Baxi 2013
Baxi 2013
Upendra Baxi*
How does, and how should, social theory conceive of the basic
human needs (“BHN”) of the worst-off in society? How should
these conceptions be translated into the language of
constitutional law? The paper will investigate the analytical
concerns of BHN and address six key concerns. First, how should
social theory define 'needs'? Second, how should state officials
identify, map, and respond to these needs? Third, how may
transnational intergovernmental networks impinge on national
spheres of public policy in regarding to meeting BHN? Fourth,
on what basis may public power be distributed for meeting BHN?
Fifth, should the appellate judiciary concern itself with the tasks
of protection of rights rather than extend its powers to
identification and meeting BHN? Sixth, when BHN remain unmet
for long stretches of time, could violent social action represent
itself as a long term agency for rectification of public indifference
towards meeting unmet BHN?
The author of the Hind Swaraj fully inveighed against free market
capitalism in ways reminiscent of Karl Marx,4 who a long while ago insisted
that modern capitalism may not be simply understood as the multiplication
of goods and services by market and industry; rather, the magic of capitalist
production consists in the unending production of desires. Mohandas
unerringly grasped this in terms of the ceaseless production of ethical evils
in a market-driven economy, as not heralding human advancement and
progress. He, unlike Marx, did not share the bourgeois Enlightenment
notions of early industrial capitalism as heralding the idea of progress,
ending feudal ways of domination and marking the advent of class struggle
as a promise for emancipatory politics. This is a story for another day,
obviously!
What Mohandas realized, contra Marx, was the fact that all
human/social needs are not created by markets alone. The Mahatma
recognized this in his movement against untouchability. The ritual
distinctions and discriminations constituting untouchability, he recognized,
produce systemic justifications for the production of social indifference
towards the Unmet Social Needs (“USN”) of untouchable peoples. As we
all know, his response to this deprivation was via temple entry agitation,
which has now blossomed into some judicial decisions allowing access
even to the sanctum sanctorum or the Hindu temples.5
7
Ambedkar this striking difference. Bhim Rao Ambedkar's response to
Mohandas crystallized in the now not so well-known Mahad Satyagraha
directed against lethal violence practiced by high caste Hindus against
untouchables, involving preventing the latter from drawing water from a
single village well. Ambedkar thus demonstrated, in my view at least, that
USN are caused by the ends of caste domination going far beyond the Hindu
'spiritual' realm. He further demonstrated acutely the ways in which this
form of slavery and servitude benefitted primarily the dominant castes and
classes.
Allow me then, and thus, at the outset that Unmet Social Needs remain a
province and function of not just of economics (market-driven) but also
mark the realms of social, religious and cultural dominance. Allow me also
to add a further remark: the Indian constitutional architecture remains fully
complicit with the creation and sustenance of vast arenas of USN.
7
Upendra Baxi, Justice as Emancipation: The Legacy of Babasaheb Ambedkar, in CRISIS
AND CHANGE IN CONTEMPORARY INDIA (Upendra Baxi & Bhikhu Parekh eds., 1995).
2013] Law and Unmet Social Needs 5
with the tasks of protection of rights rather than extend its powers to the
identification and meeting social needs? Sixth, when social needs remain
wantonly unmet for long stretches of constitutional time, could violent
social action represent itself as a long term agency for rectification of public
indifference towards meeting USN? Each one of these questions is related
but also distinct and needs to be further nuanced. In this conversation, I will
briefly respond to some of these concerns.
Pound insisted that the fact that a demand is made constitutes an interest
and all demands thus made, no matter their ethical content, ought to be
regarded as valid just because these are articulated. Obviously, some
demands may be outside the existing law and may even be framed against it
(the very essence of legal transformation and law reform); other demands
may be made in terms that Hannah Arendt made famous via the expression
“the right to have rights”9 (the province and function of human rights
8
III ROSCOE POUND, JURISPRUDENCE 3-324 (1959).
9
HANNAH ARENDT, THE ORIGINS OF TOTALITARIANISM (1986).
6 Journal of National Law University, Delhi [Vol. 1
If, however, some interests are disarticulated at the threshold, the law
itself becomes (as Harold Laski once put this) merely a “beatification of the
status quo.”11 In this event, the law becomes a near complete means of
domination or repression, leading at times to advocacy of violence as a just
program for social transformation.
Julius Stone in a critique of Pound further suggested that for the theory
of interests to work well, certain demands have to acquire the status of near-
absolutes.12 Put another way, freedom of speech and expression, movement
and association are interests that inhibit, and even prevent, disarticulation
of demands and no adjustment of conflicting demands may ever be
legitimate when these near-absolute demands stand compromised. Put still
another way, certain demands acquire the status of inviolable fundamental
13
human rights with their accompanying freedoms.
of the postcolony lie not just in responding to social demands (interest) but
rather in provoking articulation of these.14 I think that a major constitutional
process achievement of India thus remains insightfully articulated here.
Even so, we may surely ask both in the contexts of the planned economy of
the yesteryear, and the unplanned economy of Indian globalization,
whether this demand-formation triggered by state, politics and law has
ended up only creating and nurturing 'wants' and 'desires' of the middle
classes while failing fully to attend to the actually experienced basic needs
of the worst-off Indian impoverished humanity. I must leave today this
enormous question 'hanging in the air' as it were.
14
JULIUS STONE, SOCIAL DIMENSIONS OF LAW AND JUSTICE (1971).
15
Upendra Baxi, From Human Rights to the Right to be Human: Some Heresies, 13(3/4)
INDIA INT'L CENTER Q. 185-200 (1986).
16
International Covenant on Social, Economic and Cultural Rights, 993 U.N.T.S. 3 (Dec. 19,
1966).
8 Journal of National Law University, Delhi [Vol. 1
17
the articulation of the BMN. At any rate, no society may deny either the
BMN or the BIN and yet claim to be a morally decent society. This remark
remains especially pertinent to Indian constitutional device of Part III and
18
Part IV. I speak to this briefly a little later.
For the moment, it needs noting that some activist CAD voices
registered some remarkable normative triumphs, notably via the Article 17
abolition of 'untouchability' and further especially via fundamental rights
against exploitation enshrined in Articles 23 and 24.
19
To be sure, as I have been saying for some time this constitutional arrangement fully
anticipates the division of contemporary human rights into civil and political rights on the
one hand and on the other the rights compendiously named as economic and social human
right;. I wonder though whether we ought to remain the least bit proud of this inaugural
innovation!
20
Perhaps the truest embodiment of what Antonio Gramsci named as a 'Modern Prince'!.
21
GRANVILLE AUSTIN, WORKING A DEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTION: A HISTORY OF THE
INDIAN EXPERIENCE 85 (1999).
10 Journal of National Law University, Delhi [Vol. 1
Further, we need to note that for the most part the principle and design
of Indian 'federalism' distributes and invests law-making and executive
competence on states within the Indian federation. No doubt, New Delhi
possesses enormous leverage in terms of framing national economic policy
planning; it distributes some enormous federal largesse via the Planning
Commission and the Finance Commission mandated distribution of public
revenues. Important as all this remains, as some recent debates concerning
23
the National Rural Employment Guarantee Act suggest, the existing
distribution of jurisdictional spheres remains, at least from the worm's eye,
a part of the problem rather than of any solution. One may only fondly hope
that the Panchayati Raj constitutional amendments may make an eventual
and decisive difference.24 I must apologize instantly for the brevity of these
remarks save highlighting that any distribution of jurisdictional spheres
remains constitutionally 'just' only in the proportion that it services the
needs of India's worst-off peoples. From this perspective, we need to
reinvent the design and detail of the Indian federalism.
22
See INDIA CONST. art. 35.
23
The Mahatma Gandhi National Rural Employment Guarantee Act, No. 42 of 2005.
24
INDIA CONST. amended by The Constitution (Seventy Third Amendment) Act, 1992 &
The Constitution (Seventy Fourth Amendment) Act, 1992.
2013] Law and Unmet Social Needs 11
25
United Nations Millennium Declaration, U.N. Doc. A/RES/55/2 (Sept. 8, 2000) .
26
FRANTZ FANON, THE WRETCHED OF THE EARTH (Richard Philcox trans., rep. ed. 2005).
27
See Upendra Baxi, Taking Suffering Seriously: Social Action Litigation in the Supreme
Court of India, 4 THIRD WORLD LEGAL STUD. 107, 108-11 (1985).
12 Journal of National Law University, Delhi [Vol. 1
If the 24/7 mass media pundits have helped create a climate instantly
de-legitimating organized political violence that indiscriminately kills, or
hurts and harms innocent lives in the process, those inclined to portray such
violence as violence for equality remain constantly asked to condemn it in
the name of the nation and its democracy. This is a contested terrain which I
may today only briefly suggest as worthy of all your serious deliberation.
28
Keshvananda Bharti v. State of Kerala, (1973) 4 S.C.C. 225.
29
Harjinder Singh v. Punjab State Warehousing Corporation, (2010) 3 S.C.C. 192.
2013] Law and Unmet Social Needs 13
Even so, one may tentatively at least proceed to draw some bright lines
between constitutional insurgencies and peoples wars against the State
30
ANTONIO NEGRI, INSURGENCIES: CONSTITUENT POWER AND THE MODERN STATE
(Maurizia Boscagli trans., 1999).
31
JACQUES DERRIDA, MARGINS OF PHILOSOPHY 17 (Alan Bass trans., 1982). See also JEAN
14 Journal of National Law University, Delhi [Vol. 1
FRANÇOIS LYOTARD, THE DIFFEREND: PHRASES IN DISPUTE (Georges Van Den Abbeele
trans., 1991).