Reading Capital's Materialist Dialectic
Reading Capital's Materialist Dialectic
Editorial Board
volume 318
By
Nick Nesbitt
leiden | boston
The terms of the cc license apply only to the original material. The use of material from other sources
(indicated by a reference) such as diagrams, illustrations, photos and text samples may require further
permission from the respective copyright holder.
This book was written as part of the grant project ga19–20319s “From Bolzano to Badiou. An Investigation
of the Foundations of Historical Epistemology and Modern European Philosophy”, supported by the Czech
Science Foundation and coordinated by the Institute of Philosophy of the Czech Academy of Sciences in
Prague, and benefitted as well from the support of Princeton University.
Typeface for the Latin, Greek, and Cyrillic scripts: “Brill”. See and download: brill.com/brill‑typeface.
issn 1570-1522
isbn 978-90-04-54868-8 (hardback)
isbn 978-90-04-70359-9 (e-book)
doi 10.1163/9789004703599
Copyright 2024 by The Institute of Philosophy, Czech Academy of Sciences. Published by Koninklijke Brill
bv, Leiden, The Netherlands.
Koninklijke Brill bv incorporates the imprints Brill, Brill Nijhoff, Brill Schöningh, Brill Fink, Brill mentis,
Brill Wageningen Academic, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, Böhlau and V&R unipress.
Koninklijke Brill bv reserves the right to protect this publication against unauthorized use.
References 267
Index 281
1 Wark 2019.
2 Walmart made $11.68B profit and McDonalds $6.88B profit in 2023 (Forbes “The Global 2000”,
June 8, 2023).
3 Wark 2019, pp. 5, 11, 48.
4 Wark 2019, p. 41.
5 ‘The wealth of societies in which the capitalist mode of production prevails appears as an
“immense collection of commodities”’ (Marx 1976, p. 125).
6 Alexis 1955/1982, pp. 8, 10, 11, my translation. All further translations are my own unless oth-
erwise indicated.
7 Nesbitt 2022, p. 265.
8 Wood 2002.
Wood argues that the commodification of food is nonetheless the crucial fac-
tor that forces the sale of labour power, the only commodity, Marx shows, that
can produce and accumulate surplus value.9
We can, however, repurpose the historicist argument of Wood’s Political
Marxism to indicate as well a general limit of the capitalist social form, in the
sense of its endpoint, beyond which some other social form would exist: when
it is no longer the case that we require a general equivalent – whether paper,
metal coin, or its onscreen cipher – to purchase commodified food and shelter
and other commodities essential to life, then, and despite all the intervening,
subsidiary modifications to its functioning, capital will be a thing of the past,
and something else, whether communism or catastrophe, will have replaced
it. The social production, distribution, and exchange of food and shelter, in this
view, thus indicates more than a mere transhistorical human right; in addition,
it constitutes a specific neuralgic point at which the capitalist social form finds
both its weakest links and real limit.
To theorise such limits, this book remains faithful to Althusser’s rejection of
a general, even universal concept of practice as such, to investigate instead the
singular category of Marx’s theoretical practice, developing a position I will call
political epistemology.10 While the political stakes of the adequacy or inade-
quacy of knowledge are no doubt immediately familiar and compelling in this
age of fake news, gaslighting, and Trumpist populism, to grasp the limits of
capitalism more specifically, to know, in other words, when, how, and under
what conditions we might exit from the capitalist social form, requires the
and Political Economy’ in that volume is the lone exception that, in its explicit
engagement with Marx’s critique of political economy, proves the rule of this
general tendency. On a more personal note, when in 2017 I edited a volume ded-
icated to assessing the legacy of Reading Capital, I was quite surprised when
not one of the distinguished contributions to that volume elected to discuss
the reading of Marx’s Capital after Althusser.15 This is to say that while there
continues to be no shortage of readers of both Capital and Althusser, few and
far between are those who since 1965 have pursued the epistemological project
of Reading Capital.
In contrast to this long-standing disregard for the specificity of Reading Cap-
ital’s object, when reading Capital with (and beyond) Althusser, epistemology
becomes political in the preliminary but consequential sense that Marx’s the-
oretical practice, in its capacity to produce adequate – as opposed to merely
imaginary or ideological – knowledge of the real complexity of the capitalist
social form, consequently produces subjects of that knowledge.16
To read Capital in the terms Althusser first proposed, refusing ontological
guarantees, presuppositions, and imaginary assertions of monism and totality,
is to assume only the single presupposition that initiates Marx’s demonstration:
that we, subjects of capital, always already have a true idea of the nature of cap-
italism – a minimal, raw, merely apparent idea, but a true one nonetheless: that
the capitalist social form is characterised by the accumulation of commodities
and the generalisation of their exchange.17 From this single, immanent starting
15 Nesbitt 2017. Robert J.C. Young’s chapter in that volume does briefly review the com-
plex publication history of the first volume of Capital in its implications for the concept
of symptomatic reading, but without engaging an explicit reading of Marx’s text per se
(Young 2017, pp. 36–9).
16 This is the general thesis Jean Matthys argues in Althusser lecteur de Spinoza: Genèse et
enjeux d’une éthico-politique de la théorie (Matthys 2023, p. 343).
17 In the 1975 ‘Soutenance d’Amiens’, Althusser underlines the crucial importance of the
Spinozist presupposition Habemus enim ideam veram for the entirety of a theoretical posi-
tion dedicated to the rejection of any and all a priori methodological guarantees: ‘Que veut
dire en substance Spinoza, quand il écrit la phrase célèbre : “Habemus enim ideam veram
?” … C’est en effet parce que, et seulement parce que nous détenons une idée vraie, que
nous pouvons en produire d’autres, selon sa norme. … C’est un fait, que nous la détenons
(habemus), et de quoi que ce soit que ce fait soit le résultat, il inscrit d’avance toute thé-
orie de la connaissance … sous la dépendance du fait de la connaissance détenue. Par là
toutes questions d’Origine, de Sujet ou de Droit de la connaissance, qui soutiennent les
théories de la connaissance sont récusées’ (Althusser 1998a, p. 218). Althusser refers to the
Emendation of the Intellect, where Spinoza writes: ‘A true idea (for we do have a true idea)
is something different from its object (ideatum). A circle is one thing, the idea of a circle
another. For the idea of a circle is not something having a circumference and a centre, as
is a circle, nor is the idea of a body itself a body’.
18 The relative neglect of Etienne Balibar’s writings in this book is not due to any disinter-
est in Marx’s masterpiece following Balibar’s initial contribution to Reading Capital. To
the contrary, and in contrast to both Macherey and Badiou, Balibar has continued to reaf-
firm the necessity of reading Capital as an unending task: ‘Are we still, will we always be,
“reading Capital”? No doubt; and we are beginning to understand that, as with every truly
great theoretical oeuvre (Hegel’s, for example), our task is by its nature endless because the
meaning we are looking for can only be found at the point where questions formulated on
the basis of current events (or even current emergencies) encounter contradictions that,
in latent fashion, haunt the writing of the text that we have to set back in motion’. That
said, Balibar’s interest in Marx remains primarily and explicitly political, to the neglect
of the epistemological problems of reading Capital that this book will explore: ‘The goal
I am pursuing [in rereading Capital], however, is not (if it ever was) purely epistemo-
logical. I am trying to shed light on the thorny question of the various conceptions of
politics, their irreducible plurality, and the choices they dictate’. Balibar 2015a, p. 205,
translation modified. Thanks to Josef Fulka for reminding me of Balibar’s masterful and
penetrating analysis of the final section of Capital in the third chapter of Violence and
Civility.
19 Althusser et al. 2015, p. 51 (henceforth rc).
creative power of the real in its immanent, ‘structural’ causality, whether that
power is grasped in the attribute of thought or material extension.20
Never a systematic thinker, Althusser was instead a semeur d’idées, and it
has been left to his readers to test and deploy those manifold ideas as to their
degree of creative productivity. It is certainly the case that Althusser does not
explicitly link Marx’s ‘apodictic’ method to Spinoza in Reading Capital, nor
even say the first word about what actually makes Marx’s demonstration ‘apo-
dictic’ (the latter task falling in part to Pierre Macherey in his long-forgotten
chapter for Reading Capital). Instead, I will take him at his word – ‘Nous étions
spinoziste’, he famously declared of the Reading Capital collective, and again,
publicly declaring to colleagues in 1967, ‘Je suis spinoziste’21 – and follow Vit-
torio Morfino’s injunction to ‘go beyond Althusser, but with Althusser’, to show
that when systematically developed, Althusser’s undemonstrated claim for the
Spinozist ‘apodicticity’ of Capital is in fact correct.22
While a thinker of polemical genius, Althusser – unlike Spinoza, Marx,
Macherey, or Badiou – never developed his countless insights into systematic,
large-scale works on the model of Ethica or Capital, but instead sought contin-
uously to refuse all reassuring guarantees of knowledge and desired to sustain
theoretical practice in a state of perpetual enquiry, critique, and questioning.
As such, his thought seems in hindsight destined never to have produced the
affect Spinoza called beatitude, and instead fitfully to signify and elicit, à ses
risques et perils, the distressing yet simultaneously exhilarating positions of
both uncompromising desire and apprehension before the absence of the law
that Lacan called anxiety (l’angoisse).23
20 Macherey has said of the Althusserian project in which he participated that ‘Spinoza was
that which, for us, bridged epistemology and politics: by returning to theoretical prac-
tice its consequential reality [poids de réalité], insofar as it made of it an order of reality
unto itself. It seemed to us by that token to open perspectives for practical investment, the
dynamic of thought simultaneously acting in reality’ (Macherey 1999, p. 24).
21 Althusser 1974. In his correspondence with Franca Madonia, Althusser describes Spinoza
as ‘mon unique maître’, and again as ‘le plus grand [philosophe] de tous, à mes yeux’.
Althusser 1998b, pp. 528, 579.
22 Morfino 2022, p. 86.
23 Lacan 2016. See McNulty 2009. Spinoza was the decisive formative thinker for Lacan, who
discovered him at the age of 14, at which point ‘he hung a diagram on the wall of his bed-
room that depicted the structure of the Ethics with the aid of colored arrows’ (Roudinesco
1995, p. 11). Spinoza then became the central conceptual reference for Lacan’s 1932 the-
sis, at which point the Ethics offered him the means to formulate a monist materialist
intervention in psychology based on the traditional ‘parallelist’ reading of the Spinozist
attributes. Subsequently, for example in the 1962–63 seminar Anxiety, Lacan’s position,
while no longer explicitly citing Spinoza, would reject the monist phantasy of an episte-
If, as Tracey McNuty has suggested, ‘anxiety is the affect that responds to
the desire of the Other’,24 the aggressive resistance this uncompromising desire
tends to provoke (think for example of Freud’s Moses, Robespierre, or more
recently Jean-Bertrand Aristide) can tell us much about the ongoing demonisa-
tion of Althusser. Equally, it can help to explain Althusser’s own initial, uncom-
promising theoretical intervention (as the Other of Marxist philosophy) as well
as his own subsequent theoretical anxiety to the point of self-destruction in his
relation to the proletarian Other. Like Moses, Robespierre, and Freud before
him, Althusser desired ruthlessly to destroy an existing god and clergy and to
construct a new, impossible object for his people: in Althusser’s case, these were
the god that was ‘Man’ for Marxist humanism, along with the Party who repre-
sented Him; the object he sought to produce, a fully adequate construction of
Marx’s philosophy, shorn of all phantasmatic Hegelian guarantees of monist
totality and the Absolute. The price he paid for this uncompromising interven-
tion is well-known.
Althusser, intensive and singular reader of Spinoza and Marx, without re-
serve pushed Spinozist thought to its furthest limit, a point where substance
is understood not as Absolute Subject, as an imaginary Abwermechanism (de-
fence) against the anxiety of not knowing, nor as reified monism (Plekhanov),
indeed, not as a thing at all. Instead, Althusser’s esoteric, unpublished writings
show that he decisively redefines substance as the infinite order of causal con-
nection within a contingent historical field (the capitalist social form), an order
existing only in the immanent immediacy of its situated effects – though I will
argue that this order can be made to nonexist through acts of theoretical for-
malisation such as the modes of schematic formalisation Marx introduces into
later drafts of Capital.
It is precisely here, I will argue, at this limit-reading of Spinoza, that Al-
thusser’s intuition of a Marx-Spinoza co-determination manifests its decisive
originality: if the logic of capital is not a whole, not a substantial thing to be
reified as an imaginary monist totality, it is nonetheless the case that this struc-
ture can be made to nonexist, produced in the attribute of thought, in other
words, as what Spinoza calls a nonexistent thing.25 This, then, is the ultimate
tendency of Marx’s original process of exposition in Capital that Althusser’s
intuition first began fitfully to construct in Reading Capital and that this book
mological whole in terms doubtless attractive for Althusser, to argue instead that ‘logic
henceforth has the essentially precarious function of condemning the real to eternally
stumble [trébucher] within the impossible’ (Lacan 2016, p. 78, translation modified).
24 McNulty 2009, p. 7.
25 eiip8.
project Althusser first called for in his 1947 thesis, i.e., to read Capital as a theory
of the ‘transcendental’ structural determinations of the capitalist social form,
Badiou objectively displacing and refiguring Althusser’s initial, undeveloped
claim that ‘Capital is our transcendental analytic’.28 I thus take Badiou’s ‘sci-
ence of appearance’ to indicate, in Marx’s terms, the science of the necessary
forms of appearance of all things of value (commodities) in the capitalist social
form, the logic, that is to say, of our world.
It would not have been possible to complete this project without the ines-
timable support of Etienne Balibar, Rok Benčin, Nathan Brown, Harrison Fluss,
Landon Frim, Josef Fulka, Peter Hallward, Roman Kanda, Ivan Landa, Jean
Matthys, Warren Montag, Vittorio Morfino, Charlie Post, and Panagiotis Sotiris,
and at Brill hm, Danny Hayward and Marlou Meems. At the imec, discus-
sions with François Bordes crucially helped test and develop these arguments,
and Allison Demailly offered invaluable assistance obtaining manuscripts from
Althusser’s archive. In Prague, my colleagues at the Philosophical Institute –
including Ivan Landa, Petr Kužel, Jana Berankova, Michael Hauser, and Joe
Grim Feinberg – continue to offer invaluable intellectual inspiration, as well
as critical perspectives on my arguments on Marx, Althusser, Badiou, and
Bolzano. Others for whose assistance, insights, and support I am grateful
include Emily Apter, Alain Badiou, Banu Bargu, Riccardo Bellofiore, Yann
Moulier Boutang, Svenja Bromberg, Rebecca Comay, Chad Córdova, Sam Diio-
rio, Maxfield Evers, Jackson Smith, Ruo Jia, Elena Louisa Lange, Philippe Le
Goff, Rob Lehman, Jacques Lezra, Tracey McNulty, Gregor Moder, Donald
Moerdijk, Alberto Moreiras, Bertrand Ogilvie, Knox Peden, Seth Rogoff, Max
Tomba, Gabriel Tupinambá, McKenzie Wark, Audrey Wasser, and Szymon Wró-
bel. Love and gratitude above all to Eva Cermanová.
Earlier versions of two of these chapters have previously appeared: Chap-
ter 2 in the volume Pierre Macherey and the Case of Literary Production (Warren
Montag and Audrey Wasser, eds., copyright © 2022 by Northwestern Univer-
sity), and Chapter 5 as ‘Capital, Logic of the World’ (Filosovski Vestnik fv xlii 2).
This book was written as part of the grant project ga19–20319s ‘From Bol-
zano to Badiou. An Investigation of the Foundations of Historical Epistemology
and Modern European Philosophy’, supported by the Czech Science Founda-
tion and coordinated by the Institute of Philosophy of the Czech Academy of
Sciences in Prague, and benefitted as well from the support of Princeton Uni-
versity.
rc Reading Capital: The Complete Edition, by Louis Althusser, Etienne Balibar, Roger
Establet, Pierre Macherey, and Jacques Rancière. Translated by Ben Brewster and
David Fernbach, New York: Verso, 2015.
lc Lire le Capital, by Louis Althusser, Etienne Balibar, Roger Establet, Pierre Mache-
rey, and Jacques Rancière, Paris: puf, 1996 [1965].
References to Spinoza’s Ethics will take the standard form: E, followed by sec-
tion, proposition, and subdivision of the proposition: appendix (A), corollary
(C), demonstration (D), definition (Def), lemma (L), proposition (P), scholium
(S). E vp39s, for instance, refers to Ethics, section 5, proposition 39, scholium.
1 The most notable exception to this striking neglect is perhaps Jacques Bidet’s Exploring
Marx’s Capital (2006). While authors such as Chris Arthur continue to assert the Hegelian
negative dialectical nature of Marx’s demonstrations, generally with only highly selective
citation of the text, it is striking how Michael Heinrich’s How to Read Marx’s Capital (2021), in
closely reading the first seven chapters of Capital line by line, actually concludes – without
ever mentioning Althusser or Reading Capital – that Marx’s process of exposition is in fact
an additive synthetic one without negative dialectical sublation of the categories, precisely
as Althusser and Pierre Macherey first claimed in 1965. The Althusserian tenor of Heinrich’s
argument is hardly surprising, as Vittorio Morfino has shown that Heinrich’s debt to Althusser
is much greater than the handful of citations – both positive and negative – to be found in
The Science of Value (2022 [1999]). In fact, Morfino shows that Althusserian categories are
crucial to Heinrich’s argument in his principal work: ‘Si infatti il nome “Althusser” appare con
parsimonia e sempre con misura critica, lo stesso non si può dire di tre concetti althusseriani
che hanno une presenza ubiqua all’interno del testo: … Bruch (rottura), … theoretisches Feld
(campo teorico), … e Problematik (problematica)’. Morfino 2023, p. 121. Heinrich’s analysis will
prove crucial to the post-Althusserian reading of Capital I will develop in Chapter 3. Thanks
to Vittorio Morfino for sharing his text ahead of its publication.
Etienne Balibar has repeatedly testified to this event, arguing that Read-
ing Capital ‘inscribed Marxism within the history of French philosophy in
the … 20th century’, its intervention forcing the human sciences more gener-
ally to ‘take Marxism seriously [as] a horizon and challenge for contemporary
thought’.2 In addition to this crucial historical accomplishment, however, this
book argues that Reading Capital marked a commanding, situated theoretical
intervention, an intervention on the Kampfplatz of the absolute, as it promul-
gated a Spinozist project of political epistemology, seeking at once to relegate
all (Hegelian) forms of negative dialectic and contradiction to their rightful
domain – existence – and to grasp the demonstration of the essential nature of
the capitalist real as a singular world in its eternal, infinite nature.
This book argues that the core epistemological3 claim of Reading Capital (‘In
Capital we find … an apodictic arrangement of the concepts in the … demon-
strational discourse that Marx calls analysis’) did not disappear as an object of
post-Althusserian theory, but instead shifted terrain: from an initial attention
in Reading Capital devoted to the literal text of Capital itself, this claim became
instead a more abstract theoretical object of investigation. No longer situated
and nominally defined as a non-Hegelian mode of reading Marx’s text itself,
the Althusserians, and above all Pierre Macherey and Alain Badiou, nonethe-
less objectively sustained the theoretical project initiated by Reading Capital at
a higher level of abstraction, henceforth defined as the theoretical imperative
to produce the concept of a positive materialist dialectic. Crucial texts such as
Badiou’s Logics of Worlds or Macherey’s essay ‘En matérialiste’ (both to be dis-
cussed in subsequent chapters) explicitly develop this notion of a materialist
dialectic in opposition as much to the Stalinist notion of dialectical materialism
as to Hegelian negative dialectics.
This book will track this concept of a positive, materialist dialectic across
various facets and moments in the writings of Spinoza, Marx, Althusser,
Macherey, and Badiou, to construct this thought object, as Althusser famously
enjoined, as the overdetermined, dynamic complexity of a theoretical force
field or constellation, a conceptual structure whose reality exists in the dis-
cursive effects produced by the heterogeneous deployments it has received. I
do so in the conviction that these varying epistemological interventions con-
2 Balibar 2018, p. 6.
3 Taking into account Althusser’s warning, in the Eléments d’autocritique, against a specula-
tive, idealist tendency inherent to the notion of epistemology (1974, p. 176n30). Jean Matthys
notes that Althusser tends to prefer the phrase ‘théorie de la pratique théorique’ to ‘episte-
mology’ due to the dominant associations of the latter with traditional theories of knowledge
(Matthys 2023, p. 237).
‘this form of reasoning is perfectly integrated within the geometric method, and is particu-
larly apt when it is a question of treating objects that – due to their absolute nature which
completely contains [renferme] their reality within themselves – seem to refuse a demonstra-
tional approach that considers causes [since these] would as such be given within themselves
[données en eux-mêmes]’ (Macherey 2001 [1998], p. 246).
6 Morfino 2022, pp. 87–8.
7 In the case of Spinozist substance, Macherey takes extraordinary care to indicate this trans-
versal, ramified network of the demonstration of general causality at every moment in his
five-volume analysis, a concern that culminates in his highly complex schematic represen-
tation of this rhizomatic logical system in the appendix to volume one of his Introduction,
‘The Demonstrative Network of the Ethics’. Macherey 2001 [1998], pp. 277–359. For every def-
inition, axiom, postulate, proposition, corollary and scholium in the five books of the Ethics,
Macherey carefully indicates both the anterior sequences by which each is justified, as well
as the ensuing claims that will depend upon it in turn for their own justification.
8 The most famous of these blanket condemnations is undoubtedly E.P. Thompson’s 1978 ful-
minating historicist polemic The Poverty of Theory, in which Thompson sees fit to dismiss
Althusser’s thought as a ‘freak’ dedicated to an ‘ahistorical theoreticism, … a structuralism
of stasis’, although Thompson begins by freely admitting that ‘I don’t understand Althusser’s
propositions as to the relation between the “real world” and “knowledge”’, which is to say, the
entire basis of Althusser’s epistemological position (Thompson 1987, pp. 17, 20, 21). While in
retrospect Thompson’s historicist diatribe is surprising mainly in its length and vehemence
(‘starting moderately and ending in a gale of fury’, Perry Anderson observes [1980, p. 4]), even
insightful and sympathetic studies of Althusser have tended to sustain this condemnation of
the ‘theoreticism’ of Reading Capital. Anderson’s own famous response to Thompson, his 1980
essay Arguments within English Marxism, in fact begins by endorsing Thompson’s empiri-
cist condemnation of theoreticism, to conclude, without analysis, that Althusser’s ‘theory
of knowledge, dissociated from the controls of evidence, is untenably internalist’ (Anderson
1980, p. 7). Similarly, in his groundbreaking 1987 book Althusser, The Detour of Theory, Gre-
gory Elliott proposes that ‘the cause defended by Althusser some twenty years ago [i.e., in
For Marx and Reading Capital] – the axiomatic scientificity of Marxism – cannot be cham-
pioned today’ (Elliott 1987, p. 45). Why is this the case, the reader might ask? Elliott provides
no theoretical reasons relating to the adequacy, or not, of this axiomatic position in relation
to the object of Marx’s analysis in Capital (the capitalist social form), but instead argues that
‘the vicissitudes of contemporary history [circa 1987]’ have shown that ‘Marxism has proven
fallible’ (1987, p. xxii). The correctness of a theoretical position, in other words, is to be judged
based on its ability to read the tea leaves of the future, or, as Engels famously put the matter
in Socialism: Scientific and Utopian, ‘The proof of the pudding is in the eating’. Althusser’s
Spinozist position in Reading Capital (Verum index sui et falsi) might instead take the alter-
nate form: ‘The proof of the pudding is in … the pudding’. All three of these quite different
and famous studies of Althusserianism share this focus on the materialist historiography of
capitalism (historical materialism), while tending to ignore the theoretical status of Capital
as the abstract analysis and exposition of the theoretical categories determining the capitalist
social form (on the latter, see Heinrich 2021, p. 39).
9 It was only in the final phases of revising this manuscript that I discovered Jean Matthys’
brilliant study Althusser lecteur de Spinoza, perhaps the only other monograph in the liter-
ature on Althusser to affirm the fundamental validity of the ‘theoreticist’ epistemological
positions of For Marx and Reading Capital. Thanks to Jean Matthys for sharing the pre-
publication manuscript of his book.
10 eivp1.
11 For recent, thoughtful examples, see Hegel’s Logic and Marx’s Capital: A Reconsideration
(Moseley and Smith 2014); Chris Arthur’s The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital (2002) and
The Spectre of Capital: Idea and Reality (2022).
12 rc, pp. 2, 11.
13 rc, p. 50.
14 Balibar 2018, p. 6. It was of course Althusser himself who identified in his autocritique the
‘deviation’ of a ‘theoreticist tendency’ in For Marx and Reading Capital, noting that the
majority of critics had instead wrongly seen these as works of ‘structuralism’ (Althusser
1998a, pp. 177–81).
15 Althusser 1974. Althusser’s revisionist position was first articulated in 1967 in the lectures
collected as ‘Philosophy and the Spontaneous Philosophy of the Scientists’ (2012).
16 Althusser 1968, p. 5.
17 Ironically, Althusser’s slogan is a perfect and explicit example of precisely the ‘traditional
theory of knowledge’ he repeatedly condemned, a mode of thought universally depen-
dent upon the principle of reason as the demand that the theoretical object adequately
represent or reflect the empirical. Althusser would in turn vehemently critique this very
theoretical orientation in Etre marxiste en philosophie in 1977 (to be discussed below).
Both Vincent Descombes (1980, pp. 134–5) and Gregory Elliott (1987, pp. 194, 222) anal-
yse Althusser’s turn to the position of ‘class struggle in theory’ as a theoretical regression
from the radically novel propositions of For Marx and Reading Capital. Jean Matthys calls
for readers of Althusser to ‘nuance’ the epistemologically extreme positions of Reading
Capital with a ‘more “politicist” conception in which political practice serves as prior
and posterior determination [fait office d’amont et d’aval] for Marxist science’, whereas
I wish to argue that the position of ‘class struggle in theory’ constitutes an unambigu-
ous regression from the political epistemology of Reading Capital that Matthys elsewhere
champions without reserve (2023, p. 292).
18 This in contrast to recent studies that have tended to emphasise the often-subterranean
continuity of thought across the arc of Althusser’s intellectual production. See for example
Goshgarian 2006; Bruschi 2021; and for a critique of this recent trend in Althusser studies,
Thomas 2013, pp. 145–6.
Goshgarian, however, arguably conflates what must necessarily remain two dis-
tinct problems or processes: A) the production of the adequate knowledge of
the capitalist social form (such as Marx constructs in Capital) and B) the polit-
ical problem of how that adequate knowledge, as a political epistemology, can
be militantly brought to bear upon an existing world and its subjects toward
the aim of its and their transformation.
In abandoning Reading Capital’s claims for the autonomy of theoretical
practice as index sui et falsi in favour of the empiricist methodology of ‘class
struggle in theory’, Althusser arguably conflated or inversed the necessary order
of these two processes via the demand that the lived experience of class strug-
gle (pre-)determine the adequacy of theory itself.20 Marx himself proceeded
would ever claim that circles exist only in thought (and strictly speaking, Spinoza argues,
they do not ‘exist’ in thought at all, but only in space-time extension); the same holds
for modes of production and the other categories of the capitalist social form Marx con-
structs, aspects of which are perfectly perceptible, if inadequately understood, in lived,
sensuous experience. The thought object and the real object are not two different things
one can compare for their correspondence, but one and the same thing, perceived alter-
nately via the absolutely distinct attributes of thought and extension.
21 Althusser 2003. On Adorno’s last months, see Müller-Doohm 2004.
22 Balibar 2018, p. 10.
23 Ibid. Similarly, François Matheron has argued that in this period, ‘Althusser progressively
destroyed the theses he had constructed’ (cited in Thomas 2013, p. 145).
24 Balibar has succinctly distilled the terms of this shift in Althusser’s theoretical orientation:
‘Au bout du compte, [Althusser in his writings of 1976–78] pointait le symptôme majeur
de la crise et de son inconscience propre dans l’énoncé de Lénine : “La théorie de Marx
est toute-puissante parce qu’elle est vraie.” Or, [Balibar continues,] à quelques variantes
près, c’est lui-même qui avait le plus hautement revendiqué cet énoncé, de 1965 à 1975,
comme l’expression provocatrice et risquée de l’objectivité du marxisme, dont les critères
de vérification (succès, échecs politiques) présupposent toujours une théorie explicative
de la lutte des classes (bien loin de pouvoir l’engendrer). Désormais il y voyait l’expression
la moins équivoque de l’illusion d’autonomie de la théorie, entretenue par son propre jeu
conceptuel (la logique formelle de son “ordre d’exposition”)’ (Balibar 1978, p. 61). Balibar
has more recently sought to nuance the vehement critique of his 1978 essay, in ‘L’objet
d’Althusser’ (2015b, pp. 85–116).
25 ‘Insistons bien sur le fait qu’il ne s’agit en aucune manière de renoncer à l’idée de connais-
sance scientifique ou “par concepts”, et a fortiori de rabattre celle-ci sur un empirisme,
un pragmatisme ou un subjectivisme. L’objectivité de la connaissance fait partie (comme
l’existence de la lutte des classes) des thèses sur lesquelles, à travers quelque autocritique
que ce soit, Althusser n’a pas cédé. Mais la référence à la pratique non théorique doit être
inscrite dans la définition même de l’objectivité, comme sa condition’ (Balibar 1978, 64).
26 Interview with L’Unità, 1 February 1968, cited in Estop 2021, p. 205. Estop goes on to inci-
sively critique the messianic, theological tenor of Althusser’s faith in this ‘fusion’ in the
period 1968–77, reminiscent of nothing less than Lukács’s humanist faith in the prole-
tariat: ‘“Man”, who had been expelled from theory [in For Marx and Reading Capital]
seems here to rediscover a history, and, moreover, a “human” history bestowed by Marx-
ism. The event of this fusion implies the self-transparency of the workers’ movement,
insofar as it possesses the science of its own history and that of humanity as a whole, a
fusion of the subject and object of knowledge. … This indistinction between science and
ideology appears to regress to a form of historicism or Hegelian absolute knowledge in
which the proletariat would be transparent to itself, not by virtue of its class conscious-
ness [as Lukács had claimed], but through its science’ (Estop 2021, p. 206, my translation).
Althusser similarly invokes the actuality of this ‘fusion’ in his unpublished 1967 ‘Book
Project on Capital Vol. 1’: ‘La situation du travail théorique a changé depuis Marx: très
précisément depuis que s’est réalisé la “fusion” du Mouvement ouvrier et de la théorie
marxiste. Cette “fusion” a produit une pratique absolument nouvelle’. imec, 20alt 16.11,
p. 36. Jean Matthys discusses the initial form of this Althusserian faith in the redeeming
force of the proletariat in his 1947 thesis: ‘Pour l’Althusser de 1947, … le prolétariat nomme
le lieu virtuel-réel, à la fois inscrit dans le contenu existant et contre lui, où pourra se
réaliser véritablement la circularité absolue d’une humanité réconciliée …: “L’action rév-
olutionnaire peut concevoir, au moins formellement, l’avènement de la totalité humaine
réconciliée avec sa propre structure”’ (Matthys 2023, p. 96).
32 In the sense that Alain Badiou has theorised the ‘conditions’ of philosophy (Conditions).
Panagiotis Sotiris writes similarly that ‘In Spinoza’s terms, freedom is a consequence of
intelligible necessity, and in Marx’s terms it is knowledge of the objective conditions of
the class struggle that makes possible the political direction of the class struggle’. Sotiris
2013, p. 37.
33 Althusser 1968, p. xvi.
34 Marx 1976, p. 125. Michael Heinrich shows that the received notion of Capital as a work
of the history of capitalism, derived from Kautsky, ‘baldly contradicts Marx’s claims in
the Preface to the first volume. There, he emphasises that the work deals with “theoretical
developments” (1976: 90), and that the text makes reference to conditions in England only
as an “illustration” of such developments. Marx makes it clear that he is by no means offer-
ing a historical depiction: “Intrinsically, it is not a question of the higher or lower degree of
development of the social antagonisms that spring from the natural laws of capitalist pro-
duction. It is a question of these laws themselves” (90). In keeping with this perspective,
Marx emphasises at the end of Volume 3 that he wants to present “the internal organi-
sation of the capitalist mode of production, its ideal average, as it were” (970). This way
of defining the object of Capital is not arbitrary, nor does it exclude historical develop-
ments from the account. On the contrary, the presentation of this “ideal average” is what
makes possible an approach to history that is not based on mere anecdotes but rather on
scientific analysis’ (Heinrich 2021, p. 397).
value and its exchange-value, which coexist as positive facts without contradic-
tion;35 that the substance of value of such commodities is abstract labour, etc.
Marx’s propositions and their demonstration in Capital are not derived from
‘the point of view of class exploitation’, as Althusser would demand in 1968
(though, again, this ‘point of view’ certainly constitutes one of their indirect
conditions), but instead from Marx’s painstaking critique of the theories of clas-
sical political economy, working at his desk and in the British Library.36 This
theoretical revisionism on Althusser’s part should be rejected as forcefully as
the conclusion that because Marx’s later unfinished manuscripts and study
notes demonstrate his concerted engagement with empirical research and his-
torical analysis (which is certainly the case), that the argument of Capital itself
bears an ‘empiricist’ dimension.37 The laws of the tendencies of capitalism that
Marx demonstrates, are, in their materialist necessity, eternal, their truth or
falsity, their adequacy or inadequacy determinable purely from their own con-
struction (Spinoza’s index sui). What Marx calls for example ‘the law of the mass
of surplus value’,38 in Chapter 11 of Capital, constitutes an abstract formalisa-
tion of an aspect of the capitalist social form, grasped in thought and derived
not from workers’ lived experience of exploitation, but as a necessary and sum-
mary consequence of the categories and relations he has demonstrated to that
point in his argument.
The opposite as well is true: insofar as they have a real theoretical content,
Marx’s essays such as ‘The Eighteenth Brumaire’ and The Civil War in France
might rightly be said to depend directly upon, and be necessarily limited by,
empirical, historical experience, as Althusser demands. Marx’s historical essays
and journalism, for all their brilliance and flashes of insight, however, remain
just that, pieces linked to a particular historical situation and do not possess
35 ‘En quoi la “valeur d’usage” qui est dite “porteur” – “Träger” – de “valeur”, peut-elle bien être
dite contradictoire à la valeur qu’elle porte? Mystère’. Althusser 1998, p. 253. I will argue this
point systematically in Chapter 3.
36 Althusser would assert precisely the opposite in a series of unpublished 1967 notes for a
‘Book Project on Capital Vol. 1’, i.e., that Capital is the result of Marx’s ‘experiments’. There,
Althusser claims that Marx’s various enquiries to Engels on the actual process of running
a capitalist enterprise (regarding the calculation of amortisation, for example), constitute
an empiricist ‘experimental usage [l’usage expérimental] that Marx made of the given facts
[données] of Engels’s practical experience’. imec, 20alt 16.11, p. 38.
37 Musto 2020, p. 151n86.
38 ‘The masses of value and of surplus-value produced by different capitals – the value of
labour-power being given and its degree of exploitation being equal – vary directly as the
amounts of the variable components of these capitals’ (Marx 1976, p. 421). I develop my
argument about the apodictic, non-empirical nature of Marx’s argument in light of this
crucial chapter of Capital below in Chapter 3.
the same degree of ‘scientific value’ Marx vaunted in his 1875 Postface to the
French edition of Capital.39 The case of a journalistic piece such as The Civil
War in France is just the opposite of the scientific apodicticity of Capital: if the
latter can rightly be said to have depended upon Marx (and Engels’s) direct
experience of class exploitation and political militancy as a condition of its
urgency and critical orientation, but not for the scientific rigour of its insights
into the capitalist social form, The Civil War in France can conversely be said to
depend upon Marx’s prior, painstakingly acquired theoretical understanding
of capitalism and its limits, but merely as an extrinsic condition that allowed
Marx accurately to judge in the heat of the historical moment a chaotic and
overwhelmingly complex empirical situation as ‘the great harbinger of a new
[communist] society’.40
Even the famous penultimate concluding chapter of Capital, Volume i, ‘The
Historical Tendency of Capitalist Accumulation’, the moment in Capital at
which Marx actually describes the ‘transformation of capitalist private prop-
39 In the sense that ‘a scientific analysis of [the forms of appearance of capital such as] com-
petition is possible only if we can grasp the inner nature of capital, just as the apparent
motions of the heavenly bodies are intelligible only to someone who is acquainted with
their real motions, which are not perceptible to the senses’ (Marx 1976, pp. 105, 433).
40 The Civil War in France. Available at: https:/www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1871/
civil‑war‑france/index.htm. It should be obvious that the problem of the material, bio-
graphical, and historical determination of Marx’s critique of political economy vastly
exceeds the scope of the problem this book addresses, the Althusserian analysis of Marx’s
process of apodictic exposition in Capital. Alain Badiou’s concept of the materialist con-
ditions of philosophy that I invoke here can do no more than serve as a placeholder for
future work in that direction that would remain faithful to Althusser’s critique of empiri-
cism and the rigorous, Spinozist distinction between theory and the capitalist real. The
outstanding existing example of such an orientation (devoid, to be sure, of any reference
to Althusser) is Michael Heinrich’s biography of Marx (Heinrich 2019). Flatly rejecting
the inadequacy of existing biographies of Marx, Heinrich combines a deep and broad
knowledge of Marx’s relation to his contemporary society and thought with an unequaled
familiarity with Marx’s theoretical project, insight richly informed, in a way no other biog-
rapher of Marx in English can even remotely claim, by Heinrich’s intimate familiarity with
Marx’s many drafts and notes for Capital across the mega2 project. This knowledge, along
with a critical approach to Marx’s biography that explicitly distinguishes documented
archival facts from the many myths and legends that have long been propounded from
one biography to another, leads Heinrich to argue against the imaginary figure of the bio-
graphical subject as totality, and to propose instead that ‘a biography contains mediations,
breaking points, and contingencies [that] dispute the idea of an unmediated access to
the subject. Biography should not aim to reveal the “essence” of the person Marx; rather,
it is about the permanent, contradictory, and often ruptured process that characterises
the constitution of a particular person under particular social conditions and conflicts’
(Heinrich 2020, 478).
erty … into social property’, does not contradict this position, but rather stands
as its negative confirmation.41 As its title and adjunct position indicate, the
chapter’s seven paragraphs constitute a brief, rhetorically powerful but ana-
lytically meagre addition to the immediately preceding historical chapters on
primitive accumulation.42 As such, this entire concluding section comprises
an exterior supplement to Marx’s systematic, apodictic demonstration of the
capitalist social form in chapters 1–25. It is no coincidence that its handful of
famous predictions,43 in the absence of any and all demonstration, articulate
a theoretically enfeebled and imaginary teleology, one that continues to rely
on the theoretical rump of a Hegelian vocabulary that demonstrates nothing:
‘Capitalist production begets, with the inexorability of a natural process, its
own negation. This is the negation of the negation’.44
Marx will renounce this teleology of historical necessity (as the necessity
that the communist social form be preceded by developed, industrial capital-
ism), a regressive, Hegelian moment of ‘writing recipes for the cook-shops of
the future’, not only by the time of his famous 1872 Postface (in which the lat-
ter phrase appears), but above all in his late turn to an aleatory position on the
problem of transition in the 1881 letters with Vera Zasulich.45
To continue to think beyond Althusser, with Althusser, we should radicalise
his famous assertion that philosophy has no object (‘Philosophy has no object,
it has its objects’), to assert more generally that critique has no object, in the
sense of a preconstituted empirical object that it analyses, subsequently to rep-
resent in thought.46 Critique – and this includes above all Marx’s critique of
47 Macherey himself seems to encourage such a position, observing in his 1997 commentary
that his 1991 essay ‘could be interpreted as the resurgence of a critical conception of phi-
losophy’ (Macherey 1999, p. 110).
48 Macherey 1999, p. 109.
49 Macherey 1999, p. 96. I will follow Macherey’s further development of this position in the
next chapter.
50 Macherey 1999, p. 97.
51 Macherey 1999, p. 98.
above all, a succession of silences, all of which I have sought to articulate – not
to reveal a truth – but instead as the exact and exacting composition of a force-
field of discursive relations that constitute Capital’s materialist dialectic.
52 rc, p. 51. In his discussion of the dialectical method Marx progressively developed in Cap-
ital, Michael Heinrich’s Science of Value makes a similar claim with distinctly Althusserian
overtones (such as the focus on the ‘placement’ of concepts): Marx, Heinrich writes, ‘sie
in eine bestimmte Ordnung bringt, die ihnen aber nicht äußerlich ist und lediglich den
Gesamtzusammenhang herstellt, sondern die zur Bestimmung der Kategorien selbst noch
wesentlich ist: eine Ordnung, die wesentliche Beziehungen der Kategorien ausdruckt.’
(Marx ‘places them [concepts] in a certain order, one that is not external to them to merely
establish an overall context, but [an order that] is essential for determining the categories
themselves: an order that expresses the essential relationships between the categories’)
(Heinrich 2022 [1999], p. 172; 2023, p. 268, my translation). Where Heinrich differs from
Althusser is in his quite traditional, empiricist theory of knowledge, one in which, for
Heinrich, Marx’s dialectical demonstration attends to ‘den Zusammenhang von Begrif-
fen (Plural) geht, die empirisches Material verarbeiten’ (‘the context of concepts (plural)
that process empirical material’, ibid.).
53 rc, p. 61.
This epistemological claim, which it is the aim of this book to sustain and
amplify, has, despite its theoretical daring, remained almost without exception
lettre morte in the literature on Reading Capital; even among the Althusseri-
ans themselves, only Pierre Macherey’s precocious, all-too-brief 1965 analysis
attends systematically to the process of exposition and demonstration Marx
deployed in Capital.
Among the results of Althusser’s theoretically self-destructive turn after 1968
is the surprising fact in question here: his general failure to extend and develop
the innovative and henceforth world-famous reading of Marx’s Capital initi-
ated by For Marx and Reading Capital itself. To my knowledge, Althusser would
reiterate the theoreticist position of Reading Capital on only three occasions.
Above all, in his inflection of the positions of Reading Capital in the single pub-
lished instance of this return, his 1977 ‘Avant-propos du livre de G. Duménil, Le
concept de loi économique dans Le capital’. There, Althusser: 1. warns against the
temptation of erecting a concept of a ‘methode dialectique’ in general (whether
Hegelian, Marxian, or otherwise) as well as that of ‘method’ tout court; 2. argues
for a process of exposition in Capital by the ‘positioning’ of concepts rather
than their idealist deduction as an ‘autoproduction’; 3. argues against any ide-
For the reader hoping for some further specification, a demonstration, even a
citation from Capital to bolster this claim, not a word, any more than in Reading
Capital. This would be Althusser’s last written statement on the logic of Capital.
59 Althusser 1994.
60 Macherey 2021.
61 Peter Thomas has called into question the adequacy of Spinozist philosophy to that of
Althusser. See Thomas 2002 and Sotiris 2021, p. 180.
Already in the essays collected in For Marx, Althusser articulates the core epis-
temological proposition of his rereading of Marx, but in an initial form marked
by various deficiencies that will find subsequent (if still problematic) devel-
opment in the essays of Reading Capital. The 1962 essay ‘Contradiction and
Overdetermination’ sounds an opening salvo in Althusser’s theoretical inter-
vention, in its steadfast refusal to take Marx’s word on Hegel at face value.
This is the Marx who famously asserted in the 1873 Postface to the second edi-
tion of Capital that ‘With [Hegel the dialectic] is standing on its head. It must
be inverted, in order to discover the rational kernel within the mystical shell’.
Althusser flatly rejects the idea that Marx simply ‘overturned’ Hegel, as Marx
himself claimed. Instead of a mere overturning that would leave the structures
of his dialectic unchanged but only inverted, Althusser famously affirms an
epistemological break between the ‘Marxist’ and the ‘Hegelian’ dialectic, as two
radically heterogeneous philosophical practices:62
62 In the Eléments d’autocritique, Althusser will reaffirm the correctness of this proposition
(‘Cette these, qui n’a pas éte épargné par les critiques, je la maintiens’), with the crucial
proviso that it be understood as an event (‘surgit quelque chose comme un événement
sans précédent’) in precisely the sense Badiou has given the concept: as a punctual break
‘à partir de L’idéologie allemande’, but one that required Marx’s ongoing fidelity as a perpet-
ual struggle to realise, step by step, to the end of his days, its full theoretical implications
(Althusser 1974, pp. 165, 164).
If the Marxist dialectic is ‘in its principal’ fully the opposite of the
Hegelian dialectic, … this radical difference must manifest itself in its
essence, which is to say in its determinations and its own structures. To
speak clearly, this implies that the fundamental structures of the Hegelian
dialectic, such as negation, the negation of the negation, the identity of
opposites, ‘sublation’, the transformation of quality into quantity, contra-
diction, etc., possess for Marx (in so far as he takes them up, which is not
always the case!) a different structure from that which they possess for
Hegel.63
On the one hand, Althusser here rightly refuses simply to take Marx at his
word, as though Marx’s declared, imaginary relation to Hegel’s thought were
sufficient in itself to resolve the complex question of the nature of the episte-
mology deployed in Capital. Marx, for all his genius, was necessarily a subject
of ideology like anyone else, even in a text as authoritative as the 1873 Post-
face to the Second Edition of Capital in which he makes his famous claim
‘to discover the rational kernel within the mystical shell’. Instead, Althusser
rightly proposes that the difference between these two forms of dialectic can
only be determined immanently, through an analysis of the ‘determinations
and structures’ of Marx’s logical demonstration itself, that is to say, through a
critical analysis of the actual dialectical method deployed in the pages of Cap-
ital.64
At the same time, Althusser’s initial formulation of his proposition suf-
fers from several inadequacies. Althusser appears hesitant and anxious at the
very thought that Marx might in fact have constructed a dialectic based upon
entirely different principles than those of Hegel’s negative dialectic. It remains
a tentative suggestion, merely hinting that the categories of the ‘Marxist dialec-
tic’ might possess ‘a different structure’ than the ‘Hegelian dialectic’, offering no
more than a summary list of the principal characteristics of the latter (‘nega-
tion, … contradiction, etc’.) without substantiating this claim through even a
minimal concrete investigation or example.
Even more problematically, Althusser immediately abandons the distinc-
tion he indicates between the Marxist and Hegelian dialectics as a question of
65 Marx 1976, p. 103, 1873 Postface. This late position from Marx’s ‘Postface’ to the second,
1872 edition of Capital, reiterated earlier statements by Marx, for example, in his corre-
spondence with Lassalle, where Marx already asserted that: ‘This [Hegelian] dialectic is,
to be sure, the ultimate word in philosophy’ (cited in Fluss 2022, p. 481).
such a statement, while suggestive, cannot resolve the question of whether and
in what ways what Marx calls the ‘method of presentation’ he deploys in Capi-
tal differs from that of Hegel. Marx’s own subjective point of view both reduces
the rich complexity of Hegel’s development and deployment of his dialecti-
cal method across a lifetime of work to a single nominal cipher (the ‘Hegelian
… dialectical method’), as well as presupposing precisely what would need to
be ascertained once those two methods were conceptualised: the determina-
tion through textual analysis of the precise factors that differentiate these two
‘methods of presentation’.
Had Marx written his projected study of dialectical method,66 he might well
have found, as Althusser repeatedly suggested, that the actual method of expo-
sition he had developed in the decades he spent writing Capital in fact dif-
fered far more fundamentally from that of Hegel than he had realised. Marx
might have found that in fact Hegel had not been ‘the first to present its [the
dialectic’s] general forms of motion in a comprehensive manner’,67 but had in
fact only identified the forms of motion of a specific, negative dialectic, one
that Marx himself gradually abandoned after 1857, to develop instead a posi-
tive dialectic of additive synthesis for his exposition in Capital, as Macherey
demonstrates in his brief contribution to Reading Capital (to be discussed in
the next chapter), a dialectic that finds antecedents in thinkers including Aris-
totle and Spinoza (both of whom Marx read intensively), and Bernard Bolzano
(whom he did not).
A final limitation of what I am calling Althusser’s nominalist deficiency
encompasses the further reference – beyond that which Althusser makes to
‘Hegelian’ and ‘Marxist’ dialectics in ‘Contradiction and Overdetermination’ –
to a putative ‘Spinozist’ method of exposition, an attribution that Althusser and
Macherey will identify in both Reading Capital as well as in subsequent works
that focus explicitly on Spinoza’s method of exposition, such as Macherey’s
Hegel or Spinoza.68 The problem is not that Spinoza lacked a coherent notion of
an additive synthetic dialectic more geometrico (he did), but rather the impossi-
bility of contrasting this with a so-called ‘Hegelian’ dialectic. Althusser’s initial
references in ‘Contradiction and Overdetermination’ to a ‘Hegelian’ dialectic
66 Marx famously intended, but never managed, to write a treatise on dialectics, as he wrote
on various occasions to Engels and Joseph Dietzgen (Fluss 2022, p. 482).
67 Marx 1976, p. 103.
68 ‘With Marx, [there occurs] the emergence of a new science … rather in the way that
Spinoza takes up the more geometrico only to give it a new and original meaning’ (rc,
p. 182).
69 Macherey himself has in fact criticised his 1979 book on the grounds that it focuses
on Hegel’s later works and the Logic in particular, neglecting Hegel’s engagement with
Spinoza in his early writings (1999, p. 146).
70 Harrison Fluss has argued that ‘Hegel’s later understanding [of Spinoza] represented not
so much an advance but a regression towards the very same anti-Spinozist positions he
had already refuted in the early Jena period. In reverting back to old characterisations of
Spinozistic substance as a-cosmic in his later work, Hegel obfuscated his own deeper con-
nections with Spinoza, who had formerly represented for him a genuine philosopher of
the absolute Idea’ (Fluss 2016, p. 2).
71 Fluss 2016, p. 7.
72 This reductive position perhaps originates with Engels’s famous assertion, in Anti-
Duhring, that dialectics, as the science of nature, can be reduced to three laws: the trans-
formation of quantity into quality; the interpenetration of opposites; and the negation of
the negation (Bhaskar 1983, p. 126).
73 A key moment in this forgetting of the plurality of dialectical methods is surely to found
in Abram Deborin’s crucial contributions to the theoretical foundations of Soviet phi-
losophy in the pages of the journal he edited from 1922–30, Pod Znamenem Marksizma
(Under the Banner of Marxism). In a 1927 article on the occasion of the 250th anniversary
of Spinoza’s death, Deborin neatly divided the forces of Soviet theory into ‘the Hegelian
front and the Spinozist front’, in which reference to Hegel (and his constitutive negative
dialectic) is judged relevant for ‘the foundation of our method’ and Spinoza for ‘our world
view’ (cited at Oittinen 2022, p. 5). At the stroke of a pen, Deborin disappears the lat-
ter’s positive dialectic as a viable methodology for dialectical materialism. More recently,
Harrison Fluss, in an otherwise insightful and informed presentation, from his first sen-
tence radically limits his definition of ‘Dialectics’ to its post-Hegelian, negative dialecti-
cal form, when he writes: ‘As the logic of contradiction, dialectics has a long pre-history
before Marx’ (Fluss 2022, p. 474, my emphasis). Similarly, in her article on ‘Dialectics’ for
the Bloomsbury Companion to Marx, Carolyn Lesjak presents the topic of her article as
the ‘imperative for thought to expose and work through the contradictions and tensions
that underlie all conceptual coherence …. This critique proceeds by the route of nega-
tion, a path whereby the contradictions of capitalism are made apparent’ (Lesjak 2021,
p. 463). Andrew Cole, in his brilliant analysis of the Medieval origins of Hegelian dialec-
tic, focuses almost entirely on the concept as ‘the dialectic of identity and difference’
and underscores the originality of Hegel’s ‘recuperation of the concept of contradiction’
(Cole 2014, p. 34). Roy Bhaskar, in the Harvard Dictionary of Marxist Thought, identifies
three predominant meanings of the term ‘dialectics’ in the Marxist tradition: ‘as (a) a
method, most usually scientific method, instancing epistemological dialectics [i.e., the
general usage Althusser invokes in For Marx and Reading Capital]; (b) a set of laws or
principles, governing some sector of the whole of reality, ontological dialectics; and (c)
the movement of history, relational dialectics’. Yet for all this real subtlety, Bhaskar too
ultimately reverts to a contradiction-based understanding of Marx’s epistemology: ‘Marx’s
dialectics is scientific, [Bhaskar summarises], because it explains the contradictions in
thought and the crises of socio-economic life in terms of the particular contradictory
essential relations which generate them’ (Bhaskar 1983, pp. 122, 124, 125). Patrick Murray is
the only reader of Capital as far as I am aware who underlines the generic, non-Hegelian
meaning of dialectic for Marx as the art of logical demonstration per se. Murray 2017,
p. 131.
74 In Latin, from which these derive, dialectica is defined as simply ‘the art of methodical
reasoning’ (Le Robert historique). In German the Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie
defines Dialektik as ‘der Art einer Disziplin mit der Analyse und Synthese von Begriffen
und dient vornehmlich der Erkenntnis des Seienden, um die Ideen zu begreifen’ [a disci-
pline in which the analysis and synthesis of concepts primarily addresses the knowledge
of being in order to comprehend Ideas]. On the multifarious interpretations of the con-
cept of dialectic in Capital, see Heinrich 1999, pp. 164–79; 2023, pp. 259–75.
75 Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, 25, note b.
76 ‘I can take as my elementary theoretical guide the definitions proposed in A. Lalande’s
Dictionnaire philosophique …. They can be taken as so many indices not only of a com-
mon theoretical background, but also of the possible resonances and inflexions of sense
this background provides’ (rc, p. 312, lc, p. 366).
77 Lalande 2010 [1923], p. 227. Lalande furthermore notes that ‘This word [la dialectique] has
received such diverse meanings that it can only be usefully employed by indicating pre-
cisely in what sense it is taken’ (ibid.). Throughout this book, I will follow Althusser’s lead
and repeatedly refer to Lalande’s definitions from his magisterial 1923 work of erudition,
currently in its eighteenth edition, a reference work that Jacques Fallon described on its
1993 reedition with puf as ‘the most famous philosophical dictionary in the French lan-
guage …. Still today, no other dictionary in our language can claim to rival either in quality
or scope this monument of French erudition’. Fallon 1993, p. 512.
78 rc, p. 51.
79 rc, p. 243.
80 Spinoza’s critique of empiricism in Book ii of Ethica is absolute: ‘Insofar as the human
mind imagines an external body, to that extent it does not have an adequate knowledge
of it’ (quatenus mens humana corpus externum imaginatur aetenus adaequatam ejus cog-
nitionem non habet) eiip26c, and again, the corollary to Proposition ii29, ‘Whenever the
human mind perceives things after the common order of nature, it does not have an ade-
quate knowledge of itself, nor of its body, nor of external bodies, but only a confused and
fragmentary knowledge’ (mens humana quoties ex communi naturae ordine res percipit
nec sui ipsius nec sui corporis nec corporum externorum adaequatam habet cognitionem)
eiip29c. Spinoza once more: ‘When we gaze at the sun, we see it as some two hundred
feet distant from us. The error does not consist in simply seeing the sun in this way but in
the fact that while we do so we are not aware of the true distance and the cause of our see-
ing it so. For although we may later become aware that the sun is more than six hundred
times the diameter of the earth distant from us, we shall nevertheless continue to see it as
close at hand. For it is not our ignorance of its true distance that causes us to see the sun
to be so near; it is that the affection of our body involves the essence of the sun only to the
extent that the body is affected by it’. Spinoza, eiip35s.
81 rc, p. 35.
82 rc, p. 41.
83 rc, p. 36.
84 Ibid.
85 Adam Smith 1999, p. 11. I take this example from the analysis of Marx’s 1857 methodology
by Juan Iñigo Carrera (2013). The same point could be made of Hegel and capitalism: none
of the various categories that Hegel develops in his social logic (Elements of the Philosophy
of Right), from the family to the free association of individuals in civil society, to political
community and the relation of states, can be properly comprehended in abstraction from
Althusser’s point is well taken, since not only does Smith appear to derive
this universal notion from empirical abstraction, but he furthermore deploys
it to distinguish an essential characteristic of human behaviour from other
inessential qualities common to human and other animal species (‘passions’,
‘acting in concert’). Marx, in contrast, does not merely demystify the illusory
nature of the various phenomenal features of capitalism, such as commodity
fetishism, money, profit, the ‘freedom’ of the wage labour contract, the illusions
of a supposedly virtuous and benevolent primitive accumulation, and of the
Trinity Formula of profit, land-rent, and wages, as well as many others. In every
case, Marx does not simply dismiss these as inessential features of capital-
ism, in contrast to the more ‘essential’ categories he discovers such as abstract
labour, labour power, or surplus value. In addition, in Spinozist fashion, he rig-
orously demonstrates in every case the systematic necessity that governs each
category of the capitalist social form, including its superficial forms of appear-
ance.86 In addition to mere negative critique, Althusser emphasises Capital’s
production of a positive theory of ideology and its forms of appearance as a
science of causes.
Rather than an extraction of truth from an empirical object, Marx asked
a more fundamental question in Capital: what are the laws of the tendencies
governing these empirical, quantitative fluctuations? In contrast, the ‘empiricist’
dimension of the initial enquiries for Capital (the Grundrisse) and the decades
of painstaking drafting and revision from 1859 to just before his death in 1883 is
arguably limited to Marx’s tired eyes scouring the markings across thousands,
even millions of sheets of paper.87
their subordination to what Marx calls the objective ‘social form’ of compulsion that is val-
orisation under the general social predominance of capital; in contrast, these remain for
Hegel (highly-developed) empirical analytical categories arguably drawn from the forms
of appearance of capitalist society, like those of Smith before him. See Tony Smith 2014,
p. 28.
86 Jacques Bidet develops this Althusserian argument in Exploring Marx’s Capital: Philo-
sophical, Economic, and Political Aspects (2009 [1985]). While Bidet’s work richly and pro-
ductively pursues the Althusserian reading of Capital, in this book I refer to his writings
only intermittently, focusing instead on the first generation of Althusserians, Macherey,
Badiou, Balibar, and Althusser himself.
87 Althusser in fact tries to argue along these lines at one point in his introduction, in con-
tradiction, I think, with the entire thrust of his general critique of empiricism: ‘Taking
Marx as an example, we know that his most personally significant practical experiences
(his experience as a polemicist of ‘the embarrassment of having to take part in discus-
sions on so-called material interests’ in the Rheinische Zeitung; his direct experience of
the earliest struggle organisations of the Paris proletariat; his revolutionary experience
in the 1848 period) intervened in his theoretical practice, and in the upheaval which led
him from ideological theoretical practice to scientific theoretical practice; but they inter-
vened in his theoretical practice in the form of objects of experience, or even experiment,
i.e., in the form of new thought objects, ‘ideas’ and the concepts, whose emergence con-
tributed, in their combination (Verbindung) with other conceptual results (originating in
German philosophy and English political economy), to the overthrow of the still ideo-
logical theoretical base on which he had lived (i.e., thought) until then’ (rc, p. 63). The
entire argument of an epistemological break is undermined by such a claim. Rather, the
theoretical break occurs, as an ongoing transitional process till Marx’s death, through the
ceaseless development of his theoretical practice.
88 Musto 2020, pp. 99–102.
89 While warning against any idealist or ideological understanding of the axiomatic nature of
Marx’s method of demonstration and reaffirming instead its materialist determination by
Marx’s preliminary enquiries (Grundrisse, etc.), Althusser nonetheless admits that ‘il faut
bien reconnaître [in Capital …] un mode de pensée très proche d’une pensée axiomatique’.
Althusser 1998, p. 259.
90 Marx 1976, p. 125. It is precisely in such Spinozist terms that Lalande formulates a general
definition of empirisme in the Vocabulaire technique de la philosophie, as ‘the generic name
of all philosophical doctrines that deny the existence of axioms as principals of knowledge
logically distinct from experience’ (Lalande 2010 [1923], p. 281).
91 Marx 1976, p. 102.
92 On the Grundrisse’s status as a preliminary inquiry into the nature of the capitalist social
form, as opposed to constituting a ‘first draft’ of Capital, see Nesbitt 2019.
93 See Heinrich 2021, p. 15; Musto 2020, pp. 85–93.
94 The thought of Cavaillès, legible in palimpsest in many of the most decisive passages
of Althusser’s introduction to Reading Capital, constitutes an emphatic rejection of all
empiricist understandings of the scientific experimental apparatus (see Nesbitt 2017,
pp. 4–8). Althusser problematically in fact proposes such an empiricist conflation in the
1966 lecture ‘The Philosophical Conjuncture and Marxist Research’ (Brown 2021, p. 14).
Althusser’s two positions from 1965 and 1966 are theoretically incoherent: the Introduc-
tion to Reading Capital finds Althusser at the peak of his theoretical powers of insight in
pages of genius, cast with Rimbaldian clairvoyance, while in the latter Althusser – consti-
tutionally weakened and theoretically ambivalent, embroiled in the debates with Garaudy
and Aragon on theory and practice, under attack by the pcf for the so-called ‘theoreticism’
of Reading Capital–weakly asserts the reductive conflation of a line of thought he names
‘rationalist empiricism’ (Brown 2021, p. 6). While Althusser is clearly making a broadly
inclusive point about the history of French epistemology, to place as he does the name
of Jean Cavaillès next to that of Bachelard in this brief essay obscures the anti-empiricist
intervention that Cavaillès initiates in On Logic and the Theory of Science: ‘Even in the
natural sciences, this increase [in the system of concepts] takes place without any input
from the outside world [l’exterieur]: there is a rupture between sensation or right thinking
[opinion droite] and science. Far from being an involvement in nature, the experiment is,
on the contrary, the incorporation of the world into the scientific universe’. Cavaillès 2021
[1942], p. 41. See also Cavaillès 1994.
95 ‘The question of the form of order required at a given moment in the history of knowledge
by the existing type of scientificity, or, if you prefer, by the norms of theoretical validity
recognised by science, in its own practice, as scientific’ (rc, p. 50).
96 Cassou-Nogès, 2017, 12. ‘Science’, Cavaillès writes, ‘is no longer considered as a mere inter-
mediary between the human mind [esprit] and being in itself, equally dependent upon
both and lacking its own reality, but rather as an object sui generis, original in its essence
and autonomous in its movement’ (2021, p. 40).
97 Cavaillès’ sole surviving reference to Spinoza comes from a personal remark to Raymond
Aron: ‘I am Spinozist. I believe in necessity. The necessity of mathematical inferences, the
necessity of the history of mathematics, the necessity also of the struggle [against fascism]
in which we are engaged’. Cited at Cassou-Noguès 2017, p. 13.
98 While Althusser only mentions Cavaillès in passing, many of his formulations on the his-
toricity of science should be read as direct refigurations of the latter’s positions in On
Logic: ‘To pose this question [of the history of the theoretical] is obviously to pose the
question of the form of order required at a given moment in the history of knowledge
by the existing type of scientificity, or, if you prefer, by the norms of theoretical validity
recognised by science, in its own practice, as scientific. … The essential problem presup-
posed by the question of the existing type of demonstrativity is the problem of the history
of the production of the different forms in which theoretical practice (producing knowl-
edges, whether “ideological” or “scientific”) recognises the validating norms it demands.
… This history [is] the history of the theoretical as such, or the history of the production
(and transformation) of what at a given moment in the history of knowledge constitutes
the theoretical problematic to which are related all the existing validating criteria, and
hence the forms required to give the order of theoretical discourse the force and value of
a proof. This history of the theoretical, of the structures of theoreticity and of the forms
of theoretical apodicticity, has yet to be constituted’ (rc, p. 50).
99 ‘The idea of the circle, which is the object of knowledge, must not be confused with the
circle, which is the real object. In the third section of the 1857 Introduction, Marx took up
this principle as forcefully as possible’ (rc, p. 40).
100 rc, p. 61. Here is Spinoza: ‘The formal being of the idea of a circle can be perceived only
through another mode of thinking as its proximate cause, and that mode through another,
and so on ad infinitum, with the result that as long as things are considered as modes of
thought, we must explicate the order of the whole of Nature, or the connection of causes,
through the attribute of Thought alone; and insofar as things are considered as modes of
Extension, again the order of the whole of Nature must be explicated through the attribute
of Extension only’ (eiip7s). See Pierre Macherey’s meticulous, materialist explication of
5 Hallucinatory Empiricism
In his critique of empiricism, Althusser argues that Capital must be read not
as a history, but instead as a logic. Not, Althusser quickly points out, as ‘logi-
cians [would, which] would have meant posing it the question of its methods
of exposition and proof’,102 in other words as a mere discursive, logical posi-
tivist word game, but as the Spinozist, materialist logic of the necessary forms
of appearance of things in the capitalist social form. While Althusser’s critique
of empiricism is encompassing and unyielding, it is not always clear on what
grounds he rejects the empiricist processes of, for example, the abstraction of a
kernel of truth from the empirical object, or the ‘scouring’ of material. Why, one
might ask, are these necessarily inadequate procedures? Spinoza, in contrast,
offers in eiip14–24 clear and simple terms for his own rejection of empirical,
sensory-derived truth.103 Macherey will interpret and develop Spinoza’s cri-
107 Macherey 1997, pp. 165–6. I cite here and the following chapters passages from Macherey’s
1997 commentary on Ethics ii not only for their power of insight, but because none of
these five volumes of extraordinary analyses of Spinoza’s materialist dialectic have yet to
be translated, and what is in my view the most important of these, Book ii, is no longer in
print even in its original French edition.
108 Macherey 1997, p. 171.
109 Macherey 1997, p. 182.
110 Macherey 1997, p. 184.
the distance of the earth from the sun).111 It is in this sense, precisely, that the
representation-based model of knowledge that Althusser rightly condemns in
his Introduction, but with little justification, can be said, in light of Macherey’s
subsequent comments on eiip13–24, to indicate the purely ‘indicative’ function
of perception, in which a thing is perceived without being understood.112
Knowledge, for Spinoza, instead of indicating the adequation of an empir-
ical object and its representation, constitutes the adequation of an idea to its
inherent degree of clarity and power within the attribute of thought alone. The
empiricist model of knowledge thus constitutes in contrast, Althusser argues,
a secular ‘transcription’ of revelation, a ‘religious reading’ compromised by its
inherent circularity, the presupposition that its truth occurs not in the con-
structed thought object, but lies hidden in the real object itself.113 This implies
in consequence that empiricist knowledge cannot inquire into the real con-
ditions of the production of an adequate idea, since this (empiricist) truth is
claimed to lie dormant, always-already present in the real object itself, await-
ing its mere extraction.
Eventually, after the compromised theoretical interlude of ‘class struggle in
theory’, Althusser would – in his late, posthumously published texts Etre marx-
iste en philosophie and Sur la philosophie – return to further specify this initial
critique of the representational nature of empiricist knowledge. In this late
thought, Althusser reformulated his initial critique of empiricism based on a
reference to the Heideggerian critique of the principal of reason. This is the
principle shared by idealism and materialism alike that, in Althusser’s words,
‘every existing thing, whether ideal or material, [must] submit to a question-
ing of the reason for its existence’, that any existing thing, in other words, must
uphold the exactness of its representation of the real object.114
the ‘logical’ order, being identical in essence with the real order and exist-
ing in the reality of the real order as its essence itself, can only follow the
real order; [and furthermore] that the real order being identical in essence
with the ‘logical’ order, the real order, which is then merely the existence
of the logical order, must follow the logical order.118
This traditional reading of Marx’s distinction between the real object and
the thought object [Gedankenkonkretum] thus follows precisely the empiricist
model Althusser has rejected a moment before in the abstract: both that the
order of thought ‘follows’ the real order of capitalism in the form of its repre-
sentation, and, furthermore, that what presents itself, in traditional Marxism,
as a materialist argument is in fact eminently idealist, since the order of the
real object (capitalism) is then said not to have priority, but instead merely to
‘follow the logical order’. Each of these positions, Althusser maintains, ‘does
violence’ to Marx’s actual argument.119
While ‘Contradiction and Overdetermination’, as we have seen, quickly
abandoned its epistemological propositions regarding Marx’s method of dem-
onstration to pursue a politico-historical discussion of Lenin and the Bolshevik
Revolution, in Reading Capital Althusser insists on staying with and pursuing
this methodological terrain as a strictly ‘theoretical problematic’.120 The force
of Althusser’s argument – lacking as it does any explicit analysis of Marx’s
mode of analysis (he leaves this to Macherey’s contribution) – has rarely been
registered as anything but dogmatic polemic. To take the position Althusser
adopts, following Marx’s own literal suggestion, that there exists not a rela-
tion but ‘a radical distinction between the order in which [conceptual] “cate-
gories” appear in knowledge, on the one hand, and in historical reality on the
other’,121 is quite simply to relegate the traditional, empiricist inquiry into the
correspondence of the thought object and the real object, along with various
monist idealist readings of Spinoza, to the status of a nonexistent problem.
118 Ibid.
119 Though both Alain Badiou and Jean Matthys read Althusser as here rejecting the Spinozist
principle of the ‘parallelism’ of the attributes, I will argue in the next chapter against
these interpretations that Althusser’s position constitutes a radicalisation of Spinoza in
his own terms, and that, in line with Macherey’s critique of this philosophical common-
place, the so-called ‘parallelism’ of the attributes (a term Spinoza never used, by which
Leibniz (mis)represented his thought) is simply a monist misreading of Spinoza, one that
Althusser overcomes by theorising substance not as a reified (monist) thing, but as struc-
tural causality.
120 rc, p. 47.
121 rc, p. 48, my emphasis.
[1999], p. 171). Marx’s 1867 Appendix can be found at Marx 1983, mega2 ii/5 ‘Anhang zu
Kapitel i, 1. Die Wertform’ 626–55.
125 I agree with Jean Matthys that ‘Behind every great Althusserian conceptual innovation,
… there lurks the figure of Spinoza. … The multiplicity of Spinozist figures in Althusser’s
[thought] is no heteroclite assemblage, … but articulates in a relatively coherent fashion
a true Spinozist “plane of consistency” or “problematic” ’ (2023, pp. 192, 43).
126 imec 20alt/32/10. See Matthys 2023, Chapter 2.
127 Estop 2021, pp. 226–32.
made to Spinoza [in Reading Capital]’.128 For Macherey, science takes on its
fundamental character as a materialist inquiry into the real ‘from the moment
it gives form to reality’.129 Science is not the representation, classification, or
explication of the real; instead, ‘the thought real [is] the real transformed’.
Macherey even seems to distinguish between the real [le réel] and reality [la
réalité], such that the former would occupy the theoretical position of the (infi-
nite, untotalisable) set of all things – both nonexistent idealities and actually
existing things – in their infinite relations, and the latter that of substance: ‘The
rupture between the real [le réel] and thought is the difference between two
forms of reality [la réalité] … the science of the real [le réel] is the institution
of a new form of reality [la réalité]’.130 Macherey’s distinction between the real
and reality seems to address, without truly explicating, this point of ambigu-
ity or obscurity in Althusser’s thought, without, on the other hand, explicitly
reverting to Spinoza’s scholastic terminology.131 In other words, if Althusser is
a self-proclaimed ‘spinoziste’, and the theory of substance, the attributes, and
modes the foundation of Spinozist thought, how does Althusser parse and criti-
cally reconfigure these crucial concepts? In the absence of explicit elaboration
on Althusser’s part, this must ultimately remain a speculative reconstruction
elaborated from materials across the expanse of his published and unpublished
works.132
Simply to distinguish between thought and the real, as does Althusser in
Reading Capital, or even between thought, the real, and reality, as Macherey
will inflect this pair in ‘En matérialiste’, constitutes a point of ambiguity in the
conceptual apparatus of Reading Capital.133 Provisionally, and I will address
aspects of this problem at different points below, I wish to indicate a series
of Spinozist concepts that can more adequately parse Althusser’s flat, binary
distinction between thought and the real. Substance, the most basic and fun-
damental of Spinozist terms, is one that Althusser publicly and polemically
refuses in its reified form, through his critique of Marxist-Hegelian philoso-
phies of monism (while tentatively affirming its necessity in private discussion
with the Groupe Spinoza).134
Instead, through attention to Althusser’s archive, it becomes clear, above
all in his 1948 notes on Spinoza, that Althusser refigures the concept of sub-
stance, rejecting the reifying implications of the word itself as well as its status
as ontological guarantee, instead to conceive of substance as the finite struc-
tural causality of a social form, a causality that exists only in its effects.135 This
is the famous concept Althusser develops in the final sections of Reading Cap-
ital:
While Althusser nowhere indicates in his published writings that his concept of
structural causality is a materialist, anti-monist refiguration of Spinozist sub-
stance, Jean Matthys has shown that this operation, which remains a constant
in Althusser’s thought, finds explicit articulation as early as Althusser’s first
notes on Spinoza from 1948. Though these notes cannot be interpreted unilat-
erally, it is here that Althusser asserts that Spinoza should not be understood
‘from the identification God = Substance but [from the position that] substance
= attribute, which is the foundation of structure’.137 Althusser further indicates
that this ‘problem’ must be understood not ‘ontologically’, as ‘the identity of
134 I will discuss Althusser’s critique of Marxist monism below in this chapter.
135 imec 20alt/32/10, ‘Notes sur Spinoza (1948)’. I take this crucial insight for my argument
from Matthys 2023, pp. 123–8.
136 rc, p. 344, translation modified, emphasis in original.
137 Cited at Matthys 2023, p. 123.
138 Matthys 2023, p. 124. Matthys’ commentary on this note is revealing: ‘Dans le but d’éviter
que cette identité soit fondée sur une essence ontologique qui réduirait les attributs
(et a fortiori les modes) au statut d’apparences phénoménales dénuées de toute forme
d’autonomie et de diversité réelles, mais en cherchant tout autant à éviter l’écueil symé-
trique d’une pure et simple juxtaposition des attributs, Spinoza invite, selon Althusser …
à penser une “identité de structure causale. … La substance n’est pas le lieu d’une identifi-
cation ou d’une réduction “essentielle” entre les attributs, où ceux-ci seraient réduits à de
simples formes secondaires et épiphénoménales réductibles à une essence commune que
serait la substance. L’identité des attributs dans la substance, et donc l’uni(ci)té de celle-
ci, réside dans l’identité de l’acte causal “naturant” qui constitue “un seul et même ordre,
autrement dit un seul et même enchaînement des causes’. Matthys 2023, pp. 127, 128.
139 Matthys 2023, pp. 127, 117.
140 Macherey 1998, p. 39.
141 Macherey 1998, p. 86.
142 eid4.
143 Macherey 1998, p. 43.
144 Lalande 2010, ‘Réel’, pp. 900, 902. In For Marx, Althusser writes that ‘Pour nous, le “réel”
n’est pas un mot d’ordre théorique: le réel est l’objet réel, existant, indépendamment de
sa connaissance, – mais qui ne peut être défini que par sa connaissance’. Althusser 2005,
p. 257.
145 eiip8 and 9. In Chapter 2, I will offer a critique of Alain Badiou’s assertion that Althusser’s
term ‘the real’ refers to Spinozist substance, to argue instead that it would be more coher-
ent to take it as the infinite set of all things. In Chapter 3, I will follow Macherey’s expo-
sition of the Spinozist distinction between nonexistent and actually existing things, to
argue that Marx’s schematic formalisation of the law of the rate and mass of surplus value
in Chapter 11 of Capital should rightly be understood as distinguishing between actually
In the case of Althusser, among the key documents that can serve to clarify
his properly Spinozist understanding of the attributes of thought and extension
is an unpublished manuscript from 16 June 1967.146 Here Althusser summarises
a discussion with Stanislas Breton on the nature of structural causality and
the attributes. Althusser emphatically rejects Breton’s assertion that in Spinoza
the attributes can be understood to emanate from substance, as an expressive
form of causality in which a reified substance retains its transcendence to the
attributes and modal expressions of being.147 Instead, Althusser affirms the ‘dis-
continuity’ and ‘cut’ [coupure] between Spinoza’s various orders or topoi of
being (substance, attributes, infinite and finite modes): ‘Though one may have
the illusion of a continuity of “emanation” between the “orders” [in fact] there
is a non-preinscription of these cuts in the concept of substance and in the
concept of immanent causality’.
The various Spinozist orders of being do not derive or emanate from sub-
stance, Althusser continues in his notes to their discussion, they are not
‘inscribed in advance’, but simply exist, as a given ‘Faktum’, as the ‘immanent
(not eminent) cause of the structuration of these regions in their efficacity,
regions structured insofar as they are separated by “cuts”’.148 These various
dimensions of being thus determine the Spinozist orders of substance as what
Althusser calls a topography [topique] of ‘defined regions’, a decentred struc-
ture of causality without a transcendent subject, a position strictly analogous
to the Freudian topographic model of the psyche.149
The point to be taken here in relation to the theoretical position of Reading
Capital is that the elliptical nature of Althusser’s presentation of the abso-
lute distinction between the orders or attributes of thought and the real as he
reads Marx’s 1857 ‘Introduction’ in his own ‘Introduction’ to Reading Capital
existing things (such as the ‘bakers’ and ‘spinners’ Marx invokes) and atemporal, nonexis-
tent things such as the generic formula for this law that he introduces to the 1875 French
translation of Capital.
146 Juan Domingo Estop is the first to have discussed this fascinating document, and to have
reproduced it in its entirety as an Appendix to his Althusser et Spinoza (2021).
147 This position from 1967 might be brought to bear on Althusser’s later, autocritique of his
‘theoreticism’ as a putative neglect of the ‘primat de la théorie sur la pratique’ (1974, p. 176).
Althusser’s later practicist position should be rejected in favour of the Spinozist one artic-
ulated in these private notes on the discussion with Breton: for a Spinozist materialist
critique, there is a primacy of neither theory nor practice, as though theory emanates
from practice (as ‘class struggle in theory’), or the converse. Instead, thought (theory) and
extension (practice) must be conceived in their sheer immanence within a structure of
causality.
148 Cited at Estop 2021, p. 286.
149 Estop 2021, p. 288. On the latter, see Laplanche and Pontalis 2018, pp. 448–453.
Given that Althusser categorically identified Spinoza as ‘in my view the great-
est philosopher of all time’,152 and publicly asserted in 1968 (in response to
Paul Ricœur’s invocations of Kantian and Hegelian positions) that ‘I am a
Spinozist’,153 it is quite surprising that one has to search through his archives
to find obscure suggestions of the link between Spinoza’s most basic, found-
ing principle and one of Althusser’s most famous and original concepts. This
absence of explicit reference to Spinozist substance is no doubt due to
Althusser’s allergy to grandiose metaphysical pronouncements and guarantees,
a position he maintained from For Marx through late texts such as Philoso-
150 In Chapter 2, I will discuss Pierre Macherey’s penetrating critique and rejection of the
philosophical commonplace of the ‘parallelism’ of the Spinozist attributes.
151 For a different parsing of the distinction between an exoteric and esoteric Althusser, see
Thomas 2013, pp. 144–5.
152 Althusser 2015, p. 76.
153 Althusser 1969.
ism of monism, with its universal dialectics. Materialist dialectics is an erroneous theory
invented by the Soviet Academy of Sciences. It just replaces Hegel’s “spirit” or “absolute
idea” with “matter”’. See also Vargas 2008, p. 162.
159 ‘What Freud means in the first place by ‘Phantasien’ are … fictions which the subject cre-
ates and recounts to himself in the waking state’ (Laplanche and Pontalis 2018, p. 315).
Althusser’s definition of materialist analysis as ‘not telling oneself stories’ invokes pre-
cisely this Freudian topos of phantasy (Althusser 1994, p. 221). I discuss Althusser’s defini-
tion in chapter 2. As Althusser constantly reasserted, ideology takes real material forms:
in Central Europe, infants are often bathed in an upright bucket or kyblík that reassur-
ingly supports and encases them in a facsimile of the intra-uterine experience. In contrast,
Lacan would name the affective position of the interminable scientific production of
knowledge anxiety: ‘With anxiety, … it’s a matter of going deeper into the function of the
object in the analytic experience’. (Lacan 2016, p. 43). On the latter, see also Matthys 2023,
p. 260.
160 On Plekhanov’s reading of Spinoza as an empiricist materialism, see Matysik 2023, Chap-
ter 6.
161 Stalin, Dialectical and Historical Materialism (1938), available online at https://www.
marxists.org/reference/archive/stalin/works/1938/09.htm. See also Estop 2021, pp. 26–
9; Elliott 1987, pp. 20, 127–9; Van Ree 2000; Thomas 2008; Oitinnen 2022. Plekhanov’s
monism was far exceeded in theoretical vulgarity by Vladimir Shulyatikov’s farcical claims
that ‘Spinoza’s conception of the world is the song triumphant of capital’, his thought
putatively the mere and direct reflection of the capitalistic organisation of the forces of
production of his era. Cited in Oitinnen 2022, p. 3.
162 Stalin, cited in Estop 2021, p. 28.
gies …) are mere phenomena of a unique reality that constitutes their essence’.
Here, Althusser observes, Mury rejoins ‘the latent substantialism’ of Plekhanov:
‘There is a unique mother-reality [réalité-mère], a sort of active substance, an
essence-cause producing effects that are its proper phenomena …. [as a form
of] of substantialism’.167
Flatly rejecting the speculative ontological dictates on the nature of reality of
Mury and those of Plekhanov and Stalin behind him, Althusser seeks to rebut
Mury by refusing all theoretical guarantees, asserting in reply that the example
of ‘the unity of a mode of production, in reality, has nothing “moniste” about it,
because the mode of production, is, in itself, a highly complex totality, in which
the forces of production, themselves complex, and the relations of production,
attain their unity in this real complexity’.168
Reality, Althusser asserts, ‘is not in the least materially constituted by a
unique reality, substance, matter, etc.’.169 Refusing all imaginary, specious guar-
antees of the nature of ontological totality, Althusser’s reply to Mury is simply
to note that ‘the unity of society for Marx … is not the unity of a substance or
single reality, but that of a structured totality …: nature, instruments of produc-
tion (tools, machines, techniques), men, technical knowledge’.170 Where Mury
talks of speculative first principals, Althusser rejects monism by invoking the
differential complexity of actually existing singular things. While Mury’s essay
lacks the clarity of Althusser’s that might make it a coherent defence of sub-
stance monism rather than a mere polemical assertion,171 Althusser’s truncated
rebuttal in For Marx articulates in turn only a polemical desire to suppress the
‘theoretically harmful’ ontological category of substance as flatly equivalent
to monism, a theoretical acting-out, one that in its refusal explicitly to work
through the problematic of a materialist reformulation of Spinozist substance
as structural causality, leaves the impression of a mechanistic pluralism of het-
erogeneous existing singular things.
172 eiip8, 9.
173 Macherey 1997, pp. 81–97.
174 Macherey 1997, p. 85.
175 Macherey 1997, p. 87. In distinguishing between nonexistent and existent things, Spinoza
is clearly reacting to Descartes’ overtly psychologistic understanding of essential: ‘[B]y
essence we understand the thing insofar as it is objectively in the intellect, by existence
[existentia], this same thing insofar as it is outside the intellect [rem eandem prout est
extra intellectum]’ (Descartes, ‘Correspondance, vol. 4,’ cited in David, 2014: 194). In con-
trast to Descartes’ psychologism, Spinoza’s purely logical understanding of res singulares
non existentes would await further theoretical development until Bolzano’s concept of
Vorstellungen an sich [Representations as such], the primary universal characteristic of
which he formulates as “Vorstellungen an sich haben kein Dasein” [“Representations as
such have no existence”] in the Wissenschaftslehre (Bolzano 1978: 75). I discuss Bolzano in
Chapter four. Spinoza’s emphasis on the atemporality of nonexistent things (vs. essence as
a lack of spatial extension, as in the thereness of ‘being there’), however, is quite unique in
The crucial corollary to the nature of nonexistent things, that which above
all and absolutely distinguishes them from actually existing things (and here
we return to the problem of monism and the heterogeneity of the real), is that
they are, Macherey observes, ‘by definition abstracted from all consideration of
duration and deploy themselves in the perspective of eternity’. The idea of actu-
ally existing singular things, in contrast, necessarily ‘implies’, Spinoza writes,
‘the existence by which they are said to endure’ (earum ideae etiam existentiam
per quam durare dicuntur involvunt). Macherey emphasises the radicality and
absolute nature of this distinction, insofar as it precludes any understanding of
existence as the actualisation of a (temporally) precedent essence, ‘the tempo-
ral passage for singular things from essence to existence’. Essence and existence
must instead be understood as ‘completely distinct manners of being, equally
real’.176
It is at this point, then, that Macherey inserts his rejection of monism as the
consequent implication of this position. Here is Macherey:
Here, as Althusser had before him, Macherey limits the problem of monism
to the domain of things (les êtres or ‘beings’ in Heideggerian jargon) rather
than Being qua Being and the nature of substance. Considered alongside his
materialist explication of Spinozist substance as uncountable causa sui, how-
ever, while certainly not accounting for the real diversity of Marxist theo-
ries of monism since Plekhanov, Macherey’s Althusserian critique nonethe-
less constitutes a coherent and compelling critique of substance monism as
such.
the complex history of the related concepts of the Latin existentia, the French and English
‘existence,’ and the German pseudo-synonyms Existenz and Dasein (David, 2014).
176 Macherey 1997, p. 91.
177 Ibid.
178 In his essay ‘En matérialiste’ (to be discussed in the following chapter), Pierre Macherey
more consistently than Althusser (who continued to the end to speak positively of cer-
tain forms of materialism), generalises this rejection of all forms of materialism, to invoke
instead a fidelity to a materialist dialectic, a commitment shared as well by Alain Badiou
(see below Chapter 5).
179 Montag 2013, pp. 84–6; Estop 2021, pp. 138–44. I discuss Macherey’s critique of the concept
of totality in Chapter 3.
180 ‘Althusser’, Estop insightfully writes in his analysis of Althusser’s 1967 notes to the discus-
sion with Stanislas Breton (discussed above), ‘makes of Spinoza his fundamental philo-
sophical reference for a theory of immanent causality. … The different orders of being are
not prefigured either positively or negatively [as a negative theology or the absent cause
of metonymic causality] in the cause; their discontinuity is of the order of the Faktum, and
not that of a necessary derivation from a [transcendent] essence. … There is only a factual
relation of substance to the attributes and these to the modes: a simple ‘there is’ [il y a]
without guarantee and without justification. … Substance [for the Althusser of these 1967
notes] is nothing but structure as such, the complexity of a plural infinity that [immedi-
ately] expresses and thus effectuates an infinite power [puissance]’ (Estop 2021, pp. 154–5,
my translation).
position of ‘class struggle in theory’ is to risk ending up, with no small irony,
at precisely the Stalinist epistemology For Marx had rightly and so powerfully
excoriated. At its most extreme, this position is nothing less than the regres-
sive endorsement of a bureaucratic politicisation of science (Lysenkoism) such
as that explicitly formulated for the pcf by Jacques Desanti in a 1950 edito-
rial for La nouvelle critique: i.e., that ‘taking a proletarian stance in science and
adopting the criteria of proletarian science [are] preconditions for objectivity
in scientific debate’.192
When Althusser made the political decision publicly to reject the onto-
logical and epistemological guarantees of substance monism in For Marx, in
order to categorically distinguish his theoretical intervention from the vulgar
materialism of Plekhanov and Stalin, he suppressed the category of Spinozist
Substance from his (public) discourse, developing the concept of structural
causality as finite determination within a contingent (capitalist) social form.
Though Macherey echoes Althusser’s condemnation of substance monism in
his five-volume commentary on the Ethics, he articulates in its place a rigor-
ous, materialist understanding of Spinozist Substance as uncounted causal-
ity.
To count Spinozist substance as One (i.e., as a monism) is for Macherey
to grasp substance from the standpoint of the imagination, which is to say,
inadequately, ‘by replacing [the concept of substance] in a network of exterior
determinations in which it is made to figure as one thing existing alongside or
above [in transcendence to] all others, which is to deny its absolute self-relation
[rapport à soi] that excludes any relation to another thing than itself’.193 Sub-
stance, in Macherey’s reading of the Ethics as a materialist dialectic of pure
immanence, cannot be ‘considered as ‘one’ [une] substance, but as subsisting
[le subsister], or existing [l’exister], considered as such’.194
For Macherey, if Proposition 1 of Ethics I emphasises the priority of sub-
stance to its modal affections, this implies not only the overarching Spinozist
epistemological imperative to ‘think the real in its totality according to
[Spinoza’s] synthetic procedure … from cause to effects, and not the inverse’,
but also, and at least as importantly, the unstated corollary of this proposi-
tion as the Spinozist position of a radical immanence of the attributes: that,
in other words, ‘substance is [in contrast to its affectations] not first in nature
in relation to its attributes. There is no more priority of substance in relation to
1 To be sure, the second edition of Lire le Capital that appeared in two volumes in 1968, com-
prised only of Althusser and Balibar’s texts (and which served for the various international
translations of the book), was eventually completed in 1973 with a third and fourth vol-
ume, containing the original contributions of Rancière (Vol. iii) and Macherey and Establet
(Vol. iv). That said, even among Francophone readers, who save a few specialists can be said
to have actually read that obscure fourth volume in the waning years of Althusserianism in
the 1970s?
2 Macherey has offered a surprisingly modest, even resentful disavowal of his contribution to
Lire le Capital: ‘When, with fifty years’ distance, I reread [my] contribution, I see all of its
imperfections. … When, subsequently, I was addressed as a ‘coauthor’ of Reading Capital,
I could not prevent myself feeling a certain malaise …. In reality, Reading Capital has only
one author: it is Althusser who, when he constructed this book on the basis of the work-
ing documents [we] provided him with, made a work unto itself, for which he himself bears
responsibility’ (Lasowski 2016, pp. 176–7).
3 rc, p. 191.
4 rc, p. 192.
tial nature as commodity.5 ‘Wealth’ is never anything more than the empirical
definition Marx gives it: ‘a mass of commodities’. In contrast, the endpoint of
Macherey’s exposition, value, is a rich concept, one that will require the entire,
incomplete exposition of Capital volumes i–iii to elaborate. Secondly, however,
Macherey argues that wealth, for all its superficiality and brevity of appear-
ance in Marx’s analysis, is nonetheless purely a concept. Wealth can never be
confused with any of its empirical manifestations; it is and remains purely a
concept.
Macherey’s analysis attends closely to the logical components and operators
he identifies in the opening pages of Capital. These constitute what he terms
‘intermediaries’, the ‘instruments of rationality’ that allow for the construction
of a rigorous demonstration. Macherey’s assertion that the various concepts
laid out in these opening lines of Capital are fundamentally and necessarily
heterogeneous is a point his own demonstration will sustain and develop step
by step; the notion of conceptual heterogeneity constitutes, moreover, ‘one of
the fundamental conditions of scientific rigour’. The system of Marx’s concepts,
and the system of rational operators more generally, in this view, consists of
various components that do not coexist ‘on one and the same level of intelligi-
bility’, but which instead inhabit multiple, incommensurable planes.6
This assertion next leads Macherey to consider the relations of heterogene-
ity between the four concepts under consideration: the ‘empirical form’ of
wealth, the contradictory pair of ‘factors’ of the commodity that are use-value
and exchange-value, and, finally, the purely relational concept of value. If use-
value, like wealth, remains tied to the empirical, but grasped as ‘the notion of
a thing’ rather than via its sensuous existence, exchange-value in contrast only
exists as a relation between commodities.7 This dual nature of the commodity,
5 rc, p. 190.
6 rc, p. 188.
7 rc, p. 194. This key point, first elaborated by Macherey in 1965, will undergo intensive devel-
opment by Michael Heinrich in his close reading of the first seven chapters of Capital: ‘Why
can’t we grasp value-objectivity in a single commodity’, Heinrich asks? ‘This is due to the
social character of the substance of value, which was emphasised in the first subsection [of
Capital]. The substance of value, abstract labour, is not inherent to a single commodity, but
rather held in common by two commodities that are exchanged. … The table can only become
an expression of equal human labour through exchange, when confronting other commodi-
ties. Then the various particular and individual acts of labour are reduced to equal human
labour. From this “purely social” character of value-objectivity, Marx says that it follows “self-
evidently” that “it can only appear in the social relation between commodity and commodity”
(1976: 139). … Commodities have value-objectivity only in the social relation of one com-
modity to another – which is why it first comes to light here. Prior to and outside of this
relation, they are mere use-values: they are on the way to becoming commodities, but far
from being commodities. When Marx speaks of the value of a single commodity (or its
magnitude of value), he always presupposes a value-relation to another commodity, of
which the individual commodity is a part’. Heinrich 2021, pp. 93–5.
8 rc, p. 195.
9 rc, p. 196. In the next chapter I will argue against Macherey that Marx’s presentation of
the concepts of use-value and exchange-value is in no sense based upon a logic of con-
tradiction [Widerspruch], but that the two are simply factual aspects or attributes of the
commodity that coexist in ‘opposition’ [Gegensatz] without contradiction.
10 rc, p. 203, original emphasis.
11 rc, p. 205, translation modified, italics in original.
has no empirical content.12 Unlike wealth or the commodity, value, the con-
cept of the measure allowing for the exchange-based equality of empirically
nonidentical commodities, is purely and only that, a concept. Like any other
concept, it is real but nonexistent, a reality in the attribute of thought alone,
rather than the empirical attribute of sensuous extension.
The conceptual relation that is value, Macherey continues, poses the equal-
ity of two commodities as a formula, a = b; it is, in other words, ‘defined as a
relation of expression’.13 Unlike the qualitative, empirical relation of two use-
values standing side by side in the market, the relation of exchange-value is
characterised by the extinction of all qualities. Fungibility is thus more pre-
cisely represented as a purely quantitative schematisation, as the expression of
relative value: ‘ax = by (a is so much of b)’.14
It is this schematic reduction of the commodity form to a purely quantita-
tive relation that then definitively displaces Macherey’s analysis in its final step,
to enjoin the concept of value itself: Marx’s ‘new analysis [now addressing of
the concept of value] begins with a decisive choice: the refusal to study the
exchange relation as a qualitative relation, to only consider it in its quantita-
tive content’.15 It is this pure conceptualisation, then, that will finally allow for
the adequate (initial) construction of the concept of value, as ‘the structure of
the relation’ of exchange itself.16
The heterogeneous, nondialectical series of logical steps Macherey iden-
tifies in Marx’s exposition then suddenly culminates in a parenthetical ges-
ture of pure conceptual abstraction, momentarily abstracting, that is, from
Marx’s exposition itself to articulate a purely axiomatic statement regarding
the nature of conceptual formalisation. It is possible, Macherey provision-
ally concludes from this exposition, to ‘formulate a general rule: … to com-
pare objects non-empirically, it is necessary as a preliminary to determine the
general form of this measurement … It is not possible to make a relation of
12 ‘In experience, it is possible to conceive that two things stand alongside the other, that
they are juxtaposed (like commodities in wealth). But they do not explicitly tolerate any
relation; from the standpoint of experience, between two things and one thing there is a
quantitative difference, but absolutely no qualitative difference’ (rc, p. 200).
13 Ibid.
14 I will present a more complex and developed version of this position first asserted by
Macherey, in my analysis in the next chapter of Marx’s introduction of a formula to
schematise the Law of the Rate and Mass of Surplus Value that is the object of Chapter 11
in Roy’s 1875 French translation of Capital.
15 rc, p. 200.
16 rc, p. 201.
17 rc, p. 201. Here too, I will argue in the next chapter that Marx rigorously and systematically
adheres to this proposition of Macherey’s above all in Chapter 11 of Capital.
18 rc, p. 201.
19 In this sense, Macherey’s precociously original analysis already points forward in 1965 to
Althusser’s assertion in his late writings (described in the previous chapter) that Marx’s
process of exposition proceeds in its demonstration through the successive ‘positioning’
[position] of concepts, as opposed to their negative dialectical (‘Hegelian’) aufhebung.
Instead, Althusser will argue, Marx’s order of exposition is no mere (structuralist/formal-
ist) combinatory, but in fact derives its materialist necessity from the priority of Marx’s
preliminary enquiries (Grundrisse, etc.) to the drafting of Capital.
20 rc, p. 205.
21 ‘As mere things’, Macherey writes, ‘objects are differentiated by their uses, i.e. their irre-
ducibility. If this character is set aside then at the same time as their empirical qualities
disappear, there appears, not their quantitative aspect, but another quality (of a quite dif-
ferent nature: not directly observable): … It will be precisely value whose substance it will
then be possible to determine’ (rc, p. 206).
22 rc, p. 206.
Pierre Macherey’s next work, A Theory of Literary Production, might seem, to all
appearances, a mere work of literary criticism, familiar in its genre, modest in
its intentions, a study in which, after a somewhat lengthy methodological intro-
duction, Macherey proceeds to offer a number of ‘materialist’ analyses of works
ranging from Lenin’s comments on Tolstoy to Jules Verne, Jorge Luis Borges, and
Defoe’s Robinson Crusoe. Such a view, however, would profoundly misrepresent
the enormous scope and compass of the book’s epistemological implications.
Instead, the achievement of A Theory of Literary Production is far more sweep-
ing than the analysis of a handful of classic novels; Macherey, in this, his first
book, in point of fact puts forward a generic protocol for the materialist analy-
sis of textual, symbolic objects of all types, a compellingly original analytical
practice for the critique of discourse as such, a procedure that can then, in
the next chapter, illuminate Marx’s process of exposition in Capital, moving
beyond Macherey’s all-too-brief propositions in his contribution to Reading
Capital.
It will surprise none of his readers that materialism in Macherey’s under-
standing receives a comprehensively Spinozist inflection. While Macherey only
mentions Spinoza nine times in Theory of Literary Production, and then only
in passing, Warren Montag has shown the degree to which Spinoza’s epis-
temology – inflected through a series of intensive exchanges with Althusser
from 1961 onward – underwrites and founds an encompassing philosophico-
critical project.23 Indeed, it is now clear, given the trajectory of Macherey’s
research, that from his initial, precocious contribution to Reading Capital in
1965, through his explosive and highly influential critique of Hegel’s misread-
ings of Spinoza in Hegel or Spinoza (1979), and culminating in his extraordi-
narily meticulous, systematic, and original interpretation of Spinoza’s Ethics
across five volumes and over a thousand pages, Macherey has synthetically
redeployed Spinoza to articulate a comprehensive theory of materialist anal-
ysis, one that fully takes into account and builds upon the classic Althusserian
critiques of empiricism, hermeneutics, totality, and negative-Hegelian dialec-
tics.
precisely … the knowledge’. rc, p. 43, emphasis in original. Similarly, in ‘On the Materialist
Dialectic’, Althusser writes, in terms that directly invoke the epistemology of Jean Cavaillès
and Gaston Bachelard, that ‘a science never works on an existence whose essence is pure
immediacy and singularity (“sensations” of “individuals”) … A science always works on
existing concepts’. Althusser 2005, p. 184.
28 Macherey 2006, p. 6.
29 Macherey 2006, pp. 8, 10, translation modified.
30 Macherey 2006, p. 13.
31 Macherey 2006, p. 85, translation modified.
32 Macherey 2006, p. 87.
40 Macherey’s critique of totality will prove essential in my critique of Chris Arthur’s reading
of Capital in the following chapter.
41 Montag 2013, Chapters 3–5.
42 Lévi-Strauss, cited in Montag 2013, p. 68.
the hidden depths of the work, but is instead constituted in the very absence of
a coherent totality of meaning, in the productive décalage and ‘real complexity’
of the constructed thought object.50 Analysis – truly adequate, materialist anal-
ysis of an object of knowledge – can in this view only refer to ‘the constitution of
a structure’, the interpretive act of structuration (structurer) as the demonstra-
tive deployment of elements, a process that paradoxically constructs the object
of knowledge in its infinite incompletion, as an ‘absence’ (of the whole).51 Such
an absence will attend to this incoherence, to the gaps and contradictions of a
text, as what Althusser had famously termed in Reading Capital a ‘symptomatic
[symptomale] reading’.52
Macherey will in fact address this problem in his 1981 essay ‘En matérialiste’,
to distinguish categorically between the process of materialist critique as the
science of causes and all forms of materialism.57 There he argues that all mate-
rialisms, including the Marxist construct ‘dialectical materialism’, are ‘theories
of matter’ to be rejected as such in their inherent idealism (in positing matter as
transcendent prime mover). Macherey does not argue this point in sustained
fashion, but instead punctually invokes Engels’s attempt to elaborate a ‘gen-
eral theory of movement’, the failure of which (‘this path led him nowhere, …
abandoning it in incompletion’) serves to indicate in abbreviated fashion the
impossibility of a coherent doctrine of materialism: ‘Engels’s aborted attempt
has produced an essential consequence: it is henceforth no longer possible to
be a materialist’.58
56 In La philosophie de Marx (2014, p. 98), Étienne Balibar observes in passing that in the
1845 Theses on Feuerbach, ‘Marx’s materialism has nothing to do with a reference to matter
[but is instead] a strange “materialism without matter” ’. Alberto Toscano has extrapolated
on Balibar’s suggestive comment in relation to Sohn-Rethel and I.I. Rubin’s analysis of
the value form, proposing that Marx’s subsequent analysis of the capitalist social form of
value constitutes precisely such a materialism, one in which, as Marx famously comments
in Capital, ‘not an atom of matter enters into the objectivity of commodities as values’.
Toscano 2014. See Marx 1976, p. 138.
57 Macherey 1999, pp. 87–113.
58 Macherey 1999, p. 88.
In the wake of his key contribution to Reading Capital, Macherey has in his pub-
lished work only occasionally returned to the analysis of Marx’s magnum opus,
most notably and extensively in the talk he gave on 13 July 1967, at Cérisy-la-
Salle during the conference ‘Le centenaire du Capital’.62 Macherey’s discussion
of the object of analysis in Capital in both these texts (as is the case in A Theory
of Literary Production) closely follows the series of imperatives first presented
in Reading Capital and reiterated in Theory: Macherey argues that Marx’s epis-
70 Under this category of high Althusserianism I would include not only the published vol-
umes For Marx, Reading Capital, A Theory of Literary Production, and Macherey and
Balibar’s contributions to the Cérisy colloquium ‘Le centennaire du Capital’, but also the
various exchanges of the Groupe Spinoza and related texts such as Althusser’s 1966 ‘Sur
Lévi-Strauss’ in Althusser 1994. On the Groupe Spinoza, Alain Badiou has reflected: ‘The
Groupe Spinoza was a group composed by Althusser, with some friends of Althusser, all
reading Capital practically, engaged in the project to write a sort of synthesis of our epis-
temological convictions. The idea was to produce a fundamental book concerning theory:
concerning what theory is, what constitutes an epistemological rupture and so on; to pro-
pose something like an educational book concerning all these sorts of themes. All that
was destroyed by 1968 and, after that, by very strong political differences and struggles’.
Badiou 2017, p. 25.
71 As Althusser famously wrote in the 1972 Essays in Self-Criticism, ‘If we were never struc-
turalists, we can now explain why: … we were guilty of an equally powerful and com-
promising passion: we were Spinozists [nous avons été spinozistes]’. Quoted in Morfino
2015, p. 2. Vittorio Morfino points to the decisive influence Spinoza brought to bear on
Althusser’s 1965 reading of Capital: ‘The reference to Spinoza … is fundamental with
respect to three decisive questions in the Althusserian re-reading of Marxism: the process
of knowledge, structural causality, and ideology’. Morfino 2015, pp. 2–3. For an outstand-
ing, often critical and always informative recent example of the ongoing effort to read
Capital as a palimpsest of Hegel’s Logic, see Moseley and Smith 2015.
2) That the attributes do not coexist in ordinal relation implies in turn that
they do not consist of elements defining one another as a totality through
their negative relation. ‘If all the attributes together belong to substance,
constituting its being,74 they do not coexist within it as parts that would
adjust to each other to finally compose the total system. If this were so,
the attributes would define themselves in relation to each other through
their reciprocal lack’.75
3) This further implies that substance itself cannot be divided up into its
various (infinite) attributes, but is instead indivisible. ‘To think the infi-
nite, whether it be in the attribute (in a kind) or in substance (absolutely),
is to exclude any notion of divisibility; substance is entirely complete in
each of its attributes (because it is identical to them), just as, moreover,
all extension is in each drop of water or all thought is in each idea …. The
infinite is not a number; this is why it evades all division. Indivisible sub-
stance is not the sum of all its attributes’.76
From these propositions Macherey then concludes that the relation of the
attributes is one of unitary (rather than comparative, negative) identity: ‘As
an attribute of substance, thought is identical to everything and therefore has
nothing above it, but the sequence through which it is realised poses, at the
same time, its absolute equality with all other forms in which substance is also
expressed, and these are infinite in number’.77
We then come to what must count among Macherey’s most radical inter-
ventions in the field of thought, his seemingly scholastic reading of Spinoza’s
proposition eiip7. The so-called parallelism of the attributes (a term that
Spinoza never uses in any of his writings, and which Macherey attributes to
Leibniz), Macherey shows conclusively, is quite simply ‘inadmissible’. This must
be the case, Macherey argues, if one reads the wording of proposition eii7
attentively: in the statement ‘Ordo et connexio idearum idem est, ac ordo, et
connexio rerum’, Spinoza identifies the order and connection of ideas as not
the same as the order of physical bodies in extension, but rather the same as
that of ‘things’ (rerum), of all things without distinction, including, of course,
ideas themselves: ‘The word things [res] absolutely does not, in a restrictive
way, designate the modes of the attribute of extension, but the modes of all
the attributes, whatever they are, including thought itself …. This is one and the
same order, one and the same connection’.78
74 eip10s.
75 Macherey 2011, p. 100.
76 Ibid.
77 Macherey 2011, p. 74.
78 Macherey 2011, p. 106, emphasis in original.
79 Macherey 1997, pp. 71–81. I insist on this development in Macherey’s 1997 volume, which
as of this writing is, like the other four volumes in the series, unavailable in English transla-
tion. Not only does it constitute the most developed explication of Macherey’s substantial-
ist, Spinozist materialist critique, but, moreover, the 400-plus pages of this crucial second
volume of his explication are currently out of print even in the French original. All trans-
lations from this volume are mine.
80 Macherey 1997, p. 71. Macherey’s analysis of this famous proposition of the Ethics strongly
resonates with that of Martial Geroult. See Peden 2014, p. 158.
81 Macherey 1997, p. 72.
82 Macherey 1997, p. 73.
9 On Telling Stories
86 One striking example of this incongruity is Althusser’s assertion in ‘The Underground Cur-
rent of the Materialism of the Encounter’ (1982) that ‘for Spinoza, the object of philosophy
is the void’. This is not simply a ‘paradoxical thesis’, as Althusser observes; it is quite simply
antithetical to Spinoza’s explicit and extensive critique of the concept of the void in Book i
of the Ethics. The free-floating associations of Althusser’s argument culminate weakly in
the metaphorical (rather than ontological) conclusion that Spinoza asserted ‘the void that
is philosophy itself ’. Althusser 2006, p. 178, italics in original. In fact, Macherey shows that
Spinoza, reaffirming Descartes’s critique, decisively rejects the atomism of the Ancients
as fully inadequate, imaginary representation, to explicitly affirm instead that ‘matter is
everywhere the same [materia ubique eadem est] in its substantial principle’. Macherey
1998, p. 124. ‘Corporeal substance’, Spinoza writes unambiguously, ‘can be conceived only
as infinite, one, and indivisible’ (41 eip15Sch). Macherey consequently reads these pas-
sages in proposition 15 of Book i and its Scholium as ‘the affirmation of a plenitude [of
substance] leaving no place for void, absence, or negativity …. Substance is thought reality
in the intense intimacy of its self-relation … such that nothing else, not even nothingness
… can disturb its infinite positivity …. To conceive of extension as constituted of distinct
parts is to deny its infinity’. In contrast to the Ancients’ imaginary depiction of atoms in
a void, ‘only the intellect’, Macherey concludes, ‘is apt [en mesure] to understand that the
materiality of extended substance is given at once as an indivisible totality’. Macherey
1998, pp. 128, 129. Althusser’s related, imagistic redeployment of the thesis of the paral-
lelism of the attributes in ‘Materialism of the Encounter’ – which Althusser claims ‘fall in
the empty space of their determination’ (Althusser 2006, p. 177) – repeats the philosoph-
ical commonplace of so-called parallelism that Macherey subjects to such extensive and
compelling critique in both Hegel or Spinoza (ch. 3) and his analysis of proposition 7 of
Ethics ii, discussed above.
87 Althusser 1990, p. 135. In Reading Capital, following Lenin, Althusser affirms that ‘In the
expression “historical materialism”, “materialism” means no more than science, and the
expression is strictly synonymous with that of “science of history” ’ (rc, p. 360). Althusser
will reiterate this definition, for example in ‘Lenin and Philosophy’: ‘Historical material-
ism thus means: science of history’, and again, in modified form, in ‘Lenin before Hegel’,
where he refers to ‘the materialist thesis of the material existence and of the objectivity
of scientific knowledge’. Althusser 2001, pp. 23, 83.
88 Althusser 1993b, p. 221.
92 Ibid.
93 Althusser 1997b, p. 10.
94 Althusser 1997b, pp. 10–11.
95 On Althusser and Macherey’s critique of Deleuze’s famous text, see Montag 2013, pp. 96–
100.
96 Althusser 1997b, p. 11.
What Althusser names his ‘nominalist’ materialism in this late, 1985 text
might indeed be more properly termed an axiomatic, substantialist material-
ist critique. For the proposition that the order of ideas and of things is the same
thing is indeed an axiomatic proposition for Spinoza: its ground lies not in the
apodictic, synthetic demonstration of proposition 7 in Ethics ii, but instead in
the initial axiomatic foundation of Spinoza’s entire system. It is in precisely this
sense that proposition eii7 explicitly refers the reader back to Ethics i, axiom 4.
It is axioms 4, 5, and 6 of Ethics I that together constitute the fundamen-
tal epistemological order of an inherent, necessary identity between the two
orders or attributes of thought and extension. While axioms 3–5 of Ethics I
affirm the necessary structure of causality under both the attributes of exten-
sion and the intellect, it is axiom 6 that draws these together to affirm that
the true idea ‘must be in conformity with its ideate [debet cum suo ideato con-
venire]’.97 Macherey’s interpretation of this key axiom bears citing in whole, as
it is this statement that arguably should be taken to summarise the entire epis-
temological apparatus of Althusser’s and Macherey’s thought:
97 EIAx6.
98 Macherey 1998, p. 61, my translation.
99 rc, p. 41.
100 Macherey 2012, p. 91.
thought reality and extended reality coincide in the absolute being of sub-
stance, where they are only distinguished by the intellect. … There is just
as much materiality, no more nor less, in reality envisaged from the per-
spective [angle] of the mental as when envisaged from the perspective
of the bodily. … Mental reality is a reality unto itself [une réalité à part
entière], whose elements, ideas, are materially existing things, no less con-
sistent, in their own order, than those that materially compose extended
nature.101
105 In The Lectures on the Philosophy of History, Hegel, to ground his accusation of Carte-
sianism in the Spinozist system, voices an astounding misrepresentation. Here is Hegel:
‘Spinoza’s philosophy is the objectification of that of Descartes, in the form of absolute
truth. The elemental thought of Spinoza’s idealism is this. What is true is quite simply the
one substance, whose attributes are thought and extension. … What comes second after
substance is the attributes. … Substance has only two attributes, Thought and Extension’
(Hegel, cited in Macherey 2011, pp. 82–3). Even the most casual reader of Spinoza must be
shocked at this extraordinary omission by close readers such as Hegel and Badiou, since
Spinoza affirms unambiguously and repeatedly that substance is comprised not of two
but of an infinity of attributes (eip11), of which humans perceive only two, thought and
extension.
106 Badiou 2017, p. 32.
107 Ibid.
108 This is the case, with even less ambiguity, in the more recent Immanance des vérités: ‘Pour
Spinoza, … les relations de causalité entre les choses matérielles immanentes à l’attribut
étendue sont identiques – isomorphes – aux relations de causalité entre les choses idéelles
immanentes à l’attribut pensée. … On voit bien qu’ici la structure des attributs est ce qui
atteste, par isomorphie, l’identité invariable et suprême de la Substance.’ Badiou 2018b,
p. 377.
109 Badiou 2017, p. 32.
110 Badiou 2017, p. 41, my emphasis.
111 Badiou 2017, p. 33.
in fact a real difficulty’.112 Here the real question is whether or not for Spinoza,
like Althusser, the ‘order’ of the attributes is nonidentical. Rather than pursuing
an immanent critique of Spinoza’s text,113 Badiou’s deus ex machina solution to
this putative problem is surprising, to say the least: ‘It is a difficulty, the solu-
tion of which is for Kant “schematism”, … precisely the mechanism by which the
formal organisation of the categories of knowledge are related to the external
existence, which we cannot know, of the world’.114 Badiou proceeds to sug-
gest an awkward admixture of Spinoza and Kant in his reading of Althusser to
resolve a (nonexistent) problem: ‘a mixture of the immanent Spinozist vision
of two attributes of the same real with this Kantian schematism. There is only
one real: it is not an ontological dualism, but instead we find two attributes of
the same substance but without parallelism, without identity of the order’.115
What Badiou here speciously presents as Althusser’s rejection of Spinoza’s
‘parallelist’ position (‘we find two attributes of the same substance but without
parallelism, without identity of the order’) is precisely that which Macherey’s
literal, grammatical reading of eiip7 has shown to be its actual proposition:
the attributes are not to be reified any more than substance. They are not two
things that can be compared point by point for their isomorphism, but are
‘that which the intellect perceives’ of substance (causality), remaining purely
and eternally heterogeneous: the concept of a circle is not round. How a neo-
Kantian schematism would mediate ‘two attributes of the same substance but
without parallelism’ remains unclear in this brief, ambiguous closing section of
Badiou’s (oral) text.116 What is immediately striking, however, is that Badiou, in
spontaneously reverting to a dualist understanding of the Spinozist attributes,
suddenly requires a Kantian solution to a problem (the ‘parallelist’ dualism of
the attributes) that Spinoza himself has criticised and superseded. The ‘mate-
rialist schematism’ that Badiou calls for is already rendered superfluous by
Spinoza’s own understanding of the attributes.
Analogous to his argument that Spinoza has already pre-empted Hegel’s var-
ious critiques, Macherey himself appears already to have anticipated Badiou’s
recourse to Kant in Hegel or Spinoza. ‘Through his critique of Cartesianism’,
Macherey writes in Hegel or Spinoza, ‘Spinoza invalidates, in advance, a Kan-
tian type of problematic of knowledge, posed in terms of the relationship of
112 Ibid.
113 eiip7.
114 Badiou 2017, p. 33.
115 Ibid.
116 The text originates from a talk Badiou presented at Princeton University, 6 December 2013,
at the conference ‘Reading Capital Today’.
subject and object or form and content’, precisely the binary relationship that
it is the conceptual mission of Kantian ‘schematism’ to mediate.117 Badiou’s
importation of the Kantian schemata as deus ex machina in fact reintroduces
the Cartesian dualism of subject and object – what Althusser had provocatively
termed ‘the latent dogmatic empiricism of Cartesian idealism’ – that Spinoza’s
thought renders inoperative.118
Badiou takes Althusser at his word (‘The production process of the object
of knowledge takes place entirely in knowledge [… an order] which is differ-
ent from the real order of real genesis’) without questioning what the phrase
‘the real order of real genesis’ might mean. Judging from his initial claim (i.e.,
that Althusser’s ‘real [indicates] the Spinozist substance, that is, the totality of
what exists’), Badiou appears to assume that for Althusser the order of the real
indicates not the intellect’s apprehension of things via the attribute of sensu-
ous, temporal extension but substance itself, (mis)understood as a determinate
thing: as ‘the order of the real’.
It is worth citing Althusser’s proposition in whole, rather than Badiou’s trun-
cated version, because Althusser clearly bases his assertion of the heterogene-
ity of order not on the causal order of being qua being, but rather on the his-
torical, factual, sensuous existence of actually existing things, apprehended in
temporally determined extension:
Althusser in this passage predominantly uses the adjectival form of ‘real’, such
that the term ‘real’ here clearly refers to factual, temporal events sensuously
117 ‘If for Spinoza’, Macherey continues, ‘the attributes are forms or kinds of being, or natures,
or even essences, they are certainly not forms in opposition to a content, any more than
they are predicates in opposition to a subject, or abstract categories in opposition to a
concrete reality that would remain outside them’ (2011, p. 86).
118 rc, p. 40.
119 rc, p. 41, my emphasis of the passages Badiou suppresses.
120 eiip8.
121 eiip9.
sions, while the latter can be constructed adequately, without this implying that
this construction refer to the ontological, infinite nature of causality as such.
In fact, and despite his initial lapses in Reading Capital into an invocation of
the social ‘whole’ (which Macherey rightly criticised), Althusser almost entirely
avoids grandiose ontological statements on the nature of being, categorically
rejecting such idealism, for example in the unpublished text Philosophy for
Non-philosophers: ‘It is inordinately pretentious of idealist philosophy to claim
to “see” the whole, “think” the whole, or aspire to “totalisation”. What gives phi-
losophy this superhuman power?’122
In his truncated citation, Badiou does not cite Althusser’s key qualifying
phrase that supports the interpretation that Althusser is limiting his claim to
that of the order of actually existing singular things in their sensuous, tempo-
ral existence: it is precisely ‘the order of real historical genesis’ which is said
by Althusser to bear a different order from that of the adequately constructed
thought-concrete. Althusser’s example of such a ‘real historical genesis’ – which
again Badiou does not cite – is, precisely, ‘a given real-concrete totality (e.g., a
given historical nation)’, in other words, a phenomenal, temporal actually exist-
ing, singular (historical) thing. In the passage Badiou (partially) cites, it seems
clear enough that the term ‘real’ refers to the phenomenal order of appearance
of historical events as the intellect grasps them via the attribute of extension,
an order that is necessarily perceived in a manner limited and qualified not
only by the finite nature of human experience but above all by the inadequacy
of imaginary, ideological modes of thought.
This interpretation of Althusser’s admittedly ambiguous text is nonetheless
confirmed quite plainly in Althusser’s critique of historicism. Only a few pages
before the passage Badiou cites, Althusser argues that the order of ‘histori-
cal genesis’, necessarily suffers from the fetishistic inscription of ‘the illusion
of an immediate reading’, a necessarily symptomatic and compromised read-
ing of the fetishised document – whether the Bible, in Spinoza’s critique that
Althusser here refers to, or the fetishisation of the archival document in histori-
cist discourse more generally. Althusser moreover explicitly indicates Spinoza
as the originator of this critique of the fetishisation of the historical document:
Spinoza was ‘the first in the world to have proposed both a theory of history
and a philosophy of the opacity of the immediate’.123
Spinoza’s critique of representation – in the final proposition 49 of Ethics
book ii, de Mente – ultimately implicates, in Macherey’s reading, the entire
sensuous order of images and words (as diverse, arbitrary and conventional
signifiers), an order necessarily subject to the confusion of the imagination. In
contrast, the necessity of the idea remains defined by the materialist order of
the intellect, in its necessity absolutely distinct from that of mere sonorous and
imagistic extension. Here is Macherey:
Ideas are themselves things, mental things, which … are not a sort of
doubling of reality, as are [for Spinoza] representations, images, signs,
and words. … By affirming that images and words are products of bod-
ily extension, and nothing more, Spinoza does not wish to say that they
have more reality or even materiality than ideas; rather … they are things
of an entirely different order. … This is why ideas are not reducible to repre-
sentations of things, as images and signs are, because, as ideas, they bear
a potential for reality and activity that is conditioned by the position they
maintain in the order of thought.124
124 Macherey 1997, p. 392, emphasis added; see also Macherey 1994, p. 85.
over the coin and take the apple and bite into it, tasting its tartness, etc., etc.,
in an infinite complex of phenomenal impressions, causes, and affects that are
factually real, but inadequately understood.
In contrast, Marx’s analysis of the capitalist social form might tell me that
at the level of common notions, in a society governed by general commodifi-
cation, the coin in my pocket is the necessary general equivalent form of value
that commands the exchange of things of value, adequately explaining how it
comes to be the case that handing over a piece of metal causes the seller to
hand me the apple; that the commodification of food and other necessities as
ongoing primitive accumulation enforces via the threat of starvation the social
command that all subjects of capital sell their labour power to capital in order
to have that coin in their pocket in the first place; etc.
Furthermore, at the level of an intuitive science of the singularity of this sit-
uation, I might conclude that the cause of the seller’s resentment is not my
touching the apple but the socially enforced sale of his own labour power,
which required him to arrive at the market in early morning freezing tempera-
tures to pay for his own necessities in order not to starve, etc. The point again, is
that a single, complex order of causality – substance as ordo et connexio – will
be apprehended in radically heterogeneous forms depending on the attribute
in question.
At the more abstract level of a grand historical narrative, Althusser argues
that it is Marx who relays the Spinozist invention of ideology critique, bringing
its force to bear upon the determinant social structure of modernity, capitalism:
126 Jacques Bidet shows more generally in this fashion how Marx’s famous critique of the
fetishism of commodities in Volume i is systematically deployed at the level of the vari-
ous forms of appearance of capital in Volume 3, and that this development constitutes, in
other words, not merely a critique of ideological illusions (though it is of course that too),
but, in truly Spinozist fashion, a ‘theory of ideology’ that adequately renders the necessity
of these very forms of appearance for the system itself: ‘This is the very project of a theory
of ideology: to show what forms of consciousness are implied in the practice of its agents,
in relation to the function they occupy in the system that has been progressively defined’
in the course of the first two volumes of Capital (2005, p. 198, emphasis in original).
127 rc, p. 244.
128 rc, pp. 242, 244.
The fact that each of these times and each of these histories is relatively
autonomous does not make them so many domains which are indepen-
dent of the whole: the specificity of each of these times and of each of
these histories – in other words, their relative autonomy and indepen-
dence – is based on a certain type of articulation in the whole, and there-
fore on a certain type of dependence with respect to the whole …. The
synchronic is eternity in Spinoza’s sense, or the adequate knowledge of a
complex object by the adequate knowledge of its complexity.129
Lacking this ultimate identity of the order of the thought-object and the order
of the real adequately understood as structural causality, the capitalist real as
the necessity of its ‘structure of structures’, beyond its various ideological, het-
erogeneous forms of appearance – as Badiou reads Althusser, that is to say –
there would be no point to Marx’s project of a materialist critique of political
economy, and the three volumes of Capital would constitute a mere idealist
exercise in the imagining of a hypothetical form of social existence.130
The point, then, is that while the mere historical forms of appearance of
social life under capitalism do indeed follow an entirely different order from
the adequately developed thought-concrete that is Capital, as a materialist cri-
tique, Marx’s analysis nonetheless ultimately allows for the comprehension
of the essential nature of capitalism as a causal structure existing only in its
effects, as one and the same order, one and the same thing, as a ‘structure of
structures’, whether grasped conceptually or in the necessity of its historical
129 rc, pp. 247, 255. ‘The structure of the whole is articulated as the structure of an organic
hierarchised whole … governed by the order of a dominant structure’ (rc, p. 245; lc,
p. 282). Macherey, as discussed above, will privately critique Althusser’s references to the
‘whole’ as superfluous and misleading, in terms that he then systematically formulates, as
noted above, in A Theory of Literary Production.
130 This is the mistaken empiricist/idealist position Engels adopts in his review of Marx’s
1859 A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, where he writes that ‘The logi-
cal method of approach … is indeed nothing but the historical method, only stripped of
the historical form and of interfering contingencies. … Its further progress will be simply
the reflection, in abstract and theoretically consistent form, of the course of history’ (cited
in van der Linden and Hubman 2019, p. 4, my emphasis). Althusser summarises Engels’s
empiricist epistemology in the following terms: ‘Engels applies to the concepts of the
theory of history a coefficient of mobility borrowed directly from the concrete empirical
sequence (from the ideology of history), transposing the ‘real-concrete’ into the ‘thought-
concrete’ and the historical as real change into the concept itself’ (rc, p. 263; lc, p. 304). It
should be noted that though Engels does not seem to have ever read the notebooks com-
prising the Grundrisse, including Marx’s now-famous methodological introduction, Marx
was elsewhere perfectly clear about this question in passages Engels knew intimately, such
as the 1873 Postface to the second edition of Volume 1 (Marx 1976, p. 102).
tutes ‘one of the fundamental conditions of scientific rigor’ (rc 188). The rela-
tions between what Marx calls the various ‘factors’ of the commodity and the
movement of Marx’s exposition occasion no procedure of dialectical Aufhe-
bung, Macherey argues, but Marx’s demonstration instead proceeds in a series
of synthetic ‘ruptures’ or leaps from one order to the next following the analyt-
ical exhaustion of each concept.
It is only in 1979, however, that Macherey will explicitly theorise this dialec-
tic without negation in the closing pages of Hegel or Spinoza. Macherey there
identifies in Spinoza a dialectic without subject, teleology, or negation. This
invocation of a positive, Spinozist dialectic puts in its place the logical subject
and its function of grounding all true propositions: ‘What Spinoza refuses to
think is the dialectic in a subject, which is exactly what Hegel does. [Spinoza]
poses the problem of a dialectic of substance, that is, a materialist dialectic
that does not presuppose its completion in its initial conditions through the
means of a necessarily ideal teleology’.132 In this manner, Spinoza limits the
principle of contradiction and its grounding in the subject to existences and
not essences. As such, Macherey concludes, Spinoza’s ‘theory of the subject’
pertains above all to the constitution of bodies in extension.133 This limitation,
moreover, holds for all bodies as such, not merely the human body, Spinoza’s
privileged example.
A Spinozist limitation of negative dialectic to existences can therefore serve
to ground a materialist analysis of the (actually existing) body of capital, an
analysis that starkly contrasts with all Hegelian idealism (Capital is no mere
reorientation of the Hegelian dialectic placed ‘on its feet’), an analysis in which
contradiction is strictly limited to the phenomenal features of the social forms
constituting the body of capital in its existence (in the form of actually existing
contradictions, between given forces and means of production, in the strug-
gle over the working day or the violent imposition of primitive accumulation,
and the like), while the essential nature of this social form (including the cru-
cial confrontational relation between capital and the proletarian owners of
labour power) will be adequately known by the intellect only as a thought-
concrete without negation.134 In this view, human social relations bear no
inner, essential drive toward their culmination in capitalism, as the imaginary
135 ‘Each part of the [Spinozist] body’, Macherey writes, ‘belongs to this global form that is
the body taken in its entirety, not according to its own essence, but in light of this external
liaison, whose transitive necessity is one of constraint, which holds together all the elements
…. The reason for this harmony is not found in an obscure predetermination of singular
essences that inclines them to converge all together toward a unique essence (an ideal
nature) but in the transitive relationship of determination that constrains them, provision-
ally, to associate’. Macherey 2011, p. 177, my emphasis. See Wood 2002 [1999]. On Marx’s
various definitions of the proletariat, see Nesbitt 2022.
136 Chapter 1 of Volume 1 is undoubtedly the section that Marx rewrote more than any other,
from the closing pages of the Grundrisse through the various drafts and editions, to Marx’s
final 1881 notes on his further intended revisions to volume i. On the latter, see Heinrich
2012, pp. 92–3; and also Heinrich 2021.
137 See the following chapter, as well as Bidet 2005, pp. 132–95.
readings of Marx (on the model of Alexandre Kojève) to represent this nature in
the humanist form of subject-based, Hegelian conflicts – the struggle between
proletariat and capitalist, between forces and relations of production, or, as
a philosophy of praxis, that of a productive, conscious human subject whose
intentionality transforms and humanises nature.138 Such a negative dialectic
describes the development of the whole and its Aufhebung in a process guar-
anteed by the rationality of a subject, whether human, logical, or absolute. As
Macherey first indicated in Reading Capital, Marx’s Gedankenkonkretum – the
unfinished work-in-progress we know as the three volumes of Capital – con-
tains a fundamental, if largely invisible, synthetic mode of presentation of its
claims.139 The identification of various moments of a synthetic demonstration
in Marx’s argument remains crucial for more adequate construction of theo-
retical protocols for the reading of Capital.
3. Capital should be read in light of the Spinozist epistemology of the three
forms of knowledge: (1) imaginary; (2) via general or common notions; and as
Althusser reminds us, (3) in light of eternity, as ‘the adequate knowledge of a
complex object by the adequate knowledge of its complexity’.140 Each of these
modes of understanding has in turn its element of truth and necessity, though
only the third is fully adequate to the comprehension of its object.
138 See Kojève 1980. Among the key theoretical distinctions Marx analyses in the opening
pages of Capital (in pure abstraction from prices, capital, and the human owners of com-
modities themselves) is that between the production of wealth (in the form of use-values),
exchange-value, and value itself (rc, pp. 188–93). These fundamental categorial deter-
minations not only delineate Marx’s decisive break with Ricardian value theory (Marx
was not a Left Ricardian) but remained as well a distinction generally overlooked by the
productivist orientation of traditional, Leninist Marxism. On the concept of Left Ricar-
dianism – that is, the failure clearly to distinguish wealth from value and the consequent
promotion of the redistribution of that wealth rather than the overcoming of the capitalist
mode of production – see Murray 2002, pp. 250–2.
139 Jacques Bidet has insightfully identified crucial moments of what I am calling after
Macherey a positive dialectic in Capital. Implicitly developing Macherey’s precocious,
Althusserian identification of various nondialectical conceptual leaps in the opening
pages of Capital, Bidet points to the crucial movement from the concept of the commodity
to that of capital in Marx’s exposition (from part 1 to part 2, chs. 4–6) – a passage ‘devoid of
dialectical continuity, genesis, deduction, or transition – between the presentation, that is
to say, of C–M–C and that of M–C–M.’ Bidet describes this as an ‘isolated intervention’ at
this crucial axial moment of Marx’s argument, one in which contradiction (the apparent
impossibility that the exchange of equal values can nonetheless produce surplus value) is
not a matter of essence, but ideological existence, a merely apparent contradiction that
in fact shrivels away in the face of Marx’s synthetic presentation of the concept of surplus
value and valorisation in chapter 6. Bidet 2006, pp. 160–2.
140 rc, p. 255.
of its object. Such a reading might take many forms; for this reader of Capi-
tal, it seems essential to take into account, for example, the full development
of Marx’s founding epistemological distinction between the production of sur-
plus value as a total mass and its subsequent distribution among many individ-
ual capitals in the manifest form of profit via competition, such as Fred Moseley
has systematically argued. While Marx famously defines abstract labour as the
substance of surplus value (‘The labour that forms the substance of value is
equal human labour, the expenditure of identical human labour-power’), we
might further say with Moseley that surplus value, as distinct from material
wealth, itself forms the general substance of capital.144
In this view, Marx abstracts from the temporal existence of production and
the phenomenology of individual labourers and capitalists, to present, at every
level of the increasing degrees of concretion that characterise his analysis in
Capital, a monetary analysis that might rightly be characterised via the eter-
nity of the concept (in the sense that Spinoza speaks of the adequate concept
of the triangle145): ‘Money’, Moseley writes, ‘is derived in the very first chapter
(Section 3) of Volume i, as the necessary form of appearance of abstract labour,
and from then on Marx’s theory is about quantities of money that represent,
and thus are determined by, quantities of labour time’.146
This in turn entails – as Moseley demonstrates in detail across Marx’s innu-
merable manuscripts – that Capital is constructed at two levels of determina-
tion: first, an initial determination of the production of a total mass of surplus
volume (its ‘substance’), and subsequently, in analytical terms, via the determi-
nation of the distribution of that mass of value among competing individual
capitals.147 Marx’s presentation, repeatedly invoking individual processes and
factors of production, is admittedly confusing on this point; Moseley convinc-
ingly argues, however, that ‘Marx’s theory in Volume i is about the total capital
144 Marx 1976, p. 129. ‘The most essential common property of all capitals [i.e., its “substance”]
… is the production of surplus-value’. Moseley 2017, p. 43. I bring this theoretical perspec-
tive to bear upon the concept of capitalist slavery in Nesbitt 2022.
145 ‘From the nature of a triangle it follows from eternity to eternity that its three angles are
equal to two right angles’. eip17s. It should be noted in the context of this argument, that
to indicate the movement of Capital from the abstract to the concrete is to grasp the ‘con-
crete’ not as the abandonment of an abstract conceptual order for that of an empiricist,
sensuous concretion but to invoke instead the meaning of ‘concrete’ closest to the Latin
concrescere, indicating the cohesion or growing together of parts into a complex mass,
compound, or composite (always remaining in the attribute of thought). Compare Bidet
2005, p. 174.
146 Moseley 2017, p. 9.
147 ‘The total amount of surplus-value must be determined prior to its division into individual
parts’. Marx, quoted in Moseley 2017, p. 46.
and the total surplus-value produced in the economy as a whole, [even though]
the theory is [necessarily] illustrated in terms of an individual capital and even
a single, solitary worker …. Individual capitals are not analysed as separate and
distinct real capitals, but rather as representatives and ‘aliquot parts’ of the total
social capital’.148 As Marx himself writes, ‘In capitalist production [i.e., in Vol-
ume i], each capital is assumed to be a unit, an aliquot part of the total capital’.149
Here again, following Moseley’s analysis, we see the necessary inherence of all
three forms of knowledge in the adequate presentation of Marx’s object, even
including in his apodictic, synthetic analysis the imaginary figure of the ‘single,
solitary worker’.
Attention to the capacious brilliance of Pierre Macherey’s thought, from
Reading Capital and A Theory of Literary Production to his five-volume expli-
cation of Spinoza’s Ethics, necessarily draws the reader onward to interrogate
the general nature of materialist critique, such as Macherey has developed that
notion across the broad expanse of a life of theoretical analysis. No mere didac-
tic exposition of the Spinozist system, the writings of Pierre Macherey as a
whole construct for contemporary thought the adequate notion of a veritably
materialist analysis of the conceptual system of knowledge, both in its immedi-
ate forms of appearance as a symbolic system and in the eternity of its singular
concepts. Such, one might rightfully conclude, is the nature of Macherey’s the-
oretical project: to grasp the eternal in a materialist way. It is this imperative,
in turn, that will in the next chapter guide my analysis of Marx’s development
of a positive dialectic adequate to his world-historical critique of the capitalist
social form.
∵
The previous chapters’ discussion of Althusser and Macherey’s concept of
a materialist dialectic – not only in For Marx and Reading Capital, but in
many of their subsequent writings, published and unpublished, texts that at
times explicitly address Marx’s Capital, but more often do not – provides the
means now to return this theoretical position back to bear upon the logics
or what Macherey calls the ‘process of exposition’ of Capital itself.1 The plu-
ral of my chapter title (‘logics’) already indicates a crucial claim of my argu-
ment: that as opposed to the still-dominant view that Marx’s theoretical expo-
sition of the capitalist social form deploys a single negation- and contradiction-
1 Needless to say, in the scope of this chapter there can be no question of addressing the huge
volume of philological and genetic research into Capital since the 1960s. Here, I only hope to
extend Althusser’s and Macherey’s original epistemological propositions in Reading Capital
in the context of their later work and its reception, in particular in relation to the problem
of a Spinozist reading of Capital. For a summary of this broader discussion, focusing on the
Germanophone field and in particular the relation of Hegel’s Logic to Capital, see Heinrich
2009, pp. 71–98 as well as the entire contents of that outstanding volume more generally; and
Heinrich 2022 [1999], pp. 167–71; 2023, pp. 263–7. Heinrich summarises his own view on the
relation of Hegelian logic to Capital in the following terms: ‘For me, the most plausible con-
clusion is the following: from Hegel, Marx gained a precise perception of the difficulties of
presentation … but regarding Hegel’s notions and lines of argumentation themselves, there
is no application’ (2009, p. 75).
based logic (i.e., a materialist version of ‘Hegelian’ logic), Capital instead imple-
ments a diverse multiplicity of logics.2 These include, predominantly, a post-
Aristotelean and Spinozist positive logic of implication that I will call additive
synthesis, which coexists with others that range from the imaginary-literary
and polemic invective, to the highly original materialist process that Althusser
names the determinate ‘positioning’ (la position) of concepts, and the related
procedure Macherey identifies in Reading Capital as the ‘exhaustion’ of con-
cepts.
Alongside these logics, remaining instances of a ‘Hegelian’, negative, contra-
diction-based dialectic, while existing in marginal passages such as Capital’s
supplementary, historical (as opposed to apodictic) Chapter 23, constitute
no more than a conceptually meagre theoretical relic of Marx’s intellectual
formation and habitus.3 Marx tendentially suppresses, in this view, the ini-
tially predominant negative dialectic of the Grundrisse, with only lingering
remnants increasingly relegated to the margins of Capital’s demonstration.
This occurs as a fundamental aspect of the ongoing process of revision that
Marx undertakes from his initial enquiries of 1857 to the final 1881 notes on
his intended, but never implemented, revisions for a third edition of Capital,
Vol. i.
Textual analysis of the various logics of exposition in Capital reveals, I wish
to argue, that the negation-based version of so-called ‘Hegelian’ logic that is
still widely referred to as Marx’s ‘dialectic’, is in fact the least significant of
these logics of exposition. More specifically, I wish to argue that Marx’s ini-
tial exposition of the concept of the commodity (in Chapter i of Capital) in
terms of an internal, constitutive contradiction [Widerspruch] between use-
value and exchange-value, and this even as late as the first, 1867 edition of Cap-
ital, proves an epistemological impediment,4 one that Marx overcomes through
2 An extreme example of the former position is to be found in Jairus Banaji’s essay ‘From
the Commodity to Capital: Hegel’s Logic in Marx’s Capital’, in which Banaji presents Marx’s
method of exposition as both static and unitary. Unitary since for Banaji every methodolog-
ical comment Marx made constitutes a moment of an expressive totality (‘It is obvious that
the methodological references express a consistent and internally unified conception’) and
static, since Banaji identifies examples of this univocal totality – among which Banaji freely
translates into Hegelese as necessary – from the 1841 dissertation to Volume ii of Capital, the
final manuscript on which Marx worked. Banaji 2015, p. 20.
3 On Marx’s complex appropriation of Hegelian thought from 1836–48, see Levine 2012.
4 I take the term epistemological impediment from Jacques Bidet, who makes an analogous
argument regarding Marx’s appropriation of Hegelian negative dialectic, but without specifi-
cally addressing this to the putative negative dialectical contradiction between use-value and
exchange-value in the concept of the commodity (Bidet 2005).
The position I present here crucially depends upon the fundamental Spinozist
distinction Althusser and Macherey sustain (described in the previous chap-
ters), between the attributes of thought and extension, attributes (along with
the infinite others to which humans do not have access) that in Spinoza’s view
remain absolutely and infinitely distinct – without, that is to say, being sub-
ject to their sublation in the Hegelian Idea of the Absolute Subject.6 Follow-
5 In a note Marx placed in his manuscript for Capital, Volume ii, he gives an example of this
practical form of contradiction: ‘Contradiction in the capitalist mode of production. The
workers are important for the market as buyers of commodities. But as sellers of their com-
modity – labour-power – capitalist society has the tendency to restrict them to their min-
imum price. Further contradiction: the periods in which capitalist production exerts all its
forces regularly show themselves to be periods of over-production; because the limit to the
application of the productive powers is not simply the production of value, but also its real-
isation. However the sale of commodities, the realisation of commodity capital, and thus of
surplus-value as well, is restricted not by the consumer needs of society in general, but by the
consumer needs of a society in which the great majority are always poor and must always
remain poor’. I take this example as well as the three-way distinction between theoretical,
practical, and (Hegelian) dialectical contradictions from Arash Abazari’s article ‘Marx’s Con-
ception of Dialectical Contradiction in Commodity’ (2019, p. 181). I will return to Abazari’s
argument below.
6 ‘Each attribute of one substance must be conceived through itself’ (eip10). Spinoza goes on
to develop this crucial point in the second section of Ethica: ‘As long as things are considered
ing Althusser and Macherey, the theoretical object I seek to construct here
adheres to this Spinozist distinction, and addresses not the historical existence
and development of capitalism as a singular existing thing bearing real con-
tradictions, but only the logics or processes of exposition to be found in Capi-
tal.
Marx famously never wrote his proposed treatise on his dialectical method,7
and in its absence, the logics of Capital do not constitute an autonomous
‘method’, but exist only immanently, discernible through what Althusser called
their ‘structural causality’. This singular (as opposed to generalisable or even
universal) ‘method’ exists nowhere else than in its real effects, which is to
say, in this case, in the text of Capital itself, but in the state of a discursive
practice as opposed to an explicit theory of a ramified apodictic demonstra-
tion. This implies that to determine the logics at work in Capital, as I seek
to do here, requires constructing a theoretical object distinct from Marx’s lit-
eral demonstration of the capitalist social form, yet simultaneously insisting
that this object of analysis remains determined in its necessity by the material
object that is the finite discourse of Capital.8 This process, as what Macherey
calls materialist explication, stands opposed to the alternative fabrication of an
autonomous interpretation;9 the latter tends in contrast to disregard the materi-
as modes of thought, we must explicate the order of the whole of nature, or the connec-
tion of causes, through the attribute of Thought alone; and insofar as things are considered
as modes of Extension, again the order of the whole of Nature must be explicated through
the attribute of Extension only. The same applies to the other attributes’ eiip7Sch. These
assertions derive in turn from Spinoza’s initial propositions eip2–4, which together imply,
Macherey comments, that ‘the attributes of substance … can be distinguished without main-
taining [entretenir] relations between themselves’. Furthermore, Macherey continues, the
attributes are precisely ‘defined by the fact that they have nothing in common between them
and therefore do not reciprocally limit one another …. There is a mental reality as there is
a corporeal reality, each neither more nor less real than the other, and without reciprocal
relations [existing] between them’ (1998, pp. 75, 94, my translation).
7 Marx was quite clear that despite the decisive influence Hegel’s thought had on his intel-
lectual development, his own method was not Hegelian: ‘My method of exposition is not
Hegelian, since I am a materialist, and Hegel an idealist’ (Letter to Ludwig Kugelmann,
6 March 1868). In consequence, Marx famously wrote to Joseph Dietzgen in 1868 that ‘When
I have cast off the burden of political economy, I shall write a “Dialectic” ’.
8 ‘If knowledge is expressed in discourse, and is applied to discourse, this discourse must by
its nature be different from the object which it animated in order to talk about it. Scientific
discourse is rigorous because its chosen object is defined by a different order of strictness and
coherence’. Macherey 2006, p. 7.
9 Crucial to Macherey’s materialist analysis of texts, as discussed in the previous chapter, is his
systematic attempt ‘to replace interpretation (why is the work made?) by explication [explica-
tion] (which answers the question, how is the work made?)’ (2006, p. 84, translation altered).
alist determination of Marx’s actual text and to create in its place an (aesthetic
idealist) theoretical object (this, I will argue, is the case of Chris Arthur’s inter-
pretation of the logic of Capital).
An example may help to clarify this distinction between the logics of Capi-
tal and capitalism as a historically existing, contradiction-prone singular thing.
Just as the concept of the circle is not circular,10 the concept of negation is
not negative, nor is that of contradiction contradictory; both can easily be
defined positively and without contradiction. Bolzano, for example, defines
negation positively, as the formal statement ‘Proposition A has no truth’, while
Lalande defines contradiction without contradiction, as ‘The relation … that
exists between two propositions, in the form: “A is true” and “A is not true”’.11
Though Marx explains how as a lived, historical phenomenon the capitalist
social form produces a multitude of lived, practical and theoretical, i.e., merely
apparent contradictions, the concept of surplus value, in the adequate, positive
formulation it receives in Chapters 6 and 7, is not contradictory in the least.
It is this Spinozist distinction, between the logical process of exposition that
is the purely conceptual analysis of the capitalist social form in Capital, and
the finite, sensuous temporality of the capitalist real, that constitutes the key
epistemological proposition and militant theoretical intervention of Reading
Capital.
At stake in this book, however, is not merely this straightforward epistemo-
logical distinction, albeit one to this day all too frequently ignored in Marx-
ist criticism (including, ironically, by Althusser himself in ‘Contradiction and
Overdetermination’, as I argued in my Introduction). As already noted, I wish
10 ‘Spinoza … warned us that the object of knowledge or essence was in itself absolutely dis-
tinct and different from the real object, for, to repeat his famous aphorism, the two objects
must not be confused: the idea of the circle, which is the object of knowledge, must not be
confused with the circle, which is the real object. In the third section of the 1857 Introduc-
tion, Marx took up this principle as forcefully as possible’ (rc, p. 41, translation modified;
lc, p. 40).
11 Bolzano 2011 [1837], p. 299; Lalande 2010, p. 183. I cite Bolzano not only because of the
elegant simplicity of his positive definition of negation, a definition as devoid of psychol-
ogism as it is of dependency on the concept (negation) it seeks to define (petitio principii),
but also because, though Marx could not have known of his work, Bolzano has come to
be recognised, since his rediscovery by Husserl after 1893, as the crucial innovator in the
development of a positive and objective logic, a logic that he developed, moreover, via
explicit critiques of both Kant and Hegel’s positions. His relation to the theory of materi-
alist dialectic I discuss in this book is, moreover, crucial yet still underappreciated, both in
the explicit importance of his theory of apodictic demonstration for Jean Cavaillès, and
through the latter, indirectly for Althusser and Badiou in particular. I discuss Bolzano’s
importance for Badiou in the following chapter.
furthermore to argue that Marx’s logical analysis of the concept of the com-
modity tends to replace a negative dialectical logic of exposition with a positive
one. This is to say that although Marx’s initial analysis of the commodity as
constituted by an internal, ontological contradiction (between use-value and
exchange-value) might well have been demonstrated (as it largely was in the
Grundrisse and the first edition of Capital) without contradiction, Marx fur-
thermore, at the level of his categorial exposition, comes to replace this nega-
tive dialectical logic with a more adequate, positive logic without (ontological,
constitutive) contradiction. The Hegelian logic of constitutive contradiction
can certainly be presented without contradiction; for all that, it may well have
proven inadequate to Marx for what Althusser calls his ‘apodictic arrangement
of the concepts [as] that type of demonstrational discourse that Marx calls
analysis’.12
12 rc, p. 51.
13 Hegel 2010a, p. 21.
No less than for Spinoza and Althusser, for Hegel, the empiricist model of truth
remains radically inadequate and subject to ideological distortions: ‘From the
fact that immediate knowing is supposed to be the criterion of truth, it follows
that all kinds of superstition and idolatry are declared to be true’.15 Aligning
himself with the epistemological tradition from Aristotle to Spinoza, Hegel
likewise sustains, in his own fashion, the necessity of adequate demonstration
and apodictic judgements.16
While I argued in my Introduction that Althusser’s initial presentation of
Marx’s theory in For Marx and Reading Capital sacrificed analytical clarity on
multiple fronts to the demands of a situated theoretical polemic (i.e., slip-
page from the theoretical to the historical, the unqualified suppression of the
concept of substance, etc.), the extreme theoretical density and interwoven
complexity of Macherey’s contrasting argument in Hegel or Spinoza, seeking
to parse Hegel’s various (mis)readings of Spinoza through Spinoza’s own pro-
leptic responses to such positions and misunderstandings, is unnecessary fully
to rehearse here, since my object is neither Spinoza nor Hegel per se, but rather
Marx’s process of exposition in Capital. Instead, in the place of proper names, it
is important to focus on the specific logical operations Marx deploys in this pro-
cess. Thus, instead of vaguely contrasting ‘Hegelian’ and ‘Spinozist’ logics, I wish
more precisely to interrogate Marx’s process of exposition in Capital in relation
to three categories, all of which are as central to Hegel’s logic as they are ten-
dentially suppressed from Marx’s: totality, negation, and contradiction. I will
proceed by confronting one of the most influential and comprehensive recent
defences of a Hegelian reading of Capital – Chris Arthur’s The New Dialectic and
Marx’s Capital – with various moments of Pierre Macherey’s critique of these
Hegelian categories, at each step bringing this critique back to bear upon the
text of Capital itself in the desire not merely to counter neo-Hegelian readings
of Capital such as Arthur’s, but to further the interrogation and articulation of
Marx’s positive, materialist dialectic as it is deployed in his magnum opus, in
the wake of the Althusserians’ relinquishing of this project after 1967.
3 Totality
Marx’s Capital does not constitute an objective totality, whether we take the
term in its material, demonstrative, or logical sense. Such a position, I wish
to argue, follows imperatively both from Reading Capital as well as Pierre
Macherey’s general critique of the concept of totality in For a Theory of Liter-
ary Production (in which he does not discuss Capital explicitly). It also follows
directly from a comparison of the Grundrisse with the revised versions of Cap-
ital, from which the term Totalität almost entirely disappears. In Grundrisse,
the Hegelian concept of totality is vital and determinant, recurring nearly a
hundred times in Marx’s notebooks: ‘The conclusion we reach is not that pro-
duction, distribution, exchange, and consumption are identical, but that they
all form members of a totality [Totalität], distinctions within a unity’.17 By the
time Marx drafts and subsequently revises Capital Volume one in 1872, the term
totality only occurs twice, within a single citation from Hegel’s Philosophy of
Right, while in the 1875 French translation, the final version Marx oversaw, the
term totalité occurs just once in reference to the figure of a given sum (‘la total-
ité du capital employé’).18
This claim, to be sure, stands in direct contrast to the Marxist humanist
tradition since Lukács and Karel Kosík, as well as to the exponents of the
so-called systematic Dialectical reading of Capital such as Chris Arthur’s neo-
Hegelian position in The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital.19 In what follows,
17 ‘Das Resultat, wozu wir gelangen, ist nicht, dass Production, Distribution, Austausch, Con-
sumtion identisch sind, sondern dass sie alle Glieder einer Totalität bilden, Unterschiede
innerhalb einer Einheit’. Marx 1973, p. 99; mega ii.1.1 [1857–58], p. 35.
18 Marx mega ii.6 [1872], p. 184; Marx mega ii.7 [1875], p. 529.
19 Riccardo Bellofiore remarks that ‘A consensus among all the ismt [International Sympo-
sium on Marxist Theory] authors is that Marx is a systematic dialectician, that is, he pro-
poses the articulation of categories to conceptualise an existent concrete whole’. Bellofiore is
referring to Arthur, Geert Reuten, Tony Smith, Roberto Fineschi, Patrick Murray, and Fred
Moseley, along with himself. Though my own reading of Capital is heavily indebted to
the work of the ismt authors, this is obviously a shared position with which I take issue.
Bellofiore 2014, p. 167, emphasis in original. Among these authors, my critique of total-
ity is closest to that of Bellofiore, who stresses, like Macherey’s Spinoza (see below), the
perspectival, subjective nature of any actually existing totality: ‘In the section on repro-
duction, Marx was looking at capital relations from a point of view [of] the whole of the
capitalist class [and] the whole of the working class’ at which point we ‘abandon the per-
spective of the single capitalist and the single worker and look instead at the capitalist class
and the working class’ (Bellofiore 2018, pp. 379, 380, emphasis added). Another proponent
of the systematic dialectic school is Norman Levine. His book Marx’s Discourse with Hegel,
taking account of both recent Hegel scholarship and the mega2, offers a detailed and
comprehensive examination of Marx’s appropriation of Hegel’s thought, drawing atten-
tion both to those texts Marx read, and others he either ignored or which only became
available after his death, along with the diverse consequences of this complex disposi-
tif. Unlike the work of Bellofiore, Arthur and Smith, however, Levine’s probing analysis
is strictly limited to the years 1836–48, and thus does not address the process of exposi-
tion in Capital. See Levine 2012. In general, the Systematic Dialectic position can be said
to move backwards from the observed reality of Capital to fabricate its imaginary cause
– the Hegelian logical categories to be found in Grundrisse – as opposed to moving for-
ward from 1857 to follow Marx’s general tendency as the necessary replacement of many
of the logical categories and operations he took from Hegel with original, more adequate
concepts of his own construction, as I seek to do in this chapter, following Althusser and
Macherey’s Spinozist protocol for a materialist science of causes.
20 Arthur 2009, p. 175.
21 I will focus here on the Encyclopedia, since, in contrast to the more widely discussed Phe-
nomenology, Logic, and Philosophy of Right, each of which constitute only partial elements
of this system, the Encyclopedia is the only site in which Hegel systematically (if schemat-
ically) develops his system of thought as a totality. See Stein and Wretzel 2022.
Yet the absolute freedom of the idea is that it does not merely pass over
into life or let life shine in itself as finite knowing [i.e., as mere logical sys-
tematicity], but instead, in the absolute truth of itself, resolves to release
freely from itself the moment of its particularity or the first determining
and otherness, the immediate idea, as its reflection [Widerschein], itself
as nature … This idea insofar as it is [diese seiende Idee], is nature.23
22 For Hegel, the sublation of nature within the absolute idea necessarily maintains what
he calls a ‘real content’, that consists ‘only in its exhibition [Darstellung], an exhibition
that it [the concept] provides for itself in the form of external existence [Dasein]’. Cited
in Schülein 2022, p. 139.
23 Hegel 2010a, p. 303, emphasis added, translation modified.
24 ‘The history of philosophy presents only one philosophy at different stages of its unfolding
throughout the various philosophies that make their appearance …. the specific principles
each one of which formed the basis of a given system are merely branches of one and the
same whole’ (Hegel 2010a, p. 42).
totality [Totalität]’.25 In this manner, Hegel’s system depends upon the notion
of totality at all three levels indicated above: the three-volume Encyclopedia
constitutes a material totality, its pretension being to present the total system
of absolute knowledge – from its most abstract initial moment, to the most
concrete, the absolute idea – across the material expanse of its pages and the
discourse they convey; a demonstrative totality, the sequence of its argument
proceeding apodictically from each moment to that which it logically entails,
to demonstrate in sum the systematic unity of being in its totality; and, logi-
cally, the Encyclopedia presents the absolute idea as the rational totality of its
determinations.
More precisely, Hegel’s entire philosophical system consists in not just one
final totality (the absolute idea) in distinction to the contradictory inadequacy
of all its prior moments, but through the articulation of its various sections,
it articulates a sequence of totalities. This is to say that each determination
of being – from the first, most abstract determination of being and noth-
ingness as becoming, through to the complete and sufficient totality of the
absolute idea, along with the many other forms of determination Hegel con-
siders along the way (finitude, identity, etc.) – constitutes an aspect of the
totality of being according to a specific, determinate form. Hegel famously
visualises this as a system in which the totality of being, understood as abso-
lute idea, ‘presents itself as a circle of circles, each of which is a necessary
moment, so that the system of its distinctive elements makes up the idea in
its entirety. … Each sphere of the logical idea proves to be a totality of determi-
nations’.26
If each Hegelian determination of being, from the most abstract to the most
concrete, forms a totality, each of these (prior to the absolute) must further-
more be understood as ontologically constituted by its inner negativity and
inadequacy;27 each determination of being, in other words, is not simply a
totality, but stands as an inadequate or illegitimate totality, to adopt Michela
Bordignon’s terminology.28 This is to say that each logical determination or cat-
25 Hegel 2010a, p. 43, emphasis in original. Though Gesamtheit and Totalität are synonymous
in German, Hegel’s preferred term is Totalität, which appears 153 times in the Encyclopedia
Logic, while the former is used only once.
26 Hegel 2010a, pp. 43, 136.
27 ‘Everything actual contains within itself opposite determinations, and therefore know-
ing and, more specifically, comprehending [Begreifen] an object means nothing more or
less than becoming conscious of it as a unity of opposite determinations’. Hegel 2010a,
pp. 94–5.
28 Bordignon 2022, pp. 115–32.
egory of being through which Hegel articulates his system of logic defines a
totality according to a certain form: being as it is perceived under the determi-
nation of quantity, of finitude, of identity, etc.
The key point, then, is that if Hegel’s analysis of being under the attribute of
identity, or any other determination, constitutes a totality (the totality of being
grasped via the concept of identity), this totality must necessarily, insofar as
it refers to the totality of being, refer as well to the definition of identity itself
as an element of this totality.29 If each logical totality constitutes a set, then
the immediate consequence to be drawn is that each and every one of these
sets (i.e., each of Hegel’s logical determinations of being) is ‘illegitimate’ in the
familiar sense of Russell’s paradox: in Bordignon’s terms, ‘each logical determi-
nation denotes a set of which it is a member, and thus refers to itself’.30
Hegel’s familiar example of the contradictory logic of identity makes this
paradox apparent.31 Being, when grasped under the attribute or determination
of identity, constitutes a totality – and since the definition of the absolute as
a determinate totality necessarily includes the definition of identity, this set
refers to itself (the concept of identity) as well. That identity is identical to
itself (necessarily, according to its definition), however, implies, as Hegel shows
in the doctrine of essence, that it is different from, not identical to, what it is
not, namely, difference. Its difference from difference is thus not merely exter-
nal, but gives identity its self-identity, making it a member of the set of all being
grasped under the determination of identity. And yet, since its difference from
difference constitutes in this sense, ontologically, the very identity of identity,
it can be said that the concept of identity necessarily, ontologically, contains
difference within itself. If this is so, then it cannot be a member of the set of
all being grasped as self-same, determinate identity without difference. Or in
Bordignon’s recapitulation: ‘Insofar as identity is identical with itself, identity
29 ‘The determination of the finite is the logical form of all there is insofar as all there is, is
finite. The determination of identity is a logical form of all there is, insofar as all there is,
is identical to itself …. If each determination is [therefore] a way in which all there is, is
defined, the determination has to define itself too. In this way, the content of each deter-
mination is a definition of all there is, including itself’ (Bordignon 2022, p. 122).
30 ‘Since the content of the determination defines a totality – all there is and all that is think-
able – according to a certain form, the whole content of this totality turn out to be inside
the totality and, at the same time, paradoxically, outside the totality itself’ (Bordignon
2022, p. 125). Alain Badiou founds his anti-Hegelian claim that there is no total universe
or world of worlds, but only purely multiple worlds each possessing its own logic, upon a
version of Russell’s paradox (2008, pp. 109–11). I discuss Badiou’s Logics of Worlds in Chap-
ter 5.
31 I take the example from Bordignon 2022, p. 124.
differs from difference and thus it involves difference in itself and transcends
the limit of the totality that it is supposed to define and that it is a part of’.32
Now, the interesting conclusion Bordignon draws from this presentation,
which simply translates the notion of Hegelian negative dialectic into the
language of set theory and Russell’s paradox, is that this ‘illegitimacy’ of all
Hegelian set theoretic determinations of being leads not to their ruination
(as it will for Badiou, for example), but rather constitutes the singular power
and dynamic source of Hegelian logic. Hegel, she argues, while not anachro-
nistically adopting set theoretical terminology, was nonetheless quite aware of
the contradictions governing such logical totalities, but simply rejected their
‘illegitimacy’ as a symptom of a specific, inadequate form of rationality, pre-
cisely one that could not incorporate such contradictions within its compass.33
Instead, Hegel affirmed such contradiction [Widerspruch], in its integral neces-
sity to the totality of the absolute idea, as a new form of logic, one precisely able
encompass such limited, determinate forms of totality, negation.
the general rejection of the category of expressive totality, finds analogous iter-
ation in Macherey’s programme in Theory of Literary Production (discussed in
the previous chapter); at the same time, it stands in direct opposition to the
neo-Hegelian reading of Capital to be found in Chris Arthur’s The New Dialec-
tic and Marx’s Capital.
To confront these two influential readings of Capital then is at once to
choose between a reconstructive interpretation of the (Hegelian, negative dia-
lectical) logical form of Capital (Arthur) and the autonomous construction of
an analytic theory of Capital’s modes of demonstration and the necessity gov-
erning their organisation. At the same time, it is to clarify the decision drawn
between an understanding of Capital as a unified, totalised negative dialectical
object, in which each moment incompletely expresses this totality, and Capital
as a materialist structure of multiple logics and concatenated conceptual sin-
gularities without totality.35 In rejecting the inadequate nominal abstraction of
‘Hegelian’ vs. ‘Spinozist’ (or Marxian) logics, I choose to focus instead on three
aspects of Marx’s apodictic demonstration: totality, negation, and contradic-
tion. I begin with the problem of totality not only because it offers a stark and
radical contrast between Arthur’s and Macherey’s understandings of the pro-
cess of exposition in Capital, but even more because Arthur’s analysis of the
status of negation and contradiction in Capital crucially depends upon his ini-
tial assertion of the book’s status as a formal totality.
Chris Arthur’s influential 2002 book The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital
offers a sustained reading of the logic of Capital as what Arthur calls a ‘sys-
tematic dialectic’.36 By this, Arthur rightly seeks to distinguish this form of
rich’s analysis of Capital has been called into question by Fred Moseley in Marx’s Theory
of Value in Chapter 1 of Capital: A Critique of Heinrich’s Value-Form Interpretation (2023).
What I take above all from Heinrich’s analysis in How to Read Capital, as will become evi-
dent below, is his demonstration of the additive, as opposed to negative dialectical nature
of Marx’s demonstration. Moseley’s critique of Heinrich in contrast addresses a problem
extraneous to the issue in question here, i.e., whether value is created by the exchange
of commodities (as Moseley reads Heinrich), or entirely in production itself (as Moseley
claims). I discuss this critique below.
35 The tendential fabrication of a mere interpretation, Macherey observes, seeks to reveal
‘the apparent expression of the unity of an intention or model that permeates and ani-
mates the work, bestowing on it life and the status of an organism. Whether this unity is
subjective (the result of an authorial choice, conscious or unconscious) or objective (the
embodiment of an essential device – a key signature, frame or model [or, for Arthur, the
ubiquitous logical device of the Hegelian negative dialectic]) the assumption remains that
it is the whole that is determinant’ (Macherey 2006, 45–6, translation modified).
36 Arthur has sustained and further specified his original analysis of the capitalist social form
in his more recent book The Spectre of Capital: Idea and Reality (2022), as well as in the
analysis as the attempt logically ‘to articulate the relations of a given social
order, namely capitalism’, from what he calls the ‘Old Dialectic’, the Soviet Stal-
inist ‘school of “Diamat”, rooted in vulgarised versions of Engels and Plekhanov’,
a tradition that, retaining Hegel’s teleological philosophy of history, has read
Capital as the historicist analysis of the origins and progression of capitalism
from so-called primitive exchange to the fully developed industrial capitalist
social form.37
In contrast, the process of exposition Arthur calls ‘systematic dialectic’
adopts Hegel’s concern to demonstrate the logical form of its object, as for
example that found in the Logic or the Philosophy of Right, arguing that Marx
univocally adopted this Hegelian logical dialectic in Capital.38 While I have
argued above that the Spinozist distinction between the historical develop-
ment of capitalism, in the attribute of temporal extension, and the exposi-
tion of its logical structure in that of thought forms the basis of Althusser’s
epistemology in Reading Capital – a theoretical reference that Arthur, in his
anti-Althusserian Hegelianism unsurprisingly neglects to mention – this quasi-
Althusserian distinction that Arthur draws constitutes little more than an
opening prelude to his analysis.
Instead, Arthur’s introductory exposition of his project confusingly – from
the Althusserian position I am arguing in this book – conflates a salutary rejec-
tion of Diamat historicist readings of Capital, with the imaginary, unexamined,
and undemonstrated presupposition that Marx’s Capital, via what Arthur calls
its ‘systematic dialectic’, presents the logic of capitalism as a unitary expressive
totality (‘the significance of each element is determined by its place in the total-
ity’, Arthur states categorically) via a negative, contradiction-based dialectic.39
article ‘Contradiction and Abstraction: A Reply to Finelli’ (2009). I focus here on his ear-
lier book both because it has been the object of sustained interest and critique, and, more
importantly, because in his most recent book he largely abandons any earlier pretense
actually to read and explicate Capital’s dialectic and instead borrows freely from Hegel
and Marx’s conceptual toolbox such that ‘what I present here [in The Spectre of Capital]
should be understood as my own view, not as Hegel’s or Marx’s’ (Arthur 2022, p. 1).
37 Arthur 2002, p. 3. Michael Heinrich articulates a similar critique of historicist readings of
Capital in Wissenschaft vom Wert (2022 [1999], pp. 172–3; see also Heinrich 2023, pp. 260–
1).
38 Macherey is unsparing in his critique of such a procedure: ‘The worst defect of such logi-
cal formalism is that it tries to explain the work in relation to a single series of conditions:
the model, by definition, is unique and self-sufficient. And here we have smuggled back
the postulate of the unity and totality of the work; its real complexity has been abolished,
dismantled, the better to be ignored’ (2006, p. 55, translation modified).
39 Arthur 2002, p. 25. This commitment to capitalism as totality is shared by other represen-
tatives of the Systematic Dialectic school, for example Geert Reuten: ‘The starting point [of
45 ‘Capital is closed in form, hence the relevance of Hegel’s totalising logic’ (Arthur 2009,
p. 172, emphasis in original).
46 Arthur 2009, p. 5, emphasis added. Arthur goes on to repeat this undemonstrated presup-
position in The New Dialectic (2002), for example pp. 17, 25, 26, 64.
47 Chris Arthur does not define his own understanding of totality, but simply deploys the
term immediately from the beginning of New Dialectic: ‘My own view starts from the
premise that theory faces an existent totality [and] hence transitions in the argument
spring from the effort to reconstruct the whole’ (2002, p. 6).
48 Arthur 2009, p. 4.
49 Macherey 2006, p. 90, translation modified. See also Bellofiore’s contrasting distinction
between the reading, interpretation, and reconstruction of Das Kapital. Bellofiore 2018,
pp. 358–60.
50 ‘What begs to be explained in the work is not that false simplicity that derives from the
apparent unity of its meaning, but the presence of a relation, or an opposition, between
elements of the exposition or levels of the composition, those disparities that point to a con-
flict of meaning. This conflict is not the sign of an imperfection; it reveals the inscription
of an otherness in the work, through which it maintains a relationship with that which
it is not, that which happens at its margins. To explain the work is to show that, contrary
to appearances, it is not independent, but bears in its material substance the imprint of
a determinate absence which is also the principle of its identity’ (Macherey 2006, p. 89,
translation modified, emphasis added).
51 Macherey 2006, p. 90.
52 Both of these critiques find eloquent elaboration in Elena Louisa Lange’s article ‘The Cri-
tique of Political Economy and the “New Dialectic”: Marx, Hegel, and the Problem of
Christopher J. Arthur’s “Homology Thesis”’ (2016).
53 ‘The mistake, to my mind, lies in the attempt to represent capitalism as a “system”, whereas
it can only be conceived in fact as a “structure”’ (Bidet 2006, p. 132).
54 In contrast to Arthur, who argues that ‘the significance of each element is determined by
its place in the totality’ (2002, p. 26), Bidet rightly reads Marx as presenting each concep-
tual category ‘as a moment possessing its own coherence and completion …. And this is
incompatible with the Hegelian concept of system …. It is not the concept that changes
[in its negative dialectical determination through the progression of Marx’s argument];
rather, there is a change of concept …. The “theory of value” is in no way transformed by
the [subsequently introduced] theory of surplus-value, which, on the contrary, expressly
presupposes it, unchanged, in the pure and perfect form that Marx has given it in his
exposition in Part One’ (Bidet 2006, p. 132). Bidet’s position precisely develops Althusser’s
schematic proposition, in his 1977 ‘Avant-propos’, that Marx proceeds by the positive
dialectical ‘positioning’ of concepts, to be discussed below, as well as echoing Heinrich’s
exhaustively detailed analysis of the additive logic of the first seven chapters of Capital in
How to Read.
57 ‘The literary work is not … a quest for its own vanishing point. The linear simplicity that
gives it boldness and freshness is actually only its most superficial aspect; we must also be
able to distinguish its real and fundamental complexity. And in this complexity we must
recognise the signs of a necessity …. In all literary works can be found the tokens of this
internal rupture, this decentring, the evidence of its subordinate dependence on precise
conditions of possibility. Thus the work is never – or only apparently – a coherent and
unified whole’ (Macherey 2006, pp. 44, 46, translation modified).
58 Macherey 2006, p. 27. In such an interpretation, ‘the work is only the expression of this
meaning, which is also to say, the shell that encases it, which must be broken to reveal
[this meaning]. The interpreter accomplishes this liberating violence: he dismantles the
work to refashion it in the image of its meaning, to make it denote directly that of which it
was the indirect expression …. Translation and reduction: to reduce the apparent diversity
of the work to its unitary signification’ (Macherey 2006, p. 85, translation modified).
59 Arthur 2002, pp. 108–9.
60 Thanks to Burhannudin Baki for helping me to think through this logical question.
tions do not result in logical contradictions. While I argue that this is the case
for the great majority of Marx’s propositions and demonstrations, Macherey,
Balibar, Antonio Negri, Jacques Bidet, Riccardo Bellofiore and others have all
shown that there exist multiple points of logical rupture and discontinuity in
Capital: in other words, that the logic of Capital is incomplete because its own
consistency or inconsistency cannot be derived from its initial axioms.61 With-
out needing to rehearse their various readings, I will simply argue below that it
is Arthur himself who undermines his own assumption for the logical totality
of Capital, insofar as he can only present this ideological image of a complete
functional system by excluding from consideration the anomalous, disjunctive,
disruptive power of living labour.
61 See rc, Ch. 3; Balibar 1991, Bellofiore 2009, Bidet 2009, and Negri 1985.
62 See Montag 2013, Ch. 5.
63 As discussed in the previous chapter, while Macherey does not discuss Capital in Theory
of Literary Production, he does explicitly apply its general critique to the case of Capital in
his 1967 intervention at the Cérisy ‘Centennaire du Capital’: ‘The enterprise of a total or
“totalising” reading is ideological in its essence …. A scientific text can only be taken up on
the condition of being continued: a closed, repetitive reading is itself an ideological read-
ing …. The object of Capital is an object constructed theoretically, and this is precisely why
Capital is not a formal system. If we were to read it as a closed system, this would consti-
tute an interpretive reading, a repetition and reprisal of a completed system’ (2006, pp. 57,
61, 92).
68 Macherey 1998, p. 65, my emphasis. Note how Macherey’s phrasing in the French original
seeks to avoid any definite or indefinite articles that would reify substance and to speak
instead ‘au sujet de tout’, a formulation difficult to render in English.
69 Macherey’s critique of the substantivisation of Spinozist substance implicitly pursues
Althusser’s initial polemical and underdeveloped rejection of Plekhanovist, monist under-
standings of dialectical materialism (discussed in Chapter 1). After Plekhanov himself,
the determinant figure in this regard is the Spinozist Marxism of Plekhanov’s disciple
Abram Deborin, editor of Pod Znamenem Marxsizma (Under the Banner of Marxism).
Tasked by Lenin and Trotsky from 1922 with developing the theoretical foundations of
Bolshevism, Deborin’s contributions to the journal were crucial in particular for orient-
ing the extensive Soviet reception of Spinoza (Oitinnen 2022, pp. 4–5). In this regard, it
is notable, for example, that in a 1927 article in which he discusses Spinoza’s ‘remarkably
dialectical formulation of the problem of finite and infinite’, Deborin speaks repeatedly
of ‘the whole of nature’ and ‘nature as a whole’ (cited in Oikinnen 2022, pp. 7–8, emphasis
added). (Of course, the Russian original, like all Slavic languages other than Macedonian,
would not use articles to identify the nominal referents of phrases, as in English or French).
On the debates in Soviet philosophy more generally, as well as its reception of Spinoza
more particularly, see Yakhot 2012 [1981]. Landon Frim and Harrison Fluss articulate a
richly argued contemporary version of Marxist substance monism, for example via a cri-
tique of Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza in ‘Substance Abuse: Spinoza contra Deleuze’ (2018).
Fluss and Frim more generally reaffirm the Plekhanovist-Deborin tendency to hypostatise
Spinozist substance as countable thing, for example in their theoreticist-materialist inter-
vention ‘Reason is Red’, where they write that ‘Marxism … demands monism, the idea that
the entire universe is an intelligible Whole’ (2022).
70 Macherey 1998, p. 86. Let me reiterate that despite our unyielding disagreement on this
point, the generous and probing comments of Landon Frim and Harrison Fluss while
drafting this chapter, not to mention their informed and original understanding of the
relation between Spinoza, Hegel, and Marx, have been essential in pushing me to better
articulate my own position.
71 Macherey emphasises that the process of enumeration in general is fundamentally linked
to the imagination: Spinoza indicates in this way ‘the privileged relation that the imagina-
tion bears, not only with the consideration of singular existences, but with the very fact
of enumerating them, and thus as well with that of counting in general, a preoccupation
from which the rational analysis of substance … is completely removed in principle’ (1998,
p. 86).
72 Macherey 1998, p. 87. Macherey continues to develop this point a few pages further in his
commentary on the second Scolium to eip8: ‘Substance can only be unique, not in the
sense of a nature that would be realised in only a single copy [exemplaire], and thus more
than zero and less than two, but of a thing of which all possible forms of realisation enter
into the nature that defines it …. In the expression “a single substance of the same nature”,
[the indefinite article] “a” is not to be taken in the sense of the number “one” as an element
of quantification’ (Macherey 1998, p. 90).
73 Macherey 1998, p. 90n1. It is interesting to note how Macherey’s critique of the hypo-
statisation of substance has distant, far cruder echoes, in the 1920s debate between the
mechanistic Spinozism of Liubov Akselrod, with its emphasis on substance as causa sui,
and Deborin’s Plekhanovist position that ‘substance is matter’ (Yakhot 2012, Chapter 6.4).
Despite basing her critique of Spinoza on a racist antisemitism that deterministically
reduces Spinoza’s thought to its putative ‘Jewish origins’, Akselrod argues: ‘What an absur-
dity to assert that Spinoza’s substance is matter. To recognise it as matter means to design
a very strange entity: substance is matter, one of its attributes is matter, and another
attribute is thinking’ (Akselrod, cited in Yakhot 2012, Ch. 6.4). To indicate the base nature
of this impassioned debate (to say nothing of Akselrod’s antisemitism), one need only
observe that for Spinoza it is not ‘matter’ that is an attribute, as Akselrod claims, but exten-
sion, which is an entirely different concept.
74 Cited in Montag 2013, p. 75.
‘the grounds of our belief that each part of Nature accords with the whole’,
Spinoza begins by pointing out that ‘the actual manner of this coherence and
the agreement of each part with the whole … is beyond my knowledge. To
know this it would be necessary to know the whole of Nature and all its parts’.
Instead, Spinoza argues to his correspondent that our knowledge of any puta-
tive whole, and not only being qua being, remains inadequate and imaginary in
the absence of its systematic, adequate demonstration, whether through com-
mon notions or intuitive knowledge. Rather than developing a systematic and
comprehensive demonstration of this point as he does in the Ethics, however,
Spinoza fabricates for his correspondent a striking, hauntingly graphic and
even fantastic image, his famous parable of the worm in the blood. The point
of Spinoza’s allegory is that the decision as to whether an object (such as the
blood in which Spinoza’s imaginary worm swims) constitutes a whole or a part
is necessarily subjective.75 It is possible to understand any determinate thing as
either part or whole, depending on how this knowledge is constructed, whether
things are understood to ‘adapt themselves to one another so that they are in
closest possible agreement’, such that each is a part of a whole, or, alternatively,
‘are different from one another’, such that each is understood to constitute a
whole. As objects of knowledge, the parts of the blood (what we today identify
as white and red blood cells, plasma, etc.), in Spinoza’s example, can readily be
understood either as whole or part: from the perspective of their ‘agreement
[they] form all together one fluid’, but were we to consider each in its singular
75 To be sure, in this letter Spinoza does explicitly speak of ‘the whole of Nature’ and of ‘the
universe as a whole’, which seems to imply for his reader a conviction that there is an objec-
tive totality of Nature, though our finite minds cannot know its infinitely infinite determi-
nations. This, however, stands in marked contrast to his definitions of substance and God
(Nature) in the Ethics, which make no reference of any kind to a whole or totality. In my
view, Spinoza’s epistolary recourse to this image of the ‘whole of Nature’ marks a rhetor-
ical compromise intended to engage his reader’s inadequate understanding of Spinoza’s
position, analogous to Marx’s parable of the linen and coat that speak to one another in
‘the language of commodities’ in Capital. Rather than speaking more adequately of sub-
stance without reference to totality or the whole, as causa sui and the in se as he does in
Ethics, Spinoza here instead adopts the relatively unclear and imaginary language of his
interlocutor (‘I presume that you are asking for the grounds of our belief that each part
of Nature accords with the whole’), a rhetorical device he regularly adopts in the Scolia
of Ethics (Macherey is at pains to indicate many of these passages in his Introduction, for
example in his lengthy commentary on the Appendix to Book i). Spinoza regularly does
so, Macherey insists, through an ethical commitment to meet his interlocutor halfway,
as it were, and to communicate more effectively with a reader who, from habit, neces-
sarily understands something entirely different by familiar terms such as God, Nature,
substance, or whole than what Spinoza means by them.
difference from the others (white vs. red cells, etc.), ‘to that extent we regard
them each as a whole, not a part’.
To call a thing either a whole or a part is thus for Spinoza merely relative and
subjective, fundamentally dependent upon how an object of knowledge is con-
structed, more or less adequately, as a figure of the understanding. As Macherey
summarises in Hegel or Spinoza, ‘For Spinoza, the notion of totality … does not
represent the positive existence of a being … but [depends] on the point of view
of the understanding that cuts it up in the infinite chain of singular things, by
considering it as a whole’. This position, moreover, indicates Spinoza’s funda-
mental antagonism with Hegelian logic, as the absolute distinction between
substance and subject, insofar as the former, by definition for Spinoza absolute
and thus indeterminate, can never be figured as a determinate whole.76
That said, Spinoza is not propounding the relativism of all judgements. He
clearly indicates to Oldenberg an entirely different path to adequate knowl-
edge of any singular thing: beginning from a true idea, it is possible adequately
to understand the essential nature of that thing, and then, constructively, to
proceed from one adequately constructed idea to another. This synthetic logic
proceeds to construct the ‘coherence [cohaerentiam] of parts’ via a cumulative
understanding by which ‘the laws or nature of another part adapts itself to the
laws or nature of another part’, absent all teleology.77 While we cannot know
in totality either the infinite determinations of any singular thing (such as the
capitalist social form) nor the infinitely infinite determinations of the whole
of Nature, the mind can nonetheless proceed constructively, from an adequate
knowledge of one true idea, to the (logical) successor with which it additively
forms a part of a larger body.78
then it appears as a single component part of that system, precisely as Spinoza argues in
his parable of the worm in the blood stream.
79 ‘Totalité’, in Lalande 2010, p. 1137, emphasis added.
80 Marx 1981, p. 274, emphasis added.
81 ‘In capitalist production, each capital is assumed to be a unit, and aliquot part of the total
capital’. Marx, quoted in Moseley 2017, p. 46. Marx’s fractional perspective has confused
many readers, since Marx repeatedly frames the rhetoric of his argument in terms of indi-
vidual examples (coats, linen, tailoring and weaving, and the like), above all in the first
chapters of Volume i. Moseley emphasises the purely theoretical nature of Marx’s analy-
sis, observing that ‘It is not always clear that Marx’s theory in Volume i is about the total
capital and the total surplus value produced in the economy as a whole, because the the-
ory is usually illustrated in terms of an individual capital and even a single, solitary worker
…. However, the individual capitals in Marx’s examples represent the total social capital of
the capitalist class as a whole. Individual capitals are not analysed as separate and distinct
real capitals, but rather as representatives and ‘aliquot parts’ of the total social capital’
(2017, pp. 45–6). In this sense, one could say of Marx’s examples of specific commodities
such as coats and linen what he says of his historical example of English capitalism, i.e.,
that coats and linen, like ‘England [are] used as the main illustration of the theoretical
developments [he] makes’ (Marx 1976, p. 90).
initiates a treatment, offering the subject the means to sustain the anxiety of
not-knowing via the progressive amendment of the intellect, in the certainty
that the finite human mind is capable of more adequate understanding than
such imaginary chimera, even to realise a scientia intuitiva – not of totality –
but of the absolute.82
82 ‘Sensing what the subject can tolerate, in terms of anxiety, is something that puts you to
the test at every moment. … As regards anxiety, there isn’t any safety net. … It’s upon the
cutting edge of anxiety that we have to hold fast’. Lacan 2014, pp. 5, 9, 15, translation mod-
ified. See McNulty 2009, pp. 1–39.
83 See Moseley 2016.
84 Heinrich 2009, p. 96.
This providential day of theoretical plenitude is one that will never arrive, as
Reuten himself knows as well as Althusser or Heinrich: Capital Volume I as
we know it, Reuten observes parenthetically, ‘requires further concrete ground-
ing of the moments presented in this sequence (Capital Volumes ii and iii, as
well as the books which Marx had planned but did not even begin to draft)’.86
The Hegelian theoretical commitments of this school of Marxology thus lead
them – despite their intensive knowledge of the extreme genetic complexity
of Marx’s Capital project that makes of it an unequivocally ‘unfinished and
incomplete project’ (Heinrich) – to adhere to this Lukácsian-Hegelian theoreti-
cal imperative, and to bestow upon Capital the aura of a transcendent, emanant
totality. Their analytic pursuit recommences a perpetually-in-process inquest
into the theoretical promised land that is Marx’s alleged Hegelian palimpsest,
as they fervently continue to invoke ‘the lonely hour of the last instance [that]
never comes’.87
Similarly, it should be obvious on even the most cursory reading that Marx
deploys a multiplicity of demonstrative modalities across the pages of Capi-
tal, from Marx’s recurrent recourse to classical modus ponens, if-then propo-
in it. This provides the basis for the transitions in the development of
the categorial ordering. There is an impulse to provide a solution to a
contradiction – a ‘push’ one might say – and there is the need to over-
come the deficiency of the category with respect to its fulfilment in the
whole.91
In this fashion, with no more than sporadic, selective textual references, Arthur
bases his claim for the negative dialectical logic of Capital upon the priority of
its status as an expressive totality: it is only because Capital is presupposed to
form a substantive totality that each of its moments, in its incompletion, can
be argued to enter into negative contradiction with that supposed-totality, log-
ically propelling its sublation from one moment to the next.
On my reading of New Dialectic, Chris Arthur variously presents three dis-
tinct arguments for the consistency of Marx’s logic of the capitalist social form
as a totality, none of which is either systematic (to adopt Arthur’s own term) or
even directly relevant to showing that ‘Capital [the book and its logic? The con-
cept? The social form?] is closed in form’.92 The first of these ‘arguments’ points
to the totalising nature of capital, its tendency subsume all things within its
logic, and to commodify all things and social relations: ‘If value depends for its
reality on the full development of capitalist production, then the concepts of
Marx’s first chapter can only have an abstract character, and the argument itself
as it advances develops the meanings of these concepts, through grounding
them adequately in the comprehended whole’.93 Arthur’s statement seems to
confuse its categories, its first clause on the reality of value apparently indicat-
ing the real, material subsumption via commodification of means and relations
of capitalist production, the second, confusingly addressing ‘the concepts of
Marx’s first chapter’.
Were we to assume, for argument, that Arthur rigorously remains at the
level of Marx’s logic, and instead means ‘the [concept] of value’ and ‘[Marx’s
concept of] the full development of capitalist production’, this obscure claim
(even granted all this the reader must still guess at Arthur’s exact meaning) has
been more adequately and systematically explicated by Fred Moseley. In Money
and Totality, Moseley comprehensively shows that throughout the expanse
of Marx’s economic manuscripts he presumes that ‘the means of production
in capitalist production are commodities, which have been purchased at the
beginning of the circuit of money capital, and which therefore enter the val-
orisation process with already existing specific prices’.94
Even so, while Arthur’s claim may be true that ‘only at the end of the recon-
struction of the totality is its truth unfolded’, this is true not because this so-
called ‘end’ – a point Arthur never concretely indicates within Marx’s exposi-
tion, nor could he, since it does not in fact exist within the incomplete and
unfinished three volumes we know as Capital – would realise the putative neg-
ative dialectical totality of Capital’s logic of exposition, but only, as Moseley
shows, because Marx, like Spinoza in the Ethics’ Scholia, chose to simplify for
his readers this aspect of his initial presentation in the second edition of 1872,
such that this ‘totality’ represents no more than a mere reductive, summary
position.
In contrast to Arthur’s ungrounded claim, Marx explicitly emphasises this
situated, subjective, provisional nature of the concept of the circularity of the
reproduction of capital as a whole when, in the final paragraph of chapter 23
he indicates that ‘The capitalist process of production, … seen [betrachtet] as
a total, connected process, i.e. a process of reproduction, produces not only
commodities, not only surplus-value, but it also produces and reproduces the
capital-relation itself’.95 Coming at the end of Volume i, this position is no
94 Moseley 2017, p. 141. ‘Capital’, Moseley summarises, ‘exists first in the form of money
advanced in the sphere of circulation, then in the form of means of production and labour
power in the form of means of production and labour power in the sphere of production,
then in the form of commodities produced at the end of the production process, and then
finally back again in the form of money recovered, including more money than was orig-
inally advanced at the beginning of this real historical process’ (2017, p. 11, emphasis in
original). See also Marx 1976, p. 709. Moseley further shows that in volume 1 of Capital,
Marx simplified for readers, at Engels’s repeated urging, his initial, comprehensive formu-
lation of the circuit of capital as a wholly monetary process in which both the constant
and variable means of production are initially purchased as actual commodities already
possessing a price form. This has resulted, in Moseley’s view, in the ‘common interpreta-
tion of Volume I that it is only about labour times, not money or prices, and that Marx’s
theory deals with money and prices only in Volume iii’ (Moseley 2017, p. 9). Through a
comprehensive reading of Marx’s various drafts and manuscripts, Moseley shows that
the ‘interpretation of these passages [in traditional Marxism] ignores and is contradicted
by all the textual evidence … – that the circuit of money capital is the analytical frame-
work of Marx’s theory, and the circuit of money capital begins with an independently
existing quantity of money capital (M) … which is “thrown into circulation” in order to
make more money; … the inputs to capitalist production and the valorisation process are
commodities with already existing prices’ (2017, pp. 185–6, emphasis in original). On the
wholly monetary nature of the circuit of capital, see also Murray 2017, p. 135; and Bellofiore
2018.
95 Marx 1976, p. 724, emphasis added.
doubt infinitely more developed and concrete than the initial, minimal true
idea with which Marx began Capital (i.e., that the capitalist mode of produc-
tion appears [erschient] as a general accumulation of commodities); for all that,
it is still a partial, incomplete position, a viewpoint obviously possessing none
of the further conceptual determinations to be introduced in Volumes ii and
iii.96
The fact that the circuit of money capital constitutes a constant in the cap-
italist social form, in other words, hardly makes of Marx’s logic or the system
itself a totality: the concept of this feedback loop is only one among the throng
of dissonant concepts Marx develops, existing alongside quite heterogeneous,
but nonetheless crucial concepts such as class struggle, the theory of ground
rent, cost price, and a hundred others composing the logical body Marx con-
structs, step by step, concept by concept, as the finite, dissonant thing without
totality that is Capital.
Related to but distinct from this first claim for the logic of Capital as total-
ity is Arthur’s similarly obscure implication that because capital requires not
just the valorisation of value (as in the previous argument), but its unceasing
accumulation, Marx’s logic thus ‘treat[s] a given whole’, this because ‘it is char-
acteristic [of Capital like the works of Hegel] that it demonstrates how [this
given whole] reproduces itself …. The movement winds back upon itself to form
a circuit of reproduction of these moments by each other’.97 Certainly, Marx
shows the necessity of this circularity of reproduction and accompanying lin-
ear accumulation; nonetheless, my response is identical: Arthur’s claim is true
and just as wholly irrelevant to the status of capital (whether the book or the
social form) as totality, as it is only one among innumerable dissonant concepts
in Marx’s logical construct.
Finally, the most developed but just as problematic argument Arthur puts
forward for capital as totality is, paradoxically, its partial nature. Building on
the previous points regarding the generality of value and subsumption, Arthur
96 Here too, among the members of the Systematic Dialectic school of reading Capital, it is
Bellofiore who has the position closest to the one I am arguing here, stressing as he does
that Capital is composed of ‘fragments of a systematic reasoning’ such that he refuses
the ‘attempts [of Arthur and Reuten in particular] to ‘rewrite’ Marx in Hegelian fashion’
and insists instead (while rightly indicating various moments where Marx deploys aspects
of Hegelian logic) that ‘we are forced to remain in a fragmentary reading of Marx’. It is
likewise surely no coincidence, given this orientation, that Bellofiore is perhaps the only
member of this school actually to refer to Althusser and Lire le Capital both explicitly and
affirmatively. Bellofiore 2018, pp. 359–60, 357.
97 Arthur 2002, p. 64.
argues that ‘It is inherent to the concept of capital that it must reproduce and
accumulate, and in this it seeks to overcome all obstacles and to make the mate-
rial reality it engages with conform as perfectly as possible to its requirements’.
But this it cannot do, ‘its ideal world of frictionless circulation and growth’ is
inevitably dependent upon recalcitrant externalities, namely, living labour and
its resistance to subsumption and the objective social demands of the valorisa-
tion process.98
Arthur makes this interesting and subtle point, one that in fact subverts the
general argument of his book, in the context of a wider claim for the compre-
hensive logical, as opposed to historical, argument of Capital. He asserts for
example that the discussion of the historical struggle over the length of the
working day in chapter ten of Volume i ‘is strictly illustrative and does not
advance the [logical] argument’.99 While literally correct, I think Arthur’s posi-
tion fails to indicate the necessity that governs Marx’s inclusion of this material
at this point in his analysis. When Marx writes that between the buyer and seller
of the commodity labour power there exists ‘an antinomy, of right against right,
both equally bearing the seal of the law of exchange’, he clearly indicates a point
in his analysis that cannot be decided theoretically, one which, having as always
first explicated the theoretical parameters of this struggle (between necessary
and surplus labour), requires reference to this historical conflict.100
Note, however, how Arthur has externalised the category of class struggle
from his governing framework of the ‘ideal world of [capital’s] frictionless cir-
culation and growth’: first as merely ‘illustrative’ historical data,101 then as a
‘material reality’102 that impinges on this ideal logical form (totality). While the
data Marx cites may well be merely ‘illustrative’, is it not the case that the pre-
sentation of this data nonetheless depends not just upon ‘material reality’, but
precisely upon a concept of class struggle, a concept obviously vital and neces-
sarily internal to Marx’s entire critique of political economy, for the data Marx
presents to make sense in his argument?
When Arthur writes that ‘The logical form of capital is by no means abso-
lute but totally insufficient to maintain itself and it requires a transition to the
domain of reality;’ that ‘while capital has the form of self-realisation it still lacks
control over its bearers’; or that ‘the logic of the development can issue only
in tendencies, which in truth depend on material premises’,103 he unwittingly
reveals the nature of the imaginary logical totality he constantly presumes:104
in contrast to the object of Arthur’s analysis, a purely imaginary logical form
purged of class struggle, Marx’s (critical) logic of the capitalist social form inte-
grally and essentially positions the dissonant concepts of class struggle and the
recalcitrance of living labour as necessary logical components of his logical sys-
tem.105
In contrast to Marx’s critique, in which concepts such as class struggle and
the working day form integral, dissonant moments, the ideal system Arthur
presents as ‘frictionless’ totality, from which these dissonances have been exter-
nalised, is none other than the ideological apology for capitalism that is clas-
sical political economy itself (and neoliberalism more generally), precisely the
imaginary totality from which class struggle has been magically erased by an
‘invisible hand’. If capital is indeed a totality, it is so only in the imagination of
its apologists and benefactors. As Arthur himself is obviously not to be counted
among these, one is left to conclude, with Spinoza, that the powerful impres-
sion of the univocal Hegelian philosophy of totality has blinded the Marxist
analysis of The New Dialectic to the discordant, polyphonous logics of Marx’s
theoretical critique.
In the sixth chapter of New Dialectic, Arthur explicates in detail the nega-
tive dialectical logic of chapter 32 of Capital Volume i, ‘The Historical Ten-
dency of Capitalist Accumulation’. While the previous chapters of New Dialectic
only punctually cited and analysed Marx’s text to support Arthur’s interpre-
tive reconstruction of the logic of capital, here, Marx’s sole reference to the
Hegelian concept of the ‘negation of the negation’ in the whole of Capital
serves Arthur as the occasion actually to cite and closely analyse the logic of
this moment in Marx’s demonstration. Beginning with an extensive, two-page
citation (to ‘remind ourselves of Marx’s text’), Arthur goes on to construct a
detailed, original interpretation of the logic of this passage.
Though the arch-Hegelian figure of the ‘negation of the negation’ amply vin-
dicates Arthur’s decision to analyse this long passage in detail, in other respects
the section is an odd choice for a study of ‘systematic dialectic’. For not only
have this chapter’s summary, teleological claims, as Arthur himself notes, long
been an object of ridicule from Dühring on, but their very formulation is pre-
cisely the opposite of the painstaking, systematic dialectic (of whatever type)
to be found in the initial chapters of Capital. In the place of the apodictic logic
of a rigorous demonstration that moves precisely, step by step, sentence by sen-
tence, to demonstrate the essential nature of the commodity and its forms, of
surplus value, of capital, etc., in this concluding chapter of volume one, Marx
famously makes sweeping, unfounded claims for the inevitable, unitary move-
ment of history: ‘At a certain stage of development [the precapitalist mode of
production] brings into the world the material means of its own destruction ….
Its annihilation … forms the pre-history of capital’. With the further develop-
ment of social productive forces, Marx continues, ‘the monopoly of capital
becomes a fetter upon the mode of production which has flourished along-
side it …. The knell of capitalist private property sounds. The expropriators are
expropriated’.106
Stuck at the very end of Marx’s thousand-page volume, its penultimate chap-
ter retains the grandiose, undemonstrated logic of an inevitable, automatic
collapse of capitalism characteristic of the Grundrisse’s famous ‘Fragment on
machines’, claims buttressed not by rigorous demonstration but instead by the
unrevised, teleological Hegelianism of Marx’s Grundrisse notebooks that is pre-
cisely the object of Arthur’s fascination: ‘Capitalist production begets, with the
inexorability of a natural process, its own negation. This is the negation of
107 Cited in Arthur 2002, p. 113. Marx’s pre-1860 reliance on the Hegelian figures of estrange-
ment, objectification, and alienation, absent from the first seven chapters of Capital,
remains predominant in this penultimate one: ‘Before he enters the process [of capitalist
production], his own labour has already been estranged from him, appropriated by the
capitalist, and incorporated with capital, it now, in the course of the process, constantly
objectifies itself so that it becomes a product alien to him’ (Marx 1976, p. 716). Arthur
rightly notes how this language is ‘reminiscent of a parallel passage in [Marx’s] 1844 Mss’
(2002, p. 133n18).
108 Arthur 2002, p. 114.
109 Arthur 2002, p. 116.
Arthur’s focus is on the source of the original capital to initiate the capitalist
production process (this being the topic of section eight of Capital more gen-
erally). Here, Marx castigates the ideological faith that the capitalist gets these
funds from his own hard labour. This, Marx observes ironically, is ‘the unani-
mous answer of the spokesmen of political economy. And in fact’, Marx adds
slyly, ‘their assumption appears to be the only one consonant with the laws of
commodity production’.110 The point of Marx’s irony, as any reader of Capital
will know, is that this appearance is not just an ideological justification on the
part of the capitalists themselves, but possesses its own necessity, given the
theoretical inadequacy of the analysis of the question prior to Marx.
Arthur’s claim then is that Marx’s ensuing rectification of this ideological –
though necessary – misapprehension adheres to a negative dialectical logic of
‘the transformation of the laws of exchange, appropriation, and property, into
their opposites’.111 And indeed, Marx’s language in this passage, which Arthur
cites extensively, seems to indicate the automatic transformation characteristic
of dialectical sublation:
both argued, a logical break or leap to another theoretical terrain, one in which
Marx’s original concept of labour power – crucially absent from the concep-
tual framework of classical political economy – can be analysed in its use by its
purchaser, the capitalist, to reveal the source of surplus value as the difference
between necessary and surplus labour.113
While the object in question differs, Marx’s basic demonstrative procedure
is identical in these two passages: he first shows the necessity governing inad-
equate, ideological forms of appearance of a phenomenon (respectively, the
origin of a capital fund and the source of surplus value), and then offers its more
adequate analysis in his own theoretical terms. Despite this superficial similar-
ity, the terms of Marx’s demonstration are radically different, fully constituting
two singular modes of logical demonstration in the pages of Capital. In both
cases, the transformation in question is a transformation in the adequacy of our
understanding of the logic governing the capitalist social form; in both cases,
Marx contrasts an initial, inadequate and ideological form of appearance of a
phenomenon, with the greater adequacy our understanding can attain thanks
to the original concepts he has constructed.
For Arthur, the conclusion to be drawn from chapter 24 is merely that even
in this most superficially ‘historical’ analysis, ‘Marx speaks “virtually” [i.e., log-
ically] rather than historically, [which] refutes any interpretation of Capital
that equates the systematic presentation of the existing totality with historical
stages, as if the first chapter explicated some prior regime of simple commodity
production’.114 While Arthur’s defence of the entirely logical status of Capital
is in my view correct, the more interesting question, I think, is one that pre-
cisely subverts the claims to logical totality (‘the systematic presentation of
the existing totality’) that accompany this assertion. A comparison between
this passage and the transition from chapter five to six and seven incontro-
vertibly shows that the unrevised negative dialectical form of presentation in
chapter 32 constitutes an epistemological impediment, obscuring Marx’s lucid,
apodictic argument behind the foggy automatism and passivity of a putative
‘internal and inexorable [negative] dialectic’.
In its place, Marx’s famous invocation to his readers to solve the riddle that
had confounded the greatest minds of classical political economy, ‘Hic Rho-
dus, hic saltus!’ invokes not the imaginary automatism of a Hegelian dialectic
but the real power of the intellect to emend its comprehension of an object
through the difficult labour of Marx’s concepts. In comparison with the con-
ceptual gymnastics Arthur must perform to reveal the logical kernel of Marx’s
eschatological historicist claims in chapter 24, the blatant superiority of Marx’s
process of exposition in chapters five, six, and seven lies in the very simplicity
of his presentation of a series of powerfully creative critical concepts: when
two commodities are exchanged at their value without cheating, the source of
profit cannot be readily discerned; for labour power to be sold as a commodity
requires that the labourer own their own person as a free subject, not a slave;
upon its sale, the commodity labour power is entirely at the disposition of its
owner who has purchased it, the capitalist, who may continue to use it beyond
what is necessary for the sustenance and reproduction of the labourer, in order
to produce surplus value.
As such, Marx’s presentation in part two of the first volume of Capital dis-
cards his earlier reliance on the logical automatisms of a negative dialectic in
the Grundrisse and other preparatory manuscripts, directly to invoke the ful-
some powers of the human intellect more adequately to understand the object
of its analysis (‘Hic Rhodus, hic saltus!’), an invocation analogous to Spinoza’s
subjective presentation of the initial definitions of the Ethics. In those opening
statements, Spinoza defines each of his founding concepts (causa sui, sub-
stance, God, etc.) in resolutely subjective terms, via the concerted repetition
of the qualification intelligo [I understand]: ‘By substance I understand that
which is in itself and is conceived through itself’ [‘Per substantiam intelligo id,
quod in se est, et per se concipitur’].115
Macherey’s illuminating commentary on this crucial dimension of Spinoza’s
presentation is worth citing in whole for its resonance with Marx’s method in
part two of Capital:
It is important to note that the first statements that confront the reader
of the Ethics make an appeal to his capacity to ‘understand’ (intelligere),
that is to say, to his ‘intellect’ (intellectus), through which he is called to
know things in themselves, as they are really [réellement] and not only
as they could be in the abstract. In this manner, [Spinoza’s] philosoph-
ical discourse installs itself immediately in the movement [mouvance]
of the third genre of knowledge. It is furthermore notable that Spinoza,
in these inaugural definitions, conjugates the verb intelligere in the first-
person indicative present [‘I understand’], which necessarily associates
the formulation of the idea in question in each of these definitions with
an activity of effective thought [pensée effective], fully engaged in its affir-
115 eid3.
Like that of Spinoza, Marx’s audacious challenge ‘Hic Rhodus, hic saltus!’ is
an encomium to the infinite powers of the human intellect progressively to
emend its capacity for understanding. While Marx’s early subjection to the fas-
cination of Hegel’s negative dialectic remains determinant in certain marginal
moments of Capital even in its second revision, such as its thirty-second chap-
ter, nowhere is this progressive emendation more evident than in the revisions
Marx operates upon his extraordinary and unparalleled analysis of the con-
cept of the commodity, as he reworked an initial presentation based upon its
putative contradiction-based determinations of reflection [Reflexionsbestim-
mungen], to formulate instead a novel ramified, additive synthetic dialectic for
the 1872 and 1875 editions of Capital.
ence) from pepper and all other spices, or, in the case of Capital, we could say
that capitalism gains its identity through its difference from feudalism and all
other modes of production.
In such contrastive negation, Abazari observes, ‘there is no contradiction in
something. Something excludes other somethings, and, as it were, remains a
harmonious ensemble of qualities and quantities’.122 While this form of exter-
nal contradiction is determinant in the first book of Hegel’s Logic, only occa-
sionally and in passing does Marx define the capitalist mode of production in
this exclusive manner, through its distinction from feudalism, slavery, or com-
munism; instead, he develops his critique through the analysis of the categories
proper and internal to the capitalist social form itself (the commodity, surplus
value, competition, etc.).123
In the second Book of the Science of Logic, the ‘doctrine of essence’, however,
Hegel shows the object to gain its essential determination not through its con-
trastive exclusion from other things, but instead through the sublation of such
external reflection as the inner, constitutive contradiction that he names the
‘determination of reflection’ [Reflexionsbestimmung].124 By this he indicates
the inner, contradictory determination of the thing by dyadic categories such
as cause and effect or essence and appearance, categories that are in internal
relation to the thing they define.125 The key point for Hegel is that such inner
This is to argue that the object is not merely a positive entity, its being consist-
ing of a synthetic addition of its various qualities (as shown in Hegel’s doctrine
of Being), but constitutes instead, from the perspective of its essence, a neg-
ative or contradictory totality: ‘The thing as this totality is contradiction [Das
Ding als diese Totalität ist der Widerspruch], … the form in which the matter is
determined … and at the same time consisting of sorts of matter that … are at
once both self-standing and negated’.127
The question in the case of the commodity is thus whether use-value and
exchange-value, what Marx calls the two ‘factors’ [Faktoren] of the commodity,
simultaneously contain and exclude one another to constitute a contradic-
tion in Hegel’s sense, or, instead, stand in positive ‘opposition’ [Gegensatz] to
one another without contradiction. Note carefully Hegel’s contention: ‘[Self-
subsistence] contains the determination which is other than it in itself …; but
no less immediately … excludes from itself the determination that negates it’.
Each determination of reflection, in other words, contains its opposite within
itself, which I will argue does not obtain in Marx’s analysis of the commodity.
There, in contrast, I will seek to show that the determinations or what Marx
calls the ‘factors’ of the commodity such as use- and exchange-value merely
stand in positive ‘opposition’ to one another without mutual reflection, pre-
cisely as Marx will state in the revised versions of this analysis.
Here, I can only agree with Roberto Fineschi, who writes that ‘I do not think that we have
to look for analogies or homologies between Marx’s theory of capital and Hegel’s logic; this
alleged ‘Hegelian approach’ has paradoxically resulted in a very non-dialectical attitude in
many scholars. In fact, Marx himself criticised any external application of categories to a
given content’ (Fineschi 2014, p. 140).
126 Hegel 2010b, p. 374, emphasis in original.
127 Hegel 2010a, p. 196, translation modified.
What Abazari does show convincingly is that in the analysis of the concept of
the commodity in the first edition of Capital, Marx systematically adopts this
Hegelian logic of constitutive negation [Reflexionsbestimmung], the commod-
ity, that is to say, as it has commonly been understood in traditional Marxism ‘as
the contradictory unity of use-value and exchange-value’.130 It is not merely the
case that Marx initially adopts the Hegelian vocabulary of externalisation, con-
tradiction [Widerspruch], the determinations of reflection [Reflexionsbestim-
mung], and essence and appearance in the first chapter of the 1867 edition.131
Abazari argues more generally that in Marx’s analysis of the value-form:
This, then, is the familiar claim for the ‘contradictory’ nature of use- and
exchange-value in the commodity, but does it hold up when measured against
the actual terminology and argument to be found in Marx’s demonstration in
the 1872 edition of Capital?
It is important to distinguish this first chapter of the 1867 edition that founds
Abazari’s claim, the argument of which, Marx warns his reader, will ‘present
the greatest difficulty’, from what Marx calls the ‘supplementary, more didactic
exposition of the form of value’ that he added as an appendix to that same first
edition, at the request of Engels and Kugelmann.133 The latter material then
formed the basis of Marx’s 1872 revision of this chapter. In that 1867 appendix –
Marx tells the reader in his Postface to the second edition – the process of expo-
sition ‘[was] completely revised’. While the 1867 appendix thus already begins
the tendential elimination of this Hegelian vocabulary, a process that will cul-
minate in the 1872 and 1875 editions, a systematic comparison of the five ver-
sions of this chapter shows that this tendency is both uneven and incomplete,
such that none of Marx’s varied analyses of the value form can be considered
as definitive.134
The revision manuscript that Marx drafted in December 1871-January 1872,135
for example, develops the social, communal nature of value-objectivity to
a degree unparalleled in any of the three published versions of his analy-
sis,136 while the 1875 French translation by Joseph Roy, which Marx person-
ally and extensively revised, inserts, for example, a negative dialectical pas-
sage absent from both the 1867 and 1872 German editions: ‘Les contradictions
que renferme la forme équivalente exige maintenant un examen plus appro-
hesitating to draw Althusserian conclusions from this absence, conclusions that Heinrich
steers clear of in his commitment to reading Capital literally and without interpretation.
132 Abazari 2019, pp. 190–1.
133 Marx 1976, pp. 89, 94.
134 Heinrich 2021, pp. 363, 370.
135 ‘Ergänzungen und Veränderungen zum ersten Band des Kapitals (Additions and Changes
to the First Volume of Capital)’.
136 Heinrich 2021, p. 375.
fondie’.137 Similarly, the 1872 edition, while abandoning the vocabulary and
logic of contradiction [Widerspruch] in its body text, nonetheless inserts a
note observing that ‘determinations of reflection [Reflexionsbestimmungen]
of this kind [i.e., in the analysis of the value form] are altogether very curi-
ous’.138
Given this complexity and unevenness between Marx’s various presenta-
tions of the value form, it is notable that Marx already distinguishes in 1867
between his materialist derivation of the form of value as ‘an external mate-
rial in which labour objectifies [vergegenständlichen] itself … as determinate
labour [bestimmten Arbeit]’, and Hegelian idealism, in which, he observes iron-
ically, ‘it is only the ‘concept’ [Begriff ] in Hegel’s sense that manages to objectify
itself without external material’.139 Marx’s 1867 critique of Hegelian idealism is
thus precociously analogous to that which Badiou will develop of Frege in Being
and Event: thought cannot imperiously determine being, but must remain sub-
ject to a materialist determination.140
Heinrich observes, however, that this position nonetheless remains a mere
negative critique; it will only be with the further revision in the 1872 version of
this chapter that Marx would develop the conceptual means to distinguish the
‘chimerical’ objectivity of the commodity form from the tangible value form.
According to Heinrich’s reading,
both in chapter 1 of the first edition and in [Marx’s 1872] revision manu-
script, Marx seems unsure about how exactly to present the relation
between the ‘purely chimerical’ objectivity of value and its tangible form
of existence in the shape of another commodity. It’s clear that this relation
is not to be grasped in the manner of Hegel’s philosophy. In fact, Marx first
found an adequate solution [only] in Capital’s second edition. There, he
distinguishes between two levels of investigation: (1) The examination of
the exchange relation between two commodities [as …] value-objectivity,
which cannot be grasped in the case of the individual commodity; (2)
Here we have one of the clearest examples of the furtive and uneven tendency
of development across the multiple versions of Marx’s exposition of the value
form, from an initial rejection of Hegelian idealist, negative dialectic that still
lacks the means replace this with a positive demonstration, to Marx’s further
development by 1872 of what Heinrich and Fred Moseley agree is an additive
synthetic method of presentation without negation, one that clearly distin-
guishes between and synthetically proceeds from an analysis of what Heinrich
identifies as the ‘exchange relation’ to that of the ‘value relation’, and Moseley,
from the substance and magnitude of value in the first two sections of chapter 1,
to its necessary form of appearance in the third.142
Abazari, in contrast, finds Marx’s 1872 insertion of the footnote 22 referring to
the ‘Determinations of reflection [Reflexionsbestimmungen]’ in the value-form
to be certain proof of a continued reliance on Hegelian logic. In comparison
with the body of the text, from which the concept of contradiction is strictly
absent, I believe, in contrast, that the insertion of this new footnote in 1872 is
rather an example of Marx falling back on an old and familiar category to inad-
equately indicate a new, post-Hegelian process he is in the process of inventing,
an original form of additive, synthetic dialectic.
This would then be another example of what Althusser identified as the
symptomatic tendency of a novel theory in its deployment to run ahead of sub-
jective recognition of its novelty:
141 Heinrich 2021, p. 380. Heinrich’s contention that the first chapter of Capital is divided
between analyses of the exchange relation and the value relation has not gone unchal-
lenged, in particular by Fred Moseley (2023). I will discuss the dispute between Heinrich
and Moseley over the nature of value in Capital below.
142 Here is Moseley: ‘The overall logical structure of Marx’s analysis of the commodity in
Chapter 1 is in terms of the concepts of the substance of value, the magnitude of value,
and the form of appearance of value. The substance and magnitude of value are derived
in Sections 1 and 2, and then the form of appearance of value is derived in Section 3,
with the predetermined substance and magnitude of value presupposed’ (Moseley 2023,
p. 236). The distinction I make throughout this chapter between Marx’s analytic method
of research in preparatory notebooks such as the Grundrisse and the synthetic method
of Darstellung characteristic of Capital is also held by the systematic dialectical school of
Marxist epistemology, including Heinrich’s vehement critic Fred Moseley, and is explicitly
developed for example in Reuten 2014, p. 251. Though I agree with Reuten, Arthur and Tony
Smith on the relevance of this analytic/synthetic distinction, as noted above, I reject the
positions of this school regarding the concepts of capital as a totality and the putatively
contradiction-based process of Marx’s exposition.
This is what Marx tells us. And there is no apparent reason not to take
him at his word …. [And yet,] at certain moments, in certain symptomatic
points, this silence [i.e., the absence of a proper name for a novel concept
or procedure Marx has invented] emerges as such in the discourse and
forces it against its will to produce real theoretical lapses, in brief blank
flashes, invisible in the light of the proof: words [such as Reflexionsbestim-
mungen] that hang in mid-air although they seem to be inserted into the
necessity of the thought, judgements which close irreversibly with a false
obviousness the space of which seemed to be opening before reason ….
Marx has not thought what he is doing to the letter.143
While the word Widerspruch (contradiction) does not appear at all in Chap-
ter 1 of the 1872 edition, Marx comes to prioritise in its place the concept of
Gegensatz (opposition) to indicate the precise nature of the relation of use- and
exchange-value in the concept of the commodity. The word Gegensatz (which
is only used 4 times in the 1867 version of Chapter 1) appears some twenty-five
times in Chapter 1 (1872), as Marx’s term of preference to indicate the relation
of use-value and value: i.e., ‘The simple form of value of a commodity is the
146 In the 1872 edition, Marx first uses the word Widerspruch only toward the end of chap-
ter 3.1, ‘The Measure of Values’: ‘The price-form … may also harbour a qualitative contra-
diction [qualitativen Widerspruch]’ (1976, p. 197). Marx refers once to the mere illusory
appearance [scheint] that exchange-value is ‘something accidental’ as a pseudo ‘contra-
diction in adjecto’, but translates the Latin as ‘Widersinn’ rather than the more Hegelian
synonym Widerspruch [1976, p. 126] (1976, p. 153).
147 In The Science of Value, Michael Heinrich casually equates the two terms in passing: ‘Das
Mangelhafte an einer Kategorie wird von Marx oft als “Gegensatz” oder “Widerspruch”
ihrer verschiedenen Bestimmungen bezeichnet’ (‘What is deficient in a category is often
defined by Marx as the “opposition” or “contradiction” between its different determina-
tions’) (Heinrich2022, p. 174; 2023, p. 270, my translation). In Hegel or Spinoza, Macherey,
in contrast, observes that ‘The contradiction (Widerspruch) distinguishes itself from the
opposition (Gegensatz) in that it is not a fixed relation between distinct and antagonistic
terms but the irresistible movement that discovers in each of these elements the truth of
the other and thus produces them as moments of a unique process in which they appear
as inseparable’ (2011, p. 121).
tled Annals of Atheism.148 While Marx’s initial intent in 1839–1841 was to defend
Hegelian logic against Trendelenburg, on at least one count, the latter’s learned
exposition of Aristotelean logic and critique of Hegelian dialectics seems to
have hit home, and to have provided for this brilliant and learned young reader
of Aristotle a signal theoretical distinction between Hegelian idealist and sci-
entific materialist methods of logical demonstration.
In Logische Untersuchungen, Trendelenburg vehemently criticizes Hegel for
confusing quite basic Aristotelean logical principles, primary among which in
Trendelenburg’s judgment is Hegel’s failure to grasp the fundamental distinc-
tion Aristotle makes between what Trendelenburg calls ‘logical negation’ and
‘real opposition [Gegensatz].’149 If Marx had not already gleaned this theoreti-
cal distinction from his reading of Aristotle, it would have been impossible to
overlook its primacy in Trendelenburg’s critique. It is, moreover, this distinction
between Hegelian ‘logical negation’ and Aristotelean, materialist ‘real opposi-
tion’ that, I wish to argue, becomes a fundamental theoretical distinction for
Marx, from his 1843 ‘Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right’ through his revi-
sions to Capital three decades later.
When Marx first came to critique Hegelian logic in the 1843 “Critique of
Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,” he reproached Hegel throughout for his logical
idealism, for his derivation, that is to say, of the empirical existence of the
orders of the state – sovereign, executive, legislative, and the Estates – from
their logical Idea. This process inevitably leads, Marx argues, to an uncritical
defence of the status quo:
later Marx came to draft and subsequently revise the various sections of Capi-
tal, it would be this nominal distinction between “contradiction” and “opposi-
tion” that would serve to clearly indicate to an informed reader the distinction
between two theoretical procedures of analysis and demonstration. It is a the-
oretical doublet that allowed Marx succinctly to realise in his various revisions,
in part, the task he had given himself in the Grundrisse: the systematic elimi-
nation of the impression that the various categories of his analysis are derived
from the Idea of the capitalist social form, rather than scientifically constructed
from his analysis of a real thing, a society typified by the accumulation and
exchange of commodities.153
If now we return to reading Capital to the letter, we do in fact find that what
Marx demonstrates in his analysis of the commodity is an “opposition” rather
than a Hegelian “contradiction” between use- and exchange-value.154 Indeed,
Marx begins his demonstration by introducing each dimension of the com-
modity positively, as what he calls ‘factors’ [Faktoren] or attributes. There is no
derivation of use-value or exchange-value in the opening paragraphs of Capi-
tal; instead, they are simply additively posed or ‘positioned’, as Althusser will
say, one after another: ‘The commodity is, first of all, an external object, a thing
which through its qualities satisfies human needs of whatever kind … The use-
fulness of a thing makes it a use-value’. And then, in his fifth paragraph, with
neither transition nor derivation of any kind, Marx immediately poses the sec-
ond factor of the commodity: ‘Exchange-value appears first of all as the quan-
titative relation, the proportion, in which use-values of one kind exchange for
use-values of another kind’.155
If we abstract from Marx’s intervening analysis of the characteristics of these
two factors or attributes of the commodity (satisfying a human need, having
both quality and quantity, etc.), we are left with two positive, underived propo-
sitions:
A. The commodity has the attribute (‘factor’) use-value.
B. The commodity has the attribute (‘factor’) exchange-value.156
153 “It will be necessary later,” Marx noted to himself in the Grundrisse, “to correct the ide-
alist manner of the presentation, which makes it seem as if it were merely a matter of
conceptual determinations and of the dialectic of these concepts” Marx, 1973, 151.
154 Here I only summarize relevant moments in Marx’s exposition of the commodity form in
Capital, chapter One (1872), referring readers to Michael Heinrich’s more detailed exposi-
tion of this chapter’s logic in How to Read Marx’s Capital.
155 Marx 1976, pp. 125–6.
156 To call these factors ‘attributes’ of the commodity implies that, analogously to the infi-
nite attributes of substance that Spinoza identifies, use-value and exchange-value are ‘that
In the relation between Marx’s initial proposition that the ‘individual com-
modity’ constitutes the ‘elementary form’ [Elementarform] of the capitalist
mode of production and the additive introduction of these two attributes in
the four succeeding paragraphs,157 there is no trace of any deduction or infer-
ence whatsoever, to say nothing of a putative negative dialectical sublation
such as is to be found in the first lines of Hegel’s Science of Logic (Being|Noth-
ing→Becoming).158 At the same time, this additive positioning of concepts is
no a priori formalist or abstract axiomatic exercise, but comprises a prop-
erly materialist critique, thanks to the necessary determination of this starting
point – the true idea that we as subjects of capitalism always already possess
of its nature (as general commodification).159 Marx has determined precisely
these as the attributes of the commodity, thanks to his painstaking research
or ‘enquiry’ [Forschungsweise] prior to the elaboration of his reproduction
[Darstellungsweise] of the capitalist real in the attribute of thought.160
which the intellect perceives of’ the ‘substance’ of the capitalist mode of production – i.e.,
what Marx has just called its ‘Elementarform’, the commodity – ‘as constituting its [the
commodity’s] essence’ at its greatest level of abstraction (eid4).
157 Marx 1976, pp. 125–6.
158 This absence of a contradiction-based logic in Capital is one of the principal themes of
Althusser’s ‘Avant-propos du livre de G. Duménil’ (written in February 1977), along with
his subsequent (unpublished) seminar of March 1978, the ‘Cours sur le mode d’exposition
chez Marx’ (imec 20 alt 28.5): ‘In what respect could use-value … be said to contradict
the value it “carries”? Mystery’ (‘Avant-propos’, p. 253). ‘The relation between use-value and
exchange-value is not a relation of contradiction (as the result of a scission) … the scis-
sion of an abstraction of value into use-value and exchange-value …. Marx insists on the
difference in function of use-value [which] can in no sense be thought of as contradictory
to exchange-value’ imec 20alt 28.5, pp. 16–17. Althusser’s assertion remains little more
than that, however, this claim in both these texts cryptically referring to Marx’s passing
observation that use-values are the ‘bearers’ [Träger] of value (‘In the form of society to be
considered here [use-values] are also the material bearers [Träger] of … exchange-value’)
(Marx 1976, p. 126).
159 What Macherey says of Spinoza’s starting point in Ethics holds identically for Marx’s begin-
ning to Capital: ‘If the exposition of the Spinozist doctrine begins with definitions, axioms,
and postulates, if it begins with substance rather than God, this does not at all indicate that
these primitive notions constitute a source of truth from which all that follows could be
simply deduced, following a rigid and predetermined course in the form of an explication.
Substance, attributes, and modes, as they appear in these liminary principals, are precisely
the equivalent of the rough, unpolished stone that the first smiths needed to “begin” their
work: these are still abstract notions, simple words, natural ideas that will only truly take
on meaning from the moment they function in demonstrations’ (Macherey 2011, p. 76).
160 Marx 1976, p. 102. In the Avant-propos to G. Duménil, Althusser offers a qualified agree-
ment with Duménil’s assertion (equivalent to that which Arthur makes in New Dialectic)
that ‘“Political economy is not an axiomatic”. Certainly’, Althusser observes, this is the case
‘in the sense of an ideological axiomatic: Marx neither positions [pose] nor adds [ajoute]
a given concept [merely] to “explore” what would follow from it, as a pure hypothesis,
or to produce consequent effects. He doesn’t indulge in arbitrary variations, nor in the
“apprehension” of a given phenomenal totality as a mere indulgence [par plaisir]. His
exposition is patently guided, behind the scenes, by the great realities discovered by the
silent “method of research” [Forschungsweise]’ (Althusser 1998, p. 259). Althusser writes in
the 1978 ‘Cours sur le mode d’exposition’, in terms that similarly emphasise the materialist
determination of Marx’s method, that ‘this method is not without resemblance [analo-
gie] with an axiomatic method, with the understanding that the positioning of concepts
… plays the role of the conceptual introduction of real [materialist] determinations that
must be introduced in abstract form in order simultaneously to think the discontinuity of
the field within a previously constituted theoretical continuity’ imec 20alt 28.5, pp. 18–
19.
161 Althusser 1998, p. 257.
162 Althusser 1998, p. 258. In the ‘Cours sur le mode d’exposition’ Althusser observes in a simi-
lar vein that the additive procedure of the positioning of concepts ‘is the condition of the
discontinuity of the theoretical field [of Capital] …. [While] Hegel proceeds by the auto-
production of concepts, Marx proceeds by the positioning of a concept, [such that] the
positioning of each concept opens and closes a new theoretical field’ (imec 20alt 28.5,
p. 17).
Althusser describes, I would add, thus coheres perfectly with Spinoza’s critique
of totality in his 1665 letter to Oldenburg, despite its telegraphic nature in this
late moment of Althusser’s thought.
While the variegated analysis of exchange-value and that of the even more
complex value relation characteristic of these two attributes will occupy Marx
in the rest of chapter one, his three-paragraph analysis of the concept of
use-value in the first two pages of Capital starkly illustrates Macherey and
Althusser’s claim that Marx’s demonstration proceeds sequentially, via the
‘exhaustive’ (Macherey) analysis of each concept; a given concept’s essential
nature having been thoroughly analysed at the corresponding level of abstrac-
tion, all without logical contradiction, Marx can then presuppose that analysis
as a given, and move to the next level of abstraction as what Althusser calls an
additive positioning.
Now, if this were all there were to Marx’s process of exposition, the case for
the tendential suppression of Aufhebung in Capital would be closed; indeed,
Macherey has it easy on this score by only considering the first five pages of
Chapter 1 in his brief contribution to Reading Capital. That said, Marx’s pro-
cess of exposition throughout Capital, if we look beyond Althusser’s elliptical
assertions and Macherey’s brief analysis, is indeed impelled not by contradic-
tory reflections of determinations [Reflexionsbestimmungen], but instead due
to what Marx variously calls the ‘insufficiency’ [Unzulägliche], ‘defects’ [Män-
gel] or ‘peculiarities’ [Eigentümlichkeit] of a concept, terms that indicate its
various inadequacies at that level of abstraction.
Indeed, the real and telling complexities can be said to begin in the third
section of the first chapter, precisely the section, that is, that Abazari, and,
indeed, Marx himself in footnote 22, identify as the locus of various Reflex-
ionsbestimmungen. It is in this section 1.3 that Marx examines not use-value,
exchange-value, and what Heinrich identifies as the basic exchange relation
of commodities in abstraction from their value form, but – at this subsequent
degree of concretion – the value relation, the complex interrelation of use- and
exchange-value in the analysis of the value form, which necessarily culminates
in the general equivalent and money form.163
Close attention to Marx’s analysis of the value form in this section unequivo-
cally shows that he additively builds upon his analysis of the exchange relation
in the preceding two sections, without those demonstrations being superseded
or invalidated. In the initial moment of his demonstration (sections 1.1–1.2),
Marx first analysed the exchange relation between two commodities, from
which he concluded that they must share a ‘common element’, value, the sub-
stance of which he shows to be abstract labour. In section 1.3, he then proceeds
to the analysis of the form of value, as the section title clearly indicates: ‘The
Value-form, or Exchange-Value’. In this logical progression from sections 1.1 and
1.2 to section 1.3 – the latter arguably one of the most crucial demonstrations
of Capital – there is not a trace of negative dialectical, contradiction-based
Hegelian logic determining the development of these categories.
Instead, Marx deploys an original process of logical demonstration that I
am calling additive synthesis. The demonstration is additive, in the sense that
Marx’s analysis of the value relation presupposes his prior adequate and com-
plete demonstration of the exchange relation, the analysis of the value relation
constituting a subsequent degree of concretion relative to the initial high level
of abstraction of section one.164 This additive mode of positive dialectic in
Part One of Capital confirms Jacques Bidet’s abstract assertion, in his review
of Arthur’s New Dialectic, that there is no Hegelian, contradiction-based ‘fluid-
ity’ of Marx’s concepts in the movement from one part or section to another
(as Arthur asserts):
It is not the concept that changes [from one section to another]; rather,
there is a change of concept, through conceptual determinations …. The
‘theory of value’ [in Part One of Capital] is in no way transformed by the
theory of surplus-value [in Part Two], which, on the contrary, expressly
presupposes it, unchanged, in the pure and perfect form that Marx has
given it in his exposition in Part One.165
164 Marx initially abstracts from the category of the form of value, in addition to the many
other variables held at bay in his incipient analysis of the commodity, such as prices,
money, other commodities, commodity owners and buyers, capital, etc. In this, I follow
Heinrich’s conclusion: ‘If we speak of the “value-relation” between two commodities, then
value is already presupposed as a result of the exchange relation …. What is new here
is that Marx has introduced the concept of form and undertakes a detailed analysis of
the value-form’ (Heinrich 2021, pp. 98, 99). In this section of my argument, I am building
on Heinrich’s comprehensive but theoretically agnostic presentation, to argue that Marx
deploys a novel process of demonstration that I am calling the additive synthetic. Hegel, in
The Science of Logic, indicated precisely the methodological procedure Marx would adopt
in Capital: ‘[One must begin a scientific exposition] with the subject matter in the form
of a universal …. The prius must be … something simple, something abstracted from the
concrete, because in this form alone has the subject-matter the form of the self-related
universal …. It is easier for the mind to grasp the abstract simple thought determination
than the concrete subject matter, which is a manifold connection of such thought deter-
minations and their relationships’ (cited in Musto 2020, p. 16).
165 Bidet 2005, p. 133. Though unattributed, Bidet’s argument clearly develops the late
Althusser’s concept of la position, described above.
In the first chapter of Capital that I discuss here, Marx implements a purely
additive synthetic method, in which the process of logical synthesis operates
in a fashion analogous to that which Macherey identifies in his commentary on
Spinoza’s method. Basing his comments on Spinoza’s Preface to the Principles of
the Philosophy of Descartes, the only site at which Spinoza reflected on method,
Macherey observes that for Spinoza, ‘synthesis [as opposed to Cartesian anal-
ysis] is the method of formal exposition that allows for the presentation of
truths [that have been previously discovered and analysed in the research pro-
cess] in a demonstrative form that proceeds from the known to the known ….
Synthesis proceeds from the knowledge of causes to that of their effects, in
conformity with the real order of things’.166 For both Spinoza and Marx, such
additive demonstration, as a science of causes without superfluous reference
to a putative totality or whole, constitutes the adequate modality of a material-
ist demonstration, the synthetic reproduction of the real order of things in the
attribute of thought.
This synthetic mode of demonstration [Macherey continues],
mentally reproduces … the order in which things effectively are and pro-
duce one another [sont et se font] …. Synthesis concomitantly expresses
the productivity of the real [as] a form of discourse, the organisation of
which, which is to say its necessary progression, adheres to that of the
causal process, and reproduces the order of the real as it is in itself, leading
to understanding as if from the interior of things, as they are and as they
develop [telles qu’elles sont et telles qu’elles se font], following the rational
movement that leads from causes to effects, rather than the inverse.167
he inserts in the first sentence of Capital, as if to say: ‘This, reader, is what I have
come to understand as the effective constitution of the real order of things and
relations of value in the capitalist social form: follow my reasoning carefully,
and judge for yourself if this is the case’.170
Let’s look at Marx’s analysis of the value relation more carefully. In Marx’s
initial analysis of the exchange relation in sections 1.1–1.2, he determined that
the value of commodities – a ‘residue’ obtained by abstracting entirely from
their characteristics as use-values – has no material form at that level of abstrac-
tion, and thus cannot exist as a sensuous singular thing, but instead constitutes
a mere ‘spectral objectivity’.171 This first stage of analysis showed that the sub-
stance of the commodity’s value is abstract labour, but did so in abstraction
from its phenomenal manifestation in any determinate form whatsoever.
The substance of this value, abstract labour, will only obtain objective, mate-
rial form, and thus actual existence, as opposed to this mere spectral objectivity,
when Marx’s logical demonstration investigates the concrete social relation of
one commodity to another, and it is to the nature of this relation that Marx
turns in section 1.3.172 At stake in this section, the development of which will
culminate in Marx’s unprecedented demonstration of the logical (as opposed
to historical) genesis and necessity of the money form, is a problem that had
previously remained at best a riddle, and at worst entirely invisible, in the his-
tory of political economy: while it is obvious to anyone that money allows for
the exchange of commodities, this does not at all explain how it is that money
possesses this strange power, and why it must necessarily be so in any soci-
ety governed by commodity relations: only Marx’s logical genesis of the money
form can answer this question.173
My point here is simply to show that each logical step in Marx’s demon-
stration fully preserves the findings that precede it, and, as opposed to any
alleged negative dialectical Aufhebung, proceeds instead through a positive,
additive logic of implication. Marx begins this analysis in section 1.3a by con-
170 ‘I welcome every opinion based on scientific criticism’, Marx writes in the Preface to the
first edition. ‘As to the prejudices of so-called public opinion, to which I have never made
concessions, now, as ever, my maxim is that of the great Florentine: “Segui il tuo corso, e
lascia dir le genti”’ (1976, p. 93).
171 Marx 1976, p. 128. This point will prove crucial when I come to discuss Moseley’s critique
of Heinrich in the next section.
172 ‘Commodities possess an objective character as values only in so far as they are all expres-
sions of an identical social substance, human labour, [such] that their objective character
as values is therefore purely social’ (Marx 1976, p. 138).
173 Heinrich 2021, p. 97. See also Bellofiore’s analysis of this spectral aspect of Marx’s demon-
stration, Bellofiore 2018, pp. 360–1.
structing the value relation in its most abstract form, one that is ‘simple’ (it
investigates only two commodities), ‘isolated’ (bearing no relationship to com-
modities other than these two he has chosen), and ‘accidental’ (because any
two commodities could be chosen as examples of this abstract relation).174 This
simple isolated and accidental form of the value relation, he next specifies,
possesses two ‘poles’ [Pole] that coexist and allow for this relation, mutually
determining and barring one another, all without contradiction, precisely as
the poles of a compass coexist in their opposing, non-contradictory difference
to define North and South.
Marx first recalls the results of his prior analysis of the exchange relation,
which involved the exchange of two commodities of equal value such that
both commodities identically and symmetrically shared a ‘common element’
(value).175 In marked contrast, when Marx now turns to the analysis of the
form of expression of value, that value relationship is by no means symmetri-
cal. Instead, the first commodity (linen) is said by Marx to actively expresses its
value in the second commodity (coat), while the second commodity remains
passive, serving as the material expression of something else, the value of the
first. Marx names these two forms the ‘relative’ and the ‘equivalent’ form of
value. Like the two attributes of the commodity that Marx introduced in the
first pages of Capital, Marx here observes that these two forms of value bear
two non-contradictory aspects or attributes: they are 1. mutually dependent,
each requiring the existence of the other, as well as being 2. mutually exclusive,
such that a given commodity can only play the role of one of these two forms
at a time.176
Having presented these attributes, in section 1.3.2, Marx next proceeds to
analyse the first of these two forms of value, the relative. Though Marx’s initial
analysis of the exchange relation has shown that the value of any and all com-
modities can be reduced to an identical unit (abstract labour), in now analysing
the form that this value must take, he proceeds to investigate the particulari-
ties of these differential roles (relative and equivalent forms of value), explicitly
calling attention to the difference between these two levels of his analysis:
While it is the case that as values, at the level of the exchange relation, com-
modities are what Marx describes as ‘congealed’ abstract human labour, this
common unit, since it possesses not an ‘atom of matter’,178 cannot be appre-
hended in the sensuous, actually existing form of a singular, isolated commod-
ity.179
Now, however, additively building upon this prior determination of an initial
‘value-abstraction’, Marx proceeds to show that when considered at the higher
level of logical concretion of the value relation, the value of the commodity
that plays the relative role in this relation (linen) does in fact acquire the mate-
rial expression of its value in and through the equivalent form possessed by the
second, actually existing commodity (coat), a material form necessarily differ-
ent from its own (the value of linen cannot be expressed in linen).180 From this
demonstration, Marx draws a simple, minimal inference: that ‘the value of the
commodity linen is therefore expressed by the physical body of the commodity
coat, the value of one by the use-value of the other’.181 This then leads him to
offer a summary statement of this stage of his analysis:
This completed, in the next step of his analysis, in section 1.3.2.ii, Marx intro-
duces the quantitative aspect of this value relation from which he had
abstracted to this point (‘The quantitative determinacy of the relative form of
value’). As a material expression or actually existing embodiment of value, in
The commodity linen brings to view its own existence as a value through
the fact that the coat can be equated with the linen although it has
not assumed a form of value distinct from its own physical form. The
coat is directly exchangeable with the linen; in this way the linen in fact
expresses its own existence as a value. The equivalent form of a commod-
ity, accordingly, is the form in which it is directly exchangeable with other
commodities.185
While the first sentence summarises Marx’s analysis of the value form to this
point, the second and third add to this a new proposition: the actually exist-
ing, material form of the linen expresses the coat’s direct ‘exchangeability’ with
it, such that the equivalent form ‘is the form in which it is directly exchange-
able with other commodities’, which is to say, that it requires no mediation (of
another commodity) for the exchange process to occur.186
Marx next indicates three ‘peculiarities’ [Eigentümlichkeiten] (none of
which constitute ‘contradictions’) of the equivalent form, in which he stresses
the necessity that governs this form, such that the appearance of the value of
the linen in the form of the coat requires and can only occur within this value-
relation:
The natural form of the commodity becomes its value-form. But, note
well, this substitution only occurs in the case of a commodity B (coat, or
maize, or iron, etc.) when some other commodity A (linen etc.) enters into
a value-relation with it, and then only within the limits of this relation.
Here again we find Marx stressing the systematic necessity that governs the
value relation between two commodities: since no commodity can express its
value in its own material form, it must relate to another, materially distinct
commodity as its equivalent, the actually existing material form of its value.
The linen (in Marx’s example) must take the physical form of the equivalent
commodity (coat) as the form of its value, since the value of linen cannot be
expressed in linen. This, Marx shows, is the real, necessary, and positive form
of the value relation, involving no contradiction whatsoever between use- and
exchange-value, but only a peculiarity that he insightfully notes, one that allows
for the value relation materially to exist.
Next, following his famous excursus on Aristotle’s socially determined inca-
pacity to grasp the nature of the value relation,188 Marx summarises his qual-
itative and quantitative analysis of the simple form of the value relation, to
which he adds the important terminological clarification that the two factors
or attributes of the commodity introduced at the beginning of chapter one
should, strictly speaking, have been identified as use-value and ‘value’ (rather
than exchange-value), since exchange-value is merely the ‘form of manifes-
tation’ of value, not something a given commodity possesses in and of itself.
Instead, Marx specifies, ‘the commodity never has this form when looked at in
isolation, but only when it is in a value-relation or an exchange relation with a
second commodity of a different kind’.189 As Heinrich specifies, ‘A commodity
“is” something double: use-value and an object of value. But it is not exchange-
value; it has exchange-value, when another commodity expresses its value’.190
While it may seem that Marx is splitting hairs, the point is important in the
context of my argument (and I will argue it applies analogously in Moseley’s
dispute with Heinrich), since it clearly indicates a key conceptual and logical
difference from the 1867 edition, where Marx did not yet clearly distinguish
between value and exchange-value.
Even more crucial is the next step in Marx’s argument, and in fact the inter-
pretation of this passage condenses and radicalises my entire argument for
Marx’s additive, positive dialectical method. Here is Marx’s observation, which
I cite in full:
Here, perhaps more than anywhere else in the first chapter of Capital, we
would expect to find a statement of the ‘contradictory’ nature of use-value and
exchange-value. Instead, Marx does not simply refuse outright the Hegelian
terminology of contradiction [Widerspruch]; what’s more, he clearly and oth-
erwise defines the nature of this relation – both within the single commodity
possessing its two attributes of use-value and value when initially analysed at
the level of the exchange relation, and now, at the level of the value relation –
as an opposition [Gegensatz].
As I have throughout this book, let me pause to invoke the lucidly contrast-
ing definitions André Lalande offers for these two concepts:
– ‘Contradiction’ [D. Widerspruch]: the relation existing between the affirma-
tion and the negation of a same element of knowledge, in particular, between
two terms, one of which is the negation of the other, such as A and not-A.
– ‘Opposition’ [D. Gegensatz, Opposition]: the relation of two contrary objects
placed facing one another in contrast or distinction.192
191 Marx 1976, p. 153, emphasis added. ‘Der in der Ware eingehüllte innere Gegensatz von
Gebrauchswert und Wert wird also dargestellt durch einen äußeren Gegensatz, d.h. durch
das Verhältnis zweier Waren, worin die eine Ware, deren Wert ausgedrückt werden soll,
unmittelbar nur als Gebrauchswert, die andre Ware hingegen, worin Wert ausgedrückt
wird, unmittelbar nur als Tauschwert gilt. Die einfache Wertform einer Ware ist also die
einfache Erscheinungsform des in ihr enthaltenen Gegensatzes von Gebrauchswert und
Wert’. mega ii 6, Karl Marx, Das Kapital: Kritik Der Politishen Ökonomie. Erster Band, Ham-
burg 1872. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1987, p. 93.
192 Lalande 2010, pp. 183, 717, emphasis added. I have added the specification ‘in contrast or
distinction’ to Lalande’s from the oed definition of opposition.
193 Hegel 2010b, p. 59. Compare Hegel’s argument with that of Spinoza in proposition 3 of
Ethics iii, as Macherey reads the latter: ‘There is nothing in the essence of a thing, follow-
ing from its definition, which can cause it not to be [qui puisse faire qu’elle ne soit pas],
or that its reality encompass [soit marquée] any negativity whatsoever [and thus Spinoza
writes:] “the definition of any thing whatsoever affirms the essence of that thing itself, but
does not negate it; that is to say, it posits the essence of the thing but does not suppress
it” (definition cujuscunque rei ipsius rei essentiam affirmat sed non negat; sive rei essentiam
point, sed non tollit)’. Macherey 1997 p. 382.
is emphatically and logically necessary, he shows, for this very distinction (as A
and B rather than A and not-A) to exist such that commodity and commodity
relations may themselves exist (and Marx has begun Capital by defining soci-
eties in which the capitalist mode of production predominates, his object of
investigation, as the general existence (appearance) of commodities and com-
modified relations).
In fact, these two contrasting starting points of Hegel’s Logic and Marx’s Cap-
ital could not be more radically opposed, though each thinker at the same time
fully comprehends and calls attention to the difficulty and crucial nature of the
beginning of any scientific analysis.194 For the one, a word, a notion, Being, con-
ceived and defined as a maximum of abstraction, as ‘without content’. For the
other, a (maximally abstract but positive) definition of capitalism as the general
accumulation of commodities, one that is quite the opposite of nothing (it is
an ‘ungeheure Waarensammlung’); instead, having come to this definition and
starting point by necessity through his materialist enquiry, Marx’s beginning
indicates something very concrete, full of positive implications that remain to
be concretised.
The negative dialectical dice are loaded if one picks a notion with no deter-
minate content to start with: then of course this ‘thing’ without content will of
necessity immediately reveal itself as a contradiction, as the negation of itself,
as nothing, as A and not-A.195 On the one hand, a logic that begins with a logi-
cal contradiction and develops this into an entire science of negative dialectical
logic, on the other, a critique of a real social form, one that begins in materialist
fashion in media res, with an abstract definition of this determinate mode of
production to initiate an increasingly concrete analysis via the logic of ramified
additive synthesis and implication.
To prepare the necessary logical passage to the expanded and then general
equivalent forms of value, Marx simply indicates that the simple form of the
value relation he has analysed to this point in section 1.3 possesses an ‘insuffi-
194 Here is Hegel: ‘That which constitutes the beginning, the beginning itself, is to be taken as
something unanalysable, taken in its simple, unfilled immediacy; and therefore as being,
as complete emptiness …. Let those who are still dissatisfied with this beginning take upon
themselves the challenge of beginning in some other way and yet avoiding such defects’
(2010b, p. 53); while Marx famously warns his readers that ‘Beginnings are always difficult
in all sciences’ (1976, p. 89).
195 Compare with Caligaris and Starosta, who write, ‘In so far as [Hegel’s] systematic dialectic
begins with the simplest thought-form (that is, with a purely ideal or formal abstraction),
his subsequent derivation of categories is bound to follow the immanent necessity of ‘pure
thought’ as such, which does not express the inner movement of the simpler determina-
tions of “real material being”’ (Caligaris and Starosta 2014, p. 96, emphasis in original).
196 Marx 1976, p. 154. Heinrich at this point underscores the purely logical nature of this
demonstration in terms that again evoke Althusser’s concept of la position: ‘The transi-
tion from the simple form of value to the expanded form is not a historical transition,
which we are merely describing; rather, it is a transition to a new level of analysis, which
we are carrying out. It’s a conceptual development – a development of our conceptual
constructions – that aims to dissect what is always mixed up and interconnected in capi-
talist reality, so that we can understand it’ (Heinrich 2021, p. 124).
197 While Marx continues to speak only of ‘Gegensatze’ (‘In demselben Grad aber, worin sich
die Wertform überhaupt entwickelt, entwickelt sich auch der Gegensatz zwischen ihren
beiden Polen, der relativen Wertform und Äquivalentform’), Fowkes inconsistently, if sug-
gestively, at this point translates the term as ‘antagonism’ (1976, p. 160). For the original
German of the 1872 edition, see mega ii/6, Karl Marx, Das Kapital: Kritik Der Politischen
Ökonomie. Erster Band, Hamburg 1872. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1987, p. 99. The wording of this
passage is identical as well in the 1890 edition; cf. mega ii 10, Karl Marx, Das Kapital: Kritik
Der Politischen Ökonomie. Erster Band, Hamburg 1890. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1991, p. 67.
the remainder of chapter 1, to turn now to the dispute between Heinrich and
Moseley over the substance of value in Capital.
198 Heinrich, as noted above, follows Althusser in rejecting the theoretical commonplace that
Marx’s dialectic is a materialist revision of Hegel’s Logic, but, to my knowledge, does so
only in passing, as opposed to the more sustained attention I seek to give the question in
these pages.
199 Heinrich 2021, p. 66. Note already that in this passage (which Moseley cites on page 117
of Marx’s Theory of Value), Heinrich does not say that value is ‘created’ by exchange (as
Moseley repeatedly reads him), but only that it ‘emerges’ in this process.
200 Moseley 2023, p. 50. Here I will primarily address Moseley’s critique, which develops in
more systematic, book-length form a position on Heinrich essentially identical to that of
Kurz and Lietz and Schwarz. See also Kurz 2016 and Lietz and Schwarz 2023.
201 Heinrich 2021, p. 95.
202 Moseley 2023, p. 155, emphasis added; Lietz and Schwarz 2023, p. 26, emphasis added.
Not only is Capital a ‘theoretical’ study in its entirety; Marx famously identifies
for his reader in the Preface to the First Edition the fundamental tool he deploys
for this analysis of the capitalist social form: abstraction. ‘In the analysis of eco-
nomic forms neither microscopes nor chemical reagents are of assistance. The
power of abstraction must replace both’.204 Abstraction, as Lalande comments,
‘isolates by thought that which cannot be isolated in representation’.205 The
point is simple, but far-reaching and, indeed, eminently Althusserian: abstrac-
tion is fundamentally opposed to the representation of an empirical object.
Instead, abstraction indicates the sui generis construction of a non-existent
thought object, what Marx called in the 1857 Introduction a Gedankenkonkre-
tum.
Marx was no doubt familiar with Hegel’s anti-empiricist appraisal of abstrac-
tion in the Encyclopedia: ‘Ordinary consciousness deals with sensory represen-
tations which crisscross and get entangled. In the act of abstraction, however,
the mind is concentrated on a single point and, by this means, the habit is
acquired of preoccupying oneself with the interiority [of things]’. He emphati-
cally rejected, however, Hegel’s ensuing condescending judgement of Aristote-
lean ἀφαίϱεσις [abstraction] as no more than training wheels for the mind till
it learns to practice true, i.e. negative dialectical, thought: ‘To occupy oneself
with this kind of formal logic is no doubt useful. It clears the head, as they say.
One learns to concentrate’.206
Instead, Marx explicitly deployed ‘the power of abstraction’ as the funda-
mental tool for his entire critique of political economy, such that Heinrich can
devote an entire Appendix of his How to Read Capital to the multiple ‘Levels of
Abstraction and the Course of Argument in the First Seven Chapters of Cap-
ital’.207 What’s more, this understanding of abstraction as the construction of
nonexistent Gedankenkonkretumen constitutes, since the very beginning of his
research in 1857 when Marx first articulated this basic epistemological posi-
tion, a further confirmation of Althusser’s assertion that Marx rejects Hegel’s
208 rc, p. 36. This distinction between Hegel’s empiricist understanding of abstraction and
Marx’s Spinozist usage reproduces to some degree the founding distinction in Aristotle
between two models of abstraction, respectively, ‘abstractive induction’ (‘epagôgê [ἐπα-
γωγή]’), the additive grouping of similar elements under a single concept, versus the
‘stripping’ (‘aphaireisthai [ἀφαιϱεῖσθαι]’) [of] the image or representation of a thing of
its individualising characteristics (essentially material). Alain de Libera, ‘Abstraction’, in
Cassin 2014, p. 1.
209 Heinrich 2021, p. 53. I say the absence of awareness of this distinction is surprising in Mose-
ley’s argument because the entire, elaborate argument of his finely constructed previous
book Money and Totality is based upon the distinction between actually existing capitals
and the purely theoretical construction of aliquot subdivisions of a total mass of surplus
value. See Moseley, 2017, 45–46; Nesbitt 2022, 224 n. 68.
210 Lalande 2010, p. 318. On the extremely complex history of the related concepts of the Latin
existentia, the French and English ‘existence,’ and the German pseudo-synonyms Existenz
and Dasein, see David, 2014. Bolzano argues that the fundamental, universal characteristic
of all Vorstellungen an sich – his preeminent logical concept, analogous to Spinoza’s res sin-
gulares non existentes (eiip9) – is that ‘Vorstellungen an sich haben kein Dasein’ (Bolzano
1978, 75). I discuss Bolzano’s logic in the next chapter.
211 Of course, the general theoretical point regarding ‘existence’ that I am making here at the
high level of abstraction of the first chapter of Capital i (the site of Moseley and Hein-
rich’s debate) in no way exhausts the complexity of the relation between living labor and
the commodity labor power at greater levels of concretion, for example as what Riccardo
Bellofiore calls ‘the ambiguity built into the notion of abstract labor itself [:] abstract labor,
on the one hand, is the immediately private labor which is becoming social in circulation;
on the other hand, it is the private labor which has become socialized on the commod-
At the same time, some of those nonexistent concepts are also sensuously
manifest as singular existing things. The nonexistent concept of concrete
labour, for example, also exists as the actual physical activity, the physiologi-
cal labour, involved in producing any singular commodity, a real coat or yard of
linen. Similarly, the nonexistent concept of exchange-value also exists in sensu-
ous form, for example as the singular price of any given commodity (as a price
on a tag), i.e., as the material form of appearance of the value of that actually
existing commodity.
The form of value as exchange-value thus constitutes at once a nonexis-
tent abstraction in thought (a concept), as well as indicating actually existing
real abstractions to be found in the material world of commodity exchange.212
It is precisely this distinction, between the non-existent thought abstraction,
Marx’s Gedankenkonkretum, and the actually existing real abstractions of the
manifest, material price-forms of value, that is entirely missing from Moseley
and Heinrich’s debate.
Now, Moseley and Heinrich, astute, seasoned readers of Capital that they are,
both agree that Marx derives the concept of the substance of value (abstract
human labour) as an abstraction from the sensuous, tangible qualities of any
singular, actually existing instance of concrete labour, in other words, as a con-
cept that Marx constructs in his analysis.213 Marx summarises this point quite
clearly in the Ergänzungen:
ity market. … The origin of the trouble goes back to the fact that Marx mostly deduces
abstract labor from exchange “as such,” but he also sometimes defines it as the labor which
is opposed to capital’ (Bellofiore, 2023, 6). In my view, however, the point Bellofiore makes
is a merely apparent contradiction, as I will argue below.
212 Adorno gives a succinct definition of real abstraction in Introduction to Sociology, confus-
ingly conflating at the same time, however, two different forms of real abstraction, the real
act of exchange and the material monetary form of value: In ‘exchange in terms of aver-
age social labour time the specific forms of the objects to be exchanged are necessarily
disregarded instead, they are reduced to a universal unit. The abstraction, therefore, lies
not in the thought of the sociologist, but in society itself’ (2002, p. 32). On the concept of
real abstraction, see Sohn-Rethel 2021; Toscano 2008; and Jappe 2013.
213 ‘I agree [with Heinrich] that Marx is not looking for the common property of commodi-
ties in the production process of a single commodity’. Moseley 2023, p. 108. Marx’s ‘focus’,
Heinrich writes, ‘is therefore upon a reduction (and abstraction) that only scientific anal-
ysis can make visible’ (2021, p. 64).
Yet while being fully aware of this point, Moseley nonetheless repeatedly reaf-
firms the real existence of the substance of value in any single, isolated com-
modity: ‘The value of the coat cannot be grasped by itself, but it does exist by
itself, [as] the values of all commodities (including the linen) exist by them-
selves’.215 If we take existence in the strict sense, however, to mean any real,
sensuous thing, sensible to us via what Spinoza calls the attribute of extension,
then it is clear that Marx’s abstraction constructs a nonexistent concept: lack-
ing a form of appearance or value-form, there is no actually existing ‘human
labour in the abstract’ or ‘identical human labour-power’; these phrases indi-
cate instead a conceptual construct without sensuous reality. In the attribute of
sensuous extension, there are only singular acts of concrete labour.216
The next step in Marx’s argument that both Heinrich and Moseley retrace is
to construct, in terms that follow directly from this initial abstraction, the con-
cept of the quantity of the substance of value in any commodity as such. One of
Marx’s great advances over the classical labour theory of value is to have under-
stood that this quantity cannot consist in the actual concrete time it took to
make any single existing commodity. Marx makes the point simply and mem-
orably in Capital:
This ‘equal human labour’ is an abstraction from actually existing concrete acts
of labour, and as such, it cannot exist in space and time without a form of
218 Here is Moseley: ‘The labour that produces commodities is private independent labour,
and private commodity producers come into contact with each [other] only through the
exchange of their products, and, therefore, the labour expended to produce their com-
modities can only “appear” or manifest itself as the exchange-value of the commodities
they produce. The exchange-value of commodities is the form of appearance of the social
character of the labour expended to produce the commodities’ (2023, p. 178).
219 Moseley 2023, p. 180.
220 Marx 1976, pp. 131, 144, cited in Moseley 2023, pp. 122, 160.
221 Moseley 2023, p. 40, emphasis added. Other examples include: ‘[Marx’s phrase] “quanti-
tatively comparable magnitude” presupposes that each individual commodity contains a
given quantity of objectified human labour (the magnitude of value)’; ‘Sections 1 and 2 of
Chapter 1 presuppose that individual commodities contain definite quantities of objecti-
fied human labour-time, as determined in production’ (Moseley 2023, pp. 68, 70 emphases
added).
Now, the one advantage of Marx’s image is to clearly indicate what it means
to believe in the existence of an object without sensuous qualities, as Moseley
apparently does: it is to believe in phantoms and spectres. Marx’s initial for-
mulation in the 1867 and 1872 editions of Capital of an ‘objectivity’ that can,
as Heinrich writes, ‘no longer be grasped by the senses’, is needlessly confus-
ing. And in fact, this does confuse Moseley, who, despite his repeated denials
that he is not speaking of a single commodity in isolation, constantly reiter-
ates that any commodity ‘possesses’ a quantity of the substance of value, as
if this were the case for any actually existing commodity in isolation from all
222 Moseley 2023, p. 39. Here is Marx: ‘How then is the magnitude of value to be measured?
By means of the “value-forming substance”, the labour, contained in the article. The quan-
tity is measured by its duration, and the labour-time itself is measured on the particular
scale of hours, days, etc.’ (Marx 1976, p. 129, emphasis in original, cited in Moseley 2023,
p. 39).
223 ‘My interpretation does not consider a single commodity by itself. Rather (as I have
emphasised), my interpretation is about a single commodity as a representative of all
commodities (the “elementary form” or the “cell-form”) and the properties that all com-
modities (i.e. each and every commodity) have in common’ (Moseley 2023, pp. 118–19).
224 Heinrich 2021, p. 64, emphasis added.
others.225 This leads Moseley confusingly to claim, for example, that ‘the unob-
servable equal human labour that exists in production appears for the first time
in exchange’.226
Moseley’s critique of Heinrich suffers from a failure clearly to distinguish
the nonexistence of Marx’s conceptual abstractions from actually existing phe-
nomena such as real, singular commodities, the concrete labour that produced
them, and the actually existing price form of their value.227 To be sure, a cer-
tain quantity of value actually exists in the production process of any singular
commodity, for example as the commodified inputs the capitalist purchases for
the production process, whether in the form of constant (machinery and raw
materials) or variable capital (labor power).228 These actually existing values,
however, are merely transmitted as such to the commodity in the production
process; at issue in this debate as I read it is instead whether a newly produced
surplus value obtained via the exploitation of labor power already comes to
exist in the production process. Extrapolating on Heinrich’s reading to Marx’s
discussion of the working day and unpaid work hours in chapter 10 of Capital,
we should say that what exists in the production process on this score are only
unpaid hours of real, concrete labor expended to produce any given commod-
ity; for these to exist as surplus value requires, Heinrich rightly argues, that they
take a value form and go on to achieve their social validation through commod-
ity exchange.
225 ‘Heinrich’s explanation confuses expressing value with possessing value. The coat
expresses the value of the linen only in relation to the linen, but the coat possesses value
on its own, independent of its relation to the linen, as a result of the homogeneous human
labour-power expended to produce the coat’ (Moseley 2023, p. 155, emphasis in original).
226 Moseley 2023, p. 186, emphasis added. Numerous passages in Heinrich’s How to Read Cap-
ital also suffer from a terminological vagueness regarding the existence or non-existence
of the substance of value prior to appearance in a value-form: ‘Commodities have value-
objectivity only in the social relation of one commodity to another – which is why it first
comes to light here. Prior to and outside of this relation, they are mere use-values: they are
on the way to becoming commodities, but far from being commodities’. Heinrich, cited in
Moseley 2023, p. 151, emphasis added.
227 Given this terminological vagueness, Moseley can even (correctly) formulate Heinrich’s
position in the terms I here insist on, only immediately to reject this position: ‘Heinrich’s
interpretation is that abstract human labour does not exist in production, but instead
abstract human labour comes to exist only in exchange’ (Moseley 2023, p. 130, emphasis
added).
228 Marx presumes in his analysis a fully developed capitalist social form, such that, Moseley
writes in Money and Totality, “The means of production in capitalist production are com-
modities, which have been purchased at the beginning of the circuit of money capital,
and which therefore enter the valorisation process with already existing specific prices.”
Moseley, 2017, 141.
229 ‘Abstract human labour, as the substance of commodities’ value, does not emerge on the
basis of the individual commodity but is based on the exchange relation between com-
modities’ (cited in Moseley 2023, p. 117).
230 Heinrich 2021, p. 59.
231 Here is one example among countless similarly fastidious statements by Moseley, each
of which repeats the same point: ‘Marx’s first sentence does not say anything about
an “exchange relation” of two commodities. Instead, Marx’s sentence says “our analy-
sis reduces them”, and “them” clearly refers to “commodities”, and thus “our analysis”
means our analysis of commodities and the value of commodities, not our analysis of the
“exchange relations” of commodities’ (Moseley 2023, p. 154).
232 Moseley 2023, pp. 98, 99. ‘The term “exchange relation”’, Moseley continues, ‘occurs only
11 times in Chapter 1: 5 times in Section 1, 0 times in Section 2, 5 times in Section 3 and
1 time in Section 4. None of these passages defines “exchange relation” as an abstraction
from presupposed acts of exchange between two commodities and money on the market’
(Moseley 2023, p. 99).
The coat and the linen as values, each for itself, were reduced [in the first
section of chapter 1] to objectifications of human labour as such. But this
reduction forgot that neither is in and of itself value-objectivity [Werthge-
genständlichkeit]; they are this only in so far as this objectivity is held in
common [gemeinsam] by them. Outside of their relationship with each
other – the relationship in which they count as equal – neither coat nor
linen possess value-objectivity or objectivity as congelations of human
labour per se. They only possess this social objectivity as a social relation-
ship (in a social relationship).237
Marx only managed to insert a single but crucial sentence into the 1875 French
edition that reflects this auto-critique, while letting stand without clarification
sentences such as that cited above (‘In the production of linen, a particular
quantum of human labour exists in having been expended’), sentences that
continue to confuse astute readers such as Moseley into the present.
That new sentence – the meaning of which in the Ergänzungen Heinrich
and Moseley disagree on (neither Moseley nor Heinrich discuss the actual pub-
lished French rendition) – marks a crucial amendment to Marx’s argument, but
one that Marx fails explicitly to flag as a general position in his text, even in its
more expansive French articulation:
L’égalité de travaux qui diffèrent toto cœlo les uns des autres ne peut con-
sister que dans une abstraction de leur inégalité réelle, que dans la réduc-
tion à leur caractère commun de dépense de force humaine, de travail
humain en général, et c’est l’échange seul qui opère cette réduction en
237 Cited in Moseley 2023, p. 212, emphasis added. Moseley interprets Marx’s ‘as congelations
of human labour’ to imply that this congelation actually exists already in the individual
commodity, when the sentence says just the opposite: that they only ‘possess’ this in social
relationship with other commodities, not individually in isolation from the social network
of exchange.
mettant en présence les uns des autres sur un pied d’égalité les produits
des travaux les plus divers.
The equality of labours that differ entirely one from another can only con-
sist in an abstraction from their real inequality, only in the reduction of
their common character as an expenditure of human force, of human
labour in general, and it is exchange alone that operates this reduction,
by placing the most diverse products of labour in the presence of one
another as equals [in value].238
While Heinrich correctly reads Marx’s ‘opère’ [vollszieht sich, ‘carried out’ in the
German Ergänzungen] to mean that ‘the abstraction of equal human labour
only exists in exchange’, Moseley instead perversely seeks to force the phrase
‘to be consistent with [Marx’s] earlier paragraphs’ (i.e., precisely the text Marx
seeks to correct here) paragraphs that putatively state that, in Moseley’s words,
‘equal human labour exists in production’.239
In fact, however, Marx’s clarification is not yet clear enough: when Marx
writes in the French edition that ‘The equality of labours that differ entirely
one from another can only consist in an abstraction from their real inequality’,
he should have added the obvious implication of this, i.e., that this ‘abstraction
from their real inequality’ results in, precisely and self-evidently, an abstrac-
tion, the nonexistent concept of abstract human labour. To clarify the theo-
retical obscurity that confounds Moseley, and given that his difficult, highly
abstract presentation in Chapter 1 relies upon singular examples (coats, linen)
to help the reader grasp his argument, Marx should have inserted in his text
an analogous clarification to his extremely important note on the difference
between value and exchange-value, which he only came to present clearly in
the 1872 edition: ‘Once we know this, our manner of speaking does no harm;
it serves, rather, as an abbreviation’.240 Once we know that the abstraction of
238 mega ii/7: 55 (my translation). In the original German in the Ergänzungen, Marx writes
more briefly that ‘The reduction of various concrete private acts of labour to this abstrac-
tion of equal human labour is only carried out [or accomplished, vollszieht sich] through
exchange, which actually equates products of different acts of labour with each other’
(‘Die Reduction der verschiednen konkreten Privatarbeiten auf dieses Abstractum gle-
icher menschlicher Arbeit vollzieht sich nur durch den Austausch, welcher Producte ver-
schiedner Arbeiten thatsächlich einander gleichsetzt’). mega ii/6: 41.
239 Moseley 2023, p. 185, emphasis added.
240 Having been inserted already in the 1872 German edition, this crucial moment of self-
clarification therefore found its way into all subsequent editions and translations, and is
thus common knowledge to any attentive reader of Capital the world over: ‘When, at the
equal human labour only exists as a real abstraction in the exchange relation via
its value-form, and is until then a nonexistent concept, our manner of speaking
– for example that ‘In the production of linen, a particular quantum of human
labour exists in having been expended’ – does no harm.
beginning of this chapter, we said in the customary manner that a commodity is both a
use-value and an exchange-value, this was, strictly speaking, wrong. A commodity is a use-
value or object of utility, and a “value”. [… Its] form of manifestation is exchange-value, and
the commodity never has this form when looked at in isolation, but only when it is in a
value-relation or an exchange relation with a second commodity of a different kind. Once
we know this, our manner of speaking does no harm; it serves, rather, as an abbreviation’
(Marx 1976, p. 152).
241 Marx 1976, p. 103. Michael Heinrich points out that Marx’s parallel explicitly and admir-
ingly posits Spinoza on equal terms with Hegel in Marx’s judgement, a point to which I
will return below. Heinrich 2019, p. 331.
(Additions and Changes to the First Volume of Capital).242 Since Marx made
no systematic statement or reflection on this process, it must be reconstructed
immanently from Marx’s text, as I have tried to do here.
What’s more, for all his customary polemical conviction, Marx’s two well-
known statements on his relation to Hegelian dialectic in the 1872 Postface are
quite ambiguous. On the one hand, he famously asserts that due to ‘the mystifi-
cation [Mystifikation] which the dialectic suffers in Hegel’s hands … it must be
inverted [umstülpen], in order to discover the rational kernel within the mysti-
cal shell’, a process of mere inversion that, Althusser famously argued, were it
true, would have left intact the principal Hegelian logical categories (negation,
contradiction, Aufhebung, etc.).243
Instead, in Reading Capital, Althusser merely asserts what I have here tried
to demonstrate: that Marx’s claim fails to do justice to the real transformations
manifest in the process of exposition concretely deployed in the second and
all subsequent editions of Capital, as what Althusser rightly calls ‘the apodictic
character of the order of [Marx’s] theoretical discourse’.244 At the same time,
a few lines before that famous statement, Marx does in fact seem to go much
further in that very direction, asserting unequivocally (though without present-
ing any evidence that would indicate more precisely his meaning) that ‘My
dialectical method is, in its foundations [Grundlage], not only different from
the Hegelian, but exactly opposite [direktes Gegenteil] to it’.245
If by 1872, in the practical process of revision, Marx had transformed his
mode of exposition in the opening chapters of Capital into what I have termed
a method of additive synthesis,246 without ever committing to paper the sys-
tematic analysis of his understanding of method that he never found time to
write, he seems to have done so spontaneously, amply drawing on the resources
of his own genius to construct an original process of materialist critique. That
242 Ergänzungen und Veränderungen zum ersten Band des Kapitals [1871–72], in mega ii/6,
Karl Marx, Das Kapital: Kritik Der Politischen Ökonomie. Erster Band, Hamburg 1872. Berlin:
Dietz Verlag, 1987, pp. 29–32. See Heinrich’s commentary on this text (2021, pp. 375–6).
243 See Althusser 2005, ‘On the Young Marx’.
244 rc, p. 50.
245 Marx 1976, p. 102.
246 The analogy with musical sound synthesis is no mere homonymic: the temporal articu-
lation of timbral singularity through the additive composition of sine waves to construct
complex harmonic overtone sequences might be said to adhere to Marx’s fundamental
(logical) imperative: always to proceed from the most abstract (whether a minimal def-
inition of the capitalist social form or a single pure sine wave) to encompass the fullest
degree of concretion, whether that is the composite body of Capital or the most complex
timbre frames of an ned Synclavier’s synthesis engine.
Marx’s knowledge of law left behind clear traces in his work. Directly legal
arguments are found in a few of his articles for the Rheinische Zeitung,
[and] his Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right from 1843 and some pas-
sages in Capital also demonstrate Marx’s legal knowledge. And last but
not least, in February of 1849 in Cologne, Marx successfully pleaded before
the court twice when the Neue Rheinische Zeitung was charged with
insulting a magistrate and in a further trial for inciting rebellion.247
This is relevant in the present context because this training gave Marx what
Heinrich describes as ‘a reasonably solid (theoretical) training in law’, one
that in addition to his study of logic with Georg Andreas Gabler, for which
he unsurprisingly received a mark of ‘extremely diligent’, would necessarily
have grounded him in the subcategory of positive logic that is legal argumen-
tation.248
Etienne Balibar argues even more strongly that though ‘there remains a
remarkable blindness in the detailed commentaries on Marx’s Capital to the
issue of juridical forms and the function of law in Marx’s analysis’, in fact, ‘juridi-
cal form is key to the understanding of Marx’s reasoning’.249 Balibar shows that
the category of legal subject as property owner is crucial to the entire demon-
strative arc of Capital, from the initial analysis of exchange in chapter Two, to
that of the wage form, and finally that of the accumulation of capital in chap-
ter 24, such that there exists ‘a homology of the juridical form with the value
form’, in the sense that without the category of legal person the process of val-
orisation cannot proceed.250
Second, Günther Schmidt has argued that given Marx’s extensive knowledge
of the works of Aristotle – including the Physics, Metaphysics, and On Genera-
tion and Corruption, to the point of having translated in 1841 sections of On the
Soul – he in fact originally intended to write his doctoral dissertation as a com-
parison of Epicurus not with Democritus, but with Aristotle himself.251 While
there is no direct evidence that Marx studied Aristotle’s Prior and Posterior
Analytics, the works in which Aristotle literally invented logic as a domain of
scientific, philosophical reflection, there is every reason to suppose that given
his training in logic, Marx was familiar with these canonical works as well. In
any case, Aristotle’s positive logic pervades at every moment the philosophical
works that Marx knew intimately, such as the Physics and Metaphysics. Marx’s
respect for Aristotle is, moreover, a constant of his intellectual universe, to the
point that in Capital he will unequivocally name the inventor of the Peripatetic
School, ‘the great investigator who was the first to analyse the value-form, like
so many other forms of thought, society and nature, … the greatest thinker of
Antiquity’.252
Finally – and here the question of influence is both significantly more
obscure but equally crucial to the argument of this book as a whole – there
is the problem of Spinoza and Marx.253 Compared to his extensive engage-
ment with thinkers such as Epicurus, Aristotle, Feuerbach, or Hegel, Marx has
little to say about Spinoza, all of it rather superficial and in passing (though
always positive and admirative). In its generality, Marx’s one theoretically sub-
stantive citation of the author of the Ethics, in a footnote to Capital, (‘These
gentlemen [the vulgar economists] would do well to ponder occasionally over
Spinoza’s “Determinatio est nagatio”’) most likely relays Hegel’s misrepresenta-
tion of Spinoza rather than a substantive engagement with Spinoza himself,
repeating Hegel’s erroneous word order rather than the original (‘determina-
251 Heinrich 2019, pp. 412–15. Charles Barbour has shown that this extensive familiarity with
Aristotle arose in part from Marx’s intensive engagement with post-Aristotelean logic
more generally in the period 1839–1842. Marx did so, Barbour shows, not just in prepa-
ration for writing his dissertation, but with the intention of writing a never-completed
response to the foremost scholar of Aristotelean logic of the time, Adolf Trendelenburg,
and his highly influential 1840 critique of Hegelian logic, Logische Untersuchungen (Bar-
bour, “The Logic Question”). See above, pp. 158–60.
252 Marx 1976, pp. 151, 532.
253 For systematic enquiries into Marx’s relation to Spinoza, none of which, however, even
raises the possibility that Marx’s familiarity with Spinoza may have impacted the epis-
temology and method of exposition of his critique of political economy, see Maximilien
Rubel’s classic article ‘Marx à la rencontre de Spinoza’ (1977); Matheron 1977; and more
recently, Matysik 2023, Chapter 3, ‘When Marx Met Spinoza’, pp. 97–134; Bianchi 2018;
Tosel 2008; Fischbach 2005; Lordon 2010.
tio est negatio’ rather than Spinoza’s ‘determinatio negatio est’).254 For Marx in
this footnote, the phrase ‘Determinatio est negatio’ is taken to refer in general
to ‘Hegelian “contradiction”, which [Marx continues] is the source of all dialec-
tics’, something quite different than its limited application in Spinoza’s letter to
Jelles.255
It would seem that Marx’s other principal reference to Spinoza (‘In oppo-
sition [Gegensatz] to Spinoza, [vulgar economics] believes that “ignorance is
a sufficient reason” [die Unwissenheit ein hinreichender Grund ist]’) is, if any-
thing, even less promising in its vagueness.256 I wish in conclusion, however, to
pause to consider this phrase that does not seem to have merited the attention
of previous commentators on Marx’s relation to Spinoza. It is my conviction
that taken in context, and given the importance Marx seems to attribute to
it judging from the phrase’s repetition from his 1841 dissertation through the
1872 edition of Capital, this seemingly cliched, even throwaway catchphrase in
fact indicates, as a sort of signpost or marker, precisely the additive synthetic
epistemological process that brings Marx’s revisions to Capital in proximity to
Spinoza’s apodictic, positive logic.
In the existing literature on Spinoza’s possible influence on Marx, the focus has
remained unrelentingly limited to questions of the critique of religion and mir-
254 Marx 1976, p. 744. Spinoza’s letter of 2 June 1674 to Jelles, in which the phrase appears, is
not among those transcribed in Marx’s 1841 notebook on Spinoza, similarly indicating that
Marx based his knowledge of the proposition on Hegel’s misreading of Spinoza (mega2
vi.1, Berlin, 1977). In contrast, Marx, unlike Hegel, actually cites Spinoza correctly in the
identical citation in Grundrisse (1973, p. 90). Macherey argues that Hegel’s addition of the
single word ‘omnis’ in his analyses of Spinoza symptomatically transforms a specific, situ-
ated comment on Spinoza’s part into a general proposition on Being as such. See Macherey
2011, Chapter 4, ‘Omnis determinatio est negatio’. Marx also substantively engages with
Spinoza in The Holy Family (1844), but merely to indicate him as a thinker ‘representative
of a rationalist and abstract metaphysical system’ (Bianchi 2018, p. 49; see also Tosel 2008,
p. 141). Marx’s characterisation of Spinozist thought in his pre-1845 texts repeats aspects
of the Hegelian misreading that Macherey has critiqued, for example in the claim that
‘Spinoza’s substance … is metaphysically disguised nature separated from man’ (cited in
Bianchi 2018, p. 50). Bianchi, however, proposes that in arguing against Hegel’s Spinoza,
Marx was in fact targeting Hegelian idealism itself (2018, p. 51).
255 Macherey 2011, p. 162. For Spinoza the determinate figure, the topic of this interjection,
serves to constitute any totality as limited to a subjective point of view, as an actually
existing singularity rather than a nonexistent thing or even substance itself.
256 Marx 1976, p. 422.
acles, freedom of speech, and the autonomy of the political. Bernardo Bianchi
remains squarely within this field of interpretation, noting only that ‘After 1844,
Marx drifts away from Spinoza as well as … the problems relating to the auton-
omy of the political’.257 No commentator to my knowledge has reflected on the
epistemological implications of the statement that ‘ignorance is no argument’,
though there is unanimous consensus that the source of this phrase in the first
volume of Capital is the Appendix to Ethics ip36.258
On at least three occasions spanning his intellectual production, from the
1841 dissertation to the final revisions of Capital, Marx cites Spinoza’s phrase
that ‘ignorance is no argument’.259 In The German Ideology, Marx briefly cites
the phrase to indicate Max Stirner’s ignorance of real human suffering, but
in the case of Marx’s 1841 dissertation, On the Difference between Democritean
and Epicurean Physics, Rubel suggests a far more consequential, epistemolog-
ical dimension, one that I will argue is carried over, amplified, and clarified
when Marx repeats it in Capital. While Marx’s lost Appendix to the Disserta-
tion, judging by the Notes that have survived, addressed potentially Spinozist
themes related to the ttp such as ‘On Individual Immortality’, ‘The Theol-
ogy of Epicurus’ and ‘The Relationship of Man to God’, in the second chap-
ter, Marx writes that ‘Spinoza says that ignorance is no argument’ in order
serenity of thought satisfied in itself, the self-sufficiency that draws its knowl-
edge ex principio interno’.264
Epicurus’ position amounts to the refusal of all supernatural or miraculous
explanations of causality, all teleologies of divine intent, and asserts instead the
adequacy of a physics-based, ‘atomistic’ account of nature. ‘The atom is per-
ceived only through reason’, Marx flatly observes.265 There are no sensations
of atoms from which to construct their concept; instead, Epicurus’ philosoph-
ical project seeks to articulate the rational order of nature, beginning from the
purely theoretical, anti-empiricist concept of the atom and the void, to culmi-
nate in a materialist cosmology. Marx’s Epicurus squarely locates the produc-
tion of knowledge within scientific reflection – as opposed to the extraction
of truth from empirical observation so characteristic of Democritus – as the
positive construction of an adequate intellection of the real. This position,
despite its rudimentary development in the dissertation, nonetheless indicates
a purely Spinozist materialist position, in which the real order of nature finds
conceptual articulation in the attribute of thought; Marx’s reading of the ttp
and Ethics in preparation for the dissertation in all certainty contributed to the
articulation of this epistemological position.
The Spinozist theoretical anti-empiricism of Marx’s first chapter stands in
marked contrast, however, to the negative dialectical logic of its succeeding
sections, the latter deploying a none-too-subtle application of Hegel’s logic
of Reflexionsbestimmung to the Epicurean theory of the atom. If Democri-
tus’ assertion of the necessarily, eternally linear fall of atoms through the void
describes for Marx a realm of pure necessity, Epicurus’ introduction of the con-
cept of their clinamen or swerve, in Marx’s reading, introduces negation not
as the mere external definition of the atom as not-void, but internally, as the
negative unity of its becoming-other, its swerve the theoretical basis of self-
consciousness and the freedom of human action:
264 Marx 1975a, pp. 99, 107, translation modified. The original German can be found in
mega ii, Karl Marx Werke, Artikel Literarische Versuche bis März 1843. Berlin: Dietz Ver-
lag, 1975, pp. 27, 30.
265 Marx 1975a, p. 134. ‘Das Atom, ihr Fundament, nur durch die Vernunft geschaut wird’
(mega ii, p. 49). In the First Notebook on Epicurean Philosophy, Marx observes in more
Hegelian terms that ‘the motion of the atoms is in principle absolute, that is, all empir-
ical conditions in it are sublated [alle empirischen Bedingungen sind in ihr aufgehoben]
…. What is lasting and great in Epicurus is that he gives no preference to conditions over
notions, and tries just as little to save them. For Epicurus the task of philosophy is to prove
that the world and thought are thinkable and possible’ (Marx 1975a, pp. 186, 189, transla-
tion modified). For the German original, see mega iv1, Karl Marx Friedrich Engels Exzerpte
und Notizen bis 1824. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1976, p. 19.
The mode of being which [the atom] has to negate [negiren] is the straight
line. The immediate negation [unmittelbare Negation] of this motion is
another motion, which … is the declination from the straight line …. Epi-
curus objectifies the contradiction [Widerspruch] in the concept of the
atom between essence and existence …. In Epicurus atomistics with all its
contradictions [Widersprüchen] has been carried through and completed
as the natural science of self-consciousness [Selbstbewusstseins].266
Here, the Hegelian logic of the determinations of reflection that would remain
a constant in Marx’s thought through the first edition of Capital already offers
the young Marx the theoretical means to develop an original reinterpretation
of Epicurus’ materialism. The contrast with Marx’s return to Spinoza in chap-
ter 11 of Capital, as we shall see in a moment, could not be greater.
That said, Rubel’s hesitant, passing mention of the importance for the young
Marx of Spinoza’s ‘second genre of knowledge’, that of common notions
[notiones communes], puts us on the trail of the true and penetrating sig-
nificance of Spinoza for Marx’s process of exposition, the final piece in the
puzzle of what I am calling in this book Capital’s Spinozist epistemology. For
while in the dissertation this Spinozism remains superficial, if determinant in
Marx’s argument, by the time of its reappearance in Capital, the reference to
Spinoza, in the context of Marx’s argument in chapter 11, precisely and exact-
ingly indicates what Rubel could only vaguely infer from the 1841 dissertation
and its accompanying notebooks: a full-fledged theoretical reconstruction and
deployment on Marx’s part of what Spinoza called general or common notions,
notions that Marx names the ‘law of motion’ of the capitalist social form. In
other words, taken in the context in which it appears in the eleventh chapter of
Capital (‘The Rate and Mass of Surplus-Value’), in saying that ‘ignorance is not a
sufficient reason’ Marx is not merely pointing to the ‘ignorance’ of the classical
political economists he criticises, but does so in the context of his contrasting
positive elaboration of an adequate mode of knowledge: specifically, the con-
cept of the ‘law’ of the rate and mass of surplus value that it is the remit of
chapter 11 to formulate.
266 Marx 1975a, pp. 112, 125, 146. mega i/1, pp. 36, 44, 58.
267 To my knowledge, while many have repeated the assumption that Marx’s citation refers
to the Appendix of Spinoza’s Ethics Book i, no one, surprisingly, seems to have reflected
on the context in which he inserts this reference in Capital.
268 Marx 1976, p. 421.
269 As the US Bureau of Labor Statistics puts the matter with naïve simplicity, ‘Inputs are any
resources used to create goods and services. Examples of inputs include labour (workers’
time), fuel, materials, buildings, and equipment’ (‘What Are Inputs?’, at https://www.bls
.gov/k12/productivity‑101/content/what‑is‑productivity/what‑are‑inputs.htm.)
270 See Nesbitt 2022, pp. 138–52.
surplus value is, in other words, not an empirical, sensuous thing, but unam-
biguously a Gedankenkonkretum.
I say replaces because Marx must here forcibly return his reader to the high
level of abstraction of the first nine chapters of Capital following the exten-
sive empirical illustration of these concepts in chapter 10 (‘The Working Day’);
equally, however, this initial prompt must be kept in mind in what follows,
because it clearly indicates that the initial presentation of this law stands
in utter distinction from the empiricism of both ‘everyone’ and the classical
economists he will then excoriate midway through the chapter in the passage
discussed above.
This point should not be forgotten when Marx immediately, in the second
paragraph, launches into a discussion of ‘the worker’ and ‘the capitalist’, offer-
ing as well specific numerical quantities of work time (‘6 hours a day’) and
its monetary expression as a specific value (‘3 shillings’) to calculate a ‘specific
mass of surplus-value’.275 How are ‘the worker’ and ‘the capitalist’ different, a
casual reader might ask, from the ‘baker’ or ‘cotton spinner’ whose empiricist
point of view he will condemn just after presenting this law? In fact, it will
shortly become clear – when Marx directly scales his analysis from a single
labour process to the ‘total capital of a society’ (‘for example … the social work-
ing day of ten million hours’) – that they inhabit utterly distinct theoretical
realms: the baker and spinner actually existing, singular examples of produc-
tive labourers with their distinct points of view and lived experiences of the
production and exchange processes, the ‘worker’ and ‘capitalist’ mere theo-
retical, abstract markers or stand-ins, imagistic ciphers of an abstract thought
construct that Marx will call ‘aliquot parts’ of a whole that can be directly scaled
up or down at will.276 Marx thus proceeds, in his third paragraph, to scale his
275 Ibid.
276 Marx 1976, p. 422. Patrick Murray writes that ‘Marx replaces the failed classical theory of
value, which explains individual prices in terms of individual values and individual prof-
its in terms of individual surplus values, with a labour theory of value that holds at the
aggregate level (the level of total capital) and explains subordinate phenomena on that
basis …. Marx revolutionises the classical labour theory of value by making the aliquot
or representative commodity the object of inquiry’ (Murray 2017, pp. 22, 23). This frac-
tional orientation can easily confuse the reader of Capital, however, since Marx repeatedly
frames the rhetoric of his argument in terms of individual examples (of coats, linen, tai-
loring and weaving, or here in chapter 11, bakers and cotton spinners). As discussed above,
Fred Moseley observes in this sense that ‘It is not always clear that Marx’s theory in Vol-
ume i is about the total capital and the total surplus value produced in the economy as
a whole, because the theory is usually illustrated in terms of an individual capital and
even a single, solitary worker …. However, the individual capitals in Marx’s examples rep-
resent the total social capital of the capitalist class as a whole. Individual capitals are not
analysis from aliquot, representative figures of the individual worker and capi-
talist, to address ‘the total value of all the labour-powers the capitalist employs
simultaneously’.277
Marx next examines factors governing the variation on this simple formula
for the production of surplus value: when variable capital invested diminishes
or increases, and when the corresponding rate of surplus value increases or
diminishes, the total mass of surplus value produced will directly vary accord-
ing to these given proportions.278 These variations, Marx insists, nonethe-
less remain governed by absolute ‘limits, which cannot be overcome’, in the
form of both limits to the working day (24 hours) and to reductions in the
number of workers employed (to the theoretical and potentially real limit of
zero).279
All of this combines, in Marx’s various simple, algebraic examples, to indi-
cate the ‘self-evident’ nature of the lrmsv: ‘With a given rate of surplus-
value, and a given value of labour-power, therefore, the masses of surplus-value
produced vary directly as the amounts of the variable capitals advanced’.280
Though Marx’s exposition in volume i to this point has focused on the rel-
ative division of capital into its constant and variable forms, ‘the law just
laid down is not affected by this’. This is the case since it is only the ele-
ment of variable capital, by definition and whatever its relative quantity to
constant capital employed in production, that effects ‘the valorisation pro-
cess performed by the labour-powers which set the means of production in
motion’.281
This final observation thus allows Marx to summarise in natural language
the lrmsv in its simplest form: ‘The masses of value and of surplus-value pro-
duced by different capitals – the value of labour-power being given and its
degree of exploitation being equal – vary directly as the amounts of the vari-
able components of these capitals, i.e. the parts which have been turned into
analysed as separate and distinct real [empirical] capitals, but rather as representatives
and “aliquot parts” of the total social capital’ (Moseley 2017, pp. 45–46). In contrast to the
examples of chapter one, here in chapter 11 Marx will make explicit this fractional scope
of his analysis through the explicit distinction between bakers and cotton spinners on the
one hand, and what he calls ‘the social working day’ as a whole, the overarching frame of
reference for the lrmsv.
277 Marx 1976, p. 417.
278 Marx 1976, p. 419.
279 On the latter point in relation to capitalist slavery, see Nesbitt 2022, pp. 145–50.
280 Marx 1976, p. 420.
281 Marx 1976, p. 421.
living labour-power’.282 Having done so, Marx turns to his critique of both the
common sense of ‘everyone’ as well as the necessary contradictions governing
the ‘vulgar economists’ discussed above.
Now, the epistemological point I wish to make about Marx’s algebraically
simple lrmsv is that on at least eight counts, Marx’s law constitutes a perfect
example of what Spinoza called a common notion, i.e., general concepts or for-
mulae that are, in contrast to imaginary ideas, Spinoza insists, always and in all
cases necessarily adequate. It is quite extraordinary, I think, that both Spinoza,
in propositions 37, 38, and 39 of Ethics ii, and Marx in Capital chapter 11:
1. Reject empirical knowledge as radically and necessarily inadequate;
2. Propose in its place an abstract science of nonexistent things (res singu-
lares non existentes) without sensuous determination;283
3. Emphasise the absolute scalability of this knowledge between aliquot
part and whole;
4. Understand this form of knowledge as relational and proportional as
opposed to the observation-based study of actually existing singular
things;
5. Articulate this form of knowledge as a process of formalisation that mod-
els reality through the power of abstraction …
6. To produce a necessarily and universally adequate mode of knowledge …
7. The nature of which follows a necessary genesis that gradually transitions
from the inadequacy of imaginary, empirical knowledge to the adequacy
of the general, in order to …
8. Constitute the paradigm of a political epistemology as epistemological
commons
In his analysis of Spinoza’s exposition of the concept of ‘notions common to all
humans’ [notiones omnibus hominibus communes], Macherey initially empha-
sises the same distinction Marx makes, described above, between the inade-
quacy of empirical observations and a general notion: while the former are
produced ‘by the chance encounters of bodies, [common notions] differ fun-
damentally from those produced by the mechanisms of perception and imag-
ination, under conditions subject to infinite variations, which prevents their
meaning, always elaborated in a determinate context, in the here and now, to
be extended beyond the moment of their appearance’.284 In contrast, Macherey
282 Ibid.
283 On Macherey’s explication of Spinoza’s crucial and difficult distinction between nonexis-
tent things (idealities) and actually existing singular things (res singulares actu existentes)
in eiip8,9, see above, pp. 53–4
284 Macherey 1997, p. 274.
argues that such notions common to all humans by their very nature escape
from ‘the instability inherent in opinions’ insofar as they possess a fixed and
determinant form that allows for their deployment ‘by all in common’.285
What then is the nature of such common notions? For Spinoza, the cru-
cial distinction between the inadequate, imaginary ideas we necessarily form
from sense impressions, and common notions, is that the latter are ideas not
about any given, actually existing singular thing (such as coats and linen or
bakers and cotton spinners, among Marx’s examples), but about certain quali-
ties common to all things in general. In the wake of Galileo, who died in 1642,
Spinoza’s privileged example in these propositions is that of physical bodies
as such, universally existing in space and following the general laws that gov-
ern their relations. If it is the case that ‘all bodies agree in certain things’286 –
i.e., that aside from their particular existences, they possess common charac-
teristics, which is to say their extension – then they therefore have in common
that ‘they are determinations of extension, and are universally and identically
subject to the same laws of movement and rest’.287
For Spinoza, this common nature is what allows for the development of a
general science of bodies, one that is founded on purely mathematical princi-
ples. The essential characteristic of this scientific understanding of the phys-
ical, material world, Macherey observes, is that it does not ‘take into consid-
eration the existence of any specific body in particular, and is thus completely
abstract’.288 This immediately recalls Marx’s famous defence of the powers of
abstraction for the analysis and critique of political economy: ‘In the analysis
of economic forms neither microscopes nor chemical reagents are of assis-
tance. The power of abstraction must replace both’.289 Like Marx’s scientific
critique of political economy (‘The ultimate aim of this work [i.e., Capital, is]
to reveal the economic law of motion of modern society’), Spinoza’s ‘science’, as
Macherey reads him, ‘determines figures of regularity that, despite the perpet-
ual variations impressed on [actually existing, singular] bodies due to the fact
that they exist en acte, constitute the manifestation of a permanence regarding
which laws can be formulated independently of the existence of any particular
body’.290
Spinoza further specifies a characteristic of common notions, one that
applies not only to physical bodies in extension, but to all actually existing
singular things as such: these common characteristics apply equally and abso-
lutely to the part and whole [quod aeque in parte ac in toto est], and are,
Macherey stresses, completely independent of any distinction between part
and whole, precisely in terms of the scalability that Marx stresses in the exam-
ple of the lrmsv: when considering aliquot, representative parts of a whole
such as the total mass of surplus value rather than actually existing labourers
such as bakers and cotton spinners and their lived experience, the law govern-
ing the rate and mass of surplus value holds absolutely.
This is necessarily the case, since a common notion such as Marx’s lrmsv
represents not actually existing singular things, but relations and proportions,
the nature of which, Macherey notes, ‘remains identical in every dimension
[ordres de grandeur], as long as the rule that defines these relations is sus-
tained’. As such, a common notion informs by this equivalence all ‘composed
and composing’ things, which, in their entirety and universally, constitute rela-
tional systems as singular structures of causality that through formalisation
come to nonexist, and do so independently of the particular conditions of exis-
tence of singular existing things (such as, for Marx, the particular characteris-
tics of baking bread or spinning cotton).291
Now, the astute reader will have noted that in my initial presentation of
chapter 11 of Capital, I skipped over what is perhaps the most striking confir-
mation of my argument that the lrmsv is a Spinozist common notion: Marx’s
graphic formula summarising the law itself in schematic form:292
s
×V
v
S ={ ′
P × aa × n
In fact, this schematic reduction and formalisation of the lrmsv, along with
the paragraphs directly preceding and following it, is absent from both the 1867
and 1872 editions of Capital.293 Retained by Engels in the 1890 ‘definitive’ edi-
tion of Capital, Marx in fact only inserted this formula, along with a number of
abbreviations and clarifications, in his revisions to Roy’s 1875 French transla-
tion. In the third paragraph, for example, he added a second sentence that more
clearly states, at a high degree of abstraction, the additive and scalable nature
of variable capital: ‘Sa valeur [that of the variable capital employed] égale la
valeur moyenne d’une force de travail multipliée par le nombre de ces forces
individuelles ; la grandeur du capital variable est donc proportionnelle au nom-
bre des ouvriers employés’.294 Immediately following the formula, Marx further
emphasises the purely abstract nature of the values it represents: ‘We assume
throughout, not only that the value of an average labour-power is constant, but
that the workers employed by a capitalist are reduced to average workers’.295
The overall tendency of Marx’s final, 1875 revisions to the first paragraphs of
this chapter are clear: simplifying its presentation, while above all emphasis-
ing the scalability of his propositions as well as their purely abstract character.
Now, I find it quite extraordinary that in his proof to eiip37, Spinoza charac-
terises the abstract, general nature of the properties common to all things (i.e.,
293 Schematisation in this sense refers not to the Kantian empiricist application of a category
to sense perception, but instead to the systematic replacement of referential terms in a
proposition by variables (n), while formalisation refers more generally to the establish-
ment of the logical form of a proposition. See Lapointe 2008, p. 29.
294 mega ii7 [1875], Le Capital, Paris, 1872–1875, Dietz Verlag, 1989, p. 257. The English in the
Penguin translation reads: ‘Its value is therefore equal to the average value of one labour-
power multiplied by the number of labour powers employed’ (Marx 1976, p. 417). Marx also
cut out the succeeding sentence from the end of the third paragraph in the 1867 and 1872
editions, presumably because it made much the same point more verbosely: ‘Der Werth
des vorgeschossenen variablen Kapitals ist also gleich dem Durchschnittswerth einer
Arbeitskraft multiplicirt mit der Anzahl der verwandten Arbeitskräfte. Bei gegebnem
Werth der Arbeitskraft wechselt also Werthumfang oder Größe des variablen Kapitals mit
der Masse der angeeigneten Arbeitskräfte oder der Anzahl der gleichzeitig beschäftigten
Arbeiter’ (mega2 ii5 [1867], p. 242; mega2 ii6 [1872], p. 303).
295 Marx 1976, p. 418, emphasis added. ‘Es wird fortwährend unterstellt, nicht nur dass der
Werth einer Durchschnitts-Arbeitskraft konstant ist, sondern dass die von einem Kapital-
isten angewandten Arbeiter auf Durchsnitts-Arbeiter reducirt sind’ (mega2 ii10 [1890],
p. 274). In fact, this sentence, a footnote in the French, replaces in the 1890 addition within
the body text an inconsequential one unique to the French, in which Marx had written:
‘Or, un produit ne change pas de grandeur numérique, quand celle de ses facteurs change
simultanément et en raison inverse’ (mega2 ii7 [1875], Le Capital, 258). An online scan
of the original French 1875 edition can be consulted at https://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/
bpt6k1232830/f1n351.pdf.
In fact, Spinoza argues, common notions, though they do not grasp the essen-
tial nature of singular things (this he reserves to the third, ‘intuitive’ form of
knowledge), are nonetheless necessarily and universally adequate, and as such
constitute an instance of the political epistemology with which this book as a
whole is concerned.
‘Those things that are common to all things and are equally in the part as in
the whole can be conceived only adequately’.298 Aside from the laws govern-
ing the movement and rest of physical bodies, Spinoza also refers to axioms as
common notions, in the sense that they hold for ‘all things that are’ [omnia que
sunt].299 When the apparatus of thought moves in this fashion away from the
empirical consideration of various actually existing things, to construct instead
ideas whose object is the purely abstract relations between things, Macherey
observes,
296 ‘Conceive, if possible, that it does constitute the essence of one particular thing, B. There-
fore, it can neither be nor be conceived without B (Def. 2, ii). But this is contrary to our
hypothesis. Therefore, it does not pertain to B’s essence, nor does it constitute the essence
of any other particular thing’ (eiip37Pr).
297 Macherey 1997, pp. 286–7.
298 eiip38.
299 eip8.
Common notions are absolute and complete ideas, precisely in the sense that
schematisation (via the introduction of variables, A or B, to replace all reference
to actually existing singular things) affords the passage from our inadequate
ideas about the actually existing, empirical things we perceive (like Marx’s bak-
ers and cotton spinners) to our conception of universally and eternally valid
relations (such as Marx’s lrmsv).
This political epistemology of common notions is grounded in what
Macherey terms ‘a dynamic of rational knowledge’, via the perfecting and
emendation of the capacity to grasp the real by means of ideas, in which the
intellect is led ‘from the activity of [sensuous] perception, in which it is at its
most passive, to that of conception, in which it is the most active … passing
from the particular to the general through a progressive process of abstrac-
tion’.301
The common notion as such thus possesses an inherent ethical and political
dimension: ideas that express properties common to all things are as such nec-
essarily ‘common to all humans’, Macherey comments, ‘which is to say that they
compose a common knowledge that can be universally shared’. This common
knowledge, accessible to all humans and necessarily identically conceived by
all who follow this democratic path, thus constitutes ‘the condition for a men-
tal community among all people …. In so far as people form common notions
that are necessarily adequate, they are actually united, and constitute as such
a single intellect and a single body’.302 Macherey insists above all on the real
actuality of this intellectual commons of theoretical practice: ‘In the intellect
of man, whoever he or she may be, there always exist common notions [such
as, I suggested above, a minimal idea of the nature of capitalism such as Marx
expresses in the first sentence of Capital] through which can be established
the forms of their union with other people, which is to say, with the maximum
possible others, and tendentially, with all’.303
greater topography of theory, passing from a latent order (the critique of polit-
ical economy) to a manifest one (Badiou’s reconstruction of abstract logic).2
The insistent recurrence of this process gives the objective and obscure
impression (uncanny on the part of a Marxist) that the structure of the cap-
italist social form can, for Badiou, only be addressed indirectly; in short, that
the various discursive iterations of Badiou’s logics (not at the level of a spu-
rious psychology but through the analysis of real discursive objects) rewrite
Marx’s Capital, but with its charge censored and diminished via its displaced
reinscription within the more abstract terms of post-Cantorean logic.
In these two concluding chapters, I will argue that if 1968 marks the end of
the Althusserian initiative to construct a Marxian, anti-humanist ‘philosophy
of the concept’ (to redeploy Jean Cavaillès’s famous imperative), the Althusse-
rian theoreticist position ended by ’68 nonetheless takes on its purest form as
Badiou’s logical materialism of the mark (in ‘Mark and Lack’ and Concept of
Model), lectures whose oral presentation was itself short-circuited by the event
of May itself. The appearance of Being and Event two decades later in 1988,
in turn, dismisses the materiality of the logical mark to sound the call for an
axiomatic reorientation of philosophy as an ontological materialism of generic
multiplicity, against both empiricism and logicist idealism, including that of
the early Badiou himself.
While this tendency, I will argue in the following chapter, will culminate
in Logics of Worlds, it is already decipherable in Badiou’s 1967 contribution to
Cahiers pour l’Analyse, ‘Mark and Lack: On Zero’. Here, as if in a logician’s dream
of Capital, is that essay’s dense opening paragraph:
Here we find Badiou already moving in silent parallel with Marx: not with the
political Marx of the Communist Manifesto, but with the theorist of the scien-
tific critique of capitalism.
2 Laplanche and Pontalis define ‘Displacement’ as ‘The fact that an idea’s emphasis, interest or
intensity is liable to be detached from it and to pass on to other ideas, which were originally
of little intensity but which are related to the first idea by a chain of associations’ (2018, p. 121).
3 Badiou 2012, p. 159.
4 Marx 1973, pp. 109–21. See also Iñigo Carrera 2013; Nesbitt 2019.
5 Badiou 2012, p. 159.
6 Marx 1973, p. 101. See rc, p. 41.
7 Badiou 2012, p. 165.
ing singular things, but purely atemporal relations.8 In this view, one could say
that Adam Smith certainly produced a scientific, natural language discourse on
political economy, but Marx’s critique reveals that Smith’s analysis is an ideo-
logical representation of the mere forms of appearance of capitalism in their
superficial regularity (as the ‘tendency to truck and barter’).9 In other words,
the putatively self-same concepts of classical political economy are revealed in
Marx’s critique as fetishised forms of appearance of the true objects that only
conceptual critique can produce: the substance of value, abstract labour power
and the general social form of relation that he names the ‘value-form’, and the
like. ‘Nothing here warrants the title of “object” ’, observes Badiou. ‘Here the
thing is null: no inscription can objectify it. Within this space, one finds noth-
ing but reversible functions from system to system, from mark to mark-nothing
but the mechanical dependencies of mechanisms’.10 Badiou’s ultra-formalism
thus radicalises in the mathematically grounded abstraction of nonexistent
idealities, I am arguing, Althusser’s initial reading of Marx’s 1857 Introduc-
tion in Reading Capital, where Althusser famously asserted the fundamentally
conceptual nature of Marx’s project, stressing Marx’s materialist rejection of
empiricism and the destruction of all merely humanist Marxism.11 This rein-
scription of Althusser’s critique then becomes even more pressing in Badiou’s
1968 lectures, The Concept of Model.
The Concept of Model consists of two brief lectures, along with a 2007 Pref-
ace by Badiou written for its reedition.12 These two lectures proceed in three
moments: the first five sections rearticulate Althusser’s critique of Lévi-
Strauss’s combinatory structuralism, rejected as an empiricist idealism, to
which Badiou then appends a similar critique of logical formalism, followed in
conclusion by Badiou’s presentation of his own materialist concept of logical
structure.
Although the text itself is a punctual intervention, one that addresses the
singular epistemological problem that Badiou calls the concept of ‘model’, it
nonetheless allows us, when read in the broader historical perspective Badiou
suggests in his 2007 introduction to the reprint of these lectures, to figure a
broader, three-part typology of this period. Its first moment stretches from
the initiation of the Althusserian philosophy of the concept, from the publi-
cation of For Marx and Reading Capital in 1965 to May ’68, including as well
the journal, Cahier pour l’Analyse that emerged out of the Althusserian project
to specifically develop this conceptual orientation and the articulation of a
philosophy of the concept and the formalisation of conceptual categories.13
This is followed by a second period marked by the retreat from theory into
political militancy (the ‘Red Years’, 1968–89). This is above all the moment
of an in-formal politics, a politique de l’informel, a period in which Foucault
and Deleuze famously invoked, against all universalism, a withdrawal into
local, situated politics – a politics of local situations, problems, and interven-
tions, refusing the overarching attempts to rearticulate the structural determi-
nants of a given social configuration or order that arguably determine both
Marx’s critique of capitalism and the dynamic of twentieth-century Marxism
itself.14
This period of retreat into local politics is followed, according to Badiou’s
chronology, by a third period: at the level of politics, universalism returns as
tragic farce with the triumph of neoliberalism as a putative global destiny, while
at the level of conceptual thought, Badiou bestows on this period (that extends
into the present) a vital determination characterised by the axiomatic orienta-
tion initiated by Being and Event.15
Badiou begins The Concept of Model by reiterating term for term Althusser’s
critique of Lévi-Strauss.16 He first defines empiricism as the (ideological) sci-
entific discourse that articulates the distinction between empirical reality and
theoretical form as a relation of representation, ‘the formal representation of
a given [empirical] object’. Within this ideological figure, Lévi-Strauss’s struc-
tural anthropology is then said (in section 3) to constitute a specific form of this
ideology, one in which
The model, in this empiricist procedure, is no more than the constructed object
that best accounts for, in the sense of representing, the observed facts. ‘To the
question, what is the criterion of this “accounting for” ’, the empiricist observer
has no other response than the circular reasoning of Lévi-Strauss, i.e., ‘the one
that accounts for all the facts’.20
To this critique of Lévi-Strauss, which takes up the first half of Badiou’s
lecture without adding anything substantial to Althusser’s previous critique,
Badiou appends, in his fifth section, a similar critique of logical positivism. In
Badiou’s presentation, the scientific doctrine of logical positivism is not at all
gratuitous, but similarly depends upon a strict correlation between a formal
system and its empirical objects. A formal system, as a system of necessary
deductions, constitutes the accurate expression or representation of its objects,
as ‘the correspondence between the statements of the formal system and the
domain of scientific objects under consideration’. The formal system adheres to
a syntactic regime of constraint at the level of its chain of deductions, without,
however, deriving the materialist necessity that would determine the necessity
of any specific axiomatic orientation.
When Badiou then turns to his own ‘construction of the concept of model’
in the final sections of his talk, it is conspicuous that this rigorous demonstra-
tion of ‘logical materialism’, as he will appropriately name this orientation in
his 2007 Preface, no more attends to its axiomatic starting point then do the
empiricisms of Lévi-Strauss and logical positivism he has just rejected. Badiou’s
2007 auto-critique is spot-on:
What is striking [in the talks comprising Concept of Model] is that of the
two general determinations of the paradigmatic function of mathematics
(the axiomatic decision and the logical constraint of its consequences), it
is the second that receives attention. [In these lectures] the recourse to
the normative script of formal logic is the principal focus, in so far as it
imposes, through the materiality of marks and symbols, a mechanism of
inscription opposed to all empiricist and idealist interpretations.21
At the same time, I would add that this ontological materialism nonetheless
fails to constitute a science of causes in the sense of the materialist critique of
Spinoza or Marx, as Badiou himself seems to sense: ‘the fact that logical struc-
tures are valid for any model only signifies their real vacuity, the fact that they
make possible thinking the transcendental form of different possible localisa-
tions’ in what he will eventually call a ‘world’ (in Logiques des mondes).
While the virtue of this later position, as we shall see in more detail in the
following chapter, is that it limits logic, against all empiricist and idealist ten-
dencies, to the rigorous description or science of the appearance of things in
a world, I will nonetheless argue that it remains, as Badiou himself calls it, a
mere materialism, one that, in the absence of a materialist axiomatic starting
point, holds true only at the level of ontology as generic multiplicity; it is, in
other words, a mere generic materialism that in its utter abstraction ignores the
singular structural logic of any specific world, such as the logic of our world,
the capitalist social form. Before developing this critique of Badiou’s generic
materialism as a logic of worlds in the next chapter, I wish to first take stock
of the real force of Badiou’s post-1988 ontological materialism, since it consti-
tutes a powerful critique of logical idealism such as that of Frege (the object of
Badiou’s explicit critique) and, implicitly, that of Hegelian Absolute Idealism
more generally.
Lacan.27 Badiou has, moreover, admitted that his knowledge of Bolzano’s work
is in fact limited and largely second-hand.28
Badiou’s neglect of Bolzano’s thought is hardly surprising, since the great
Czech-German philosopher’s pioneering and foundational work, in set theory,
in the critique of post-Kantian Idealism and intuitionism, in the semantic for-
malisation of mathematics and logic, in the formal nature of axiomatisation,
his precocious articulation of a realist, mathematics-based platonism a century
before Albert Lautman’s ‘transplatonism’, and in many other fields, remained
little acknowledged and even less studied until quite recently.29 As late as 1993,
Jacques Bouveresse could still decry this ‘historical injustice’ done to ‘the most
gifted and original adversary of German Idealism’.30
Decades before Frege, Husserl, Cantor, Tarski, and Gödel, Bolzano founded
or made possible many of the crucial discoveries of modern analytic philoso-
phy and set theory, innovations for which the former would become famous.
Following the prohibition of his publications and his early retirement to the
Czech countryside, Bolzano’s discoveries remained overlooked after his death
in 1848, and thus the breakthroughs of his major, posthumous works Para-
doxes of the Infinite and Theory of Science were only belatedly recognised
by Cantor and famously celebrated by Husserl in the Philosophical Investiga-
tions.31
Bolzano’s vast and still underexplored body of work announces Badiou’s
thought in a series of crucial dimensions, of which I will briefly indicate three:32
1) Bolzano’s thought remains the most original and decisive critique of post-
Kantian Idealism in the first half of the nineteenth century. While Badiou can-
27 ‘Les noms de cette première modernité [de la pensée du nombre] ne sont pas Proust et
Joyce, ce sont Bolzano, Frege, Cantor, Dedekind, Peano’. Badiou 1990, p. 24. ‘Après que
l’infini eut reçu dans la mathématique un statut clair, grâce à Bolzano, Weierstrass et Can-
tor, il cesse de jouer un rôle dans l’argumentation philosophique’. Badiou 2013b, pp. 256–7.
In English: Badiou 2008. Badiou 2018. See also Bolzano 1950 [1851].
28 Personal communication, New York, 18 October 2017.
29 Badiou 2013a, p. 12.
30 Bouveresse, ‘Préface’, in Laz 1993, p. iv.
31 ‘Bernhard Bolzano’s Wissenschaftslehre, published in 1837, a work which, in its treatment
of the logical ‘theory of elements’, far surpasses everything that world-literature has to
offer in the way of a systematic sketch of logic’. Husserl 2001 [1900], p. 68. See Bolzano
2014; 2011. On Bolzano’s life, see the biographical information in Rusnock and Šebestík
2019. Bolzano publicly articulated as radical a critique of Viennese militarism as was per-
haps possible in his Austro-Hungarian milieu, and it was this in particular that led to the
banning of his publications and his forced early retirement from Charles University.
32 I develop other points at which Bolzano announces Badiou’s thought, for example on the
concept of the infinite, in Nesbitt 2021.
not be said to reject Hegelian dialectical modes of thought entirely, and in fact
has returned repeatedly to interrogate its modalities, it is arguably Bolzano
who initiates a tendency in European philosophy to supplement and com-
plete philosophical investigations with apodictic demonstrations formulated
in the precise, emphatically un-Hegelian mathematical terms of set-based the-
ory. This mode of demonstration culminates in Badiou’s mathematical appara-
tus deployed throughout the three volumes of Being and Event.
While Bolzano’s Theory of Science reiterates and refines the terms of Bol-
zano’s initial critique of post-Kantian Idealism, Jacques Laz has shown that
Bolzano’s 1810 Beiträge zu einer begründeteren Darstellung der Mathematik
[Contributions to an Exposition of Mathematics on a Firmer Basis], written when
Bolzano was only twenty-nine, already sets forth the principal propositions of
his thought.33 Key among these is his systematic critique of Kantian philoso-
phy, attacked at its root via what Bolzano shows to be the contradictory nature
of Kant’s claims for an a priori intuition that would ground the entire project of
the Critique of Pure Reason.34 While the extraordinary brevity of the Appendix
to Bolzano’s Contributions (‘The Kantian Doctrine of the Construction of Con-
cepts by Intuitions’) articulates its powerful critique in a mere eleven dense
and methodically parsed paragraphs,35 elsewhere Bolzano decries more gener-
ally the ‘love of imagistic language’, lack of expressive precision, and reliance
upon ‘analogies, paradoxes, and tautologies’ dominant in the Schellingian and
Hegelian thought of the age.36
Bolzano unequivocally condemns what he views as a catastrophic tendency
of philosophy, ‘the essence of [which] consists in … playing with images and
passing off the slightest superficial analogy between two objects as an iden-
tity’.37 The core of this limitation, Bolzano concludes, is that ‘the thinkers of our
age do not feel themselves in the least subject to … the rules of logic, notably to
the obligation always to state precisely and clearly of what one is speaking, in
what sense one takes this or that word, and then to indicate from what reasons
one affirms this or that thing’.38 Bolzano’s critique proved decisively productive
for his invention of what Jean Cavaillès would famously call a ‘philosophy of the
concept’.39 Badiou can be said in turn to have taken from Cavaillès’ critique a
33 Bolzano 2010.
34 Kant 1998.
35 See Bolzano 2010.
36 Cited in Laz 1993, p. 33.
37 Cited in Laz 1993, pp. 32–3.
38 Cited in Laz 1993, p. 32.
39 Cavaillès 2008. Note that beginning with his critique of Fregean logicism in ‘Meditation 3’
of Being and Event, Badiou decisively rejects the notion of logic as a purely syntactic oper-
ation: ‘Logic is not a formalisation, a syntax, a linguistic apparatus. It is a mathematised
description of possible mathematical universes, under the generic concept of Topos’. Cited
in Hallward 2003, p. 109. I will return to this point below, in reference to Bolzano’s innova-
tive formalisation of axiomatic method. While Cavaillès celebrates, in On Logic, Bolzano’s
rigorous attention to the necessary modalities of adequate, apodictic demonstration, he
nonetheless criticises the ahistorical nature of these conditions, to offer instead a his-
torically developmental concept of adequate demonstration. Hourya Benis Sinaceur has
argued that Cavaillès’ critique of Bolzano indicates a subterranean Hegelianism latent in
Cavaillès’ thought. Sinaceur 2013, pp. 114–16.
40 Thanks to David Rabouin for clarifying this point.
41 On Leibniz’s influence on Bolzano, see Laz 1993, pp. 33–5; and on Bolzano’s reconfigura-
tion and critique of Aristotelean logic, see Laz 1993, pp. 27–30.
42 Cited in Laz 1993, p. 29.
43 Cited in Laz 1993, p. 45.
44 Laz 1993, pp. 46–8.
45 Cited in Rusnock and Šebestík 2019, p. 417.
Bolzano can thus be said to announce not only central features of Badiou’s
thought, but more generally the structuralist analysis of what Marx called
‘social form’ that is the topic of this book as a whole; structuralist analysis,
that is to say, in the quite specific sense in which Louis Althusser and Pierre
Macherey developed it in Reading Capital. Here, Bolzano’s concerted critiques
of intuitionism, psychologism, and empiricism, and above all his concept of
propositions in themselves can be said to second and further develop the
Spinozist critiques that Althusser, Rancière, Macherey, and Balibar deployed
in their readings of Marx’s Capital.
If Althusser and Macherey in particular looked back three hundred years
prior to Spinoza in order to develop their critiques of Hegel and Hegelian
Marxism, it is surely no less plausible to suggest that Bolzano, who developed
the single most rigorous critique of Kantian and Hegelian Idealism prior to
1848, might offer compelling theoretical arguments to further develop this anti-
Hegelian line of thought. Bolzano argued for an objective semantics governing
not subjective, hermeneutic knowledge of objects, but their objective proper-
ties and relations. He inaugurates, this is to say, the affirmation that Badiou will
formalise in 1988 as the governing imperative of Being and Event: that mathe-
matics ‘writes that which, of being itself, is expressible [dicible]’.50 This, Bolzano
argues, implies the independence of these concepts apart from conscious rep-
resentation. Their meaning, he argues, is rigorously objective and independent
from acts of judgement. In fact, I would willingly push this argument even fur-
ther, to suggest that Bolzano can rightly be said to formulate crucial theoretical
resources in the path leading to the Lacanian theory of the symbolic and real,
above all perhaps via his realist, semantic critique of the Kantian thing in itself.
As Badiou writes of Lacan’s notion of the real,
Lacan is not a critic. To be sure, the real differs from reality, which attaches
its regime to knowing. But Lacan immediately says: I don’t mean to say
the real is unknowable. I’m not a Kantian. … Although the real, as distinct
from reality, is exempted from the knowable, which is the essence of real-
ity, the real nevertheless does not end up being the absolute unknowable but
is instead exposed to being demonstrated.51
That said, the explicit referent for Badiou’s critique of idealist ultra-formalism
is not Bolzano, but Frege, a thinker with whom he engages repeatedly across his
work – in ‘Mark and Lack’, in Being and Event, and again in Number and Num-
bers. Already the object of Badiou’s critique in ‘Mark and Lack’, the inventor
of formal logic will become, in both the Meditation Three of Being and Event
and the second chapter of Number and Numbers, the object of a critique of for-
malist idealism that will motivate and justify Badiou’s essential turn from his
initial logicism of 1967–68 to an axiomatic of Being as the pure presentation of
inconsistent multiplicity prior to all logic.
The key moment in the development of Alain Badiou’s thought, the cru-
cial turn is undoubtedly this conceptual decision to reorient ontology around
an axiomatic, anti-logicist, anti-Fregean position. This takes form in Badiou’s
axiomatic displacement and debasement of logical formalism, the destitu-
tion of the entitlement of Logic to legislate over Being classically sought after
by Frege and David Hilbert. Badiou instead relegates logic to an unimpeach-
of, first, the completeness of first-order logic as the predicate calculus – the
proof, in other words, that ‘every consistent formal system has a model’ – along
with Gödel’s proof of the existence of arithmetically true but unprovable state-
ments, the effective separation of the criteria for semantic truth from those
of provability.59 Gödel demonstrates that ‘there are provably unprovable, but
nevertheless true, propositions in any formal system that contains elementary
arithmetic, assuming the system to be consistent’.60
Badiou draws the ontological implication of incompleteness as the desti-
tution of monism with remarkable force: Since given not just Russell’s para-
dox, but above all incompleteness, ‘it is necessary to abandon all hope of
explicitly defining the notion of set, … axiomatisation is required such that
the multiple, left to the implicitness of its counting rule, be delivered without
concept, that is, without implying the being-of-the-one’.61 Even more strongly,
we read in the concluding lines of ‘Meditation Three’ this summation of the
ineluctable ontological conclusion to be drawn from incompleteness: ‘The
power of language does not go so far as to institute the “there is” of the “there
is”. It confines itself to posing that there are some distinctions within the “there
is”’.62
For what, after all, is Zermelo’s axiom of separation if not the restrictive war-
rant of the symbolic to operate critically upon a necessarily prior given in its
merely provisional totality, counted-as-one? Under the aegis of Separation, it
is the case, Badiou tells us, that ‘a property only determines a multiple under the
supposition that there is already a presented multiple’.63 There is always already
a presented multiple in Badiou’s ontological materialism, a generic multiplicity
prior to any counted-as-one. If this is the case, the ontological necessity of Zer-
melo’s axiom, required to save the operations of first-order logic from the proof
of incompleteness, logically necessitates the initiation of any critique from the
prior givenness of a world, as opposed to the idealist engendering of existence
from the loins of logic.
The axiom of separation certifies the absolute necessity that apodictic cri-
tique begin not from the absolute of an esoteric logical demonstration of a
logical structure as a closed, complete system, but, instead, as an ontologi-
cal materialism, from the most universal and immediate, a multiplicity as the
givenness, the il y a, of a generic plurality (for example, of commodities as an
As such, among the most striking features of Being and Event and Number and
Numbers is their reiteration and further development of the association noted
above in ‘Mark and Lack’ and Concept of Model, as the pressing refiguration of
Marx’s critique. Here too, these later texts schematise the logical reduction and
restatement of Marx’s initial derivation of the concept of exchange-value and
the commodity in Chapter One of Capital, Vol. 1. Here is Badiou on Frege: ‘To
say that two concepts are equinumerate is to say that they have the “same quan-
tity”, that their extensions are the same size, abstracting from any consideration
as to what the objects are that fall under those concepts’.67
And here, beside that formal statement of equinumeracy, is a passage from
Marx’s famous presentation of exchange-value in the first chapter of Volume i
of Capital:
Let us take two commodities, such as a coat and 10 yards of linen, and let
the value of the first be twice the value of the second, so that, if 10 yards
of linen = W, the coat = 2W. … Just as, in viewing the coat and the linen
as values, we abstract from their different use-values, so, in the case of the
labour represented by those values, do we disregard the difference between
its useful forms, tailoring and weaving [etc ….]68
The essence of Badiou’s critique is that while Frege’s idealism claims to con-
jure the self-same object – zero, that is – through the pure powers of logic, for
Marx and Badiou both, the thought-object can only be the production of an
entirely secondary operation. Marx calls this process in the 1857 Introduction
the reproduction of the concrete as materialist thought-concrete, while Badiou
names this secondary derivation, more generally, the operation of the count-
as-one.69
5 A Materialist Axiomatic
In what sense then can we say that Marx’s beginning to Capital (‘The wealth
of societies in which the capitalist mode of production prevails appears as an
“an immense collection of commodities”’) constitutes a materialist axiomatic?
It is axiomatic, to begin with, in the minimal sense Lalande gives the term, as
‘a premise considered evident, and taken as true without demonstration by all
those who understand its meaning’.70 Marx chooses as his starting point just
such a ‘premise considered as evident’; he proposes a minimal, true idea, that
all its subjects, he wagers, already possess of the nature of capitalism: that it
appears as the general commodification of things.
Throughout this book, however, I have argued that the first sentence of Cap-
ital furthermore functions in a stronger, logically determinant sense, firstly
that of an axiom as Lalande further defines the concept as ‘every proposition,
in a hypothetico-deductive system … that is not deduced from another, but
which is posed by a decisionary [décisoire] act of thought, at the beginning of a
deduction’.71 This emphasis on the decisionistic aspect is precisely the sense in
which Badiou qualifies axioms, ‘which must’, he argues, ‘be affirmed, taken into
account [assumés], explicit, and which, as such, introduce into every rational
69 One could, I think, follow through nearly every step of this presentation to translate and
formalise Marx’s discursive analysis of exchange-value into Badiou’s more logically ade-
quate form, in which each logical step of derivation is indicated, beginning with the
famous initial postulation of the concept of commodities as given, as pre-existent mate-
rialist fact in the first sentence of Capital: ‘The wealth of societies in which the capitalist
mode of production prevails appears as “an immense collection of commodities” ’ (Marx
1976, p. 125). From this follows the proposition that there are, in fact, commodities that fall
under that concept; this is followed by the extension of the concept of the commodity to
name the set of all commodities; to assert in turn the equinumeracy of all such concepts in
their consistent multiplicity, as differing quantities of use-values that relate to one another
as equivalent exchange-values (1 coat = 2 yards of linen); next the set of concepts that is
the consistent multiplicity of use-values that fall under the concept of equinumeracy, etc.
70 Lalande 2010, p. 105.
71 Lalande 2010, p. 105, emphasis added.
72 Badiou 2007, p. 40. Similarly, Macherey emphasises how Spinoza’s definitions in their
axiomatic contingency forgo ‘all attempts at rhetorical persuasion, since these truths pro-
posed for examination are to take or leave as such, addressed to [the reader’s] completely
free mind, free to pursue – or not – the path they open’, (1998, p. 30).
73 ‘Nothing seems more natural than to begin with ground rent, with landed property, since
this is bound up with the earth, the source of all production and of all being, and with
the first form of production of all more or less settled societies – agriculture. But nothing
would be more erroneous …. Capital is the all-dominating economic power of bourgeois
society. It must form the starting-point as well as the finishing-point, and must be dealt
with before landed property. After both have been examined in particular, their interrela-
tion must be examined’ (Marx 1973, pp. 106, 107).
74 Analogously, Macherey emphasises the determination Spinoza’s initial starting point, the
definition of causa sui, governs the entirety of his ensuing exposition: ‘the concept [of
causa sui] sustains from beginning to end Spinoza’s entire philosophy, which one could
present in a general manner as an effort to explain all things by their causes’ (1998, p. 31).
75 Marx 1976, p. 154. See the previous chapter on this point.
Alain Badiou’s oeuvre sits uneasily astride a bewildering paradox. Badiou re-
peatedly asserts that the single most imposing impediment to our subjective
access to truths, to our finite, yet substantial and materialist participation in the
infinite, is the tyrannical domination of global social relations and subjectivity
by the economic rationality of capitalism. In Number and Numbers, he writes:
‘Number governs the economy; and there, without a doubt, we find … the
“determination in the last instance” of its supremacy’.1 Similarly, in one of his
most recent books, Happiness, he tells us that the good and real life, ‘la vraie vie
absente’ as Rimbaud writes in Une saison en enfer, is systematically reduced in
the world of global capitalism to the specious freedom of consumerist choice:
‘Freedom is coded or precoded in the infinite shimmer of commodity produc-
tion and in what monetary abstraction institutes on that basis’.2 In the face of
this overdetermined and seemingly universal untruth, the name Badiou has
steadfastly maintained to indicate the political dimension of the true life, is, of
course, the ‘Idea of Communism’.
And yet, for all that, one could assert with little exaggeration that Badiou’s
engagement with Marx’s critique of political economy is a veritable empty
set. Badiou’s repeated, sustained, admiring and attentive engagement with this
great thinker is, in other words, addressed almost univocally to the political
Marx, the Marx of the Communist Manifesto and The Civil War in France. But if
capitalism constitutes the dominant logic of our untrue world, and not merely
a passing epiphenomenon, how can a reader hope to formalise the logic of
the true life, life subtracted from the reign of commodity fetishism, without
a systematic, formal construction of the categories and logic of the world of
capitalism?
Like Adorno’s superficial comments in Negative Dialectics on capitalism as
universal fungibility, Badiou’s explicit pronouncements on capitalism are not
false, but remain manifestly inadequate to the real complexity of their object,
betraying only the vaguest sense of the complexity of the logic governing the
valorisation of value, the many laws of the tendencies determining production,
circulation, exchange, and accumulation that Marx painstakingly develops. We
1 Badiou 2008, p. 3.
2 Badiou 2019, p. 43.
know as much as Badiou tells us about the logic of capitalism from even the first
sentence of Capital volume one: that the form of appearance of social relations
in which the capitalist form of production predominates is that of universal
commodification and exchange.3
This disinterest is of course odd coming from Badiou, who devotes metic-
ulous care precisely to the formalisation of his primary objects of inquiry in
systematic, philosophical and mathematical-logical terms. But while this is the
case, for example in Logics of Worlds, it is nonetheless striking that the worlds in
question there, along with the events that break free from them remain either
entirely generic, worlds as such, events as such, or else constitute decidedly
minor, even ‘baroque’ subsets of what Marx called the general social forms
(gesellschaftliche Formen) that govern social existence in any specific histori-
cal domain and period:
then, this means nothing more, though nothing less, than subjecting Logics
of Worlds to a Marxian torsion: what Badiou has neglected, Marx has in fact
already accomplished (with his own specific formal, conceptual, and discur-
sive means): the systematic, synthetic demonstration of the necessary forms of
appearance of commodities in the capitalist social form.
While Badiou fully grasps the essential nature of formal demonstration for
Lacan, his 1994–95 seminars circle around, and yet nonetheless betray a symp-
tomatic repression or blindness regarding Marx’s critique of political economy.
In these lectures, Badiou explicitly names Marx alongside Lacan as occupying a
very particular status in the pantheon of anti-philosophy, insofar as both Marx
and Lacan mount a critique of philosophy and truth in the name of science,
rather than Nietzsche’s poetic utterances or Wittgenstein’s language games.
Despite this crucial insight, Badiou nonetheless remains symptomatically deaf
in these lectures, as elsewhere, to Marx’s scientific discourse – to Capital, that
is to say.
This repression results in a highly problematic suturing in Badiou’s dis-
course, a suturing of the ideological imaginary to a politics of the real. In sup-
pressing any consideration of scientific discourse – whether of Marx’s Capital
or even Lacan’s systematic demonstration in the 1950s of the structure of the
unconscious, a demonstration that Badiou suggestively names a ‘hyperstruc-
tural axiomatic’7 – Badiou enacts a short-circuiting of analytical critique. The
result of this suture as theoretical short-circuit is that politics in Badiou’s Lacan
seminar lacks any consequential formalisation of the categorial structure of
capitalism understood as social form, as the value-forms of abstract labour, that
is to say. In its absence, politics can take the form not of a true act, but only and
ever the mere acting-out of ideological fantasy.
This becomes eminently clear in what is for me the key passage in the entire
seminar. Here is Badiou’s citation from Lacan’s Radiophonie:
What Marxism has shown by its actual revolution: that there’s no progress
to be expected from truth, nor any well-being, but only the shift from
imaginary impotence to the impossible, which proves to be the real by
being grounded only in logic: in other words, where I claim the uncon-
scious is located, but not so as to say that the logic of this shift shouldn’t
hasten the act.8
Badiou’s commentary of this passage is revealing, both in what it says and does
not say:
The first point to note in Lacan’s original statement is his indication of Marx’s
refusal of ‘truth’ and ‘well-being’. This formulation reiterates Lacan’s post-May
’68 rejection of traditional, Leninist Marxism, as both a moralism of the prole-
tariat as the universal class, and Bolshevism as a mere programmatic redistribu-
tionism of wealth. It is Lacan’s rejection of the Leninist misreading of Marx’s
critique, the reduction of the critique of political economy to an ideological
moralism of the working class in the form of a politicised redistribution of
the wealth of production, in short, Left Ricardianism.10 Leninist Left Ricardian-
ism ignores Marx’s systematic demonstration of the laws of the tendencies of
capitalism as a structure and social form, while the mere superficial forms of
appearance of modes of market exchange become the target of political redis-
tributionism.
8 Jacques Lacan, ‘Radiophonie’, cited in Badiou 2018a, p. 155. Note the tortuous, ambivalent
grammar and tense structure of Lacan’s original phrasing: ‘Ce que le marxisme a démon-
tré par sa révolution effective: qu’il n’y a nul progrès à attendre de la vérité ni de bien-être,
mais seulement le virage de l’impuissance imaginaire à l’impossible qui s’avère d’être le
réel à ne se fonder qu’en logique: soit là où j’avertis que l’inconscient siège, mais pas pour
dire que la logique de ce virage n’ait pas à se hâter de l’acte’ (Lacan, cited in Badiou 2013b,
p. 155).
9 Badiou 2018a, p. 132, my emphasis.
10 This programme is encapsulated by the famous Leninist slogan ‘Communism is Soviet
power plus the electrification of the whole country’, the redistribution, that is to say, of
the wealth of production under the directives of the dictatorship of the proletariat, while
leaving untouched, and even expanding as a general productivist imperative, the general
social form that to this day demands the endless valorisation of value.
It is clear from his many disparaging comments on the proletariat and pro-
letarian politics after May ’68, a number of which Badiou cites in the course
of the seminar, that Lacan discounted all mythification of the proletariat as
ideological, as what he calls here the ‘impotent imaginary’. Virtually no atten-
tion, including Badiou’s presentation, however, has been devoted to a number
of brief but incisive comments Lacan makes on the formal logical structure of
Marx’s analysis in Capital in the seminars from the 1950s, precisely the period
when Lacan was elaborating his own systematic formalisation of the symbolic
structure of the unconscious. That said, Badiou rightly reads Lacan as here, in
the wake of May ’68, affirming in place of all utopian ‘philosophical reveries
on the good state and good society’ the systematic analysis of the structure
of capitalism. The point though is that this work, both Lacan reading Capital
and Lacan articulating his own structural demonstration of the nature of the
unconscious, had occurred long before, in the 1950s seminars, a period of his
thought Badiou studiously ignores in these seminars.
In this passage, Badiou reads in Lacan’s assertion a rejection of philoso-
phy (‘no clamor of being or nothingness’), revealingly identifying Marx as an
anti-philosopher of the same stripe as Lacan himself. In this vein, in order
to analyse Lacan’s assertion that philosophy merely plugs the hole of politics,
Badiou had reminded his listeners of Marx’s famous taking leave of philoso-
phy in the eleventh thesis on Feuerbach: ‘Philosophers have only interpreted
the world; the point is to change it’. While this disparagement of philosophy
and truth casts both Lacan and Marx as anti-philosophers, they are, as Badiou
points out regarding Lacan, different from all others in that for both, the rejec-
tion of philosophies of truth is enacted in the name of the rigour of scientific,
apodictic demonstration; for Lacan, the demonstration of the structure of the
unconscious, for Marx, the demonstration of the structure of capitalism.11
11 In articulating his critique of Freudian Ego-psychology, Lacan had striven to give a mate-
rialist turn to the notion of the symbolic, one that draws it into more direct proximity to
Marx’s Spinozist, materialist dialectic. In his 1954 Seminar ii, Lacan displaced the process
of signification from the intentionality of a subject, to argue instead that the figures of
machine language (cybernetics) offered a perfect illustration of the function of the Sym-
bolic. Lacan there reduces meaning (le sens) to the logical assemblage and concatenation
of signs, the purely formal relation of logical marks, such that Lacan can assert that ‘the
symbolic world is the world of the machine’ (Lacan 1991, p. 47). The symbolic, as Lacan
formulated it at this point, is understood to constitute an asubjective system of codes that
are supported, in Lacan’s example, by the materiality of computing (rather than the inten-
tionality of an ego). In this view, the Lacanian symbolic would constitute the asubjective
system of meaning into which we are thrown, to be interpellated as subjects of Capital.
The real is the remainder of the disjunction between the knowable and
the unknowable. Here we take the measure of the anti-dialectical dimen-
sion of every anti-philosophy: the point of access to the real cannot be
reached negatively. As compared with knowable reality, no negation pro-
cedure provides any access to the real.14
12 Lacan, ‘Radiophonie’, cited in Badiou 2018a, p. 151. ‘Ainsi le réel se distingue de la réalité.
Ce, pas pour dire qu’il soit inconnaissable, mais qu’il n’y a pas question de s’y connaître,
mais de le démontrer’ (Lacan, cited in Badiou 2013b, p. 178).
13 Roudinesco 1997, pp. 52–4.
14 Badiou 2018a, p. 152.
in the notes and manuscripts of the 1860s and 70s: there, what Jacques Bidet
has called various Hegelian theoretical impediments (the identity and non-
identity of production and consumption, for example, or the merely apparent
contradiction between the exchange of equivalents and the realisation of sur-
plus value) are removed and in their place Marx develops, or tends increasingly
to develop in his unfinished masterpiece, the full relational complexity of the
laws of the tendencies and counter-tendencies as they determine the increase
in the organic composition of capital: not the mere falsity, but the absolute
necessity governing the phenomenal, fetishistic forms of appearance of cap-
ital (profit, rent, finance, for example).
Adequate knowledge, knowledge of both the general laws governing the
unconscious as well as the essence of any singular case, governs Lacan’s under-
standing of analysis. While in the Écrits and seminars Lacan develops a sys-
tematic exposition of the structure of the unconscious, it is no accident that
we are left, as Badiou laments toward the end of his seminar, without a the-
ory of the act. For the analytic act occurs on the register of Spinoza’s third,
intuitive mode of knowledge, as the knowledge of the singular essence of any
given case. We cannot know what to do in the case of a given, real analy-
sis, no matter how adequate our knowledge of the laws governing the struc-
ture of the unconscious may be. We can only approach the real of a given
subject via an adequate understanding of the singular essence of that case,
a process that indeed requires, along with the scientific mastery of general
laws, an improvisational genius attendant to Spinoza’s third genre of knowl-
edge.15
Badiou’s commentary is revealing: ‘Although the real, as distinct from reality,
is exempted from the knowable, which is the essence of reality, the real never-
theless does not end up being the absolute unknowable but is instead exposed
to being demonstrated’.16 ‘Demonstration’ is arguably the key epistemologi-
cal concept in the French tradition from Cavaillès and Koyré to Althusser and
Badiou himself. Beyond the knowable and the unknowable, lies not the will
Let me restate in the most deliberate terms the paradox that determines the
limits of Badiou’s philosophical and political critique: On the one hand, Badiou
clearly and repeatedly states the obvious, that the overarching and predom-
inant form of contemporary global social relations is, quite simply, capital-
ism. Most recently, for example, Badiou has repeated this in the form of an
axiomatic truism: ‘Allow me to begin … from a perfectly banal conviction:
the dominant socio-economic structure, which is today in place at a global
scale, is capitalism. Everyone, or nearly so, agrees’.22 Who could disagree? On
the other hand, while I have argued above that the corresponding absence
of any concrete analysis of the capitalist social form on Badiou’s part occa-
sionally, as in the Lacan seminars, reaches symptomatic proportions, the one
moment where one would most expect such an engagement with ‘the dom-
inant socio-economic structure’ that governs the contemporary world is pre-
cisely in Badiou’s second magnum opus, Logics of Worlds. Instead, in the vast
complexity of its 638 pages comprising seven books and dozens of chapters,
‘Qu’en est-il de la logique?’, ‘What then of logic?’ Badiou asks in his theoretical
prolegomenon to Logics of Worlds, the 1998 Court traité d’ontologie transitoire.25
To answer this question will require that Badiou reconceive the ontological sta-
tus of logic – this is the project of the Short Treatise – which will then allow him
to deploy this new, categorial logic of the forms of appearance of things in any
given world in Logics of Worlds. Badiou is forced to turn to the problematic sta-
tus of logic in the wake of Being and Event because, he argues, that book left
unaddressed a crucial aspect of any ontology: the being-there, existence, and
forms of appearance of beings that manifest themselves in any determinate
situation:
To ‘establish the possibility of the logic of existence’, Badiou first steps back in
the Short Treatise to condense the problem of logic in the form of an axiomatic
decision between ‘Plato or Aristotle’.27 Either logic remains integrally linked to
the Idea of mathematical truths, as it does for Plato, he argues, or, in the case of
Aristotle, ‘thought is the [mere] construction of an adequate descriptive frame-
work’, the weaving together, in the form of demonstrations that construct a
‘purely ideal’ set of admissible consecutions, an aesthetic ‘art of calculation’.28
In Badiou’s reading, Aristotle’s logic remains ontologically determined (‘For
Aristotle, ontology prescribes logic’) in a manner analogous to that of Frege,
whom (as discussed in the previous chapter) Badiou had criticised in the cru-
cial Meditation 3 of Being and Event.
Badiou’s initial presentation would seem to relegate Aristotelean logic to the
dustbin of the history of philosophy, but in fact, surprisingly (and crucially in
the case of Marx, for whom Aristotle, not Plato, stands as ‘the greatest thinker
of Antiquity’29), this refoundation of logic as a categorial science of appear-
This plurality of logics that Badiou will formalise in Logics of Worlds is not only
a necessary characteristic of any adequate materialist logic since Cantor, but,
I would add, indicates the relevance of a categorial logic to Marx’s critique of
political economy. Any world and its attendant logic of the existence of beings
must, Badiou argues, necessarily be local and contingent; there exists, Marx
argues analogously, no overarching ontology or anthropology of production,
labour, or commodities and their value as such, understood transhistorically;
each of these and other categories of political economy always necessarily exist
within a historically and conceptually distinct ‘social form’ (gesellschaftlich
Form) (feudalism, capitalism, communism, etc.).32
of modern social life by means of the categories of his mature critique. … A categorial
reinterpretation, therefore, must focus on Marx’s distinction between value and material
wealth; it must show that value is not essentially a market category in his analysis, and
that the “law of value” is not simply one of general economic equilibrium’. Postone 1993,
pp. 17, 123.
33 Badiou 2006, p. 113, translation modified.
34 ‘For a long time I had believed this superseding of Platonism involved a destitution of for-
mal logic as the royal path by which we have access to rational languages. Accordingly, and
so deeply French in this respect, I rallied to the suspicion that, in the minds of Poincaré
and Brunschvicg, was cast upon what they called “logistics” ’. Badiou 2006, pp. 159–60.
35 Badiou defines appearance as follows: ‘what links a being to the constraint of a local or sit-
uated exposure of its manifold-being we will call the “appearing” of this being [l’apparaître
de cet étant]’. Badiou 2006, p. 162, translation modified.
36 Badiou restates this Hegelian point categorically and without demonstration, but, against
both Kant and Hegel, in the form of an asubjective phenomenology: ‘It is the being of the
existent to appear [Il est de l’être de l’étant d’apparaître], insofar as the totality of Being does
not exist. … Appearing in no way depends on space or time, or more generally on any tran-
scendental field whatsoever. It does not depend on a subject whose constitution would
be presupposed. The manifold of beings [L’étant-multiple] does not appear for a subject.
Instead, it is rather the essence of a being to appear as soon as, unlocalizable within the
whole, it must assert the value of its being-multiple [ fasse valoir son être-multiple] from
the point of view of a non-whole’. Ibid., translation modified.
world can both be pure, inconsistent multiplicity (as Being and Event had
described), as well as intrinsically determined as the existence of beings and
their attendant and necessary forms of appearance. This affirmation of the
strict equivalence of logic and appearance then becomes a shibboleth in Logics
of Worlds (‘“Logic” and “appearance” are one and the same thing’) such that for
Badiou the compass of any given logic, as it governs the existence of things in
any singular world as such (rather than a particular world or social form such
as capitalism), remains strictly limited to the laws that determine the ‘cohesion
of appearing’.37
37 Badiou 2009, pp. 100–1. ‘We are speaking here of any appearing whatsoever in any world
whatsoever. In other words, our operational phenomenology identifies the condition of
possibility for the worldliness of a world, or the logic of the localisation for the being-
there of any being whatever’. Badiou 2009, p. 102.
38 Badiou 2009, p. 95.
39 Badiou 2009, p. 94. This ‘Greater Logic’ Badiou distinguishes from ‘ordinary logic, [i.e.]
the formal calculation of propositions and predicates’ which he considers a mere subset
of Greater Logic as such. Badiou 2009, p. 173.
It is thus the task of Logics’ Greater Logic to set forth this ‘logical machinery’ in
the form of a novel series of concepts or ‘logical operators’, the functions that
provide any world with its singular coherent forms of appearance, the most
important of which for this task is what Badiou names, after Kant, the ‘tran-
scendental’.41
Reasserting in the wake of Russell’s paradox the inexistence of totality as a
necessary and governing condition of any contemporary materialist logic, Log-
ics analyses both worlds and their attendant logics in their plurality.42 One of
the few significant differences between the refoundation of logic in the Short
Treatise and its systematic exposition in Logics is a terminological one. Where
the Short Treatise spoke ambiguously of multiple ‘universes’, in Logics Badiou
reserves this term to indicate not a world but only the inexistence of the Whole
figured as an empty set or void (le vide).43 In its place, he substitutes the more
precise term of ‘world’, and crucially indicates by this not a material, exten-
sive space to be filled with beings, but instead only the governing logic of that
world.44 This is to formalise the concept of world in the order of thought, to
grasp the real structuration that allows for the manifestation of objects as they
appear in sensuous lived experience.
It is the concept of the transcendental that then enables Badiou to pass, log-
ically, from the inconsistency of any set in its abstract, ‘neutral’ multiplicity, to
account for the existential consistency of any object in a given world. Badiou
develops this process in four steps, steps that correspond, in the abstract,
to Marx’s initial and familiar demonstration of the basic categories of the
commodity form in the first three chapters of Capital: use-value, exchange-
value, value as such and its substance (abstract labour), along with the nec-
essary form of appearance of any commodity, the price-form. These steps,
given their high degree of abstraction in Logics of Worlds, can be rapidly sum-
marised.
Badiou’s demonstration sets off from the ontological standpoint of Being
and Event, and its description of the abstract multiplicity of the elements of
any set in its bare neutrality.45 To this corresponds Marx’s concept of the com-
modity’s use-value: every commodity possesses, and must possess if it is to be
sold, its singular identity. The set of all commodities in the capitalist social
form consists of an infinite variety of things, each of which – at this general
level of abstraction of use-values as such – exists in its singularity, unique unto
itself, in its abstract nature as use-value devoid of any systematic relation to
other commodities, each existing in sheer externality to all others within this
set. ‘The commodity is, first of all’, Marx writes, ‘an external object, a thing
which through its qualities satisfies human needs of whatever kind’.46 The set of
commodities taken solely as use-values refers each use-value to its singular pos-
session of any given quality whatsoever, the only requirement being the most
abstract one, that a commodity in fact have some use-value of whatever kind
(lest it be unsellable, and thus, in the capitalist social form, worthless). Were
we to reproduce capitalism analytically in this fashion as a structured totality
of the Symbolic, a Badiouian rearticulation of the opening sentence of Capital
might thus read: ‘The wealth of a society subject to the logic of the world of cap-
italism appears as a consistent multiplicity of commodities’. To posit being as
the abstract multiplicity of the objects in any world entails for Logics of Worlds
no more than a passing reference to Being and Event (‘A multiple is only identi-
cal to itself, and it is a law of being-qua-being’).47 Marx similarly spends a mere
three paragraphs analysing the use-value of commodities.
45 To initiate his Greater Logic, Badiou explicitly invokes this starting point: ‘Previously, I
identified [in Being and Event] situations (worlds) with their strict multiple-neutrality.
I now [in Logics of Worlds] also envisage them as the site of the being-there of beings’.
Badiou 2009, p. 99.
46 Marx 1976, p. 125.
47 Badiou 2009, p. 155.
48 Heinrich analyses in detail the various levels of abstraction in Marx’s presentation across
the initial chapters of Capital, pointing out for example that in Chapter One (which I am
discussing here), ‘Marx is analysing a capitalistically produced commodity, which is nor-
mally exchanged for money, but he is doing so initially not only in abstraction from capital
but also in abstraction from money [as well as from the human subjects that exchange
commodities]. For that reason, Marx does not yet mention prices. The relation between
the money price that we are familiar with in everyday life and exchange-value still has to
be explained. … The object of inquiry, the “commodity”, is not simply drawn from experi-
ence. Instead, it is constructed, by means of abstraction’. Heinrich 2021, p. 53.
49 Badiou 2009, p. 118.
50 Badiou 2009, p. 119.
But what are the values of the function of appearing? What measures the
degree of identity between two appearances of multiplicities? Here too
there is no general or totalising answer. The scale of evaluation of appear-
ing, and thus the logic of a world, depends on the singularity of that world
itself. What we can say is that in every world such a scale exists, and it is
this scale that we call the transcendental.56
54 ‘The busiest streets of London’, Marx observed matter of factly in the 1859 ‘Contribution
to the Critique of Political Economy’, ‘are crowded with shops whose show cases display
all the riches of the world, Indian shawls, American revolvers, Chinese porcelain, Parisian
corsets, furs from Russia and spices from the tropics, but all of these worldly things bear
odious, white paper labels with Arabic numerals and then laconic symbols £ s. d. This
is how commodities are presented in circulation’. Cited in Murray 2017, p. 471. See Hein-
rich 2021, pp. 92–143 for an extraordinarily meticulous, word-by-word analysis of Marx’s
demonstration of the logical and materialist necessity governing Marx’s monetary labour
theory of value.
55 ‘How, then, is the magnitude of this value to be measured? By means of the quantity of
the “value-forming substance”, the labour, contained in the article … The labour that forms
the substance of value is equal human labour, the expenditure of identical human labour-
power’. Marx 1976, p. 129.
56 Badiou 2009, p. 156.
Translating Badiou’s jargon to Marx’s analysis, we can say that the quantitative
degree of strength of an object, what Marx calls a commodity’s exchange-value,
is the monetary form of appearance of the substance of value of that commod-
ity, what Badiou terms the scale of values inhering in any world. In capitalism,
this scale is simply the price or exchange-value of any commodity.
Capitalist society, Marx argues, is that specific historical epoch in which
every thing and relation that counts as a value must bear a monetary price.
‘In this form’, Marx concludes, ‘when they are all counted as comparable with
the [general equivalent, money], all commodities appear not only as qualita-
tively equal, as values in general, but also as values of quantitatively comparable
magnitude’. Any commodity, under the general, monetary form of value, can
thus relate to any other through its equation with the universal equivalent: x
(quantity) of (any given commodity) a = $1. This, the general capitalist form
of appearance of value, is quite simply the price form: in Marx’s example, ‘20
yards of linen = 2£’.57
Here we should note that Badiou furthermore argues, again analogously to
Marx, that the existence of the things composing any world forms a relational
system; no single thing (such as a commodity) can exist on its own. Rather, the
logic of the necessary forms of appearance of things in a world necessitates a
relational order: ‘What is measured or evaluated by the transcendental organ-
isation of a world is in fact the degree of intensity of the difference of appear-
ance of two beings in this world, and not an intensity of appearance considered
[ontologically] “in itself”’.58 Badiou’s transcendental logic of appearance of any
world demands that each thing that appears in that world do so in relation to
all other things; the intensity of appearance of one thing must be relational,
‘measured by the intensity of appearance of one of them’.59 This ‘conjunction’,
Badiou states, is ‘carried’ by one of the two things in relation. The parallelism
with Marx’s analysis is here as well uncanny: in Marx’s derivation of the neces-
sity of the price form of appearance of any commodity in the capitalist social
form, he famously begins by defining exchange-value as a necessarily relational
determination.
While Badiou’s abstract point can be briefly stated as such, Marx’s more
complex analysis of the relational nature of the commodity can be summarised
in four crucial steps of his argument. In the famous opening sentence of Cap-
ital, Marx chooses to begin his demonstration with an axiomatic declaration
of the nature of the capitalist social form: ‘The wealth of societies in which
Badiou’s abstract summary of the relational nature of any system of the tran-
scendental valuations governing the strength of appearance of the objects in a
world constitutes, therefore, a precise reformulation of Marx’s analysis of the
systematic logic governing the forms of appearance of commodities in the cap-
italist social form. ‘The transcendental values’, Badiou concludes,
The logic of the forms of appearance of existence in any world, Badiou argues,
can be succinctly summarised at this high level of abstraction with only three
basic operations: 1) the determination of a minimum value for any thing to
appear in that world (in capitalism, that a commodity bear a numerical price);
2) that there exist the possibility of conjoining the degrees of value of any
two objects (in capitalism, the determination of what Marx calls a relative
exchange-value between two commodities); and 3) the possibility of a ‘global
synthesis’ of these values among a specific number of multiples (in capitalism,
the necessity of the monetary price form to allow for the universal exchange-
ability of any and all commodities one for another). The degree of congruence
between Badiou’s abstract analysis of the logics of worlds and Marx’s analysis
of the necessity governing the forms of appearance of commodities in the cap-
italist social form is uncanny, all the more so as judging at least by his writings,
Badiou seems never to have closely studied Marx’s synthetic demonstration of
this logic in the third chapter of Capital.
This book has argued that Marx’s demonstration of the nature of value in the
capitalist social form, of its forms of appearance (above all as money), and
of the essence of surplus value, are not derived from obscure metaphysical
elucubrations (as Marx’s academic and empiricist critics have often asserted),
nor from the theoretical reversals of a negative-dialectical (Hegelian) logic.69
Marx’s theory is at heart a materialist logic of the real process of the circuit of
capital as it passes, without logical negation, through its various forms. Marx
was not improvising when he methodically, revision after revision, constructed
the various drafts of Capital from 1861 to 1883, but instead sought the most
adequate (logical) form of demonstration to present the conceptual order of
the capitalist social form. Though he certainly continued to develop and fine
tune the diverse categories of his analysis till his last days, he had already con-
ducted his fundamental ‘inquiry’ into the structure of the capitalist social form
to arrive at his central notion of the monetary labour theory of value in the final
pages of the Grundrisse notebooks.70 Among the greatest accomplishments of
Capital, in this view, is to have constructed for readers the real, dynamic logic
of the capitalist social form, the immanent logic of a social form, to reveal, as
Marx proudly proclaims in his first Preface from 1867, ‘the natural laws of cap-
italist production, … these tendencies winning their way through and working
themselves out with iron necessity’.71
If capitalism appears as the general accumulation of commodities, and if
its predominant form of social relations is that of the exchange of commodi-
ties, then, Marx argues, a series of necessary consequences immediately follow.
What Marx will argue, in the limpid terms of a synthetic logical demonstration,
is that given this predominance, abstract labour, the substance of value, must
take a monetary form of appearance. To do so, he takes his reader step by step
to discover the essential nature of the commodity form. From the dual nature
of the commodity as both use- and exchange-value to the substance of value
(abstract labour) as the determination of what exchange-value measures in the
capitalist social form, Marx’s demonstration of the logic governing the com-
modity form culminates in his demonstration of the necessity of its monetary
form of appearance. If a thing does not possess this dual form, if, specifically,
it does not possess an exchange-value, Marx tells us, it cannot appear as, and
thus is not, a commodity. Marx categorically and unambiguously affirms this
often-overlooked point: ‘Money as a measure of value is the necessary form
of appearance of the measure of value which is immanent in commodities,
namely labour-time’.72
As does Badiou in his general theory of the logics of worlds, Marx repeat-
edly emphasises the criterion of appearance in his analysis, not just critically,
but positively. This is to say that the object of his critique of the commodity, the
substance of its value, and its various value-forms is not only to reveal the illu-
sory, ideological nature of social relations under the capitalist social form. Marx
undertakes in his analysis not just a negative critique of commodity fetishism,
but also a positive construction of the commodity in the form of a thought-
object, to demonstrate the logical necessity of its monetary form of appear-
ance. In arguing that in commodity relations, value must take a monetary form
of appearance, Marx is constructing not an adequate syntax of capital, but a
When Althusser articulated the concept of theoretical practice (la pratique thé-
orique) in his introduction to Reading Capital, he intended the concept not
as a conflation of the traditional pairing of theory and practice, nor by any
means as an elimination of other forms of revolutionary practice, but just the
opposite, as an enlargement of the concept of practice to include that of theo-
retical production, bypassing the subject-object doublet of traditional theories
of knowledge.1 He did so, moreover, by deploying the central Spinozist episte-
mological tenet, verum index sui et falsi to make the famous claim that underlies
the argument of this book:
Knowledge working on its ‘object’ [writes Althusser] does not work on the
real object but on the peculiar raw material, that constitutes … its ‘object’
(of knowledge), and which, even in the most rudimentary forms of knowl-
edge, is distinct from the real object.4
There is no practice in general, but only distinct practices that are not
related in any Manichaean way with a theory which is opposed to them
in every respect. For there is not on one side theory, a pure intellectual
vision without body or materiality – and on the other side a completely
material practice which ‘gets its hands dirty’. This dichotomy is merely an
ideological myth in which a ‘theory of knowledge’ reflects many ‘interests’
other than those of reason.7
In these pages, I have tried to further develop in this fashion the singular modal-
ity of theoretical practice that is Marx’s critique of political economy, following
its transformations across the drafts, editions, and notes to Capital from 1857–
75, reading the history of these mutations through the thought of Althusser,
Macherey, Balibar, and Badiou.
That this conception of plural, singular practices maintains into the present
a certain validity is perhaps confirmed by the counter-example of Badiou’s
essential division of theory and practice, strikingly manifest for example in
ditional Marxism’: the fight for the Ricardian redistribution of wealth within
an unchanged, unexamined, and ill-comprehended capitalist social form by
‘Marxists’ of all stripes.11
Among the most surprising examples in Badiou’s memoir of this profound
theoretical obliviousness to the nature of capitalism is his commentary on the
third demand of the Chausson workers for a 40-hour workweek: ‘A guaranteed
forty-hour workweek without salary decrease. This is the median proposal we
[the UCFml] supported. The question of salary must be separated from that
of work time’. I was astounded to read, in 2023, Badiou’s next two sentences,
a still-enthusiastic and approving explanation of the significance of this posi-
tion: ‘The UCFml militants explained [to the workers] that this more or less
amounted to saying that one had abolished capitalism! The bosses make their
own profit from surplus value, work time extorted invisibly and without pay
from the workers’.12
Leaving aside the condescending tone of the passage, how is it possible for
an avowedly anti-capitalist, Marxist philosopher so thoroughly grounded in
theory, to believe today – a half century after the Reading Capital project (in
which, of course, Badiou himself played no role, having left the ens in 1961
for the army and then Reims), after the Neue Marx-Lektüre, after the critiques
of Postone, of Robert Kurz’s Wertkritik, after the contributions of the Interna-
tional Symposium on Marxist Theory – that the firm would not simply go out
of business or relocate in search of cheaper labour power were they unable to
realise a profit with this 40-hour workweek? That the ongoing class struggle
over the workweek and wages is not entirely integral to the laws of tendencies
of capitalism (and thus analysed by Marx smack in the middle of Volume i of
Capital, as Chapter 10, ‘The Working Day’)? That capitalism is a matter of free
choice from which a handful of workers could simply opt out, rather than an all-
encompassing social form? That both these workers and the UCFml militants
instructing them, having successfully negotiated their 40-hour workweek and
thus ‘abolished capitalism’, would not continue to require cash in hand to pur-
chase their bundle of life necessities, necessities otherwise unavailable because
they have been universally commodified in the capitalist social form? I could
go on.
My point is plain and simple, though perhaps far-reaching in its implications
for how we think about theoretical practice today. Between the lofty theory
of Badiou’s Idea of communism and both hollow UCFml claims to have tran-
scended capitalism and the modest, benevolent practice of UCFml militancy,
lies an abyss: the unexplored Dark Continent that is Marx’s theoretical practice.
In the previous chapter, I constructed a palimpsest of Marx’s critique drawn
from the manifest content of Badiou’s agnostic logic of worlds. In the absence
of actual engagement with and working through of that critique at any point in
Badiou’s vast oeuvre, however, theory and practice alike are distorted: reduced
to acting out the causality of a social form, the nature of which one is unaware,
practice remains limited to the histrionic throwing of stones – granite or con-
ceptual – at the imaginary villains of capitalist misdeeds, whether evil Wall
Street bankers or ‘a handful of billionaires’,13 the self-proclaimed subjects of
anti-capitalism struggle on, secure in their faith, as was Lukács a century before,
that ‘Capitalism, after a fight of barely a century, has with great difficulty won
a round. In the end, it will be defeated by a knockout’.14
As the capitalist social form increasingly destroys not just human lives and
well-being, but planetary survivability for the majority of living species, we dis-
cover that it was Marx himself who refused all facile ideas of ‘communist’ or
‘Marxist’ practice, and instead remained faithful to the imperative of an ever-
developing, relentlessly transformed theoretical practice.15 There is no royal
road to overcoming the capitalist social form, and as its global subjects, we are
condemned to working through and ever more adequately conceptualising its
nature, if future generations are to live on to escape its contingent, historically
limited, but nonetheless implacable dynamic. What other, more incisive forms
of practice might arise from this more adequate theoretical practice is a ques-
tion, as Zhou Enlai famously said of the French Revolution and Commune, that
it is too soon to answer definitively.
Althusser, Louis 2016, Les vaches noires: Interview imaginaire, Paris: puf.
Althusser, Louis, Jacques Rancière, Pierre Macherey, Roger Establet, and Etienne Bal-
ibar 2015, Reading Capital: The Complete Edition, translated by Ben Brewster and
David Fernbach, New York: Verso.
Anderson, Kevin B. 2010, Marx at the Margins, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Anderson, Perry 1980, Arguments within English Marxism, London: New Left Books.
Aristotle 1960, Posterior Analytics, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
Arthur, Chris 2002, The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital, Leiden: Brill.
Arthur, Chris 2009, ‘Contradiction and Abstraction: A Reply to Finelli’, Historical Mate-
rialism, 17: 170–82.
Arthur, Chris 2022, The Spectre of Capital: Idea and Reality, Leiden: Brill.
Badiou, Alain 1990, Le Nombre et les Nombres, Paris: Editions du Seuil.
Badiou, Alain 1998, Court traité d’ontologie transitoire, Paris: Seuil.
Badiou, Alain 2005 [1988], Being and Event, London: Continuum.
Badiou, Alain 2006, Briefings on Existence: A Short Treatise on Transitory Ontology,
translated by Norman Madarasz, Albany: State University of New York Press.
Badiou, Alain 2007 [1968], The Concept of Model: An Introduction to the Materialist Epis-
temology of Mathematics, Melbourne: Re.Press.
Badiou, Alain 2008 [1990], Number and Numbers, translated by Robin Mackay, Cam-
bridge: Polity.
Badiou, Alain 2009 [2006], Logics of Worlds. Being and Event, 2, translated by Alberto
Toscano, London: Continuum.
Badiou, Alain 2010 [2008], Communist Hypothesis, Brooklyn: Verso.
Badiou, Alain 2012, ‘Mark and Lack: On Zero’, in Concept and Form, Volume 1: Key Texts
from the Cahiers pour l’Analyse, edited by Peter Hallward and Knox Peden, New York:
Verso.
Badiou, Alain 2013a, Being and Event, translated by Oliver Feltham, London: Blooms-
bury.
Badiou, Alain 2013b, Le Séminaire. Lacan: L’antiphilosophie 3, 1994–1995, Paris: Fayard.
Badiou, Alain 2013c, Plato’s Republic: A Dialogue in Sixteen Chapters, translated by
Susan Spitzer and Kenneth Reinhard, New York: Columbia University Press.
Badiou, Alain 2015, À la recherche du réel perdu, Paris: Fayard.
Badiou, Alain 2017, ‘The Althusserian Definition of “Theory” ’, in The Concept in Crisis:
Reading Capital Today, edited by Nick Nesbitt, Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Badiou, Alain 2018a, Lacan: Anti-philosophy 3, translated by Kenneth Reinhard and
Susan Spitzer, New York: Columbia University Press.
Badiou, Alain 2018b, L’immanence des vérités: L’être et l’événement, 3, Paris: Fayard.
Badiou, Alain 2019a, Happiness, translated by A.J. Bartlett and Justin Clemens, London:
Bloomsbury.
Badiou, Alain 2019b, Sometimes, We Are Eternal, Lyon: Suture.
Bellofiore, Riccardo, Guido Starosta, and Peter D. Thomas (eds) 2013, In Marx’s Labora-
tory: Critical Interpretations of the Grundrisse, Leiden: Brill.
Bellofiore, Riccardo, and Massimiliano Tomba 2014, ‘The “Fragment on Machines” and
the Grundrisse: The Workerist Reading in Question’, in Beyond Marx: Theorising
Global Labour Relations of the Twenty-First Century, edited by Marcel van der Lin-
den and Karl Heinz Roth, Boston: Brill, pp. 345–68.
Bellofiore, Riccardo, and Roberto Fineschi (eds) 2009, Re-reading Marx: New Perspec-
tives After the Critical Edition, London: Palgrave.
Bhaskar, Roy 1983, “Dialectic” in Tom Bottomore (ed.) 1983, Dictionary of Marxist
Thought, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bianchi, Bernardo 2018, ‘Marx’s Reading of Spinoza: On the Alleged Influence of Spi-
noza on Marx’, Historical Materialism, 26, no. 4: 35–58.
Bidet, Jacques 2005, ‘The Dialectician’s Interpretation of Capital’, Historical Material-
ism, 13, no. 2: 121–46.
Bidet, Jacques 2009 [1985], Exploring Marx’s Capital: Philosophical, Economic, and Polit-
ical Aspects, Chicago: Haymarket.
Bischoff, Joachim, and Christoph Lieber 2008, ‘The Concept of Value in Modern Econ-
omy: On the Relationship between Money and Capital in Grundrisse’, in Karl Marx’s
Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy 150 Years Later, New
York: Routledge, pp. 33–47.
Bolzano, Bernard 1804, Beiträge zu einer begründeteren Darstellung der Mathematik.
Bolzano, Bernard 1950 [1851], Paradoxes of the Infinite, New York: Routledge.
Bolzano, Bernard 1978, Grundlegung der Logik: Ausgewählte Paragraphen aus der Wis-
senshaftlehre, band i und ii. Friedrich Kambartel, ed. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Ver-
lag.
Bolzano, Bernard 2010, Premiers écrits: Philosophie, logique mathématique, Paris: Vrin.
Bolzano, Bernard 2011, Théorie de la science, i–ii, Paris: Gallimard.
Bolzano, Bernard 2014, Theory of Science, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bordignon, Michela 2022, ‘Hegel’s Logic as a System of Illegitimate Totalities’, in Hegel’s
Encyclopedic System, edited by Sebastian Stein and Joshua Wretzel, New York: Rout-
ledge, pp. 115–32.
Bottomore, Tom (ed.) 1983, A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Bouveresse, Jacques, imec 20 alt 51.7.
Brown, Nathan 2021, Rationalist Empiricism: A Theory of Speculative Critique, New York:
Fordham University Press.
Brunschvig, Léon 1912, Les étapes de la philosophie mathématique, Paris: puf.
Bruschi, Fabio 2021, Le matérialisme politique de Louis Althusser, Paris: Editions Mimé-
sis.
Caffentizis, G. (2013), ‘From the Grundrisse to Capital and Beyond: Then and Now’, in
versies about Value and Capital, and New Insights from the Critical Edition’, in
Re-reading Marx: New Perspectives After the Critical Edition, edited by Riccardo
Bellofiore and Roberto Fineschi, London: Palgrave.
Heinrich, Michael 2012, An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s ‘Capital’,
translated by Alexander Locascio, New York: Monthly Review Press.
Heinrich, Michael 2013, ‘The “Fragment on Machines”: A Marxian Misconception in the
Grundrisse and its Overcoming in Capital’, in In Marx’s Laboratory: Critical Interpre-
tations of the Grundrisse, edited by Riccardo Bellofiore, Guido Starosta, and Peter
D. Thomas, Leiden: Brill, pp. 197–212.
Heinrich, Michael 2019, Karl Marx and the Birth of Modern Society, New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Heinrich, Michael 2020, ‘Marx and the Birth of Modern Society: An Interview with
Michael Heinrich’, Journal of the History of Ideas Blog, 25 November, https://www
.jhiblog.org/2020/11/25/marx‑and‑the‑birth‑of‑modern‑society/?fbclid=IwAR0vPe
O3Ldp_5y9Y0oLfNKBUv7uzmLZfRYn5Ig6bdKLAJZGME63MdV2Lap4.
Heinrich, Michael 2021, How to Read Marx’s Capital, translated by Alexander Locascio,
New York: Monthly Review Press.
Heinrich, Michael 2022 [1999], Die Wissenschaft vom Wert: Die Marxsche Kritik der poli-
tischen Ökonomie zwischen wissenschaftlicher Revolution und klassicher Tradition,
Münster: Verlag Westfälisches Dampfboot.
Heinrich, Michael 2023, La Scienza del Valore: La Critica Marxiana Dell’Economia Polit-
ica tra Rivoluzione Scientifica e Tradizione Classica [Die Wissenschaft vom Wert. Die
Marxsche Kritik der politischen Ökonomie zwischen wissenschaftlicher Revolution
und klassicher Tradition], edited by Riccardo Bellofiore and Stefano Breda, trans-
lated by Stefano Breda, Rome: PGreco Edizioni.
Huhn, Wilson 2022, The Five Types of Legal Argument, Durham, NC: Carolina Academic
Press.
Hussain, Athar 1972, ‘Marx’s “Notes on Adolph Wagner”: An Introduction’, Theoretical
Practice, 5: 18–34.
Husserl, Edmund 2001 [1900], Philosophical Investigations, New York: Routledge.
Iñigo Carrera, Juan 2003, El Capital: Razón Histórica, Sujeto Revolucionario y Conciencia,
Buenos Aires: Ediciones Cooperitivas.
Iñigo Carrera, Juan 2013, ‘Method: From the Grundrisse to Capital’, in In Marx’s Labora-
tory: Critical Interpretations of the Grundrisse, edited by Riccardo Bellofiore, Guido
Starosta, and Peter D. Thomas, Leiden: Brill, pp. 43–70.
Jameson, Fredric 2014, Representing Capital: A Reading of Volume One, New York: Verso.
Jappe, Anselm 2013, ‘Sohn-Rethel and the Origin of “Real Abstraction”: A Critique of
Production or a Critique of Circulation’, Historical Materialism, 21, no. 1: 3–14.
Kant, Immanuel 1998, Critique of Pure Reason, edited by Paul Guyer, translated by Allen
Wood, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kaplan, E. Ann, and Michael Sprinker (eds) 1993, The Althusserian Legacy, London:
Verso.
Kautsky, Karl 1887, Karl Marx Oekonomische Lehren: Gemeinverständlich dargestellt und
erläutert, Stuttgart: Dietz.
Kojève, Alexandre 1980 [1947], Introduction à la lecture de Hegel, Paris: Gallimard.
Kurz, Robert 2016, The Substance of Capital, London: Chronos.
Labelle, Gilles 2020, ‘Marx, lecteur d’Épicure’, Cahiers société, 2: 151–70.
Lacan, Jacques 1991, The Ego in Freud’s Theory and in the Technique of Psychanalysis,
1954–1955. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book ii, translated by Sylvana Tomaselli,
New York: W.W. Norton.
Lacan, Jacques 2016, Anxiety, The Seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book x, Cambridge: Polity.
Lalande, André 2010 [1923], Vocabulaire technique et critique de la philosophie, Paris:
puf.
Lange, Elena Louisa 2016, ‘The Critique of Political Economy and the “New Dialectic”:
Marx, Hegel, and the Problem of Christopher J. Arthur’s “Homology Thesis” ’, Crisis
and Critique, 3, no. 3: 235–72.
Lange, Elena Louisa 2018a, ‘Capital’, in The Bloomsbury Companion to Marx, edited by
Jeff Diamanti, Andrew Pendakis, and Imre Szeman, London: Bloomsbury.
Lange, Elena Louisa 2018b, Value Without Fetish: Uno Kozo’s Theory of Pure Capitalism
in Light of Marx’s Critique of Political Economy, Leiden: Brill.
Lange, Elena Louisa 2019a, ‘Form Analysis and Critique: Marx’s Social Labour Theory of
Value’, in Capitalism: Concept, Idea, Image. Aspects of Marx’s Capital Today, edited
by Peter Osborne, Eric Alliez, and Eric-John Russell, London: crmep Books, pp. 21–
35.
Lange, Elena Louisa 2019b, ‘Money versus Value?’ Historical Materialism, 28, no. 1: 1–34.
Laplanche, Jean, and Jean-Bertrand Pontalis 2018, Language of Psychoanalysis, New
York: Routledge.
Lapointe, Sandra 2008, Qu’est-ce que l’analyse? Paris: Vrin.
Lapointe, Sandra 2011, Bolzano’s Theoretical Philosophy, New York: Palgrave.
Lasowski, Aliocha 2016, Althusser et nous. Paris: puf.
Laz, Jacques 1993, Bolzano, critique de Kant, Paris: Vrin.
Lazarus, Sylvain (ed.) 2015, Politique et philosophie dans l’oeuvre de Louis Althusser,
Paris: puf.
Lecourt, Dominique 1975, Marxism and Epistemology: Bachelard, Canguilhem, and Fou-
cault, translated by Ben Brewster, New York: nlb.
Lesjak, Carolyn 2021, ‘Dialectics’, in The Bloomsbury Companion to Marx, edited by Jeff
Diamanti, Andrew Pendakis, and Imre Szeman, London: Bloomsbury.
Levine, Norman 2009, ‘Hegelian Continuities in Marx’, Critique, 37, no. 3: 345–70.
Levine, Norman 2012, Marx’s Discourse with Hegel, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Lietz, Barbara, and Winfried Schwarz 2023, ‘Value, Exchange, and Heinrich’s “New
Marx, Karl 1983, mega2 ii/5, Karl Marx, Das Kapital: Kritik Der Politischen Ökonomie.
Erster Band, Hamburg 1867, Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
Marx, Karl 1987, mega2 ii/6, Karl Marx, Das Kapital: Kritik Der Politischen Ökonomie.
Erster Band, Hamburg 1872, Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
Marx, Karl 1989, mega2 ii/7, Le Capital, Paris, 1872–1875, Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
Marx, Karl 1991, mega2 ii/10, Karl Marx, Das Kapital: Kritik Der Politischen Ökonomie.
Erster Band, Hamburg 1890, Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
Marx, Karl 1996, Later Political Writings, translated by Terrell Carver, Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press.
Marx, Karl 2008, ‘Historical Materialism in Forms which Precede Capitalist Production’,
in Karl Marx’s Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy 150 Years
Later, edited by Marcello Musto, London: Routledge, pp. 79–92.
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels 1986, Manifesto of the Communist Party, edited by Ter-
rell Carver, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Matheron, Alexandre 1977, ‘Le Traité Théologico-Politique vu par le jeune Marx’, in
Cahiers Spinoza, 1 (Summer): 159–212.
Matthys, Jean 2023, Althusser lecteur de Spinoza: Genèse et enjeux d’une éthico-politique
de la théorie, Sesto S. Giovanni: Editions Mimésis.
Mattick, Paul 2019, Theory as Critique: Essays on ‘Capital’, Chicago, Haymarket.
Matysik, Tracie 2023, When Spinoza Met Marx: Experiments in Nonhumanist Activity,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
McIvor, Martin 2008, ‘The Young Marx and German Idealism: Revisiting the Doctoral
Dissertation’, Journal of the Philosophy of History, 46, no. 3: 395–419.
McNulty, Tracy 2009, ‘Demanding the Impossible: Desire and Social Change’, Differ-
ences, 20, no. 1: 1–39.
Meaney, Mark 2015, ‘Capital Breeds: Interest-bearing Capital as Purely Abstract Form’,
in Marx’s Capital and Hegel’s Logic, edited by Fred Moseley and Tony Smith, Chica-
go: Haymarket.
Montag, Warren 2013, Althusser and His Contemporaries, Durham, NC: Duke University
Press.
Montag, Warren 1998, ‘Editor’s Introduction’, in In a Materialist Way: Selected Essays, by
Pierre Macherey, New York: Verso.
Montag, Warren 1999, Bodies, Masses, Power: Spinoza and His Contemporaries, New
York: Verso.
Morfino, Vittorio 2015, Plural Temporality: Transindividuality and the Aleatory between
Spinoza and Althusser, Chicago: Haymarket.
Morfino, Vittorio 2022, ‘Althusser’s Spinozism: A Philosophy for the Future?’, Journal of
Spinoza Studies, 1, no. 1, https://jss.rug.nl/article/view/38522.
Morfino, Vittorio 2023, ‘Una nota su Heinrich e Althusser’, in La Scienza del Valore: La
Critica Marxiana Dell’Economia Politica tra Rivoluzione Scientifica e Tradizione Clas-
sica, by Michael Heinrich, edited by Riccardo Bellofiore and Stefano Breda, trans-
lated by Stefano Breda, Rome: PGreco.
Moseley, Fred (ed.) 2005, Marx’s Theory of Money: Modern Appraisals, New York: Pal-
grave Macmillan.
Moseley, Fred (ed.) 2013, ‘The Whole and the Parts: The Early Development of Marx’s
Theory of the Distribution of Surplus-Value in the Grundrisse’, in In Marx’s Labora-
tory: Critical Interpretations of the Grundrisse, edited by Riccardo Bellofiore, Guido
Starosta, and Peter D. Thomas, Leiden: Brill, pp. 285–302.
Moseley, Fred (ed.) 2016, ‘Editor’s Introduction’, in Marx’s Manuscripts of 1864–65,
Chicago: Haymarket.
Moseley, Fred (ed.) 2017, Money and Totality: A Macro-Monetary Interpretation of
Marx’s Logic in ‘Capital’ and the End of the ‘Transformation Problem’, Chicago: Hay-
market.
Moseley, Fred 2023, Marx’s Theory of Value in Chapter 1 of Capital: A Critique of Hein-
rich’s Value-Form Interpretation, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Moseley, Fred, and Tony Smith (eds) 2015, Marx’s Capital and Hegel’s Logic: A Reexam-
ination, Chicago: Haymarket.
Müller-Doohm, Stefan 2004, Adorno: A Biography, Cambridge: Polity.
Murray, Patrick 2002, ‘The Illusion of the Economic: The Trinity Formula and the
“Religion of Everyday Life”’, in The Culmination of Capital: Essays on Volume iii
of Marx’s Capital, edited by Martha Campbell and Geert Reuten, New York: Pal-
grave.
Murray, Patrick 2013, ‘Unavoidable Crises: Reflections on Backhaus and the Develop-
ment of Marx’s Value-Form Theory in the Grundrisse’, in In Marx’s Laboratory: Crit-
ical Interpretations of the Grundrisse, edited by Riccardo Bellofiore, Guido Starosta,
and Peter D. Thomas, Leiden: Brill, pp. 121–48.
Murray, Patrick 2017, The Mismeasure of Wealth: Essays on Marx and Social Form,
Chicago: Haymarket.
Mury, Gilbert 1963, ‘Matérialisme et hyperempirisme’, La Pensée, 108 (April): 38–51.
Musto, Marcello 2008a, ‘History, Production, and Method in the 1857 “Introduction”’,
in Karl Marx’s Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy 150 Years
Later, New York: Routledge, pp. 3–32.
Musto, Marcello 2020, Last Years of Karl Marx, Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Negri, Antonio 1985, Marx au-delà de Marx, Paris: L’Harmattan.
Nesbitt, Nick 2017, The Concept in Crisis: Reading Capital Today, Durham, NC: Duke
University Press.
Nesbitt, Nick 2019, ‘Marx’s Grundrisse: An Inquiry into the Categorial Structure of Capi-
talism’, in The Bloomsbury Companion to Marx, edited by Andrew Pendakis and Imre
Szeman, London: Bloomsbury, pp. 41–56.
Nesbitt, Nick 2020, ‘The Concept of the Commodity: Badiou and Marx, 1968/1989’, in
Revolutions for the Future: May 68 and the Prague Spring, edited by Jana Berankova,
Michael Hauser, and Nick Nesbitt, Lyon: Suture, pp. 122–39.
Nesbitt, Nick 2021, ‘Bolzano’s Badiou’, Filozofski Vestnik, 41, no. 2.
Nesbitt, Nick 2022, The Price of Slavery: Capitalism and Revolution in the Caribbean,
Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press.
Norris, Christopher 1991, Spinoza and the Origins of Modern Critical Theory, Oxford:
Blackwell.
Oittinen, Vesa 2022, ‘Soviet Spinoza: introduction’, Studies in East European Thought,
March, 2022.
Peden, Knox 2014, Spinoza contra Phenomenology: French Rationalism from Cavaillès to
Deleuze, Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Post, Charles 2012, The American Road to Capitalism, Chicago: Haymarket.
Postone, Moishe 1993, Time, Labor, and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of Marx’s
Critical Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Read, Jason 2007, ‘The Order and Connection of Ideas: Theoretical Practice in Mache-
rey’s Turn to Spinoza’, Rethinking Marxism, 19, no. 4.
Reuten, Geert 2014, ‘An Outline of the Systematic-Dialectical Method: Scientific and
Political Significance’, in Marx’s Capital and Hegel’s Logic, edited by Fred Moseley
and Tony Smith, Leiden: Brill.
Roudinesco, Elisabeth 1995, Lacan, New York: Columbia University Press.
Rosdolsky, Roman 1992 [1968], The Making of Marx’s ‘Capital’, London: Pluto Press.
Rubel, Maximilien 1977, ‘Marx à la rencontre de Spinoza’, Cahiers Spinoza, 1 (Summer):
7–28.
Rusnock, Paul, and Jan Šebestík 2019, Bernard Bolzano: His Life and Work, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Saito, Kohei 2017, Karl Marx’s Ecosocialism, New York: Monthly Review Press.
Schülein, Johannes-Georg 2022, ‘On the Status of Nature in Hegel’s Encyclopedic Sys-
tem’, in Hegel’s Encyclopedic System, edited by Sebastian Stein and Joshua Wretzel,
New York: Routledge.
Šebestík, Jan 1986, ‘La classe universelle et l’auto-appartenance chez Bernard Bolzano’,
Eleutheria: Mathematical Journal of the Seminar P. Zernos.
Sinaceur, Houya Benis 2013, Cavaillès, Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
Smith, Adam 1999, The Wealth of Nations, New York: Penguin.
Smith, Steven B. 1984, Reading Althusser: An Essay on Structural Marxism, Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press.
Smith, Tony 2013, ‘The “General Intellect” in the Grundrisse and Beyond’, in In Marx’s
Laboratory: Critical Interpretations of the Grundrisse, edited by Riccardo Bellofiore,
Guido Starosta, and Peter D. Thomas, Leiden: Brill, pp. 213–32.
Smith, Tony 2014, ‘Hegel, Marx, and the Comprehension of Capitalism’, in Marx’s Cap-
ital and Hegel’s Logic: A Reexamination, edited by Fred Moseley and Tony Smith,
Leiden: Brill.
Tosel, André 2008, ‘Pour une étude systématique du rapport de Marx à Spinoza: Remar-
ques et hypotheses’, in Spinoza au xix e siècle, Paris: Editions de la Sorbonne, pp. 127–
47.
Trendelenburg, Adolf 1840, Logische Untersuchungen. Berlin: Gustav Bethge, 2 vols.
Uchida, Hiroshi 2016 [1988], Marx’s Grundrisse and Hegel’s Logic, New York: Routledge.
Van der Linden, Marcel, and Gerald Hubman (eds) 2019, Marx’s Capital: An Unfinish-
able Project? Chicago: Haymarket.
Van Ree, E. 2000, ‘Stalin as a Marxist Philosopher’, Studies in Eastern European Thought,
52: 259–308.
Vargas, Yves 2008, ‘L’horreur dialectique (description d’un itinéraire)’, in Althusser: Une
lecture de Marx, Paris: puf.
Wark, McKenzie 2019, Capital is Dead: Is This Something Worse? New York: Verso.
Williams, Caroline 2013, ‘Althusser and Spinoza: The Enigma of the Subject’, in Encoun-
tering Althusser: Politics and Materialism in Contemporary Radical Thought, edited
by Katja Diefenbach, Sara R. Farris, Gal Kirn, and Peter Thomas, London: Blooms-
bury, pp. 157–8.
Williams, Eric 1994, Capitalism and Slavery, Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina
Press.
Wood, Ellen Meiksins 2002 [1999], The Origin of Capitalism: A Longer View, London:
Verso.
Yakhot, Yehoshua 2012 [1981], The Suppression of Philosophy in the ussr, Oak Park:
Mehring.
Young, Robert J.C. 2017, ‘Rereading the Symptomatic Reading’, in Nesbitt 2017, pp. 35–
48.
capitalist accumulation (a. of commodi- Deleuze, Gilles 74, 87, 129, 213
ties) viii, 14, 104, 141, 144, 161, 174, 175, Democritus 84, 192, 195, 196
191, 232, 254, 258 Derrida, Jacques 72
capitalist mode of production viii, 12, Desanti, Jacques 59, 217, 260
31, 63, 84, 103, 109, 128, 134, 141, 144, 145, Descartes, René 45, 46, 53, 85, 90, 107,
151, 162, 174, 224, 229, 254 166
critique of c. 20, 210, 213, 227 Descombes, Vincent 7
development of c. 110, 121, 122 dialectics xii, 2, 22, 23–27, 50, 68, 121, 137,
industrial c. 15, 121 159, 139, 238
posthuman c. 227, 228, 242 Diefenbach, Katja x
primitive accumulation viii, 15, 30, 97, Dietzgen, Joseph 24, 110
101, 102, 104, 145 Dilthey, Wilhelm 72
Carrera, Juan Iñigo 29, 211 Dragstedt, Albert 153, 155
Cassin, Barbara x, 128, 179 Dukas, Paul 233
Cassou-Noguès, Pierre 33 Duménil, Gérard 18, 162
Cavaillès, Jean 18, 32, 33, 70, 111, 133, 210, 217, Duroux, Yves 56
219, 220, 224, 239
class struggle 7–8, 10–11, 12, 17, 19, 31, 38, 47, Elliott, Gregory 5, 7, 50, 58, 271
59, 141, 142–143, 265 Engels, Friedrich 5, 12–14, 24, 26, 31, 41,
class exploitation 12–13, 14 58, 76, 99, 121, 135, 136, 140, 154, 196,
Cole, Andrew 26 205
commodity (nature of c., c. production) Epicurus 192, 195–197
viii, ix, xvi, 12, 31, 46, 63, 64–66, Establet, Roger 62
101, 103, 104, 108–09, 112, 119, 122, Estop, Juan Domingo Sánchez xviii, 10, 11,
125, 126, 128, 133–34, 137, 138, 142, 38, 39, 42, 43, 47, 50, 51, 55–57
144, 146, 147, 148, 149–58, 161–62,
165, 167, 168–75, 179–86, 189, 198– Fallon, Jacques 27
99, 200, 229, 231, 232, 249–57, 258– Farris, Sara R. x
60 Feuerbach, Ludwig Andreas 192, 237,
c. fetishism xvi, 30, 98, 232, 258 260
c.-based society 98, 251 Fineschi, Roberto 114, 152
commodification vii, viii–ix, 46, Fischbach, Franck 192
97, 139, 162, 175, 215, 229, 230, 233, Fluss, Harrison 23, 24–26, 129, 130
256 Forster, Edward Seymour 27
communism viii, ix, 151, 208, 209, 231, 236, Foucault, Michel 213
240, 245 Fowkes, Ben 175, 194
contradiction (Widerspruch) xii, xvii, 2, Frege, Gottlob 155, 217, 218, 221, 223, 224,
16, 22, 23, 26, 30, 42, 65, 72, 75, 101, 228, 244, 245
103, 104, 108, 109, 110, 111–12, 113, 119, Freud, Sigmund xiv, 56, 238
120, 125, 127, 133, 134, 135, 138–39, Frim, Landon 129, 130
146, 149, 150–58, 161, 162, 164, 165, Fulka, Josef xii
168, 170, 171, 172–73, 174, 180, 189, 190,
193, 197, 199, 202, 204, 230, 231, 238– Gabler, Georg Andreas 191
39 Gane, Michael 8
Cutler, Antony 8 Garaudy, Roger 9, 32, 49–51
Geroult, Martial 83
Darimon, Alfred 32 Goshgarian, G.M. 7, 8, 58
Deborin, Abram 26, 129, 131 Gracq, Julien 233
Defoe, Daniel 68
Haeckel, Ernst 50 145, 146, 147, 155, 167, 168, 169, 180–89,
Hallward, Peter 213, 220 198, 199, 245, 251, 252, 255, 256
Hegel, G.W.F. xii, xvii, 6, 21–26, 29, 30, 39, abstract labour 13, 64, 67, 104, 124, 165,
41, 43, 50, 51, 60–62, 68, 80, 90, 92, 101, 167, 168, 169, 176, 186, 235, 241, 251, 252,
107, 108, 110–19, 121–26, 130, 137, 138, 255, 258, 259, 260
141, 145, 149–53, 155, 159, 160, 162, 163, labour power viii, ix, xvi, 13, 30, 97,
165, 173, 174, 176, 178, 179, 186, 189–93, 101, 105, 109, 126, 138, 140, 147, 148, 199,
195, 196, 212, 222, 223, 238, 243, 246, 201–02, 204, 205, 212, 227, 228, 249, 262,
260 265
Absolute Subject xiv, 109 labour theory of value viii, ix, 200, 243,
Aufhebung xvii, 65, 67, 100, 101, 103, 164, 258
167, 190 Lacan, Jacques xiii, xiv, 50, 56, 135, 136,
Hegelian negative dialectics 2, 68, 238 218, 222–23, 235–42
Reflexionsbestimmungen xvii, 41, 149, Lalande, André x, 27, 31, 32, 46, 49, 111, 134,
150, 151, 156, 157, 160, 164 172, 178, 179, 229, 230
Heinrich, Michael 1, 5, 12, 14, 17, 27, 32, 41, Lange, Elena Louisa 124
64, 65, 102, 107, 119–21, 124, 136, 137, 142, Laplanche, Jean 47, 50, 210
150, 153–56, 158, 161, 164, 165, 167–71, Lapointe, Sandra 205, 217
175–92, 231, 250–52 Lasowski, Aliocha 63
Hemming, Laurence xvi Lassalle, Ferdinand 23
Hubman, Gerald 99 Laz, Jacques 218–221, 223
Huhn, Wilson 191 Lazarus, Sylvain 263
Hume, David 28 Lenin, Vladimir Ilyich 23, 40, 68, 85, 87, 129
Hussain, Athar ix Lesjak, Carolyn 26
Husserl, Edmund 72, 111, 218 Levine, Norman 108, 115, 195
Lévi-Strauss, Claude 72, 73, 80, 87, 213–15,
ideology (theory of i., i. critique) 10, 22, 227
30, 50, 70, 77, 80, 97, 98, 99, 211, 214, Libera, Alain de 179
216 Lietz, Barbara 176, 177
Iñigo Carrera, Juan 29, 211 Linden, Marcel van der 99
Lordon, Frédéric 192
Jacobi, Carl Gustav Jacob 25 Louverture, Toussaint 233
Jameson, Fredric 104 Lucretius Carus, Titus 75, 84
Jappe, Anselm 180 Lukács, Georg 10, 114, 115, 122–23, 128, 133,
Jelles, Jarig 193 135, 266
Luxemburg, Rosa 115, 122
Kant, Immanuel 18, 92, 111, 219, 223, 226,
243, 246, 248 Macherey, Pierre xii–xiii, xv, xvii, 1–4, 6,
Kaplan, E. Ann x 16, 18, 20–21, 23–25, 27, 28, 30, 34–40,
Kautsky, Karl 12, 177–78 42–43, 45, 46, 48, 53–56, 58–85, 87–93,
Kirn, Gal x 95–96, 99–104, 106–10, 112–15, 120, 121,
Kojève, Alexandre 103, 238 123–34, 138, 148–49, 158, 162–64, 166,
Kosík, Karel 114 173, 193, 202–04, 206–07, 222, 223, 230,
Koyré, Alexandre 239 238, 262
Kugelmann, Ludwig 110, 154 literary (textual) production (p. of the
Kurz, Robert 176, 265 text) 70, 74, 77
materialist analysis 68, 75, 76, 80–81,
Labelle, Gilles 195 101, 104, 106, 110
labour xvi, 15, 35, 64, 73, 104, 105, 138, 142, Madonia, Franca xiii
Schoenberg, Arnold 233 163–64, 166, 189, 193, 225, 226, 243, 245,
Schwarz, Winfried 176, 177 246, 248, 249
Šebestík, Jan 218, 220 Trendelenburg, Adolf 158–60, 192
Shulyatikov, Vladimir 50 Trotsky, Leon 129
Smith, Adam 29, 30, 32, 35, 63, 69, 211, 212
Smith, Tony xii, 6, 30, 80, 114, 115, 156, 257 Valéry, Paul 233
Sohn-Rethel, Alfred x, 76, 180 value (nature or substance of v., v.-form –
Sotiris, Panagiotis ix, 8, 12, 20, 56 Wertform, v.-objectivity, v.-relationship)
Spinoza, Baruch xi–xv, xvii, 2–4, 6–9, viii, xvi, xviii, 12–13, 14, 18, 21, 22,
12, 13, 16, 17, 20, 21, 24–26, 28, 29, 31, 34, 35, 36, 63, 64, 66, 67, 76, 97, 100,
33–38, 40–50, 53–62, 68, 69, 71, 73– 102, 103, 104, 105, 109, 120, 122, 124, 126,
75, 79–96, 98–102, 105–06, 109–13, 133, 134, 136, 138, 139, 141, 148, 150, 151,
115, 116, 124, 127–35, 140, 143, 148– 153–56, 157–58, 164–65, 167–73, 174–77,
49, 158, 161, 162, 164, 166, 173, 179, 181, 179–89, 191, 192, 198–201, 204, 205, 212,
189, 192–95, 197–99, 202, 203, 205, 230–31, 232, 235, 236, 241, 243, 245–46,
206, 208, 215, 216, 222, 230, 238, 239, 249, 251–53, 254–60
262 exchange-value 13, 63, 64, 65, 66, 103,
attribute of extension 34, 46, 60, 81, 82, 108, 112, 133, 134, 151, 152, 153–54, 157,
94, 95, 96, 110, 181 158, 161–62, 164–65, 172, 173, 176, 179–80,
attribute of thought xiii, xvi, 3, 6, 16, 182, 188, 189, 228–29, 249–53, 254–56,
29, 34, 38, 57, 66, 77, 81, 88, 94, 96, 105, 257, 258, 259
110, 162, 166, 196, 259, 261 surplus value ix, xvi, 13, 30, 42, 46, 64,
common notions 3, 42, 57, 87, 96–97, 98, 65, 66, 103, 104, 105, 106, 109, 111, 119,
103, 132, 197, 202, 203, 206–07 124, 125, 126, 134–35, 140, 143, 144, 146–
substance x, xi, xiv, xv, xvi, 3, 4, 6, 13, 147, 148, 151, 165, 179, 184, 197, 198, 199,
18–25, 40, 43–52, 54–61, 64, 67, 81–82, 200, 201, 204, 227, 239, 251, 257, 265
84, 85, 88–93, 97, 98, 101, 104, 105, 109– use-value 64, 65, 67, 100, 103, 108, 112,
10, 113, 124, 129–34, 143, 148, 156, 159, 134, 138, 151, 152, 153–54, 157–58, 161–62,
161–162, 165, 167, 176, 177, 179, 180–85, 164, 167, 169, 171, 172, 173, 179, 183, 185,
193, 212, 227, 241, 249, 251, 252–53, 255, 189, 226, 228–29, 249–50, 256
258, 259–60 Vargas, Yves 50
Stalin, Joseph Vissarionovich 50–52, 54, 59 Verne, Jules 68
Starosta, Guido 174
Stein, Sebastian 115 Wagner, Adolph ix, 185, 231, 254
Wark, Mackenzie 7
Thompson, Edward Palmer 5, 57, 58 Williams, Eric 56
Tolstoy, Lev Nikolayevich 68 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 235
Toscano, Alberto 76, 180 Wood, Ellen Meiksins viii, ix, 102
Tosel, André 192, 193 Wretzel, Joshua 115
totality (Totalität) xi–xii, xiv–xv, xvii, 3,
4, 14, 26, 42, 45, 50, 52, 55, 59, 68–69, Yakhot, Yehoshua 128, 129, 131
71–72, 74–76, 78, 80, 82, 85, 88, 90, 93,
95, 100, 108, 113–41, 143, 147, 152, 156, Zasulich, Vera 15