0% found this document useful (0 votes)
9 views

Antonio Gramsci

The document provides biographical information about Antonio Gramsci, an influential Marxist theorist. It discusses his background and early life in Sardinia, his political activism in Turin as a journalist and member of the Socialist Party, and his later work developing theories of cultural hegemony while imprisoned under Mussolini. His most famous writings were produced during his imprisonment in the Prison Notebooks.

Uploaded by

Hawaid Ahmad
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
9 views

Antonio Gramsci

The document provides biographical information about Antonio Gramsci, an influential Marxist theorist. It discusses his background and early life in Sardinia, his political activism in Turin as a journalist and member of the Socialist Party, and his later work developing theories of cultural hegemony while imprisoned under Mussolini. His most famous writings were produced during his imprisonment in the Prison Notebooks.

Uploaded by

Hawaid Ahmad
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 20

Antonio Gramsci

First published Fri Jan 13, 2023


Antonio Gramsci (1891–1937) has been enormously influential as a Marxist theorist of
cultural and political domination in “developed” capitalism. However, his career was that of
a radical journalist and revolutionary organizer, not a professional philosopher. Gramsci was
a socialist activist, cultural commentator and, later, communist party leader in Italy. Most of
his writings are concerned with assessing the immediate political situation and, particularly,
the prospects for revolution in interwar Italy. Nonetheless, Gramsci was conversant with
philosophical currents of the time—especially Italian neo-idealism, native intellectual and
political traditions dating back to Machiavelli, and the major currents of Marxist thought. It
was only with his imprisonment by the Fascist authorities that he produced his most well-
known and philosophically rich texts: the Prison Notebooks. The insights therein account for
much of his posthumous recognition.
In the Notebooks, Gramsci undertook a series of historical and theoretical reflections on the
conditions for revolution in modern states—such as Italy’s—where degrees of popular
consent had been achieved. He employed the concept “hegemony” to describe a process of
“intellectual and moral leadership” that embedded a ruling class across society. He rejected
the economic determinism of classical Marxism in favor of a nuanced political analysis
attuned to contingent variation in historical circumstance. Gramsci brought Marxism into
dialogue with neo-idealist insights into practical subjectivity and he sketched a revolutionary
strategy aimed at preparing a new collective identity. Although fragmentary and open to
contrasting emphases, the Notebooks set out a radical philosophy of politics that has been of
enduring value to critical political and cultural theory.

• 1. Life and Political Activity


o 1.1 Sardinia (1891–1911)
o 1.2 Turin (1911–1922)
o 1.3 Moscow (1922–1923)
o 1.4 Vienna and Rome (1923–1926)
o 1.5 Prison (1926–1937)
• 2. Pre-Prison Journalism and Political Writings
o 2.1 Cultural Socialism
o 2.2 The Factory State
o 2.3 Communist Party Strategy
• 3. Prison Writings
o 3.1 Hegemony
o 3.2 State and Civil Society
o 3.3 The Theory of Intellectuals
o 3.4 Ideology and Common Sense
o 3.5 The Philosophy of Praxis
o 3.6 The Modern Prince
• 4. Reception of the Prison Writings
• Bibliography
o Primary Literature
o Secondary Literature
• Academic Tools
• Other Internet Resources
• Related Entries

1. Life and Political Activity


1.1 Sardinia (1891–1911)
Antonio Francesco Gramsci was born on 22 January 1891 in Ales, Sardinia to a middle-class
family of Albanian descent. Located in Italy’s southern Mezzogiorno, the island of Sardinia
shared the region’s arid landscape, widespread poverty, and fragile social hierarchies.
Gramsci was the fifth of seven children born to Giuseppina (née Marcia) and Francesco
Gramsci and spent his early childhood near Cagliari, where his family had moved in 1897. In
infancy he developed Pott’s Disease, a spinal form of tuberculosis that was not properly
treated and, as a result, he grew up with a “hunched” back. He suffered frequent health
problems throughout the rest of his life (Davidson 1977: 22–23).
His father, a local civil servant, was suspended from his job in 1898 on politically motivated
charges of corruption (he had supported an opposition candidate in local elections) and
subsequently sentenced to five years in prison (Davidson 1977: 23–25). This brought years
of terrible hardship for the family, who relocated to the town of Ghilarza. In 1903 the young
Antonio—known as “Nino”—even suspended his schooling to support his family by
working in a Land Registry office. On his return to education two years later, following his
father’s release, he progressed well. A reserved character but an avid reader with a strong
will, he entered high school in Cagliari, where he lived with his elder brother, Gennaro.
Gennaro introduced him to socialist literature, and he began to read Italian critics such as
Gaetano Salvemini, Giuseppe Prezzolini, and Benedetto Croce, as well as Karl Marx.
Gramsci shared many Sardinians’ deep resentment at the shortcomings of the “liberal” state
since its unification in the nineteenth century, especially its protectionist policies, which
contributed to the South’s cultural and economic underdevelopment.
In 1911 Gramsci won a monthly stipend to support his studies at the Carlo Alberto College at
the University of Turin in the northern region of Piedmont.

1.2 Turin (1911–1922)


Turin contrasted radically with Gramsci’s southern upbringing: it was an advanced industrial
city, dominated by the FIAT car factories and connected to wider European cultures. For
some years, Gramsci endured the precarious existence of an impoverished student; his
education was frequently interrupted by poverty, nervous exhaustion, and ill-health. At
university he studied philology, or linguistics, and worked under the guidance of the socio-
linguist Professor Matteo Bartoli, who was drawn to Gramsci’s native familiarity with
Sardinian dialect (see Ives 2004). Bartoli envisaged Gramsci becoming a linguist. Studying
in the Humanities, Gramsci’s own ambitions were, originally, to train as a teacher. At
university, he contributed to reviews with articles on Futurism (SCW: 46–49).
Gramsci did not formally complete his university studies. He abandoned education in 1915
and became a full-time journalist and socialist activist. Joining the Italian Socialist Party
(Partito socialista italiano, or PSI) in 1913, he became involved in worker’s education. Two
years later, he was offered a position as a journalist for the Turin edition of the PSI daily
newspaper, Avanti! Already a contributor to the weekly Il Grido del Popolo (“The People’s
Cry”), he accepted the offer and began writing political commentaries and theatre reviews
under a regular column, titled “Sotto la Mole” (“In the shadow of the Mole Antoniella”, a
landmark in Turin, designed originally as a synagogue, near to where Gramsci lodged). In
1917, he co-published a single issue socialist cultural review, aimed at young socialists,
entitled La Città futura (“City of the Future”).
The prospect of world war deeply split the Italian public and political parties into
“interventionists” and “neutralists”. The firebrand revolutionary socialist, Benito Mussolini,
came out for intervention against the PSI’s official neutrality. Entering the war, he hoped,
would initiate a wider collapse of the liberal order and ignite social revolution. Mussolini
was eventually forced out of the party. The young Gramsci was also tempted by that stance
and declared his preference not for intervention but for an “active neutrality” that took the
war as a moment to prepare for radical transformation (SPWI: 6–9). For this milder
resistance to the party’s formal position, he was thereafter treated with some suspicion by
fellow socialists.
Inspired by the Russian Revolutions of February and October 1917, Gramsci aligned himself
with the “intransigent revolutionary” faction in the PSI, urging it to pursue its “maximalist”
program of radical transformation. He became secretary of the executive committee of the
Turin socialists and, in the same year, took up the role of editor of Il Grido del Popolo. In
December 1917 he published “The Revolution Against Capital” in Avanti!, and used Il
Grido to publicize news and commentary on events in Russia, including texts by Lenin and
Trotsky (SPWI: 34–7). He made various efforts to organize a local proletarian cultural
association to galvanize political and economic struggles into a general revolutionary project,
although they did not take off.
After the war Gramsci joined with university and socialist friends to found and edit a new
review, L’Ordine Nuovo (“The New Order”). Intended, initially, as a journal of “socialist
culture” it became a medium to discuss the industrial factory struggles then underway in
Turin. In Ordine Nuovo, Gramsci presented a theory of a workers’ state inspired by the
efforts at self-management by skilled workers (see SPWI: 65–124). Spurred on by the
workers’ disputes and factory occupations across the years 1919 and 1920, he published
writings by syndicalist thinkers, participated in debates, and set out his own views on the
potential for the factories to become the locus of proletarian state institutions (see Clark
1977).
After the occupations ended in defeat, Gramsci aligned with the communist faction of the
PSI, calling for the party to be renewed as a revolutionary organization. In January 1921 in
Livorno, the communists formally split from the PSI and established the Communist Party of
Italy (Partito comunista d’Italia or PCd’I). Led by the militant, Amadeo Bordiga, the new
party required rigid discipline and had firm ideological roots in Marxist doctrine. Gramsci
was elected to its central committee and Ordine Nuovo was transformed into the party’s daily
paper.
The PCd’I remained too small to have any serious impact on events. Despite substantial
success in the 1919 elections, the now divided left were increasingly outwitted by the
maneuverings of Mussolini, and his “fascist” movement. Throughout 1921 and 1922, fascist
“squads” terrorized trade unions across the north of Italy, burning down their offices and
sending armed gangs to violently assault workers and peasants. In October 1922, Mussolini
was invited by the King to lead a coalition government, supported by conservative politicians
increasingly alarmed at the intensity of social disorder and the prospect of a workers’
revolution.

1.3 Moscow (1922–1923)


In June 1922 Gramsci was dispatched to Russia as the PCd’I delegate to the Executive
Committee of the Communist International (or “Comintern”) to participate in its Moscow
conference. Exhausted by the recent years of frenetic activity, he soon booked into a
sanatorium to recover his health. During that sojourn, he met Julija Schucht who in the next
year became his wife and, later, mother to his two sons.
In Moscow, Gramsci was absorbed into the bureaucratic complexities of international
communist politics, negotiating with the Comintern over the PCd’I’s relations to other left
parties. Events in both Russia and Italy compelled Gramsci to reconsider his position on
party tactics. In November, the fourth congress of the Comintern agreed that the PCd’I
should fuse with the PSI (which, by then, had expelled its own reformists and renewed its
links to the International). In truth, there was little enthusiasm among Italian communists for
this option and no real opportunity after Mussolini had taken power. Leading members of
each party (including Bordiga) were being persecuted by the regime and detained by the
police. From prison, Bordiga circulated a draft manifesto openly rejecting the policy of
fusion, but Gramsci—increasingly concerned at Bordiga’s open divergence from the
Comintern—refused to sign it, arguing later that he had “a different conception of the Party”
(GTW: 197).

1.4 Vienna and Rome (1923–1926)


Gramsci relocated to Vienna in late 1923 to open the PCd’I’s Foreign Bureau and maintain
closer links with events in Italy. There he began to articulate a conception of party tactics
that contrasted with Bordiga’s sectarian inclinations—under which, Gramsci claimed, “We
detach ourselves from the masses” (GTW: 159)—and began organizing a new leading group
with his comrades from Turin. Gramsci sought a United Front policy with other radical
organizations and parties in Italy to maintain a presence across the country—particularly in
the South—rather than simply await a crisis to hand leadership to the party. This view
brought him closer to the policy of the Comintern. In Vienna he initiated the publication of a
new daily party paper, L’Unità (“Unity”), aimed at an inclusive audience of “workers and
peasants”.
Gramsci was elected in April 1924 (in his absence) to the Italian Parliament, which granted
him immunity from prosecution. He returned to Italy in May and took part in the PCd’I’s
clandestine conference at Como. There he made clear his tactical differences with Bordiga,
although the majority remained aligned to Bordiga’s position. In the summer Gramsci took
over the role of party General Secretary (GTW: 321). The political situation in Italy
continued to intensify following the abduction and murder by fascist thugs of the socialist
deputy Giacomo Matteotti and the subsequent withdrawal in protest of opposition parties
from Parliament. Initially, public revulsion at the murder threatened to destabilize the regime
but the opposition gradually crumbled, and police harassment of anti-fascists continued.
In January 1926 the PCd’I held its third congress in Lyons, France. Gramsci’s conception of
party tactics finally won substantial support from the membership. The so-called “Lyons
Theses”, co-written by Gramsci and Togliatti, underscored the urgency of adapting strategy
to national conditions in Italy. With its partial capitalist development, extensive agrarian
sector, and the precarious “compromise” between the northern bourgeoisie and southern big
landowners, the unified state lacked a substantial popular base (see SPWII: 340–75).
Fascism, they argued, merely preserved the rule of these two classes by armed force and with
petty bourgeois support. The PCd’I, they continued, therefore needed to build mass support
among both workers and peasants so that, when a revolutionary situation eventually returned,
it could exercise effective leadership. In the meantime, Gramsci underscored the necessity of
a united front with other democratic parties (SPWII: 406–7).
Concerned at the growing divisions within the Soviet leadership between Stalin and Trotsky,
Gramsci wrote a letter in October 1926 underlining the danger this split posed to Russia’s
leading role in the communist movement (GTW: 369–76). However, Togliatti, who was
entrusted to pass on the letter to the Russian Central Committee, did not deliver it for fear of
causing greater friction.
Gramsci himself was now increasingly in danger in Italy where, despite formal immunity,
the regime increased its harassment of opposition parties as it transitioned into a full
authoritarian dictatorship. On 8 November 1926, Gramsci was arrested by the authorities and
placed in prison.

1.5 Prison (1926–1937)


To await trial Gramsci was transferred from Rome, via Naples and Sicily, to the island of
Ustica, where he was confined in a private house with other communists (including Bordiga).
In January 1927 he was conveyed to Milan, where he was placed in isolation and underwent
interrogation. Permitted to receive books and write two letters a week, Gramsci indicated
some potential writing projects in correspondence to his sister-in-law, Tatiana Schucht, who
remained in Italy during his imprisonment and became a vital source of support. He
suggested that he would like to write something “from a ‘disinterested’ standpoint, für ewig”
(“for eternity”, borrowing a phrase from Goethe) (GPL: 45). He was visited by his Turin
friend, Piero Sraffa (later a well-known Cambridge University economist), who helped
supply reading materials and acted as an interlocutor with Togliatti.
Eventually, in May 1928, a special tribunal was held in Rome. Gramsci was sentenced to 20
years, 4 months and 5 days in prison (but in 1932 the sentence was commuted to 12 years).
The prosecutor had remarked “We must stop this brain from functioning for twenty years”
(PPW: xxviii). Already in fragile health, he was transferred to the prison in Turi di Bari, in
the region of Apulia. Later—and despite the prosecutor—he was granted a cell of his own
and permission to read and write. The first of his Notebooks is dated 8 February 1929.
Life in prison was not easy. Gramsci’s health continued to deteriorate—he was badly
neglected by the prison authorities—and he suffered psychologically from his isolation. Yet
was he not entirely cut off from events outside. He received visits from Tatiana and from his
brothers, who (in addition to servicing his study needs and advocating on his behalf for
medical treatment) passed on news concerning the PCd’I and the Russian leadership. So, at
least initially, he was not wholly unaware of changing policies and strategic decisions. The
Comintern’s switch in policy from 1928—the so-called “Third Period”: abandoning the
united front tactic in favor of class insurrection, on the assumption that a crisis in capitalism
was imminent, denouncing potential socialist and social democratic parties as “social
fascists”—contrasted with Gramsci’s position supporting alliances. Gramsci’s criticism of
this new policy brought ostracism from other communist prisoners (Spriano 1977 [1979: 70–
1]).
Gramsci’s correspondence (like his Notebooks) was read by the prison authorities and subject
to censorship, meaning that political references to outside events had to be muted or entirely
absent. Nonetheless, he kept in regular contact with his wife and children (one of whom he
had never met), and his mother. His letters offer fascinating insight into his intellectual
interests, personal feelings, and health during incarceration (see GPL). He wrote stories for
his young sons and reminisced about his own childhood in Sardinia. Initially, with other
party members in the prison, he took part in reading groups and political conversations.
However, his declining health over the years encouraged supporters to request his release or
transfer to an infirmary. Gramsci refused to agree to his own conditional release if that meant
renouncing all political activity.
In 1933 he was finally moved to a clinic in Formia. He continued to write but less
productively and, after 1935, mostly correspondence. At Formia he eventually applied for
and was granted conditional freedom (which enabled him to leave the grounds in the
company of Tatiana). In August 1935 he moved to the “Quisisana” sanatorium in Rome
where he received visits from Sraffa and from his brothers, and where in April 1937 his
sentence finally expired. By that time, he was gravely ill. On the evening of 25 April 1937,
Gramsci suffered a cerebral hemorrhage. He died in the early hours of 27 April.
Gramsci’s funeral was held the next day and his ashes were kept locally until after the war,
when they were moved to the English Cemetery in Rome, where his grave remains. Tatiana
retrieved Gramsci’s thirty-three handwritten Notebooks; these were secured secretly in a
bank until the following year when they were smuggled to Moscow and passed on to the
PCd’I (Spriano 1977 [1979: 133–34]).

2. Pre-Prison Journalism and Political Writings


Gramsci’s overt “philosophical” references in his writings prior to the Notebooks are
sporadic and bound closely to his responses to wider events. He wrote as a committed
socialist and revolutionary critic, albeit as an intellectual skeptical of prevailing orthodoxies
(influenced, arguably, by his southern upbringing which made him something of an
“outsider” to mainstream progressive opinion). Like many Italian commentators, he shared
the view that the liberal state’s fundamental shortcoming consisted in a failure to build
popular and inclusive governing institutions. The task remained, therefore, “to make Italians”
(fare gli italiani) as one critic put it, that is, to find a model of association to culturally
integrate citizens (see Bellamy 1987). This general problem informs Gramsci’s pre-prison
writings as well as his later account of hegemony (see Bellamy & Schecter 1993).
The period up to Gramsci’s arrest was a dramatically evolving context of social and political
crisis in Italy and across Europe generally. Gramsci earned local recognition during and after
the war as a biting, “serious” radical journalist. He was acerbically critical of Italy’s ruling
elite and the bourgeoisie’s shallow moral sensibilities. For example, in 1918 he denounced
the widespread use of cocaine as “an index of bourgeois progress” and bemoaned the
absence, demonstrated by the Italian card game scopone, of a “concept of ‘fair play’” proper
to developed capitalist societies (see PPW: 72, 74). From the early 1920s, by contrast, his
audience was primarily party members, and his writing was steeped in the technical language
of revolutionary communist analysis.
Despite this shifting register, several related philosophical themes and influences can be
discerned that characterized his thinking throughout his pre-prison activities. These can be
summarized as:

1. a “humanist” opposition to scientific positivism


and materialist determinism for its neglect of the
subjective dimension to human action. Here he
was influenced by neo-idealist philosophers and
critics of the classical Marxist tradition, primarily
Benedetto Croce;
2. a radical insistence on the force of subjectively
motivated collective action, expressed as the
formation of a unified moral will. The most
popular source of this view in Italy was the
revolutionary syndicalist thinker, Georges Sorel;
and
3. a preference for collective self-liberation and a
rejection of authoritarian, elitist, or artificially
imposed systems of rule. Such views were
common among radical critics of the liberal state
and its protectionist policies, such as the socialist
reformer and analyst of southern
underdevelopment, Gaetano Salvemini.
These themes and influences combined in Gramsci’s criticism of the liberal political class
and his promotion of socialism. Three sequential phases of his pre-prison thinking can be
distinguished: his early cultural socialism (§2.1); his post-war theory of the factory-based
workers’ state (§2.2); and his later, developing reflections on communist party strategy
(§2.3).

2.1 Cultural Socialism


Gramsci’s early writing was informed by the influential critical framework of the neo-
Hegelian philosopher Benedetto Croce. Croce had denounced scientific positivism—
prevalent among social scientists and European Marxists—for its abstract, ahistorical
reasoning and emphasis on material “causes” in social change. Positivism neglected the
historically particular and practically creative dimension of “spirit” (or consciousness)
which, beyond any political program, motivated all social and cultural transformation. Croce
invited a view of Italy’s political failings as the absence of a robust, unifying culture—a
secular civic faith—rather than economic underdevelopment as such (see Croce 1914). He
inspired numerous “aesthetic” critics of the liberal state to understand socio-political
improvement as inseparable from free artistic self-creation, the assertion of moral will, and
the cultivation of a shared “inner” sensibility.
Gramsci admitted later to having been “tendentially somewhat Crocean” in his early writing
(FSPN: 355). For example, he endorsed the acquisition by workers of a “faith” based on
intellectual self-discipline and independence of thought, severely castigating any tendency to
passive “indifference” (SPWI: 17–18). Echoing Sorel, whose writings Croce had
championed, he presented socialism not as the outcome of historical “laws” but as “an
integral vision of life”, the adoption of an invigorating, moral consciousness to supplant the
failed bourgeois order (SCW: 22). In 1917 he welcomed the Russian Revolution as the
“revolution against Capital”, viewing it not as proof of Marx’s economic theories but as
evidence of the practical force of a collective will (SPWI: 34–7). Later, in 1918, Gramsci
offered his own idealist version of Marx, imagined as “a master of moral and spiritual life”
teaching the proletariat to become consciously aware of “its power and mission” in history
(PPW: 57, 56).
This somewhat ascetic, pedagogic humanism distinguished the young Gramsci from other
socialists who appealed to historical progress or invested in the slow, practical advance of
trade unionism and application of scientific reason. Gramsci regarded such appeals as rooted
in an elitist attitude aimed at bringing reform to the masses from on-high. Instead, he
endorsed a grass-roots self-organization that underscored the integrity and moral autonomy
of a uniquely proletarian worldview. This placed him closer to other radical critics of the
PSI, such as anarchists and syndicalists who also looked to a libertarian politics “from
below” (see Levy 1999).

2.2 The Factory State


The first original initiative for which Gramsci became known was his theory of factory-based
democracy, which he promoted during the so-called biennio rosso—or “two red years”—of
1919–1920.
Inspired by the industrial unrest and factory occupations in Turin and beyond, as well as by
the new “soviets” in Russia, Gramsci published in Ordine Nuovo various opinions and
resources on the topic of a nascent workers’ state (see SPWI: 65–124). His contributions
took his earlier humanism in a more concrete, practical direction. Efforts by workers to wrest
the management of production from industrialists—in part via “factory councils”, formerly
grievance committees—instantiated, for him, an initiative rooted in actual history, where a
new moral community was “spontaneously” expressing its own independent identity beyond
the limits of trade unionism. Focused on the practical planning and control of material
production, he claimed, the occupying workers were not responding passively to abstract
historical laws or to the directions of their leaders but, rather, acting as agents of their own
self-creation.
Gramsci sketched a model of industrial democracy in which a new type of state, based inside
the factories, would replace the discredited parliamentary regime. Free trade capitalism was
exhausted, and trade union organization had now reached its limit, he argued. Emerging
organically inside the factories were
institutions which will replace the person of the capitalist in his administrative functions and
his industrial power, and so achieve the autonomy of the producer in the factory. (SPWI: 77)
Rather than administer over isolated citizens by separating public authority from everyday
life—as under liberalism—the factory instantiated a new type of polity formed around the
collective material needs of production (see Schecter 1991). Gramsci envisaged a
participatory system of factory councils functioning in a hierarchical democratic system
through which workers would relay and manage the practical needs of national life.
Authority would be reconciled to liberty, not opposed to it, as under liberalism. The atomistic
individual would give way to the “producer”, an individual already psychologically and
organizationally oriented to the collective through its role in the labor process (SPWI: 110–
11).
Gramsci envisaged a system in which a communal identity had priority over individual
initiative. His was an “organic” model of state in which all parts related to the primary needs
of the whole. This was a potentially illiberal system that assumed substantive moral
agreement among workers (see Sbarberi 1986). Some see here the influence of the neo-
idealist (and soon fascist) philosopher, Giovanni Gentile. His radical philosophy of
“actualism”—in which the subject’s inner conscience creates its own unified world and
community—supported the idea of the “ethical state” (stato etico) in which public authority
and individual freedom, coercion and consent, were essentially indistinguishable (Gentile
1919; see also Schecter 1990). Such anti-liberal sentiments were common in the wake of the
war and chimed with widespread public disenchantment with elite-led parliamentary politics.

2.3 Communist Party Strategy


By the end of the occupations in 1920, Gramsci had already begun to shift away from
advocating workers’ self-liberation. For him, the complete absence of political leadership
from the PSI had undermined the occupations’ revolutionary potential. With the formation of
the PCd’I, he committed to a hierarchical, centralized leadership and strict ideological
discipline via a Bolshevik model of the revolutionary party. This new position was, arguably,
less a wholesale volte face than a realization that the PSI was culturally and organizationally
incapable of responding to the situation. Indeed, his understanding of the party’s role
continued to evolve thereafter. Nonetheless, his thinking from here onwards remained within
a “Leninist” frame of reference concerning revolutionary leadership, tactics, and
organization.
What is notable about Gramsci’s writings on party strategy in the period 1921–26 is not that
they offer a coherent or novel political theory but, rather, that they show he was developing
an independent position that echoed fragments of his earlier thinking. This involved: the
rejection of “formalistic” reasoning that neglected specific historical conditions; attention to
the Italian social structure and the distinctive, cultural-political role of “intellectuals”; and the
necessity of a mass-based party that incorporated the southern peasantry. These topics were
central points of reference in Gramsci’s mature thinking about hegemony in the Notebooks.
For Gramsci, the critique of formalism underscored his growing concern that the new party
wasn’t reading the “objective situation” but, rather, imposing a rigid view “deduced” from
abstract principle (SPWII: 360). The surprising success of fascism in mobilizing part of the
populace against the proletariat revealed just how intellectually and politically unprepared
communists had been. Gramsci now began to underline the view that the received model of
revolution—a violent seizure of power in the midst of a catastrophic crisis—needed to be
adapted to conditions that had not applied in Russia. As he noted in September 1926:
in the advanced capitalist countries, the ruling class possesses political and organizational
reserves which it did not possess, for instance, in Russia. (SPWII: 408)
Economic crises did not lead automatically to political instability because forces could be
found to support the regime. In peripheral states like Italy’s, he observed, “a broad stratum of
intermediary classes”—middle classes of various kinds—influenced the proletariat and the
peasantry, steering them away from revolution.
In his notes on the “Southern Question”, written just prior to his arrest, Gramsci also
explored the neglected problem of Italy’s South, which he described as “a great social
disintegration” (SPWII: 454). He noted the influence of southern intellectuals, such as
Benedetto Croce and Giustino Fortunato, in ideologically legitimating the liberal regime.
Croce, especially, had performed a “national function” by endorsing liberalism, helping to
prevent radical southern intellectuals from joining with peasants in opposition to the
conservative agrarian bloc. Although he believed it unlikely in the short term, Gramsci
argued the PCd’I needed to develop its own supporting intellectuals if it was to undertake an
inclusive national strategy to overcome the agrarian bloc.
Even within the constrained horizons of communist politics, then, Gramsci was beginning to
pose the question of revolution on a different plane than others in the movement. The
unplanned interruption brought by his arrest and imprisonment permitted him to explore
many of these issues in much greater depth.

3. Prison Writings
Gramsci’s Prison Notebooks (or Quaderni del carcere) comprise around three thousand
pages of thematically organized essays, observations and comments, written between 1929
and 1935 (see QC). A number of his notes were revised over time, which indicates they were
not written randomly but conformed, in part, to a plan. Recent research offers some clue as to
the logic and chronology of their drafting (see Francioni 1984). Nonetheless,
the Notebooks were not written for publication and, as a whole, they remain fragmentary
with no explicit guide as to how, or in even what order, the contents might be read.
In his earliest letters from detention, Gramsci indicated various themes that he hoped to
explore, including Italian intellectuals, comparative linguistics, the plays of Pirandello,
newspapers and other forms of “popular literature” (GPL: 45–6). Later he listed more
topics—including historiography, the development of the Italian bourgeoisie, the southern
question, common sense, and folklore.
These cultural and historical headings may appear uncontroversial. But they permitted
Gramsci to develop his wider thoughts on the practical and intellectual problems that had
preoccupied him prior to his arrest. That included: historical features of the Italian state;
theoretical concepts for analyzing the cultural and political conditions of class domination;
and the organizing principles and character of a revolutionary strategy. Freed from the
immediate constraints of tactical decisions and their repercussions, Gramsci drew on his
humanistic training to extend and deepen his understanding of these problems (see
Schwarzmantel 2015).

3.1 Hegemony
The concept often regarded as the locus of innovation in the Notebooks—and hence their
philosophical linchpin—is “hegemony” (egemonia), signifying both leadership and
domination.
Hegemony had been a common term in debates among Russian Marxists and usually
described the leading (or “hegemonic”) role of the working class over its allies in a political
coalition. But it had also been employed by Italian political thinkers in the nineteenth century
to imagine gradually building consent across the nation for the new state—“making
Italians”—rather than relying exclusively on the exercise of force. Gramsci fused these
meanings to present hegemony as the general hypothesis that a social class aims to achieve
consensual domination for its rule by progressively expanding its leadership across society
(see Femia 1981).
This idea—with its potential for variation in empirical focus and application—was developed
across different notes and topics, sometimes as a methodological device to analyze historical
situations, at other times alongside different concepts to make strategic observations. But it
also functioned more broadly as a philosophical horizon highlighting the inseparability of
thought and action, signaling that all intellectual enquiries were unavoidably implicated in
the formation of an integral “way of life”. Focusing on hegemony permits us to appreciate
the Notebooks as a unified intellectual project, despite their disparate themes and contrasting
accents.
The major themes of Gramsci’s ideas concerning hegemony are explored below, starting
with his “sociological” observations on the state, intellectuals, and ideology (§3.2–4), and
then looking at his theoretical reconstruction of Marxist philosophy (§3.5), and his
observations concerning the revolutionary party (§3.6).

3.2 State and Civil Society


Gramsci’s discussion of hegemony hinged, in part, on the empirical observation that
capitalist rule in developed western states, increasingly, is founded on the generation of
consent across civil society, not solely on the deployment of coercion via the army, police or
law courts.
Expanding on his suggestion from 1926 (see §2.3 above) that the ruling class had available to
it “political and organizational reserves”, Gramsci now argued that modern states since the
mid-nineteenth century have tended to cultivate consensual support—or hegemony—across
civil society such that coercion, or its threat, was no longer the primary form of rule, except
in “moments of crisis of command and direction when spontaneous consent has failed”
(SPN: 220–21).
Gramsci drew on a distinction, common in Italian political thought, between “force” and
“consent”. Hegemony referred to consent, although this was understood usually to be
balanced with force. Modern states aimed to absorb threats to their power by winning over
potentially hostile social groups and classes, compromising the immediate interests of the
dominant class to maintain general support. Such efforts may often be fragile or limited, but
that basic condition fundamentally altered the terrain of political contest. States could not be
reduced to mere administrative units of executive authority—that is, to a separate “political
society”—but were intertwined with a “sturdy structure of civil society”—schools, churches,
“private associations”, newspapers, intellectuals and so on (SPN: 238). Unlike in Russia—
where state power was strong and civil society weak (“primordial and gelatinous”)—modern
states utilize the “trenches” of civil society by exercising “civil hegemony” (SPN: 243). This
protected them from the threats to their rule caused by economic crises or civil disruption.
The state, then, was a complex structure combining both force and consent: it was both the
instrument by which a ruling class maintained its dominance over society and the medium
through which it undertook a “civilising activity”, functioning as an “ethical state” or
“educator” by promoting “a certain way of life” for its citizens (SPN: 247; see also SPN: 12).
At one point Gramsci formulated this as “State = political society + civil society (in other
words hegemony protected by the armour of coercion)”, or what he also called an “integral”
conception of the state.
Gramsci’s remarks elaborated his earlier rejection of an exclusively insurrectionary model of
revolution. In the Notebooks he was further suggesting that hegemony described a general
condition applicable to both bourgeois and proletarian forms of rule. Revolutionary
transformation—for any class—cannot be focused exclusively on the seizure of coercive and
bureaucratic power but must engage the state’s wider system of defenses. He referred to this
in the military terms that had become commonplace after the First World War as a switch
from a “war of manoeuvre”—a direct and violent assault on the forces of the state—to a “war
of position”—the gradual winning of tactical strongholds (SPN: 238–39). A revolutionary
project, he suggested, must first build consent across civil society before taking formal power
(SPN: 57). That did not mean that coercion would never be necessary, only that its status was
diminished in modern states.
Understanding variations in the exercise of hegemony required a political analysis attuned to
the “equilibrium” of force and consent at any conjuncture. In place of the common Marxist
division of economic “structure” and “superstructure”, Gramsci proposed the concept of a
“historical bloc” (blocco storico). This was a composite of distinct class and social forces
joined politically and culturally under a specific form of hegemony (SPN: 137). Additionally,
it was possible to gauge the extent to which a class had sacrificed its “economic corporate”
interests in expanding its leadership across civil society (SPN: 161). Empirical analysis of
hegemony would assess the “relations of forces” that combined structures and
superstructures in a historical situation (SPN: 181–85; for a discussion, see Bellamy &
Schecter 1993: ch. 6).
Gramsci explored various historical examples and concepts of political rule in the Notebooks.
In extensive notes on the Italian Risorgimento (the period of state building in the nineteenth
century) he highlighted the failure of the northern bourgeoisie to develop an extensive
hegemonic leadership by incorporating “subaltern” social classes in the South (see SPN: 52–
120). He borrowed the concept of “passive revolution” to describe this situation in which a
change in economic structure occurs but without a radical political transformation; this was a
concept he also suggested could describe Fascism (SPN: 105–20).
3.3 The Theory of Intellectuals
Intellectuals formed a major theme of the Notebooks and developed Gramsci’s brief
observations on the topic prior to his arrest. Intellectuals, he noted,
are the dominant group’s “deputies” exercising the subaltern functions of social hegemony
and political government. (SPN: 12)
As such, they were key agents in the state’s connection to civil society.
To understand their role in organizing consent, he argued, it was necessary to expand the
concept of intellectual. Rather than refer to academics or artists, who work explicitly with
ideas, the category comprised all those whose social function was to communicate with, and
educate, non-specialists (SPN: 9). Those undertaking the function of intellectuals included
industrial technicians, managers, entrepreneurs, bureaucrats, and scientists. Gramsci
distinguished between “organic” and “traditional” types: organic intellectuals emerged from
a specific social class and functioned to elaborate that class’s productive activity as a set of
general principles; traditional intellectuals, such as philosophers or the clergy, were remnants
of a former historical stage who retained social prestige but no longer directly served a
productive class. Intellectuals were therefore rooted in material relations of production but
undertook the “critical elaboration” of that activity into a “new and integral conception of the
world” (SPN: 9).
The construction of hegemony, Gramsci underlined, would require both the elaboration of
new organic intellectuals and the assimilation of traditional intellectuals. He noted that his
work with Ordine Nuovo in Turin had already involved developing new forms of
“intellectualism” among skilled workers who constituted, in his view, the organic
intellectuals of a future communist society (SPN: 9–10). In his notes on “Americanism and
Fordism”, he explored this theme in modern rationalized and mechanized production
systems, still with little optimism that proletarian organic intellectuals were ready to promote
a new worldview (SPN: 279–318). Notably, Gramsci devoted considerable attention to an
assessment of Croce, a traditional intellectual with an unparalleled “role in Italian life”
(FSPN: 360), comparable “with that of the Pope in the Catholic world” (FSPN: 469; see also
SPN: 94–95).

3.4 Ideology and Common Sense


Gramsci’s attention to intellectuals connected to his reflections on popular consciousness and
its practical organization in, for example, religion, education, language, and folklore (see
FSPN: 1–137, 138–60; SPN: 26–43; SCW: 167–95). Popular attitudes, he underlined—
drawing on his linguistic training—should not be dismissed but, rather, understood as part of
how ordinary people lived and experienced their world (see Ives 2004). They were also the
medium through which hegemony was exercised.
The tendency among Marxists to diminish “ideology and politics”, reducing them to an
immediate expression of an economic structure, was dismissed by Gramsci as “primitive
infantilism” (SPN: 407). Instead, ideology should be grasped as a conception of the world
that “serves to cement and unify” human practice (SPN: 328). It had a lived “psychological”
validity that enabled people to become conscious of their practical situations, however
inadequately (SPN: 377). It was therefore important to explore and understand that practical
function. Gramsci did this in his remarks on “common sense” (senso comune).
Common sense—popular attitudes and beliefs, frequently accepted as “eternal” truths by
ordinary people—denoted, for Gramsci, a largely uncritical and “fragmentary” mode of
consciousness (SPN: 419). Consisting of superstitions and forms of “folklore” concerning the
nature of reality and ethical conduct, common sense was a “philosophy of the popular
masses”, often born from religion, that differentiated “simple” folk from educated
intellectuals. Its danger was that it tended to invite resignation and passivity rather than
collective action. That was a problem for what Gramsci referred to as “subaltern” groups—
marginalized and subordinate classes such as the peasantry and the proletariat—who, despite
periodic rebellions, never adequately challenge dominant classes (see Green 2002). Yet,
common sense thinking often had a “healthy nucleus” in “good sense”, that is, in the
practical and realistic attitudes that could be made “more coherent and unitary” (SPN: 328) if
joined to a systematic and critical conception of the world. It was necessary not to dismiss
common sense thinking (nor the struggles of subaltern groups) but to critically engage the
“contradictory consciousness” of ordinary people (SPN: 326)—that is, the tendency to hold
beliefs contradicted by actual conduct—and educate it.
Gramsci understood that educative task to belong to intellectuals—not merely to advance a
superior and abstract philosophy but to work on common sense, thereby “renovating and
making ‘critical’ an already existing activity” (SPN: 331). A hegemonic worldview had to
connect to the “simple” to become embedded in everyday life. The past success of traditional
intellectuals in this regard explained the ongoing influence of the Catholic Church in Italy.

3.5 The Philosophy of Praxis


The Notebooks present an extensive critique of what Gramsci saw as the prevailing
orthodoxy in Marxist philosophy. Exemplary here was the analysis by the Russian
philosopher and economist, Nikolai Bukharin, in his Theory of Historical Materialism: A
Popular Manual of Marxist Sociology (published in 1921), a text Gramsci had utilized in
party schools. Gramsci now rejected Bukharin’s treatment of Marxism as a deterministic
science of society and used his text as a foil to present an alternative account of historical
materialism that he labelled the “philosophy of praxis”, following the late nineteenth century
Hegelian Marxist philosopher, Antonio Labriola. Gramsci probably used Labriola’s term to
evade the prison censor but, undoubtedly, it captured the primacy he gave to practical,
political questions in his approach to theorizing. He saw Marxism as a philosophy aimed at
critically engaging popular common sense, laying the basis for a new hegemony.
The Popular Manual, as Gramsci referred to it, demonstrated the worst of what he called
“vulgar materialism” (SPN: 407). It reduced Marxism to a search for the causal laws of
social evolution and accepted, without reflection, the positive sciences as the sole model of
knowledge. It took up a speculative “method” positioned outside of history to observe
supposedly “objective” mechanical regularities and to make predictions about their
development (see SPN: 425–40). This view was mistaken for various reasons: instead of
treating Marxism as an original philosophy, it subordinated it to the natural sciences; it failed
to grasp the “dialectic” in Marxism, which underscored the critical struggle against
established thought (SPN: 434–35); and it separated thought from action, “science and life”,
and therefore divided intellectuals with knowledge from the experiences of “the great
popular masses” (SPN: 442).
To remedy these defects, Gramsci argued that Marxism, or historical materialism, be
understood as a philosophy rooted in history, as an expression of the practical struggle to
rethink those circumstances anew. As such it “contains in itself all the fundamental elements
to construct a total and integral conception of the world” (SPN: 462). Thought and action
should be understood as dialectically intertwined in a developmental process that can “bring
into being a new form of State […] a new intellectual and moral order […] a new type of
society” (SPN: 388). Historical materialism was not an abstract framework from which
merely to observe historical change; it was the philosophical vehicle whose expansion into a
cultural outlook aimed to bring about that change (see FSPN: 395–96). Gramsci affirmed
Labriola’s designation of Marxism as a “philosophy of praxis” because it insisted on the
unity of thought and action (praxis)—and, through that, the gradual formation of an
autonomous moral and cultural worldview—as the guiding principle of Marx’s philosophy
(SPN: 388).
Gramsci also proposed that Croce’s idealism could be of “instrumental value” to a renewed
philosophy of praxis. Influenced by Marxism, Crocean historicism conceived thought and
expression as entirely “immanent” to history, that is, as responses to concrete problems,
undetermined by any transcendent scheme or teleology. Croce presented “liberty” as the
unifying ethical principle expressing this historicist sensibility; the basis to what he
conceived as a modern religion. Gramsci acknowledged that Croce had
forcefully drawn attention to the importance of cultural and intellectual factors in the
development of history […] to the moment of hegemony and consent. (FSPN: 357)
Yet, he claimed, Croce also erased class conflict in his historical writing, emphasizing only
periods of liberal hegemony—the consensual, ethical aspects of history and not the violence
or political struggles that ushered in bourgeois society, such as the French Revolution (SPN:
119; see also GPL: 213–14, 215–16). By contrast, a philosophy of praxis would build on
Croce’s insights, focusing instead on “ethico-political” history—the socio-economic
divisions that bring, dialectically, a new culture into existence—without his partial, liberal
gloss. It would vigorously critique received common sense beliefs, philosophies, and
hierarchies that prevented the advance of ordinary people (SPN: 330–31). Gramsci described
the philosophy of praxis as an “absolute ‘historicism’, the absolute secularisation and
earthliness of thought” (SPN: 465).
In rejecting the scientific model of knowledge in favor of a form of historical consciousness,
Gramsci radically shifted Marxism’s epistemological bearings. The measure of historical
materialism lay not exclusively in the immediate empirical “truth” of its propositions or
predictions but, moreover, in the cultural and political efficacy of its overall intellectual and
moral reform, which enabled creative subjective engagement with objective conditions: “it is
a philosophy which is also politics” (SPN: 395). He suggested that mass “adhesion or non-
adhesion to an ideology is the real critical test of the rationality and historicity of modes of
thinking”, not just direct correspondence of theory to an independent reality (SPN: 341); and
that “prediction” was not so much “a scientific act of knowledge” as “the abstract expression
of the effort made, the practical way of creating a collective will” (SPN: 438). Gramsci
compared the philosophy of praxis to the Protestant Reformation in so far as its success
resided in generating cultural agreement to cement civil and political unity (SPN: 395).
Gramsci was not suggesting that truth was only a matter of shared agreement. The
philosophy of praxis still aligned to the foundational Marxist principle that social
consciousness “corresponds” to material relations of production, knowledge of which was
necessary for any practical effort. Marxism therefore required “the critique of ideologies”
which “tend to hide reality” (FSPN: 396) and, in this, it sought to bring thought and action
into rational correspondence. But the philosophy of praxis could achieve that only if it were
grasped as a form of politics, not an abstract science.
These comments are consistent with Gramsci’s general line of argument in the Notebooks on
the strategic importance of building consent prior to revolution. They indicate that such a
strategy was not a momentary, tactical initiative. It aligned with his aspiration for a cultural
transformation over the longer term. His focus on the subjective, “superstructural” element of
class politics certainly put Gramsci at odds with more objectivist accounts of Marxism, but it
was far from an aversion to the reality of “structural” and empirical constraints (see Morera
1990). Whatever its shortcomings as a generalizable Marxist theory, Gramsci’s philosophy
of praxis was in keeping with his attempt to conceive revolutionary politics as the
preparation of a “total, integral civilisation” (SPN: 462; see Thomas 2009).

3.6 The Modern Prince


Gramsci still considered the agent of a revolution to be, by necessity, a centralized and
ideologically disciplined party. But now he presented the party as the vehicle of a “total and
integral conception of the world” that, in advance of the revolution itself, would organize
across civil society.
The character of the revolutionary party, for Gramsci, could be grasped by reference to
Niccolò Machiavelli’s treatise on political leadership, The Prince. The figure of the prince
combined in one person both tactical calculation and an ambition to lead the people in
building a state (see SPN: 125). That image of leadership, Gramsci continued, was later
exemplified in Georges Sorel’s notion of “myth”, that is, a motivating ideal or “concrete
phantasy which acts on a dispersed and shattered people to arouse and organise its collective
will” (SPN: 126). Elaborating and diffusing “conceptions of the world” was what modern
political parties were designed to do (SPN: 335). Gramsci’s reflections on communist party
strategy were therefore formulated as a treatise on what he conceived as “The Modern
Prince” (il moderno Principe).
Drawing from the experience of the French Revolution, a modern Prince (or revolutionary
party) must present itself as the type of “Jacobin force” which then had “awakened and
organised the national-popular collective will, and founded the modern States” (SPN: 131).
Its strategy could not be oriented exclusively to the moment of revolutionary rupture but,
moreover, “to the question of intellectual and moral reform, that is to the question of religion
or world-view” (SPN: 132). The party’s aim was to realize “a superior, total form of modern
civilisation” rooted in economic relations (SPN: 133). Yet the “national-popular” dimension
required it to do this by transcending the corporate interests of one class alone, presenting its
goals on a “universal plane”: “thus creating the hegemony of a fundamental group over a
series of subordinate groups” (SPN: 182). The party would lead by making itself the
repository of popular common sense, gathering the support of allied intellectuals, and
developing its own distinct worldview built on the philosophy of praxis. Gramsci’s
conception of the party’s role, therefore, went beyond a temporary or mechanical alliance of
separate classes; it meant mobilizing a wholly new and inclusive vision of modern society.
The modern Prince was to be organized in such a way as to maintain contact with workers,
but also to ensure disciplined leadership. It would be a party of “ordinary, average men”,
with a leadership “endowed with great cohesive, centralising and disciplinary powers”, and
an “intermediate element” to keep the two in mutual contact (SPN: 152–53). The party
would thus be a mass-based organization under firm direction. To ensure “organic”
discipline, Gramsci endorsed the principle of “democratic centralism” whereby decisions
would be open to discussion by rank-and-file members. But, once taken, those decisions
would be unquestioningly obeyed. That way “bureaucratic” rigidity would be avoided and
there would be a continual adaptation of the organisation to the real movement; a matching
of thrusts from below with orders from above. (SPN: 188)
This hybrid of classically “Leninist” and mass-based models of the party reflected Gramsci’s
concern to steer a course between sectarian closure and reformist, representational politics.
Gramsci was not optimistic that ordinary members could participate effectively without
strong direction from a disciplined cadre, however much he thought revolution would
eventually overcome the separation of leaders and led (SPN: 144). Hegemonic strategy
inevitably meant creating a new leading elite (SPN: 340) whose superior philosophy would
“in the masses as such, […] only be experienced as a faith” (SPN: 339). Although some see
in Gramsci’s politics the basis of a radically democratic politics (Sassoon 1987), his was not
a particularly liberal conception (see Femia 1981: 172–85).

4. Reception of the Prison Writings


Gramsci’s prison writings were first published in Italy after the Second World War: his
letters from prison in 1947 (see GLP), winning the Viareggio literary prize that year; and
his Notebooks in six, thematic volumes of selections between 1948 and 1951. A complete,
“critical” edition of the Notebooks (in four volumes) was published in 1975 (see QC).
The distance in time since their drafting, and the fragmented nature of the texts themselves,
meant that the prison writings did not directly address the new environment into which they
emerged. The meaning and implications of his thinking were therefore heavily mediated by
national and geopolitical concerns through which, inevitably, the Notebooks were read. Over
time—as his writings became available and scholarship on his thought improved—
recognition of his distinctiveness as a thinker has grown around the world. Gramsci’s
account of hegemony, especially, has been a highly effective resource for cultural and
political analysis (see Martin 2022).
Where precisely did Gramsci’s philosophical innovations lie for his later readers? Over the
years, different, interpretations of Gramsci have tended to emphasize competing aspects of
his thought as its philosophical “core” (see Liguori 2012 [2022]).
The initial reception of Gramsci’s writings was shaped by the Italian Communist Party
(Partito comunista italiano, or PCI), particularly by its leader since the mid-1920s, Palmiro
Togliatti, who emphasized their significance for a renewed communist strategy. To
demonstrate allegiance to Stalin and the USSR, Togliatti presented an “acceptable” version
of Gramsci that suited the PCI’s cautious post-war politics. Selective editing of
the Notebooks downplayed overt conflict with Stalin, emphasizing Gramsci’s continuity with
the Soviet philosophical orthodoxy of “dialectical materialism” and a Leninist model of
revolution. However, following Stalin’s death in 1953 Togliatti underscored Gramsci’s
unique formulation of Marxism and his continuity with native Italian currents of philosophy.
This endorsed Togliatti’s own view of the PCI as a pragmatic, mass-based party pursuing its
own “Italian road to socialism”; operating as a “collective intellectual” to mobilize the
proletariat and its allies in a uniquely national and democratic project (see Togliatti 1979).
Now a canonical figure in Italian Marxism, Gramsci’s reading of history—particularly his
view of the Risorgimento as a failed bourgeois revolution—was called into question in the
late 1950s. In one notable debate, liberal historian Rosario Romeo disputed that economic
conditions could have permitted the nineteenth-century bourgeoisie to act as a “Jacobin”
force by mobilizing the peasantry and other subaltern classes. Gramsci’s reasoning (and, by
extension, the PCI’s sense of its distinctive national strategy) was premised on a moral and
political, rather than genuinely objective, interpretation of history (Liguori 2012 [2022: 121–
23]; Davis 1979).
Although Romeo’s critique was disputed by Gramscian historians, from the 1960s, as more
of his writings were published and translations became available, Gramsci was increasingly
read independently of (and in opposition to) the PCI’s strategic concerns (see Mouffe 1979).
His seemingly “heretical” formulation of Marxist theory came to occupy his readers,
especially as regards his debt to Crocean historicism, his ambiguous relation to materialism
and to Leninism (see Bobbio 1979). More widely, Gramsci’s exploration of cultural and
political superstructures resulted in a tendency to categorize him as a “western” Marxist,
concerned less with economic conditions or coercion and more with ideological barriers to
class consciousness (see Anderson 1976, 1976–77). Hegemony was associated with a general
theory of cultural and ideological domination relevant to the critique of consumer capitalism.
Through the late 1960s and 70s, as western states experienced economic and ideological
crises, Gramsci’s analyses were applied separately from communist strategy or philosophical
idealism. Marxist sociologists such as Nicos Poulantzas (1968 [1973]) and, later, Bob Jessop
(1990) found in hegemony a resource to explore the permutations of the capitalist state and
its shifting class coalitions. British Cultural Studies—especially the work of Raymond
Williams and Stuart Hall—saw in Gramsci an inventive, “cultural Marxist” framework for
examining popular lived experience of class domination. Debates over the functions of mass
media and populist ideology, particularly with the emergence of “Thatcherism” in the 1980s,
were uniquely attuned to the dynamics of hegemonic politics suggested in Gramsci’s
writings (see Hall 1988; Jessop et al. 1988).
“Post-Marxist” approaches to hegemony from the 1980s built on the established popularity
of Gramsci’s thought, particularly its application in the field of ideology studies. Ernesto
Laclau and Chantal Mouffe’s Hegemony and Socialist Strategy (1985) recast hegemony as
the theoretical basis to a strategy of “radical democracy”, aimed at unifying multiple and
diverse social struggles. Drawing on “poststructuralist” philosophies, hegemony was
conceived as a general principle of “discursive articulation”—the contingent formation of a
collective identity—with no “necessary” foundation in economic class. For them, Gramsci’s
core philosophical insight lay in demonstrating hegemony’s political “logic”, rather than any
sociological concerns. They sought to discard the residual economism in his thinking and
thus the automatic privilege granted by Marxism to class agency in hegemonic politics. In
their view, various hegemonic formations co-exist, and a radical democratic politics does not
require working class leadership.
Gramsci’s Notebooks continued to attract scholarly interest after the demise of the Soviet
Union and the dissolution of the PCI. Recent approaches have been drawn, increasingly, to
the nuances and inflections in his analyses, often neglected in the tendency to focus on
“hegemony” and its relation to Marxist theory. While the concept remains important, there is
growing appreciation of other themes in Gramsci’s philosophy of politics and their relevance
to a variety of fields. His ideas remain a source of insight for non-orthodox Marxisms (see
Thomas 2009), and his concepts have been extended to academic fields such as International
Relations and Global Political Economy (see Gill 1993) and to socio-political contexts
beyond Europe and the “West” (see Morton 2007; Fonseca 2016). Gramsci’s own experience
as an internal migrant who “looked at modernity from the bottom of its peripheries”
(Urbinati 1998: 371), and his particular attention to the struggles of “subaltern” classes in the
formation of national cultures, have inspired forms of postcolonial literary criticism and
politics quite at odds with the communist frame in which his ideas originated (see Srivastava
& Bhattacharya 2012).

You might also like