYSICAL GOOD, and realities contingent in themselves are CONTINGENT GOOD [ . . . ].”
¹⁷ This follows from BIP §32, which states that goods only have goods as their implications, evils
only evils as their implications.
¹⁸ That he could not do so is signaled by the fact that he first defines “good” in his empirical
psychology, and thus as a concept that makes sense only in relation to human nature. In both the
German and Latin writings, goodness is defined as “whatever perfects us and our own state” (“quinquid
nos statumque nostrum perfecit,” “Was uns und unserun Zustand vollkommener machet” ) (WDM §422;
WPE §554). Wolff does mention, but notably without endorsing, what he refers to as the Scholastic
“bonitas transcendentalis” (WO §503). He equates this however with perfection a such, which—if he is
to be consistent with the above definition of goodness—means that goodness would not even be a
species of perfection, but instead, its cause according to natural laws. Baumgarten, as noted, defines
goodness already in his ontology as whatever, when posited, posits perfection. Hence, for him, moral
goodness is simply a species of goodness as such, namely, that in respect to free determinations insofar
as they are free. This change is clearly fundamental as are its consequences for understanding the
intrinsic goodness of moral acts.
¹⁹ I refrain from making the claim here that Kant explicitly recognized this fact.
196 .
the necessity of performing good actions, which themselves are such only because
they cause an increase in the perfection of the world. But since God clearly cannot
be made more perfect in any way, let alone made so by our actions within the
world, there can be no direct duties toward God and hence no direct duty to know
God, i.e. to develop religion. Unwilling, however, to consider there may be no duty
to religion at all, Wolff concludes that the only possibility is that we have an
indirect duty to meditate on God’s perfections in order to increase our motives for
performing our other duties (WTL §651). So, if one is religious in a Wolffian sense,
one will, for instance, brush their teeth more vigorously and frequently in the
awareness that God, with all his power and majesty, wants them to do so and so
has chosen it to be the natural law of the world in which they live. In this manner,
religion is good for us and is a duty because it lends support to other acts through
which we perfect ourselves and others. That is to say, religion is good, and so is a
duty, because it brings about or causes acts that themselves in turn cause perfec-
tions. The indirectness of this role played by religion here is mirrored in the fact
that Wolff first deals with it in the penultimate chapter of his German Ethics and
in the third of his five-volume Latin Ethics.
By contrast, almost the first quarter of Baumgarten’s own Philosophical Ethics
focuses on duties of religion, and he provides no less than ten distinct proofs that
we have a duty to religion. Here is one sample paragraph, which I think imme-
diately demonstrates the main difference between him and Wolff:
It is a reality to know the most perfect being most abundantly, worthily, truly,
clearly, certainly, and brilliantly (BM §36). Therefore, the glory of God posits a
reality in you (BM §947). The illustration of divine glory also posits a reality in
you; otherwise it would be evil (BM §146). That would contradict BM §947.
Therefore, the glory of God and his illustration in you agree as the determining
ground of perfection (BM §94), and are good for you (BM §660). Therefore,
religion perfects you as an end (BM §947) and indeed you are obligated to
religion (BM §10). (BEP §11; emphasis added)
Here Baumgarten makes use of both possible ways in which a thing can be good,
that is, in a non-consequentialist and in a consequentialist manner, the latter
being the only one articulated by Wolff himself. What Baumgarten here calls the
“glory of God”—as the Metaphysics tells us—consists in nothing but the greater
knowledge of God (BM §942). So part of this paragraph tells us that knowing God,
which is one aspect of religion (BM §947), perfects us directly or internally, insofar
as we have that very knowledge, thus “as an end,” and this goodness does not
depend on any consequence such knowledge may have. This glory of God, by
itself, is good (BM §942).
Now, also in this passage Baumgarten talks about the goodness of the “illus-
tration of divine Glory.” A little research reveals that this is just the Wolffian,
197
IV
esp. Refl 6750, 19:148). As stated already in the Herder notes, Kant believes that
Baugmarten’s Elements contains a fully adequate, general account of practical
perfection, but fails to properly distinguish and specify moral perfection and
hence moral goodness (PrHer 27:16). In this respect, Kant agrees with perfection-
ism’s claim that the essential form of the good lies in something’s degree of formal
diversity and unity under laws, completeness, or formal perfection. What he
rejects is that a grasp of this form can provide a criterion, as Wolff seemed to
believe it able, for discovering unconditioned, substantive, and thus moral goods
through our empirical experience of physical and mental nature. Kant has three
related insights here.
First, this form is insufficient by itself to specify the morally good (Refl 6624–5,
19:116). Baumgarten, following Wolff in this regard, had already indicated the
path forward, even if he had not trod it himself, by defining perfection not
just as the harmony of a manifold under general laws, but more determinately
as such agreement in respect to one thing, the so-called “determining ground
of perfection” (BM §94). The question, then, was this: What is the determining
ground of moral perfection as that one thing with which everything specifically
moral must harmonize according to the essential, albeit general form of perfec-
tion? Kant’s answer is that this is not human nature, but the will itself (Refl 6589,
6590, 19:97–8). In future formulations, this will come to mean that the moral
determining ground of all the will’s actions must be the will itself as an end. But at
this moment Kant is still working out the conception of a will that would be
distinct in kind from the empirically determined will of Wolff and Baumgarten.
The second insight concerns the metaphysical concept of unconditionality.
One, unquestioned presupposition of Kant’s reflections is that morality must
consist in the duty to follow an unconditional or absolutely necessary law. But
here Kant makes a fundamental break with Baumgarten’s conception of concepts
like “unconditioned,” “absolute,” and “in itself ”—a break that, as we will see, has
the unexpected consequence of making Baumgarten’s hyper-Leibnizian cosmol-
ogy (and so his conception of the perfection of nature) immediately relevant to his
(Kant’s) conception of intrinsic goodness. As we saw above in relation to
Baumgarten, he defends both an intrinsic and an extrinsic conception of the
moral goodness of an act,²⁰ that is, goodness with respect to its own being
as well as goodness as conformity with the natural nexus of all other things.
Now, as Kant notes, Baumgarten defines the above terms as follows: “Whatever is
²⁰ Although I cannot defend the view here, I think it may be more accurate to say he defends three
distinct ways (which can overlap) in which an action can be considered good, namely, in regard to its
own being, in regard to its relations to other things in the nexus of nature, and finally in regard to the
divine will and its possible supernatural nexus. The second of these corresponds to the Wolffian sense
of intrinsic goodness and I think also is contained in Baumgarten’s own conception of objective
morality, along with the first. On a similar but in some ways strikingly different account, see Bacin’s
chapter in this volume.
199
considered, but not in a nexus with those things that are posited externally to it,
(intrinsically, simply, absolutely, per se)” (BM §15). As
I have explained elsewhere, for reasons central to the Critical turn, Kant rejects
this conception of the “in itself” or “absolute” as what is valid in abstraction from
external relations and replaces it with the concept of what is valid in every respect
or in every possible relation (BM 30–1). To illustrate the difference: Whereas for
Baumgarten the absolutely possible may be impossible in the actual world (in
some external nexus), what is absolutely possible for Kant would be possible not
only in this world but in every possible world. Now, the upshot for morality is this:
the unconditioned good, as the object of an unconditional or absolutely necessary
law, according to Kant, rests on the notion of a law valid in every possible respect
or relation. That is to say: “The worth of an action or person is always decided
through relation to the whole. But this is only possible through agreement with the
conditions of a universal rule” (Refl 6711, 19:138; also, Refl 6712, 19:138). It would
thus be a law that is necessary in every possible moral world and so also, of course,
prescribes a sort of unity—a good—that can be considered a condition of the
possibility of any moral world at all. What is more, if it is necessary even in every
relation, it is not only necessary with regard to the world as a whole, but also
prescribes some sort of condition and so unity to every relation within that whole.
The third and final insight concerns the implications of this absoluteness of the
moral law. The otherwise empty Wolffian moral principle, noted above, was to be
provided with sufficient content through its empirical specification by way of
observation and experiment. But empirically determined laws (Kant would call
these merely “general rules”) will, on Kant’s view, always be conditional, and so
not necessarily, let alone unconditionally, good. They will be valid only in some
relation, not in every relation possible. The only possible unconditional good,
then, would have to consist in an unconditional formal perfection of the act itself;
the proposition expressing the necessity of the conformity of action to such would
alone be worthy of the name of a moral “law.” Here Kant silently adheres to the
view that action must be good in itself in Baumgarten’s, and not Wolff ’s, sense of
intrinsic goodness, while incorporating his own conception of intrinsic or absolute
goodness as good in every possible relation (Refl 6648, 6651, 19:124; 6700, 19:135;
6711–3, 19:138–9). Now, as the form of what is naturally good in every possible
relation must, on his Baumgartenian understanding of natural perfection, har-
monize with the most perfect possible absolute but also natural totality of free
beings (as a moral nature), Kant seems to have just adopted this same form as the
form of any intrinsically good act. The upshot is that the determining ground of
moral perfection, i.e. the will, cannot be the empirical will of Wolff and
Baumgarten but rather must be understood as practical reason not only as
unconditioned by any sensible inclinations and hence as pure and free (Refl
6621, 19:114; Refl 6639, 19:122), but also precisely insofar as it imposes upon
itself the pure and complete form of natural perfection. Thus, by reversing
200 .
Here we see Kant precisely equating the “perfection of freedom” with its uncon-
ditional agreement with itself and with the totality of other free wills according to
universal laws.
Similarly, note 7254, written between the lines of text in which Baumgarten
explains the central principle of perfectionism, reads:
The proposition “perfect yourself <perfice te>” is tautological. One wants to know
what the perfection that is the object of the categorical imperative consists in.
Moral perfection is the condition under which alone all others can be called
perfection. Now, I want to know what this consists in. It is a perfection of the will:
but what [does it consist] in?
At this point, as we have seen, Kant has his answer. The absolute perfection of the
will can only be that its acts within any world (and so also this one) are necessary
and so valid in respect to every possible world of free wills in which the will itself is
under no empirical limiting condition. The only limiting condition left is that of
201
the form of natural perfection itself, articulated by Baumgarten as the only form of
perfection knowable to the philosopher. This includes the inner “natural” lawful-
ness of the acts themselves as well as the maximal harmony of all wills within a
completely determined totality of “natural” laws.
In this way, the abstract form of natural perfection—though it remains formal
and a priori empty with respect to given nature, natural ends, and even moral
ends—becomes for Kant something substantively good, i.e. a specific end guiding
free choice, because imposing that form on every act of choice now itself becomes
the will’s own end and not just the form of an end that would only be discoverable
empirically. In addition to now being its own end insofar as it unconditionally and
intentionally wills the idea of its own acts as unconditioned, the free will is now
also its own supreme good, but only insofar as it acts essentially or purely in view
of the form of perfection, first discoverable to us as in the form of a nature
in general.
Finally, as this form of perfection in Baumgarten’s sense is essentially the form
of an absolute totality, maximally unified under laws of order, it is basically what
Kant would later call an “idea.” The idea “contains the greatest perfection in a
certain intention” and “[a]ll morality rests on ideas” (Refl 6611, 19:108; also, Refl
6978, 19:219). So following this, Kant naturally thinks of this unconditional good
as consisting in the will’s imposing upon itself not just some lawful order, but
indeed the idea of a complete or absolute order, the “natural” perfection of the will
in every possible respect (Refl 6725, 19:141–2). In this way, Kant talks about
absolute or moral goodness as simply equivalent to whatever harmonizes with the
whole of all possible acts of willing according to an “idea,” namely that of a
completely determinate kingdom of ends thought in analogy with a kingdom of
nature.
Hence, even before this specific term “kingdom of ends” appears in Kant’s
published writings, we find many notes to Baumgarten’s Elements in which the
idea is already present. To take just one example:
We can say that in a world all ends descend from the universal (the whole) to the
particular and thus the end of the whole contains in itself the condition of the
ends of the parts, i.e. that everyone must see himself as subject to the laws
through which he conforms to universal laws in every condition either of nature
or freedom. (Refl 6899, 19:200)
To summarize this point, Kant argues that the actions of a free will can be
absolutely good only because the principle that they arise from is precisely the
awareness of their fitness to completely harmonize with, or to constitute an
absolutely perfect whole with, all possible acts of willing. In this last step, Kant
fully detaches perfectionism from any empirical or natural-scientific remnant.
And in doing so, he also does away with any need for Baumgarten’s softening of
202 .
Wolffian intellectualism. For Kant, we need not be assured that we are all, whether
by insight or instinct, somewhere on the better side of things, possibly due to our
confused mirroring of the best possible world, since the goodness of our free will
lies entirely within our power to impose our own formal conception of natural
perfection on our own, unconditioned acts.
Conclusion. With this story, all the surprising features I mentioned in my intro-
duction fall into place. It is now clear why Kant’s theory looks so Leibnizian; it in
fact is a direct descendent of, and so borrows many structural features from,
Baumgarten’s hyper-Leibnizian perfectionism. The difference is that Kant’s per-
fectionism is a perfectionism of the free will qua unconditionally free rather than
qua a form of natural causality through the will (i.e. Wolffian “freedom”). We can
also see why Kant would look to the form of nature for the principles of this form
of moral perfection. That idea was already present in Wolff ’s perfectionism and
had become central in Baumgarten’s, but with the first Critique’s isolation of the a
priori form of a nature in general, the notion of natura formaliter spectata can
now provide the pure categorial structure for an intelligible world (“supersensible
nature”) of moral beings. The following note, penned in direct reference to
Baumgarten’s endorsement of the Stoic duty to live according to nature, makes
this connection in Kant’s mind particularly clear:
The principle of the unity of freedom under laws establishes an analogue with
what we call nature, and so also an internal source of happiness that nature
cannot provide of which we ourselves are authors. Thereupon we find ourselves
in a world of the understanding bound according to special laws that are moral.
And therein we are pleased.
The unity of the intelligible world according to practical principles, just like the
world of sense according to physical laws. (Refl 7260, 19:296–7)
11
Baumgarten, Kant, and the Subdivisions
of Practical Philosophy
Frederick Rauscher
This chapter is an attempt to understand this specific passage that Kant wrote as a
note to §88 of Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten’s Elements of First Practical
Philosophy, the book Kant used as a text for his lectures on ethics:
What immediately puzzles me about this passage is how this triad fails to
accord with Kant’s own later mature dual division of practical philosophy into
right and virtue. Right seems to match the third item in Kant’s list, outer freedom
under outer laws, and virtue seems to match the first item in Kant’s list, inner
freedom under inner laws. But there is no obvious match for the second item in
Kant’s list, outer freedom under inner laws. Could it be precisely the same set of
actions labeled “outer freedom under outer laws” but given the distinct viewpoint
of inner laws? Or are there two types or perhaps two aspects of outer freedom,
each subject to either inner or outer laws? And what is the difference between the
inner and the outer such that it differs for freedom and laws? In working out what
Kant might have meant in this jotting in his book, I will concentrate on the most
immediate evidence we have of Kant’s assessment of Baumgarten, namely, the
reflections Kant wrote in his own copy of Baumgarten’s Elements. I will show that
Kant uses some of Baumgarten’s own distinctions between inner and outer in
practical philosophy and follows some of Baumgarten’s understanding of types of
law, but that unlike Baumgarten Kant makes freedom itself the key value in
practical philosophy, resulting in various possible divisions of the subject. There
is some tension among these various distinctions between the inner and the outer,
¹ For the convenience of those examining the new edition that combines a translation of
Baumgarten’s Elements and Kant’s own notes in his copy of that text, I use those translations,
occasionally modifying them.
Frederick Rauscher, Baumgarten, Kant, and the Subdivisions of Practical Philosophy In: Baumgarten and Kant on the
Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press.
© Frederick Rauscher 2024. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0012
204
a tension I will claim remains in Kant’s final division between right and virtue in
the Metaphysics of Morals.
In this chapter I will first examine how Baumgarten uses the terms “inner” and
“outer,” or “internal” and “external,” identifying ten specific divisions that can be
understood to express four different ways of distinguishing those terms. I then
briefly examine his explanation of law and touch on freedom. I then turn to Kant’s
initial reaction to Baumgarten as revealed in the reflections, showing the various
ways that Kant saw possible divisions among the parts of practical philosophy and
tying them to different ways of understanding “inner” and “outer.” I show that
Kant’s emphasis on freedom rather than perfectionism led him to apply these
distinctions in his own way. The resulting set of distinctions that Kant was
considering in the 1760s and 1770s ultimately lies at the basis of his mature
moral philosophy in the Metaphysics of Morals.
² For Baumgarten, the natural moral laws are at the same time positive divine moral laws. Since the
will of God is the result of God’s supreme knowledge, and the natural moral laws are those that are
known by the nature of the action or agent conceptually, God knows all the natural moral laws and thus
wills them as God’s own positive law (BIP §69). Because of this correspondence, even the theoretical
atheist is able to know all the proper moral laws that would be thought of as divine laws were that
205
person a theist, although this knowledge of the atheist falls somewhat short of perfection in breadth,
certainty, etc. (BIP §71). Thus morality can be known independently of religion. Kant’s reaction to this
is clear in Refl 7092 (AA 19:247) where he comments on BIP §62: “God is not the author of the moral
law through his will, but instead the divine will is the moral law, namely the archetype of the most
perfect will and also the principle of all conditions for determining our wills in agreement with his own,
consequently all conditions of a necessary consent.”
206
[G]oods either belong to one through internal laws, or through external laws as
well (§§61, 43). The collection of the former is ’
(broadly considered, internally owed); the collection of the latter is ’
(externally owed, strictly considered), which, in right
and hence in natural right strictly considered, are unqualifiedly called one’s own.
(§§64, 65)
This division rests on the division between internal and external laws, such that
the goods themselves are not necessarily internal or external. And importantly,
Baumgarten allows an overlap in what is targeted or is the subject of the internal
and external laws when he allows that some are “through external laws as well.”
This division between external and internal is based not on the nature or char-
acteristics of the material goods themselves but simply on how those goods are
identified through different types of law. In addition, the division is not exhaustive
but allows for overlap.
A seventh division is about honor in §94 where what is internally honorable is
obedience to internal law and what is externally honorable is obedience to external
law. Here the obedience to the law is in a sense one’s comportment toward the law
and is not itself equitable with the law in the way that duty, obligation, and even
harms are. Rather the honor applies to the person as a result of their response to
these laws in obeying or not. In this way, this division is more similar to “what is
owed” above.
The eighth of the internal/external divisions concerns happiness (BIP §98):
“I [ . . . ] is to be obtained through internal laws [ . . . ]
happiness . . . is to be obtained through external laws.” Although this
sounds as if there are two different substantive kinds of happiness, instead, like the
conception of internal and external good, the division is only based on the laws
themselves. But since it refers not to the laws but to the result of the laws, it is like
the previous two divisions.
The final two divisions between internal and external³ appear in §180 when
Baumgarten turns to a court of judgment regarding imputation of deeds:
³ I have examined ten different but interrelated divisions between internal and external but make no
claim here to have exhausted this distinction as presented by Baumgarten. There may be other uses of
the distinction that escaped my notice.
208
Deeds are called internal (unqualifiedly internal) insofar as they occur in the soul
alone, observable by no signs or anything external, through the body; however,
external deeds are thus harmonic such that they are also indicated by external
signs through the body.
Here the ninth division between internal and external refers to the observability of
the deed, with internal deeds having no apparent expression outwardly through
the body, while external deeds are indicated through some expression through the
body. However, Baumgarten’s “also” indicates that the external deeds do have a
component inside the soul, and the term “harmonic” relates to Baumgarten’s
metaphysics of a pre-established harmony between the soul and the body.
External deeds, then, presumably have their imputable origin in the soul but
their expression in the physical world, while internal deeds relate only to decisions
that originate and affect the soul itself.
In the tenth division two types of courts are divided in relation to deeds: “The
external court is that in which only external deeds can be validly subsumed under
external laws. However the internal court is that in which internal deeds can also
be validly subsumed under internal laws” (BIP §180). The internal court is
identified as either the court of conscience or the court of reason (BIP §182),
with the court of reason also having an external counterpart. (There is also a
divine court described in §185 that will be passed over here.) The external court
can be a civil court, and “rights strictly considered only belong to external courts”
(§186). External and internal courts, then, are correlated with external and
internal deeds. This last division between external and internal also concerns,
like the ninth, the mental and the physical.
In the end we can compare and contrast the ten divisions I have discussed to
identify four different ways that Baumgarten distinguishes internal and external:
We will see which of these Kant ends up referring to in his own division
between internal and external.
209
⁴ The Fugate/Hymers Baumgarten translation usually construes “jus naturae” as “the right of
nature” but sometimes as “natural right.” For consistency I render them all as “natural right.”
210
Since the characteristic of external law is that it is known from someone’s free
choice, the distinction is merely in the source of the law.
The section of the Elements called “The Principles of Right ” (§87–99) contains
the place where Kant wrote in his own copy the passage with which I started
this chapter. Baumgarten begins by distinguishing between subjective and objective
principles (the objective principles belong to a discipline inherently, while the
subjective principles are instead used for knowing the discipline), but more
relevant is that he further distinguishes between external and internal objective
principles. “F” principles are external and “do not pertain to a given
discipline as conclusions, i.e. as parts that are only to be taught in that discipline”
and “” principles are internal and “pertain to a given discipline as
conclusions, i.e. especially as parts belonging to it that are only to be taught in
that discipline” (BIP 87). Part of what Baumgarten says in §88 is “do not let the
external be invoked, when it is a question of the internal and the domestic.” This
is the only direct reference to internal or external in §88, and there is no mention
of freedom or laws. The focus of that section is on principles of natural right.
Since natural right was earlier distinguished into natural right broadly or
narrowly construed, Baumgarten has both of these aspects in mind. He notes in
§89 that the first, or highest, principle of natural right narrowly construed,
although something chosen (arbitrarium, that is, a product of a faculty of choice),
is the result not of blind choice but of prudent choice. Baumgarten devotes the
next few sections to providing criteria that should be used to determine that
prudent choice of the first principle; for example, he says to prefer a principle
appropriate to the whole discipline over which it would be first (BIP §90). Using
these criteria, he rejects as too broad the principle “furnish the good or seek
perfection as much as you are able” for natural right narrowly construed; this
principle does serve as the first principle of natural right broadly construed (BIP
§91). Instead of this, Baumgarten identifies in the following few sections three
principles, essentially matching the traditional triad from Ulpian, “you shall harm
nobody (externally)” (BIP §92), “attribute to each (to a human being, negatively at
least) what is known with certainty and without faith to be his own (with regard to
right)” (BIP §93), and “cultivate the (external) honorableness that is to be known
with certainty but without faith” (BIP §94), each of which he identifies as suitable
to be the first principle of natural right narrowly construed.
His argument for the first of these principles is important because it utilizes the
divisions between internal and external duties and internal and external harms
(described above) corresponding to the division between internal and external
laws. As he explains,
since the whole of natural right strictly considered encompasses laws strictly
considered, and external duties (§65), everything will be deduced from the
211
principle you shall harm nobody (externally), which will be the first domestic
objective principle of natural right, strictly considered. (BIP §92)
Here the broader principle simply to furnish the good or seek perfection, which
was adequate for natural right broadly construed, is rejected as being too broad, as
is the somewhat more narrowly tailored principle “you shall harm nobody (either
internally or externally),” which would apply to more than simply the narrowly
considered natural right focused only on the external. Thus the highest principle
for natural right narrowly construed must match the nature of that narrow
construal, which Baumgarten had identified earlier in relation to the external:
“ (constraining, external), contradistin-
guished from counsels, internal laws and persuasions, insofar as they are natural”
(BIP §65).
Baumgarten sees two different kinds of positive law as correlated with the
internal and external in a different way. In §98, he argues that although the
discipline of natural right is complete in itself, it is not necessarily known as
such to everyone. “Hence,” he writes,
This distinction between the internal and external right regarding human perfec-
tion is correlated with internal and external happiness, each of which are said to
stem from the respective internal and external laws.
Regarding freedom—a term that Kant uses in the passage with which I started
this chapter and one that Kant of course makes central to his moral philosophy—
Baumgarten says little in the Elements. He links practical philosophy to freedom
only in the sense that moral beings are those who are free to choose their actions
and thus must use the guidance of moral laws. “Morally possible” things are “free
determinations,” which concern only “persons” described as “free substances”
(BIP §10). Although the being ultimately has free will, this freedom is still subject to
“impelling causes” that determine obligations. Baumgarten does not define free-
dom using the contrast between external and internal. In his Metaphysics, he does
discuss freedom in terms of actions and determinations, but there is no attempt
to discuss a freedom of actions independently of a freedom of determinations.
Instead, determinations are the specific decisions in the superior faculty of desire
that result in actions (BM §721–3). There is also no separate discussion of
freedom of the body when Baumgarten discusses the interaction of soul and body
212
(BM §733–9). We can conclude that, at least as far as it affects his moral theory,
Baumgarten does not have a conception of external freedom substantially different
from a mere display of internal freedom.
II
Kant on Inner, Outer, Laws, and Freedom. Kant’s notes in his personal copy of
Baumgarten’s Elements range from as early as 1764 through the 1780s. I choose to
focus on the material prior to 1780 because by that time Kant was well on his way
to working out his critical ethical position. I am more interested in how Kant
worked his way toward that position in relation to Baumgarten. Because the
dating of these reflections is not exact, and because they all fall within the pre-
Critical time period, and because they are not formulations Kant intended for
public consumption but only his private working-out of ideas, perhaps to be used
in his course lectures, and finally because they do not reveal systematic compre-
hensive positions that can be compared with one another, I will treat them all as
chronologically equivalent. That is, I will assume that each reflection represents
some idea or ideas Kant had during the fifteen-year period between 1764 and 1780
that can be usefully compared and connected with one another without speculat-
ing about chronological development within that period. I will also refer very
briefly to two sets of student lecture notes for the courses Kant taught on ethics:
the Herder lecture notes of 1764 and the Collins lecture notes of 1784–85, which
are however thought to reflect Kant’s lectures from 1775.
In this section, I will first present a few of the ways in which Kant sought to
divide morality into parts. This will suggest that he approaches practical philos-
ophy broadly and has different possible ways to subdivide it. I will then examine in
more detail his emphasis on the value of freedom—the main way in which he
differs from Baumgarten regarding these divisions. This will then suggest a way to
examine internal freedom and external freedom. Regarding internal freedom,
Kant will be seen to transform Baumgarten’s conception of perfection into a
specific focus on the cultivation of one’s own capacity of free choice. Regarding
external freedom, Kant will be seen to distinguish between a negative and a
positive relation to other individuals’ choices, one which will relate to the distinc-
tion between not interfering with their freedom and helping others use their
freedom. I will pull this together with a suggestion about how different senses of
“internal” and “external” bring about these different divisions.
I will start with a look at the ways that Kant distinguishes morality into different
parts.⁵ The most relevant division is that between right and virtue, corresponding
⁵ Kant’s mature theory, of course, divides morality into parts along several different lines that are
outside the scope of this chapter. Two other ways that Kant divides morality in general but that are not
213
to the two parts of the published Metaphysics of Morals. That division is explained
in general in terms of lawgiving that has incentives other than duty (mainly
constraint) and internal lawgiving that has only duty itself as the incentive (MS
6:218). One hint of this eventual division is in Refl 7084, where Kant says: “The
whole of natural right is without civil order a mere doctrine of virtue and has the
name of a right purely as a plan for possible external laws of constraint, hence of
civil order” (AA 19:245).
One important note divides the whole of our practical considerations into four:
There are various degrees of the determination of our choice:
This four-fold division uses the concepts of universal and private to pair each
with choice, good, or inclination. There is a movement from the most objective to
the least objective from top to bottom. Starting at the bottom, the fourth of these is
merely individual sensuous drives that can determine choice but only in a
particular way; this element of practical philosophy is not related to objective
grounds and plays no important role. The second and third each refer to “good”
seen as private or general. The private good here is “self-love” and might be
associated with prudence. The “good in general,” or “beneficence,” is contrasted
with the private good and both fall under general rules. Here good is divided into
an individual private good and an unexplained “good in general” that may simply
be the sum total of all the private goods; Kant’s identification of this good in
general with beneficence indicates that he has something like that in mind. At the
top of this list, and presumably the widest degree of determination of choice, is
simply laws of choice in general, equated with right. Importantly here, Kant is
stating that there are laws of choice in general unrelated to any particular or even
general good, or any other consideration. Also important to notice is that there is
no reference to internal or external here, nor relation to self compared with
relation to others (besides the unstated comparison between beneficence and
self-love).
Some other divisions of practical philosophy Kant proposes also involve free-
dom. One of these explanations is Refl 7054 (AA 19:236):
at issue in this chapter are a. the division between critical philosophy (mainly in the Groundwork and
Critique of Practical Reason) and an exposition of duties (mainly in the Metaphysics of Morals), b. the
division between an a priori metaphysics of morals and an empirical moral anthropology.
214
The practical laws based on the mere idea of freedom are moral. Those based on
the idea of internal freedom concern all actions and are ethical; those based
merely on the idea of external freedom are juridical and concern merely external
actions.
Here the overall highest laws in morality are based on the idea of freedom, which
is then divided into internal and external freedom.
Kant sees another way to distinguish right from ethics as negative from positive.
Refl 6597 defines right and ethics in terms of different ways of implementing
“common will” or “common choice”:
The rule of right is: impede nobody in the use of their free choice contained
under the law of common choice. The rule of ethics is: add that which is sufficient
complement to the [otherwise] inefficacious will of others according to the rules
of the common will. (AA 19:102)
Freedom is a subjective lawlessness. One does not know according to which rule
one should judge his own actions or those of other human beings. Whims,
peculiar taste, evil or empty fancies can produce effects for which one was not
215
In addition to agreement with nature, free will must harmonize with itself in
regard to the internal and external independence from impulses. Without moral-
ity, folly and chance are the masters of human fortune. (Refl 6961, 19:215)
Kant’s point here is that without a rule, freedom would be random or chaotic and
would lead to confusion and self-contradiction.⁶
The potential for contradiction, however, is not identified only with freedom
being in contradiction with itself. Kant does consider that a lawless freedom would
be in contradiction with other things, and those other things turn out to relate to
parts of his final division of morality. One reflection lists a large number of
possibilities:
If your will ought to harmonize with all your inclinations through universally valid
conditions, then it must harmonize with that to which they all refer, namely, your
own self, i.e. personality. Duty towards oneself. Your actions ought to harmonize
with your freedom and ([with] the universality of) your inclinations, with the
freedom of others and ([with] the universality of) their inclinations.
(With your inclination and the inclination of others, with your freedom and
the freedom of others.)
(The universally valid will is a pure will, which is not affected by impulse and
inclination, and its object is the good.) (Refl 6851, 19:179; translation modified)
Here the will must harmonize with (a) one’s own self, (b) your freedom, (c) other’s
freedom, (d) your inclinations, (e) others’ inclinations. It seems to me that Kant is
including some of the latter four options not as an addition to the first but as an
elaboration. Harmonizing with oneself involves harmonizing with one’s own free-
dom and one’s own inclinations. But he also includes harmonization with others.
Harmony with inclinations is also seen in Kant’s claims about a harmony or
maximization of happiness: Refl 6603 declares that right is related to happiness by
coordinating the intentions of all:
All right has a universal relation to happiness insofar as each brings it about
through themselves in such a way that the rules of private intention do not
contradict one another according to universal laws. All duties of love consist in
the desire to promote universal (not merely one’s own) happiness through one’s
own actions. (AA 19:105)
But when he is clearest Kant separates this sort of rule as tied not to freedom
but only to inclination. Refl 6672 starts with this separation: “Whatever is
possible according to the rule of the pure will, taken universally, is right;
whatever is possible according to the rule of inclination, taken universally.”
But it suddenly breaks off here, as if Kant is hesitant to label a rule of inclination.
He continues: “The universally valid rule of inclinations is a rule of happiness;
for what is universal in all inclinations is agreeableness and its abstraction,
happiness.” Then he finally identifies the universal rule for inclinations
with beneficence in the next paragraph: “The judgments concerning right and
obligation consider the rules of pure will, and so are the easiest; those of
beneficence concern inclinations, circumstances of well-being, and are difficult”
(AA 19:129–30).
Beneficence as concern for the happiness of others is excluded from right:
With respect to the right of another, neither my own need (as in regard to
beneficence), nor the need of others, nor the worthiness of others is taken into
account; indeed, also the certain advantage of the other never gives me a right,
but rather only his will. (Refl 6732, 19:143)
The will of others, which is essentially the same as the choice of others, is the
concern of right. Right, then, is taken to exclude any relation to happiness but to
concern only the relation of wills, and that relation can be only one of maximi-
zation of the harmony of those wills.
What is not included in this approach is that helping other individuals to fulfil
their own choices is a relation of wills, or powers of choice, in a positive way. Kant
has based the most general practical philosophy not on happiness but merely on
freedom understood only negatively as the capacity or opportunity for choice, not
in terms of the actual ends or aims of free choices. A clear statement of this comes
in Refl 7063: “Laws of freedom in general are those that contain the conditions
under which alone it is possible for them to harmonize with themselves: condi-
tions of unity in the use of freedom in general” (AA 19:240). In the Collins lectures
Kant says “[i]n the moral imperative the end is quite undetermined, nor is the
action determined by the end, for it relates only to free choice, be the end what it
may [ . . . ] our free acting and refraining has an inner goodness and thus gives the
human being an immediate inner absolute worth of morality” (MoC 27:247,
translation modified).
217
There is at least a tension, then, regarding whether the happiness of others, the
fulfillment of their chosen ends, is included in practical philosophy or not. Kant
quite often limits morality, and certainly limits right, to mere conditions of
freedom without relation to actual fulfillment of ends. But he also sometimes
includes beneficence in the broad scope of morality, and even sometimes identifies
ethics, as opposed to right, with the concern for the happiness of others as
fulfillment of their ends.
If freedom is seen as the main concern of practical philosophy, it is not simply
one unitary understanding of freedom. The division of freedom into internal and
external freedom means that there are two types of freedom. How does Kant
characterize them? In general, external freedom is a maximization or harmoniza-
tion of the actual choices of everyone, while internal freedom is the state of the
individual’s own will (or power of choice) being geared toward free choices. Refl
6605 makes this clear:
The chief rule of externally good actions is not that they harmonize with the
happiness of others, but rather that they harmonize with their choice, and just as
the perfection of a subject rests not on its being happy but rather on its state being
subordinated to freedom. (AA 19:106, Kant’s emphasis)
I believe that Kant is taking our duties to be of two main kinds. First is the
consistency of our free actions with the free actions of others understood as the
result of choice. This is purely external. The second is not concerned with others
or with actions but with the capacity for free actions, the state of the individual in
fostering their capacity to choose morally rather than based on inclinations or
happiness; Kant even identifies this latter as perfection, to which I will return
below. This division between internal and external freedom is given using differ-
ent wording in Refl 6795:
The essential laws are those without which freedom would be a dangerous
behemoth; namely, freedom must not be used in such a way that it is contrary
to humanity in itself, 2 is not contrary to the freedom of others. So there are
rights of humanity and rights of human beings: rights of humanity in one’s own
person and the same rights in regard to others. (AA 19:163)
That freedom alone is the consideration for one’s external actions, the harmoni-
zation of free choices not of inclinations or happiness, lies behind this point Kant
makes in Refl 6796:
What restrains freedom is only the universality for choice with respect to all actions.
The pleasure in this rests on the harmony of all actions of choice among one
another through agreement with what is universally valid of them. (AA 19:164)
218
And Refl 6864 is even more emphatic that freedom’s consistency is of importance:
It is clear, of course, that Kant takes external freedom, as the universal harmony of
one’s free choices with the free choices of others, to be a basis for right. Refl 7054
quoted above, for example, says that laws “based merely on the idea of external
freedom are juridical and concern merely external actions” (AA 19:236). But Kant
equally discusses internal freedom in his reflections, as in the other half of the
contrast given in that same reflection: laws “based on the idea of internal freedom
concern all actions and are ethical.” What precisely does Kant mean by internal
freedom? And how does it relate to his responses to Baumgarten?
Kant was always critical of Baumgarten’s identification of perfection as the basis
for morality and ends up linking inner perfection to the capacity for inner
freedom. For Baumgarten, of course, the laws did relate to something more than
choice itself, namely, perfection. But for Kant, perfection is not a substantial
concept on its own but must be based upon some other consideration. On the
very first surviving page of Herder’s 1764 notes to Kant’s lectures, Kant is recorded
as saying “[t]he disinterested feeling for the welfare, etc., of another has our own
perfection not as an end but as a means” (PrHer 27:3). Perfection is not itself the
aim of morality; rather, one must be perfect in order to fulfil the separate aim of
morality (here identified as the welfare of others, i.e. beneficence). Later in that
lecture Kant calls a claim to seek perfection “objectively speaking an empty
proposition, since it is wholly identical” (PrHer 27:16).
In the Collins lectures Kant provides an argument that perfection is related to
the capacity of the will:
The perfection of a man does not yet signify morality. Perfection and moral
goodness are different. Perfection here is the completeness of the man in regard
to his powers, capacity, and readiness to carry out all the ends he may have.
Perfection can be greater or less; one man can be more perfect than another. But
goodness is the property of making good and proper use of all these perfections:
so moral goodness consists in the perfection of the will, not the capacities.
(MoC 27:265–6)
good perfection, then, is specifically perfection of the will for its own capacities.
Thus the more general conception of perfection that Baumgarten had used is
narrowed by Kant only to the specific perfection of the capacity of the will to will
correctly. And this we will see is to will freedom itself.⁷
In Refl 6980, Kant makes clear that perfection must be aimed at free choice:
“Perfect yourself means: make all your faculties and powers, but proportionally,
greater. Above all the power that directs their employment: the free and rational
choice” (AA 19:219). In another reflection, he explains how this free choice is the
core of perfection:
There is a free choice that has no personal happiness as its intention, but rather
presupposes it. The essential perfection of a freely acting being depends on this
freedom [crossed out: choice] not being subject to inclination or in general not
being subject to any foreign cause at all. (Refl 6605, 19:105–6)
The free choice must not be subject to any foreign cause or inclination but subject
only to itself.
Kant’s discussion of suicide is also related to internal freedom. Suicide is an
extreme example of a lack of harmony of inner freedom: “One who commits
suicide also displays freedom in the greatest conflict with itself, hence in the
greatest ruin of its own delusion” (Refl 6801, 19:165). Suicide is not merely the
taking of a life, it is the contradiction of freedom with itself, a use of freedom to
destroy freedom, hence a disharmony of maximal consistent freedom. This
internal duty to oneself to preserve one’s capacity for freedom and the ability to
choose freely is the way that Kant gives content to the otherwise vague idea of self-
perfection in Baumgarten.
So far I have reviewed Kant’s discussion of internal and external freedom. These
explain that internal freedom is the individual’s capacity to use the power of
choice itself, and harmony or consistency of that internal freedom is the basis of
duties to oneself. External freedom is the effect of one’s choices in actions, so the
mutual effect of everyone’s choices relative to everyone else. Kant does not identify
external freedom with any kind of perfection, or with achieving any end such as
one’s own happiness or the happiness of others. The discussion of internal and
external freedom has touched upon internal and external laws, and I will now
focus on how Kant sees these laws.
⁷ Bacin (2015) suggests that Kant’s acceptance of Baumgarten’s separation of perfection and
happiness is a precursor to the division in the Doctrine of Virtue in the Metaphysics of Morals. “The
coordination of the two objective ends stated later in the Metaphysics of Morals can thus also be tracked
back to Kant’s elaboration on Baumgarten’s greater case in separating perfection and happiness and in
defining the proper meaning of each” (22). This is correct as an explanation of the division in the
Doctrine of Virtue between ends of one’s own perfection and the happiness of others. The story of how
Kant got there is more complicated than it might seem at first.
220
And Kant also sees what Baumgarten had called “internal constraint” simply as
duty: “The motive to satisfy obligation (subjective necessitating) is either external
(constraint) or internal (duty). The first is juridical, the second ethical” (Refl 7056,
19:236). Kant here rejects Baumgarten’s use of the term “constraint” both internally
and externally and sees one’s internal obligations not as a matter of constraint but
only of duty. As he says in Refl 7064, “[o]ne can act in conformity to law based on
principles or on constraint: because one wills to or one must” (AA 19:240).
If the source of external laws is outside the agent as a positing of law by a state,
what is the source of internal laws? For Baumgarten, referring to “internal” laws,
like internal duties, obligations, and harms, simply meant that they were intrinsic
to the agent or to the action. Kant does not explicitly reject this understanding of
the internality of non-posited laws, but he does not think that these laws and
moral concepts are independent of reason itself. Kant identifies reason as the
221
source of laws in many reflections (e.g. Refl 6627, 19:117; Refl 6690, 19:134; Refl
6802, 19:167; Refl 6864, 19:184; and Refl 7029, 19:230) but most clearly stresses
reason in Refl 6760: “the principle of moral judgment is not the divine will, not the
general concept of perfection, not the general concept of happiness, not private
happiness, not the moral feeling and taste, instead reason” (AA 19:151). Reason
itself is able to judge what belongs in practical philosophy.
III
⁸ I would like to thank Courtney Fugate for helpful suggestions that resulted in a clearer chapter.
12
Three Models of Natural Right
Baumgarten, Achenwall, and Kant
Fiorella Tomassini
The modern tradition of natural right starts from the assumption that the
notion of ius refers not only to the existence of coercive public laws but also to
a possible object of rational knowledge.¹ The idea of ius naturae was well known
in antiquity and the Middle Ages, but its use to describe a systematic doctrine,
the universal principles of which can be determined through reason alone
when using the proper method, did not appear until the seventeenth century
(see Scattola 2003). At the very beginning of the Doctrine of Right, Kant remarks
that his discussion of right is grounded in this tradition. He situates the
Rechtslehre in the realm of “systematic knowledge of the doctrine of natural
right (Ius naturae)” and claims that the purpose of this doctrine is “to establish
the basis for any possible giving of positive laws” (MS 6:230). With that said,
Kant reformulates the idea of ius naturae to the point that the term itself is no
longer used in his moral system: laws of nature (referring to moral laws) are now
called laws of freedom, and the doctrine of natural right (Naturrechtslehre) (i.e.
the system of juridical principles based on reason alone) is now called a meta-
physical doctrine of right.
Since Kant abandons the language of natural right, it remains unclear how,
exactly, his Rechtslehre relates to the natural right tradition. Some historians of the
modern natural right tradition go so far as to state that “Kant wrote little that
directly engaged with the authors of the ‘modern’ natural law tradition, although
he regularly lectured from Achenwall’s Wolffian textbook on natural law”
(Hochstrasser 2004, 197). Others link his work to “the philosophical destruction
of the doctrine of natural right” (Hartung 1999, 167). I contend, by contrast, that
Kant did engage with the authors of the natural right tradition and in fact aimed to
refound the discipline rather than destroy it. The fact that he does not employ the
language of natural right is neither an expression of an intention to “destroy” the
¹ I would like to thank Pauline Kleingeld for her insightful feedback on earlier versions of this
chapter, as well as Janis Schaab, Lu Zhao, Luke Davies, Mike Gregory, Pablo Zadunaisky and Sabina
Vaccarino Bremner for their helpful comments. I am grateful to the Dutch Research Council (NWO)
for supporting this research.
Fiorella Tomassini, Three Models of Natural Right: Baumgarten, Achenwall, and Kant In: Baumgarten and Kant on the
Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press.
© Fiorella Tomassini 2024. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0013
224
tradition as such nor a mere terminological change. Instead, it reflects the radical
transformation of the discipline.
Moreover, I argue that by considering Kant’s engagement with previous theor-
ists of natural right, we can gain a clearer understanding of how he transformed
the discipline from its foundations. To do this, I will focus my analysis on Kant’s
(Critical) reception of two models of natural right with which he was very familiar:
one from Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten’s Elements of First Practical Philosophy,
the other from Gottfried Achenwall’s Natural Law. The Elements served as a basis
for Kant’s lectures on moral philosophy for over three decades and may thus be
considered as having played an important role in shaping his practical philosophy
as a whole (Allison 2011, 6). Achenwall’s Natural Law was the textbook that Kant
employed in his lectures on natural right for over two decades. I will argue that
Kant distances himself from previous models of natural right in three main
regards: the identification of moral laws with laws of nature; the normative
connection between the principles of right and a natural end; and the place of
God as the author of moral laws. I will then briefly discuss what Kant retains
of Baumgarten’s and Achenwall’s models of natural right. Kant’s Metaphysics of
Morals preserves the view that a rational doctrine of right belongs to a broader
systematic doctrine that comprehends the entire system of duties. I will address
the question of the division of the Sittenlehre into two branches and claim that,
whereas Kant did not consider Baumgarten’s answer to the problem of distin-
guishing juridical from ethical principles to be satisfactory, he found a key piece of
his own solution in Achenwall’s Natural Law, namely the definition of right as a
power to coerce.
of obligations of a person that are to be known without faith” (BIP §1). This
reformulation of Wolff ’s programmatic idea of a philosophia practica universalis
brings Baumgarten closer to the modern tradition of natural right—initiated by
Grotius and further developed by Hobbes, Pufendorf, Locke, and Thomasius,
among others—according to which philosophical reflection on human praxis is
primarily organized in terms of obligations, duties, and rights. In opposition to
this, Leibniz’s and Wolff ’s moral philosophies are concerned with the good and
perfection, dealing with duties and obligations solely in an indirect manner (see
Schneewind 1993, 56; Schwaiger 2009).
As stated in the preface to the Elements, Baumgarten hopes to contribute with
this work to “achieving an adequately solid science of natural right” (BIP IX). By
this he is referring not to a doctrine of right and juridical duties but to a broader
discipline. This broader sense of the notion of ius naturae was not uncommon in
the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Previous authors, such as Pufendorf and
Wolff, used it with different meanings and understood it as primarily referring to
the universal system of duties, and thus as equivalent to moral philosophy.³ For
them, the basic, systematic division in moral philosophy was not that between
right and ethics but that between duties to oneself, duties to others, and duties to
God (see Scattola 2008, 241; Schröder 1995, 337). Baumgarten agrees with this
general account of ius naturae, but instead of conceiving it as a science of duties,
he understands it in terms of obligations.⁴ He believes that, as long as the science
of natural right concerns all kinds of obligations that emerge from the human
beings as such, it coincides with practical philosophy. Therefore, the concepts,
categories, and principles of practical philosophy are, at the same time, the first
elements of ius naturae (see Scattola 2008, 242). Not only was Baumgarten
concerned with the division and classification of duties and obligations, but,
like any modern theorist of natural right, he addressed the question of its
fundamental principle. Following an accurate method, he aimed to establish the
first and universal principles of practical philosophy (or ius naturae) in order to
³ “It is evident that there are three sources of man’s knowledge of his duty, of what he is to do in this
life because it is right <honestum> and of what he is to omit because it is wrong <turpe>: the light of
reason, the civil laws and the particular revelation of the Divinity. From the first flow the most common
duties of a man, particularly those which render him capable of society <sociabilis> with other men; [ . . . ]
Hence there are three distinct disciplines. The first is the discipline of natural law, which is common to all
nations; [ . . . ] Each of these disciplines has its own method of proving its dogmas, corresponding to its
principle. In natural law a thing is affirmed as to be done because it is inferred by right reason to be
essential to sociality <socialitas> among men” (Pufendorf 1991, 8). In the Leviathan, Hobbes also presents
the set of laws of nature as the true content of moral philosophy: “all men agree on this, that peace is good,
and therefore also the way, or means of peace, which (as I have shewed before) are justice, gratitude,
modesty, equity, mercy, & the rest of the laws of nature, are good; that is to say, moral virtues, and their
contrary vices, evil. Now the science of virtue and vice, is moral philosophy; and therefore the true
doctrine of the laws of nature, is the true moral philosophy” (Hobbes 1985, 216).
⁴ In §65, Baumgarten provides the different definitions of ius naturae. Among other meanings, it is
defined in a broad sense as “the collection of natural laws that obligate human beings”; only in a strict
sense does it refer to the sum of natural laws that admit of external coercion (BIP §65; cf. BIN §1–2).
226
deductively obtain the complete content of the doctrine (cf. BIN §1, 88). I will now
briefly examine these principles as presented in the Elements.
Ia
⁵ This can be done in two ways: either by positing perfection in ourselves, becoming more perfect as
ends, or by positing perfection in others, becoming more perfect as means. This implies the obligation
to “omit, as much as you can, those things that render you more imperfect either as an end, or as means,
or in either respect” (BIP §43).
227
(BIP §46) and that the injunction to “live according to nature, as much as you can”
(BIP §46) is a moral imperative. Here, Baumgarten introduces a Stoic principle
that is found throughout the natural right tradition and may be regarded as one of
its main tenets: the measure of what is right and wrong, the beneficial and the
harmful, is conformity with nature as such (cf. Hespe 2007, 278). Finally, he adds
that pursuing perfection involves being more pleased by the perfection of what is
best and, consequently, loving the best. Thus the universal moral obligation
“quaere perfectionem, quantum potes” can be reformulated as the command to
“love the best, as much as you can” (BIP §48).
Having presented the universal laws of practical philosophy, Baumgarten draws
a distinction within the notion of obligation that will later allow him to delimit the
sphere of right (in a strict sense), namely the distinction between internal and
external obligations. In BIP §56, we read: “an obligation to some free determina-
tion through the exacting <extorsio> permitted to another human being is external
(complete, perfect), and the rest are internal obligations (incomplete, imperfect)”
(cf. BIN §146).⁶ Baumgarten also claims that an external obligation cannot take
place without an internal one. In the case of an external obligation, the free
determination is represented as being exacted by another person, and thus as
morally necessary. This extorsio can be considered a reason to act, but other
motives must occur along with it. These additional motives are occasionally “more
noble, known more truly, more clearly, more certainly” than mere external
coercion (BIP §57). By contrast, internal obligations can apply in the absence of
any external obligation, and the more apt one is to fulfill them, the less one
requires the presence of an external obligation (BIP §58). Furthermore,
Baumgarten distinguishes between external and internal moral laws, on the one
hand, and external and internal duties, on the other. External moral laws are those
“norms of free determinations that are to be exacted” (BIP §61). Accordingly, an
external duty refers to an action’s conforming to an external law (BIP §91). This
delimitation of external obligations, laws, and duties leads us to the domain of
natural right in a strict sense.
Ib
Natural Right in a Strict Sense and Ethics. As was common in the natural right
tradition, Baumgarten identifies the principles of right with the Ulpian formulae:
honeste vive, neminem laede, suum cuique tribue.⁷ In a first move, he introduces
the second classical command, “neminem laede.” Since every transgression of duty
⁶ Translation amended.
⁷ Natural right theorists commonly employed Ulpian’s formulae to explain the principles of
practical philosophy, but they disputed whether the first corresponds to a principle of right or of
ethics. In the Doctrine of Right, Kant holds that Ulpian’s commands correspond entirely to the
228
is called “wrong” <laesio>, and since natural right (strictly considered) deals
with external duties, its first domestic principle is: “you shall wrong nobody
(externally)” (BIP §92).⁸ Baumgarten then turns to the third Ulpian formula. He
maintains that “one’s own (what is mine, what is yours) is the collection of one’s
good” (BIP §93) and that these goods can be possessed through either internal or
external laws. If one does not attribute to someone else what is their own good,
one harms them and thus acts against a universal law of right. From this
Baumgarten infers that the precept “attribute to each (to a human being, nega-
tively at least) what is his own (with regard to right) can be established as the first
principle of the right of nature” (BIP §93). Finally, he discusses the first Ulpian
precept. If one acts according to the second and third principles of right,
i.e. does not harm anybody (externally) and attributes to each what is his own
(with regard to right), one lives honorably. Baumgarten concludes that “the
proposition live externally honourably [ . . . ] can be established as the first princi-
ple of the right of nature strictly considered” (BIP §94). These three commands are
presented as first, objective, domestic (i.e. belonging to the discipline alone)
principles of natural right, with no seeming preeminence given to any of them.⁹
Furthermore, Baumgarten argues that each of these moral precepts is not exclu-
sive to ius naturae in a strict sense but extends beyond it. Honeste vive, neminem
laede, and suum cuique tribue also hold in the case of internal moral laws, duties,
and obligations. They can therefore be regarded as principles of practical philos-
ophy or natural right, broadly speaking.
According to Baumgarten, the principles of right are not qualitatively different
from the principles of ethics. Rather, they are the same principles restricted to a
specific scope of application (the sphere of free actions that can be constrained by
others). His practical philosophy is devoid of a systematic principle capable of
drawing a clear distinction between right and ethics—or at least this was Kant’s
view, as recorded in the Vigilantius lecture notes: “the principia juris must be
sharply distinguished from the principia ethicis, which Baumgarten has neglected
to do, just as the determination of the supreme principle of distinction, which in
itself is very difficult, has never till now been worked out” (MSVig 27:359). We will
consider this criticism in Section III; before turning to Kant’s position, however,
we must first examine Achenwall’s notion of natural right.
principles of juridical duties. If we look at the fragments, lecture notes, and drafts of published works,
however, we see that Kant seems to have changed his mind when interpreting the first formula. In a
reflection from the pre-critical period (Refl 7078, 19:243), in the lecture notes Naturrecht Feyerabend
(NRFey 27:1336), Mrongovius II (MoM II 29: 631) and Vigilantius (MSVig 27:527, 587), and in the
drafts of the Doctrine of Virtue (AA 23:386), he presents the first command, “honeste vive,” as an ethical
duty and the second, “neminem laede,” as the first juridical duty.
⁸ Translation amended.
⁹ The principles of natural right trace back to the universal principle of practical philosophy “furnish
the good or seek perfection as much as you are able” (BIP §91), and all of them, in turn, to the
absolutely first objective principle that belongs to metaphysics (BIP §87). Cf. Scattola (2008, 261).
229
II
Achenwall. Achenwall bases his doctrine of natural right on Wolffian grounds, but
he introduces important conceptual changes that take him a step away from the
old ius naturae of the German Enlightenment (Schwaiger 2012, 87). Among other
innovations, he presents a clear distinction between the juridical and the ethical
domain—a distinction that is absent in Baumgarten—by analytically connecting
right and coercion.¹⁰ Like Wolff and many Wolffians, Achenwall characterizes
moral obligation as the connection of a motive with the necessity of an action
(AIN §7; APIN §12). In addition, his doctrine of natural right has the imperative
perfice te as its main principle, although it is combined with the precept of striving
for self-preservation and happiness (AIN §29; APIN §84). Moreover, in an
appendix to his Natural Right, Achenwall offers remarks on the history of natural
right, praising Wolff and Köhler for “shining an excellent light on the discipline”
(AIN Appendix, VII). His doctrine of natural right does not merely repeat
Wolffian arguments, however. In particular, Achenwall equates perfect or strict
right (in a subjective sense) not with a moral capacity to act, as Wolff and
Baumgarten do, but with a moral power to coerce. This, as I will argue next,
had a significant influence on Kant’s account of right.
IIa
Natural Right and Coercion. Achenwall’s Natural Right is devoted to natural right
in a strict sense, namely, to knowledge of external or perfect natural laws, rights,
and obligations. He distinguishes this doctrine from the collection of imperfect
natural laws and duties, which is called “ethics” or “moral philosophy, strictly
considered” (AIN §35).¹¹ In this way, he draws a distinction between right and
ethics that corresponds to the division between perfect and imperfect laws, as
many modern natural right theorists did before him. But then Achenwall goes on
to argue that a perfect obligation (expressed by a perfect law) is characterized by
being “connected to another man’s moral ability to coerce the violator” (AIN §34;
APIN §102). By contrast, imperfect obligations cannot be enforced. This moral
ability to coerce, corresponding to perfect obligations, is called “natural right.”
¹⁰ Klippel holds that the limitation of ius to perfect rights that are enforceable through coercion is a
feature of the “new” conception of German Naturrecht, which according to him appeared in the
textbooks on the discipline of the 1780s (2000, 77). As we will see, however, we can find this definition
of strict right in Achenwall, whose texts are from at least two decades earlier. It is possible that this
conceptual change, which according to Klippel took place in the 1780s, was facilitated by the reception
of Achenwall’s textbook, which was very popular at the time.
¹¹ Achenwall mentions that if we consider natural right in a broad sense, it coincides with moral
philosophy (also considered broadly) (AIN §26). Nevertheless, the text is centered on the discussion of
natural right in a strict sense.
230
This means that right and obligation are two sides of the same coin: “to every
perfect obligation on my part corresponds a strict natural right on someone else’s,
and vice versa, to every perfect right on my part corresponds a perfect obligation
on someone else’s” (AIN §36). Regarding the normative content of this juridical
relation, Achenwall holds that one’s primary obligation is to seek perfection, and
this includes the obligation to preserve one’s own life and body. Since the latter is
connected to a natural right to coerce others to refrain from committing acts that
hinder one’s preservation, it is a perfect obligation. This in turn means that others
have an obligation not to infringe upon one’s own life and body. Achenwall
concludes the argument by formulating the universal principle of right: “the
natural law Do not do things that go against another person’s preservation can be
called the internal, first, and adequate principle of the perfect laws” (AIN §36).
Achenwall’s position regarding the systematic division between perfect and
imperfect moral laws (or right and ethics) therefore rests on a new understanding
of the concept of right as a power to coerce—one that was absent, as far as I know,
in the Wolffian school of natural right.¹² Indeed, Baumgarten and Wolff conceive
of ius, in the subjective sense (i.e. considered as a potestas or facultas that human
beings have), as a mere capacity to act. In the Elements, Baumgarten defines right,
in the subjective sense, as a “moral faculty granted by laws strictly considered”
(BIP §64; cf. BIN §34). According to this, there is an obligation in the first place
(established by a strict natural law), from which, in the second place, follows a
right: insofar as we have an obligation to pursue an end, we have a right to the
means that are necessary to fulfill that obligation. Subjective right is therefore
conceived of as a moral capacity or power to act with a view to achieving the end
prescribed by the law of nature. Wolff explains this conceptual relationship
between right and obligation as follows: “the capacity, or moral faculty to do, or
to omit, something, is called right. From this it becomes clear that right arises from
the passive obligation, and that there would be no right if an obligation did not
exist; and also that, through the natural law, a right to any action without which
we could not comply with the natural obligation is given to us [ . . . ]. For it is
impossible that one can obtain an end without serving oneself of the means”
(WGNV §46). In the Prolegomena, Achenwall provides a general definition of right
(in a subjective sense) as “a man’s physical ability in as far as it does not go against
any moral law,” that is to say, “his moral ability” (APIN §44). This definition holds
for the whole domain of moral philosophy and retains Wolff ’s and Baumgarten’s
¹² A similar definition of ius in subjective sense can be found in Gottlieb Heineccius’s Elementa iuris
naturae et gentium: “and therefore the former species of obligation is called internal; the latter is called
external [ . . . ] right is the correlate (as it is called in the schools) to both. For if one person be under an
obligation, some other person has a right or capacity to exact something from him” (HIN, I.i.vii,
translation amended). Heineccius, a former pupil of Thomasius, was a well-known jurist and professor
of natural law. Achenwall attended Heineccius’s lectures while he was a student in Halle (cf. Schwaiger
2020, 342).
231
conception of ius as a moral ability to act according to the laws of nature. But
then he distinguishes between a perfect or strict right (taken subjectively) and an
imperfect right (§AIN 36; APIN §100). A perfect or strict right corresponds
to a perfect obligation and amounts to a moral ability to coerce. Therefore,
this concept belongs exclusively to the doctrine of natural right in a strict
sense. Accordingly, an imperfect right is a “moral ability that is given without
another man’s correlated perfect obligation” (APIN §100). This concept belongs
to ethics or moral philosophy in a strict sense, which, in turn, is defined as
“the knowledge of the imperfect natural laws” (AIN §35).
This definition of strict right as a moral capacity to coerce plays a significant
role in Kant’s doctrine of right. Following Achenwall, he argues that right,
subjectively considered, is a moral capacity to put others under obligations (MS
6:237) and limits the set of juridical duties to those that “correspond to rights of
another to coerce someone (facultas iuridica)” (MS 6:383). Nevertheless, and
despite his agreement with this formal or logical aspect of the relationship between
right and coercion, Kant rejects the foundations of Achenwall’s doctrine of ius
naturae. In the Feyerabend lecture notes, we read: “the author says that I am
bound by my nature to preserve my life; this would be the principle of right [ . . . ].
That is certainly not a juridical proposition. How does his self-preservation
concern me? I am required only not to resist his freedom” (NRFey 27:1334).
From a natural end, whether perfection or preservation, we cannot deduce (nor
justify) any obligation or the power to coerce (cf. AA 8:129). Right, as a rational
doctrine that deals with duties and obligations, must be founded on freedom and
its laws. Let us now examine Kant’s account of natural right more closely.
III
Kant. In the Metaphysics of Morals of 1797, Kant presents his definitive system of
moral philosophy, positioning right as one of the two branches of pure morals.
The old doctrine of ius naturae is now conceived as a metaphysical doctrine of
right, namely as a system of a priori principles through pure concepts, the object
of which is freedom of choice in its external use.¹³ This means that the principles
of right are part of the Sittenlehre but are restricted to the sphere of reciprocal
interactions between persons and to the form of coexistence of their actions,
leaving aside the end of their maxims (MS 6:230). It is on the basis of this notion
of external freedom, i.e. freedom concerning how human beings interact, and not
¹³ “What is metaphysics? The science of a priori principles through concepts, not constructed
through intuition . . . Duty and Right alone are concepts which concern freedom and its laws and do
not belong to nature like cause and effect . . . Thus every doctrine of Right must contain metaphysics”
(AA 23:135–6; my emphasis).
232
on the basis of some conception of human nature and its ends that our natural (i.e.
innate) right and natural (i.e. supra-positive) obligations are to be determined. In
what follows, I will first present Kant’s critique of previous models of natural right
(IIIa). I will then explore what Kant’s Doctrine of Right retains from them,
focusing on the problem of the distinction between right and ethics (IIIb).
IIIa
Kant’s Critique of Previous Models of Natural Right. We can identify three main
tenets separating Kant’s conception of right, at least regarding its foundations,
from the earlier tradition of natural right: (i) the identification of the Sittenlehre
with a doctrine of laws of freedom, (ii) the disassociation of the moral law from
natural ends, and (iii) the conception of reason as a source and ultimate ground of
the moral law. These conceptual changes brought forth by the Critical philosophy
in turn imply a clear rejection of the account of moral laws, shared in general by
natural right theorists, as laws known through reason that (i) are to be understood
in terms of laws of nature, (ii) are normatively connected to an end ascribed to
human nature, and (iii) have God as their author (see Tomassini 2018). Despite
their several differences, Baumgarten’s and Achenwall’s models of ius naturae fit
this schema, and, through the testimony of the lecture notes and Kant’s own
annotations to his copies of the textbooks, we can see how he engages with them.
IIIb
Laws of Nature as Laws of Freedom. When one begins to trace the notion of
Naturrecht (and the different terms related to it) in Kant’s moral philosophy, it is
immediately apparent that he does not refer to moral laws as laws of nature, although
he does understand them as laws of reason. Rather than constituting a mere termi-
nological shift, Kant’s reformulation of moral laws in terms of laws of freedom
reflects a new paradigm for thinking of moral obligation and its source (cf. Baum
2012, 114). In the Feyerabend lectures notes, we find the following passage:
¹⁴ Cf. MSVig 27:523–4: “since all obligation also rests on freedom itself, and has its ground therein
insofar as freedom is regarded under the condition whereby it can be a universal law, Professor Kant
calls all moral laws (i.e. those that lay down the condition under which a thing should happen, as
233
IIIc
Moral Law and Natural Ends. Kant dismantles the normative connection, present
in the natural right tradition, between natural ends and the moral law. He agrees
with the idea, rooted in Stoicism, that human beings have an end in virtue of their
nature. This end is happiness and “can be presupposed as actual in the case of all
rational beings,” as a “purpose that they not merely could have but [ . . . ] actually
do have by a natural necessity” (GMS 4:415). Rules that indicate how to pursue
happiness express the necessity of an action only in a conditional way, however,
and thus lack universal validity. This type of rule, which natural right theorists
considered a moral command of reason (i.e. a lex naturalis) is, from the perspec-
tive of the Critical philosophy, an imperative of prudence.
According to the students’ notes from his lectures on moral philosophy,
Kant describes the universal principles proposed by Baumgarten in terms of
opposed to leges naturae, physicae, which merely state the condition under which a thing does happen)
leges libertatis, laws of freedom, and includes thereunder the aforementioned leges justi et honesti
(ethicae).”
234
¹⁵ See also the Vigilantius lecture notes: “in his practical philosophy §§39–46, Baumgarten has put
forward various formulae which, as imperative, are supposed to serve for the general principle of all
obligation, though Professor Kant rejects every one of them” (MSVig 27:517ff.)
¹⁶ If the principle were to mean “live according to your rational nature,” it would still be tautological;
it would tell us “do your duty” without answering the question of how we ought to act (MSVig 27:518).
235
IIId
The Source of the Law. Kant believes that by locating the origin of the law in a will
other than one’s own, previous authors renounced the unconditional character
that a moral command must have (cf. GMS 4:433–4). He calls this capacity of
reason to find the law in itself, independently of external objects (including the
will of God), autonomy (GMS 4:440). This seminal thesis separates Kant’s moral
philosophy from the natural right tradition: moral laws do not have an external or
divine will as their ultimate source.
With regard to the source of obligation, Baumgarten and Achenwall not only
hold that the ground of moral laws lies in God’s reason, in line with classical
rationalism, but also conceive of God as the legislator of the law (cf. Bacin 2015,
26; Schwaiger 2020, 348f.). In the Elements, Baumgarten rejects Grotius’s famous
claim that the natural principles of justice would still be valid even if there were no
God (BIP §71). Baumgarten also affirms that natural right can be derived from the
will of God and argues that he is both the author of obligation and “the legislator of
natural law and the whole of the right of nature broadly considered” (BIP §100,
my emphasis). Furthermore, he argues that since natural laws are also divine
positive laws grounded in the will of God, the principle “act according to the
divine will” can be considered a universal principle of practical philosophy (BIP
§102). Like Baumgarten, Achenwall believes that to act according to natural laws
¹⁷ “The doctrine of this end [i.e. an end that is in itself a duty (FT)] would not belong to the doctrine
of right but rather to ethics, since self-constraint in accordance with (moral) laws belongs to the concept
of ethics alone. Ethics can also be defined as the system of the ends of pure practical reason. Ends and
duties distinguish the two divisions of the doctrine of morals in general” (MS 6:381).
236
is to act in accordance with the will of God (AIN §20; APIN §43, 60). Moreover, he
endorses the Pufendorfian definition of law as the command of a superior. Natural
laws, says Achenwall, “are made by the superior and obligating the subjects with
the threat of punishment [ . . . ] God thus is the legislator of all natural law, i.e. the
superior who is the creator of the juridical laws” (AIN §44).
As expected, in his lectures Kant rejects Baumgarten’s and Achenwall’s views
regarding the will of God as the ultimate ground of obligation. Interestingly, in the
Vigilantius lecture notes, he relates Baumgarten’s ideas to the voluntarist position
held by Crusius: “although the obligation is established by reason, it is nevertheless
assumed that in the performance of our duty we have to regard ourselves as
passive beings, and that another person must be present, who necessitates us to
duty. Crusius found this necessitating person in God, and Baumgarten likewise in
the divine will, albeit known through reason” (MSVig 27:510).¹⁸ And, according to
Feyerabend’s notes, when explaining the concept of right Kant rejects the identi-
fication of juridical with divine laws, as had been proposed in Achenwall’s
textbook: “here neither happiness nor a command of duty but freedom is the
cause of right. The author has grounded it in his Prolegomena by saying that it is a
divine law and that we would be made happy through it, but that is not needed
here at all” (NRFey 27:1329).¹⁹
In the lectures, Kant criticizes not only the idea that God is the legislator of the
laws of nature but also the thesis, shared by Baumgarten and Achenwall, that he is
their author. In fact, Kant rejects the notion that moral laws have an author
altogether. Only in the case of positive or statutory laws can we think of an auctor
legis, for these kinds of laws need to proceed from the will of the legislator in order
to obtain obligatory force; that is, they “become binding rules merely ex voluntate
superioris” (MSVig 27:546; cf. Refl 6771, 19:156). Since moral laws do not emanate
from a superior will in the first place, they need not have an author.
IIIe
Right and Ethics. Thus far, I have stressed that Kant’s enterprise of establishing a
metaphysics of morals entails a reformulation of the concept of ius naturae that
decisively breaks with the Wolffian tradition of natural right. However, Kant’s
mature and definitive system of pure moral philosophy, as developed in the text of
1797, has some continuities with this tradition. One of them is that the meta-
physics of morals preserves the view, found in Baumgarten and Achenwall, and
¹⁸ Cf. “Kant goes on to maintain, contra Baumgarten, that the moral law does not make it a
condition to acknowledge a God and assume that the laws are His commands” (MSVig 27:546).
Kant also denies the idea that moral laws have an author (MSVig 27:544).
¹⁹ Cf. “the author bases himself on the claim that obligation rests on divine command. But we have
already refuted that by claiming that it would be useless to refer here to God” (NRFey 27:1334).
237
²⁰ On the relationship between Kant’s idea of a metaphysics of morals and the philosophia practica
universalis, see Anderson (1923) and Schwaiger (2001).
238
²¹ In the Collins lecture notes, Kant gives the following example to explain Baumgarten’s position:
“but a person can be morally compelled from without by others, if another exacts from us, according to
moral motives, an action that we do with reluctance. If, for example, I am in debt to someone, and he
says: If you wish to be an honest man, you must pay me; I will not sue you, but I cannot let you off,
239
independent of ethical obligations and do not include any claims about our
reasons to act. Still, one can always comply with a juridical duty from the idea
of duty itself, turning this duty into an ethical one. This is why Kant holds that “all
duties, just because they are duties, belong to ethics” (MS 6:219). This does not
mean that the distinction between right and ethics is collapsed after all. Rather, it
indicates that the specificity of juridical duties rests not on their content (i.e. the
action prescribed or forbidden) but on “the difference in their lawgiving” or “the
kind of obligation” (MS 6:220). A duty is “that action to which someone is bound,”
“the matter of obligation, and there can be one and the same duty (as to the
action) although we can be bound to it in different ways” (MS 6:222). Juridical
duties thus express a particular way in which we are bound to an action: we ought
to perform (or omit) the relevant action, but we are not required to do so from a
specific motive. In sum, Kant flatly dismisses Baumgarten’s distinction between
ethical and juridical principles, finding in Achenwall’s Natural Right a key concept
for defining juridical duties and thus for distinguishing them from duties of virtue.
However, Kant’s division between right and ethics is also based on the claim that
juridical duties abstract from motives and ends. This claim is completely absent in
the Wolffian school of natural right and relates to Kant’s own reformulation of the
traditional idea of ius naturae.
IV
Conclusion. My aim in this chapter has been to shed light on the relationship
between Kant’s Doctrine of Right and the natural right tradition. I have argued
that Kant did not aim to “destroy” or reject the idea of ius naturae as such but
rather to provide the discipline with a completely new foundation. The whole
enterprise of establishing a rational doctrine of right cannot be abandoned, for
only principles based on reason alone, as Kant states in the Introduction to the
Doctrine of Right, can provide a moral justification of the power to coerce and a
normative standard by which to judge existing positive laws. By analyzing Kant’s
model of right in comparison with Baumgarten’s and Achenwall’s models, we
have reached a clearer picture of what he discards and what he retains from the
tradition of natural right. Kant agrees with them that there are laws of reason that
tell us how we ought to act, but he dismisses the identification of these laws with
laws of nature that are ultimately grounded in a divine will. I have also argued that
Kant’s moral philosophy preserves the view, found in Baumgarten and Achenwall,
that a rational doctrine of right belongs to a broader systematic doctrine (i.e. a
Sittenlehre) that, through its laws, regulates the internal and external sphere of
because I need it—then this is a moral compulsion from without, by the choice of another. The more a
man can compel himself, the freer he is. The less he can be compelled by others, the more inwardly free
he is” (MoC 27:269).
240
The Contemporary Inherent Right to Defense. The just war tradition is an ancient
and yet living body of thinking that tries to describe in what cases armed force
is morally permissible. As such, it opposes two other main tendencies—“war
realism,” as Michael Walzer terms the first (2015, 4), and pacifism. War realism
holds that expediency, i.e. the interest of the sovereign, alone justifies war, while
pacifism holds that nothing justifies it.¹ Where the first holds that war is excluded
from moral judgment and thus permits violence for victory, the second holds that
because war permits the violence necessary for victory, it is excluded by moral
judgment. Both paradoxically permit wars to be fought à outrance, as Anscombe
argues: the first explicitly so, because the taking of life by armed force needs no
justification beyond expediency; the second implicitly so, because it cannot dis-
tinguish between the taking of innocent life and the taking of any life and so in
practice allows any injustice to occur without any viable means for preventing or
resisting it (1961, 46–50). The just war tradition, to which Alexander Gottlieb
Baumgarten belongs, is the moderating position between these. In essence, it
argues against expediency on the grounds that war requires a moral justification,
and against pacifism on the grounds that wars can be necessary for justice.
Today’s understanding of the legality of war is largely captured by a hodge-
podge of international declarations, treaties, pacts, conventions, judgments, and
charters that comprise the international law of war, all of which determines a
rather restrictive right to go to war (ius ad bellum) and an equally restrictive right
to use force in war (ius in bello). Although there are countless agreements having
impact on the international legality of war, the two most recognized sources of law
with respect to war are the UN Charter, and the Geneva Conventions; the first
¹ Since pacifism is not the matter at stake here, I reduce it to absolute pacifism in the sense of
Anathagoras, Origin, Lactantius, and Menno Simons, ignoring the other sorts of pacifism such as selective
pacifism (e.g. Tertullian) and nuclear pacifism (e.g. Robert Drinan). John Howard Yoder has in fact
identified twenty distinct strains of pacifism (Friesen 2005, 357). Kant, lecturing on Baumgarten’s text,
pithily refers to pacifism as peace-loving, as opposed to peace-making (1997, 416; AA 27:686).
John Hymers, A Case Study of the Right of Nature: War, Violence, and Punishment in Baumgarten In: Baumgarten and
Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy. Edited by: Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, Oxford University Press.
© John Hymers 2024. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192873538.003.0014
242
governs the right to go to war (the ius ad bellum), and the second largely govern
what is right, or permitted, in war (the ius in bello).
Key to the UN Charter are article 2 (§4) and article 51. The former runs “All
Members shall refrain in their international relations from the threat or use of
force against the territorial integrity or political independence of any State, or in
any other manner inconsistent with the purposes of the United Nations”; whereas
the latter runs “Nothing in the present Charter shall impair the inherent right of
individual or collective self-defense if an armed attack occurs against a Member of
the United Nations.” Taken together, these two represent a rather restrictive ius ad
bellum. Article 2 (§4) follows the tradition’s attempt to end war as the sport of
kings,² which is to say along with Christian Wolff and Baumgarten, to stop the
right of war from becoming the license³ to war. With this article, aggression
officially becomes an international crime. But article 51 goes much further than
does article 2 (§4)—for article 51 expressly limits the just war to self-defense. This
limitation is famously already found in Immanuel Kant’s Perpetual Peace, a work
largely taken to have prefigured the United Nations.⁴ In this chapter I will
demonstrate that this limitation—i.e. that self-defense is the sole justifying cause
of war—is found prior to Kant in the works of Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten,
and thus that he is a hitherto unacknowledged father of the modern international
view of the ius ad bellum.
II
Punishment and the early modern just war tradition in Grotius and Wolff. Before
we consider Baumgarten’s role in the contemporary understanding of just war, we
² The first attestation of the sport of kings is not to horse racing but to war, and is found in the works
of William D’avenant. See his tragi-comedy The Just Italian: “Oh trivial property of life! Some do attend
the mighty war, and make divinity their yoke; ‘till for the sport of Kings the’ augment the number of the
dead” (1673, 454); see also his song “The souldier going to the Field”: “For I must go where lazy Peace, /
Will hide her drouzy head; / And, for the sport of Kings, encrease / The number of the Dead” (1673,
322; spelling not modernized).
³ Baumgarten defines license as “the state of a person for whom there are no external prescriptive
laws, and this is impossible <status licentiae est status hominis, cui nullae leges externae praescriptae
sunt, et est impossibilis>” (BIN §26). See also Wolff (WIG §630), Achenwall (§78), and Köhler
(KE §920).
⁴ The literature on Kant’s influence is legion, but Carl J. Friedrich’s “The Ideology of the United
Nations Charter and the Philosophy of Peace of Immanuel Kant 1795–1945” (Friedrich 1947) is its
fountainhead. For a far-too-brief reading list, cf. Franck 1995 (especially chapter 2), Musiał 2019,
Thorpe 2019, and Tesón 1992. Jochen Rauber 2009 notes that Kant’s name never appears in the official
records of the UN (2008, 50), but then argues both historically and philosophically for Kant’s paternity.
Nevertheless, carefully tracing Kant’s work, he concludes that the UN in its present form is a rather
imperfect version of Kant’s thinking. For instance, the Security Council essentially excuses five nations
from international censure, and non-democratic nations are equal members of the body alongside
democracies (2008, 76).Thus, he holds that Kant is rather the yardstick against which a cosmopolitan
order must be measured (2008, 76).
243
⁵ Baumgarten’s debt to Wolff is surely too well known to comment upon, and well explained
elsewhere in this volume.
⁶ The eminent British jurist J.L. Brierly tersely considers this opinion as common as it is spurious:
“Few books have won so great a reputation as the De iure belli ac pacis, but to regard its author as the
‘founder’ of international law is to exaggerate its originality and to do less than justice to the writers
who preceded him; neither Grotius, nor any other single writer, can properly be said to have ‘founded’
the system” (1963, 28); and again, on the supposed success of Grotius’s book, he writes “but if by
success is meant that the doctrines of Grotius as a whole were accepted by states and became part of the
law which since his time has regulated their relations, then his work was almost a complete failure”
(1963, 32). Rupp (1924) offers a comprehensive but condensed overview of the history of Grotius’s
reputation, and concludes nothing more than that he was “immensely popular and influential” because
he overcame the scholastic formulation dominating the field (365). Van Ittersum (2016) takes a
formulation typical of the early twenty-first century and considers his fame as founding father to be
a construct concocted by the American delegation to the 1899 Hague Peace Conference within an
imperialist and colonial context.
⁷ The Grotius literature, and that of the just war tradition in general, often but not exclusively
translates ius as “law,” and hence ius naturae and ius gentium as the law of nature and the law of
nations, but here will be translated as “right” not only to keep our vocabulary consistent but also to
delineate it clearly from “law,” i.e. lex, legis. See also the translator’s Introduction to BIP (28) for a
discussion of this difficult-to-translate term. Brierly simply says that the “law of nations” is a “mis-
translation” of ius gentium that has unfortunately become necessary (1963, 30).
244
⁸ “Societatis custodia, humano intellectui conveniens, fons est eius iuris, quod properie tali nomine
appellatur: quo pertinent alieni abstinentia et si quid alieni habeamus aut lucri inde fecerimus restitutio,
promissorum implendorum obligatio, damni culpa dati reparatio, et poenae inter homines meritum.”
⁹ For a fuller discussion that addresses Grotius’s Stoic influences, see Straumann’s thorough
“Oikeiosis and appetitus societas” (2003/2004).
¹⁰ The standard translation (Wolff 1934, 13 and passim) calls this the “supreme state,” but this
translation obscures that Wolff is clearly calling it maxima because of the size of the state: “The size of
a state is determined by the number of its citizens. Therefore, a greater state cannot be conceived <maior
itaque civitas concipi nequit> than that whose members are all nations in general, inasmuch as they
together include the whole human race” (WIG §10, zusatz), which is language oddly appropriated from
St Anselm’s ontological argument. Maxima is the superlative corresponding to maior. Köhler condition-
ally considers this paradigm a well-founded fiction and morally useful: “If in the law of nations and
society a society or an entire people is considered to be the same as a human individual, this is a possible
fiction, and it is formed with sufficient ground when it is constructed and arranged conformable to
human nature and other principles of reason, and such that, with its assistance, the natural right of
individuals can be applied to entire communities and nations <Si in jure sociali & Gentium consideretur
societas vel integer populus instar individui humani fictio hæc est possibilis & cum ratione sufficiente
formata cum illa naturæ humanæ & aliis principiis rationis convenienter sit concinnata & ita comparata
ut ope illius jus naturale singulorum ad integras societates & gentes applicari possit>” (KE §45).
245
War is a particular means that states have to enforce and protect what is their
own against harm. The first and most important distinction in war, think both
Grotius and Wolff, is that among private, public, and mixed¹¹ wars (GDIB Bk I,
Ch 3, Sect. 1, §1; WIG §607–9). Private war is the right granted to individuals in
the state of nature to redress a wrong, and both argue that it remains real even if it
is greatly attenuated by state structures. Public war, accordingly, is the manner
whereby the individual states in this greatest state obtain justice from one another,
and this precisely because there is no competent court found in this greatest state,
as there is any given state. Grotius begins his De Jure Belli ac Pacis (1625) by telling
us that war concerns those “disputes between peoples who are not bound by
common civil right” <controversiae eorum quos nulla iuris civilis tenet commu-
nio>” (GDIB Bk. 1, Ch. I, Sect. 1). It is for this reason that Grotius argues that
the laws are silent in war (Cicero’s famed “inter arma silent leges,” Pro Milone
4, 10; 1931, 16), provided that the silent law is restrictively understood as the
positive law summed up in the civil right of any given state; the natural laws
imposed by the right of nature in the form of the right of nations, and embodied
in its rights and obligations, still obtain (GDIBP prol. §26). Thus, in defining war
he explicitly widens the definition of Cicero, to whom he ascribes “contesting by
force <certationem per vim>”:¹² “war is the state of those as such who are
contending by force <bellum status per vim certantium qua tales sunt>” (GDIB
Bk. 1, Ch. I, Sect. 2, §1). By adding the notion of “state” to Cicero, as Wolff
argues, Grotius “improves <emendans>” Cicero in being more faithful to the
true nature of war, as this definition does not limit war to the action, i.e. the
fighting, but rather includes the entire condition of the peoples at war.¹³
¹¹ Mixed war is waged on one side by public authority and on the other by private individuals, and it
does not get much of a treatment in Grotius. Wolff says that the quashing of rebellion is a mixed war:
“an example of a war is when the leader of a state wages war against rebellious subordinates
<Exemplum belli mixti est si Rector civitatis bellum gerit cum subditis rebellibus>” (WIG §609,
Zusatz). A contemporary example is asymmetrical war, in which a state (a public authority) confronts
non-state actors (private actors), such as the just-ended American war in Afghanistan, or the non-
ending war on drugs. Köhler does not seem to address this tripartite distinction in his Exercitiones, and
Baumgarten notices this. In the fragmentary second part of his BIN, Baumgarten, remarking in his
commentary on Köhler’s KE §1646 concerning military occupation, notes: “Here we ask: whether the
term ‘occupation’ is correctly applied to the enemy and hostile objects, when they do not belong to
anyone. Private and public war must be distinguished <Hic quaeritur: an terminus, occupatio, recte
applicetur ad hosticum et res hostiles, cum nullius non sint. Distinguendum bellum privatum et
publicum” (BIN §1646).
¹² Cicero defines war in De Officiis as “contending by force”: “For there are two ways of contending:
one through discussion, and the other through force, and since the former is proper to the human
being, and the latter to beasts, we can only take refuge in the second if we cannot take advantage of the
better <Nam cum sint duo genera decertandi, unum per disceptationem, alterum per vim, cumque illud
proprium sit hominis, hoc beluarum, confugiendum est ad posterius, si uti non licet superior>” (De Off.
I:11; 1913, 36).
¹³ Wolff: “Enimvero loquendi usui convenientius, ut bellum sumatur non de actione, sed de statu”
(WIN 1, §1102). Köhler, on the other hand, has no obsession with the strictness of the definition, and
holds that war can be considered either in terms of the very act of contesting by force or in terms of the
state: “Sumitur bellum vel pro actu ipso certandi per vim vel pro statu” (KE §806, scholion 1). See also
Hobbes, who would famously connect this state with the state of nature in chapter 13 of his Leviathan
246
Moreover, Grotius’s new definition also moves war more in the direction
of Augustine, who holds that international relations are essentially a state of
war, and peace was just the name we give the relatively brief interlude between
contesting with arms.¹⁴ Wolff, though, likewise attempts to improve Grotius’s
definition by defining war as “the state of persons, in which one pursues
one’s right by force against another <status hominum in quo unus ius suum vi
persequitur adversus alterum bellum dicitur>” (WIN 1, §1102). Wolff holds that
Grotius’s definition, which Grotius himself claims covers all possible wars,
strangely lacks the notion of ius, and thus its absence in the definition seems
to be an important oversight.¹⁵ After all, for Grotius war is always waged in
pursuit of some right, whether real, imagined, or claimed. Wolff thus ties the
definition of war to the right of nature; for, since there is no right in common
between two peoples, as Grotius argues, beyond the right of nature, it is the
natural right that war attempts to ensure. This does not at all mean that Wolff
thinks that war is just by definition, which he begins to clarify in his definition
of the right of war: “the right of war is thus the right of pursuing one’s own
right against the one who does not wish to attribute it to us <Jus itaque belli eft
jus vi persequendi jus suum adversus eum qui idem nobis tribuere non vult>”
(WIN 1, §1103).
Since war thus has what Walzer calls a moral reality, which for Grotius and
Wolff is found in the right of nature, wars may thus be described as just or unjust
according to their causes. Grotius distinguishes between justifying causes (causae
iustificae) and utility (Wolff like Baumgarten will term the causes stemming from
of 1651: “Hereby it is manifest that during the time men live without a common power to keep them all
in awe, they are in that condition [conditionem] which is called war; and such a war as is a war of every
man against every man. For war consists not in battle only, or the act of fighting, but in a tract of time,
where the will to contend by battle is sufficiently known . . . so the nature of war consists not in actual
fighting, but in the known disposition to war during all the time there is no assurance to the contrary”
(1985, 102). The interpolation of conditionem comes from the later and revised Latin translation (1668,
64); conditio is clearly intended as a synonym for Grotius’s status. Köhler partially cites this passage in
KE §806, scholion 1: “Hobbius hac in re ita se explicat: consistit natura belli non in pugna sed in tractu
aliquo temporis quo durante voluntas armis decertandi est manisesta.”
¹⁴ Says Augustine in the City of God: “Such is the instability of human affairs that no people has ever
been allowed such a degree of tranquility as to remove all dread of hostile attacks on their dwelling in
this world. That place, then, which is promised as a dwelling of such peace and security is eternal, and is
reserved for eternal beings” (Augustine 1958, 17: 13). Hobbes likewise famously sees war as primary,
and peace as derived, for the quotation from Leviathan directly above ends: “All other time is peace,”
which has more punch in the Latin translation: “the time devoid of war is peace <tempus bello vacuum
pax est>” (Leviathan, Ch. XIII; 1668, 64). Kant agrees: “A state of peace among men living together is
not the same as the state of nature, which is a state of war” (1991, 98). Vivaldi stirringly set this thought
to music in his motet Nulla in mundo pax sincera sine felle (catalogued as RV 630). Baumgarten will
also define “external peace” in terms of war “the state opposite to war, i.e. the absence of war, is external
peace” (BIN Pr. §161).
¹⁵ Wolff: “By contesting, here he can only understand the prosecution of one’s own right. Whence
[Grotius’s] definition falls together with the one we give, even if ours is more perspicuous <Per
certationem hic intelligi nequit nisi persecutio juris sui. Unde haec definitio cum ea, quam dedimus
coincidit, etsi nostra sit magis perspicua>” (WIN I, §1102).
247
utility as rationes suasoriae, i.e. persuasive grounds):¹⁶ “let us now come to the
causes of war that I understand as justifying; for there are other causes that operate
on the ground of utility, which are sometimes distinct from those which operate
on the ground of what is just <veniamus ad causas bellorum: iustificas intelligo:
nam sunt & aliae quae mouent sub ratione utilis, distinctae interdum ab iis quae
mouent sub ratione iusti>” (GDIB Bk. 2, Ch. 1, Sec. 1, §1). Next follows his
historically definitive list of three justifying causes: “Most [authorities] establish
that there are three just causes for wars: defense, recuperation of property, and,
punishment <Plerique bellorum tres statuunt causas iustas, defensionem, recuper-
ationem rerum, & punitionem>” (GDIB Bk. 2, Ch. 1, Sect. 2, §2). Wolff mirrors
Grotius perfectly; he also follows a threefold justification of war, but he unites all
three reasons in one simple justifying ground: iniuria. Only “an injury that has
been, or is bound to be, done <iniuria facta vel facienda>” (WIG §§217, 219) is the
just ground for war. The first justification is (1) seeking after what is or ought to be
our own and has been lost due to injury, which is a vindictive war (WIG §620); (2)
the second is punishing the one who injures, which is a punitive war (WIG §616);
and (3) the third is resisting unjust force, i.e. injury, which is a defensive war (WIG
§615). The defensive war is just if the offensive war is unjust, but offensive war is
not unjust per se; Wolff sees both vindictive and punitive wars as offensive wars,
and they can be just if we have exhausted the Ciceronian injunction to employ all
peaceful options to obtain justice for what is or ought to be our own, or if armed
force alone is an appropriate punishment. Likewise, in the case of a justified
offensive war, the corresponding defensive war is unjust (WIG §629); unlike
with Vitoria, for instance, it is not possible to consider any war just on both
sides (WIG §633), nor, again contrary to Vitoria, does Wolff allow for invincible
ignorance in the case of waging war (WIG §635).¹⁷ As examples of punitive wars,
Wolff offers the punishment by arms for injuries to legates, or the war waged to
demand that a nation give up its idolatry (WIG §616, Zusatz). He considers the
first of these to be legitimate, but not the second; as he explains in WIG §§637 and
638, wickedness, impiety, idolatry, Deism, atheism, and the like fail the sole test
for justifying causes of punitive war: “punitive war is only permitted for the
one who has received irreparable harm and cannot obtain satisfaction for the
same in any other way <Bellum punitivum licitum non est nisi ei qui injuriam
¹⁶ Wolff adds a third category: quasi-justifying causes are causes that are labeled just but in fact are
unjust “when properly reasoned out” (WIG §624). A contemporary example would be Russia’s
preemptive de-Nazification of Ukraine, or perhaps the WMD supposedly concealed by Iraq.
¹⁷ Baumgarten will disagree with Wolff here; in BIN §132 he provides a list of conditions in which a
war can be seen as just on both sides (e.g. “one side may begin a war justly, continue it unjustly, and
perhaps end it justly, while the other begins unjustly, continues it justly, and perhaps ends it unjustly
<initia potest pars vna iuste caepisse continuans iniuste, iuste forsan finiens, altera incipiente iniuste
iuste continuante, finiente forsan iniuste>”), or unjust on both sides (e.g. “if internal justice of a certain
degree be denied to both belligerents <si iustitia interna certi maioris gradus vtrique belligerantium
parti denegetur>”). In the same paragraph, Baumgarten also allows for the invincible ignorance of
Vitoria. On invincible ignorance, see also BIP §187.
248
III
¹⁸ See AIN II §264: “And since a wrong is the only cause to justify war, a war is wrongful that is
waged on grounds of profit alone and on the basis of rhetorical arguments alone, since these are derived
from profit; or to persuade another nation to embrace our religion. Hence starting a war against a
nation because of idolatry, atheism and other crimes against God—a punitive war, as it is called—is
forbidden.”
¹⁹ The Ius Naturae is Baumgarten’s commentary on Köhler’s Exercitationes iuris naturalis.
Baumgarten completed the two-chapter prologue (BIN Pr. §1–167), and chapters 1 to 7 of part one
(BIN §1–156). He got as far as the first paragraph of part 1, chapter 8 (BIN §157), before ill health made
him abandon the work. All of the paragraphs after §157 are taken directly from Baumgarten’s notes,
and are undeveloped, uncorrected, and unchanged. Their numbers correspond directly with the
concerned paragraphs in Köhler. Heinrich Köhler was a Wolffian jurist, and Schwaiger points out
that Baumgarten made a number of pilgrimages from Halle to nearby Jena to attend his lectures in
person when teaching Wolff was still forbidden in Halle (2011, 117).
249
IV
Just war in the Sciagraphia. For Baumgarten, what is right in war, as opposed to
what happens in war, is governed by the right of nature. As we’ve seen, the right of
nature has three precepts: live honorably, do no harm to the other, and render to
each their own. Thus, a just war will follow these three precepts, and, as we will
see, Baumgarten permits no other concept of just war. However, in his Sciagraphia
(BSEP §208–12), Baumgarten does provide a brief and objective description of
international relations and war, which is the closest he comes to anything like a
Realpolitik. Hence, we begin with this account as it is the briefest, and furthest
removed from Baumgarten’s moral judgment of war.
²⁰ On the useful fiction, see note XXX above. In his treatment of the ius gentium in The Metaphysics
of Morals, Kant explicitly adopts the moral personhood of states (MS 6:343–4).
²¹ “Belli et pacis ius plerumque strictius est ius gentium. Latius si dicas ius complexum legum
externarum ius facultatem his concessam circa bellum quodcumque vel pacem externam versantia
naturale cum iure naturae stricte sumto coincidit. Principium adaequatum IN strictissime sumti erit
etiam principium iuris belli et pacis quatenus ad ius naturae strictissme sumtum pertinet.”
²² “Encyclopaedia philosophica . . . vel ita vt quis intendat quid in qualibet philosophiae parte et
quomodo sciri possit distincte cognoscere, et dici potest sciagraphia encyclopaediae philosophicae.”
250
A state’s public actions either “remain within the state <immanentes ciuitati>,”
and are called domestic; or they “cross over . . . to other states <transeuntes . . . erga
alias ciuitates>” and are called foreign.²³ The right of nations governs actions toward
the latter, and politics the former (BSEP §208). He identifies the “right of public
external war and peace <ius belli et pacis publicae externae>” with “polemical
politics, i.e. the irenical or the grounds for war <politica polemica s. ratio belli et
irenica>” (BSEP §208). Before war, polemical politics weighs the grounds for war;
Baumgarten does not here morally qualify such justifying, persuasive, and dissua-
sive reasons as he does in BIP §137 or BEP §190. The politicians (togata) consider
the ultimate ends of a declared war, and the generals (sagata) the more proximate
ends (i.e. strategy) (BSEP §209). He thus calls “public strategic right <ivs stratege-
ticum publicum>” “the complex of external laws that are to be observed against an
enemy itself ” (BSEP §209). For war leaders, both right and strategic prudence
provides for the right and prudence of building fortifications and other battle
tactics²⁴ (BESP §210), as well as for the right and prudence of blockades (obsidio)
and sieges (poliorcetica) (BESP §211). Finally, the class (status) of those citizens
especially intending external public security is that of the military, and the right and
public politics furnishing the laws of the military class are military, which is not to
be confused with the right of war and the polemical politics of nations.
Lest someone doubt the difference between ethics and economics and politics,
one should attend to the different states and the difference will be clear. For since
economics is the science of the internal obligations of a person in the family state,
and politics is the science of the same in the civil state, the difference is already
clear. Ethics says ‘worship God’ and indeed from the principle ‘perfect yourself,’
²³ Domestic and foreign events are rendered by the classic formulation “res domi forisque
gerendae”—literally, “the affairs that are to be conducted at home and abroad.”
²⁴ In BESP §129, Baumgarten, following an ancient practice, reserves the word “tactics” for the
science of deploying soldiers: i.e. “the science of forming battle lines <hoc nomen scientiae aciem
bellicam constituendi iam proprium est ab antiquis>.”
251
without respect to any other particular state but rather, as much as by abstracting
from every particular society I can be considered in the natural state; and
economics teaches the same as well, but thus ‘worship God as a member of a
family,’ and so too politics, but ‘as a member of a civil state.’ (BVEEP §1)²⁵
That is, each branch deals with the same natural law imperative (here: worship
God) within its own realm. So, by extension the art of the ius gentium, which we
might call statecraft, is the art of guiding a nation within that which Wolff calls the
“greatest state,” and concerns the right of nature as it applies to the individual
states. It teaches the same thing as ethics (the fitting imperative here is “be
peaceable”), but in a different realm. Thus, in the BEP, Baumgarten’s just war
doctrine then takes on a much more personal tone, calling for individuals to avoid
war—were sovereigns to follow his doctrine in the BEP, they would do so
according to the dictates of the right of nature, the laws that bind all persons as
persons, and not according to the expediency of politics or national interest—that
is, without concern for statecraft. For ethics concerns the state of nature, and there
are no sovereigns to be found there.²⁶
Baumgarten’s ethics depends on a Wolffian framework of perfectionism. In
brief, for Baumgarten, ethics is the internal obligation to bring about some sort of
perfection. In the Ethica, there is a two-fold specification of perfection: first with
regard to perfect yourself (perfice te) understood in terms of duties toward God
and then toward oneself strictly speaking,²⁷ and second with regard to other
things. Any perfection is to be understood as the successful unity of the various
predicates that determine the ground of a given thing (BM §94), so as to achieve a
harmony in that being that is to be perfected by these essential and grounding
predicates (either the self, or the other, and thus of course their nexus). In the
sense that either something belonging to the self, or to something else, is to be
perfected, both of these poles thus alternately constitute what Baumgarten calls
²⁵ “Ne quis dubitet de discrimine Ethices ab Oeconomica et Politica, attendat modo varios status, et
differentia patebit. Oeconomica enim quum sit scientia obligationum internarum hominis in statu
familiae; et Politica scientia earundem in statu ciuili, discrimen iam adest. Sic Ethica dicit: Cole
Deum: et qui dem ex principio, Perfice Te, sine respetu ad ullum unquam statum peculiarem, sed potius,
quantum ab omni societate peculiari abstrahendo, in statu naturali considerari possum; praecipit et hoc
oeconomica, sed ita: cole Deum, ut membrum familiae, sic et Politica; ut membrum civitatis.”
²⁶ See Kant in Perpetual Peace: “After all, war is only a regrettable expedient for asserting one’s rights
by force within a state of nature, where no court of justice is available to judge with legal authority.”
²⁷ Although the first part, General Ethics, concerns three species of duties (Religion, self, and other),
Baumgarten is clear that God is not a determining ground of perfection in ethics, as God cannot be
perfected: “the glory of God posits a reality in you . . . Therefore religion perfects you as an end” (BEP
§11). The determining ground of perfection in religion remains one’s own perfection, of which the
glory of God (i.e. religion) is one grounding element and is necessary for blessedness, which in turn is
necessary for, but not sufficient, for happiness. The distinction between religion and the self is found
therein that in the first, religion posits realities in you that are to be perfected (e.g. your knowledge and
worship of God), whereas in the second this positing occurs through the obligations to one’s own soul
(e.g. cultivating the intellect or perfecting sensitive desire), body (e.g. health), or external state
(e.g. labor).
252
the “determining ground of perfection.” The first two chapters of the general
ethics concern the duties to religion and the self, while the third chapter concerns
the duties to “external things.” Baumgarten locates his ethical treatment of just
war in this third chapter. The first and most general duty of the third chapter is to
universal love, which is, as the general love of the best, the eagerness for the best
possible world (BEP §302). The best possible world clearly involves other people,
so this duty quickly leads to a second duty toward others, which is the universal
love for other people, or panphilia (§§304–14). Panphilia intrinsically implies
friendship, and thus the avoidance of enmity (BEP §313). This then in turn
leads to the duty toward peace, which is the locus of his discussion of just war
within the Ethica.
Thus, following the irenic pattern established by Plato, Cicero, Augustine, and
Thomas Aquinas, in answer to the realist paradigm, Baumgarten frames his just
war theory within the framework of love and peace. Yet, his definition of war in no
way mirrors Cicero, Grotius, or Wolff, who all stress contending by force. Rather,
his definition is closer to his Jena-master Köhler, who had defined war as “the state
of persons who are mutually engaged in an efficacious attempt to inflict evil
on one another <bellum est status hominum qui conatu efficaci sibi invicem
inferendi mala feruntur>” (KE §806). Accordingly, Baumgarten’s first definition
of war runs “the state in which one party has resolved to inflict evil on the other
<inimicitia externa hostilitas et bellum quum sit status hominum quo alter alteri
malum inferre decernit>” (BEP §315, cf. note 21 on p. 185 of the translation,
Baumgarten 2024). However, Baumgarten had revised this definition for the
second and third editions: “external enmity, i.e. hostility and war, is the state of
persons in which one party has declared a resolution of inflicting evil on the other”
(§315).²⁸ This emendation is important as it lines up with Cicero’s insistence that
war be competently declared (De rep. 3:23; 1928, 212). This definition bristles with
technicalities. First, Baumgarten sees war as inflicting evil. Evil is a limitation on
finite reality, which is either necessary, i.e. metaphysical, and involves definition
(e.g. to be a mother is not to be a father), or it is contingent (e.g. a physical
privation like being blind, or a moral privation like murder); cf. BM §§146
and 778. But evil is not the same as harm, which is when a person derogates
one’s own duty to another. Harm is for Baumgarten the only thing that will justify
war, which he will not explain until BIN §144; in BEP §319 Baumgarten indeed
²⁸ In the 2nd and 3rd editions of BEP §315, the Latin of this definition runs “inimicitia externa,
hostilitas et bellum, [est] status hominum quo alter alteri malum inferendi declaratum decretum
habent.” This later formulation closely echoes that found previously in Achenwall: “a declared
statement of inflicting force on the other is called hostility <Propositum declaratum alteri vim inferendi
hostilitas; et is cui est tale propositum hostis nuncupatur>” (AIN I §263). Baumgarten’s most complete
definition runs: “war (hostility, external enmity) is the state of persons within which each party has
declared the resolution of inflicting evils on the other <Bellum (hostilitas, inimicitia externa) est status
hominum quo alter alteri mala inferendi declaratum vterque decretum habent>” (BIN Pr. §161,
emphasis added), a superior definition as it introduces the idea of mutuality.
253
exhorts us not to give another the justifying cause of war through harm, but he
never limits harm to the sole justifying cause in that work. Although one is
absolutely obligated to avoid harm, at the same time one can in fact have a
duty to an evil. The latter is covered by Baumgarten’s doctrine of abnegation
(BEP §§238f), whereby one has a duty to an evil that will impede a greater evil,
such as unpleasant medicine for the sake of avoiding a worse illness. Hence for
Baumgarten war is fundamentally an evil that may even be necessary, even
morally so, and is not for that reason something that can be avoided in principle
as pacifism would have it. But war is not by definition harm, again contrary to
pacifism. This is the sense in which Plato, Cicero, Ambrose, and Augustine see
war: as a regrettable way of winning a better peace.
Baumgarten contrasts this definition of war with friendship: “external friends
will be those among whom there is no hostility” (BEP §315). An important, in fact
guiding, distinction within the Initia and the Ethica is that between internal and
external. Roughly, internal has to do with one’s own self as the determining
ground of perfection, and external with the other as the determining ground of
perfection. That is: internal duties involve perfecting oneself, and external duties
both perfecting others and perfecting one’s own nexus with others. In this context,
peace means nothing more than the absence of hostility, which, as we have seen,
Baumgarten terms “external friendship” (BEP §315), as opposed to the higher
perfection of mutual internal friendship, which is when two parties mutually
admire the perfections of each other. Thus, external peace is simply enough love
(i.e. admiration of perfection, BEP §308) to avert hostility, and does not require
any inner conversion. For Baumgarten, we have a duty to this external perfection,
a duty to be peaceful, and to effect peace, as it is a perfection, since we have a duty
to seek perfection in all things, both internally and externally (BEP §301). As such,
the human has a duty to be a pacificus, a peacemaker; consequently, the human
has a duty to being a mediator insofar as it is possible (BEP §315), which is to
say, to encourage and maintain peace among others, not just between oneself
and others.
Being a peacemaker means to eschew harming anyone. The specific duty here
follows from the right of nature, whose premise is the duty to give each one’s own
(BIP §93). Hence, to harm someone is to transgress this duty to give each one’s
own: “ ‘in the natural state, harm nobody externally’ is the first principle of the
whole of the right of nature” (BEP §316). This duty leads to the virtues of justice
and innocence. Justice is when one actually attributes to each one’s own (BEP
§317), and innocence is the bearing whereby one harms nobody (BEP §319). Since
harm is the only justifying cause of war, innocence likewise demands that one
avoid providing the pretext for war by harming others, either internally or
externally. Innocence, though, must not be confused with naivety (“simplicity in
a bad sense,” BEP §319). Baumgarten accordingly defines injury as an evil emer-
ging from harm (BEP §320). Hence, if one injures another, one is obligated
254
Leniency, when it is compelled to repel injuries by itself, and this without force,
can be sufficiently furnished with very stern means and does not descend to
force: if force is necessary, an enemy is made, an external foe (BEP §§324, 315);
it prevents, defends, and avenges strenuously but not violently <vehementer>
(BM §699) with internal enmity (BEP §314), not only within (externally) just but
also (internally) fair limits (BEP §§324, 315), and also from within internal
255
innocence (BEP §319), the flight from satisfying one’s own vindictiveness (BEP
§322), and gentleness (BEP §323) in the midst of arms, and indeed always having
peace in mind (BEP §315). (BEP §326)
As we will see in BIN, Baumgarten will explain each of these three actions
(prevention, defense, and avenging) as some form of defense. But let us notice
in anticipation that this trio is not isomorphic with those of Grotius and Wolff.
In sum: we are obligated to leniency (lenitas), which for Baumgarten is the
perfection comprising innocence, gentleness, mildness, and placability (BEP
§327). This is even more the case when our enemy is drawn to harm us due to
the “privilege of necessity,” which is to say along with Achenwall, when the
aggressor “has a certain moral ability to ignore a perfect duty in order not to
perish” (APIN §145).
VI
Just war in BIN. As we saw above, Wolff had claimed that the only justifying cause
of war is iniuria; Baumgarten sees it in laesio. The distinction is purely verbal for
Baumgarten’s Jena-master Köhler: his Exercitationes repeats the phrase injuria vel
laesio here and there, and the index entry for iniuria begins “see laesio.”
Baumgarten agrees, defining “iniuria” in its widest sense as “any sort of harm
<iniuria latissime est laesio quaecunque>” (BIN §112), and laesio as “that which is
opposed to a duty toward somebody <laesio est oppositum officii erga aliquem>,”
where “somebody” is defined as “God, myself, or another person” (BIN §148).
Baumgarten thus formulates the ius laesi, “a right of the harmed,” which is to
“extort reparation” from the one who harms (BIN §123). Whoever has a right to
the end has a right to the means (remedia) (BIN §126). Complete means are those
that are proportionate, i.e. they are as great as is necessary to achieve the end (i.e.
reparation) (BIN §128). Proportionate means are just, even if they are very harsh;
but they may not be harsher than what is required to obtain the end (BIN §130).
Baumgarten like Grotius and Wolff also sees three just cases for war, but he
explicitly refines Wolff ’s bipartite structure of a past inuria facta and future
iniuria facienda into a more complete temporal structure: “Since only harm to
oneself is a justifying cause for a war that is to be taken up by you, and since, like
all actual things in this universe, this harm however can be present, future, or past:
hence there is a threefold justifying cause of war” (BIN §144).²⁹ This is an
innovation, since Köhler like Wolff gives a two-fold temporality: “since harm is
either present or future, i.e. imminent, we conceive of a two-fold cause of just war
²⁹ “Sola laesio tui quum belli sit caussa iustifica a te suscipiendi haec autem vt actualia huius vniuersi
omnia vel praesens sit vel futura vel praeterita triplex hinc enascitur belli caussa iustifica.”
256
(§1092), which is to say, suffering a harm that either has been inflicted upon us or
is still to be, i.e. one that is imminent” (KE §1109).³⁰ Before we turn to the
temporality, let us first note here that Baumgarten writes laesio tui, which goes
further than Köhler, who writes “harm is the justifying cause of war <laesio sit
causa belli justifica>” (KE, Diss. Prol. §29),³¹ and Achenwall, who likewise writes
“only a harm is a justifying cause of coercion <sola laesio est caussa iustifica
coactionis>” (AIN I, §260; 2020, 93).³² These two both consider laesio simpliciter
as opposed to Baumgarten’s more restricted laesio tui as a justifiable cause. The
consequences of the tui are rather large for Baumgarten; since only harm to
oneself justifies a war, it strictly follows that a harm to others alone does not
justify the taking up of arms: “in this same sense, a war taken up only on behalf of
others constituted in this state together with you is not just, or, at any rate,
mercenary war on behalf of those whom you judge are unjustly waging war”
(BIN §133).³³ Baumgarten’s tui also bans harms against God as a causa iustifica;
thus, like Wolff, his tui bars Grotius’s wars against impiety.
As harm to oneself is the only justifying cause of war, the only just form of war
for Baumgarten is repelling such, which he calls defense. The whole point of
defense is the state of security: “We bring ourselves to the state of security with
regard to someone else if we have activated as many and as great physical
impediments to the harm that he will attempt against us such that it is morally
³⁰ “Cum laesio vel praesens vel futura seu imminens sit, duplicem concipiemus causam belli justificam
(§1092), nimirum laesionem vel illatam vel adhuc nobis perferendam seu imminentem.” Note that
Köhler is ambiguous, slipping between the present (laesio praesens) and the past (laesionem . . . illatam).
This an ambiguity that Baumgarten cleans up.
³¹ In KE §1092, Köhler makes clear that harm is the only justifying cause: “There can therefore be no
other just cause for undertaking war than violation of one’s own (§1091). Now, since a violation of this
kind is called a harm or injury, injury strictly considered alone is the justifying cause of war, i.e. that
cause which causes a war to be taken as just <Causa itaque justa belli suscipiendi nulla esse alia potest
nisi violatio του suum cuique (§1091). Jam cum violatio ejusmodi dicatur læsio seu injuria (§764), causa
belli justifica, quæ efficit, ut bellum habeatur pro justo, sola læsio stricte dicta est>.”
³² The closest I am aware of that Achenwall comes to defining war is “since a nation is a free person,
a nation in a just war has the right to all the coercive means necessary to achieve its right <Quum gens
sit persona libera; genti in bello iusto ius competit in omnia media coactiua, sine quibus ius suum
consequit nequit>” (AIN IV §269; 2020, 197; translation altered here and above to preserve the
vocabulary of the present chapter); the index gives this paragraph as the definition of war. Hence
war is the coercive means for achieving one’s right.
³³ “iustum in eodem non eft hoc significatu susceptum tantum pro aliis tecum in hoc statu constitutis
aut omnino mercenarium pro talibus, quos iniuste bellantes autumas.” Baumgarten’s pro aliis tecum in
hoc statu constitutis indicates a “common harm <communis laesio>” suffered by two or more parties, a
concept which is not found in KE §1092, which BIN §133 glosses. Nevertheless, in his own gloss on KE
§1092, Köhler says that communis laesio is “a common justifying cause of war <communis causa belli
iustifica>” (Köhler 1738, ad §1092, p. 113). Secondly, the brief passage on mercenaries leaves open the
question of whether or not Baumgarten accepts a mercenary war fought on behalf of a just belligerent.
Wolff dedicates a number of paragraphs to the law of mercenary warfare (WIG §765–8), but neither
Köhler nor Achenwall take up the issue of mercenaries, and this is the sole reference in Baumgarten.
Mercenaries are only mentioned in passing in Grotius, but Van Der Mandere suggests that this is
because those are the only soldiers with which Grotius was familiar (1925, 442). In his Perpetual Peace,
Kant speaks lowly of mercenaries, whom he would ban as surely as he did standing armies.
257
certain that he will not be harmful” (BIN §124).³⁴ Thus, his threefold system of
temporal justification also delivers a three-fold temporal typology of just war,
which remains solely defensive:
There is an innate right of self-defense, even extortive or violent, for every person
in the natural state against the harm-doer, but not against just anyone who causes
offense. The harm-doer, and so too the offender, consists either in a past harm or
offense, and the defense undertaken against such is called vengeance, which is
not to be confused with vindictiveness; or again consists in a present harm or
offense, and the defense undertaken against such is called defense most strictly
considered; or again consists in a future harm or offense, and the defense
undertaken against such is called prevention. (BIN §149)³⁵
In the first form of defense, i.e. vengeance, we see Baumgarten’s attempt to clean
up an ambiguity in Cicero’s use of vltio which we will see below when we discuss
punishment. For Baumgarten, vengeance (vltio) has the rather restricted meaning
of only “extorting reparation” (BEP §324); in BIN §50, Baumgarten will say
“reparation is the act of adding to what is my own that which the one who
harms had subtracted,” which is consonant with the mathematical strain of his
ethics.³⁶ Reparation is understood in two ways: either as restitution, which is when
the same thing that has been lost is returned, or as satisfaction, which is when the
value of that which has been lost is returned in full (BIN §51).³⁷ This indeed
reflects the classic Roman virtue as extolled by Cicero; a war should seek no more
than to regain what is lost (cf. the repetitis rebus of De Off. 1:36).³⁸ Köhler makes
the standard argument that the right of reparation is “goes to infinity <in
infinitum>,” a legal term which here means that something cannot be determined
in advance, and lasts “until satisfaction has been made for the damage inflicted
<donec ipsi ratione damni illati satisfactum fuerit>” (KE §1079). Baumgarten
³⁴ “In statum plenariae securitatis nos erga hominem redegimus si tot ac tanta impedimenta physica
laesionis ab ipso contra nos tentandae actuauimus vt eum non laesurum moraliter certum fit.” This state
of security toward persons is clearly not the same as the state of security toward God, as described in
BEP §437, which is when a sinner acts with a sense of impunity.
³⁵ “Ius est cuiuis homini connatum in statu naturali defensionis etiam extorquentis etiam violentae
contra laesorem quemcunque non contra offensorem quemcunque. Laesor et offensor nunc est ex laesione
vel offensione praeterita, contra quem suscepta defensio dicitur vltio, non confundenda cum vindicta,
nunc ex praesenti, contra quem suscepta defensio dicitur defensio strictissime dicta, nunc ex futura
contra quem suscepta defensio dicitur praeuentio.”
³⁶ On the mathematical nature of Baumgarten’s thinking in general, see Heidegger (2010, 42–5); see
also my introduction to the translation of the BEP (p. 2), and also note c thereto. See also Buchenau’s
chapter 2 in this volume.
³⁷ “Idem, quod reparando redditur, vel est prorsus idem, tunc reparatio est restititio, vel idem respectu
pretii, s. aesquipollens, et haec reparatio est satisfactio.”
³⁸ Cicero’s sense of justice was particularly offended for instance by Caesar’s treatment of Massilia
(modern Marseilles) and the Aduatuci in that Caesar sought gain and conquest and thus exceeded any
idea of vltio (see Lockwood 2022).
258
qualifies Köhler’s infinite right, in some detail: “the right of the injured to extort
reparation, (§54) is given to him infinitely, which is to be understood as indefinite
in the natural state, because it weighs (1) the amount of damage, and hence (2) the
amount and (3) manner (§57) of the reparation (§50) to be assessed, (4) and the
manner, place, and time of restitution, which is defined and determined by
external law, and no one beyond the injured party accordingly has the right to
be able to compel someone’s acquiescence by extortion” (BIN §123).³⁹ “Thus,”
says Baumgarten, “let nobody dream that the right of the injured against the
harm-doer is either really infinite, or at least that the use of the same would be
defined and limited by no counsel of conscience” (BIN §123).⁴⁰ Note that this
passage again stresses that one can only defend against harms to oneself.
The second case of just war, which is against present harm, is “defense most
strictly considered” (BIN §149). Typically, Baumgarten gives a layered definition
of defense, ranging from the broadest to the strictest. Defense most broadly
speaking is “the endeavor (1) to hold onto what is good and (2) to repel what is
evil,” i.e. “taking precautions against evils” (BIN §145). More broadly speaking, it
is an “action against another person that repels evils” but more strictly speaking
defense “repels harms.”⁴¹ And thus when an action is taken to repel present harm,
as opposed to past or future harm, and certainly harm but not mere offense, we
have defense most strictly spoken.
Likewise, the third and last form of just war is also a form of defense: preven-
tion. Its temporal ekstase has its own particular difficulty, as unlike a harm that has
occurred, or one that is occurring, it is merely one that is to occur. But that it is to
occur does not imply that it will certainly occur, and hence future harm can only
be judged according to probability. Just as it is wrong to defend oneself against
those who have not harmed, or are not harming, it is also wrong to defend against
those who will not in fact harm (BIN §151). Thus, as the BIP stipulates concerning
imputation of deed, we must apply the fitting degree of probability, and hence
must thus be “moral certainty,” which today we understand under the formula
“beyond reasonable doubt” (BIP §143; see also notes 261 and 262 thereto in the
translation, Baumgarten 2024). “Although it can never be completely certain that
one person will hurt another in the future, the harm, be it either imminent or not,
can be truly and genuinely probable, and through various degrees of certain
³⁹ “Laesi ius extorquendi reparationem, (§54) illi tribuitur in infinitum, quod intelligas indefinitum in
statu naturali, quia (1) quantum damni , et hinc pendens (2) quantum reparationis (§50) taxandi, (3)
huius modum (§57), (4) reposcendi modum, locum, tempus externo iure definiendi, determinandique
nemo ius extra laesum ita habet, vt ipsum ad acquiescendum extorquendo compellere possit (§§22, 23).”
⁴⁰ “Ne quis ergo hinc somniet ius laesi contra laesorem vel realiter infinitum vel saltim nullis
conscientiae consiliis definiendum et circumscribendum eiusdem vsum.”
⁴¹ The final chapter in the published work is “The Right of Defense Most Strictly Considered,” but,
as noted above, he was not able to go beyond the first paragraph (§157) before ill health intervened. BIN
§157 comments on K §1116; there Köhler is interested in allowing the defender, whom he defines as
“the one who will be harmed <laedendus>,” the right of proportionate violent response. On violence,
see below.
259
futurity, as long as it is morally certain to the one who will defend; this grants the
right of prevention to this person” (BIN §153).⁴² Hence, it is not defense more
strictly considered to inflict force on those concerning whose harmfulness one
finds, or should find, dubious, or improbable, and thus such prevention is unjust
(BIN §154).⁴³ And finally, even though any preventive act of defense comes before
the harm, Baumgarten still considers the future aggressive act to be the shot across
the bow:
For those who are morally certain about it in the state of nature, there is a right of
prevention against a future harm to oneself, even extortive, violent, or hostile (§150).
Now, the first harm, i.e. the first act of aggression more strictly speaking or the
first hostility that will cause harm is the future harm; therefore, it is what grants the
right of prevention more strictly speaking to those morally certain about the same in
the state of nature, that is, the right of defense before the first harm. (BIN §156)⁴⁴
⁴² “Laesio hominis in hominem futura quum nequeat vnquam esse complete certa, possit esse
probabilis vero et genuino significatu, variosque per gradus moraliter certae futuritionis siue sit haec
imminens siue minus modo sit certa moraliter defensuro huic dat ius praeuentionis.” Wolff too warns us
against considering an injury imminent on the grounds that it is not impossible: “Etenim iniuria
nondum spectari potest ut facienda quia non impossibilis” (WIG §640, Zusatz).
⁴³ “Vis illata illi de quo dubium aut improbabile est eum esse laesurum non est iusta defensio strictius
dicta hinc nec iusta praeuentio.”
⁴⁴ “Contra laesionem sui futuram de eodem <sic> moraliter certis in statu naturali ius est praeuentionis,
etiam extorquentis, etiam violentae, etiam hostilis. lam prima laesio primus aggressionis strictius dictae
actus, prima laesura hostilitas est laesio futura, ergo de eadem moraliter certis in statu naturali dat ius
praeuentionis strictius dictum quod est ius defensionis ante primam laesionem.” Reading eodem as eadem.
⁴⁵ “Sola caussa belli iustifica eft defensio strictius dicta iusta, vel vltio vel defensio strictissime dicta vel
praeuentio.”
⁴⁶ Achenwall never thematizes defense as the sole just cause: “Thus violence is licit and war is
rightful if its aim is indemnity, self-defense, security for the present and for the future, §267, 271. The
rightfulness of war is thus extended in the strictest sense as far as the rights to indemnity, self-defense
and security reach” (AIN I §272).
260
defense can be unjust, which is when it repels offense most simply speaking, or an
attacking force but one that does no harm, and repels harm with the harshest
force, whereas it is always just when it uses the “mildest of the most proportionate
means for averting harm <remediorum proportionatorum ad auertendam laesio-
nem mititissimum>” (BIN §147).⁴⁷ He is here clarifying Köhler’s claim: “If there-
fore, we endeavor to inflict violent evil on another with the intention of being able
to avert an imminent harm to ourselves, we are said to defend, insofar as this term
is taken most strictly” (KE §1111).⁴⁸ Baumgarten clearly explicates Köhler’s
term violentia as just when force is proportionately arrayed against harm. One
looks in vain for any definition of violentia, and likewise its adjective violentus,
in Grotius,⁴⁹ Wolff, Köhler, and Achenwall, although none shy away from using it
uncritically according to its common usage.⁵⁰ Perhaps Achenwall’s use best
sums up the word’s ambiguous literary reception in this tradition: “now if one
of two parties uses violence <violentiam> and the other tries to avert it with force
<vi> . . .” (AIN I §264).⁵¹ Achenwall, like the tradition before him, clearly takes
violence as a synonym for force. However, we saw that above in BEP §326,
Baumgarten explicitly rejects violence—but not force—as belonging to just war.
Baumgarten in fact is unique in offering a distinction between violence, i.e.
violentia, and force, i.e. vis.⁵² He scarcely uses the term violence, clearly finding it
unsatisfactory. Although he indeed used violentia in the first three editions of the
BM, he programmatically replaced it with coactio, “constraint,” as of the fourth
⁴⁷ See Wolff, who, in his Institutiones iuris naturae et gentium, had limited force in the following
manner: “and since war is waged for the purpose of protecting and obtaining one’s right, in war it is
permissible to use as much force as is required for the achievement of one’s right and to overcome
resistance by just force. And in this way the lawful acts in war are distinguished from the unlawful <Et
cum bellum geratur juris sui tuendi ac consequendi causa; in bello tanta vi uti licet quanta ad
consecutionem juris sui & superandam resistentiam vi justa factam requiritur. Et hoc modo actus in
bello liciti ab illicitis distinguuntur>” (Wolff 1754, §159).
⁴⁸ “Si alteri nos laesuro malum violentum eo animo connitamur ut laesionem imminentem a nobis
avertere possimus nos defendere dicimur quatenus hic terminus arctius sumatur.”
⁴⁹ Grotius at least twice defines vis, force, as taking the law into one’s own hands, which he notes is
forbidden by civil law (e.g. GDIB Bk 1, Ch. 3, Sect. 1, §2), but then says that according to natural law it is
permissible when one has no other means to protect one’s life according to the right of nature (GDIB
Bk 1, Ch. 3, Sect. 2, §1).
⁵⁰ However, Grotius, in his historical answer to the question of whether war could ever be just, is quite
careful to discuss vis and not violentia. He takes his guide from Cicero’s definition of war “decertandum
unum per vim,” quotes his rhetorical question “quid est quod contra vim fieri sine vi possit?,” and
approvingly notes Ulpian’s “vim vi repelle licere Cassius scribit” (GDIB Bk 1, Ch 2, Sect. 2, §6).
⁵¹ “Quodsi duorum alter violentiam adhibet alter eamdem vi repellere molitur . . .”
⁵² Thomas Aquinas also comes close to this distinction and with very similar language; but he never
explicitly contrasts the terms as far as I can tell. He refers to the justified constraint of the state as vis: Cf.
ST I–II.90.3, ad 2: “A private person cannot lead another to virtue efficaciously: for he can only advise,
and if his advice be not taken, it has no constraining force <vim coactivam>, such as the law should
have, in order to prove an efficacious inducement to virtue, as the Philosopher says (Ethic. x. 9). But this
constraining force is vested in the whole people or in some public personage, to whom it belongs to
inflict penalties.” And concerning violence, he writes “violence directly opposes the free will, and nature
<violentia directe opponitur voluntario, sicut enim et naturali>”—“whence it is contrary to the nature
<rationis> of the will’s own act that it be compelled or violated <Unde contra rationem ipsius actus
voluntatis est quod sit coactus vel violentus>” (ST I.II.6.4).
261
edition, which Kant used, for example in BM §714 (however, this change was not
effected in the index, where violentia remains). Constraint simply means to effect
another’s action against their wishes (again, BM §714), so this seems to be
Baumgarten’s early and unqualified understanding of violence. Violentia itself
stems from violatio, and violatio denotes injury, as does its English cognate
“violation.” We are forbidden from causing injury, and thus from violence:
“nobody is to be harmed <nemo est laedendus>” (KE §768; repeated in BIN
§150); “you shall harm nobody <neminem laedas>” (BIP §92); but we are also
obligated to repelling injury mildly, and even when applying force. Thus, contrary
to the tradition both preceding and following him, force and violence, when
strictly understood, cannot be synonyms, for the former maps strictly onto evil,
while the latter onto the nexus of harm and injury. Now, in BM §699, to which
Baumgarten refers above, he had defined the violent person, i.e. the vehemens, as
“being faulty in excess” in the use of force, whereas the one who correctly uses
one’s force is strenuous (and the deficient one is weak). Thus, for Baumgarten,
violence is disordered, i.e. excessive, force. It is vicious in Aristotle’s sense. Violence
is then an illicit species of force, as is pacifism (deficient force); the proportionate
use of force is justice. Thus mildness, although it may resort to force, must eschew
violence. As such, mildness may seek vengeance, but only within fair limits and
thus must eschew vindictiveness; such a person is placable (placabilis) (BEP §326).
So, in the BIN, the concept of a putative just violence⁵³ in fact corresponds to
the Metaphysics’s constraint or strenuous use of force—the posthumous BIN,
which Baumgarten never polished for publication, is the only remaining place
in the Baumgarten corpus where the family of words indicating violence is
interpreted so positively or broadly: “Physical evils are those that are either
recognized as such by the very judgment of the senses by the one in whom they
belong or are inferred. If evils of the senses, or more distressing phenomena, arise
in any person due to the force of another person, these are indeed said to be the
result of this person’s force simply speaking, or violence” (BIN Pr. §172).⁵⁴ “Force
simply speaking <vis simpliciter>” is the key term here, for this indicates that force
is only to be called violence when we take force without qualification, or most
broadly. For, as we’ve seen, ethics forbids us not from inflicting evils, which is
forceful constraint, but from inflicting harms, which constitutes violence. This
lesson stretches back to Plato’s Republic and Laws (among other places). In fact,
Baumgarten argues that this precept goes beyond right itself and is among the
first principles of “the whole of practical philosophy” (BIP §92). Harm is a
⁵³ I have argued elsewhere against Weigel that the concept of just violence is an oxymoron, since, as
excessive, violence per se is disordered force. Please see my “Regrounding the Just War’s ‘Presumption
Against Violence’ in Light of George Weigel” (Hymers 2004).
⁵⁴ “Mala physica vel ipso iudicio sensuum agnoscenda pro talibus ab illo, cui insunt, vel inferuntur,
mala sensus sunt. Mala sensus tristiora phaenomena si oriantur alicui homini per vim alterius hominis,
ea quidem huius vis simpliciter seu violentia, dicuntur.”
262
transgression or violation of law, i.e. violence, and “is the opposite of duty”
(BIP §83), repeated in BIN Pr. § 148.⁵⁵ And just as defense more strictly con-
sidered attempts to prevent harm, offense more strictly considered causes harm
(even if more broadly speaking offense can be understood along with Wolff simply
as inflicting evil). Baumgarten thus greatly nuances Wolff ’s concept of a just
offensive war. Offense more broadly speaking is to inflict an evil on another, but
more strictly speaking, it is to inflict harm (BIN §145). Thus, although offense
more broadly speaking may be just (e.g. a just war of prevention), offense more
strictly speaking is always unjust (BIN §148), a conclusion that Köhler also
reaches on the same grounds (KE §1124–5). More strictly speaking, offense is
aggression, and violent in the stricter sense as it harms, or intends such. So, when
Baumgarten uses the term violentia simply or without qualification, he uses it in
Köhler’s uncareful sense to mean to inflict a constraining evil (which is also its
original meaning in BM). But when he understands violence in a qualified sense,
which for him is a stricter and even strictest sense, he understands it as inflicting
harm—which of course again is forbidden.
VII
Punitive war in Baumgarten. The idea that punishment is a justifying cause of war
is moribund today, although thinkers like George Weigel are trying to resurrect it;
see for instance his “Moral clarity in a time of war” (Weigel 2003). As I noted
above, the relevant sections of the UN charter make no mention of punishment
but only of aggression. International convention in fact currently holds that
punishment is only to be carried out after a war where necessary, but it does not
justify war, and historically punishment concerns only conduct during war,
as both the International Military Tribunal in Nuremburg (IMTN) and the
International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) testify.⁵⁶ This
seems to be Walzer’s position as well. Contemporary abhorrence to punitive war is
⁵⁵ In his notes to the Elements, Kant in fact glosses this sentence with laesio personae violentia|
offensio laesio juris (E6505)—“violence, harm to a person | offense, harm to right.” In BIN Pr. §148,
Baumgarten writes “Harm is opposed to the duty to someone: (1) to God, (2) to myself, (3) to another
<Laesio est oppositum officii erga aliquem, (1) Dei, (2) mei ipsius, (3) alius>.” With respect to the other,
this harm is either internal (opposed to internal duty) or external (opposed to external duty).
Baumgarten considers the second, external harm to harm strictly considered (BIN Pr. §148).
⁵⁶ The IMTN considered the crime of aggression (the crime of war) to be the most serious charge.
Although individual Germans were indeed held accountable punitively for crimes against humanity
(specifically for the Holocaust), crimes against Jews prior to 1939 (i.e. the beginning of hostilities) were
not imputable; cf. Mouralis 2019, 25. On the other hand, the ICTY nowhere addresses aggression, but
instead is concerned strictly with “serious violations of international humanitarian law committed in
the territory of the Former Yugoslavia since 1991” (Updated Statute Of The International Criminal
Tribunal For The Former Yugoslavia 2009, art. 1). The specific crimes—murder, extermination,
enslavement, deportation, imprisonment, torture, rape, political, racial and religious persecution, and
other inhume acts—are listed in art. 5; art. 9 clarifies the no crimes before Jan. 1, 1991 are prosecutable.
263
also demonstrated by a negative: the Iraq war of 2003 itself was so very contro-
versial precisely because it was not widely seen as a defensive war (and even
Weigel tried to stay within the defensive-war paradigm by painting the then-
imminent invasion as defensive on the grounds that Iraq’s supposed possession of
WMD made it a de facto, if not de iure, aggressor). Nevertheless, the US
Congress’s Authorization for Use of Military Force Against Iraq Resolution of
2002 included among its justifications non-compliance with international treaties,
and the mistreatment of its own population. Hence, Washington justified the
war—at least partially—on punitive grounds.⁵⁷
Weigel and others (e.g. Langan 1984) register slight surprise that our age has
abandoned punishment as a causa justifica. We saw above that both Grotius and
Wolff permit punitive war.⁵⁸ However, the idea that a just war can be punitive
seems to go back as far as Cicero, the co-father of the just war tradition alongside
Plato. Cicero indeed held that the overarching just cause of a war is to live in peace
unhindered, which he shares with Plato. However, he also arguably sees punish-
ment as playing some role, as we read in a fragment of De Off. which Isadore of
Seville preserves: “those wars that are undertaken without a cause are unjust. For
beyond the cause of ulciscendi or repelling an enemy, a just war cannot be waged
<Illa iniusta bella sunt, quae sunt sine causa suscepta. Nam extra ulciscendi aut
propulsandorum hostium causam bellum geri iustum nullum potest>” (Cicero
1869, 309). Ulciscendi can mean either avenging or punishing, and here it is
unclear which Cicero means. But there is no ambiguity in St Augustine, who
famously saw war as primarily punitive, and, as Langan argues, he does so at the
expense of any concept of defense. For Augustine, war is necessary for restoring—
or at least shoring up—the moral order, not protecting national interests.
Although Augustine never delivers a comprehensive declaration of the ius ad
bellum, he nevertheless writes: “It is generally to punish [evils], when force is
required to inflict the punishment, that, in obedience to God or some lawful
authority, good men undertake wars” (Contra Faustum 22: §74, quoted in Langan
1984, 22).⁵⁹ Augustine saw war as the engine of history, like Heraclitus. But unlike
Heraclitus, he saw history as God’s plan. And hence war for Augustine is prov-
idential punishment. Here he is strikingly different than his patron Ambrose, the
⁵⁷ The best overview of a possible renaissance of punitive just war in the early twenty-first century is
O’Driscoll 2008, chapter 3. O’Driscoll takes the Iraq War of 2003 as its point of departure.
⁵⁸ See Luban 2011 for a comprehensive philosophical overview of the history of punitive just war.
⁵⁹ There is ambiguity in Augustine’s position though; he seems to argue for sovereign authority and
defense in Contra Faustum: “A great deal depends on the causes for which men undertake wars, and on
the authority they have for doing so; for the natural order which seeks the peace of mankind, ordains
that the monarch should have the power of undertaking war if he thinks it advisable, and that the
soldiers should perform their military duties in behalf of the peace and safety of the community”
(Augustine 1887, 22:§75). That is, here he argues not for the punishment of wrongdoers, but the
defense of the natural order. Langan quotes this passage too, but sees in it only the question concerning
authority, not defense (1984, 23).
264
founder of the Christian just war tradition (Swift 1970, 532), who held war was
only justified if it was defensive.⁶⁰
Defense in its three forms provides an exhaustive account of just war for
Baumgarten. Although various writers have long lists of what justifies war, and
Augustine among others even suggests such justifications as divine command
and, like Cicero, defense of honor, Baumgarten never strays beyond his three
temporal forms of defense. Thus, absent from his list of justifications is punish-
ment, which practically every just war writer prior to Baumgarten accepts (an
extremely abbreviated list includes Augustine, Cicero, Grotius, and Wolff); as
such, Baumgarten seems to be among the first notable just-war thinkers to
have struck punishment from the list of causae belli justificae, especially in the
modern period. Grotius, as we saw above, had in fact cemented punishment as a
justification when he claimed that defense, vengeance, and punishment are
accepted by most authorities, without noting the dissenting voices. Köhler how-
ever nowhere seems to discuss punitive warfare, and his sole example of punish-
ment within the context of war concerns the necessity to punish soldiers to
preserve military structure.⁶¹ This absence in Köhler explains its complete absence
from Baumgarten’s commentary, the BIN, which nowhere mentions punitive war.
Rather, he is content to give defense as the exclusive cause, and thereby excluding
all other forms.
But although punitive war is missing explicitly in the texts of both Köhler and
Baumgarten, it is there implicitly. Their works make punitive war impossible
beyond defense taken exclusively, and do so on the grounds that there is no
proper framework for punishment within the right of nature. For, Köhler writes:
In the state of nature nobody is superior. And thus, there is nobody superior in
that state to another, so to speak, who can carry out an evil that is connected with
those actions of his that are to be avoided or carried out. If that evil is called
punishment more strictly considered, in that same state nobody can punish
another. (KE §919)⁶²
⁶⁰ “Ambrose also follows the Roman tradition in spelling out the conditions that must govern the
right to war. These include the provisions that every conflict be defensive in nature (De Off. Min.
1.27.129; cf. 35.I76–7, 4I.201), that agreements be honored (De Off. Min. 2.7.33; cf. 3.14.86–7), that no
unfair advantage be taken of the enemy (De Off. Min. 1.29.139), and that mercy be exhibited to the
defeated (De Off. Min. 3.14.87; f. In Luc. 5.76, In Ps. 38. II). Within such limits war could be considered
not only justifiable but praiseworthy” (Swift 1970, 533).
⁶¹ “What is the proportion between the punishment of hanging and the rape committed by a soldier
and considered in itself? But you will understand the justice of military laws once you compare the deed
of the soldier with the danger into which the army is thrown by the violation of the command <quæ
proportio inter poenam suspendii & rapam a milite ablatam & in se spectatam? sed justitiam legum
militarium concipies si factum militis cum periculo in quod a violatione mandati conjicitur exercitus
comparaveris>” (KE §1119).
⁶² “In statu naturali nullus datur homo superior. Nullus itaque in eodem statu tanquam superior
alteri potest repræsentare malum connexum cum illius actionibus fugiendis vel expediendis. Quod
malum si dicatur poena strictius dicta in eodem statu nemo alterum punire potest.” On the superior
265
and inferior, see BIP §105: “The legislator strictly considered is a human being who has the right to give
laws strictly considered for other human beings; with respect to the laws and to the human beings that
are to be obligated, the same person is a superior strictly considered (a commander, a lord), since the
superior broadly considered is everyone who is more honoured. A human being for whom there is a
superior strictly considered is, with respect to him, an inferior strictly considered (a subject, a
subordinate, a servant), since the inferior broadly considered is he who is less honoured.”
⁶³ See also AIN II §40 for a similar position. The Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court
(2011) follows this, holding that there is nullum crimen sine lege (Part 3, art 22) and especially that there
is nulla poena sine lege (Part 3, art. 23).
⁶⁴ A distinction not found in Achenwall. Köhler refers to both the arbiter and the iudex, but only
alludes to the distinction that Baumgarten so clearly derives.
⁶⁵ Cf. Hobbes: “Where there is no common power, there is no law; where no law, no injustice”
(Leviathan, xiii.13; Hobbes 1985, 188).
⁶⁶ Hence it is strange when Van Der Mandere claims that Grotius rejected war as a judicial means
and located it only within the preservation of the right to exist (1925, 442).
266
The right to punish emerges from the nature of the crime (GDIB Bk. 2, Ch. 20,
Sect. 2, §3); the criminal, as it were, has voluntarily submitted oneself to the
punishment. Grotius indeed grants that although the right of nature grants the
right of punishment, it does not say precisely who should have it, but nevertheless
the right of nature suggests that it be granted to superiors, and in carrying out a
criminal act, the criminal necessarily makes oneself inferior (GDIB Bk. 2, Ch. 20,
Sect. 3, §1).⁶⁷ This is more an act of hand waving than a strong argument, for it
glosses over precisely the point to which Köhler and Baumgarten consistently
cling—in the state of nature there simply are no superiors or judges (KE §919): “in
the natural state,” writes Baumgarten, “there is neither servant, nor commander”
(BIN §11).⁶⁸ Baumgarten simply cannot find punishment in the right of nature,
but rather only the commands to live honorably, harm nobody, and give to each
one’s own.
VIII
Baumgarten’s contemporary importance. What we have seen so far is that the just
war tradition, especially embodied by Grotius’s pre-eminent position in it, but
stretching back to Cicero and going as far as Wolff, had accepted punishment as a
justification of war, and thus had given us a punitive just war tradition. But
something happened in the twentieth century, as embodied in the fullest attempt
that the world has come to implementing a true ius gentium in the guise of the
international order of the United Nations. The world community has, officially at
least, rejected the punitive just war under the exclusive principle of self-defense.
Under the premise of Kant’s intellectual paternity of the UN, this position can and
has been ascribed to Kant, who, 150 years before the articles of the UN were
drafted in 1945, had written in his Perpetual Peace: “but between states no
punitive war (bellum punitivum) is conceivable, because there is no relation
between them of master and servant,” which he repeats practically verbatim in
the Metaphysics of Morals (MS 6:347); Luban (2011, 315) cites this as the intel-
lectual turning point against punitive just war. But as we have seen, this is
essentially a direction quotation from Baumgarten’s BIN §11 And, like Köhler,
⁶⁷ Luban points out that Cajetan likewise wrestles with this question, arguing “that ‘he who has a just
war embodies a judge of proceedings in vindicative justice against foreign disturbers of the common-
wealth’ ” (2011, 315–6). This is essentially the same response as Grotius.
⁶⁸ See Wolff ’s definition of ethics for a clear statement on the egality of the state of nature: “Now,
elsewhere we give another definition of Ethics, that it is the science of directing free actions in the state
of nature, or insofar as a person is the subject of his own right, and subject to the command of no other”
(WDP §64). See also Meier: “Concerning his duties, a person is chiefly thought to be in a two-fold state:
in a natural and in a social state. In the first, one is merely considered as a human being, without being
regarded as belonging to a particular society in which not all humans belong. In the natural condition,
man is regarded neither as a father nor as a son, neither as a master nor as a servant, neither as a lord
nor as a subject” (MPS §2).
267
Achenwall, and Baumgarten, who all belong to a school that Schwaiger identifies
as the “Young Wolves <jungen Wölfen>” (2011, 115), Kant also sees punitive war
as impossible precisely because of the leveling essential to the state of nature: “up
to the present, Hugo Grotius, Pufendorf, Vattel, and many other irritating com-
forters have been cited in justification of war, though their code, philosophically
or diplomatically formulated, has not and cannot have the least legal force,
because states as such do not stand under a common external power.” Thus,
Kant dismisses Grotius et al. as paper tigers (“there is no instance on record that a
state has ever been moved to desist from its purpose because of arguments
backed up by the testimony of such great men”),⁶⁹ and, drawing inspiration
from Hobbes (Kant 1997, 339; AA 27:590), insists on the moral necessity of
leaving the state of nature in order to create a federation of nations for the sake
of peace (1991, 98 and 102f.).
Baumgarten’s own treatises on peace have none of the practical geo-political
detail of Kant’s famous argument. No argument for the importance of republican
government, no separation of powers, no popular sovereignty, no call for a league
of nations, and no School of Salamanca-like call for the freedom of movement,
trade, and communication. No real doctrine of international treaties (although the
subject of good faith, fides, is briefly broached in BIN §96–114, esp. in §102–3, and
BEP §347), and no plan to replace standing armies with ad hoc national militias.
But nevertheless, Baumgarten’s view of war is strongly contemporary. Even
though he stays within the state of nature and does not attempt a Kantian
cosmopolitanism, he limits war to harms committed against oneself and thus
strictly and explicitly limits war to self-defense, distinguishes between force and
violence (accepting the latter and rejecting the former), and rejects punitive wars.
That self-defense becomes the sole justification for war in the twentieth century is
rooted in Baumgarten’s concept of the right of nature, even if only indirectly
through Kant. Kant’s influence on the UN and its position on punitive war did not
emerge ex nihilo. This suggests that an intellectual paternity test of the UN Charter
delivers at least some of Baumgarten’s DNA.
⁶⁹ I ignore here the question of whether or not Kant embraces just war. See Orend 2008 for a
discussion of this problem; Orend holds that Kant indeed has a just war theory. See Eberl 2021 for the
opposing position. Kant’s discussion of the “right to war” in MS §56 (6: 152), although it seems to
contradict his argument in the Perpetual Peace that such a right is unimaginable, seems to make Eberl’s
theory untenable. As such, Orend argues that critics simply choose whichever of these two texts proves
their point. Grotius offered his own bleak assessment of his life’s work: “I have wasted my life by taking
great pains to achieve nothing <ah vitam perdidi operose nihil agendo>!” (Fleming 1699, 74, 5n).
Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy
Courtney D. Fugate (ed.), John Hymers (ed.)
https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192873538.001.0001
Published: 2024 Online ISBN: 9780191976162 Print ISBN: 9780192873538
END MATTER
Works Cited
Published: June 2024
1 5
Achenwall, Gottfried. 1750. 1763. Ius naturae. Göttingen.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Achenwall, Gottfried. 2020a. Natural Law: A Translation of the Textbook for Kantʼs Lectures on Legal and Political Philosophy. Ed.
Pauline Kleingeld, trans. Corinna Vermeulen, with an Introduction by Paul Guyer. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Achenwall, Gottfried. 2020b. Prolegomena to Natural Law. Trans. Corinna Vermeulen and ed. Pauline Kleingeld. Groningen:
University of Groningen Press.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Aichele, Alexander. 2004a. “Grüße von Sam. Zum Verhältnis von Zurechenbarkeit und Menschheit am Paradigma der
Rechtsphilosophie Kants.” In Kaufmann and Renzikowski 2004. 247–62.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Aichele, Alexander. 2004b. “Sive vox naturae sive vox rationis sive vox Dei? Die metaphysische Begründung des
Naturrechtsprinzips bei Heinrich Köhler, mit einer abschließenden Bemerkung zu Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten.” Jahrbuch für
Recht und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics 12. 115–35.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Aichele, Alexander. 2005. “Die Ungewißheit des Gewissens. Alexander Gottlieb Baumgartens forensische Aufklärung der
Aufklärungsethik.” Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics 13. 3–30.
WorldCat
Aichele, Alexander. 2011a. “Zurechnungsmetaphysik? Samuel Pufendorfs Begri der imputatio als Realitätsgrund von Moralität.”
Annual Review of Law and Ethics 19. 325–46.
Aichele, Alexander. 2011b. “Enthymematik und Wahrscheinlichkeit. Die epistemologische Rechtfertigung singulärer Urteile in
Universaljurisprudenz und Logik der deutschen Aufklärung: C. Wol und A.G. Baumgarten.” Rechtstheorie 42. 495–513.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Aichele, Alexander. 2017. Wahrscheinliche Weltweisheit: A.G. Baumgartens Metaphysik des Erkennens und Handelns. Hamburg:
Meiner.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Aichele, Alexander. 2019. “Jenseits jeden vernün igen Zweifels. Die Herstellung subjektiver Gewissheit in A.G. Baumgartens
Theorie der Zurechnung.” Annual Review of Law and Ethics 27. 269–98.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Alexy, Robert. 2015. “Zwang.” In Kant-Lexikon. Ed. Marcus Willaschek, Jürgen Stolzenberg, Georg Mohr, and Stefano Bacin. Berlin:
de Gruyter. 2741–4.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Allison, Henry E. 2006. “Kant on Freedom of the Will.” In The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Ed.
Paul Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 381–415.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Allison, Henry E. 2011. Kantʼs “Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals.” A Commentary. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Anderson, Georg. 1923. “Kants Metaphysik der Sitten. – ihre Idee und ihr Verhältnis zur Ethik der Wol schen Schule.” Kant-
Studien 28. 41–61.
WorldCat
Anscombe, G.E.M. 1961. “War and Murder.” In Nuclear Weapons: A Catholic Response. Ed. Walter Stein. New York: Sheed and
Ward. 44–52.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Aso, Ken, Masao Kurosaki, Tanchisa Otabe, and Shiro Yamauchi (eds). 1989. Onomasticon philosophicum latinoteutonicum et
teutonicolatinum. Tokyo: Tetsugaku-Shobo.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Augustine. 1887. “Contra Faustum.” In Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, First Series, Vol. 4. Ed. Philip Scha . Trans. Richard
p. 270 Stothert. Bu alo, NY: Christian Literature Publishing.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Augustine. 1958. City of God. Ed. Vernon J. Bourke. Trans. Gerald G. Walsh et al. New York: Image Books.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Bacin, Stefano. 2013. “Legge e obbligatorietà; lʼidea di autolegislazione morale.” Studi kantiani 26. 55–70.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Bacin, Stefano. 2015. “Kantʼs Lectures on Ethics and Baumgartenʼs Moral Philosophy.” In Kantʼs Lectures on Ethics. A Critical
Guide. Ed. Lara Denis and Oliver Sensen. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 15–33.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Bacin, Stefano. 2017. “Rationalism and Perfectionism.” In The Cambridge History of Moral Philosophy. Ed. Sasha Golob and
Jens Timmermann. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 79–393.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Bacin, Stefano. 2018a. “Autonomy and Moral Rationalism: Kantʼs Criticisms of ʻRationalistʼ Moral Principles 1762–1785.” In The
Emergence of Autonomy in Kantʼs Moral Philosophy. Ed. Stefano Bacin and Oliver Sensen. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 48–66.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Bacin, Stefano. 2018b. “Moral Realism by Other Means: The Hybrid Nature of Kantʼs Practical Rationalism.” In Realism and
Antirealism in Kantʼs Moral Philosophy: New Essays. Ed. Robinson dos Santos and Elke Elisabeth Schmidt. Berlin–Boston: de
Gruyter. 153–76.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Bacon, Francis. 2001. The Advancement of Learning [1605]. Ed. G.W. Kitchin. Philadelphia, PA: Dry Books.
Baeumler, Alfred. 1975. Das Irrationalitätsproblem in der Ästhetik und Logik des 18. Jahrhunderts bis zur Kritik der Urteilskra .
Darmstadt: Wissenscha liche Buchgesellscha .
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baum, Manfred. 2012. “Prior Concepts of the Metaphysics of Morals.” In Kantʼs Tugendlehre: A Comprehensive Commentary. Ed.
Andreas Trampota, Oliver Sensen, and Jens Timmermann. Berlin: de Gruyter. 113–38.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baum, Manfred. 2014. “Sittengesetz und Freiheit. Kant 1785 und 1788.” In Kants Rechtfertigung des Sittengesetzes in
Grundlegung III. Ed. Heiko Puls. Berlin: de Gruyter. 209–26.
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb (chair). 1746. Christian Ludwig von Brand (author). Scenographia iuris socialis primarii.
Dissertation. Frankfurt.
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb (chair). Samuel Wilhelm Spalding (author). 1741b. De vi et e icacia ethices philosophicae.
Dissertation. Frankfurt on the Oder: Typis Martini Hübneri.
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1735. Meditationes philosophicae de nonnullis ad poema pertinentibus. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
1 2 3 4
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1739. 1743. 1750. 1757. Metaphysica. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
1 2 3
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1740, 1751, 1763. Ethica philosophica. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1740. Gedancken vom vernün igen Beyfall auf Academien. Frankfurt.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1741a. Philosophische Brie e von Aletheophilus. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1743. Scriptis quae moderator conflictus academici disputavit. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1750. Dissertatio inauguralis de fidei in philosophia utilitate. Frankfurt.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1760. Initia philosophiae practicae primae. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1783. Metaphysik. Trans. Georg Friedrich Meier. Remarks by Johann August Eberhard. First
edition, Halle 1766. [Reprint: Ed. Dagmar Mirbach, Jena 2004.]
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1983a. Philosophische Betrachtungen über einige Bedingungen des Gedichtes. Meditationes
philosophicae de nonnullis ad poema pertinentibus. Latin-German. Trans. Heinz Paetzold. Hamburg: Meiner Verlag.
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1983b. Bigaku. Tran. Hiroshi Matsuo. Tokyo: Tamagawa Daigaku Shuppanbu. [Revised reprint:
Kodansha, 2016.]
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 1999. Die Vorreden zur Metaphysik. Ed. and trans. Ursula Niggli. Frankfurt: Klostermann.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2007. Aesthetik. 2 vols. Latin-German. Trans. Dagmar Mirbach. Hamburg: Meiner Verlag.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2011. Metaphysica/Metaphysik: Historisch-kritische Ausgabe. Ed. and trans. Günter Gawlick and
Lothar Kreimendahl. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2013. Metaphysics: A Critical Translation with Kantʼs Elucidations, Selected Notes, and Related
Materials. Ed. and trans. Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers. London: Bloomsbury.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2017a. Lʼinvention de lʼesthétique—Méditations philosophiques sur quelques sujets se rapportant
au poème. Trans. Jean-Yves Pranchère. Paris: Paris Ouest.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2017b. Estetica. Edizione italiana annotata. Trans. Francesco Piselli. Bornato in Franciacorta:
Sardini.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2019a. Anfangsgründe der praktischen Metaphysik—Initia Philosophiae Practicae Primae. Latin
and German bilingual edition. Trans. and ed. Alexander Aichele. Hamburg: Meiner.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2019b. Métaphysique. Trans. Luc Langlois and Emilie-Jade Poliquin. Paris: Vrin.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2020. Elements of First Practical Philosophy: A Critical Translation with Kantʼs Reflections on
Moral Philosophy. Ed. and trans. Courtney. D. Fugate and John Hymers. London: Bloomsbury.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2022. Reflections on Poetry. Trans. Karl Aschenbrenner and William B. Holther. Oakland, CA:
University of California Press.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb. 2024. Philosophical Ethics. Ed. and trans. John Hymers. London: Bloomsbury.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten, Siegmund Jacob. 1738. Unterricht von dem rechtmäßigen Verhalten eines Christen, oder Theologische Moral. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baxley, Anne Margaret. 2010. Kantʼs Theory of Virtue: The Value of Autocracy. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baxley, Anne Margaret. 2015. “Virtue, Self-Mastery, and the Autocracy of Practical Reason.” In Kantʼs Lectures on Ethics: A Critical
Guide. Ed. Lara Denis and Oliver Sensen. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 223–38.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Beiser, Frederick C. 2009. Diotimaʼs Children: German Aesthetic Rationalism from Leibniz to Lessing. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Böhm, Hans. 1926. “Das Schönheitsproblem bei G.F. Meier.” Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie 56. 177–252.
Google Scholar WorldCat
p. 272 Brandt, Reinhard. 1993. “Gerechtigkeit bei Kant.” Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics 1. 24–44.
WorldCat
Breuer, Ulrich. 2005. “Lebendige Erkenntnis. August Hermann Franckes Lebenslauf.” In Aedificatio. Erbauung im interkulturellen
Kontext in der Frühen Neuzeit. Ed. Andreas Solbach. Tübingen: Niemeyer. 49–63.
Brierly, James Leslie. 1963. The Law of Nations: An Introduction to the International Law of Peace. Ed. Humphrey Waldock. 6th ed.
Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Buchenau, Stefanie. 2011. “Notions directrices et architectonique de la métaphysique. La critique kantienne de Wol en 1763.”
Astérion 9.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Buchenau, Stefanie. 2023. Menschenwürde; Kant und die Aufklärung. Hamburg: Meiner Verlag.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Buchenau, Stefanie and Annelise Rey (trans.). 2000. Philosophia practica universalis. Translation of the prologue and chapter 1 of
the 1703 work by Christian Wol . DATA n° 31.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Busche, Hubertus. 1991. “Die innere Logik der Liebe in Leibnizens ʻElementa Juris Naturalisʼ.” Studia Leibnitiana 23. 170–84.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Campagna, Norbert. 2013. “De la religion comme objet dʼun devoir envers soi-même.” In Kant. Théologie et religion. Ed.
Robert Theis. Paris: Vrin. 197–206.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Carboncini, Sonia. 2021. “Development and Di usion of Wol ʼs Psychology Through His Disciples and Followers.” In The Force of
an Idea: New Essays on Christian Wol ʼs Psychology. Ed. Saulo de Freitas Araujo, Thiago Constâncio Ribeiro Pereira, and
Thomas Sturm. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. 197–215.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Cicero. 1869. Librorum de Re Publica Sex Quae Supersunt. Klotz, Reinhold (Ed.). Leipzig: Teubner.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Cicero. 1913. On Duties. Trans. Walter Mille. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Cicero, Marcus Tullius. 1928. On the Republic. On the Laws De Re publica, De Legibus. Trans. Clinton W. Keyes. Cambridge, MA:
Loeb.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Cicero. 1931. Pro Milone. In Pisonem. Pro Scauro. Pro Fonteio. Pro Rabirio Postumo. Pro Marcello. Pro Ligario. Pro Rege Deiotaro.
Trans. N.H. Watts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Curran, Jane V., and Christophe Fricker (eds). 2005. Schillerʼs “On Grace and Dignity” in Its Cultural Context: Essays and a New
Translation. Rochester, NY: Camden House.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Dʼavenant, William. 1673. “The Just Italian.” In The Works of Sir William Dʼavenant, Knight. Ed. Henry Harringman. London: T.N.
441–63.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Descartes, René. 1985. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. 3 vols. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stootho , and Dugald
Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Descartes, René. 1964–74. 1897–1910. Œuvres de Descartes. 12 vols. Ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery. Paris: Vrin.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Dyck, Corey W. 2018. “Between Wol ianism and Pietism: Baumgartenʼs Rational Psychology.” In Baumgarten and Kant on
Metaphysics. Ed. Courtney Fugate and John Hymers. Oxford: Oxford UP. 78–93.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Eberl, Oliver. 2021. “Kantʼs Rejection of Just War: International Order between Democratic Constitutionalism and Revolutionary
Violence.” In: The Justification of War and International Order: From Past to Present. Ed. Lothar Brock and Hendrik Simon. Oxford:
Oxford UP. 129–144.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Enskat, Rainer. 2007. Bedingungen der Aufklärung. Philosophische Untersuchungen zu einer Aufgabe der Urteilskra . Velbrück:
Weilerswist.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
p. 273 Erdmann, Johann Eduard. 1866. Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie. Vol. 2. Berlin: Verlag von Wilhelm Hertz.
Favaretti Composampiero, Matteo. 2018. “Sciences Without a Name: Teleology, Perfection, and Harmony in the Leibniz-Wol
Debate.” Studia Leibnitiana 50. 10–25.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Favaretti Camposampiero, Matteo. 2024. “Objective Morality: Wol and the Impious Hypothesis.” In Christian Wol ʼs German
Ethics. Ed. Sonja Schierbaum, Michael Walschots, and John Walsh. Oxford: Oxford UP. 129–52.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Feiereis, Konrad. 1965. Die Umprägung der natürlichen Theologie in Religionsphilosophie. Ein Beitrag zur deutschen
Geistesgeschichte des 18. Jahrhunderts. Leipzig: St Benno-Verlag.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Fleming, Robert. 1699. Θεοκρατια, or the divine government of nations considered and improved. London: Andrew Bell.
Förster, Johann Christian. 1765. Charactere dreyer berühmter Weltweisen nämlich Leibnitzens, Wolfs und Baumgartens. 2nd ed.
Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Franck, Thomas M. Fairness in International Law and Institutions. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Friedman, Shterna S. 2022. “The Unity of the Highest Good: Kant on Systemic Justice.” Journal of Transcendental Philosophy
3(3). 345–67.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Friedrich, C. J. 1947. “The Ideology of the United Nations Charter and the Philosophy of Peace of Immanuel Kant 1795–1945.”
Journal of Politics 9(1). 10–30.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Friesen, Duane K. 2005. “The Convergence of Pacifism and Just War.” In War and Christian Ethics. Ed. Arthur F. Holmes. Grand
Rapids, MI: Baker Academic. 352–72.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Fuchs, Hans-Jürgen. 1972. “Egotismus, Egoismus, Egomismus.” In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Vol. 2. Ed.
Joachim Ritter. Basel: Schwabe. 315–17.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Fugate, Courtney D. 2014. “Alexander Baumgarten on the Principle of Su icient Reason.” Philosophica 44. 127–47.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Fugate, Courtney D. 2015. “The Unity of Metaphysics in Kantʼs Lectures.” In Reading Kantʼs Lectures. Ed. Robert R. Clewis. Berlin:
de Gruyter. 64–87.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Fugate, Courtney D. 2018. “Baumgarten and Kant on Existence.” In Fugate and Hymers (eds). 131–53.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Fugate, Courtney D. 2023. “Baumgarten on the Nature and Role of Metaphysics.” In Metaphysics as a Science in Classical German
Philosophy. Ed. Robb Dunphy and Toby Lovat. London: Routledge. 50–72.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Fugate, Courtney D. 2024. “Wol ʼs Ethical Experimentalism and Its Roots in his German Ethics.” In Christian Wol ʼs German
Ethics. Ed. Sonja Schierbaum, Michael Walschots, and John Walsh. Oxford: Oxford UP. 273–95.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Fugate, Courtney D. and John Hymers (eds). 2018. Baumgarten and Kant on Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Gabriel, Gottfried. 1995. “Solipsismus.” In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Vol. 9. Ed. Joachim Ritter and
Karlfried Gründer. Basel: Schwabe. 1018–1023.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Gerhardt, Carl Immanuel (Ed.). 1860. Briefwechsel zwischen Leibniz und Christian Wol . Aus den Handschri en der Koeniglichen
Bibliothek zu Hannover. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Gottsched, Johann Christoph. 1736. Erste Gründe der gesammten Weltweisheit, Practischer Teil. Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Goubet, Jean-François. 2021. “The Relation Between Psychology and the Other Parts of Metaphysics: Ontology, Cosmology, and
Theology.” In The Force of an Idea. New Essays on Christian Wol ʼs Psychology. Ed. Saulo de Freitas Araujo,
Thiago Constâncio Ribeiro Pereira, and Thomas Sturm. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. 175–96.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Groß, Ste en W. 2001. “Felix Aestheticus und Animal Symbolicum. Alexander G. Baumgarten—die ʻvierte Quelleʼ der Philosophie
p. 274 Ernst Cassirers?” Deutsche Zeitschri für Philosophie 49. 275–98.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Grote, Simon. 2017. The Emergence of Modern Aesthetic Theory: Religion and Morality in Enlightenment Germany and Scotland.
Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Grotius, Hugo. 1625. De iure belli ac pacis libri tres. Paris: Buon.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Grotius, Hugo. 2005. The Rights of War and Peace. With the notes by Jean Barbeyrac, anonymous English translation of 1738. Ed.
Richard Tuck. 3 vols. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Guyer, Paul. 2007. “Perfection, Autonomy, and Heautonomy: The Path of Reason from Wol to Kant.” In Christian Wol und die
europäische Aufklärung. Ed. Jürgen Stolzenberg and Oliver Pierre-Rudolph. Akten des 1. Internationalen Christian—Wol —
Kongresses. Hildesheim: Olms. 299–322.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Guyer, Paul. 2016b. “Kant, Mendelssohn, and Immortality.” In The Highest Good in Kantʼs Philosophy. Ed. Thomas Höwing. Berlin:
de Gruyter. 157–79.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Guyer, Paul. 2016c. “Setting and Pursuing Ends: Internal and External Freedom.” In Guyer 2016e. 87–104.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Guyer, Paul. 2016d. “The Twofold Morality of Kantian Recht.” Kant-Studien 107. 34–63.
Guyer, Paul. 2016e. Virtues of Freedom: Selected Essays on Kant. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Guyer, Paul. 2019. Kant on the Rationality of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Guyer, Paul. 2020. Reason and Experience in Mendelssohn and Kant. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Guyer, Paul. 2021. “The Original Empty Formalism Objection: Pistorius and Kant.” In Practical Philosophy from Kant to Hegel:
Freedom, Right, and Revolution. Ed. James A. Clarke and Gabriel Gottlieb. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 10–27.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Guyer, Paul. 2024. “Perfectionism and Duties to Self in Wol and Kant.” In Wol ʼs German Ethics. Ed. Sonia Schierbaum,
Michael Walschots, and John Walsh. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Haizmann, Albrecht. 1997. Erbauung als Aufgabe der Seelsorge bei Philipp Jakob Spener. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Halbfaß, Wilhelm. 1968. Descartesʼ Frage nach der Existenz der Welt. Untersuchungen über die cartesianische Denkpraxis und
Metaphysik. Meisenheim am Glan: Anton Hain Verlag.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Hartung, Gerald. 1999. Die Naturrechtsdebatte. Geschichte der Obligatio vom 17. bis 20. Jahrhundert. Munich: Verlag Karl Alber.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper & Row.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Heidegger, Martin. 2010. Being and Truth. Trans. Gregory Fried and Richard Polt. Bloomington, IN: Indiana UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Heineccius, Johann Gottlieb. 1746. Elementa juris naturae, et gentium. New edition. Venice.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Heineccius, Johann Gottlieb. 2008. A Methodical System of Universal Law: Or, the Laws of Nature and Nations with Supplements
and a Discourse by Geoge Turnbell. Trans. George Turnbull, ed. Thomas Ahnert and Peter Schröder. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Heinrich, Gerd. 1983. “Die Geisteswissenscha en an der brandenburgischen Landesuniversität Frankfurt/Oder um 1800.
Bemerkungen zu Studienangebot und Gelehrtenbestand der Hochschule Heinrich von Kleists vor ihrer Auflösung.” In Kleist-
Jahrbuch 1983. Ed. Hans Joachim Kreutzer. Berlin: Erich Schmidt. 71–97.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Hespe, Franz. 2007. “Der Grund der Verpflichtung in Christian Wol s Naturrecht.” In Wol iana II.3: Christian Wol und die
europäische Aufklärung. Ed. Jürgen Stolzenberg and Oliver-Pierre Rudolph. Hildesheim: Georg Olms. 273–91.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
p. 275 Hesse, Johann Gustav Wilhelm. 1757. De egoismo morali. Dissertation. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Hill, Thomas E., Jr. 1971. “Kant on Imperfect Duty and Supererogation.” Kant-Studien 62. 55–76.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Hobbes, Thomas. 1668. Leviathan, sive, De materia, forma, & potestate civitatis ecclesiasticae et civilis. Amsterdam.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Hochstrasser, Timothy. 2004. Natural Law Theories in the Early Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Hruschka, Joachim. 1987. “Strafe und Strafrecht bei Achenwall—Zu einer Wurzel von Feuerbachs psychologischer
Zwangstheorie.” Juristenzeitung 42. 161–9.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Hruschka, Joachim. 1995. “Die Nötigung im System des Strafrechts.” Juristenzeitung 50. 737–45.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Hruschka, Joachim. 2004. “Zurechnung seit Pufendorf. Insbesondere die Unterscheidungen des 18. Jahrhunderts.” In Kaufmann
and Renzikowski 2004. 17–27.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Hüning, Dieter. 2004a. “Christian Wol s ʻallgemeine Regel der menschlichen Handlungen.ʼ Über die Bedeutung des
Vollkommenheitsprinzips in Wol s Moralphilosophie.” In Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics 12. 91–
113.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Hüning, Dieter. 2004b. “Christian Wol s Begri der natürlichen Verbindlichkeit als Bindeglied zwischen Psychologie und
Moralphilosophie.” In Die Psychologie Christian Wol s. Systematische und historische Untersuchungen. Ed. Oliver-Pierre Rudolph
and Jean-François Goubet. Berlin: de Gruyter. 143–67.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Hüning, Dieter. 2015. “Gesetz und Verbindlichkeit—Zur Begründung der praktischen Philosophie bei Samuel Pufendorf und
Christian Wol .” In Das Band der Gesellscha . Verbindlichkeitsdiskurse im 18. Jahrhundert. Ed. S. Bunke, K. Mihaylova and
D. Ringkamp. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. 37–58.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Hüning, Dieter. 2019. “Christian Wol s Konzeption der Verbindlichkeit. Eine Antizipation der Ethik Kants?” In Rivero 2019a. 15–
34.
Hüning, Dieter. 2021. “In-Between Psychology and Moral Philosophy: Christian Wol ʼs Principle of Natural Obligation” In The
Force of an Idea. New Essays on Christian Wol ʼs Psychology. Ed. Saulo de Freitas Araujo, Thiago Constâncio Ribeiro Pereira, and
Thomas Sturm. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. 153–74.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Hymers, John. 2004. “Regrounding the Just Warʼs ʻPresumption Against Violenceʼ in Light of George Weigel.” Ethical Perspectives
11(2–3). 111–21.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Irwin, Terence. 2004. “Kantian Autonomy.” In Agency and Action. Ed. John Hyman and Helen Steward. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
137–64.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Irwin, Terence. 2009. The Development of Ethics. A Historical and Critical Study. Vol. 3: From Kant to Rawls. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Jorati, Julia. 2017. Leibniz on Causation and Agency. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kain, Patrick 2004. “Self-Legislation in Kantʼs Moral Philosophy.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 86. 257–306.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Kant, Immanuel. 1963. Lectures on Ethics. Trans. Louis Infield. Forward by Lewis White Beck. New York: Harper Torchbook.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. 1992. Theoretical Philosophy: 1755–1770. Ed. David Walford and Ralf Meerbote. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. 1996a. Practical Philosophy. Ed. and trans. Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. 1996b. Religion and Rational Theology. Ed. and trans. Allen W. Wood and George Di Giovanni. Cambridge:
Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
p. 276 Kant, Immanuel. 1997. Lectures on Ethics. Ed. and trans. Peter Heath and John B. Schneewind. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Ed. and trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. 1999. Correspondence. Ed. and trans. Arnulf Zweig. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. 2000. Critique of the Power of Judgment. Ed. and trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambidge
UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. 2004. Vorlesung zur Moralphilosophie. Ed. Werner Stark. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. 2007. Anthropology, History and Education. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Trans. Mary
Gregor, Paul Guyer, Robert B. Louden, Holly Wilson, Allen W. Wood, Günter Zöller, and Arnulf Zweig, ed. Günter Zöller and
Robert B. Louden. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. 2015. Réflexions sur la philosophie moral. Précédé de A.G. Baumgarten, Principes de la philosophie pratique
première. Trans. and ed. with an introduction by Luc Langois, in collaboration with Matthieu Robitaille and Émilie Jade-Poliquin.
Paris: Vrin.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kant, Immanuel. Forthcoming. Kantʼs Lectures on Moral Philosophy 1784–85: The Mrongovius II Notebook. Ed. Jens Timmermann
and Stefano Bacin. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kaufmann, Matthias, and Joachim Renzikowski (Eds). 2004. Zurechnung als Operationalisierung von Verantwortung. Frankfurt:
Peter Lang.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Klemme, Heiner F. 2007. “Werde vollkommen! Christian Wol s Vollkommenheitsethik in systematischer Perspektive.” In
Christian Wol und die europäische Aufklärung. Ed. Jürgen Stolzenberg and Oliver-Pierre Rudolph. Akten des 1. Internationalen
Christian-Wol -Kongresses (2004). Hildesheim: Olms. 163–80.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Klemme, Heiner F. 2011. “Johann Georg Sulzers ʻvermischte Sittenlehre.ʼ Ein Beitrag zur Vorgeschichte und Problemstellung von
Kants Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten.” In Johann Georg Sulzer 1720–1779: Aufklärer zwischen Christian Wol und David
Hume. Ed. Frank Grunert and Gideon Stiening. Berlin: de Gruyter. 309–22.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Klemme, Heiner F. 2013. “Kants Erörterung der ʻlibertas indi erentiae.ʼ In der Metaphysik der Sitten und ihre philosophische
Bedeutung.” In Internationales Jahrbuch des Deutschen Idealismus/International Yearbook of German Idealism. Vol. 9. (2011). Ed.
Fred Rush and Jürgen Stolzenberg. Berlin: de Gruyter. 22–50.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Klemme, Heiner F. 2014. “Freiheit oder Fatalismus? Kants positive und negative Deduktion der Idee der Freiheit in der
Grundlegung und seine Kritik an Christian Garves Antithetik von Freiheit und Notwendigkeit.” In Kants Rechtfertigung des
Sittengesetzes in Grundlegung III. Ed. Heiko Puls. Berlin: de Gruyter. 59–102.
Klemme, Heiner F. 2016. “Gewissen und Verbindlichkeit. Kants Idee eines ʻinneren Gerichtshofsʼ zwischen Christian Wol und
Adam Smith.” In Der innere Gerichtshof der Vernun . Ed. Saša Josifović und Arthur Kok. Leiden: Brill. 63–83.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Klemme, Heiner F. 2018. “How is Moral Obligation Possible? Kantʼs Principle of Autonomy in Historical Context.” In The
Emergence of Autonomy in Kantʼs Moral Philosophy. Ed. Stefano Bacin and Oliver Sensen. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 10–28.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Klemme, Heiner F. 2019. “How is Moral Obligation Possible? Kantʼs ʻPrinciple of Autonomy.ʼ In Historical Context.” In The
Emergence of Autonomy in Kantʼs Moral Philosophy. Ed. Stefano Bacin and Oliver Sensen. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 10–28.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Klemme, Heiner F. 2020. “ʻdaß mich Gott der Universität gewiedmet hätte.ʼ Christian Wol und die Erfindung der allgemeinen
praktischen Philosophie.” In Innovationsuniversität Halle? Neuheit und Innovation als historische und als historiographische
p. 277 Kategorien. Hallesche Beiträge zur Europäischen Aufklärung 63. Ed. Andreas Pecar und Daniel Fulda. Berlin: de Gruyter. 261–74.
Klippel, Diethelm. 2000. “Ideen zur Revision des Naturrechts. Die Diskussion zur Neubegründung des deutschen Naturrechts um
1780.” Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics 8. 73–90.
Google Scholar WorldCat
1 2 3
Köhler, Heinrich. 1729. 1732. 1738. Exercitationes iuris naturalis, eiusque cumprimis cogentis, methodo systematica propositi.
Jena. [later: Frankfurt.]
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Köhler, Heinrich. 1738. Meditationes und Annotationes über dessen Natur- und Völkerrecht. Ed. Johann Michael Hörselmann.
Jena.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Kuehn, Manfred. 2010. “Kantʼs Metaphysics of Morals: the History and Significance of its Deferral.” In Kantʼs Lectures on Ethics. A
Critical Guide. Ed. Lara Denis and Oliver Sensen. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 9–27.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Küenburg, Max. 1925. Ethische Grundfragen in der jüngst verö entlichten Ethikvorlesung Kants. Studie zur Geschichte der
Moralphilosophie. Innsbruck: Rauch.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Lamarra, Antonio, Roberto Palaia, and Pietro Pimpinella. 2001. Le prime traduzioni della Monadologieʻdi Leibniz (1720–1721).
Introduzione storica-critica, sinossi dei testi, concordanze contrastive. Florence: Olschki.
Langan, J. 1984. “The Elements of St. Augustineʼs Just War Theory.” The Journal of Religious Ethics 12(1). 19–38.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Lange, Joachim. 1724. Bescheidene und ausführliche Entdeckung der falschen und schädlichen Philosophie in dem Wol ianischen
Systemate Metaphysico von Gott, der Welt und dem Menschen. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Lange, Joachim. 1726. Nova anatome, seu idea analytica systematis metaphysici Wolfiani. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Lange, Joachim. 1734. Hundert und dreyßig Philosophische Fragen aus der neuen mechanischen Morale. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Langlois, Luc. 2019. “Der Begri der Verbindlichkeit bei Baumgarten und sein Einfluss auf Kants Moralphilosophie.” In Rivero
2019a. 35–50.
Lauterpacht, Hersch. 1975. “The Grotian Tradition in International Law.” In International Law: Being the Collected Papers of
Hersch Lauterpacht, vol. 2. Ed. E. Lauterpacht. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 307–65.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1667. Nova methodus discendae docendaeque jurisprudentiae. In Sӓmtliche Schir en und Briefe,
Sechste Reihe, Erster Band. 1990. Ed. Akademie der Wissenscha en der DDR. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag. 261–364.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1720. Essais de Theodicée, oder Betrachtung der Gütigkeit Gottes. Amsterdam and Hannover.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1744. Theodicee, das ist, Versuch von der Güte Gottes. Trans. Johann Christoph Gottsched. Hannover
and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1765. Nouveaux Essais sur lʼentendement humain. Saint-Empire.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1671–2. In Sӓmtliche Schir en und Briefe, Sechste Reihe, Zweiter Band. 1990. Ed. Akademie der
Wissenscha en der DDR. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag. 479–86.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1952. Theodicy. Ed. Austin Farrer and trans. E.M. Huggard. New Haven, CT: Yale UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1971. Briefwechsel zwischen Leibniz und Christian Wol . Aus den Handschri en der Koeniglichen
Bibliothek zu Hannover. Ed. Carl Immanuel Gerhardt, Halle. 1860. Reprint. Hildesheim: Olms.
Lenders, Winfried. 1979. “Nachwort.” In Philosophia practica universalis, pars posteriori. By Christian Wol . Gesammelte Schri en.
p. 278 Abteilung II, Bd. 11. Hildeshein: Olms. 835–49.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Locke, John. 1975. An Essay concerning Human Understanding. Ed. Peter H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Lorini, Gualtiero. 2016. “Till I die I will not remove mine Integrity from Me. On Kantʼs ʻAnthropologicalʼ Theodicy.” In Kantʼs Shorter
Writings: Critical Paths Outside the Critiques. Ed. R.V. Orden Jeménez, R. Hanna, R. Louden, J. Rivera de Rosales,
N. Sánchez Madrid. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing. 116–31.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Lorini, Gualtiero. 2019. “A Kingdom of God on Earth. Kantʼs Legacy on Church and State in German Idealism.” Giornale di
Metafisica 41. 278–98.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Lorini, Gualtiero. 2022. “Bewusstsein und innerer Sinn bei Baumgarten: ein Beitrag zu Kants Begri der Apperzeption?” In Kantʼs
Transcendental Deduction and the Theory of Apperception. New Interpretations. Ed. Giuseppe Motta, Denis Schulting, and
Udo Thiel. Berlin: de Gruyter. 93–111.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Lockwood, Thornton. 2022. “Ciceroʼs Philosophy of Just War.” In Cicero as Philosopher. Interpretation, Legacy, and Judgment.
Andree Hahmann and Michael Vazquez. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Luban, David. 2011. “War as Punishment.” Philosophy & Public A airs 39(4). 299–330.
Google Scholar WorldCat
McQuillan, Colin. 2017. “Clear and Distinct Ideas in Eighteenth Century Germany: Metaphysics, Logic, Aesthetics.” In Leibniz en
Dialogo. Ed. Manuel Sánchez-Rodríguez and Miguel Escribano. Seville: Themata. 149–60.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Meier, Georg Friedrich. 1744. Theoretische Lehre von den Gemüthsbewegungen überhaupt. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Meier, Georg Friedrich. 1754–9. Anfangsgründe aller schönen Wissenscha en. 2nd ed. 3 vols. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Meier, Georg Friedrich. 2007. Philosophische Sittenlehre. 2nd ed. 5 vols. 1762–74. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Meier, Georg Friedrich (Chair) and Johann Jacob Plitt (Author). 1747. Meditationes philosophicae de vita cognitionis ab eius
claritate, veritate et certitudine non necessario pendente. Dissertation. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Mendelssohn, Moses. 1764. “Abhandlung über die Evidenz.” In Gesammelte Schri en, Jubilämsausgabe. By Moses Mendelssohn,
ed. Fritz Bamberger et. al. Vol. 2. 1972. Schri en zur Philosophie und Ästhetik. Ed. Fritz Bamberger and Leo Strauss. Stuttgart-Bad
Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog. 267–330.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Mendelssohn, Moses. 1997. Philosophical Writings. Ed. Daniel O. Dahlstrom. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Miller, Christian B. 2019. “The Naturalistic Fallacy and Theological Ethics.” In The Naturalistic Fallacy. Ed. Neil Sinclair.
Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 206–25.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Mühlpfordt, Günter. 1986. Radikaler Wol ianismus. Zur Di erenzierung und Wirkung der Wol schen Schule ab 1735. In Christian
Wol 1679–1754. Interpretationen zu seiner Philosophie und deren Wirkung. Ed. Werner Schneiders. 2nd ed. Hamburg: Meiner.
237–53.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Müller, Ernst. 2004. Ästhetische Religiosität und Kunstreligion . In den Philosophien von der Aufklärung bis zum Ausgang des
deutschen Idealismus. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Musiał, Aleksandra, 2019. “Common Concepts of Immanuel Kantʼs ʻThe Perpetual Peaceʼ and The Charter of the United Nations.”
p. 279 Studies in Global Ethics and Global Education 10. 47–55.
Oberhausen, Michael and Riccardo Pozzo (Eds). 1999. Vorlesungsverzeichnisse der Universität Königsberg (1720–1804). 2 vols.
Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
OʼDriscoll, Cian. 2008. The Renegotiation of the Just War Tradition and the Right to War in the Twenty-First Century. New York:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Orend, Brian. 2008. “The Key to War: How ʻThe Metaphysics of Moralsʼ Unlocks Kantʼs Just War Theory.” Jahrbuch für Recht und
Ethik / Annual Review of Law and Ethics. 16. 183–201.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Osawa, Toshiro. 2018. “Kantʼs Debt to Baumgarten in His Religious Un‐Grounding of Ethics.” Kant Yearbook 10 1. 105–123.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Penner, Sydney. 2013. “Suárez on the Reduction of Categorical Relations.” Philosophersʼ Imprint 13 2.
http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.3521354.0013.002.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Peters, Hans Georg. 1934. Die Ästhetik Alexander Gottlieb Baumgartens und ihre Beziehungen zum Ethischen. Berlin: Junker und
Dünnhaupt Verlag.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Pimpinella, Pietro. 1993. “Baumgarten e le origini dellʼestetica.” In Meditationes philosophicae de nonnullis ad poema
pertinentibus di A. G. Baumgarten. Testo, indici, concordanze. Ed. Antonio Lamarra and Pietro Pimpinella. Florence: Olschki. 3–42.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Pimpinella, Pietro. 2001. “ʻCognitio intuitivaʼ bei Wol und Baumgarten.” In Vernun kritik und Aufklärung. Studien zur Philosophie
Kants und seines Jahrhunderts. Norbert Hinske zum siebzigsten Geburtstag. Ed. Michael Oberhausen. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt:
frommann-holzboog. 265–94.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Poppe, Bernhard. 1907. Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten: seine Bedeutung und Stellung in der Leibniz-Wol ischen Philosophie und
seine Beziehungen zu Kant. Borna-Leipzig: Noske.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Poser, Hans. 1980. “Die Bedeutung der Ethik Christian Wol s für die deutsche Aufklärung.” In Theoria cum praxi: Zum Verhältnis
von Theorie und Praxis im 17. und 18. Jahrhundert. Akten des III. Internationalen Leibniz-Kongresses, Hannover, 12. bis 17. 11. 1977.
Ed. Reinhard Finster and Albert Heinekamp. Vol. 1. Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner. 206–17.
Pufendorf, Samuel. 1991. On the Duty of Man and Citizen According to Natural Law. Trans. Michael Silverthorne. Cambridge:
Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Pufendorf, Samuel. 2003. The Whole Duty of Man, According to the Law of Nature. With commentary by Jean Barbeyrac. Ed.
Ian Hunter and David Saunders, trans. David Saunders. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Rauber, Jochen. 2009. “The United Nations—a Kantian Dream Come True? Philosophical Perspectives On The Constitutional
Legitimacy Of The World Organisation.” Hanse Law Review 5(1). 49–76.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Rauscher, Frederick. 2013. “Chaos and Control: The Nature of Practical Philosophy.” In Kant und die Philosophie in
weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses 2010. Ed. Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin,
Claudio La Rocca, and Margit Ru ing. Vol. 3. Berlin: de Gruyter. 559–70.
Reath, Andrew. 2006. Agency and Autonomy in Kantʼs Moral Theory. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Reiner, Hans and Wilhelm Halbfaß. 1972. “Egoismus.” In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Vol. 2. Ed. Joachim Ritter. Basel
and Stuttgart: Schwabe. 310–14.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Reusch, Johann Peter. 1734. Systema logicum antiquiorum atque recentiorum item propria praecepta exhibens. Jena.
p. 280 Rivero, Gabriel (Ed.). 2019a. Pflicht und Verbindlichkeit bei Kant. Aufklärung 30 (2018). Hamburg: Meiner Verlag.
Rivero, Gabriel. 2019b. “Von der Abhängigkeit zur Notwendigkeit. Kants Perspektivenwechsel in der Au assung der Verbindlichkeit
zwischen 1784 und 1797.” In Rivero 2019a. 217–36.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Rivero, Gabriel. 2021. “Dependence and Obedience. Crusiusʼ Concept of Obligation and its Influence on Kantʼs Moral Philosophy.”
In Christian August Crusius 1715–1775. Philosophy between Reason and Revelation. Ed. Frank Grunert, Andree Hahmann, and
Gideon Stiening. Berlin: de Gruyter. 301–17.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Rupp, Max. G. 1924. “Hugo Grotius and His Place in the History of International Peace.” Catholic Historical Review 19(3). 358–66.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Sala, Giovanni B. 2004. “Das Reich Gottes auf Erden. Kants Lehre von der Kirche als ʻethischem gemeinem Wesen.ʼ” In Kants
Metaphysik und Religionstheorie. Ed. Norbert Fischer. Hamburg: Meiner. 225–64.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Scattola, Merio. 2003. “Before and a er Natural Law. Models of Natural Law in Ancient and Modern Times.” In Early Modern
Natural Law Theories. Contexts and Strategies in the Early Enlightenment. Ed. Tim Hochstrasser and Peter Schröder. Dordrecht:
Springer. 1–30.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Scattola, Merio. 2008. “Die Naturrechtslehre Alexander Gottlieb Baumgartens und das Problem des Prinzips.” Aufklärung 20.
239–65.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Schierbaum, Sonja, Michael Walschots, and John Walsh (Eds). 2024. Christian Wol ʼs German Ethics. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schierbaum, Sonja. 2022. “Christian Wol über motivierende Gründe und handlungsrelevante Irrtümer.” Archiv für Geschichte
der Philosophie 104. 131–63.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Schilpp, Paul Arthur. 1938. Kantʼs Pre-Critical Ethics. Evanston: Northwestern UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schloemann, Martin. 1974. Siegmund Jacob Baumgarten . System und Geschichte in der Theologie des Überganges zum
Neuprotestantismus. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schmucker, Josef. 1961. “Die Ursprünge der Ethik Kants.” Monographien zur philosophischen Forschung. Vol. 22. Meisenheim am
Glan: Verlag Anton Hain.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schneewind, Jerome. 1993. “Kant and Natural Law Ethics.” Ethics 104. 53–74.
Schröder, Jan. 1995. “Einleitung.” In Elementa iuris naturae/Anfangsgründe des Naturrechts. By Gottfried Achenwall and Johann
Stephan Pütter, trans. and ed. Jan Schröder. Frankfurt: Insel Verlag.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 1995. Das Problem des Glücks in Denken Christian Wol s . Eine quellen-, begri s- und
entwicklungsgeschichtliche Studie zu Schlüsselbegri en seiner Ethik. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog.
Schwaiger, Clemens. 1999. Kategorische und andere Imperative: zur Entwicklung von Kants praktischer Philosophie bis 1785.
Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2000. “Ein ʻmissing linkʼ auf dem Weg der Ethik von Wol zu Kant: Zur Quellen- und Wirkungsgeschichte der
Praktischen Philosophie von Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten.” In Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics.
Ed. B. Sharon Byrd, Joachim Hruschka, and Jan C. Joerden. 8. 257–61.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2001. “Die Anfänge des Projekts einer Metaphysik der Sitten. Zu den wol ianischen Wurzeln einer
kantischen Schlüsselidee.” In Akten des IX. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Ed. Volker Gerhardt, Rolf-Peter Horstmann, and
Ralph Schumacher. Berlin: de Gruyter. 52–8.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2005. “Christian Wol s ʻPhilosophia practica universalis.ʼ Zu ursprünglichem Gehalt und späterer Gestalt
einer neuen Grundlagendisziplin.” In Macht und Bescheidenheit der Vernun . Beiträge zur Philosophie Christian Wol s. Ed.
p. 281 Luigi Cataldi Madonna. Hildesheim: Olms. 219–33.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2008. “Baumgartens Ansatz einer philosophischen Ethikbegründung.” Aufklärung 20. 219–37.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2009. “The Theory of Obligation in Wol , Baumgarten, and the Early Kant.” In Kantʼs Moral and Legal
Philosophy. Ed. Karl Ameriks and Otfried Hö e. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 58–73.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2011a. Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten—ein intellektuelles Porträt. Studien zur Metaphysik und Ethik von
Kants Leitautor. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2011b. “Philosophie und Glaube bei Christian Wol und Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten.” Aufklärung 23.
213–27.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2012. “Gottfried Achenwall.” In Dictionary of Eighteen-Century German Philosophers. Ed. Heiner Klemme
and Manfred Kuehn. Online Version, Oxford Reference. London: Continuum.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2016a. “Alexander Gottlieb Baumgartens Begri der Religion im Spannungsfeld von Wol ianismus und
Pietismus.” In Religion und Aufklärung. Akten des Ersten Internationalen Kongresses zur Erforschung der Aufklärungstheologie
(Münster, 30. März bis 2. April 2014). Ed. Albrecht Beutel and Martha Nooke. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. 437–47.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2016b. “Zwischen Laxismus und Rigorismus. Möglichkeiten und Grenzen philosophischer Ethik nach
Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten.” In Schönes Denken. Baumgarten im Spannungsfeld zwischen Ästhetik, Metaphysik und
Naturrecht. Ed. Andrea Allerkamp and Dagmar Mirbach. Hamburg: Meiner. 255–70.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2018a. “Baumgartenʼs theory of freedom. A contribution to the Wol -Lange controversy.” In Baumgarten
and Kant on Metaphysics. Trans. John Hymers, ed. Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers. Oxford: Oxford UP. 42–60. Chapters 4
and 5 of Schwaiger 2011a.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2018b. “Wol s Vollkommenheitsbegri im Kreuzfeuer pietistischer Kritik.” In Perfektionismus und
Perfektibilität. Theorien und Praktiken der Vervollkommnung in Pietismus und Aufklärung. Ed. Konstanze Baron and Christian
Soboth. Hamburg: Meiner Verlag. 53–74.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2020. “Achenwalls Theorie der Verbindlichkeit. Quellen- und entwicklungsgeschichtliche Erkundungen.”
Rechtsphilosophie 6. 337–51.
Schwaiger, Clemens. 2021. “Das Wesen des Moralischen bei Christian Wol und Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten.
Begri sgeschichtliche Erkundungen.” In Kulturen der Moral : Beiträge zur DGEJ-Jahrestagung 2018 in Paderborn. Ed.
Kristin Eichhorn and Lothar van Laak. Hamburg: Meiner Verlag. 54–65.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Schwitzke, Heinz. 1930. Die Beziehungen zwischen Ästhetik und Metaphysik in der deutschen Philosophie vor Kant. Dissertation.
Berlin.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Sedylitz, Christian Gotthold. 1765. Tractatus philosophicus de moralitate actionum, tam obiectiva quam subiectiva. Copenhagen.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Sensen, Oliver. 2015. “Moral Obligation and Free Will.” In Kantʼs Lectures on Ethics: A Critical Guide. Ed. Lara Denis and
Oliver Sensen. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 138–55.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Sheridan, Patricia. 2020. “Lockeʼs Moral Philosophy.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Edward N. Zalta.
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/locke-moral (accessed December 11, 2023).
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
p. 282 Sportelli, Silvano. 2003. “ʻEgoismoʼ metafisico ed ʻegoismoʼ morale nel XVIII secolo.” Dianoia 8. 159–82.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Straumann, Benjamin. 2003/2004. “Appetitus societatis and oikeiosis: Hugo Grotiusʼ Ciceronian Argument for Natural Law and
Just War.” Grotiana (new series) 24–26. 41–66.
WorldCat
Stern, Robert. 2012. Understanding Moral Obligation: Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Strube, Werner. 2000. “Baumgartens Ästhetik als Transformation seiner Theorie des Gedichts.” In Texte − Bilder − Kontexte.
Interdisziplinäre Beiträge zu Literatur, Kunst und Ästhetik der Neuzeit. Ed. Ernst Rohmer, Werner Wilhelm Schnabel, and
Gunther Witting. Heidelberg: Universitätsverlag Winter. 21–41.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Sutor, Johannes Paul. 1774. Allgemeine praktische Weltweisheit. Ein Versuch für die Philosophie in Bayern. Jena.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Suárez, Francisco. 2015. Selections from Three Works. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Swi , Louis J. 1970. “St. Ambrose on Violence and War.” Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association
101. 533–43.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Tesón, F.R. 1992. “The Kantian Theory of International Law.” Columbia Law Review 92(1). 53–102.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Thorpe, Lucas. 2019. “Kant on the ʻGuarantee of Perpetual Peaceʼ and the Ideal of the United Nations.” Dokuz Eylül University
Journal of Humanities 6(1). 223–245.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Thümmig, Ludwig Philipp. 1725–6. Institutiones philosophiae wol ianae in usus academicos adornatae. 2 vols. Frankfurt and
Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Tomassini, Fiorella. 2018. “Kantʼs Reformulation of the Concept of Ius Naturae.” Idealistic Studies 48. 257–74.
Tonelli, Giorgio. 1959. “Der Streit über die mathematische Methode in der ersten Häl e des 19. Jahrhunderts und die Entstehung
von Kants Schri über die Deutlichkeit.” Archiv für Philosophie 9. 37–66.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Updated Statute Of The International Criminal Tribunal For The Former Yugoslavia. 2009. International Tribunal for the
Prosecution of Persons Responsible for Serious Violations of International Humanitarian Law Committed in the Territory of the
Former Yugoslavia since 1991. Online: https://www.icty.org/x/file/Legal%20Library/Statute/statute_sept09_en.pdf. Last
accessed: August 1, 2023.
WorldCat
Van Der Mandere, H.G.H. 1925. “Hugo Grotius—Founder of International Law. Current History (1916–1940) 22(3). 439–46.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Van Itterssum, Martine Julia. 2016. “Hugo Grotius: The Making of a Founding Father of International Law.” In The Oxford
Handbook of the Theory of International Law. Eds. Anne Orford and Florian Ho mann. Oxford: Oxford UP. 82–100.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Villiez, Carola Freiin von. 2015. “Nötigung, moralische.” In Kant-Lexikon. Ed. Marcus Willaschek, Jürgen Stolzenberg, Georg Mohr,
and Stefano Bacin. Berlin: de Gruyter. 1677–8.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Walschots, Michael. Forthcoming. “Incentives of the Mind: Kant and Baumgarten on the Impelling Causes of Desire.” Archiv für
Geschichte der Philosophie.
Walschots, Michael. 2024. “Wol on the Duty to Cognize Good and Evil.” In Christian Wol ʼs German Ethics. Ed. Sonja Schierbaum,
Michael Walschots, and John Walsh. Oxford: Oxford UP. 219–36.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Walsh, John. 2024. ʻWol on Natural Obligation.” In Christian Wol ʼs German Ethics. Ed. Sonja Schierbaum, Michael Walschots,
and John Walsh. Oxford: Oxford UP. 105–28.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Waltzer, Michael. 2015. Just and Unjust Wars. 5th ed. New York: Basic Books.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Ward, Keith, 1972. The Development of Kantʼs View of Ethics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
p. 283 Watkins, Eric. 2014. “What is, for Kant, a Law of Nature?” Kant-Studien 105. 471–90.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Weigel, George. 2003. “Moral Clarity in a Time of War.” First Things 128. 20–27.
Google Scholar WorldCat
Wiebecke, Ferdinand. 1967. Die Poetik Georg Friedrich Meiers. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der Dichtungstheorie im 18. Jahrhundert.
Dissertation. Göttingen.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Wol , Christian. 1703. Philosophia practica universalis, mathematica methodo conscripta. Leipzig.
1 14
Wol , Christian. 1712–13. 1754. Vernün ige Gedanken von den Krä en des menschlichen Verstandes und ihrem richtigen
Gebrauche in Erkenntnis der Wahrheit. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
1 2
Wol , Christian. 1718. 1735. Ratio praelectionum wolfianarum in mathesin et philosophiam universam. Halle.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
1 4
Wol , Christian. 1720. 1733. Vernün ige Gedancken von der Menschen Thun und Lassen, zu Beförderung ihrer Glückseeligkeit.
Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
1 11
Wol , Christian. 1720. 1751. Vernün ige Gedancken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen
überhaupt. Den Liebhabern der Wahrheit mitgetheilet. New, expanded edition. Halle.
1 4
Wol , Christian. 1724. 1740. Anmerckungen über die vernün igen Gedancken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen,
auch allen Dinge überhaupt, zu besserem Verstande und bequemeren Gebrauche derselben. Halle and Frankfurt 1740.
1 2
Wol , Christian. 1726. 1733. Ausführliche Nachricht von seinen eigenen Schri en die er in deutscher Sprache von den
verschiedenen Theilen der Welt-Weißheit herausgegeben, auf Verlangen ans Licht gestellet. Frankfurt.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Wol , Christian. 1729–41. Horae subsecivae Marburgenses. 3 vols. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
1 2
Wol , Christian. 1730. 1736. Philosophia prima seu ontologia methodo scientifica pertractata, qua omnis cognitionis humanae
principia continentur. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
1 2
Wol , Christian. 1732. 1738. Psychologia ermpirica, methodo scientifica pertractata. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
1 2
Wol , Christian. 1734. 1740. Psychologia rationalis, methodo scientifica pertractata. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Wol , Christian. 1738–9. Philosophia practica universalis, methodo scientifica pertractata. Parts I-II. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Wol , Christian. 1740–8. Ius naturae methodo scientifica pertractatum. 8 vols. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
3
Wol , Christian. 1746. Philosophia rationalis sive Logica, methodo scientifica pertractata et ad usum scientiarum atque vitae
aptata . Praemittitur d iscursus praeliminaris de philosophia in genere. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Wol , Christian. 1750–3. Philosophia moralis sive ethica, methodo scientifica pertractata. 5 vols. Frankfurt and Leipzig.
Wol , Christian. 1763. Anfangsgründe aller Mathematischen Wissenscha en. Vol. 1. Vienna.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Wol , Christian. 1934. Ius Gentium Methodo Scientifica Pertractatum. Volume Two: The Translation. Ed. and trans. Joseph H. Drake
. Oxford: Clarendon.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Wol , Christian. 2019. Über den Unterschied zwischen einem systematischen und einem nicht-systematischen Verstand: Lateinisch-
p. 284 Deutsch. Trans. and ed. by Michael Albrecht. Hamburg: Meiner.
Wunderlich, Falk. 2021. “Wol on Monadology and ʻMaterialisterey.ʼ” In The Force of an Idea: New Essays on Christian Wol ʼs
Psychology. Ed. Saulo de Freitas Araujo, Thiago Constâncio Ribeiro Pereira, und Thomas Sturm. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
105–19.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Zedler, Johann Heinrich. 1732–54. Grosses vollständiges Universal-Lexicon aller Wissenscha en und Künste. Halle and Leipzig.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Zimmermann, Johann Liborius. 1728. De actionum humanarum moralitate nec non de obligatione iuris, legibusque stricte dictis
dissertatio philosophica, in qua celeberrimi Prof. Wol ii principia nonnulla moralia examinantur. Jena: Litteris Buchianis.
Google Scholar Google Preview WorldCat COPAC
Baumgarten and Kant on the Foundations of Practical Philosophy
Courtney D. Fugate (ed.), John Hymers (ed.)
https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192873538.001.0001
Published: 2024 Online ISBN: 9780191976162 Print ISBN: 9780192873538
END MATTER
Index
Published: June 2024
For the bene t of digital users, indexed terms that span two pages (e.g., 52–53) may, on occasion, appear on
only one of those pages.
abnegation 252–253
Achenwall, Gottfried 15, 159–160, 223–224, 228–232, 235–236, 242, 259–260
action
external 23n.25, 155, 214, 217–218
free 5, 9–10, 31n.62, 42, 47, 62–65, 68, 75–76, 80–83, 94n.10, 94n.12, 96–97, 101, 141–142, 155–156,
164–165, 168, 175–176, 182, 192–193, 205, 217, 224–226, 228, 266n.68
future 3–4, 146, 154–155, 258–259
in conformity with laws 184, 199–200
moral 23–24, 54, 92, 115–116, 123–124, 127–128, 146, 206–207, 233–234
physical 12–13, 143, 154–155
aesthetics 8–9, 17–18, 26–27, 41n.119, 54–55, 58, 108–109, 177–178
agent (free, moral, or rational) 11–12, 51–53, 57, 111, 117, 134–135, 137–139, 151, 174, 184, 205
Aletheophilus 41
Anscombe, Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret 142, 241
anthropology 38n.97, 57, 71n.4, 106, 129, 212n.5
anti-voluntarism 21, 109, 126–127
aporia 120–121, 142–143, 146–149, 154
Aristotle, Aristotelian 28, 141–142, 243–244, 261–262
arithmetic 43–45
armies 256n.33, 264n.61, 267
arms 246–248, 255–257
astronomy 48, 187–188
atheism 96–97, 100, 104–105, 113, 204n.2, 205–206, 246–248, 248n.18, 248n.18
Augustine, St. 246–248, 252–253, 263–264
aversion 25–26, 40n.113, 43–44, 74–75, 79, 82–83, 253, 259–260
belief 24–25, 124, 130
rational 120, 125
blessedness 251n.27
bliss 42, 47–48
body 78, 80–81, 162–164, 168, 174–180, 208, 211–212, 229–230, 251n.27
cause, impelling 3–4, 33, 40, 49–50, 54, 57–58, 78–84, 88–89, 108, 133, 169–170, 204–206, 211–212, 226
certainty
complete, objective 141–143, 148
mathematical 47n.15
moral 41n.115, 44–45, 99–100, 205–206, 258–259
of cognition 14, 25–26, 39–40
of conscience 136
of natural right 210
subjective 152–158
chastity 178–179
choice, free 86, 96–99, 112, 151, 167, 170–171, 191–192, 201, 204–205, 208–209, 212, 214, 216, 219
Cicero 51, 182–183, 183n.3, 245–248, 252–253, 257–258, 260n.50, 263–264, 266–267
coercion 15, 62–64, 170n.9, 205, 225n.4, 227, 229–231, 237–238, 256–257
cognition (knowledge)
dead 11–12, 24–25
lifeless 25–26
living 7–8, 11–12, 23–27, 40, 108–109, 111
moral 24–26, 182n.2
moving 25–26
rational 111, 223
self-cognition 40–41, 49–50, 139, 175–177
sensitive 26, 189
command 87, 95–96, 125, 127, 130, 175–176, 226–228, 233, 235–236, 266n.68
divine 11–12, 97, 104–105, 113n.11, 124–126, 129–130, 236n.19, 264
moral 233, 235
con ict 10–11, 20–21, 49–50, 133–134, 154–155, 219, 264n.60
conscience 7, 12, 47–48, 129–140, 148, 175–177, 208, 257–258
best 12, 132
light 135
micrological 135, 138
moral 12, 47–48, 53n.36
p. 286 perfect and imperfect 135
proportionate and disproportionate 135
servile 135
consciousness 27, 37–38, 52–53, 123–125
consensus 45–46, 162, 164–165, 226–227
constraint
external 77, 80–81, 85n.31, 86, 205, 220
external moral 81–82, 205
internal moral 81–82, 88–89, 205
moral 63–64, 81–83, 86–89, 205
physical 80–81
self- 3–4, 9–10, 85–86, 172–173, 235n.17
contradiction 44–45, 66, 67n.21, 87, 112, 118, 125, 147, 214–215, 219, 233
cosmology 181, 183n.4, 198–199
cosmopolitanism 15–16, 242n.4, 243–244, 267
court 130, 134–139, 149, 157, 175–176, 207, 251n.26
competent 245–246
civil 208
divine 208
external 12, 131, 208
internal or inner 131, 136, 138–140, 208
International Criminal Court, the 265n.63
crime 122–123, 138, 242, 265–266
against God 248n.18
of aggression 242, 262n.56
of fortune 132
Crusius, Christian August 60n.7, 89n.36, 114, 163–164, 236
culpability 132, 149–151, 243–244
deduction of moral law 117–121
deed 12, 95–96, 130–133, 135–137, 140, 149–152, 155–157, 175–176, 207
external 208
imputation of 131, 155, 258–259
internal 208
Descartes, René 44–46, 48n.19
determination
free 22–23, 33, 54, 63, 78–82, 97–99, 108–109, 155, 162, 169–170, 191–192, 195n.18, 205, 211–212,
226–227
self- 22–23, 75, 117
determinism, psychological 84, 88–89
dignity 52–53, 57
dilemma
Euthyphro 91, 105
moral 133–134, 139–140
Dio Cassius 11–12, 106, 127
displeasure 9–10, 83
duty
conformity to 148–149, 151
ethical 13–14, 134, 159–160, 168–177, 228, 238
exercise of 23–24, 28, 39–40
external 206–207, 210–211, 220, 227–228, 253, 262n.55
false 23n.28, 34
free 220
imperfect 13–14, 57–58, 159–160, 168–172, 174–179, 206–207, 222
internal 32–33, 206–207, 219–221, 227, 253, 262–263
juridical 13–14, 159–160, 170–172, 174–175, 220, 225–226, 228, 231, 238–240
moral 28, 34, 116, 120, 130, 148, 173, 221
perfect 13–14, 169, 170n.10, 171–172, 174, 176–177, 179, 203, 222, 255
supererogatory 171–172
to oneself 13–14, 24, 39–41, 126, 159–160, 166–168, 171–172, 174–178, 219, 222, 225–226
to others 13–14, 39–40, 126, 220, 222, 225–226
to religion 251–252
to God See God, duties to
Eberhard, Johann August 2, 129
economics 42, 60, 250–251
edi cation 24, 39–40, 44n.4
education 163–164, 167, 188
egoism, moral See also solipsism7–8, 36–39
end(s)
established by pure reason 235, 238
external 57
kingdom of 117, 164–165, 183–185, 199–201
natural 179, 185, 201, 224, 231–233, 235
of pure practical reason 235n.17
rational beings as ends in themselves 164–165, 172–173
enemies 250, 254–255, 263–264
Enlightenment, the 18, 21n.17, 24n.32, 38n.101, 41–43, 45–46, 229
Enlightenment, the Pietist 28, 112
enlightenment, moral 25–26, 186–187
Epicurus, Epicureanism 3–4, 163–164, 167
error
avoidance of 155
in imputation 156–157
moral, or error in moral judgment 49–52, 132, 136–139, 156
theoretical-speculative of God 122–123
ethics
chimerical 8–9, 23, 34
deceptive 23n.28, 34n.76
sexual 178–179
Euclid 45, 51
Eudaimonism 106
Euthyphro See dilemma, Euthyphro
p. 287 experience 5–6, 25–26, 45, 47–48, 61–62, 76–77, 83, 118, 122–125, 148–149, 157, 177–178, 186–187,
189, 191, 193, 197–198
extortion 169–172, 205–206, 209, 255, 257–260
fables 54–55
faculty
appetitive 20n.12, 22, 32n.69, 175–176, 178–179, 211–212
cognitive 22, 56n.43, 189
faculties of the soul 173
inferior cognitive faculties 22–23
of moral judgment 132, 136–138
faith 11–12, 24n.30, 54n.37
good faith 267
philosophy and ethics as known without 5–6, 11–12, 19–20, 32–33, 53, 60, 99–100, 111–112, 191, 210,
225–226
pure, of reason 123
re ecting 124
feeling
disinterested 218
moral 114, 163–164, 167, 175–176, 220–221
of pleasure 118, 163
of respect 57, 70
physical 163–164
ction(s) 94
useful 244n.10, 248–249
nitude, human 8–9, 10n.18, 40–41, 88–89, 100–101, 119, 153–155, 158, 190, 193n.14
formalism, moral 162, 164n.5
fortune 132–133, 215
Francke, August Hermann 7–8, 40
freedom
exercise of 143, 164–165, 172–173
external 14–15, 211–212, 214, 217–219, 222, 231–232
internal 211–212, 214, 217–219
perfection of 168, 200
gnoseology 11–12, 109, 117, 121
God See also postulate of practical reason
as archetypal 190–191, 197, 205–206
celebration of 39n.106
cognition of 11–12, 24, 39–40, 111, 115–116
duties to 11–12, 24, 39–41, 111n.8, 121, 124–127, 195–197, 225–226, 251–252
fear of 242–248
idea of 120, 124–125, 175
good, the 6–7, 20–21, 28, 49–53, 62–64, 66–67, 73–80, 84, 101–102, 109–110, 161–163, 182–183, 197–
198, 205, 211, 213, 215, 224–225, 234
imperative to commit, do, or furnish the 49–50, 67–69, 101–102, 109–110, 161–162, 210–211, 226–
227, 228n.9, 233–234
unconditional 4n.9, 199–201
goodness, moral 11–12, 110, 162–163, 195n.18, 197–199, 201, 218
Gottsched, Johann Christoph 27, 60–61, 66–67
government 163–164, 167, 221, 267
gratitude 134, 159–160
Grotius, Hugo 15–16, 97, 169, 224–225, 235–236, 242–249, 252–253, 255–256, 259–260, 263–267
ground, determining 3–4, 22, 109–110, 121, 123, 146, 163–164, 173, 183, 190, 196, 198–200, 251n.27, 253
habituation 49–50, 94–95, 205
happiness 3–4, 11–12, 36, 42, 47–48, 51–52, 57, 113, 125, 168, 171–176, 200, 202, 207–208, 211, 215–217,
219–221, 229, 236, 251n.27
of others 36, 126, 167, 171–174, 216–217, 219, 222, 235
relation to ethics 7–8, 11–12, 19–20, 31–32, 49–50, 107, 109–110, 114, 118–120, 122, 130, 163–164, 168,
233
worthiness of 118, 120, 125, 130, 168, 200, 216
harm 15–16, 139–140, 206–207, 228, 243–249, 252–263
culpable 243–244
external 206–207, 210
future 255–259
imperative to harm nobody 210–211, 253–254, 260–261, 265–266
harmony, pre-established 67–68, 190, 208
hatred, penitential 41
heautophilia 36n.90, 175–176
Helvétius, Claude Adrien 167
heteronomy 69, 114, 116
Hobbes, Thomas 21, 66, 108, 167, 225–226, 245n.13, 246n.14, 265n.65, 266–267
holiness 121–123
honesty 123, 131–132
honor, honorableness 37n.94, 52–53, 57, 207–208, 210, 264
God’s honor 37–38
hostility 252–253, 259, 262n.56
humanity
end or right of in one’s own person 168–169, 172–173, 179–180, 217
Hutcheson, Francis 114, 163–164, 167
idolatry 36–37, 246–248, 248n.18
ignorance 132, 145, 153
invincible 246–248
imagination 173, 177–178
immortality 118–119, 177n.14
p. 288 imperative
as Baumgarten’s innovation 7–8, 33–36
categorical 2–4, 11–12, 61–62, 69–70, 87, 117–118, 120–121, 125, 143, 145–152, 161–162, 164–165, 185,
200
hypothetical 2, 69, 125
Kant’s de nition of 85
moral 7–8, 86, 88, 91–92, 110, 216, 226–227, 233–234
imperfections, one’s own 36, 175–176
impiety, as cause of war 246–248, 255–256
impossible, morally 7–8, 23, 34, 63, 78–80, 133, 143, 155, 161–162
impulse 23–24, 86–88, 148, 215, 220
natural 50–51
sensitive 7–8, 22–25, 33, 173
imputability 132–133, 155
imputation 7, 52–53, 130–135, 139–140, 142, 154–155, 207
moral 12–14, 47–48, 149–152, 155–158
physical 12–13, 151–152, 155–156, 158
incentives 22, 24–25, 27, 33, 40, 78–79, 82–84, 108–109, 123, 148, 212–213
moral 102–103
inclination 20–21, 28, 66–70, 72–73, 85–89, 114n.12, 144–145, 164–165, 167–168, 199–200, 213, 215–219,
221, 233–235
innocence 12, 131–132, 138, 241, 253–255
intellect 61n.8, 74n.14, 87, 94, 136, 243–244, 251n.27
intellectualism 25–27, 186, 192–193, 201–202
irenicism 250
injury 246–248, 253–254, 256n.31, 259n.42, 260–261
judge, the 121, 131, 134–135, 137–138, 140, 149, 265
judgment
best 12, 137
imputational 151–152, 156–157
moral 12–13, 41n.115, 115, 130–132, 135–138, 141–151, 154–156, 164–165, 182, 218, 220–221, 241, 249
practical 148–149, 149n.4, 151
knowledge See cognition
Köhler, Heinrich 3n.5, 7–8, 15–16, 18–19, 21n.19, 30–35, 36n.89–90, 36n.91, 39–40, 52, 94–95, 98n.23,
108, 112, 224n.2, 229, 242n.3, 244n.10, 245n.11, 246–249, 248n.19, 252–253, 255–258, 258n.41, 259–262,
264–267
Lange, Joachim 35–37
law
author of 114, 115n.14, 116, 125–126
Baumgarten’s de nition of 205–206
civil 220, 225n.3, 243–244, 260n.49
criminal 129
conformity to 63, 184, 199–200, 218, 220
divine 113n.11, 191–192, 204n.2, 236, 265
external 206–213, 219–220, 227–228, 250, 258
external moral 209, 227
internal 207–209, 211, 220–221
internal moral 227–228, 248–249
moral 4–6, 11–14, 47–48, 53, 57–59, 62–63, 68–70, 85–89, 103–104, 112–122, 124, 127–128, 132, 138,
145–149, 151, 155, 162–163, 174–176, 181–183, 185–189, 191–192, 199–200, 204–207, 209, 211–212,
214–215, 221, 223–224, 226–233, 236
natural law 2n.3, 4–7, 11–12, 42, 46–48, 49n.23, 52, 57, 91, 96n.20, 107, 113–114, 150–152, 181, 183n.3,
186–188, 191–192, 195–196, 209, 223–224, 229–231, 235–236, 251, 260n.49
natural laws 5, 56–57, 99n.25, 112–115, 191–195, 195n.18, 200–201, 209, 225n.4, 229–231, 235–236,
245–246, 265
objective laws of reason 71–72, 84–85, 144
physical 202
practical 4, 120–121, 125, 145–146, 164–165, 214, 226, 236–237
positive 99n.25, 112, 191–192, 204n.2, 209–211, 223, 235–236, 239–240, 243–246, 265
unconditional 123
lawgiver See legislator
laxity, moral 34
legislation 113–114, 125, 139
self- 111–120
legislator (lawgiver) 51n.29, 57, 113–117, 120–121, 123–125, 130, 220, 235–236, 265–266
distinct from author of law 114, 115n.14, 116, 126
supreme 126
Leibniz, Gottfried 9–10, 21–23, 27, 30n.58, 36, 43–47, 48n.19, 59n.2, 60–61, 66–68, 70, 75, 108, 185–187,
192, 225–226
Theodicy 60–61, 67, 75–76, 120–121
leniency 138, 254–255
Locke, John 44–46, 182, 224–225
Mandeville, Bernard 163–164, 167
mathematics 42–46, 48–52, 188
of intensive qualities 109, 192–193, 197
mathesis universalis 43–45, 47, 51
matrimony 178–179
maxim 4, 12–13, 53, 59, 85, 115–116, 123, 144–149, 151, 155, 166–167, 170–173, 179–180, 183–185, 193–194,
231–232, 236–237
Meier, Georg Friedrich 2, 23n.28, 24n.30, 25n.35, 25n.37, 26n.40, 30n.57, 31n.59, 34, 35n.87, 36n.91, 43n.2,
49n.26, 51n.32, 52n.34, 54n.37, 54n.39, 59–61, 65, 68, 91n.2, 94–95, 96n.20, 129, 266n.68
p. 289 Mencke, Otto 43–44, 46–47
Mendelssohn, Moses 160
mildness 254–255, 261–262
Montaigne, Michel de 163–164, 167
moral proof 122–123
morality
external 95
internal 94n.12, 95–98, 181–182
natural 96n.20, 101
objective 10–11, 90–105, 198n.20
subjective 10–11, 91–92, 98–102
motives
internal 222
psychological 57
rational 24–25, 33, 79n.22, 108–109, 233
sensuous 3–4
nature
conformity with 226–227
kingdom of 164–165, 184–185, 201
physical 192
state of 243–246, 246n.14, 248–249, 251, 259, 264–267
supersensible 184–185, 202
necessitation 7–9, 11–12, 20–23, 33–34, 54, 59–73, 80–81, 84–89, 108, 116n.17, 117, 173
necessity
hypothetical 80, 193–194
moral 20–21, 33–34, 63–68, 108, 266–267
natural 155, 233
objective 59
physical 193–194
unconditional 57
Neumann, Caspar 44–45
norms 45–46, 56–57, 149, 227
Baumgarten’s de nition of 190
external and internal 206
moral 101, 141, 205–206, 209
natural 192
practical 12–13, 33–34, 100–101, 141–143, 148–150, 152, 154, 156–158
obligation
active 20–21, 33n.70, 108
author of 11–12, 113, 116, 235–236
ethical 11–12, 172–173, 238–239
external 204–205, 209, 227, 238–239
imperfect 229–230
internal 32n.67, 204–205, 220, 227, 238–239, 248–252
juridical 237–239
moral 3–4, 11–12, 19, 22–23, 33–34, 49–50, 55, 60–62, 68, 72n.5, 77n.20, 88–89, 108–109, 111, 114,
126, 130, 226–227, 229, 232
natural 9–10, 62, 71–75, 74n.16, 77–78, 81–83, 88–89, 100, 209, 226, 230–231, 237
passive 20–21, 20n.16, 33n.72, 230–231
perfect 229–231
positive 51n.29, 78, 157, 209
psychologization of 7–8, 11–12, 21, 34, 108–109
unconditional 4n.9
o ense 246–248, 254, 257–262
ontology 6–7, 31, 50–51, 192–193
order
intelligible 119, 121
natural 184, 191, 226–227, 263n.59
Osawa, Toshiro 72n.7, 110–111, 124
paci sm 241, 252–253, 260–261
peace 15–16, 245–246, 248–255, 263–264, 266–267
peacemaker 253–254
perfection
as agreement 109, 186–188, 190, 198
determining ground of 196, 198, 251n.27, 252–253
external 253
imperative to seek 4, 34–35, 101–102, 109–110, 161–162, 192, 210–211, 218, 226–227, 228n.9, 229–
230, 253
internal 162
moral 86–87, 118–119, 175–177, 186–187, 197–200, 202
natural 14, 159–160, 175–176, 179, 186–188, 190–192, 197, 199–202
principle of 14, 36–37, 110
self- 13–14, 159–160, 171–176, 179–180, 219
supreme 110
perfectionism, moral 3–4, 6–7, 13–14, 159–164, 167–168, 181–182, 185–186, 195–198, 200–202, 204
Wol an 181–182, 185–186
philautia 36–37, 36n.90, 176–177
philosopher, role of the
Pietism 6–9, 17–18, 24, 27–28, 35–37, 39–41, 112–113
placability 248–249, 255
Plato 252–253, 261–264
poetry 27, 54–55
postulate of practical reason
God as 11–12, 118–120, 123, 125
immortality of the soul as 119, 177n.14
precepts 21, 51–52, 169n.8, 233–234
of right of nature 227–228, 249, 261–262
principle(s)
ethical 123–124, 224
rst 4–6, 31n.62, 34, 34n.81, 42, 47–48, 49n.26, 52–53, 56n.43, 109, 160–164, 190, 192–193, 210, 227–
228, 253–254, 261–262
rst domestic 53, 227–228
juridical 223, 239–240
p. 290 moral 6n.13, 8–9, 12–14, 34–35, 45, 87, 110, 127, 162, 182–183, 185, 187–188, 199–200, 233–234
objective 145, 210–211, 228n.9
of autonomy 59–60, 68–69, 116n.17
of contradiction 66, 112
of ethics 235
of morality 69n.25, 120–121, 129, 144, 159–164, 166–168
of moral judgment 218, 220–221
of obligation 69
of perfectionism 161–162, 200
of self-defense 266–267
subjective 145–147, 210
supreme principle of morality 69, 120–121, 143, 237
probabilism 153–154
proper-love 36
Pufendorf, Samuel 21, 108, 142–143, 169, 193, 224–226, 266–267
punishment 3–4, 15–16, 47–48, 51n.29, 65, 72–75, 77–78, 88–89, 115–116, 149–152, 156–157, 169n.8,
235–236, 242–244, 246–248, 253–254, 257–258, 262–267
fear of 21, 77
natural 265
rationalism 6–9, 41n.119, 53, 119–120, 235–236
moral 112
Wol an 7–8, 24n.30, 90–91, 104, 113n.11
realism
moral 10–11, 95–96, 104
war 241
reason, analogue of 189, 192–193, 197
reward 3–4, 21, 47–48, 51n.29, 57, 65, 113, 115–116, 120–122, 149–150, 152, 156
right
distinguished from ethics 214
divine positive 112, 120, 211
doctrine of 15, 30, 159n.1, 166–167, 171–172, 178–179, 221, 227n.7, 231–232, 235n.17, 236–237, 239–
240
of humanity 168–169, 172–173, 217
of nations 243–246, 250, 265–266
of nature / natural right 15–16, 19–21, 30–33, 52–53, 107, 112–114, 120, 207, 209n.4, 210–213, 223–
241, 243–249, 251, 253–254, 260n.49, 264–267
of war 242, 245–246, 248–250
positive 32–33
Schiller, Friedrich 72–73, 86–87
self-examination 41, 148
Seneca 243–244
sensibility 18, 24–25, 33, 39, 68–69, 85, 108–109, 150, 162–163, 233
sexual intercourse 178–179
Shaftesbury, Lord (Anthony Ashley Cooper) 167
skepticism 47, 142, 152–153, 158
slavery
moral 41, 188–189
to the senses 52
solipsism See also egoism37–38
stealing 74–75, 75n.18, 77, 206–207
Stoicism 3–4, 45–46, 50, 127, 163–164, 181–183, 187–188, 192, 197, 202, 227, 233, 243–244
Suárez, Francisco 182
suicide 171–172, 174, 178–179, 219, 222
syllogism 45–46, 49n.26, 189
imputational 156–157
tautological, Kant’s criticism of Baumgarten’s ethics as 4, 110, 161–162, 200, 233–234
teleology 99–100, 104, 184, 187–188, 235
temperance 178–179, 254
textbooks
Baumgarten’s use of 19, 30–31
Kant’s use of 1–3, 5n.10, 14–15, 17, 29, 56, 60, 71–72, 129, 162, 172–173, 197, 223–224, 232, 236
theodicy See also Leibniz, Gottfried120, 123
theology 50–51, 126–127
ethico- 24n.32, 39n.106
moral 19–20, 30n.56, 106, 111–113, 113n.11, 120–121, 211
natural 52, 56–57, 71n.4, 99–100, 111–112, 121, 129, 160, 192–193, 197
revealed 124
Thomas Aquinas, St. 147n.3, 243–244, 252–253, 260n.52
Thomasius, Christian 19, 224–225, 224n.2
Tschirnhaus, Ehrenfried Walther von 44–45
Ulpian 210, 227–228, 260n.50
Vitoria, Francisco de 246–248
war 15–16, 241–267
defensive 256–257, 262–264
license to 242
o ensive 246–248, 261–262
punitive 246–248, 262–267
will
free 3–4, 14, 65, 76–77, 96n.20, 98–99, 118–119, 146, 181, 200–202, 205, 211–212, 215, 233, 260n.52
good 11–12, 59–62, 68–69, 133
holy 59, 68, 85, 145
wisdom 45–46, 49–50, 58, 66n.20, 122–123, 131–132
p. 291 Wol , Christian
adversaries of 10–11, 30–31, 35, 97, 100
Ausführliche Nachtricht von seinen eigenen Schri ten 44n.4, 50n.28, 90–91, 97, 101n.28, 187–188, 194
German Ethics 21n.19, 22n.22, 24n.33, 35n.82, 49–50, 62, 67n.23, 73–77, 97, 100, 101n.28, 108, 109n.6,
111n.8, 112, 187–188, 193, 196
German Metaphysics 6–7, 22n.22, 35n.88, 62, 73–77, 85–86, 194–195
German Logic 24n.33
Ius naturae methodo scienti ca pertractatum 36n.90, 107, 243–246, 245n.13
Philosophia moralis, sive ethica, methodo scienti ca pertractata 32n.69, 36n.90, 109n.6
Philosophia practica universalis, methodo scienti ca pertractata 20n.13, 20n.16, 21n.19, 23n. 27, 24n.33,
25n.36, 33n.70, 34n.81, 45n.9, 49–51, 53, 55n.40, 74–77, 101n.28, 108, 224–225
Preliminary Discourse 20n.12, 32n.69, 43–44, 48n.19, 50–51, 266n.68
Psychologica empirica, methodo scienti ca pertractata 6–7, 22n.22, 35n.88, 74, 109n.5, 189, 194–195
Ratio praelectionum wol anarum in mathesin et philosophiam 24n.33
universam 24n.33, 47–48, 111n.8
Wol anism, Baumgarten’s break from 7–9, 17–18, 110
p. 292 world, intelligible 118, 120–121, 184–185, 202