01 - The Behavior of Animal Mechanisms, Functions and Evolution
01 - The Behavior of Animal Mechanisms, Functions and Evolution
List of Tables
Chapter 2
Table 2.1 Invariance in Gestalt perception...
Table 2.2 From heterogeneous summation...
Table 2.3 Feature discrimination causes dishabituation.
Table 2.4 Command neuron hypothesis.
Table 2.5 Constants α and β...
Table 2.6 Minimum number of cell types...
Chapter 8
Table 8.1 Experimental designs in classical conditioning
Chapter 10
Table 10.1 Three Conceptions of Animal...
Chapter 11
Table 11.1 Payoffs to the row player...
contributors
Professor Gregory F. Ball
Department of Psychology
University of Maryland
2141 Tydings Hall
7343 Preinkert Drive
College Park, MD 20742
USA
Professor Jacques Balthazart
University of Liege
GIGA Neurosciences
Quartier Hôpital
15 Avenue Hippocrate
Tour Pharmacie (Bat. B36, 1er étage)
B-4000 Liège
Belgium
Professor Johan J. Bolhuis
Cognitive Neurobiology
Department of Psychology
Utrecht University
PO Box 80.086
Yalelaan 2
3584 CM Utrecht
The Netherlands
Professor Gillian R. Brown
School of Psychology & Neuroscience
University of St. Andrews
South Street
St. Andrews, Fife, KY16 9JP
United Kingdom
Dr Harald Burghagen†
Universität Kassel
Fachbereich Naturwissenschaften
Abteilung Zoologie/Physiologie, Neurobiologie
Heinrich-Plett-Str. 40
D-34132 Kassel
Germany
Dr Catharine P. Cross
School of Psychology & Neuroscience
University of St. Andrews
South Street
St. Andrews, Fife, KY16 9JP
United Kingdom
Professor Dr Jörg-Peter Ewert
Universität Kassel
Fachbereich Naturwissenschaften
Abteilung Zoologie/Physiologie, Neurobiologie
Heinrich-Plett-Str. 40
D-34132 Kassel
Germany
Professor David Fraser
Animal Welfare Program
Faculty of Land and Food Systems
University of British Columbia
2357 Main Mall
Vancouver, British Columbia
Canada V6T 1Z4
Professor Luc-Alain Giraldeau
Institut national de la recherche scientifique
490, rue de la Couronne
Québec QC
Canada G1K 9A9
Professor Geoffrey Hall
Department of Psychology
University of York
York YO10 5DD
United Kingdom
Professor Robert A. Hinde, FRS†
St. John’s College
Cambridge CB2 1TP
United Kingdom
Professor Jerry A. Hogan
Department of Psychology
University of Toronto
Toronto, Ontario
Canada M5S 3G3
Professor Kimberly Kirkpatrick
Director, Cognitive and Neurobiological Approaches to Plasticity
Center
Department of Psychological Sciences
Kansas State University
496 Bluemont Hall
Manhattan, KS 66506
USA
Professor Kevin N. Laland
Centre for Biological Diversity
School of Biology
University of St. Andrews
Sir Harold Mitchell Building
St. Andrews
Fife KY16 9TF
United Kingdom
Professor Ralph E. Mistlberger
Department of Psychology
Simon Fraser University
8888 University Drive
Burnaby, British Columbia
Canada V5A 1S6
Dr Anders Pape Møller
Directeur de Recherche
Ecologie Systématique Evolution
Université Paris-Saclay
CNRS, AgroParisTech
F-91405 Orsay Cedex
France
Professor Pierre-Olivier Montiglio
Groupe de Recherche en Ecologie Comportementale et Animale
Département des Sciences Biologiques
Université du Québec à Montréal
CP 8888, succursale centre-ville
Montréal, Québec,
Canada H3C 3P8
Professor Stephen Nowicki
Department of Biology
Duke University
130 Science Drive
Durham, NC 27708
USA
Professor Denis Réale
Groupe de Recherche en Ecologie Comportementale et Animale
Département des Sciences Biologiques
Université du Québec à Montréal
CP 8888, succursale centre-ville
Montréal, Québec,
Canada H3C 3P8
Professor Benjamin Rusak
Departments of Psychiatry and Psychology & Neuroscience
Dalhousie University
5909 Veterans Memorial Lane
Halifax, Nova Scotia
Canada B3H 2E2
Professor Michael J. Ryan
Department of Integrative Biology
University of Texas
Austin, TX 78712
USA
Professor William A. Searcy
Department of Biology
University of Miami
Coral Gables, FL 33124
USA
Professor David F. Sherry
Advanced Facility for Avian Research
Departments of Psychology and Biology
Western University
1393 Western Road
London, ON
Canada N6G 1G9
Professor Ian Tattersall
Division of Anthropology
American Museum of Natural History
New York, NY 10024
USA
Professor Daniel M. Weary
Animal Welfare Program
Faculty of Land and Food Systems
University of British Columbia
2357 Main Mall
Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada V6T 1Z4
foreword
ROBERT A. HINDE
Writing a foreword for such a stimulating series of chapters, which
represent the state of animal behavior studies at this time, is a
considerable responsibility. Perhaps I can do best by looking not
forward, as might seem appropriate, but backward, and thus attempt
to provide a context for the chapters that follow. Of course it cannot
be a fully objective backward view, because I am looking from where
I am now, and what I see is biased by my own experience. It is bound
also to involve simplification. But I hope that it will provide a useful
perspective.
In the early decades of the twentieth century, most studies of animal
behavior fell into two groups. In one were the naturalists, mostly
amateurs, without scientific pretensions but with a long tradition
stretching back beyond the nineteenth century. In the other were the
psychologists, producing an increasing body of data and theory
mostly concerned with learning processes. Of course this dichotomy
is already unjust and simplistic. Darwin himself could be called a
naturalist; and an originator of learning theory (J.B. Watson) started
from naturalistic observation. However, the work of the learning
theorists, impressive in its own right, was not to have much impact
on the traditions that led to the chapters in this book until much
later.
Those traditions can be said to stem from the emergence of ethology
in the 1930s. This was due to Lorenz, an Austrian MD with a PhD in
comparative anatomy, and Tinbergen, a Dutch zoologist who moved
to England a few years after the end of World War 2. Both men had a
passionate interest in animals, but this was expressed in very
different ways. Lorenz kept a menagerie of diverse animals in his
home, though also studying the local jackdaws and the semi-tame
geese that he reared. Tinbergen, by contrast, was a dedicated field
naturalist. Although he later worked with captive animals, it was
always with problems that he had brought in from the field, and he
liked best to be in the field himself. Tinbergen’s first pupil, Baerends,
suggested that the contrast lay in their attitudes to their subjects:
Tinbergen saw himself as a nonparticipant hidden observer of
animals, Lorenz as an adopted alien member and protector. Lorenz
was a thinker who tried to relate or contrast his observations with
current biological and philosophical views, while Tinbergen was
much more empirical, an experimenter as well as an observer.
But both rejected the vitalist view that the phenomena of “instinct”
were unanalysable and the misuse of the Gestalt concept to imply
that analysis is unnecessary because the whole is always more than
the sum of its parts. They also rejected the focus of most learning
theorists on the input/output relations of the whole organism, with
neglect of the “physiological machinery,” and the sterility of the
artificial environments used to study animals in many psychological
laboratories.
The term “ethology” has been applied primarily to the work of
students who, though differing widely in the problems they tackled,
the methods they used, the level of analysis at which they worked,
and the theoretical interpretations (if any) that they adopted, shared
certain orienting attitudes. They insisted that the proper description
of behavior is a necessary preliminary to its analysis; and that the
behavior of an animal must be studied in relation to the environment
to which it has become adapted in evolution. In addition they held
that full understanding of behavior required knowledge not only of
its development and causation but also of its biological function and
its evolution. The result was a vast amount of data on the behavior of
animals and a certain amount of model-building to elucidate the
mechanisms underlying behavior. In 1973 Lorenz and Tinbergen
(together with von Frisch) were awarded the Nobel Prize in
Physiology and Medicine.
Although ethology was primarily a European phenomenon in the
early postwar years, two research workers in the USA were to have a
considerable influence on its development, though in very different
ways. Beach, a behavioral endocrinologist interested primarily in the
hormonal control of sexual behavior, met Tinbergen in the USA and
became a powerful supporter of ethology. Schneirla, a comparative
psychologist working at the American Museum of Natural History,
was intensely critical. One of his students, Lehrman, published a
hard-hitting critique of ethology in 1953. There were three main
issues. Lehrman and Schneirla took exception to Lorenz’s distinction
between “innate” and “acquired” behavior as neither empirically
valid nor heuristically valuable. They objected to the energy model of
motivation that Lorenz used, though this also came in for criticism
from within ethology. And both were unhappy about the ethologists’
tendency to apply concepts across a wide range of species differing in
their levels of cognitive capacity. On their side, the ethologists felt
that the adjective in “comparative psychology” was a sham, for
contrasting distantly related species did not constitute comparison in
a biological sense. They were also unhappy about the manner in
which many comparative psychologists (though not so much those
influenced by Schneirla) generalized on the basis of studies of a few
mammalian species, predominantly the laboratory rat. For a while
the differences between the two groups seemed irreconcilable.
However, soon after his critique was published, Lehrman came to
Europe and met a number of European ethologists. Tinbergen,
Lorenz, and Lehrman were all bird watchers, with a passionate
enthusiasm for natural history. Lehrman had an infectious geniality,
and friendships were soon made. This brought about a
rapprochement between ethology and many of the members of
Schneirla’s group, a rapprochement that came not so much from
academic discussion, but from the compatibility of personalities. On
the issue of ontogeny, both sides changed their emphasis, the
comparative psychologists withdrawing from their extreme emphasis
on experience, and the differences in approach to the “comparative”
issue were recognized.
It seems to happen not infrequently in the history of science that
those regarded as originating a branch of science are subsequently
seen to have been wrong in many of their generalizations. For
instance, Freud (psychoanalysis) used a misleading model of
motivation, Piaget (developmental psychology) based generalizations
on a tiny sample of subjects, and Jeffreys (geophysics) refused to
accept the evidence for continental drift. This was also the case with
ethology. Many of the concepts that had been invaluable tools in the
early days of ethology—the “innate releasing mechanism” and “fixed
action pattern” for instance—were subsequently seen to involve
oversimplification, and now seldom figure in the literature. But not
surprisingly the change in outlook was not adopted simultaneously
by all ethologists, and this led to some divisions within ethology.
Lorenz, whose influence was particularly strong in Germany and the
USA (through two research workers who had worked with him, Hess
and Barlow), was slower to relinquish the innate/acquired
dichotomy and energy model of motivation than Tinbergen and
workers in the Netherlands and the UK.
An issue important for the nature/nurture debate became prominent
in the 1960s. Both Tinbergen and Lorenz had long argued on the
basis of empirical evidence that species were specially equipped for
particular learning tasks that were biologically important for them.
Thorpe’s book on birdsong, published in 1961, showed that the
chaffinch was predisposed to learn the species-characteristic song
pattern. A few years later, Rozin, Garcia, and others demonstrated a
predisposition to avoid toxins in mammals. Such findings were
directly contrary to the orientation of the learning theorists, who
were searching for laws of learning valid for all species and all
situations. It thus became apparent that, in many cases, what was
“innate” was a predisposition to learn some things in particular
contexts. This was to be of special importance for the study of human
behavior.
Lorenz, originally a comparative anatomist, had used species
differences and similarities as a taxonomic tool, and Tinbergen had
always had an interest in the function of behavior. But, of the four
problems of causation, development, function, and evolution, the
main (though by no means the only) emphasis in ethology had been
on the first two. In the 1970s this changed with the publication of
Wilson’s Sociobiology. The orienting attitudes of ethology continued
but the motivational models disappeared and many of the old
concepts fell into disuse. Behavioral ecology came to the fore, and
new theoretical approaches made possible the study of function in a
quantitative fashion. Data on foraging behavior were compared with
the behavior to be expected (on certain assumptions that were not
always made fully explicit) from an organism foraging with maximal
efficiency. Later, attention turned to such issues as sperm
competition and the role of fluctuating asymmetry. Hamilton’s work
on kin selection, first published in 1964 but neglected for much of the
next decade, made possible a new approach to social behavior. Game
theory was recruited, and mathematical modeling came to be a much
used tool in studies of behavior.
At the same time, the influence of ethology started to penetrate into a
number of other disciplines. Lehrman and Rosenblatt, as well as
Beach and his many students, adopted the orienting attitudes of
ethology in their work on behavioral endocrinology. Von Holst had
already studied the elicitation of fixed action patterns by brain
stimulation through implanted electrodes, and the importance of
using unconfined animals where possible was recognized by
neurophysiologists. Bowlby, a psychoanalyst concerned with the
effects of maternal deprivation in children, realized that what had
been called the “irrational fears of childhood” (fear of falling, being
alone, etc.) would have been highly adaptive in the environments in
which early hominids lived, and an ethological element was
incorporated in the “attachment theory” which he elaborated, an
approach that was to become central in studies of child development.
The study of human nonverbal communication profited from the
input of ethologists, such as Eibl Eibesfeldt. The techniques of the
behavioral ecologists were applied in studies of preindustrial human
groups. An ethological influence is to be seen in studies of human
personal relationships, and even in studies of religion and morality.
Thus, while ethology as a set of concepts or as a theory of animal
behavior has been largely superseded, the influence of its orienting
attitudes has increased and is potent in other disciplines.
While behavioral ecology took center stage in the study of animal
behavior, many felt it to be impoverished by the neglect of problems
of development and causation. This book will go a long way toward
setting the balance straight. Each of the four problems is covered,
and the chapters introduce the growing points in the study of animal
behavior at the start of the twenty-first century.
preface
The idea for this book arose out of a need that we (and many of our
colleagues) felt for a comprehensive textbook on animal behavior.
There is no shortage of animal behavior textbooks, so why did we
want to produce a new one? First, animal behavior is a dynamic field
of research, and we believe that a modern textbook should
incorporate all the contemporary subdisciplines of behavioral
biology, such as animal welfare, evolutionary psychology, animal
cognition, and behavioral neuroscience. In some ways, the science of
animal behavior has become a victim of its own success, as it covers a
much wider field than it did initially. Gone are the days when one
author could write a textbook both comprehensive and authoritative:
Robert Hinde’s classic Animal Behaviour: A Synthesis of Ethology
and Comparative Psychology (1970) is an outstanding example of
such a book, and it continues to inspire many of us. Given the
breadth of contemporary animal behavior research, we felt that it
was important to invite experts in the respective subdisciplines to
write a chapter about their specialist topic.
Second, a large proportion of extant textbooks are single-author
volumes that approach animal behavior from a particular
perspective, for example from an evolutionary point of view or with
the emphasis on mechanisms. We believe that a modern science of
animal behavior should encompass both functional and causal
approaches. For such a comprehensive approach, we found the
classic formulation of the aims and methods of ethology (the study of
animal behavior) by Niko Tinbergen, one of its founding fathers,
most useful. Tinbergen suggested that there are four basic questions
in animal behavior, namely about causation, development, survival
value (function), and evolution. We agree with Tinbergen that all
these four questions are equally important. Hence all of them are
represented in this book. Like Tinbergen, we also find it important to
distinguish among the four questions. In particular, it is important to
realize which of the four questions is addressed, and to use a
research approach appropriate for that question. Most chapters in
the book focus on one of the four questions, with cause and
development being the main subjects of the first ten chapters, and
survival value (function) and evolution being the main subjects of the
last seven chapters. But most chapters are also concerned with more
than one question, noted separately of course, supporting
Tinbergen’s claim that all questions should be answered.
We are very pleased with the enthusiastic response we received from
the authors invited to contribute to this book. They are all leaders in
their respective fields, and we feel privileged that they participated in
this project. Robert Hinde has passed away since his foreword was
written, but his words are just as relevant to the second edition of
this book as they were to the first. His influence remains.
1
the study of animal behavior
JOHAN J. BOLHUIS, LUC-ALAIN GIRALDEAU AND JERRY A.
HOGAN
INTRODUCTION
The scientific study of animal behavior is often called ethology, a
term used first by the nineteenth century French zoologist Isidore
Geoffroy Saint Hilaire, but then used with its modern meaning by
the American zoologist Wheeler (1902). Ethology is derived from
the Greek ethos, meaning “character.” The word “ethics” is also
derived from the same Greek word, which makes sense, because
ethics is basically about how humans ought to behave.
Unfortunately, the word “ethology” is also often confused with
the word “ethnology” (the study of human peoples), with which it
has nothing in common. In fact, the very word processor with
which we are writing this chapter keeps prompting us to replace
“ethology” by “ethnology”! For whatever the reason, the word
“ethology” is not used as much as it used to be, although there is
still an active animal behavior journal bearing this name. Instead
of “ethology,” many authors now use the words “animal behavior”
or “behavioral biology” when they refer to the scientific study of
animal behavior.
Behaviorism
The emphasis of the North American psychologists on learning was
epitomized by the rise of behaviorism in the 1930s. Behaviorism was
a very influential school of thought initiated by the American
psychologist John B. Watson (1878–1958), with his book
Behaviorism (1924). Essentially, Watson considered psychological
phenomena to be physical activity rather than some kind of mental
event. He proposed that we cannot make any scientific statements
about what might be going on in our minds, and that introspection
was unreliable. Rather, for behaviorists, psychology is the study of
observable behavior and of the external physical factors that
influence it. At the time, behaviorism was extremely influential in
science and beyond. Within North American psychology it was the
dominant school of thought for several decades. Behaviorist theory
also affected education practice, particularly with Watson’s book
Psychological Care of Infant and Child (1928). Watson once made
the famous statement:
Give me a dozen healthy infants, well-formed, and my own specified
world to bring them up in and I’ll guarantee to take any one at
random and train him to become any type of specialist I might select
—doctor, lawyer, artist, merchant-chief, and, yes, even beggarman
and thief, regardless of his talents, penchants, tendencies, abilities,
vocations, and race of his ancestors.
This epitomizes behaviorist ideas about child rearing. Watson
considered the upbringing of children to be an objective, almost
scientific exercise, without the need for affection or sentimentality.
Watson’s most famous student was Burrhus Frederic Skinner (1904–
1990), who applied behaviorist ideas to the study of learning. For
Skinner (1938) and his behaviorist colleagues, learning had to do
with changing relationships between visible entities, not with what
might be going on inside the animal’s head. In particular, behaviorist
learning theorists suggest that learning refers to changes in the
frequency of responding due to its consequences. Most of their
experiments involve operant conditioning (see Chapter 8), in which a
certain response by the animal (e.g., pressing a lever) is rewarded
(“reinforced”) with food.
Cognitive psychology
Within experimental psychology there came a reaction to
behaviorism in what we now call cognitive psychology. In contrast to
behaviorism, cognitive psychologists start with the assumption that
individuals (humans and other animals) have a mental life that can
be investigated (Chapter 9). For instance, Skinner (1957) maintained
that language development in children was a learning process, in
which responses (i.e., uttering certain sounds) were reinforced. The
American linguist Noam Chomsky (1959) wrote a highly critical
review of Skinner’s book on language development, suggesting that
language acquisition is not a case of instrumental conditioning, but a
much more complex interaction between experience and internal
cognitive mechanisms (Chapter 7). At birth the child is already
endowed with essential knowledge of language, the theory of which
is known as Universal Grammar. Clearly, learning is involved in the
development of language, but it is not the only factor. Chomsky and
colleagues have recently described the growth of language in the
child as “the interplay of three factors: domain-specific principles of
language (Universal Grammar), external experience, and properties
of non-linguistic domains of cognition including general learning
mechanisms and principles of efficient computation” (Yang et al.
2017). Another important publication that signaled the beginning of
the cognitive revolution is a book by the British psychologist Donald
Broadbent (1958) who, in contrast to Skinner, analyzed learning and
memory in terms of cognitive mechanisms rather than stimulus–
response relations. Hogan (1988, 2017) has noted that what cognitive
psychologists call “cognitive structures” are in fact the same as the
causal mechanisms that were proposed by ethologists such as Lorenz
and Tinbergen (Chapters 3 and 9).
FURTHER READING
Tinbergen’s (1963) paper on the four whys is essential reading for
any serious student of animal behavior. It was reprinted in Houck
and Drickamer (1996), which is a collection of classic papers on all
aspects of animal behavior, and in Tinbergen’s Legacy (Bolhuis &
Verhulst 2009), which is a collection of contemporary essays
reflecting on Tinbergen’s classic paper. The four-part reader by
Bolhuis and Giraldeau (2010) is organized on the basis of
Tinbergen’s four whys and has a collection of classic and
contemporary papers on the evolution, function, development, and
causation of animal behavior. Tinbergen’s (1951) classic book is still
very much worthwhile. It was reprinted in 1992 and is still available.
The British ethologist William Thorpe (1979) has written a brief
history of ethology, viewed from the inside, while Dewsbury (1989)
provides a more recent account from the North American
perspective. Boakes (1984) is an excellent review of the history of the
study of animal behavior by psychologists, while Laland and Brown
(2011) provide a very clear account of the different ways in which the
behavior of animals (including humans) can be studied from an
evolutionary perspective. Functional and evolutionary aspects of
behavior are also discussed in Davies et al. (2012). Hogan’s (2017)
book provides an exposition and critique of behavioral concepts and
of historical and contemporary studies of behavior.
REFERENCES
Boakes, R.A. 1984. From Darwin to behaviorism. Psychology and
the minds of animals. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press.
Bolhuis, J.J. 2015. Evolution cannot explain how minds work.
Behavioural Processes, 117, 82–91.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Giraldeau, L.-A. (eds.). 2010. Animal behaviour, 4
volumes. London: Sage Publications.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Macphail, E. M. 2001. A critique of the neuroecology
of learning and memory. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 426–
433.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Macphail, E.M. 2002. Everything in neuroecology
makes sense in the light of evolution. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 6, 7–8.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Verhulst, S. (Eds.) 2009. Tinbergen’s legacy:
Function and mechanism in behavioral biology. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Wynne, C.D.L. 2009. Can evolution explain how
minds work? Nature, 458, 832–833.
Broadbent, D.E. 1958. Perception and communication. London:
Pergamon.
Chomsky, N. 1959. A review of B.F. Skinner’s ‘Verbal Behavior’.
Language, 35, 26–58.
Darwin, C. 1859. On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural
Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle
for Life. London: John Murray.
Davies, N.B., Krebs, J.R. & West, S.A. 2012. An introduction to
behavioural ecology. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Dewsbury, D. 1989. A brief history of the study of animal behavior in
North America. In: P.P.G. Bateson & P.H. Klopfer (eds.),
Perspectives in ethology, pp. 85–122. London: Plenum.
Ewert, J.P. 1980. Neuroethology. An introduction to the
neurophysiological fundamentals of behavior. Berlin: Springer.
Healy, S. & Braithwaite, V. 2000. Cognitive ecology: a field of
substance? Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 15, 22–26.
Hogan, J.A. 1988. Cause and function in the development of
behavior systems. In E. M. Blass (ed.), Handbook of behavioral
neurobiology, vol. 9, pp. 63–106. New York: Plenum.
Hogan, J.A. 1994. The concept of cause in the study of behavior. In J.
A. Hogan & J. J. Bolhuis (eds.), Causal mechanisms of
behavioural development, pp. 3–15. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Hogan, J.A. 2017. The study of behavior: Organization, methods,
and principles. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Houck, L.D. & Drickamer, L.C. (eds.). 1996. Foundations of animal
behavior. Classic papers with commentaries. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Krebs, J.R. & Davies, N.B. (eds.). 1978. Behavioural ecology: An
evolutionary approach. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Laland, K.N. & Brown, G.R. 2011. Sense and nonsense. Evolutionary
perspectives on human behaviour, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Lehrman, D.S. 1953. A critique of Konrad Lorenz’ theory of
instinctive behavior. Quarterly Review of Biology, 28, 337–363.
Macphail, E.M. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2001. The evolution of intelligence:
adaptive specialisations versus general process. Biological
Reviews, 76, 341–364.
Maynard Smith, J. 1982. Evolution and the Theory of Games.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mayr, E. 1961. Cause and effect in biology. Science, 134, 1501–1506.
Pavlov, I.P. 1927. Conditioned reflexes. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Shettleworth, A.J. 2010. Cognition, evolution, and behavior. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Skinner, B.F. 1938. The behavior of organisms. New York: Appleton-
Century-Crofts.
Skinner, B.F. 1957. Verbal behavior. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice
Hall.
Spalding, D.A. 1873. Instinct, with original observations on young
animals. Macmillan’s Magazine, 27, 282–293. Reprinted in 1954
in: British Journal of Animal Behaviour, 2, 2–11.
Thorndike, E.L. 1911. Animal Intelligence. New York: Macmillan.
Thorpe, W.H. 1979. The origins and rise of ethology. London:
Heinemann/Praeger.
Tinbergen, N. 1951. The study of instinct. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Tinbergen, N. 1963. On aims and methods in ethology. Zietschrift für
Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–433.
Tinbergen, N., Broekhuysen, G.J., Feekes, F. et al. 1962. Egg shell
removal by the black headed gull, Larus ridibundus: a behaviour
component of camouflage. Behaviour, 19, 74–117.
Vander Wall, S.B. 1990. Food hoarding in animals. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Watson, J.B. 1924. Behaviorism. New York: W.W. Norton.
Wheeler, W.M. 1902. ‘Natural history’, ‘ecology’ or ‘ethology’?
Science, 15, 971–976.
Wilson, E.O. 1975. Sociobiology, the new synthesis. Cambridge, MA:
Belknap/Harvard University Press.
Wouters, A.G. 2003. Four notions of biological function. Studies in
History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences,
34, 633–668.
Yang, C., Crain, S., Berwick, R.C., Chomsky, N. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2017.
The growth of language: Universal Grammar, experience, and
principles of computation. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral
Reviews, 81, 103–119.
2
stimulus perception
H. BURGHAGEN AND J.-P. EWERT
INTRODUCTION
Driving a car during rush-hour, we are exposed to a flood of
information that bombards our sensory systems through various
channels: visual, auditory, vibratory, somatosensory, etc. If the
central nervous system (CNS) were to respond to all this
information simultaneously, chaos would develop. Thus, on the
one hand, the CNS must be ready to collect information from
different sensory channels and to process these in parallel and
concurrently; on the other hand, it must be selective: perceiving
the right thing in the right place at the right time—say, a traffic
sign—and responding to it appropriately, for example, by
stepping on the brakes. This involves localization, identification,
and decision-making. In general, all animals employ their
sensory instruments for the translation of perception into action
in order to select a specific goal-oriented skill.
In this chapter, we start with a survey of sensory modalities and
show that sense organs and corresponding neural networks
(sensory maps) provide animals with their own sensory worlds.
In the light of current investigations in different animal species,
including humans, we select examples showing that Niko
Tinbergen’s ideas and concepts have paved the way for
ethological and neuroethological studies over the last six decades.
We go on to describe quantitative relationships between stimulus
and behavioral response, including discussion of the concepts of
sign-stimulus, innate releasing mechanism (IRM), heterogeneous
summation, supernormal releaser, and the influences of attention
and motivation. Our intention is to show that various classical
ethological concepts can be redefined, filled with physiological
content, and thus integrated into our current knowledge.
Moving from the behavioral to the neurophysiological level of
analysis, we explore stimulus perception and the behavior that
ensues, from which some general principles across species
emerge. In the CNS, there are stimulus-response mediating
pathways and neural loops that modulate, modify, or even specify
that mediation. Using neuronal correlates of releasing
mechanisms as well as neural network modeling, which operate
as sensori-motor interfaces, we discuss sensory structures
involved in feature detection including olfaction in insects,
configurational visual object perception in toads and monkeys,
and visual perception in primates.
Stimulus Reception
Heterogeneous summation
The concept of Gestalt implies that the efficacy of a configuration is
greater than the sum of the efficacies of its components (features).
However, there are examples showing that independent different
stimulus features are additive in their efficacy, whereby the whole is
equal to the sum of its parts (Seitz 1940: “Reizsummenphänomen”).
For instance, herring gulls, Larus argentatus, recognize their eggs by
different features, such as size, shape, color. These features are
additive in their influence upon retrieval of an egg having rolled out
of the nest. Heiligenberg and coworkers (see Leong 1969)
quantitatively demonstrated a comparable phenomenon in male
perch, Haplochromis burtoni. The level of aggression A in these fish
averaged at x bites/min. In a model fish (a), a black eye-bar
increased the attack rate of conspecific males at
Aa = x + 2.8 bites/min,
while a model fish (b) with orange spots on skin, but no eye-bar,
lowered the attack rate:
Ab = x–1.7 bites/min.
A model fish (c) containing eye-bar and orange spots caused an
attack rate of
Ac = x + 1.1 bites/min,
which correlates well with the algebraic sum of the rates (1.0)
obtained in (a) and (b). Hence, the opposite effects of both features
summed algebraically: “heterogeneous summation.”
It is suggested that Gestalt perception of human faces is derived from
heterogeneous summation both in phylogenetic and ontogenetic
histories. For example, Bower (1966) showed in 2-month-old human
babies that the number of conditioned orienting responses toward a
face-model—consisting of head-outline, eye-dots, and cross—equaled
the algebraic sum of the orienting activities measured to each
component of the model (Table 2.2). In 5-month-old babies the
responses to the face-model were about twice as high as the sum of
the responses to each face component: Gestalt perception.
Supernormal stimulus
Stimulus summation introduces the phenomenon of supernormal
stimulus, i.e., a stimulus that is more effective at eliciting a response
than the stimulus for which it evolved. In studies using dummies,
various examples show that exaggeration of a sign-stimulus leads to
an extraordinary increase in its efficacy. The courting behavior of a
male stickleback depends on the swollen abdomen of the pregnant
female. When presented with two model females, one showing a
normal swollen and the other a hyper-swollen abdomen,
respectively, the male will choose the latter (Rowland 1989).
Another example concerns the egg-retrieval behavior of brooding
greylag geese, Anser. After an egg rolls out of its nest, the goose
extends its neck toward the egg and with its flat mandible slowly rolls
it back toward the nest (Lorenz & Tinbergen 1938; cit. Tinbergen
1951). If the goose is offered a choice of eggs of different sizes placed
outside the nest, the largest one will be preferred, even if it is twice
the size of its own egg and thus difficult to handle. Egg retrieval by
the brooding herring gull, Larus argentatus, has been studied in
even more detail by Baerends and his colleagues (Baerends & Drent
1982). In hundreds of experiments carried out over many years, they
showed that a green, speckled egg the size of a football was preferred
over the gull’s own brown egg, which is the size of a large hen’s egg.
Humans, too, take advantage of exaggerated stimuli for various
communicative purposes. Messages can be made appealing by
stressing features. In cartoons, caricatures, and graphic icons certain
cues are accentuated in order to abstract and emphasize the
expression of a subject or an object. Women’s eyes and lips are
underlined cosmetically in order to make the face attractive and
distinctive from other faces.
Visuomotor access
Prey-selective T5.2-neurons send their axons from the optic tectum
to the medullary premotor/motor cells that innervate jaw and tongue
muscles (Weerasuriya & Ewert 1981, Satou & Ewert 1983; cit. Ewert
1984; see also Table 2.6).
Table 2.6 Minimum number of cell types linking photoreception
and snapping reaction. Additional interacting cells (e.g., retinal
horizontal and amacrine cells; pretectal/thalamic neurons) have
tuning and specifying functions at different processing levels.
Such a neuron can be examined by recording its activity with an
electrode chronically implanted in the tectum of a freely moving toad
in response to a prey-like stripe: a strong burst of impulses preceded
toad’s tongue-projection at prey (Schürg-Pfeiffer et al. 1993). The
same stripe presented in threat configuration elicited little neuronal
activity and no prey-catching, probably due to pretectal/thalamic
inhibition (see Figure 2.10B).
Test: If a second electrode—fastened at the skull—delivered an
electrolytic lesion to the ipsilateral pretectal thalamus, a moving
stripe strongly activated the prey-selective T5.2 neuron and elicited
prey-capture regardless of whether the stripe was presented in prey
or threat configuration. Pretectal/thalamic lesion (Figure 2.10D)
impaired the discrimination between prey and threat both
neuronally and behaviorally—hence evidencing linkage between
prey-selective neuronal activity and prey-catching behavior (Schürg-
Pfeiffer et al. 1993).
No motor command can be issued when motivation and attention
are not appropriate: if a toad was satiated after feeding on
mealworms or frightened by some noise by the experimenter, a prey
object neither activated T5.2 neurons nor any prey capture.
Sensorimotor codes
The concept of command releasing system CRS interprets
Tinbergen’s concept of (innate) releasing mechanism in a
neurophysiological context.
A CRS considers combinatorial aspects of stimulus perception as a
sensorimotor code in a sensorimotor interface. A coded command
involves different types of neurons, each type monitoring or
analyzing a certain stimulus aspect, e.g., prey-selective T5.2 neurons.
The idea is that a certain combination of such command elements
cooperatively activates a certain motor pattern–generating system in
the presence of adequate motivational and attentional inputs. It is
suggested that certain command elements can be shared by different
sensorimotor codes.
FURTHER READING
Textbooks
The Study of Instinct by Tinbergen (1951) is a classic textbook of
ethology—especially impressive in view of Tinbergen’s foresight, e.g.,
in terms of the neuroethological fundamentals of behavior.
Hogan (2017) provides new insights in the study of animal behavior
including behavioral ecology, neuroscience, cognitive psychology,
and evolutionary developmental biology.
Prete (2004) presents a multi-author textbook describing in depth
what the perceptual worlds of animals of various species might be.
Readers interested in the research of olfactory perception in insects
will enjoy the ambitious review by Kaissling (2014).
Carew (2004) and Zupanc (2019) provide the best up-to-date
treatments of neuroethology.
Movies
Ewert, J.-P. & IWF (Institut für den Wissenschaftlichen Film,
Göttingen). Voice-Over: English.
If you scan this QR code with the QR app of your smartphone, or
click the URL, you’re directed to an internet TIB|AV-Portal, which
allows you to watch three English versions of movies about the
visually guided prey-catching and threat-avoidance behaviors in
toads and the underlying neurophysiological processes.
A1: Image Processing in the Visual System of the Common Toad:
Behavior, Brain Function, Artificial Neuronal Net (No.: C1805).
https://av.tib.eu/media/15148
This weblink refers to the movie dealing with: Image processing in
the toad’s visual system from behavior to brain function, which is
explained by a global model (“window hypothesis”) and simulated
by an artificial neuronal net that—in an experimental platform of
neuroengineering—advises a robot to select and pick out different
objects moving on a conveyor belt.
A2: Gestalt Perception in the Common Toad-1: Innate Prey
Recognition (No.: C1430). https://av.tib.eu/media/15241
This weblink refers to the movie dealing with: Species-specific prey-
selection in the common toad with reference to the “worm” vs. “anti-
worm” discrimination and its invariance under changes of other
stimulus parameters, such as object motion, movement pattern,
shift of retinal image (induced movement), direction of movement,
background contrast, and background texture.
A3: Gestalt Perception in the Common Toad-2: Modification of Prey
Recognition by Learning (No.: C1431).
https://av.tib.eu/media/15242
The weblink refers to the movie dealing with: Modification of
species-specific prey selection in common toads by learning, such as
visual/olfactory associative learning, visual/visual (hand-feeding)
associative learning and non-associative learning (stimulus-specific
habituation).
REFERENCES
Baerends, G.P. & Drent, R.H. (eds). 1982. The herring gull and its
eggs. Behaviour, 82, 1–416.
Barinaga, M. 1997. Visual system provides clues to how the brain
perceives. Science, 275, 1583–1585.
Barlow, H.B. 1953. Summation and inhibition in the frog’s retina.
Journal of Physiology London, 173, 377–407.
Bower, T.G.R. 1966. Heterogeneous summation in human infants.
Animal Behaviour, 14(4), 395–398.
Brzoska, J. & Schneider, H. 1978. Modification of prey-catching
behaviour by learning in the common toad (Bufo bufo L., Anura,
Amphibia): Changes in response to visual objects and effects of
auditory stimuli. Behavioural Processes, 3, 125–136.
Burghagen, H. 1979. Der Einfluss von figuralen, visuellen Mustern
auf das Beutefangverhalten verschiedener Anuren. Math.-Nat.
Dissertation, University of Kassel.
Burghagen, H. & Ewert, J.-P. 1982. Question of “head preference” in
response to worm-like dummies during prey-capture of toads.
Bufo bufo. Behavioural Processes, 7, 295–306.
Burghagen, H. & Ewert, J.-P. 1983. Influence of the background for
discriminating object motion from self-induced motion in toads
(Bufo bufo L.). Journal Comparative Physiology, 152, 241–249.
Capranica, R.R. 1976. Morphology and physiology of the auditory
system. In R. Llinas & W. Precht (eds.), Frog Neurobiology, pp.
551–575. Berlin: Springer.
Carew, T.J. 2004. Behavioral Neurobiology, 2nd ed. Sunderland,
MA: Sinauer.
Cohen, J.D. & Tong, F. 2001. The face of controversy. Science, 293,
2405–2407.
Cohen, L.G., Celnik, P., Pascual-Leone, A. et al. 1997. Functional
relevance of cross-modal plasticity in blind humans. Nature, 389,
180–183.
Collett, T. 1977. Stereopsis in toads. Nature, 267, 349–351.
Cott, H.B. 1936. The effectiveness of protective adaptations in the
hive-bee, illustrated by experiments on the feeding reactions,
habit formation and memory of the common toad (Bufo bufo).
Proceedings of the Zoological Society London, 1, 113–133.
Damasio, A.R. 1990. Category-related recognition defects as clue to
the neural substrates of knowledge. Trends in Neurosciences, 13,
95–98.
Eaton, R.C. 2001. The Mauthner cell and other identified neurons of
the brainstem escape network of fish. Progress in Neurobiology,
63, 467–485.
Elbert, T., Pantev, C., Wienbruch, C., Rockstroh, B. & Taub, E. 1995.
Increased cortical representation of the fingers of the left hand in
string players. Science, 270, 305–307.
Ewert, J.-P. 1974. The neural basis of visually guided behavior.
Scientific American, 230(3), 34–42.
Ewert, J.-P. 1976. Neuro-Ethologie. Berlin: Springer, [Engl. edn.
1980, Neuroethology. Introduction to the Neurophysiological
Fundamentals of Behavior. Berlin: Springer. Japanese edn. 1982,
Tokyo: Baifukan. – Chinese edn. 1986, Beijing: Science Press,
Acad. Sinica].
Ewert, J.-P. 1984. Tectal mechanisms that underlie prey-catching
and avoidance behaviors in toads. In: H. Vanegas (ed.),
Comparative Neurology of the Optic Tectum, pp. 247–416.
[Review 1965-1984]. London: Plenum Press.
Ewert, J.-P. 1987. Neuroethology of releasing mechanisms. Behavior
and Brain Sciences, 10, 337–405.
Ewert, J.-P. 1997. Neural correlates of key stimulus and releasing
mechanism: a case study and two concepts. Trends in
Neurosciences, 20, 332–339.
Ewert, J.-P. 2004. Motion perception shapes the visual world of
amphibians. In F.R. Prete (ed.), Complex Worlds from Simpler
Nervous Systems, pp. 117–160. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Ewert, J.-P., Dinges, A.W. & Finkenstädt, T. 1994. Species-universal
stimulus responses, modified through conditioning, reappear
after telencephalic lesions in toads. Naturwissenschaften, 81,
317–320.
Ewert, J.-P. & Schwippert, W.W. 2006. Modulation of visual
perception and action by forebrain structures and their
interactions in amphibians. In E.D. Levin (ed.), Neurotransmitter
Interactions and Cognitive Function, pp. 99–136. Birkhäuser
Verlag.
Fingerling, S., Ewert, J.-P., Menzel, R. & Pfeiffer, F. 1993. From the
toad to a robot—implementation of neurobiological principles of
object discrimination in neural engineering.
Naturwissenschaften, 80, 321–324.
Finkenstädt, T., Adler, N.T., Allen, T.O., Ebbesson, S.O.E. & Ewert,
J.-P. 1985. Mapping of brain activity in mesencephalic and
diencephalic structures of toads during presentation of visual key
stimuli—a computer assisted analysis of 14C-2DG
autoradiographs. Journal Comparative Physiology A, 156, 433–
445.
Finkenstädt, T. & Ewert, J.-P. 1983. Processing of area dimensions of
visual key stimuli by tectal neurons. Salamandra salamandra.
Journal Comparative Physiology A, 153, 85–98.
Finkenstädt, T. & Ewert, J.-P. 1988. Effects of visual associative
conditioning on behavior and cerebral metabolic activity in toads.
Naturwissenschaften, 75, 95–97.
Hansen, K. 1984. Discrimination and production of disparlure
enantiomers by the gypsy moth and the nun moth. Physiological
Entomology, 9, 9–18.
Harnad, S.E. (ed.). 1987. Categorial perception: The groundwork of
cognition. Cambridge University Press.
Hartline, H.K. 1949. Inhibition of activity of visual receptors by
illuminating nearby retinal areas in the Limulus eye. Federation
Proceedings, 8(1), 69.
Heiligenberg, W. & Rose, G. 1985. Neural correlates of the jamming
avoidance response (JAR) in the weakly electric fish.
Eigenmannia. Trends in Neurosciences, 8, 442–449.
Heiligenberg, W.F., Kramer, U. & Schulz, V. 1972. The angular
orientation of the black eye-bar in Haplochromis burtoni
(Cichlidae, Pisces) and its relevance to aggressivity. Zeitschrift
vergleichende Physiologie, 76, 168–176.
Hinde, R.A. 1954. Changes in responsiveness to a constant stimulus.
Behaviour, 2, 41–54.
Hogan, J.A. 2017. The study of behavior. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Hubel, D.H. & Livingstone, M.S. 1987. Segregation of form, colour,
and stereopsis in primate area 18. Journal of Neuroscience, 7,
378–415.
Hubel, D.H. & Wiesel, T.N. 1977. Functional architecture of macaque
monkey visual cortex. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London
B, 198, 1–59.
Ishai, A. & Sagi, D. 1995. Common mechanisms of visual imagery
and perception. Science, 268, 1719–1720.
Islam, R., Prater, C.M., Harris, B.N. & Carr, J.A. 2019.
Neuroendocrine modulation of predator avoidance/prey capture
tradeoffs: Role of tectal NPY2R receptors. Comparative
Endocrinology, 282, 113214. doi: 10.1016/j.ygcen.2019.113214.
Kaas, J.H. 1991. Plasticity of sensory and motor maps in adult
mammals. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 14, 137–167.
Kafka, W.A. 1970. Molekulare Wechselwirkungen bei der Erregung
einzelner Riechzellen. Zeitschrift Vergleichende Physiologie, 70,
105–143.
Kaissling, K.-E. 2014. Pheromone reception in insects. The example
of silk moths. In C. Mucignat-Caretta (ed.), Neurobiology of
chemical communication, pp. 99–146. Taylor & Francis: CRC
Press.
Kendrick, K.M. 1994. Neurobiological correlates of visual and
olfactory recognition in sheep. Behavioural Processes, 33, 89–
112.
Koffka, K. 1922. Perception: An introduction to the Gestalt-theorie.
Psychological Bulletin, 19, 531–585.
Konishi, M. 2003. Coding of auditory space. Annual Review of
Neuroscience, 26, 31–55.
Kupfermann, I. & Weiss, K.R. 1978. The command neuron concept.
Behavior and Brain Sciences, 1, 3–39.
Kutschera, U., Burghagen, H. & Ewert, J.-P. 2008. Prey-catching
behaviour in mudskippers and toads: A comparative analysis.
OnLine Journal Biological Sciences, 8(2), 41–43.
Labhart, T. & Meyer, E.P. 2002. Neural mechanisms in insect
navigation: polarization compass and odometer. Current Opinion
in Neurobiology, 12, 707-714.
Langley, C.M., Riley, D.A., Bond, A.B. & Goel, N. 1996. Visual search
and natural grains in pigeons (Columba livia): search images and
selective attention. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal
Behavior Processes, 22, 139–151.
Lara, R., Cervantes, F. & Arbib, M. 1982. Two-dimensional model of
retinal-tectal-pretectal interactions for the control of prey-
predator recognition and size preference in amphibia. In: S.
Amari & M.A. Arbib (eds.), Lecture notes in biomathematics 45.
Competition and cooperation in neural nets, pp. 371–393. Berlin:
Springer-Verlag.
Leong, C.Y. 1969. The quantitative effect of releasers on the attack
readiness of the fish Haplochromis burtoni (Cichlidae: Pisces).
Zeitschrift vergleichende Physiologie, 65, 29–50.
Lettvin, J.Y., Maturana, H.R., McCulloch, W.S. & Pitts, W.H. 1959.
What the frog’s eye tells the frog’s brain. Proceedings of the
Institute for Radio Engineering, 47, 1940–1951.
Macaluso, E., Frith, C.D. & Driver, J. 2000. Modulation of human
visual cortex by crossmodal spatial attention. Science, 289, 1206–
1208.
Markl, H. & Hölldobler, B. 1978. Recruitment and food-retrieving
behavior in Novomessor (Formicidae, Hymenoptera). Behavioral
Ecology and Sociobiology, 4, 183–216.
Mountcastle, V.B., Lynch, J.C., Georgopoulos, A., Sakata, H. &
Acuna, C. 1975. Posterior parietal association cortex of the
monkey: command functions operations within extrapersonal
space. Journal of Neurophysiology, 38, 871–908.
Narins, P.M. 1981. Responses of torus semicircularis cells of the
coqui treefrog to fm sinusoids. In J.-P. Ewert, R. R. Capranica &
D. J. Ingle (eds.), Advances in vertebrate neuroethology, pp.
889–894. New York: Plenum Press.
Newman, E.A. & Hartline, P.H. 1982. The infrared “vision” of snakes.
Scientific American, 246(3), 116–127.
Pascalis, O., De Haan, M. & Nelson, C. A. 2002. Is face processing
species-specific during the first year of life? Science, 296, 1321–
1323.
Perret, D.I. & Rolls, E.T. 1983. Neural mechanisms underlying the
visual analysis of faces. In J.-P. Ewert, R. R. Capranica, & D. J.
Ingle (eds.), Advances in vertebrate neuroethology, pp. 543–566.
New York: Plenum Press.
Prater, C.M., Harris, B.N., & Carr, J.A. 2020. Tectal CRFR1 receptor
involvement in avoidance and approach behaviors in the South
African clawed frog, Xenopus laevis. Hormones and Behavior,
120, 104707. doi:10.1016/j.yhbeh.2020.104707.
Prete, F.R. (ed.). 2004. Complex worlds from simpler nervous
systems. Cambridge, MA: MTT Press.
Reddipogu, A., Maxwell, G. & MacLeod, C. 2002. An innovative
neural network based on the toad’s visual system. Proceedings of
ACIVS, Advanced Concepts for Intelligent Vision Systems, Ghent,
Belgium.
Rowland, W.J. 1989. Mate choice and the supemormality effect in
female sticklebacks (Gaster-osteus aculeatus). Behavioral
Ecology and Sociobiology, 24, 433–438.
Ryan, M.J. & Rand, A.S. 1995. Female responses to ancestral
advertisement calls in the tungara frog. Science, 269, 390–392.
Schleidt, W. 1961. Über die Auslösung der Flucht vor Raubvögeln bei
Truthühnern. Naturwissenschaften, 48, 141–142.
Schürg-Pfeiffer, E., Spreckelsen, C. & Ewert, J.-P. 1993. Temporal
discharge patterns of tectal and medullary neurons chronically
recorded during snapping toward prey in toads Bufo spinosus.
Journal Comparative Physiology A, 173, 363–376.
Seitz, A. 1940. Die paarbildung bei einigen cichliden. Zeitschrift
Tierpsychologie, 4, 40–84.
Singer, W. 1995. Development and plasticity of cortical processing
architectures. Science, 270, 758–764.
Spreckelsen, C., Schürg-Pfeiffer, E. & Ewert, J.-P. 1995. Responses of
retinal and tectal neurons in non-paralyzed toads Bufo and B.
marinus to the real size versus angular size of objects moved at
variable distance. Neuroscience Letters, 184, 105–108.
Suga, N. 1990. Biosonar and neural computation in bats. Scientific
American, 262, 60–68.
Ter Polkwijk, J.J. & Tinbergen, N. 1937. Eine reizbiologische Analyse
einigen Verhaltensweisen von Gasterosteus aculeatus. Zeitschrift
für Tierpsychologie, 1, 194–200.
Tinbergen, N. 1951. The Study of Instinct. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Reissued in 1989 by Oxford University Press, New York.
Tinbergen, N. & Kuenen, D.J. 1939. Über die auslösenden und die
richtunggebenden Reizsituationen der Sperrbewegung von jungen
Drosseln (Turdus m. merula L. und T. e. ericetorum Turton).
Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 3, 37-60.
Udin, S. 1977. Rearrangements of the retinotectal projection in Rana
pipiens after unilateral caudal half-tectum ablation. Journal
Comparative Neurology, 173(3), 561–582.
Ungerleider, L.G. & Mishkin, M. 1982. Two cortical visual systems.
In D.J. Ingle, M.A. Goodale & R.J.W. Mansfield (eds.), Analysis of
visual behavior, pp. 549–586. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Valenza, E., Simion, F., Cassia, V.M. & Umilta, C. 1996. Face
preference at birth. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
Perception and Performance, 22, 892–903.
Von Uexkiill, J. 1921. Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere. Berlin:
Springer.
Wiersma, C.A.G. & Ikeda, K. 1964. Interneurons commanding
swimmeret movements in the crayfish, Procambarus clarkii
(Girard). Comparative Biochemistry and Physiology, 12, 509–
525.
Wiltschko, W. & Wiltschko, R. 2002. Magnetic compass orientation
in birds and its physiological basis. Naturwissenschaften, 89,
445–452.
Yoshida, N. 2016. From retina to behavior: prey-predator
recognition by convolutional neural networks and their
modulation by classical conditioning. Adaptive Behavior, 1–23.
doi:10.1177/1059712316650265.
Zupanc, G.H. 2019. Behavioral neurobiology. An integrative
approach, 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
3
motivation and emotion
JERRY A. HOGAN
INTRODUCTION
The word motivate means “to cause to move,” and I will use the
concept of motivation to refer to the study of the immediate
causes of behavior: those factors responsible for the initiation,
maintenance, and termination of behavior. Thus, motivation is
another word for aspects of Tinbergen’s causal question (see
Chapter 1). Causal factors for behavior include stimuli, hormones,
and the intrinsic activity of the nervous system. How do these
factors cause a female rat to behave maternally to her pups? Or a
chicken to bathe in dust in the middle of the day? Or a male
stickleback fish to stop responding sexually to receptive females?
These are the types of questions asked in the first part of this
chapter.
Motivated behavior often produces emotion, but the concept of
emotion is problematic because there is no consensus about its
definition. In the second part of this chapter I will analyze the
concept of emotion as applied primarily to humans and conclude
with a section on nonhuman emotion and its relation to animal
welfare.
Behavior Systems
Causal Factors
Stimuli
Stimuli can control behavior in many ways: they can release, direct,
inhibit, and prime behavior. Chapter 2 discussed many examples of
stimuli that release and direct various behavior patterns. Some
stimuli can have exactly the opposite effect: rather than facilitate
behavior, they inhibit it. A good example is provided by the nest-
building behavior of many species of birds. Birds typically build their
nests using specific behavior patterns. The stimuli that release and
direct their behavior have been studied in several cases and conform
to the general principles already discussed. However, at a certain
point the birds stop building and no longer react to the twigs,
lichens, or feathers with which they construct their nest. There are
several possible reasons why they stop, but one reason is that the
stimuli provided by the completed nest inhibit further nest building.
This can be seen when a bird takes over a complete nest from the
previous season and shows very little nest-building behavior. Other
birds, in the same internal state, that have not found an old nest
show a great deal of nest-building behavior (Thorpe 1956).
Another example of the inhibitory effects of stimuli is seen in the
courtship behavior of the three-spined stickleback (Gasterosteus
aculeatus), a small fish. Male sticklebacks set up territories in small
streams early in the spring, build a nest of bits of plant material, and
will generally court any female that may pass through their territory.
Courtship includes a zigzag dance by the male, appropriate posturing
by the female, leading to and showing of the nest entrance by the
male, following and entering the nest by the female, laying eggs, and
finally fertilization (see Figure 3.4). The female swims away and the
male then courts another female. The male could continue courting
egg-laden females for many days, but usually he does not.
Experiments in which eggs were removed from or added to the nest
have shown that visual stimuli from the eggs inhibit sexual activity: if
eggs are removed from the nest, the male will continue courting
females, but if eggs are added to the nest he will cease courting,
regardless of the number of eggs he has fertilized (Sevenster-Bol
1962). This is an especially interesting example because the same
visual stimulus that inhibits sexual activity has an activating effect on
the parental behavior (fanning the eggs) of the same male.
Figure 3.4 Courtship and mating behavior of the three-spined
stickleback. The male is on the left and the female, with a swollen
belly, is on the right. A typical courtship sequence is indicated below
the diagram. (From Tinbergen 1951).
Stimuli not only control behavior by their presence, but in many
cases continue to affect behavior even after they have physically
disappeared. When a stimulus has arousing effects on behavior that
outlast its presence, priming is said to occur. Aggressive behavior
in the male Siamese fighting fish (Betta splendens) provides a good
example (Hogan & Bols 1980). This fish shows vigorous aggressive
display and fighting toward other males of its species (including its
own mirror image). If a fish is allowed to fight with its mirror image
for a few seconds and the mirror is then removed, it is very likely to
attack a thermometer introduced into the aquarium. If the
thermometer had been introduced before the mirror was presented,
the fish very likely would have ignored it. Thus, the sight of a
conspecific not only releases aggressive behavior, it must also change
the internal state of the fish for some time after the conspecific
disappears. We can say that the stimulus primes the mechanism that
coordinates aggressive behavior or, more simply, that it primes
aggression. Similar priming effects have been demonstrated with
food and water in rats and hamsters, and with brain stimulation in
several species (see Hogan & Roper 1978). An especially elegant
mathematical analysis of priming in cichlid fish and crickets is
presented by Heiligenberg (1974).
These examples of priming all occur during the time span of a few
minutes. Some stimuli prime behavior over a much longer period.
Stimuli from the eggs of the stickleback inhibit sexual behavior, as
we have just seen, but they also prime parental behavior. Male
sticklebacks fan the eggs in their nest by moving their fins in a
characteristic manner, which directs a current of water into the nest
and serves to remove debris and provide oxygen to the developing
embryos. The amount of fanning increases over the 7 days it takes for
the eggs to hatch. It has been shown that CO2, which is produced by
the eggs, is one of the stimuli releasing fanning, and the amount of
CO2 produced is greater from older eggs. Thus, one might expect that
the increased fanning is a direct effect of CO2 concentration. This
supposition was tested in an experiment by Van Iersel (1953). He
replaced the old eggs on day 4 with newly laid eggs from another
nest. There was a slight drop in fanning with the new eggs, but
fanning remained much higher than the original day-1 level. Further,
the peak of fanning activity was reached the day the original eggs
would have hatched. This means that the stimuli from the eggs must
prime a coordinating mechanism and that the state of the
coordinating mechanism is no longer completely dependent on
stimulation from the eggs after 3 or 4 days.
A similar example is provided by the development of ovulation in
doves. A female ring dove (Streptopelia risoria) will normally lay an
egg if she is paired with an acceptable male for about seven days. If
the male is removed after 2 or 3 days, the developing egg regresses
and is not laid. However, if the male is allowed to remain with the
female for 5 days before he is removed, the majority of females will
lay an egg 2 days later. Experiments by Lehrman (1965) and his
colleagues demonstrated that it is the stimuli from the courting male
that prime the mechanism responsible for ovulation.
Longer-term effects of stimuli can be seen in the yearly cycle of
gonad growth and regression in some birds and fish as a result of
changes in day length. And changes in day length can also stimulate
a host of other physiological changes including those that prepare
migratory birds for their long-distance flight (e.g., Piersma & Van
Gils 2011) or various mammals for hibernation in the winter (Nelson
2016).
Causal factors for many behavior systems are present at the same
time, yet an animal can generally only do one thing at a time. This is
a situation of motivational conflict. In this section I consider the
kinds of behavior that occur in conflict situations, as well as some
mechanisms that have been proposed for switching from one
behavior to another. There have been two major ways of studying
conflict behavior. One way to classify conflicts is in terms of the
direction an organism takes from a goal object: either toward or
away. Many psychologists have distinguished three basic kinds of
motivational conflict, each designated according to the direction
associated with the specific tendencies aroused: approach–approach,
avoidance–avoidance, and approach–avoidance (e.g., Miller 1959).
Other psychologists have used approach/withdrawal concepts as the
basis for a theory of behavioral development (Schneirla 1965). An
alternative way to classify conflict situations, used by ethologists, is
to look at the specific behavior systems that are activated and analyze
the behavior that is actually seen. Four major types of outcome have
been studied: inhibition, ambivalence, redirection, and
displacement. I will briefly discuss each.
Ambivalence
When a female stickleback enters the territory of a male, she is both
an intruder and a potential sex partner. The appropriate response to
an intruding conspecific is to attack it; the appropriate response to a
sex partner is to lead it to the nest. The male essentially does both; he
performs a zigzag dance (see Figure 3.4). He makes a sideways leap
followed by a jump in the direction of the female, and this sequence
may be repeated many times. Sometimes the sideways leap continues
into leading to the nest, and sometimes the jump toward the female
ends in attack and biting. Thus, the zigzag dance can be considered a
case of successive ambivalence. Ambivalent behavior is behavior that
includes motor components belonging to two different behavior
systems; in successive ambivalence , these components occur in
rapid succession.
A somewhat similar case is provided by the “upright” posture of the
herring gull (Larus argentatus; Figure 3.6). This display often occurs
during boundary disputes when two neighboring gulls meet at their
mutual territory boundary. The bird’s neck is stretched and its bill
points down; the carpal joints (wrists) of the wings are raised out of
the supporting feathers; the plumage is sleeked. The position of the
bill and wings are characteristic of a bird that is about to attack
(fighting in this species includes pecking and wing beating the
opponent), and the stretched neck and sleeked plumage are
characteristic of a frightened bird that is about to flee. Further, actual
fighting or fleeing often follows the upright posture. Thus, the
upright posture is a behavior pattern that includes motor
components belonging to two different behavior systems. Unlike the
zigzag dance of the stickleback, however, these components occur
simultaneously. The upright posture can be considered a case of
simultaneous ambivalence . Figure 3.6 also shows that the
upright posture can occur in varying forms. In the “aggressive
upright,” components of attack predominate, whereas in the “anxiety
upright,” components of fleeing predominate.
Displacement
Ambivalent behavior and redirected behavior are appropriate
responses to causal factors that are obviously present in the situation
in which the animal finds itself. Sometimes, however, an animal
shows behavior that is not expected, in that appropriate causal
factors are not apparent. A male stickleback meets its neighbor at the
territory boundary and shows intention movements of attack and
escape; then it suddenly swims to the bottom and takes a mouthful of
sand (which is a component of nest-building behavior). A young
chick encounters a wriggling mealworm and shows intention
movements of approach to peck and eat the mealworm and of
retreating from the novel object; then, while watching the mealworm
the chick falls asleep. A pigeon, actively engaged in courtship,
suddenly stops and preens itself. A student studying hard for an
exam, puts down her book, walks to the kitchen, and makes herself a
sandwich. These behaviors are all examples of displacement
activities that are controlled by a behavior system different from
the behavior systems one might expect to be activated in a particular
situation.
In the case of the stickleback, it is reasonable to show components of
attack and escape behavior at the boundary of its territory because
the neighboring fish is an intruder when it crosses into our subject’s
territory, and our subject loses the security of home when it ventures
into its neighbor’s territory. But why should it engage in nest-
building behavior? The stickleback has probably already built its nest
elsewhere and, in any case, would not normally build it at the edge of
its territory. What are the causal factors for nest building in this
situation? Similar considerations apply to the other examples as well.
In all cases, causal factors for the displacement activity appear to be
missing. It is this apparent inexplicableness of displacement
activities that has caused so much attention to be focused on them.
Why does this unexpected behavior occur?
There have been two main theories put forward to account for
displacement activities: the overflow theory and the disinhibition
theory. The original theory was proposed independently by Kortlandt
(1940) and by Tinbergen (1940) and is usually called the overflow
theory. They proposed that when causal factors for a particular
behavior system (e.g., aggression) were strong, but appropriate
behavior was prevented from occurring, the energy from the
activated system would “spark” or flow over to a behavior system
that was not blocked (e.g., nest building) and a displacement activity
would be seen. The appropriate behavior might be prevented from
occurring because of interference from an antagonistic behavior
system (e.g., fear or escape) or the absence of a suitable object or
thwarting of any sort.
This theory was formulated in the framework of Lorenz’s model of
motivation, which accounts for the graphic metaphor of energy
sparking over or overflowing. In more prosaic terms, this is actually a
theory in which causal factors have general as well as specific effects.
Many examples of displacement activities are described as being
incomplete or hurried—the stickleback does not calmly proceed to
build a nest during a boundary conflict—and such observations give
support to a theory that posits general effects of causal factors. It can
be noted that Freud’s (1940/1949) theory of displacement and
sublimation of sexual energy (libido) is basically the same as the
overflow theory: sexual energy is expressed in nonsexual activities
such as creating works of art.
The alternative theory is called the disinhibition theory. In
essence, it states that a strongly activated behavior system normally
inhibits weakly activated systems. If, however, two behavior systems
are strongly activated (e.g., sex and aggression), the inhibition they
exert on each other will result in a release of inhibition on other
behavior systems (e.g., parental) and a displacement activity will
occur. The general idea was proposed by several scientists, but the
most detailed exploration of the theory was made by Sevenster
(1961). He studied displacement fanning in the male stickleback,
which often occurs during courtship before there are any eggs in the
nest. The sex and aggression behavior systems are known to be
strongly activated during courtship. By careful measurements, it was
possible to show that fanning occurred at a particular level of sex and
aggression when their mutual inhibition was the strongest. Of special
importance for the disinhibition theory, the amount of displacement
fanning that occurred depended on the strength of causal factors for
the parental behavior system. When extra CO2 was introduced into
the water, there was an increase in fanning.
The primary difference between the two theories is that according to
the disinhibition theory the displacement activity is motivated by it
own normal causal factors and the conflict between systems merely
serves a permissive role; whereas according to the overflow theory
the displacement activity is motivated by causal factors for one or
both of the conflicting systems. In the disinhibition theory, causal
factors always have specific effects; in the overflow theory, they have
general effects. Which theory is correct? As is so often the case,
neither theory, by itself, is able to account for all the phenomena
associated with displacement activities. The disinhibition theory is in
many ways more satisfying because it only requires that causal
factors have their normal and expected effects on behavior.
Nonetheless, more general effects of causal factors must be invoked
to account for the frantic or excited aspects of displacement activities
seen in many situations.
It is frequently true that the causation of a behavior pattern is even
more complicated. For example, ground pecking occurs as a
displacement activity during aggressive encounters between two
male junglefowl. Arguments for considering this activity as a
displaced feeding movement include the fact that it is often directed
to food pieces on the ground and the fact that it occurs more
frequently when the animals are hungry. This same activity can also
be considered redirected aggression, and experimental evidence also
supports this interpretation. Thus, one behavior pattern can be both
a displacement activity and a redirected activity at the same time
(Feekes 1972). Each contribution to the causation of a behavior
pattern can be analyzed separately, but the list of causal factors
affecting the behavior pattern can be very long. Indeed, multiple
causation of behavior is the rule rather than the exception. The
causation of behavior is a very complex question, and it is
unreasonable to expect a simple answer.
Nonhuman Emotion
FURTHER READING
Amplification of many of the ideas in this chapter can be found in
The Study of Behavior (Hogan 2017). An Introduction to Behavioral
Endocrinology (Nelson 2016) provides an excellent source for details
on the physiological control of most of the behavior systems
mentioned in this chapter. Toates’ (1986) book Motivational
Systems presents a review of behavior systems with an emphasis on
control theory variables, and Enquist and Ghirlanda (2005) discuss
behavior systems from a neural network point of view. Lorenz’
(1966) controversial, but entertaining, book On Aggression gives his
views on how ethological concepts can be applied to human
behavior. James’ (1890) chapter on emotion should be read by
anyone interested in the subject.
REFERENCES
Adrian, E.D., Cattell, M. & Hoagland, H. 1931. Sensory discharges in
single cutaneous nerve fibres. Journal of Physiology, 72, 377–391.
Baerends, G.P. 1976. The functional organization of behaviour.
Animal Behaviour, 24, 726–738.
Baerends, G.P., Brouwer, R. & Waterbolk, H.T. 1955. Ethological
studies on Lebistes reticulatus (Peters): 1. An analysis of the male
courtship pattern. Behaviour, 8, 249–334.
Barrett, L.F. 2013. Psychological construction: The Darwinian
approach to the science of emotion. Emotion Review, 5, 379–389.
Barrett, L.F. & Russell, J.A. (eds.). 2015. The Psychological
Construction of Emotion. Guilford Press.
Beach, F.A. 1948. Hormones and Behavior. New York: Hoeber.
Berridge, K.C. 2004. Motivation concepts in behavioral
neuroscience. Physiology and Behavior, 81, 179–209.
Bols, R.J. 1977. Display reinforcement in the Siamese fighting fish,
Betta splendens: Aggression motivation or curiosity? Journal of
Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 91, 233–244.
Borbély, A.A., Dijk, D.-J., Achermann, P.& Tobler, I. 2001. Processes
underlying the regulation of the sleep-wake cycle. In: J.S.
Takahashi, F.W. Turek & R.Y. Moore (eds.), Circadian Clocks:
Handbook of Behavioral Neurobiology, vol. 12, pp. 458–479. New
York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum.
Buhusi, C.V. & Meck, W.H. 2005. What makes us tick? Functional
and neural mechanisms of interval timing. Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 6, 755–765.
Buntin, J.D. 1996. Neural and hormonal control of parental behavior
in birds. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 25, 161–213.
Cannon, W.B. 1927. The James-Lange theory of emotions: A critical
examination and an alternative theory. American Journal of
Psychology, 39, 106–124.
Darwin, C. 1872. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and
Animals. London.
Dawkins, M.S. 2008. The science of animal suffering. Ethology, 114,
937–945.
Dawkins, M.S. 2015. Animal welfare and the paradox of animal
consciousness. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 47, 5–37.
Ekman, P. & Davidson, R.J. (eds.). 1994. The Nature of Emotion:
Fundamental questions. New York: Oxford University Press.
Enquist, M. & Ghirlanda, S. 2005. Neural Networks and Animal
Behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Feekes, F. 1972. “Irrelevant” ground pecking in agonistic situations
in Burmese red junglefowl (Gallus gallus spadiceus). Behaviour,
43, 186–326.
Fleming, A.S. & Blass, E.M. 1994. Psychobiology of the early mother-
young relationship. In: J.A. Hogan & J.J. Bolhuis (eds.), Causal
Mechanisms of Behavioural Development, pp. 212–241.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Freud, S. 1905. Three Contributions to the Theory of Sexuality.
London: Hogarth Press.
Freud, S. 1915. Instincts and Their Vicissitudes. London: Hogarth
Press.
Freud, S. 1940/1949. An Outline of Psycho-Analysis. New York:
Norton.
Gendron, M. & Barrett, L.F. 2009. Reconstructing the past: a century
of ideas about emotion in psychology. Emotion Review, 1, 316–
339.
Glimcher, P.W. 2011. Understanding dopamine and reinforcement
learning: the dopamine reward prediction error hypothesis.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108, 15647–
15654.
Hall, C.S. 1934. Emotional behavior in the rat: 1. Defecation and
urination as measures of individual differences in emotionality.
Journal of Comparative Psychology, 18, 385–403.
Heiligenberg, W. 1974. Processes governing behavioral states of
readiness. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 5, 173–200.
Hinde, R.A. 1960. Energy models of motivation. Symposia of the
Society for Experimental Biology, 14, 199–213.
Hogan, J.A. 1988. Cause and function in the development of
behavior systems. In: E.M. Blass (ed.), Handbook of Behavioral
Neurobiology, vol. 9, pp. 63–106. New York: Plenum Press.
Hogan, J.A. 1997. Energy models of motivation: A reconsideration.
Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 53, 89–105.
Hogan, J.A. 1998. Motivation. In: G. Greenberg & M.M. Haraway
(eds.), Comparative Psychology: A Handbook, pp. 164–175. New
York: Garland.
Hogan, J.A. 2001. Development of behavior systems. In: E.M. Blass
(ed.), Handbook of Behavioral Neurobiology, vol. 13, pp. 229–
279. New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum.
Hogan, J.A. 2015. A framework for the study of behavior.
Behavioural Processes, 117, 105–113.
Hogan, J.A. 2017. The Study of Behavior: Organization, Methods,
and Principles. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hogan, J.A. & Bols, R.J. 1980. Priming of aggressive motivation in
Betta splendens. Animal Behaviour, 28, 135–142.
Hogan, J.A. & Roper, T.J. 1978. A comparison of the properties of
different reinforcers. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 8, 155–
255.
Hogan, J.A. & Van Boxel, F. 1993. Causal factors controlling
dustbathing in Burmese red junglefowl: some results and a model.
Animal Behaviour, 46, 627–635.
Hull, C.L. 1943. Principles of Behavior. New York: Appleton-
Century-Crofts.
James, W. 1890. Principles of Psychology, vol. 2. New York: Holt.
Kortlandt, A. 1940. Wechselwirkung zwischen Instinkten. Archives
Néerlandaises de Zoologie, 4, 443–520.
Kruijt, J.P. 1964. Ontogeny of social behaviour in Burmese red
junglefowl (Gallus gallus spadiceus). Behaviour, Suppl. 9, 1–201.
Lashley, K.S. 1938. Experimental analysis of instinctive behavior.
Psychological Review, 45, 445–471.
LeDoux, J. 2012. Rethinking the emotional brain. Neuron, 73, 653–
676.
Lehrman, D.S. 1955. The physiological basis of parental feeding
behaviour in the ring dove (Streptopelia risoria). Behaviour, 7,
241–286.
Lehrman, D.S. 1965. Interaction between internal and external
environments in the regulation of the reproductive cycle of the
ring dove. In: F.A. Beach (ed.), Sex and Behavior, pp. 355–380.
New York: Wiley.
Lorenz, K. 1937. Über die Bildung des Instinktbegriffes.
Naturwissenschaften, 25, 289-300, 307-318, 324-331.
Lorenz, K. 1950. The comparative method in studying innate
behaviour patterns. Symposia of the Society for Experimental
Biology, 4, 221–268.
Lorenz, K. 1966. On Aggression. London: Methuen.
McDougall, W. 1923. An Outline of Psychology. London: Methuen.
McFarland, D.J. 1974. Time-sharing as a behavioral phenomenon.
Advances in the Study of Behavior, 5, 201–225.
McFarland, D.J. & Houston, A. 1981. Quantitative Ethology: The
State Space Approach. London: Pitman.
Mendl, M., Burman, O.H.P. & Paul, E.S. 2010. An integrative and
functional framework for the study of animal emotion and mood.
Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 277, 2895–2904.
Miller, N.E. 1959. Liberalization of basic S-R concepts: extensions to
conflict behavior, motivation, and social learning. In: S. Koch
(ed.), Psychology: A Study of a Science, vol. 2, pp. 196–292. New
York: McGraw-Hill.
Nelson, R.J. 2016. An Introduction to Behavioral Endocrinology, 4th
ed. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Panksepp, J. 2005. Affective consciousness: Core emotional feelings
in animals and humans. Consciousness and Cognition, 14, 30–80.
Panksepp, J. 2010. Affective consciousness in animals: Perspectives
on dimensional and primary process emotion approaches.
Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 277, 2905–2907.
Paul, E.S., Harding, E.J. & Mendl, M. 2005. Measuring emotional
processes in animals: the utility of a cognitive approach.
Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 29, 469–491.
Piersma, T. & Van Gils, J.A. 2011. The Flexible Phenotype. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Roeder, K.D. 1967. Nerve Cells and Insect Behavior, Revised ed.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Russell, J.A. 2003. Core affect and the psychological construction of
emotion. Psychological Review, 110, 145–172.
Schachter, S. & Singer, J.E. 1962. Cognitive, social, and physiological
determinants of emotional state. Psychological Review, 69, 379–
399.
Schneirla, T.C. 1965. Aspects of stimulation and organization in
approach/withdrawal processes underlying vertebrate behavioral
development. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 1, 1–74.
Sevenster, P. 1961. A causal analysis of a displacement activity
(fanning in Gasterosteus aculeatus L.). Behaviour, Suppl. 9, 1–
170.
Sevenster-Bol, A.C.A. 1962. On the causation of drive reduction after
a consummatory act. Archive Néerlandaises de Zoologie, 15, 175–
236.
Sherry, D.F., Mrosovsky, N. & Hogan, J.A. 1980. Weight loss and
anorexia during incubation in birds. Journal of Comparative and
Physiological Psychology, 94, 89–98.
Skinner, B.F. 1938. The Behavior of Organisms. New York: Appleton-
Century-Crofts.
Thorpe, W.H. 1956. Learning and Instinct in Animals. London:
Methuen.
Tinbergen, N. 1940. Die Übersprungbewegung. Zeitschrift für
Tierpsychologie, 4, 1–40.
Tinbergen, N. 1951. The Study of Instinct. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Tinbergen, N. 1952. Derived activities: Their causation, biological
significance, origin and emancipation during evolution. Quarterly
Review of Biology, 27, 1–32.
Tinbergen, N. 1959. Comparative studies of the behaviour of gulls
(Laridae): a progress report. Behaviour, 15, 1–70.
Toates, F.M. 1986. Motivational Systems. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Toates, F.M. & Jensen, P. 1991. Ethological and psychological models
of motivation: towards a synthesis. In: J.-A. Meyer & S. Wilson
(eds.), From Animals to Animats, pp. 194–205. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Tracy, J.L. & Randles, D. 2011. Four models of basic emotions: A
review of Ekman and Cordaro, Izard, Levenson, and Panksepp
and Watt. Emotion Review, 3, 397–405.
Van Iersel, J.J.A. 1953. An analysis of the parental behaviour of the
three-spined stickleback (Gasterosteus aculeatus L.). Behaviour,
Suppl. 3, 1–159.
Vestergaard, K.S. 1982. Dust-bathing in the domestic fowl: diurnal
rhythm and dust deprivation. Applied Animal Ethology, 8, 487–
495.
Vestergaard, K.S. et al. 1999. Regulation of dustbathing in feathered
and featherless domestic chicks: The Lorenzian model revisited.
Animal Behaviour, 58, 1017–1025.
Von Holst, E. 1935. Über den Prozess der zentralnervösen
Koordination. Pflügers Archiv für die gesamte Physiologie, 236,
149–158.
4
biological rhythms and behavior
RALPH E. MISTLBERGER AND BENJAMIN RUSAK
INTRODUCTION
A clockwork chipmunk
The eastern chipmunk Tamias striatus is a solitary terrestrial
squirrel that inhabits forests of eastern North America. It sleeps
at night in complete darkness in an underground burrow. During
the summer months, it emerges daily to collect food and eat. In
the autumn it switches to hoarding prodigious amounts of acorns,
beechnuts, and maple samaras in its burrow to eat during the
winter months, which it spends in its burrow under layers of
snow. If food runs short, the chipmunk becomes torpid to save
energy. By early spring the chipmunk emerges from its den to
seek a mate. The chipmunk’s behavior thus varies predictably
with time of day and season, expressing highly regular cycles in
synchrony with its environment. How are these rhythms
controlled? How does the chipmunk know the correct time to
emerge from its den each day in the summer or at the end of the
winter, given that it rests underground in constant dark and near
constant temperature? These questions of timing are the topic of
this chapter. As we shall see, biological organisms have evolved
endogenous (internal) timing devices that can be used like clocks
to enable them to do the right thing at the right time.
The Spectrum and Discovery of Biological
Rhythms
Mammals
Localization of a circadian pacemaker in mammals
Localization of the circadian clock in mammals was guided by the
reasonable assumption that it must receive information about light
and dark, possibly by a direct pathway from the retina. Cutting the
optic nerves in mammals eliminates entrainment to LD cycles but
does not eliminate circadian rhythms of behavior and physiology;
therefore, the eyes must contain the photoreceptors necessary for
entrainment but not the circadian pacemaker itself. The axons of
retinal ganglion cells form the optic nerves, which communicate
photic information to the brain. The two nerves cross, at least
partially, forming the optic chiasm at the base of the brain just below
the hypothalamus (Figure 4.5). The nerves, now renamed the optic
tracts, exit the chiasm and project to various areas of the brain
responsible for vision, oculomotor reflexes, and other functions. If all
optic tracts are cut posterior to the chiasm, the animal is rendered
visually blind; however, it remains entrained to LD cycles. Therefore,
the retinal pathway mediating photic entrainment must enter the
brain at the level of the chiasm. Sensitive tract-tracing techniques
revealed that some retinal fibers do innervate the hypothalamus
above the chiasm, particularly the SCN, which, as its name implies,
lies atop the chiasm. Surgical ablation of this small, bilateral
structure was then shown to completely eliminate circadian rhythms
of locomotor activity, body temperature, and hormones in rats, mice,
hamsters, and other species in constant conditions (Weaver 1998).
Figure 5.5 The rat brain and some areas that exhibit circadian
rhythmicity in vivo or in vitro. The SCN (suprachiasmatic nucleus) in
the hypothalamus functions as a master circadian pacemaker that is
entrained to daily LD cycles by a direct input from the retina. The
SCN exhibits circadian oscillations of neural activity and expression
of so-called clock genes, which can persist indefinitely in explants
maintained in culture (see the panel plotting bioluminescence driven
by the clock gene Per2 fused with the firefly gene encoding
luciferase). The retina itself harbors a circadian oscillator, which
controls among other things retinal production of melatonin and
light sensitivity. The SCN coordinates oscillators elsewhere in the
brain (a subset of regions that oscillate are labeled) and in the body
(peripheral organs and tissues), both directly (solid arrows) and
indirectly (dashed arrows), by its control over autonomic efferents,
hormones, body temperature, and behaviors such as eating.
(Adapted from Guilding & Piggins 2007).
Additional experiments were needed to clarify the role of the SCN: Is
it the site of the clock, or is it merely permissive for the expression of
circadian rhythms (e.g., by conveying output from the clock to the
rest of the brain)? To address its role, studies demonstrated that
stimulation of the SCN, electrically or with drugs, caused phase shifts
of circadian rhythms, mimicking those produced by light or by other
stimuli. The capacity of the SCN to generate a circadian rhythm of
metabolic and electrical activity was demonstrated both in vivo and
when isolated from the rest of the brain in a constant environment in
vitro (the SCN are dissected out and maintained in a perfusion
chamber providing oxygen and nutrients). This demonstration of
endogenous capacity to generate circadian rhythms was followed by
evidence that transplanting an SCN from a donor animal to one in
which the SCN had been ablated surgically could restore free-
running circadian rhythms of behavior. Notably, the restored
rhythms displayed a τ characteristic of the donor animal’s genotype,
not that of the host animal (Ralph & Lehmann 1991). This
remarkable series of lesion, stimulation, recording, and transplant
experiments, conducted over approximately 20 years in numerous
laboratories, established that the SCN are an autonomous circadian
oscillator responsible for setting the phase and period of circadian
rhythms (Klein et al. 1991). The SCN have thus been accorded the
status of master oscillator, or pacemaker, within the mammalian
circadian system.
Seasonal Rhythmicity
Circannual clocks
Seasonal rhythms driven by a circannual clock are those that persist
for one or more years in constant environments. Circannual clocks
have been demonstrated in a variety of longer-lived species,
including ground squirrels, marmots, deer, sheep, and some species
of bats and primates. Although generated endogenously, circannual
rhythms, like circadian rhythms, are entrained by environmental
changes in light exposure. In all species studied, annual changes in
daylength are the primary, if not exclusive, circannual Zeitgeber. In
some species, entrainment may require a gradual change in
photoperiod, as occurs in the natural habitat.
The location of the circannual clock is not known for any species
(Paul et al. 2008). Ablation studies have ruled out a necessary role
for the SCN circadian clock in most species, although in experiments
with ground squirrels, a minority of animals with SCN ablations
failed to exhibit circannual rhythms in body mass. Under some
conditions, the circannual cycle of hibernation is also disrupted by
SCN damage.
Although the pineal gland is also not necessary for the generation of
circannual rhythms, it is necessary for their entrainment by
photoperiod. The pineal gland secretes the hormone melatonin at
night, under the control of the SCN circadian pacemaker. Neural
activity in the SCN increases during the daytime (in both diurnal and
nocturnal animals) and the duration of this increased activity is
proportional to daylength. Pineal melatonin synthesis is also
inhibited by light (in mammals via the SCN). The duration of
melatonin secretion each night thus varies with the length of the day
and serves as an endogenous signal of season, when combined with
information about the direction of change in duration. Surgical
removal of the pineal abolishes entrainment of circannual rhythms.
Ultradian Rhythmicity
REFERENCES
Balsalobre, A. 2001. Clock genes in mammalian peripheral tissues.
Cell and Tissue Research, 309, 193–9.
Beersma, D.G., Daan, S. & Hut, R.A. 1999. Accuracy of circadian
entrainment under fluctuating light conditions: contributions of
phase and period responses. Journal of Biological Rhythms,
14(4), 320–9. doi:10.1177/074873099129000740.
Bloch, G., Barnes, B.M., Gerkema, M.P. & Helm, B. 2013. Animal
activity around the clock with no overt circadian rhythms:
patterns, mechanisms and adaptive value. Proceedings of the
Royal Society B. Biological Sciences, 280(1765), 20130019.
Buhr, E.D. & Takahashi, J.S. 2013. Molecular components of the
Mammalian circadian clock. Handbook of Experimental
Pharmacology, 217, 3–27.
Carskadon, M.A., Acebo, C. & Jenni, O.G. 2004. Regulation of
adolescent sleep: implications for behavior. E.P. Annals of the
New York Academy of Science, 1021, 276–91.
Cassone, V.M. 2014. Avian circadian organization: a chorus of clocks.
Frontiers in Neuroendocrinology, 25(1), 76–88.
Castillo-Ruiz, A., Paul, M.J. & Schwartz, W.J. 2012. In search of a
temporal niche: social interactions. Ch. 16. In: A. Kalsbeek, M.
Merrow, T. Roenneberg & R.G. Foster (eds.), Progress in Brain
Research, vol. 199, pp. 267–80. Elsevier.
Czeisler, C.A. & Dijk, D.-J. 2001. Human circadian physiuology and
sleep-wake regulation. In: J.S. Takahaski, F.W. Turek & R.Y.
Moore (eds.), Circadian Clocks. Handbook of Behavioral
Neurobiology, vol. 12, pp. 531–69. New York: Kluwer
Academic/Plenum.
Czeisler, C.A., Duffy, J.F., Shanahan, T.L. et al. 1999. Stability,
precision, and near-24-hour period of the human circadian
pacemaker. Science, 284(5423), 2177–81.
Czeisler, C.A., Weitzman, E.D., Moore-Ede, M.C., Zimmerman, J.C.
& Knauer, R.S. 1980. Human sleep: its duration and organization
depend on its circadian phase. Science, 210(4475), 1264–7.
Daan, S. 1981. Adaptive daily strategies in behavior. In: J. Aschoff
(ed.), Handbook of Behavioral Neurobiology 4: Biological
Rhythms, pp. 275–98. New York: Plenum.
Danilenko, K.V. & Levitan, R.D. 2012. Seasonal affective disorder.
Handbook of Clinical Neurology, 106, 279–89.
Davidson, A.J., Sellix, M.T., Daniel, J., Yamazaki, S., Menaker, M. &
Block, G.D. 2006. Chronic jet-lag increases mortality in aged
mice. Current Biology, 16, R914–6.
DeCoursey, P.J. 1986. Light-sampling behavior in photoentrainment
of a rodent circadian rhythm. Journal of Comparative Physiology
A, 159(2), 161–9. doi:10.1007/BF00612299.
DeCoursey, P.J. 2014. Survival value of suprachiasmatic nuclei
(SCN) in four wild sciurid rodents. Behavioral Neuroscience,
128(3), 240–9.
Dijk, D.-J. & Von Schantz, M. 2005. Timing and consolidation of
human sleep, wakefulness, and performance by a symphony of
oscillators. Journal of Biological Rhythms, 20, 279–90.
Edgar, R.S., Green, E.W., Zhao, Y. et al. 2012. Peroxiredoxins are
conserved markers of circadian rhythms. Nature, 485(7399),
459–64.
Gerkema, M.P., Daan, S., Wilbrink, M., Hop, M.W. & Van Der Leest,
F. 1993. Phase control of ultradian feeding rhythms in the
common vole (Microtus arvalis): the roles of light and the
circadian system. Journal of Biological Rhythms, 8, 151–71.
Guilding, C. & Piggins, H.D. 2007. Challenging the omnipotence of
the suprachiasmatic timekeeper: are circadian oscillators present
throughout the mammalian brain? European Journal of
Neuroscience, 25, 3195–3216.
Gwinner, E. & Brandstatter, R. 2001. Complex bird clocks.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B,
356, 1801–10.
Hut, R.A. 1999. Natural entrainment of circadian systems: A study of
the diurnal ground squirrel (Spermophilus citellus). Doctoral
dissertation, University of Groningen.
Hut, R.A., Kronfeld-Schor, N., Van Der Vinne, V. & De La Iglesia, H.
2012. In search of a temporal niche: Environmental factors. In: A.
Kalsbeek, M. Merrow, T. Roenneberg & R.G. Foster (eds.),
Progress in Brain Research, vol. 199, Ch. 17, pp. 281–304.
Elsevier.
Hut, R.A., Pilorz, V., Boerema, A.S., Strijkstra, A.M. & Daan, S. 2011.
Working for food shifts nocturnal mouse activity into the day.
PLoS One, 6(3), e17527.
Hut, R.A., Van Oort, B.E. & Daan, S. 1999. Natural entrainment
without dawn and dusk: the case of the European ground squirrel
(Spermophilus citellus). Journal of Biological Rhythms, 14(4),
290–9. doi:10.1177/074873099129000704.
Idda, M.L., Bertolucci, C., Vallone, D. et al. 2012. Circadian clocks:
lessons from fish. Progress in Brain Research, 199, 41–57.
Klein, D.C., Moore, R.Y. & Reppert, S.M. 1991. Suprachiasmatic
Nucleus: The Mind’s Clock. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kleitman, N. 1963. Sleep and wakefulness. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Kleitman, N. 1993. Basic rest-activity cycle. In: M.A. Carskadon (ed.),
Encyclopedia of Sleep and Dreaming, pp. 65–66. New York:
Macmillan.
Kramer, G. 1950. Orientierte Zugaktivität gekäfigter Singvögel. Die
Naturwissenschaften, 37, 188.
Lesku, J.A., Rattenborg, N.C., Valcu, M. et al. 2012. Adaptive sleep
loss in polygynous pectoral sandpipers. Science, 337, 1654–8.
Lu, W., Meng, Q.J., Tyler, N.J.C., Stokkan, K.A. & Loudon, A.S.I.
2010. A circadian clock is not required in an arctic mammal.
Current Biology, 20, 533–7.
Micic, G., Lovato, N., Gradisar, M. et al. 2016. Circadian melatonin
and temperature taus in delayed sleep-wake phase disorder and
non-24-hour sleep-wake rhythm disorder patients: an ultradian
constant routine study. Journal of Biological Rhythms, 31, 387–
405.
Mistlberger, R.E. 2009. Entrainment of circadian rhythms by food:
concepts and methods. European Journal of Neuroscience, 30(9),
1718–29.
Mistlberger, R.E. 2011. Neurobiology of food anticipatory circadian
rhythms. Physiology and Behavior, 104, 535–45.
Mistlberger, R.E. & Marchant, E.G. 1995. Computational and
entrainment models of circadian food-anticipatory activity:
Evidence from non-24 h feeding schedules. Behavioral
Neuroscience, 109, 790–8.
Mistlberger, R.E. & Skene, D.J. 2004. Social influences on circadian
rhythms in mammals: animal and human studies. Biological
Reviews, 79(3), 1–23.
Mohawk, J., Green, C.B. & Takahashi, J.S. 2012. Central and
peripheral circadian clocks in mammals. Annual Review of
Neuroscience, 35, 445–62.
Moore-Ede, C.A., Sulzman, F.M. & Fuller, C.A. 1982. The Clocks That
Time Us: Physiology of the Circadian Timing System.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Moore-Ede, M.C. 1986. Physiology of the circadian timing system:
predictive versus reactive homeostasis. American Journal of
Physiology, 250, 737–52.
Mrosovsky, N. 1999. Masking: history, definitions, and
measurement. Chronobiology International, 16, 415–29.
Mulder, C.K., Gerkema, M.P. & Van Der Zee, E.A. 2013. Circadian
clocks and memory: time-place learning. Frontiers in Molecular
Neuroscience, 6, article 8.
O’Neill, J.S., Maywood, E.S. & Hastings, M.H. 2013. Cellular
mechanisms of circadian pacemaking: beyond transcriptional
loops. Handbook of Experimental Pharmacology, 217, 67–103.
Patke, A., Young, M.W. & Axelrod, S. 2020. Molecular mechanisms
and physiological importance of circadian rhythms. Nature
Reviews Molecular and Cell Biology, 21(2), 67–84.
doi:10.1038/s41580-019-0179-2.
Paul, M.J., Zucker, I. & Schwartz, W.J. 2008. Tracking the seasons:
the internal calendars of vertebrates. Philosophical Transactions
of the Royal Society of London B, 363(1490), 341–61.
Pittendrigh, C.S. 1993. Temporal organization: reflections of a
Darwinian clock-watcher. Annual Review of Physiology, 55, 16–
54.
Pittendrigh, C.S. & Daan, S. 1974. Circadian oscillations in rodents: a
systematic increase of their frequency with age. Science, 186,
548–50.
Pittendrigh, C.S. & Daan, S. 1976. A functional analysis of circadian
pacemakers in nocturnal rodents: IV Entrainment: Pacemaker as
clock. Journal of Comparative Physiology A, 106, 291–331.
Ralph, M.R. & Lehman, M.N. 1991. Transplantation: a new tool in
the analysis of the mammalian hypothalamic circadian
pacemaker. Trends in Neuroscience, 14, 362–66.
Rastogi, A., Kumari, Y., Rani, S. & Kumar, V. 2011. Phase inversion
of neural activity in the olfactory and visual systems of a night-
migratory bird during migration. European Journal of
Neuroscience, 34, 99–109.
Rattenborg, N.C., Mandt, B.H., Obermeyer, W.H. et al. 2004.
Migratory sleeplessness in the white-crowned sparrow
(Zonotrichia leucophrys gambelii). PLoS Biology, 2, 924–36.
Rattenborg, N.C., Voirin, B., Cruz, S.M. et al. 2016. Evidence that
birds sleep in mid-flight. Nature Communications, 7, 12468.
Roenneberg, T., Kantermann, T., Juda, M., Vetter, C. & Allebrandt,
K.V. 2013. Light and the human circadian clock. Handbook of
Experimental Pharmacology, 217, 311–31. doi:10.1007/978-3-
642-25950-0_13.
Roenneberg, T., Kuehnle, T., Pramstaller, P.P. et al. 2004. A marker
for the end of adolescence. Current Biology, 14(24), R1038–9.
Rowsmitt, C.N. 1986. Seasonal variations in activity rhythms of male
voles: mediation by gonadal hormones. Physiology and Behavior,
37, 797–803.
Scheibler, E., Wollnik, F., Brodbeck, D. et al. 2013. Species
composition and interspecific behavior affects activity pattern of
free-living desert hamsters in the Alashan Desert. Journal of
Mammalogy, 94, 448–58.
Stratmann, M. & Schibler, U. 2006. Properties, entrainment, and
physiological functions of mammalian peripheral oscillators.
Journal of Biological Rhythms, 21(6), 494–506.
Tosini, G. & Menaker, M. 1996. Circadian rhythms in cultured
mammalian retina. Science, 272, 419–21.
Van Oort, B.E., Tyler, N.J., Gerkema, M.P. et al. 2005. Circadian
organization in reindeer. Nature, 438(7071), 1095–6.
Vanin, S., Bhutani, S., Montelli, S. et al. 2012. Unexpected features of
Drosophila circadian behavioural rhythms under natural
conditions. Nature, 484, 371–5.
Voirin, B., Scriba, M.F., Martinez-Gonzalez, D. et al. 2014. Ecology
and neurophysiology of sleep in two wild sloth species. Sleep, 37,
753–61.
Wallraff, H.G. 1981. Clock-controlled orientation in space. In: J.
Aschoff (ed.), Handbook of Behavioral Neurobiology, vol. 4, pp.
275–98. New York: Plenum.
Weaver, D.R. 1998. The suprachiasmatic nucleus: a 25-year
retrospective. Journal of Biological Rhythms, 13, 100–12.
Webb, I.C., Antle, M.C. & Mistlberger, R.E. 2014. Regulation of
circadian rhythms in mammals by behavioral arousal. Behavioral
Neuroscience, 128(3), 304–25.
Welsh, D.K., Logothetis, D.E., Meister, M. & Reppert, S.M. 1995.
Individual neurons dissociated from rat suprachiasmatic nucleus
express independently phased circadian firing rhythms. Neuron,
14, 697–706.
Yamada, N., Shimoda, K., Ohi, K., Takahashi, S. & Takahashi, K.
1988. Free-access to a running wheel shortens the period of free-
running rhythm in blinded rats. Physiology and Behavior, 42,
87–91.
Yamazaki, S., Numano, R., Abe, M. et al. 2000. Resetting central and
peripheral circadian oscillators in transgenic rats. Science,
288(5466), 682–5.
5
brain and behavior
DAVID F. SHERRY
INTRODUCTION
The brains of animals do many things. For the purposes of this
chapter the things brains do are organized into three broad
categories. Brains obtain information from the environment, they
carry out cognitive operations, and they control movement:
input, central processing, and output. These categories are broad
because although they are certainly the conventional way of
thinking about the brain and behavior, from the beginning of
systematic work on the topic (Lashley 1929) to present-day
research (Poeppel et al. 2020), it is often not possible to find a
clear demarcation between, say, receiving sensory input from the
environment and performing cognitive operations on that input.
The “cognitive” category itself is a very broad one, including
everything from memory to spatial orientation, timing, decision-
making, and social interactions. These categories are therefore
more an organizational convenience that corresponds to how we
think about the things a brain does than how the nervous system
actually divides up the tasks it performs. With this in mind, let us
begin with the first category, how animals obtain information
about their environment.
Cognition
We turn next to the cognitive functions of the brain. “Cognition” in
animals means many things to many people (see also Chapter 9). For
some it implies that animals think, possess consciousness, and
experience the world as we do (Griffin 2001). We will not be using
the term “cognition” in this sense. Apart from the obvious problem of
verifying what another organism, even another human, thinks or
experiences, using our own thoughts or conscious experience to
understand cognition can be misleading. Neuropsychological
research with humans shows that what we experience is rarely a
reliable guide to how our cognitive processes actually work (Schacter
1996). In addition, using human experience as a model for cognition
in animals seems likely to seriously underestimate the diversity of
animal experience, whatever it might be.
The term “cognition” is used by many researchers, in this chapter
and in Chapter 9, in quite a different way, to refer to information
processing in a general sense. The term is broad enough to embrace
widespread forms of learning, like Pavlovian conditioning, as well as
kinds of learning that seem to follow rules of their own, like song
learning, imprinting, and some learned components of navigation.
So at the cost of fuzziness about exactly what cognition is and what it
is not, our working definition of cognition will be the processing of
information about the animal’s environment.
Honeybee learning
Honeybees (Apis mellifera) have a characteristic response to sugars
that does not require learning. When sensory cells on their legs,
antennae, or mouthparts detect sucrose, usually in the nectar of a
flower, bees extend their proboscis and siphon up the nectar
(Figure 5.4). Honeybees do not respond, however, to the colors,
shapes, or odors of flowers in this way. They have preferences for
approaching certain colors, shapes, and odors more than others, but
identifying which flowers within flying distance of the hive are
producing nectar and which are not requires learning the visual and
olfactory characteristics of flowers and associating them with the
presence of nectar.
Figure 5.4 Electron micrograph of the head of a honeybee
showing the antennae and proboscis. (From the Centre for Electron
Optical Studies, University of Bath, Bath, UK; Copyright University
of Bath).
The neural pathways involved in learning the olfactory traits of
flowers and associating them with the presence of nectar have been
investigated extensively by Menzel and his colleagues (Menzel &
Müller 1996; Menzel et al. 2001). The neuroanatomical circuitry, and
especially the intracellular processes involved in the formation of
memory, are the topics of the next section. Learning in the honeybee
provides an illustration of the neural basis of what is, conceptually at
least, a relatively simple cognitive event: forming a Pavlovian
association between two stimuli (see Chapter 8).
Pavlovian conditioning involves an unconditioned stimulus (US)
that elicits an unlearned response. For the honeybee, the US is
sucrose and the response is extension of the proboscis. The second
stimulus is the conditioned stimulus (CS), in this case floral odor,
to which the bee does not initially respond with proboscis extension.
As a result of experiencing a contingent relation between detecting
the odor and encountering sucrose, the odor eventually comes to
elicit the conditioned response of proboscis extension. In the
terminology of contemporary Pavlovian learning theory, an
association is formed between odor and sucrose because the odor is a
good predictor of the presence of sucrose. Conditioning of the
proboscis extension response (PER) in the honeybee provides an
opportunity to examine the cellular and molecular processes that
take place in the honeybee brain during the formation of this learned
association.
The idea that a record of experience—whether we call it an
association, a memory trace, or an engram—involves a structural
change at the cellular level was most clearly articulated by Donald
Hebb in 1949, and this idea has come to be called Hebb’s rule:
When an axon of cell A is near enough to excite a cell B and
repeatedly or persistently takes part in firing it, some growth
process or metabolic change takes place in one or both cells such
that A’s efficiency, as one of the cells firing B, is increased.(Hebb
1949, p. 62)
A “Hebb synapse” is thus a connection between neurons that
becomes more effective at stimulating its target neuron as a
consequence of correlated activity in the two cells. A great deal of
contemporary research in the neurosciences has been directed at
finding cells and synapses that conform to Hebb’s rule. There are
some limitations to Hebb’s rule. In its simplest form it allows the
probability that one cell will fire another to increase indefinitely,
even when cells occasionally fire together by coincidence, and so
modifications of Hebb’s rule are used in modelling neural networks.
But Hebb’s rule remains a useful heuristic and neurons in the
mushroom bodies of the honeybee brain that are responsible for
Pavlovian conditioning are one example of a system that has been
discovered to follow the rule Hebb had in mind.
Mushroom bodies
The mushroom bodies are a paired structure, one on the left and one
on the right, in the most anterior part of the honeybee brain, the
protocerebral lobe. The mushroom bodies vary enormously among
insects and can be identified in many other arthropods, including
spiders, scorpions, horseshoe crabs, and the pycnogonids or sea
spiders (Strausfeld et al. 1998). The honeybee mushroom body
consists of two cup-shaped structures, the calyces, joined by a stem
called the peduncle (Figure 5.5a,b). Surrounding the calyces are the
cell bodies of Kenyon cells, which receive converging input from
olfactory receptors in the proboscis and antennae and sucrose
receptors in the tarsae. Much of the structure of the mushroom body
consists of densely packed fiber projections of the Kenyon cells and
axons conveying input from, or sending output to, other parts of the
brain.
Figure 5.5 (a) The brain of the honeybee (Apis mellifera) shown
as a three-dimensional reconstruction in its approximate location in
the head. Red: mushroom bodies; blue: central body; yellow: optic
lobes; green: antennal lobes. (b) Structure of the mushroom body. l,
lateral; m, medial; col, collar; Pe, peduncle; br, basal ring; vl, vertical
lobe. a & b from Avargues-Weber & Giurfa. (2013). (c) Acetylcholine
(ACh) released at the conditioned stimulus (CS) synapse causes an
influx of calcium ions (Ca2+) in the Kenyon cell. Octopamine (Oc)
released at the unconditioned stimulus (US) synapse causes an influx
of Ca2+ and activation of adenylate cyclase (AC). Adenylate cyclase
converts ATP to cyclic AMP (cAMP), which activates protein kinase A
(PKA). PKA phosphorylates the cAMP-binding protein (CREB).
Signals from olfactory receptors in the honeybee antennae, the
pathway conveying information about the odor CS, are relayed first
to the antennal lobes and then to the mushroom body calyces. Input
from receptors in the proboscis, the pathway conveying the
information about the sucrose US, is relayed first to the
suboesophageal ganglion and then along a branch of the ventral
unpaired median neuron (VUM) to the mushroom body calyces.
Electrical stimulation of this branch of the VUM or injection of
octopamine, the neurotransmitter used by this neuron, can
substitute for the sucrose US and produce conditioning of the PER to
an odor.
Converging input
Encountering a floral odor followed by detection of sucrose should
thus cause firing of Kenyon cells by input from the antennae and,
immediately following or concurrently, further firing caused by input
from the proboscis. If Pavlovian conditioning of the PER follows
Hebb’s rule we would expect to find mushroom-body Kenyon cells
that, as a result of this concurrent neural activity, are more easily
fired by odor input alone. Such change in the ability of an odor to
activate a Kenyon cell would be the fundamental basis of the
conditioned PER to odor. A great deal of progress has been made in
identifying the molecular events within Kenyon cells that follow CS
and US stimulation. Interestingly, these molecular events are broadly
similar to the intracellular events that underlie conditioning in the
sea slug Aplysia and are also involved in the phenomenon of long-
term potentiation (LTP) in vertebrates (Bliss & Lømo 1973). LTP
is an experimental procedure that follows the Hebb rule par
excellence. Repeated stimulation of neurons in the rat hippocampus,
for example, results in a greater response by these cells to
subsequent stimulation. This increased responsiveness can persist
for days or weeks (hence “long-term” potentiation) and is thought to
resemble processes involved in neural plasticity and learning.
Induction of LTP depends on one of the several different receptors
for the neurotransmitter glutamate, the N-methyl-D-aspartate
(NMDA) receptor. These receptors only function when there is both
depolarization of the postsynaptic neuron and activation of the
NMDA receptor by glutamate released from the axon terminals of
the presynaptic neuron. Induction of LTP thus depends on
simultaneous activation of the presynaptic and postsynaptic neuron,
the same mechanism that Hebb proposed.
Activation of mushroom body Kenyon cells by a CS signal from the
antennae and a US signal from the proboscis initiates a cascade of
molecular events inside the cell that leads ultimately to gene
transcription, protein synthesis, and permanent structural or
metabolic changes in neurons. The discussion that follows describes
only a few of these molecular events, but enough to give an idea of
the molecular processes known to characterize learning and the
formation of memory across a wide variety of animals.
Release of acetylcholine, the neurotransmitter in the CS pathway
from the antennal lobe to the mushroom bodies, causes an increase
in the concentration of calcium ions (Ca2+) inside the Kenyon cell
(Figure 5.5c). Release of octopamine, the neurotransmitter in the US
pathway from the proboscis, increases activity of the enzyme
adenylate cyclase as well as increasing the intracellular concentration
of Ca2+. Adenylate cyclase converts adenosine 5´-triphosphate (ATP)
to cyclic adenosine monophosphate (cAMP). cAMP is one of the best
known and the first discovered second messengers, agents that
respond to signals originating outside the cell and which relay these
signals inside cells. One of the effects of cAMP is to activate protein
kinase A (PKA). The protein kinases are a family of catalysts that
facilitate phosphorylation, the transfer of phosphate from ATP to a
wide variety of proteins, regulating the activity of these proteins.
If the two events of CS activation and US activation occur
successively, their effects not only summate but interact. This is
because one consequence of elevated Ca2+ concentration inside the
cell is greater adenylate cyclase activity, the signal that ultimately
leads to elevated levels of PKA. Thus, if Ca2+ levels produced by the
CS odor signal are still high when the US sucrose signal arrives, there
will be greater PKA activity than produced by the sucrose signal
alone.
PKA activity, and the effect it has on phosphorylation of proteins
inside the Kenyon cell, is known to be a necessary step in
conditioning of the PER in the honeybee. Interfering with PKA
synthesis impairs memory measured 1 day after training (Fiala et al.
1999). Similar memory impairments occur in the fruit fly Drosophila
with mutations affecting PKA activity.
How does phosphorylation of a protein by PKA result in memory
formation? The activity of some genes is regulated by a region of
DNA called the cAMP-response element (CRE). Activation of the
CRE sequence is in turn controlled by a protein, the CRE-binding
protein (CREB). CREB is one of the proteins under the control of
phosphorylation mediated by PKA.
This series of interacting switches and controls, initiated by CS and
US stimulation, leads finally to gene transcription and the synthesis
of proteins inside the Kenyon cell. In the honeybee, disruption of
protein synthesis has little effect on learning in the first 24 hours
after odor conditioning, but 3 days later there are significant
impairments (Wüstenberg et al. 1998). The activity of genes coding
for many proteins are regulated by CREB. One such gene codes for
synapsin I, a protein that releases vesicles containing
neurotransmitter and allows them to move to the axon terminal
where they can be released into the synapse (Montminy & Bilezikjian
1987). Another gene regulated by CREB codes for ubiquitin, a
protein that forms part of a feedback loop that causes successive
bouts of PKA activity to be increasingly long-lasting, producing long-
term changes in cell chemistry, gene transcription, and protein
synthesis (Chain et al. 2000).
The second messenger system and its target, gene expression, are
tightly regulated to produce functional behavioral consequences.
Molecular signals of the kind involved in Pavlovian conditioning of
proboscis extension in the honeybee are known to underlie learning
and memory, as well as other forms of neural plasticity, in a wide
variety of animals and appear to be relatively conserved in evolution
despite enormous change in behavior. Molecular signaling systems
and the regulation of gene expression are essential cell functions
throughout the body, not just in the nervous system, and even in the
nervous system serve many functions beside forming permanent
records of experience. These cell signaling systems have been
recruited to produce the neural plasticity involved in the formation
of associations and give us a glimpse of the events inside neurons
that make cognition possible.
Control of Behavior
FURTHER READING
Sound localization in birds, mammals, and reptiles is discussed by
Ashida and Carr (2011) and the evolution of sound localization by
Carr & Christensn-Dalsgaard (2016). Multimodal courtship
displays like those of cowbirds are examined by Mitoyen et al.
(2019). Leonard and Masek (2014) take an ethological approach
to the neural and cognitive mechanisms of odor and color learning
in bees, and the neural basis of olfaction and olfactory learning in
honeybees is reviewed by Paoli and Galizia (2021). The
neurobiology of vocalization in birds and mammals is examined
by Mooney (2020) and contrasting views on adult neurogenesis
are presented in a collection of papers in the Journal of
Neuroscience (vol. 22, no. 3, February 2002). A wealth of
information on animal communication can be found in Bradbury
and Vehrencamp (2011) and Searcy and Nowicki (2005). Poeppel
et al. (2020) contains many chapters by researchers in the
neurosciences on auditory and visual perception, cognition, and
motor control.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I would to thank Scott MacDougall-Shackleton, Jeff Martin, Maddie
Brodbeck, and the late Peter Cain for their many helpful comments
and suggestions on this chapter and Carrie Branch for discussion of
perception and female choice.
REFERENCES
Altman, J. 1962. Are neurons formed in the brains of adult
mammals? Science, 135, 1127–8.
Alvarez-Buylla, A., Theelen, M. & Nottebohm, F. 1990. Proliferation
“hotspots” in adult avian ventricular zone reveal radial cell
division. Neuron, 5, 101–9.
Andersson, M. 1994. Sexual Selection. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Ashida, G. & Carr, C.E. 2011. Sound localization: Jeffress and
beyond. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 21, 745–51.
Avargues-Weber, A. & Giurfa, M. 2013. Conceptual learning by
miniature brains. Proceedings of the Royal Society B-Biological
Sciences, 280, 20131907.
Balthazart, J., Boseret, G., Konkle, A.T.M., Hurley, L.L. & Ball, G.F.
2008. Doublecortin as a marker of adult neuroplasticity in the
canary song control nucleus HVC. European Journal of
Neuroscience, 27, 801–17.
Bliss, T.V.P. & Lomo, T. 1973. Long-lasting potentiation of synaptic
transmission in the dentate area of the unanaesthetized rabbit
following stimulation of the perforant path. Journal of Physiology
London, 232, 331–56.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Moorman, S. 2015. Birdsong memory and the brain:
In search of the template. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral
Reviews, 50, 41–55.
Bradbury, J.W. & Vehrencamp, S.L. 2011.Principles of animal
communication, 2nd ed. Sunderland MA: Sinauer.
Carr, C.E. & Christensen-Dalsgaard, J. 2016. Evolutionary trends in
directional hearing. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 40, 111–7.
Carr, C.E. & Konishi, M. 1990. A circuit for detection of interaural
time differences in the brain stem of the barn owl. Journal of
Neuroscience, 10, 3227–46.
Catchpole, C.K. & Slater, P.J.B. 1995. Bird Song: Biological Themes
and Variations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chain, D.G., Schwartz, J.H. & Hegde, A.N. 2000. Ubiquitin-
mediated proteolysis in learning and memory. Molecular
Neurobiology, 20, 125–42.
Deisseroth, K. 2011. Optogenetics. Nature Methods, 8, 26–9.
Doetsch, F. & Hen, R. 2005. Young and excitable: the function of
new neurons in the adult mammalian hippocampus. Current
Opinion in Neurobiology, 15, 121–8.
Fiala, A., Müller, U. & Menzel, R. 1999. Reversible downregulation of
protein kinase a during olfactory learning using antisense
technique impairs long-term memoiy formation in the honeybee,
Apis mellifera. Journal of Neuroscience, 19, 10125–34.
Fux, M. & Eilam, D. 2009. How barn owls (Tyto alba) visually follow
moving voles (Microtus socialis) before attacking them.
Physiology & Behavior, 98, 359–66.
Goldman, S.A. & Nottebohm, F. 1983. Neuronal production,
migration, and differentiation in a vocal control nucleus of the
adult female canary brain. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences USA, 80, 2390–4.
Gould, E., Tanapat, P., Hastings, N.B. & Shors, T.J. 1999.
Neurogenesis in adulthood: a possible role in learning. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, 3, 186–92.
Griffin, D.R. 2001. Animal Minds: Beyond Cognition to
Consciousness, 2nd ed. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Hebb, D.O. 1949. The Organization of Behavior: &
Neuropsychological Theory. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Hegemann, P. & Nagel, G. 2013. From channelrhodopsins to
optogenetics. Embo Molecular Medicine, 5, 173–6.
Jarvis, E.D. & Nottebohm, F. 1997. Motor-driven gene expression.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 94, 4097–
102.
Jeffress, L.A. 1948. A place theory of sound localization. Journal of
Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 41, 35–9.
Kee, N., Teixeira, C.M., Wang, A.H. & Frankland, P.W. 2007.
Preferential incorporation of adult-generated granule cells into
spatial memory networks in the dentate gyrus. Nature
Neuroscience, 10, 355–62.
Kettler, L., Griebel, H., Ferger, R. & Wagner, H. 2017. Combination
of interaural level and time difference in azimuthal sound
localization in owls. eNeuro, 4, e0238-0217.2017.
Konishi, M. 1995. Neural mechanisms of auditory image formation.
In: M.S. Gazzaniga (ed.), The Cognitive Neurosciences, pp. 269–
77. Cambridge, MA: MTT Press.
Lashley, K.S. 1929. Brain Mechanisms and Intelligence. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Leonard, A.S. & Masek, P. 2014. Multisensory integration of colors
and scents: insights from bees and flowers. Journal of
Comparative Physiology a-Neuroethology Sensory Neural and
Behavioral Physiology, 200, 463–74.
Menzel, R., Giurfa, M., Gerber, B. & Hellstem, F. 2001. Cognition in
insects: the honeybee as a study case. In: G. Roth & M.F.
Wullimann (eds.), Brain Evolution and Cognition, pp. 333–66.
New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Menzel, R. & Müller, U. 1996. Learning and memory in honeybees:
from behavior to neural substrates. Annual Review of
Neuroscience, 19, 379–404.
Mitoyen, C., Quigley, C. & Fusani, L. 2019. Evolution and function of
multimodal courtship displays. Ethology, 125, 503–15.
Moiseff, A. 1989. Bi-coordinate sound localization by the barn owl.
Journal of Comparative Physiology A, 164, 637–44.
Moiseff, A. & Konishi, M. 1981. Neuronal and behavioral sensitivity
to binaural time differences in the owl. Journal of Neuroscience,
1, 40–8.
Moiseff, A. & Konishi, M. 1983. Binaural characteristics of units in
the owl’s brainstem auditory pathway: precursors of restricted
spatial receptive fields. Journal of Neuroscience, 3, 2553–62.
Montminy, M.R. & Bilezikjian, L.M. 1987. Binding of a nuclear
protein to the cyclic-AMP response element of the somatostatin
gene. Nature, 328, 175–8.
Mooney, R. 2020. The neurobiology of innate and learned
vocalizations in rodents and songbirds. Current Opinion in
Neurobiology, 64, 24–31.
Moorman, S., Mello, C.V. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2011. From songs to
synapses: Molecular mechanisms of birdsong memory. BioEssays,
33, 377–85.
Nottebohm, F. 1981. A brain for all seasons: cyclical anatomical
changes in song control nuclei of the canary brain. Science, 214,
1368–70.
Paoli, M. & Galizia, G.C. 2021. Olfactory coding in honeybees. Cell
and Tissue Research, 383, 35–58.
Peña, J.L., Viete, S., Funabiki, K., Saberi, K. & Konishi, M. 2001.
Cochlear and neural delays for coincidence detection in owls.
Journal of Neuroscience, 21, 9455–9.
Poeppel, D., Manguin, G.R. & Gazzaniga, M.S. (eds.). 2020. The
cognitive neurosciences, 6th ed. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Rayleigh, L. 1907. XII. On our perception of sound direction.
Philosophical Magazine Series 6, 13, 214–32.
Ronald, K.L., Fernandez-Juricic, E. & Lucas, J.R. 2018. Mate choice
in the eye and ear of the beholder? Female multimodal sensory
configuration influences her preferences. Proceedings of the
Royal Society B, 285, 20180713.
Schacter, D.L. 1996. Searching for Memory. New York: Basic Books.
Searcy, W.A. & Nowicki, S. 2005. The evolution of animal
communication: Reliability and deception in signaling systems.
Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.
Seidl, A.H., Rubel, E.W. & Harris, D.M. 2010. Mechanisms for
adjusting interaural time differences to achieve binaural
coincidence detection. Journal of Neuroscience, 30, 70–80.
Shaaya, M., Fauser, J. & Karginov, A.V. 2021. Optogenetics: The art
of illuminating complex signaling pathways. Physiology, 36, 52–
60.
Strausfeld, N.J., Hansen, L., Yongsheng, L., Gomez, R.S. & Ito, K.
1998. Evolution, discovery, and interpretations of arthropod
mushroom bodies. Learning and Memory, 5, 11–37.
Takahashi, T., Moiseff, A. & Konishi, M. 1984. Time and intensity
cues are processed independently in the auditory system of the
owl. Journal of Neuroscience, 4, 1781–6.
Tramontin, A.D. 1998. Seasonal plasticity and sexual dimorphism in
the avian song control system: stereological measurement of
neuron density and number. Journal of Comparative Neurology,
396, 186–92.
Tramontin, A.D. & Brenowitz, E.A. 1999. A field study of seasonal
neuronal incorporation into the song control system of a songbird
that lacks adult song learning. Journal of Neurobiology, 40, 316–
26.
Tramontin, A.D. & Brenowitz, E.A. 2000. Seasonal plasticity in the
adult brain. Trends in Neurosciences, 23, 251–8.
Wagner, H., Kettler, L., Orlowski, J. & Tellers, P. 2013.
Neuroethology of prey capture in the barn owl (Tyto alba L.).
Journal of Physiology-Paris, 107, 51–61.
Wüstenberg, D., Gerber, B. & Menzel, R. 1998. Long- but not
medium-term retention of olfactory memories in honeybees is
impaired by actinomycin D and anisomycin. European Journal of
Neuroscience, 10, 2742–5.
Zhao, W.C., Garcia-Oscos, F., Dinh, D. & Roberts, T.F. 2019.
Inception of memories that guide vocal learning in the songbird.
Science, 366, 83–9.
6
hormones and behavior
JACQUES BALTHAZART AND GREGORY F. BALL
INTRODUCTION
In order to form pluricellular organisms, it is necessary for cells
to be able to communicate with each other in an adaptive manner
that allows them to synchronize metabolism, rhythmic activity,
and eventually behavior between the parts forming a given
individual. Two significant solutions emerged over the course of
the evolution of life to address this problem, especially in
vertebrates: a centralized nervous system and hormones. Within
the nervous system, cells communicate via electrochemical
means or direct electrical communication (see Chapter 5).
Hormones are, in contrast, chemical messengers secreted by
specialized endocrine cells, organized into ductless glands, that
transport information via body fluids (mainly blood in
vertebrates) to specialized cells with specific receptors that allow
them to bind the hormone, which then results in a change in
signaling or metabolic activity.
In this chapter we present, in a synthetic manner, the wealth of
information that has accumulated primarly in the past 50–60
years concerning the mechanisms through which hormones
modulate behaviors. In the first section, we provide a brief
introduction to how hormones are able to affect brain activity in
relation to the control of behavior. The second section then
describes the major concepts that have been established to
account for the reciprocal interactions between hormones and
behavior. A third and final section will illustrate these concepts
with a few selected examples. We will concentrate on examples of
hormone–behavior interactions that we think are among the best
understood, namely the roles of sex steroid hormones in the
control of reproductive behaviors in birds and mammals. A few
other behavioral systems modulated by hormones will, however,
also be briefly discussed.
A Primer on Hormone Action in the Brain
Steroid metabolism
When entering the target tissues, testosterone, progesterone, and to
some extent estradiol undergo metabolic transformations. Two
enzymes, aromatase and 5α-reductase, catalyze the transformation
of testosterone into behaviorally relevant metabolites estradiol and
5α-dihydrotestosterone (5α-DHT), respectively. Additional enzymes
inactivate the steroid (e.g., 5β-reductase producing the behaviorally
inactive compound 5β-DHT). Progesterone is similarly metabolized
by the 5α- and 5β-reductase into 5α- and 5β-progesterone that have
a very different behavioral impact compared to progesterone; 5α-
progesterone namely is a high affinity ligand for the GABA (gamma-
aminobutyric acid) receptors. Estradiol is also subjected to
hydroxylations in brain cells to form compounds known as
catecholestrogens but their functional significance remains poorly
understood.
Because the concentration and activity of all these enzymes is
regulated, the ratio of active versus inactive metabolites that are
produced in the brain that can interact with the corresponding
receptors is affected by factors such as the sex, age, season, or
hormonal condition of the subjects. This provides a mechanism,
potentially fine-tuning the expression of hormone-dependent
behavior.
In many species, testosterone acts as a pro-hormone, i.e., it must
first be metabolized into another steroid before acting at the cellular
level. In a large number of species of birds and mammals, including
rats and Japanese quail, it is estradiol, sometimes erroneously
considered as a “female hormone,” that is locally produced in specific
regions of the male brain by aromatization of testosterone that
induces, at the cellular level, the neurochemical changes resulting in
the activation of male sexual behavior. In other species, such as
rabbits or guinea pigs, it is the 5α-DHT obtained by local 5α-
reduction of testosterone that activates copulatory behavior. In most
species, however, the full activation of male sexual behavior results
from a synergistic action of both testosterone metabolites, estradiol
and 5α-DHT. The relative role of these two steroids in this process
varies between species, but it seems that both are usually involved.
In many fish species, the main androgenic steroid found in the blood
that plays a major role in the activation of male sexual and aggressive
behaviors is not testosterone itself but a related compound derived
from testosterone called 11-ketotestosterone (11KT). In this case,
however, the critical transformation of testosterone into 11KT
already takes place in the testis, and the active steroid is also the
steroid found in the blood, whereas in the avian and mammalian
examples just discussed, testosterone is the circulating pro-hormone
and the transformation into the active metabolite (estradiol and/or
5α-DHT) takes place in the target organ itself, in specific neurons
that express the relevant enzymes. Testosterone therefore often acts
as a pro-hormone in the control of behavior, and the chemical signal
that acts at the cellular level to affect behavior is in fact a metabolite
of this prohormone. Interestingly, thyroxine is also a pro-hormone
released into the blood by the thyroid gland and it is locally
transformed via enyzmatic action to an active metabolite
triiodothyronine in target tissues. Thus, an important concept in
behavioral endocrinology is that hormonal effects can be amplified
via their transformation at specific times and and in specific
locations to more active forms.
Membrane receptors and the modulation of intracellular
signaling cascades
Steroid-induced behavioral changes described so far usually appear
after an exposure to the steroid, ranging from a few hours to a few
days. Such a time course can explain changes in reproductive
behavior that are observed over months during the annual cycle in
seasonally breeding animals. However, much faster actions of
steroids have also been identified, suggesting that these hormones
may also act via fundamentally different mechanisms. This is
particularly the case for estradiol, a steroid produced in the brain by
aromatization of testosterone that plays a key role in the activation of
male sexual behavior.
It was observed already in the 1970s that estradiol is able to
modulate the electrical activity of hypothalamic neurons within
minutes if not seconds. More recently, evidence has accumulated
indicating that estrogens acutely influence behavioral processes such
as pain perception, memory, and aggressive and sexual behaviors. It
was, for example, demonstrated that a subcutaneous injection of
estradiol stimulates mounts and anogenital investigations within 35
minutes in castrated rats (Rattus norvegicus), a latency too short to
be compatible with an activation by genomic mechanisms.
Subsequent studies demonstrated that a single injection of estradiol
facilitates the expression of most aspects of male sexual behavior
within 10–15 minutes in quail (Coturnix japonica) and mice (Mus
musculus). The existence of such rapid behavioral effects of estradiol
seems to be an ancient feature in vertebrates since these effects are
also observed broadly across taxonomic groups including fishes. For
example, the injection of estradiol modulates within minutes the
production of courtship vocalization in the plainfin midshipman fish
(Porichthys notatus).
Although purely cytoplasmic effects have also been described, these
rapid effects are generally initiated by steroids acting at the plasma
membrane, resulting in the activation of a wide variety of
intracellular signaling pathways. Even if many questions remain
open, it is now clear that multiple estrogen receptors are present at
the neuronal membrane including the two classical nuclear estrogen
receptors (ERα and ERβ, which in addition to being present in the
cytoplasm and the nucleus can fuse to the membrane via
palymitolyation processes and association with caveolin-1), a G-
protein-coupled receptor (GPR30) and two other membrane
receptors that have been postulated based on functional or
pharmacological evidence but have not been formally identified at
this time. The binding of estradiol to these receptors activates a
variety of intracellular signaling cascades that result in the
phosphorylation of various proteins such as enzymes or receptors,
changes in intracellular calcium concentration or even activation of
genomic transcription (indirect genomic effects) that ultimately
result in behavioral effects.
It is currently difficult to assess how general these membrane-
initiated steroid effects on behavior are, but research in this field is
very active at present and regularly leads to new discoveries. It has
been argued that in this short-term temporal context, estradiol
displays most, if not all, functional characteristics of a
neurotransmitter or at least a neuromodulator and thus can regulate
short-term changes in behavior that are usually considered to be
controlled by classical transmitters such as dopamine, noradrenalin,
and serotonin. Estradiol and other steroids could thus control both
the long-term and short-term changes in behavior allowing the
animal to adapt to lasting changes in the environment (e.g., seasons)
but also to more discrete disruption events (presence of a receptive
female, of a predator, snow storm, etc.). These steroids thus act in in
two different time domains to control long- and short-term changes
in behavior (Cornil et al. 2015).
It should also be noted that in addition to sex steroids, other larger
or more polar molecules such as the peptidergic or protein hormones
(e.g., vasopressin/vasotocin, oxytocin, gonadotropin-releasing
hormone, prolactin, etc.) that also play a role in the control of social
behaviors similarly produce their effects by binding to receptors
located at the cell membrane that are coupled to the activation of a
second intracellular messenger system (e.g., activation of adenylate
cyclase leading to the synthesis of cyclic AMP). It is, however, beyond
the scope of this chapter to review all these cellular mechanisms that
differ among hormones, brain regions, and species.
Basic Physiological Mechanisms
Mediating Hormone Effects on Behavior
Birds
In avian species that have been studied in detail, mainly quail
(Coturnix japonica) and to some extent chickens (Gallus
domesticus) and ducks (Anas platyrhynchos), exposure to steroids
early in ontogeny also affects the responsiveness to steroids in
adulthood, but this sexual differentiation process seems to affect
exclusively male-typical behaviors. A variety of male-typical sexual
behaviors have been described that cannot be activated in females
even after treatment with high doses of testosterone. Female
reproductive behaviors (e.g., sexual receptivity postures such as
squatting) are in contrast not sexually differentiated and can be
activated in both sexes provided an adequate treatment with
estrogens is administered. In these avian species, the sex difference
in responsiveness to adult testosterone is the result of the early
exposure of female embryos to ovarian estrogens (as opposed to
exposure of males to testicular androgen as is the case in mammals).
In the absence of embryonic steroids, the male phenotype of
responsiveness to testosterone develops. In the presence of
estrogens, behavior is demasculinized: birds lose the capacity of
express, as adults, male-typical copulatory behavior in response to
testosterone.
This physiological process can be experimentally manipulated so that
the male or female behavioral phenotypes are induced in either
genetic sex by adequate embryonic endocrine manipulations. In
Japanese quail, treatment of a male embryo with estrogens on day 9
of incubation produces an adult that will never exhibit the male-
typical copulatory patterns even after treatment with behaviorally
active doses of testosterone. Conversely, early treatment of female
embryos with an aromatase inhibitor that blocks estrogen synthesis
leads to the development of a fully masculine behavioral phenotype.
Contrary to what is observed in mammals, in the absence of gonadal
steroids, these avian species thus develop a male phenotype while the
female phenotype develops in the presence of estrogens.
These contrasting patterns of differentiation in birds and mammals
(i.e., relative absence of endocrine stimulation during early life
results in male behavioral phenotype in birds and in female
behavioral phenotype in mammals) might be related to the fact that
females are the homogametic sex in mammals (female XX and male
XY) while males are homogametic in birds (male ZZ and female ZW).
This observation could then highlight a more general rule according
to which the phenotype of the heterogametic sex (male mammals
[XY] and female birds [ZW]) would always develop in response to
hormonal stimulation during ontogeny while the behavioral
phenotype of the homogametic sex would be the “default” sex
observed in the absence of early endocrine stimulation (also referred
to as the “neutral” sex). This principle must be accepted cautiously at
present because the proximate mechanisms that might explain this
connection between the nature of the sex chromosomes in males and
females and the process of behavioral differentiation have still not
been identified. In particular, the process of sexual differentiation of
the gonads is reasonably well established in mammals (the sry gene
of the Y chromosome induces formation of the testes) but not in
birds where the differentiation of the gonad seems to be the result of
the presence on one or two Z chromosomes of the gene DMRT1 (gene
dosage effect).
Other vertebrates
In other vertebrate classes including fishes, amphibians, and reptiles,
many species do not have sex chromosomes (Bachtrog et al. 2014).
Their brain and behavior differentiate by endocrine mechanisms that
are driven by the physical (e.g., temperature) or social environment
(presence of congeners of the other sex, position in a dominance-
subordinate hierarchy). For example, in reptiles, the first identified
event signaling sexual differentiation is an increase in aromatase
expression in the female gonad leading to an increase in estrogen
concentration that will by itself transform the undifferentiated gonad
into an ovary. Whether gonadal steroids have an early and
irreversible effect on the brain and its responsiveness to steroids in
adulthood is not broadly established in fish, amphibians, and
reptiles. There are, however, indications that such a phenomenon
may take place at least in some species. For example, in species with
alternative mating strategies, early events in development seem to
have long-lasting consequences. In tree lizards (Urosaurus ornatus),
concentrations of progesterone and testosterone during development
determine, in an apparently irreversible manner, whether the adult
males will be territorial during their entire life or will switch from
nomadic to satellite male as a function of environmental conditions.
In the midshipman fish (P. notatus), the physiological “decision” to
become a territorial male who builds a nest to attract females or a
sneaker (satellite male) is made early in development and is
apparently irreversible, but the endocrine bases of this “decision” are
unclear at present. However, given the plasticity in the expression of
sex-typical behaviors that can be observed by adult fish species, it
seems likely that, in many species, the brain and the behavioral
phenotype are not determined in an irreversible manner by the early
endocrine environment.
Lordosis in rats
In rats, like in many other species, sexual activity of the female is
restricted to a limited period of time around ovulation when the
chances of fertilization are maximal and rapid changes in endocrine
conditions take place. In the female rat, increased levels of estrogens
are observed for a couple of days before a peak of progesterone that
takes place immediately before the onset of sexual receptivity.
Ovariectomy suppresses all aspects of female sexual behavior that
can be restored by a sequential treatment with estrogens and
progesterone that mimics these physiological endocrine changes
normally observed during the estrous cycle. In other species (e.g.,
prairie vole, ferret, Japanese quail), estrogens alone are fully
effective in restoring sexual receptivity in the ovariectomized female.
A substantial amount of research has been carried out to dissect the
neural mechanisms that mediate these behavioral effects of
estrogens and progesterone. Estrogens and progesterone receptors
(ERα and PR) are densely expressed in the ventromedial
hypothalamus (VMH) and detailed stereotaxic implantation studies
by Barfield and colleagues showed that their activation is usually
sufficient to stimulate lordosis in ovariectomized females. One
critical aspect of estrogen action during the cycle is in fact the
induction of PR expression in the hypothalamus. The increased
ovarian progesterone secretion will then act on a pre-sensitized brain
to activate behavior.
The activation of the lordosis response is, however, not only a
hypothalamic phenomenon and involves a complex neural circuitry.
The male mounting behavior stimulates pressure receptors in the
female’s flanks, rump, and perineum. Axons of these receptors then
project to the spinal cord, and these inputs will be relayed to the
medullary reticular formation, the hindbrain, and the midbrain
central gray area. In response to these inputs and to
estrogen/progesterone action, several brain regions, including the
VMH and mPOA, then activate spinal motoneurons innervating
deepback muscles whose contraction will result in the characteristic
lordosis position. Estrogens and progesterone act at several of these
levels and in particular estrogens increase the size of the receptive
field of flank sensory neurons, so that tactile stimuli from the male
become more prominent. In addition to these well-documented
effects on sensory inputs and motor outputs there is an effect of
steroids that induces a generalized arousal that is essential for
successful reproduction to occur.
Estrogens alone or in association with progesterone also modulate
the concentration and activity of numerous neurotransmitters and
neuropeptides including dopamine, noradrenaline, serotonin,
acethylcholine, oxytocin, substance P, β-endorphin, and the
gonadotropin releasing hormone (GnRH). These changes are often
mediated by a regulation of the transcription of corresponding
enzymes such as acetylcholine esterase (acetylcholine catabolism),
tyroxine hydroxylase and dopamine β-hydroxylase (synthesis of
dopamine and noradrenaline), catechol-o-methyl-transferase and
monoamine-oxidases (dopamine and noradrenaline catabolism), or
of the neurotransmitters/neuropeptides receptors. Through these
neurochemical changes, steroids directly and indirectly modify
synaptic transmission and thus behavior.
Endocrine controls
In male quail, the expression of both ASB and CSB responses are
androgen-dependent. These behaviors are markedly inhibited if not
completely suppressed in castrated males and are restored to rates
observed in intact sexually mature males by treatments with
exogenous testosterone either injected systemically or implanted
directly in the mPOA. As observed for copulatory behavior, effects of
testosterone on the two measures of ASB seem to be mediated by its
aromatization into an estrogen in the mPOA. The activating effects of
testosterone on these two measures are indeed blocked by the
concurrent injection of an aromatase inhibitor or an estrogen-
receptor blocker (antiestrogen) and they can be mimicked to a large
extent by a treatment with exogenous estrogens.
Thus, both ASB and CSB (copulation) are activated by similar if not
identical endocrine stimuli. This is understandable from an ultimate
causation point of view since natural selection should favor the
control by similar hormones of behaviors that must by nature be
expressed in sequence to ensure successful reproduction. This
similarity in the endocrine controls of ASB and CSB has also been
observed in rats
Neural circuits
Despite this similarity in endocrine regulation, neural controls of
ASB and CSB should by necessity be distinct to some degree. Barry
Everitt and his colleagues at Cambridge University, UK, initially
showed that lesions to the mPOA in rats eliminate male-typical
copulatory behavior but have more limited or no effects on some
measures of sexual motivation. Rats with such lesions still pursue
and attempt to mount females. They also perform learned
instrumental responses (in operant conditioning paradigms) to gain
access to females. In contrast, lesions to the basolateral amygdala
inhibited the ability of males to acquire learned responses that are
rewarded with access to females. These observations suggested the
existence of a double dissociation between brain areas mediating
CSB (mPOA) on the one hand and ASB/arousal/motivation
(amygdala, bed nucleus striae terminalis) on the other hand.
Experimental analysis of the neuroanatomical bases of these
behaviors in a variety of species, however, also indicates a clear role
for the mPOA in the control of ASB. This was confirmed in quail
where data also suggested the existence of anatomical specializations
within mPOA areas controlling ASB vs. CSB.
In one set of experiments, discrete electrolytic lesions aimed at the
mPOA strongly inhibited, as expected, copulatory behavior and also
decreased to various degrees the expression of the learned social
proximity response. Closer inspection of the data revealed that
lesions in the caudal mPOA were associated with decreased
expression of CSB, while slightly more rostral lesions were
specifically associated with inhibition of the measure of ASB. In
another experiment, mPOA lesions also completely abolished the
expression of RCSM induced by the view of a female, but the
anatomical specificity of this latter effect could not be established
due to the limited number of available subjects.
A second set of studies correlatively indicated a localized induction of
the expression of the immediate early gene c-fos in birds that had
expressed ASB vs. CSB just before brain collection. Testosterone-
treated castrated males who had been able to interact freely with a
female and express the full sequence of copulatory behavior
displayed 90 minutes later an increased c-fos expression throughout
the rostrocaudal extent of the mPOA. In contrast, birds that were
only allowed to view the females and had therefore only performed
RCSM, one measure of ASB, showed an increased c-fos expression in
the rostral mPOA only. These data thus support the idea that the
mPOA is implicated in the expression of both ASB and CSB but the
rostral part would be more specifically implicated in the control of
ASB while copulatory behavior sensu stricto would rather be
controlled by the posterior part of this brain region
This anatomical specificity within the mPOA might not be restricted
to quail. In rats also, lesions of the caudal POA and anterior
hypothalamus block the expression of copulatory behavior, but more
rostral lesions in the POA had little or no effect in at least one
experiment. In hamsters (Mesocricetus auratus), pheromones alone
are able to activate c-fos expression in neurons of the mPOA in the
absence of copulatory interaction with females, indicating that
stimuli encountered during the appetitive phase of male sexual
behavior are processed, at least in part, in the mPOA. Similarly, in a
songbird, the house sparrow (Passer domesticus), female-directed
song, an appetitive behavior that precedes copulation, relates
positively to the induction of the immediate early genes c-fos and
zenk in the rostral POM but not the caudal part of this nucleus.
Role of dopamine
Testosterone and the derived estrogens activate behaviors by
modulating the activity of neurotransmitters. Extensive evidence
indicates that in quail, like in rats, dopamine (DA) release and
activity critically control male sexual motivation and copulatory
performance. A suite of pharmacological experiments tested the
effects on the performance of ASB and CSB of agonists and
antagonists and the D1-like and D2-like DA receptors. A consistent
effect of all drugs was observed on CSB that was stimulated by the D1
agonist but inhibited by the D2 agonists. Antagonists consistently
displayed the opposite effects (inhibition of behavior by D1
antagonist and stimulation by D2 antagonists). Far fewer effects of
the treatments were detected on measures of ASB: they were
decreased by treatment with D2 agonists but not affected by the
other treatments.
An in vivo microdialysis technique was also established and allowed
to measure changes in DA concentrations in the mPOA during social
and sexual interactions. This demonstrated that preoptic DA
concentrations increase as soon as a male detects the presence of a
female and starts interacting with her. This rise in DA actually
predicts whether copulation will or will not follow the initial
interaction and therefore represents an accurate measure of the
male’s motivation to engage in sexual behavior.
Parthenogenesis
Parthenogenetic reproduction, that is, asexual reproduction in which
females can reproduce without fertilization by a male, is sometimes
observed in invertebrates (aphids, some bees, and parasitic wasps)
but is very rare in vertebrates (a few sharks and reptiles species). It
has, however, been extensively documented in one species of lizard.
Cnemidophorus uniparens females are able to lay eggs that will
produce female offspring in the absence of sperm. They also display,
over time, cycles of sexual activity during which they successively
assume the role played by males in closely related lizard species and
they mount a female that is about to lay eggs or they will be mounted
and will lay eggs. The female-like receptive behavior is displayed just
before ovulation when circulating estrogen concentrations are high,
while the male-typical mounting behavior is displayed when plasma
concentrations of progesterone are elevated. Accordingly, these two
types of behaviors can be induced in the laboratory by injecting
ovariectomized females either with estrogens or with progesterone.
Progesterone rather than testosterone is thus responsible for the
activation of male-typical copulatory behavior in this species.
Progesterone, however, still acts in the POA that expresses a high
density of progesterone receptors. These pseudocopulations play an
important functional role in reproduction: females that undergo
mounting release more eggs and produce more offspring than
females that do not engage in this behavioral interaction.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Our research reviewed in this chapter has been supported by grants
from the NIMH (MH 50388) and NINDS (NS104008) as well as by
support from the Belgian FNRS and the IAP program. We thank our
students and post-docs for their hard work and good discussions
about the data we have reviewed here.
REFERENCES
Adkins-Regan, E. 2005. Hormones and Animal Social Behavior.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Agate, R.J., Grisham, W., Wade, J. et al. 2003. Neural, not gonadal,
origin of brain sex differences in a gynandromorphic finch.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 100,
4873–8.
Arnold, A.P. & Chen, X. 2009. What does the “four core genotypes”
mouse model tell us about sex differences in the brain and other
tissues? Frontiers in Neuroendocrinology, 30, 1–9.
Bachtrog, D., Mank, J.E., Peichel, C.L. et al. 2014. Sex
determination: why so many ways of doing it? PLoS Biology, 12,
e1001899.
Ball, G.F. & Balthazart, J. 2008. How useful is the appetitive and
consummatory distinction for our understanding of the
neuroendocrine control of sexual behavior? Hormones and
Behavior, 53, 307–11.
Ball, G.F., Balthazart, J. & McCarthy, M.M. 2014. Is it useful to view
the brain as a secondary sexual characteristic? Neuroscience and
Biobehavioral Reviews, 46, 628–638.
Balthazart, J. & Ball, G.F. 2006. Is brain estradiol a hormone or a
neurotransmitter? Trends in Neurosciences, 29, 241–9.
Balthazart, J. & Ball, G.F. (eds.). 2012. Brain Aromatase, Estrogens
and Behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Balthazart, J. & Young, L.J. 2014. Mate selection, sexual orientation
and pair bonding. In: T.M. Plant & A.J. Zeleznik (eds.), Knobil
and Neill’s Physiology of Reproduction, pp. 2157–2210.
Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Baum, M.J. & Bakker, J. 2013. Roles of sex and gonadal steroids in
mammalian pheromonal communication. Frontiers in
Neuroendocrinology, 34, 268–84.
Becker, J.B., Berkley, K.J., Geary, N., Hampson, E., Herman, J.P. &
Young, E.A. 2008. Sex Differences in the Brain. From Genes to
Behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cornil, C.A., Ball, G.F. & Balthazart, J. 2015. The dual action of
estrogen hypothesis. Trends in Neurosciences, 38, 408–16.
Crews, D. 2005. Evolution of neuroendocrine mechanisms that
regulate sexual behavior. Trends in Endocrinology and
Metabolism, 16, 354–61.
Etgen, A.M. & Pfaff, D.W. 2009. Molecular Mechanisms of Hormone
Actions on Behavior. Amserdam: Elsevier.
Forlano, P.M., Sisneros, J.A., Rohmann, K.N. & Bass, A.H. 2015.
Neuroendocrine control of seasonal plasticity in the auditory and
vocal systems of fish. Frontiers in Neuroendocrinology, 37, 129–
45.
Goodson, J.L. & Kabelik, D. 2009. Dynamic limbic networks and
social diversity in vertebrates: from neural context to
neuromodulatory patterning. Frontiers in Neuroendocrinology,
30, 429–41.
Goy, R.W. & McEwen, B.S. 1980. Sexual Differentiation of the Brain.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hinde, R.A. 1970. Animal Behaviour, 2nd ed. New York: McGraw-
Hill.
McEwen, B.S., Luine, V.N. & Fischette, C.T. 1988. Developmental
actions of hormones: from receptors to function. In: S.S.J. Easter,
K.F. Barald & B.M. Carlson (eds.), From Message To Mind, pp.
272–87. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Nelson, R.A. and Kriegsfeld, L.J. 2016. An Introduction to
Behavioral Endocrinology, 5th ed. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Pfaff, D.W. 1980. Estrogen and brain function. New York: Springer.
Pfaff, D.W. & Pfaffmann, C. 1969. Olfactory and hormonal influences
on the basal forebrain of the male rat. Brain Research, 15, 137–56.
Phoenix, C.H., Goy, R.W., Gerall, A.A. & Young, W.C. 1959.
Organizational action of prenatally administered testosterone
propionate on the tissues mediating behavior in the female guinea
pig. Endocrinology, 65, 369–82.
Rissman, E.F. & Adli, M. 2014. Minireview: transgenerational
epigenetic inheritance: focus on endocrine disrupting compounds.
Endocrinology, 155, 2770–80.
Romero, L.M. & Wingfield, J.C. 2016. Tempests, Poxes, Predators
and People: Stress in Wild Animals and How They Cope. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Saldanha, C.J., Remage-Healey, L. & Schlinger, B.A. 2011.
Synaptocrine signaling: steroid synthesis and action at the
synapse. Endocrine reviews, 32, 532–49.
Young, L. & Alexander, B. 2014. The Chemistry Between Us; Love,
Sex and the Science of Attraction. Penguin.
7
development of behavior
JOHAN J. BOLHUIS
INTRODUCTION
What is behavioral development? Roughly, it is about the changes
in behavior and particularly its underlying mechanisms in
individuals from conception to death. This definition includes the
behavior of individuals before they are born, which may come as
a surprise. In fact, the embryo has a rich behavioral repertoire,
with which it communicates with its parents or siblings. Also,
embryos can learn and remember. Later in this chapter we shall
discuss some examples of behaviors studied in what is known as
behavioral embryology. Is behavioral development important?
Classical ethological theory had surprisingly little to say about the
development of behavior, in spite of the fact that early in the last
century Konrad Lorenz (1935) had published a landmark paper
on the phenomenon of imprinting, a key concept in behavioral
development that is discussed in detail later in this chapter. For
instance, Niko Tinbergen’s (1951) famous book, The Study of
Instinct, has only one short chapter on development, and only
one paragraph on imprinting. Lehrman (1953), in his influential
critique of ethological theory, pointed out this neglect of
developmental questions, which subsequently led many
behavioral biologists to consider problems of development (Kruijt
1964; Bateson 1966). It also led Tinbergen (1963), some 10 years
later, to reformulate his views on the aims of ethology. In the first
chapter of this book, we described how in this seminal paper
Tinbergen considered development to be so important that he
added it to Huxley’s three questions in biology and made it one of
the four main problems in the study of animal behavior. So it is
important, then. It is certainly the case that some of the major
scientific discussions in animal behavior involve different
concepts of development, and we will discuss these debates. In
addition, we shall see that many concepts and findings
concerning behavioral development in animals have had
important consequences for the study of human development.
Basic Developmental Issues
Imprinting
Filial imprinting
Although filial imprinting may occur in mammals (Sluckin 1972), it
has been studied mostly in precocial birds. Soon after hatching, these
birds will approach and follow an object to which they are exposed.
In a natural situation the first object the young bird encounters is
usually its mother. In the absence of the mother, other animals or
even Lorenz can be adequate mother-surrogates. Amazingly,
inanimate mother-surrogates such as colored balls or illuminated
boxes are also effective in eliciting approach and following behavior
and the animals will readily form a social preference for these
unnatural stimuli (Bateson 1966; Sluckin 1972; Horn 1985, 2004;
Bolhuis 1991; McCabe 2019). When the chick or duckling is close to
an appropriate object (see below), it will attempt to snuggle up to it,
frequently emitting soft twitters. Initially the young bird approaches
a wide range of objects. After the bird has been exposed to one object
long enough, it remains close to this object and may run away from
novel ones. If the familiar object is removed, the bird becomes
restless and emits shrill calls. When given a choice between the
familiar stimulus and a novel one, the bird preferentially approaches
the familiar stimulus. It is important to realize that filial imprinting
refers to the acquisition of a social preference and not just an
increase in following (Sluckin 1972; Bolhuis 1991).
Sexual imprinting
Lorenz suggested that the main consequence of imprinting is the
determination of adult sexual preferences. Other research suggests
that filial imprinting and sexual imprinting are two separate
(although perhaps partially overlapping) processes. First, the time of
expression of the preference differs, with filial preferences being
expressed in very young birds, whereas sexual preferences are
expressed during courtship, when the animals are sexually mature.
Second, the period of time during which experience affects
preferences also differs between filial and sexual imprinting. Sexual
preferences continue to be affected by experience up to the time of
mating. Furthermore, filial preferences may be formed after a
relatively short period of exposure to an object. In contrast, sexual
preferences develop as the result of a long period of exposure to, and
social interaction with, the parents as well as the siblings.
Normally, sexual imprinting ensures that the bird will mate with a
member of its own strain or species. However, when the young bird
is cross-fostered (i.e., reared with adults of a different species) it may
develop a sexual preference for the foster species. For instance, when
young zebra finch (Taeniopygia guttata) males are reared with
Bengalese finch (Lonchura striata, also known as the society finch)
parents (Figure 7.3), they will later show courtship behavior mostly
to Bengalese finch females. Interestingly, when young zebra finch
males are reared with mixed parents (one Bengalese finch and one
zebra finch), they will later show a sexual preference for a female of
the species with which they had interacted most. More specifically, in
Japanese quail (Coturnix coturnix japonica) and domestic chickens,
mating preferences are for individual members of the opposite sex
that are different, but not too different, from individuals with which
the young bird was reared (Bateson 1978).
Sensitive periods
Sensitive periods are an important characteristic of developing
behavior. At the same time, the concept of “sensitive period” is often
misunderstood. It needs to be separated from the idea of “critical
period,” which implies a much stricter separation of sensitivity and
insensitivity to external influences. The idea of a critical period
simply does not correspond with biological reality. However, there is
considerable evidence to suggest that during development there are
periods of increased sensitivity to external experience, preceded and
followed by periods of less sensitivity. The transition between these
developmental states may be gradual.
Bateson (1979) likened some of the different interpretations of
sensitive periods to a train traveling through a landscape. The train is
a metaphor for the developmental process. At the beginning of the
journey all the windows of the train, which are opaque, are closed so
that passengers cannot see the landscape outside the train. In the
simplest interpretation, the windows open at some stage and close at
a later stage. This is very much like the old idea of a critical period.
Another interpretation is that some windows open at some stage and
others open at other stages, i.e., different onset of sensitivity at
various stages. The different windows may or may not close again.
The most realistic interpretation, inspired by studies of filial
imprinting, is that windows may open at different stages and not
close again. The passengers can obtain information from outside the
train and may decide on the basis of that information that they need
to get off the train at the next station. In other words, the end of an
apparent sensitive period is not a result of an end to external
experience influencing the organism (i.e., windows being closed
again) but the result of the effect that external experience has on the
organism. In the case of imprinting, when the young bird has been
exposed to an imprinting stimulus and learned its characteristics, it
will form a social preference for this stimulus. As long as that
stimulus is present, the animal will follow it around and spend most
of its time close to it, so the animal will not have much opportunity to
imprint on other stimuli. As we saw earlier, if the original imprinting
stimulus is removed and replaced with a novel stimulus, the animal
can imprint on the novel stimulus, suggesting that sensitivity for
experience relevant for imprinting has not waned.
Various models have been put forward to explain sensitive periods,
ranging from endogenous factors (e.g., “clock models”) to self-
terminating mechanisms, where an apparent sensitive period comes
to an end solely as a result of external experience (Bateson 1979; Ten
Cate 1989). It has become clear that sensitive periods should not be
seen as rigid mechanisms where a window to the external
environment opens briefly, never to be opened again. Rather,
sensitive periods are regarded as flexible mechanisms, the timing of
which can be modified, and that depend for a large part on external
influences on the organism (Bolhuis 1999).
Hunger
An example of a developing behavior system is the hunger system in
the junglefowl chick (Hogan 1988). This system involves perceptual
mechanisms for the recognition of features (color, shape, etc.),
objects (grain, worms, etc.), and functions (food versus nonfood).
Then there are motor mechanisms underlying behavior patterns
such as ground scratching and pecking, and there is a central hunger
mechanism. Importantly, several of these mechanisms and the
connections between them (dashed lines in Figure 3.5) develop as a
result of specific functional experience. For instance, only after a
substantial meal will the chick differentiate between food items and
nonfood items to eat.
On the motor side of the system, the mechanisms underlying
pecking, scratching, and walking are present as soon as the chick
hatches, as is the effective coordination of these behaviors into
foraging sequences. On the other hand, for at least 3 days, feeding-
related behavior (in this case pecking) is not dependent on the level
of food deprivation. Thus, the central hunger mechanism and the
pecking motor mechanism are not initially connected. Only after the
experience of pecking and swallowing (and not necessarily of food:
pecking and swallowing sand is equally effective) do the two
mechanisms become connected, and only then is the level of pecking
dependent on the level of food deprivation (Hogan 1984). A similar
phenomenon occurs in the case of suckling in rat pups, as described
earlier (Hall & Williams 1983). Suckling decreases as weaning
approaches but, importantly, suckling behavior does not become
deprivation dependent until about 2 weeks after birth.
Unfortunately, we still do not know whether functional experience is
required, and if so what type of experience is needed, to connect the
suckling motor mechanism with the central hunger mechanism in
the rat pup.
Dustbathing
The development of behavioral structure is not uniform but may
proceed along different pathways for different behavior systems. An
example of this is the development of dustbathing in junglefowl
chicks, as studied by the Danish ethologist Klaus Vestergaard and
coworkers (Vestergaard et al. 1990, 1993; see also Chapter 3).
Dustbathing is a behavior that adult birds of many species frequently
engage in. It consists of a sequence of coordinated movements of the
wings, feet, head, and body that serve to spread dust through the
feathers (see Figure 3.6). The function of this behavior is to remove
excess lipids from the feathers and to maintain good feather
condition. Unlike the development of feeding behavior in rats or
chicks, dustbathing is deprivation dependent as soon as it appears in
the animal’s behavioral repertoire (Hogan 2001). Thus, in this case
chicks do not require functional experience to connect the motor
mechanisms with the central dustbathing mechanism.
On the perceptual side, other experiments have shown that initially
the chick will perform dustbathing on virtually any kind of surface,
including wire mesh, suggesting that the perceptual mechanism and
the central mechanism are not yet connected. The perceptual
mechanism itself develops more quickly with some substrates than
with others, which is similar to the development of perceptual
mechanisms in song learning and filial predispositions discussed
earlier. Furthermore, it turns out that preferences for functionally
unlikely surfaces (e.g., a skin of junglefowl feathers) can be acquired
as a result of experience with them. This is another example of the
development of a perceptual mechanism, and one that is not
dissimilar to filial imprinting.
SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS
According to Niko Tinbergen, development is one of the four
main questions that should be asked about the behavior of
animals. The study of the development of animal behavior has
often been hampered by misrepresentation, mainly in the
popular literature, of early theoretical proposals. In particular,
interpretations of the concept of “instinct” have led to a stubborn
belief in the existence of “innate” behaviors, and the mistaken
idea that genes “determine” behavior. Also, some early intuitions
about imprinting have led to a rather rigid view on behavioral
development, where events occurring during “critical periods”
early in life are crucial for the development of behavior, an idea
that could be expressed metaphorically as once one has missed
the developmental bus there is no way back. It turns out that
there is considerable plasticity in development, extending into
adulthood. Nevertheless, events during development have a great
influence on adult behavior, for instance in imprinting and the
development of birdsong. In social behavior, even brief
separation from the mother can have profound effects on the
development of attachment. At the same time, there is
considerable plasticity and flexibility in the way in which these
events affect the development of animal behavior.
FURTHER READING
A number of classic papers on behavioral development,
supplemented with some important recent ones, have been collected
in the book by Bolhuis and Hogan (1999), which has crucial
publications on all aspects of development. Volume 2 of the 4-part
reader by Bolhuis and Giraldeau (2010) is devoted to behavioral
development. A collection of contemporary essays on the
development of behavior can be found in Hogan and Bolhuis (1994).
Gottlieb (2002b) provides a monograph on the relation between
development and evolution. Classic and contemporary papers on the
development of brain and cognition have been collected in a
comprehensive reader (Johnson et al. 2008), while a concise
introduction to the field of developmental cognitive neuroscience is
provided by Johnson and De Haan (2015). Review papers on the
development of brain and behavior include Bolhuis (1999), Hogan
(2001), Prather et al. (2017) and Yang et al. (2017).
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I am grateful to Luc-Alain Giraldeau, Jerry Hogan and the late
Gabriel Horn, for their comments on earlier versions of this chapter.
REFERENCES
Ainsworth, M.D.S., Blehar, M.C., Waters, E. & Wall, S. 1978.
Patterns of Attachment: Assessed in the Strange Situation and at
Home. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Bateson, P. 1979. How do sensitive periods arise and what are they
for? Animal Behaviour, 27, 470–86.
Bateson, P. 1978. Imprinting as a process of competitive exclusion.
In: J.P. Rauschecker & P. Marier (eds.), Imprinting and Cortical
Plasticity: Comparative Aspects of Sensitive Periods, pp. 151–68.
New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Bateson, P. 1999. Foreword. In: J.J. Bolhuis & J.A. Hogan (eds.), The
Development of Animal Behavior: A Reader, Oxford: Blackwell
Publishers.
Bateson, P.P.G. 1966. The characteristics and context of imprinting.
Biological Reviews, 41, 177–220.
Bateson, P.P.G. 1978. Sexual imprinting and optimal outbreeding.
Nature, 273, 659–60.
Benus, R.F., Den Daas, S., Koolhaas, J.M. & Van Oortmerssen, G.A.
1990. Routine formation and flexibility in social and nonsocial
behavior of aggressive and nonaggressive male mice. Behaviour,
112, 176–93.
Berwick, R.C., Okanoya, K., Beckers, G.J.L. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2011.
Songs to syntax: The linguistics of birdsong. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 15, 113–21.
Bischof, H.-J. 1994. Sexual imprinting as a two-stage process. In:
J.A. Hogan & J.J. Bolhuis (eds.), Causal Mechanisms of
Behavioural Development, pp. 82–97. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Bolhuis, J.J. 1991. Mechanisms of avian imprinting: a review.
Biological Reviews, 66, 303–45.
Bolhuis, J.J. 1996. Development of perceptual mechanisms in birds:
predispositions and imprinting. In: C.F. Moss & S.J. Shettleworth
(eds.), Neuroethological Studies of Cognitive and Perceptual
Processes, pp. 158–84. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Bolhuis, J.J. 1999. The development of animal behavior. From
Lorenz to neural nets. Naturwissenschaften, 86, 101–1.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Bateson, P.P.G. 1990. The importance of being first: a
primacy effect in filial imprinting. Animal Behaviour, 40, 472–83.
Bolhuis, J.J., Beckers, G.J.L., Huybregts, M.A.C., Berwick, R.C. &
Everaert, M.B.H. 2018. Meaningful syntactic structure in songbird
vocalizations? PloS Biology, 16(6), e2005157.
Bolhuis, J.J., De Vos, G.J. & Kruijt, J.P. 1990. Filial imprinting and
associative learning. Quarterly Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 42B, 313–29.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Everaert, M. (eds.). 2013. Birdsong, Speech &
Language. Exploring the Evolution of Mind and Brain.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Gahr, M. 2006. Neural mechanisms of birdsong
memory. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7, 347–57.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Giraldeau, L.-A. (eds.). 2010. Animal Behaviour, vol.
2. Development of Animal Behaviour. London: Sage Publications.
Bolhuis, J.J., Gobes, S.M.H., Terpstra, N.J., Den Boer-Visser, A.M. &
Zandbergen, M.A. 2012. Learning-related neuronal activation in
the zebra finch song system nucleus HVC in response to the bird’s
own song. PLoS One, 7(7), e41556.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Hogan, J.A. (eds.). 1999. The Development of Animal
Behavior: a Reader. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Honey, R.C. 1998. Imprinting, learning and
development: from behaviour to brain and back. Trends in
Neurosciences, 21, 306–11.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Moorman, S. 2015. Birdsong memory and the brain:
In search of the template. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews,
50, 41–55.
Bolhuis, J.J., Okanoya, K. & Scharff, C. 2010. Twitter evolution:
Converging mechanisms in birdsong and human speech. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience, 11, 747–59.
Bolhuis, J.J., Tattersall, I., Chomsky, N. & Berwick, R.C. 2014. How
could language have evolved? PLoS Biology, 12(8), e1001934.
Bolhuis, J.J., Zijlstra, G.G.O., Den Boer-Visser, A.M. & Van Der Zee,
E.A. 2000. Localized neuronal activation in the zebra finch brain
is related to the strength of song learning. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences USA, 97, 2282–5.
Bowlby, J. 1969. Attachment and Loss, vol. 1. Attachment. London:
Hogarth Press.
Catchpole, C.K. & Slater, P.J.B. 1995. Bird Song: Biological Themes
and Variations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
DeVoogd, T.J. 1994. The neural basis for the acquisition and
production of bird song. In: J.A. Hogan & J.J. Bolhuis (eds.),
Causal Mechanisms of Behavioural Development, pp. 49–81.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Doupe, A.J. & Kuhl, P.K. 1999. Birdsong and human speech:
common themes and mechanisms. Annual Review of
Neuroscience, 22, 567–631.
Everaert, M.B.H., Huybregts, M.A.C., Chomsky, N., Berwick, R.C. &
Bolhuis, J.J.2015. Structures, not strings: Linguistics as part of
the cognitive sciences. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 19, 729–43.
Friederici, A.D., Chomsky, N., Berwick, R.C., Moro, A. & Bolhuis, J.J.
2017. Language, mind and brain. Nature Human Behaviour, 1,
713–22.
Gottlieb, G. 1976. The roles of experience in the development of
behavior and the nervous system. In: G. Gottlieb (ed.), Neural
and Behavioral Specificity: Studies in the Development of
Behavior and the Nervous System, pp. 237–80. New York:
Academic Press.
Gottlieb, G. 1980. Development of species identification in
ducklings: VI. Specific embryonic experience required to maintain
species-typical perception in Peking ducklings. Journal of
Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 94, 579–87.
Gottlieb, G. 2002a. On the epigenetic evolution of species specific
perception: the developmental manifold concept. Cognitive
Development, 17, 1287–1300.
Gottlieb, G. 2002b. Individual Development and Evolution: The
Genesis of Novel Behavior. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Greenough, W.T., Black, J.E. & Wallace, C.S. 1987. Experience and
brain development. Child Development, 58, 539–59.
Hall, W.G. 1979. Feeding and behavioral activation in infant rats.
Science, 190, 1313–5.
Hall, W.G. & Williams, C.L. 1983. Suckling isn’t feeding, or is it? a
search for developmental continuities. Advances in the Study of
Behavior, 13, 219–54.
Harlow, H.F. 1958. The nature of love. American Psychologist, 13,
573–685.
Harlow, H.F. & Harlow, M.K. 1962. Social deprivation in monkeys.
Scientific American, 207, 136–46.
Hebb, D.O. 1949. The Organization of Behavior: &
Neuropsychological Theory. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Heinroth, O. 1911. Beiträge zur Biologie, nahmentlich Ethologie und
Psychologie de Anatiden. Verhandlungen des 5. Internationaler
Ornithologischer Kongress Berlin, 589–702.
Hinde, R.A. 1977. Mother-infant separation and the nature of inter-
individual relationships: experiments with rhesus monkeys.
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London Series B, 196, 29–50.
Hinde, R.A. & Bateson, P. 1984. Discontinuities versus continuities
in behavioural development and the neglect of process.
International Journal of Behavioral Development, 7, 129–43.
Hogan, J.A. 1984. Pecking and feeding in chicks. Learning and
Motivation, 15, 360–76.
Hogan, J.A. 1988. Cause and function in the development of
behavior systems. In: E.M. Blass (ed.), Handbook of Behavioral
Neurobiology, vol. 9, pp. 63–106. New York: Plenum Press.
Hogan, J.A. 1994. The concept of cause in the study of behaviour. In:
J.A. Hogan & J.J. Bolhuis (eds.), Causal Mechanisms of
Behavioural Development, pp. 3–15. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Hogan, J.A. 2001. Development of behavior systems. In: E.M. Blass
(ed.), Handbook of Behavioral Neurobiology, vol. 13, pp. 229–79.
New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum.
Hogan, J.A. & Bolhuis, J.J. (eds.). 1994. Causal Mechanisms of
Behavioural Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Horn, G. 1985. Memory, Imprinting, and the Brain. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Horn, G. 1998. Visual imprinting and the neural mechanisms of
recognition memory. Trends in Neurosciences, 21, 300–5.
Horn, G. 2004. Pathways of the past: the imprint of memory. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience, 5, 108–120.
Johnson, M.H., Bolhuis, J.J. & Horn, G. 1985. Interaction between
acquired preferences and developing predispositions during
imprinting. Animal Behaviour, 33, 1000–6.
Johnson, M.H., Davies, D.C. & Horn, G. 1989. A sensitive period for
the development of a predisposition in dark-reared chicks. Animal
Behaviour, 37, 1044–6.
Johnson, M.H. & De Haan, M. 2015. Developmental Cognitive
Neuroscience: An Introduction, 4th ed. Chichester: Wiley-
Blackwell.
Johnson, M.H. & Horn, G. 1988. Development of filial preferences in
dark-reared chicks. Animal Behaviour, 36, 675–83.
Johnson, M.H. & Morton, J. 1991. Biology and Cognitive
Development: The Case of Face Recognition. Oxford: Wiley-
Blackwell.
Johnson, M.H., Munakata, Y. & Gilmore, R.O. 2008. Brain
Development and Cognition: a Reader, 2nd ed. Oxford: Wiley-
Blackwell.
Kruijt, J.P. 1964. Ontogeny of social behaviour in Burmese red
junglefowl (Gallus gallus spadiceus). Behaviour, (Suppl. 9), 1–
201.
Kruijt, J.P. & Meeuwissen, G.B. 1991. Sexual preferences of male
zebra finches: effects of early and adult experience. Animal
Behaviour, 42, 91–102.
Lagerspetz, K. 1964. Studies on the aggressive behaviour of mice.
Annales Academiae Scientiarum Fennicae, Series B, 131, 1–131.
Lehrman, D.S. 1953. A critique of Konrad Lorenz’s theory of
instinctive behavior. Quarterly Review of Biology, 28, 337–63.
Lehrman, D.S. 1970. Semantic and conceptual issues in the nature-
nurture problem. In: L.R. Aronson, E. Tobach, D.S. Lehrman &
J.S. Rosenblatt (eds.), Development and Evolution of Behavior,
pp. 17–52. San Francisco: Freeman.
Lorenz, K. 1935. Der Kumpan in der Umwelt des Vogels. Journal fur
Ornithologie, 83, 137–213, 289–413.
Lorenz, K. 1937a. The companion in the bird’s world. Auk, 54, 245–
73.
Lorenz, K. 1937b. Uber die Bildung des Instinkbegriffes.
Naturwissenschaften, 25, 289–300, 307–18, 324–31.
Lorenz, K. 1965. Evolution and Modification of Behavior. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Marler, P. 1976. Sensoiy templates in species-specific behavior. In: J.
Fentress (ed.), Simpler Networks and Behavior, pp. 314–29.
Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Marler, P. 1977. The structure of animal communication sounds. In:
T.H. Bullock (ed.), Recognition of Complex Acoustic Signals:
Report of the Dahlem Workshop on Recognition of Complex
Acoustic Signals, pp. 17–35. Berlin: Abakon-Verlagsgesellschaft.
Marler, P. 1987. Sensitive periods and the roles of specific and
general sensory stimulation in birdsong learning. In: J.P.
Rauschecker & P. Marler (eds.), Imprinting and Cortical
Plasticity: Comparative Aspects of Sensitive Periods, pp. 99–135.
New York: John Wiley.
Marler, P. 1991. Song-learning behavior: the interface with
neuroethology. Trends in Neurosciences, 14, 199–206.
Marler, P. & Peters, S. 1987. A sensitive period for song acquisition in
the song sparrow, Melospiza melodia: a case of age-limited
learning. Ethology, 76, 89–100.
McCabe, B.J. 2019. Visual imprinting in birds: Behavior, models, and
neural mechanisms. Frontiers in Physiology, 10, 658.
Mello, C.V. & Clayton, D.F. 1994. Song-induced ZENK gene
expression in auditory pathways of songbird brain and its relation
to the song control system. The Journal of Neuroscience, 14,
6652–66.
Moorman, S., Gobes, S.M.H., Kuijpers, M., Kerkhofs, A.,
Zandbergen, M.A. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2012. Human-like brain
hemispheric dominance in birdsong learning. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences USA, 109, 12782–7.
Moorman, S. & Nicol, A.U. 2015. Memory-related brain
lateralisationin birds and humans. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral
Reviews, 50, 86–102.
Nottebohm, F. 2000. The anatomy and timing of vocal learning in
birds. In: M.D. Hauser & M. Konishi (eds.), The Design of Animal
Communication, pp. 63–110. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Oppenheim, R.W. 1981. Ontogenetic adaptations and retrogressive
processes in the development of the nervous system and
behaviour: a neuroembryological perspective. In: K.J. Connolly &
H.F.R. Prechtl (eds.), Maturation and Development: Biological
and Psychological Perspective, pp. 73–109. Philadelphia:
Lippincott.
Prather, J., Okanoya, K. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2017. Brains for birds and
babies: Neural parallels between birdsong learning and speech
acquisition. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 81, 225–37.
Rutter, M. 2002. Nature, nurture, and development: from
evangelism through science toward policy and practice. Child
Development, 73, 1–21.
Salzen, E.A. & Meyer, C.C. 1967. Imprinting: reversal of a preference
established during the critical period. Nature, 215, 785–6.
Slater, P.J.B. 1983. The development of individual behaviour. In:
T.R. Halliday & P.J.B. Slater (eds.), Genes, Development and
Learning. Animal Behaviour, vol. 3. New York: W.H. Freeman.
Sluckin, W. 1972. Imprinting and Early Learning. London:
Methuen.
Snowdon, C.T. & Hausberger, M. (eds.). 1997. Social Influences on
Vocal Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Spalding, D.A. 1873. Instinct, with original observations on young
animals. Macmillan’s Magazine, 27, 282–293. Reprinted in 1954
in British Journal of Animal Behaviour, 2, 2–11.
Ten Cate, C. 1989. Behavioral development: toward understanding
processes. In: P.P.G. Bateson & P.H. Klopfer (eds.), Perspectives
in Ethology, vol. 8, pp. 243–69. New York: Plenum Press.
Tinbergen, N. 1951. The Study of Instinct. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Tinbergen, N. 1963. On aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschria für
Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–33.
Vestergaard, K.S., Hogan, J.A. & Kruijt, J.P. 1990. The development
of a behavior system: dustbathing in the Burmese red junglefowl:
I. The influence of the rearing environment on the organization of
dustbathing. Behaviour, 112, 99–116.
Vestergaard, K.S., Kruijt, J.P. & Hogan, J.A. 1993. Feather pecking
and chronic fear in groups of red junglefowl: its relations to
dustbathing, rearing environment and social status. Animal
Behaviour, 45, 1117–26.
Waddington, C.H. 1966. Principles of Development and
Differentiation. New York: Macmillan.
Yang, C., Crain, S., Berwick, R.C., Chomsky, N. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2017.
The growth of language: Universal Grammar, experience, and
principles of computation. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral
Reviews, 81, 103–19.
8
learning and memory
KIMBERLY KIRKPATRICK AND GEOFFREY HALL
INTRODUCTION
When first faced with a particular set of circumstances, an animal
will behave in a certain way; but when these same circumstances
occur again, its behavior may be different. The animal, having
interacted with its environment, is changed by the experience and
thus becomes capable of behaving differently in the future. The
process of interaction that produces the change in the animal is
called learning, and the mechanisms involved in this process
form the subject matter of the first two main sections of this
chapter; the change itself is often referred to as the formation of a
memory, and the properties of animal memory will be
considered in the third and fourth sections of the chapter. Most of
this chapter will be taken up with discussing not the functional
implications of learning, but the mechanisms by which it is
achieved. Although field studies have supplied some important
information, our knowledge of these mechanisms comes mainly
from experimental work conducted with laboratory animals;
discussion of such experiments forms the bulk of the chapter.
Those who have done this work (often experimental psychologists
rather than ethologists) claim to have detected learning
mechanisms of general relevance—mechanisms that form the
basis of a whole range of seemingly different types of learning,
and that operate in most or all species. Others have doubted this
claim, suggesting that the narrow focus of laboratory studies of
learning has led researchers to overlook specialized mechanisms
of learning and memory that have evolved. This issue will be
discussed in the final section of the chapter.
Procedures for the Study of Learning and
their Results
Pairing of events
Classical conditioning
Although the phenomenon of imprinting had been demonstrated
some years earlier, the experimental study of animal learning began
in earnest only about 1900 when the Russian physiologist Ivan
Pavlov turned his attention to the topic. Pavlov’s experimental
procedure involved explicit pairing of stimuli. From his earlier work
on the processes controlling digestive secretions, Pavlov knew that a
dog would salivate in response to a wide range of stimuli—not just to
the presentation of food but, for instance, to the appearance of the
laboratory attendant who supplied the food. This latter response
clearly depended on experience, and by taking a version of it into the
laboratory, Pavlov hoped that he would be able to use it to elucidate
the brain mechanisms responsible for learning.
In his standard experimental situation (Pavlov 1927) a lightly
restrained dog, isolated in a quiet room, received a series of training
trials in which presentations of food were paired with (usually
slightly preceded by) presentations of a neutral event, such as the
flashing of a light or the clicking of a metronome. From the outset,
the presentation of food evoked salivation—this response did not
require special training and was therefore described as an
unconditional (or unconditioned) response. The event that elicited it
was called an unconditioned stimulus (US). Over the course of
training, the light, which had originally been ineffective in this
respect, acquired the power to evoke salivation; this response, since
it was conditional on the animal having received training, was called
a conditioned response and the light itself a conditioned stimulus
(CS). The whole procedure thus became known as conditioning, and
since this term has also been applied to other examples of learning,
Pavlov’s original version is distinguished by the qualifier classical.
The central feature of the classical conditioning procedure is that the
animal is subjected to the paired presentation of two stimuli. The
result is a change in behavior (the dog comes to salivate to a stimulus
that did not originally elicit this response), but it should be noted
that there is nothing in the procedure that requires the animal to do
anything—pairings of the stimuli are scheduled irrespective of what
the animal does. Although Pavlov’s salivary conditioning procedure
has been little used in recent years, its essence is to be found in
other, widely used, training paradigms. For example:
Conditional control
The experimenter can arrange, for a rat lever-pressing in the Skinner
box, that the response will produce food only when certain other
conditions are met (e.g., only when a tone is sounding). The
response-reinforcer contingency holds, therefore, only when the tone
is on. The rat will come to respond only in the presence of the tone
and will withhold responding in its absence. This phenomenon,
known as stimulus control, reveals an ability to learn about higher-
order relationships (food will be presented only if a response is
made, and even then, only when the tone is present). Such
conditional learning is not confined to the instrumental procedure.
In the Pavlovian analogue the animal receives trials on which CSA is
followed by the US only if it is accompanied or preceded by some
other stimulus B; no US occurs when A is presented on its own. The
animal shows its sensitivity to this conditional relationship as it
comes to produce the CR to A only on the B-A trials.
Discrimination learning
In the procedure just described the animal must discriminate
between two sets of circumstances in which a given CS occurs. The
standard discrimination training procedure is similar in principle,
but two different stimuli are used and they are given different
consequences. For example, a pigeon may be given autoshaping
training consisting of trials in which presentations of a red light (the
positive stimulus) are followed by food, intermixed with trials on
which a green light (the negative stimulus) is presented, but no food
follows. Not only will the bird come to respond to the red light, as
might be expected, it may also initially show some responding to
green. This phenomenon is known as generalization (the CR
established to the CS generalizes to another, similar stimulus). With
extended training, however, the tendency to respond to green will
decline—a discrimination between red and green will be established.
The instrumental version of discrimination training often involves a
choice procedure. For example, the rat at the choice point of a maze
can be confronted with two arms, one black and one white. If a move
into the white arm gives access to food whereas choice of the black
does not, the rats will, after a few training trials, come to choose the
white arm on each occasion, even when the left-right position of the
arms is swapped at random from trial to trial. This same apparatus
can be used to study spatial discrimination learning. In this case no
extra visual cues are presented and reward is available after choice of
one arm, and never after choice of the other. Rats learn spatial
discriminations readily, even when the task cannot be solved by
learning to perform a specific response. In one widely used
procedure (Morris 1981) the rat is placed in a pool of water from
which it can escape by climbing on to an invisible platform, the top of
which lies just below the surface. After a few trials the rat learns to
swim directly to the platform from whatever point it is placed in the
pool. To do this, the rat must have learned something about the
spatial relationships between the platform and the various cues
present in the room in which the pool is located.
Mechanisms of Learning
Instrumental conditioning
The associative analysis has also been applied to instrumental
conditioning, and the debate over the nature of the association
involved has much in common with classical conditioning. Again, the
S–R account, which dominated for many years, has been challenged
by later research showing the importance of another association (in
this case between the response and its outcome); and again the
resolution turns out to be that both forms of association may be
established, given the appropriate conditions.
Thorndike’s interpretation of instrumental learning was that the
relevant association was between S and R. This was couched in terms
of his law of effect. In its most general form, this law is simply that
the effect produced by an action will change the likelihood of that
action for the future (e.g., the frequency of lever-pressing will
increase when that behavior produces a food pellet). In the specific
form proposed by Thorndike it was suggested that the mechanism
responsible for the increase in response frequency was the
strengthening (reinforcement) of a connection between the
current stimulus situation (the sight of the lever in this example) and
the response (depressing the lever).
Experiments investigating this interpretation have made use of a
reinforcer-devaluation procedure, analogous to the US-devaluation
experiment of Holland and Straub (1979), described earlier. In one of
these, Adams and Dickinson (1981) trained rats to press the lever in a
Skinner box for food, training that should, according to the theory,
simply establish a link between the S of the lever and the R of
pressing. In a further stage of training the rats ate food pellets of the
type they had previously earned by lever pressing and this was
followed by an injection known to induce nausea. The fact that the
rats now showed an aversion to this form of food should, according
to the S–R theory, be irrelevant to the behavior shown in the Skinner
box—the reward would have done its job of reinforcing the S–R
connection in the first stage of training and subsequent changes in
value should be of no consequence. It was found, however, that when
the rats were returned to the Skinner box, those that had been
subjected to the reinforcer-devaluation procedure showed a reduced
willingness to press the lever. We may conclude that the role of the
reinforcer in this procedure is not simply to stamp in some
connection between a stimulus and a response—rather, the animal
clearly knows something about what the outcome of its response will
be. Put in associative terms, this means that the critical link is
between R (in this case the lever-press) and S (the outcome of the
response). When the outcome is of value, the R–S connection results
in a high rate of response; when it is not, the rate of response will be
low.
It remains to point out that some conditions of instrumental training
will generate responding that is independent of the current value of
the reinforcer; in these cases the rat will continue to perform a
response that was initially established using a reinforcer that is no
longer of value. There are several possible reasons why this might
arise, but among them is the possibility that what the animal has
learned in initial training is an S–R rather than an R–S association.
Particularly intriguing in this context is the observation that animals,
given extensive initial training, can become insensitive to the value of
the reinforcer, an outcome consistent with the fact of everyday
experience that an act acquired initially with reference to the effect it
produced can, if repeated often enough, turn into an automatic habit.
ΔV = α(λ−∑V)
where α is parameter that varies with the salience of the CS, λ
represents the maximum associative strength that the US can
support, and ∑V is the summed associative strength of all CSs
present on the trial. It will be noted that when ∑V equals λ there
can be no further change in associative strength, as the value
inside the brackets will be zero. Conditioning with A as the CS (as
in the first stage of the blocking experiment, see Table 8.1) will
thus proceed until the associative strength of A (VA) has risen to
the value of λ. Further trials in the second stage, in which A is
presented in compound with B will produce no further increase
in VA. What is more, they will not produce any increase in the
associative strength of the newly introduced B, as the value of
λ−∑V will be zero by virtue of the associative strength of A. This
outcome is the result obtained experimentally (the blocking
effect).
This simple equation neatly captures the notion that an expected
US (one preceded by a CS that has a high level of associative
strength) will be poor at supporting further learning. It has
proved to have wide explanatory power and has been very
influential not only in the study of conditioning, but also in the
psychology of cognition more generally.
FURTHER READING
For a review of earlier work on animal learning and memory see
Spear et al. (1990), who cover not only the topics dealt with in the
present chapter but also includes information on the development of
learning and memory in young animals. An approachable account
that deals with later work is provided by Pearce (2013). The book
edited by Mackintosh (1994) is an advanced text that will make
considerable demands on the reader but which provides state-of-the-
art expositions by specialist contributors on many of the topics
covered in the present chapter. The contributors to this book are
mainly experimental psychologists. For a different perspective, see
the book by Shettleworth (2010); this book offers an emphasis on the
evolutionary approach to the understanding of learning and
memory.
REFERENCES
Adams, C.D. & Dickinson, A. 1981. Instrumental responding
following reinforcer devaluation. Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 33B, 109–21.
Babb, S.J. & Crystal, J.D. 2006. Episodic-like memory in the rat.
Current Biology, 16, 1317–21.
Baddeley, A.D. 1976. The psychology of memory. New York: Basic
Books.
Blough, D.S. 1959. Delayed matching in the pigeon. Journal of the
Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 2, 151–60.
Bolhuis, J.J. 2015. Evolution cannot explain how minds work.
Behavioural Processes, 117, 82–91.
Bolhuis, J.J. & Macphail, E.M. 2001. A critique of the neuroecology
of learning and memory. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 426–33.
Bolles, R.C. 1979. Learning Theory, 2nd ed. New York: Holt,
Rinehart and Winston.
Clayton, N.S. & Dickinson, A. 1998. Episodic-like memory during
cache recovery by scrub jays. Nature, 395, 272–4.
Cook, R.G., Levinson, D.G., Gillett, S.R. & Blaisdell, A.P. 2005.
Capacity and limits of associative memory in pigeons.
Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 12, 350–8.
Craig, M., Rand, J., Mesch, R., Shyan-Norwalt, M., Morton, J. &
Flickinger, E.2012. Domestic dogs (Canis familiaris) and the
radial arm maze: Spatial memory and serial position effects.
Journal of Comparative Psychology, 126, 233–42.
Deweer, B., Sara, S.J. & Hars, B. 1980. Contextual cues and memory
retrieval in rats: alleviation of forgetting by a pretest exposure to
background stimuli. Animal Learning & Behavior, 8, 265–72.
Duncan, C.P. 1949. The retroactive effect of electroshock on learning.
Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 42, 32–
44.
Garcia, J. & Koelling, R.A. 1966. The relation of cue to consequence
in avoidance learning. Psychonomic Science, 5, 123–4.
Grant, D.S. 1976. Effect of sample presentation time on long-delay
matching in the pigeon. Learning and Motivation, 7, 580–90.
Hall, G. 1979. Exposure learning in young and adult laboratory rats.
Animal Behaviour, 27, 586–91.
Harper, D.N., McLean, A.P. & Dalrymple-Alford, J.C. 1993. List item
memory in rats: Effects of delay and task. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 19, 307–
16.
Holland, P.C. & Straub, J.J. 1979. Differential effects of two ways of
devaluing the unconditioned stimulus after Pavlovian appetitive
training. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior
Processes, 5, 65–78.
Humphrey, G. 1933. The nature of learning. London: Kegan Paul.
Hunter, W.S. 1913. The delayed reaction in animals and children.
Behavior Monographs, 2, 1–86.
Kamin, L.J. 1968. “Attention-like” processes in classical
conditioning. In: M.R. Jones (ed.), Miami symposium on the
prediction of behavior: Aversive stimulation, pp. 9–33. Miami:
University of Miami Press.
Lewis, D.J. 1979. Psychobiology of active and inactive memory.
Psychological Bulletin, 86, 1054–83.
Mackintosh, N.J. (ed.). 1994. Handbook of perception and
cognition. Vol. 9: Animal learning and cognition. San Diego:
Academic Press.
Macphail, E.M. 1982. Brain and intelligence in vertebrates. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Macphail, E.M. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2001. The evolution of intelligence:
adaptive specialisations versus general process. Biological
Reviews, 76, 341–64.
Maki, W.S. & Hegvik, D.K. 1980. Directed forgetting in pigeons.
Animal Learning & Behavior, 8, 567–74.
Miller, G.A. 1956. The magical number seven plus or minus two:
Some limits on our capacity for processing information.
Psychological Review, 63, 81–97.
Morris, R.G.M. 1981. Spatial localization does not require the
presence of local cues. Learning and Motivation, 12, 239–60.
Nelson, K.R. & Wasserman, E.A. 1978. Temporal factors influencing
the pigeon’s successive matching-to-sample performance: Sample
duration, intertrial interval, and retention interval. Journal of the
Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 30, 153–62.
Pavlov, I.P. 1927. Conditioned Reflexes. New York: Dover. (reprinted
1960).
Pearce, J. 2013. Animal learning and cognition, 3rd ed. New York:
Psychology Press.
Qadri, M.A.J., Leonard, K., Cook, R.G. & Kelly, D.M. 2018.
Examination of long-term visual memorization capacity in the
Clark’s nutcracker (Nucifraga columbiana). Psychonomic
Bulletin and Review, 25, 2274–80.
Rescorla, R.A. & Wagner, A.R. 1972. A theory of Pavlovian
conditioning: Variations in the effectiveness of reinforcement and
nonreinforcement. In: A.H. Black & W.F. Prokasy (eds.), Classical
conditioning II: Current research and theory, pp. 64–99. New
York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Roberts, W.A. & Grant, D.S. 1976. Studies of short-term memory in
the pigeon using the delayed matching to sample procedure. In:
D.L. Medin, W.A. Roberts & R.T. Davis (eds.), Processes of animal
memory, pp. 79–112. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Shettleworth, S.J. 2010. Cognition, evolution, and behavior, 2nd ed.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Skinner, B.F. 1938. The behavior of organisms. New York: Appleton-
Century-Crofts.
Spear, N.E. 1973. Retrieval of memory in animals. Psychological
Review, 80, 163–75.
Spear, N.E., Miller, J.S. & Jagielo, J.A. 1990. Animal memory and
learning. Annual Review of Psychology, 41, 169–211.
Squire, L.R. & Fox, M.M. 1980. Assessment of remote memory:
Validation of the television test by repeated testing during a
seven-day period. Behavioral Research Methods, Instruments
and Computers, 12, 583–6.
Squire, L.R. & Slater, P.C. 1975. Forgetting in very long-term
memory as assessed by an improved questionnaire technique.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and
Performance, 104, 50–4.
Terrace, H.S. 1991. Chunking during serial learning by a pigeon: I.
Basic evidence. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal
Behavior Processes, 17, 81–93.
Tulving, E. 1972. Episodic and semantic memory. In: E. Tulving & W.
Donaldson (eds.), Organization of Memory, pp. 381–403. New
York: Academic Press.
Vaughan, W., Jr. & Greene, S.L. 1984. Pigeon visual memory
capacity. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior
Processes, 10, 256–71.
Wagner, A.R. 1976. Priming in STM: An information-processing
mechanism for self-generated or retrieval-generated depression in
performance. In: T.J. Tighe & R.N. Leaton (eds.), Habituation:
Perspectives from child development, animal behavior, and
neurophysiology, pp. 95–128. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Wagner, A.R. 1981. SOP: A model of automatic memory processing
in animal behavior. In:N.E. Spear & R.R. Miller (eds.),
Information processing in animals: Memory mechanisms, pp. 5–
47. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
9
animal cognition
JERRY A. HOGAN
INTRODUCTION
According to the American Heritage Dictionary, cognition is “the
mental process or faculty by which knowledge is acquired.” What
does it mean to study the mental processes in animals? For some
social scientists, “animal cognition” is an oxymoron: they believe
that nonhuman animals do not possess anything like what they
consider mental processes. For others, like the early behaviorists
(see Chapter 1), mental processes are too amorphous and difficult
to study. But animals, from insects, to fish, birds, rodents, and
apes, behave in ways that go well beyond reacting in an inflexible
manner to the situations in which they find themselves. They
perceive things, they learn, they find their way around in their
environment, they remember, they plan, they organize into
groups, and do many other things that imply mental processes
are occurring. During the past hundred years, psychologists and
behavioral biologists have developed many ways to study these
topics, some of which have been discussed in other chapters in
this book. In this chapter, I will be concerned primarily with
evidence that focuses on the nature and usage of knowledge. At
the end I will return to the question of what a mental process is.
A Wasp’s Story
In early summer, in certain regions of central Netherlands, digger
wasps of the species Ammophila campestris emerge from the
underground chambers in which they have developed from an egg
deposited the previous summer. The following description of the
wasps’ behavior is derived from the work of the Dutch ethologist
Gerard Baerends (1941) who studied these animals for his PhD
dissertation. Males emerge first, and females a few days later.
Courtship and mating occur as soon as the females appear. Each
female then goes immediately about the business of digging nests,
laying eggs, and providing her offspring with food. Nest building is a
complicated, arduous task. The female first searches for an
appropriate nesting site in the diluvial sand soil amid the heath
vegetation and pine trees. She may scratch and bite the ground in
several locations before choosing a site for the nest. When a suitable
site is found, she begins digging with her mandibles and forelegs.
With the sandy soil wedged between her mandibles and mouth, she
flies about 20 cm from the nest, sprays the sand on the ground, and
then returns to digging. This is repeated many times until she has
completed digging a tunnel about 2 cm deep with an elliptical, 2½
cm chamber at the bottom. She then closes the nest, which is a feat in
itself. First, she must find a clump of sand of the right size and shape
to fit in the tunnel but not fall into the chamber, and then other bits
of wood and stone to fill the tunnel. Finally, she covers it with sand
so that it is not visible. Then she searches for a caterpillar that she
stings to paralyze and carries back to her nest, either flying with the
caterpillar suspended under her body like a missile or in some cases
dragging it on the ground. She pulls the paralyzed caterpillar down
the tunnel into the chamber and deposits an egg on it (see Figure
9.1). After one or a few days, she returns to the nest, opens it, and
determines whether the egg has hatched. Whether it has or not, she
closes the nest. If the egg has not hatched, she returns again a few
days later and inspects again. If the egg has hatched and the larva
has devoured the caterpillar, she searches for a new caterpillar,
reopens the nest, replenishes the food supply, and closes the nest.
She may do this several times, depending on the amount of food in
the nest. Each time, she opens and closes the nest. In the course of
the summer, the female wasp may dig and provision five to ten nests
often with two or sometimes even three nests active at the same time,
each at a different stage of development. The nests of an individual
female may be a meter or more distant from each other, but the nests
of other females are located in between.
Figure 9.1 (a) Ammophiia sabulosa, a close relative of A.
campestris. Copyright Beentree, Wikimedia creative commons. (b)
Steps in provisioning and egg-laying the Ammophila nest. 1.
Bringing the prey. 2. Opening the nest. 3-6. Dragging the prey into
the nest. 7. Egg laying. 8. Leaving the nest. From Baerends (1941).
There are many more fascinating aspects of the behavior of these
wasps, but the details presented here already illustrate the
considerable cognitive abilities required of these tiny (about 1½ cm)
creatures. The female must first discover a suitable location for the
nest and perform the activities necessary to build the nest and to
close it. She must be able to find and recognize a caterpillar; she
must be able to find her way back to the nest after a foraging
expedition and then discriminate among her nests and the nests of
other females. She must inspect each nest to plan how much food
each nest will need. She must remember the state of development of
each nest even when multiple nests are at different stages at the
same time. How does she do these things? These are the types of
questions that are discussed in this chapter.
In the previous paragraph, I have used the words discover, build,
forage, recognize, discriminate, remember, inspect, and plan. I will
use these and similar words throughout this chapter to describe the
activities of many animals, including humans. These are all words
naming the function of different activities of an animal, but it is
important to realize that these words do not imply that the cognitive
mechanisms underlying these activities are the same in different
species. In particular, it is important not to assume that these
mechanisms are the same as they are in people. Doing so is called by
the name anthropomorphism: attributing human characteristics
to other animals. I chose the behavior of digger wasps to illustrate
the problems that mental processes are used to solve because digger
wasps are so different from humans that attributing human abilities
and motives to them is not likely. Such attributions, however,
become much more likely with animals we feel are more similar to
us, as we will see later in the chapter.
Central Mechanisms
Central cognitive mechanisms come in several forms, and I find it
convenient to distinguish among comparator mechanisms,
oscillator mechanisms, and representations. Comparator
mechanisms involve feedback and are basically expectations. An
extremely important exemplar is the reafference system and
efference copy. The principle has been explained by von Holst
(1954). He considers all stimulus input to an organism from all its
receptors to be afference, and information sent from the central
nervous system (a “command”) to motor mechanisms to be
efference. He then distinguishes between exafferent stimulation that
is produced by movement in the external world and reafferent
stimulation that is produced by an animal’s own movement. For
example, “if I shake the branch of a tree, various receptors of my skin
and joints produce a re-afference, but if I place my hand on a branch
shaken by the wind, [stimulation] of the same receptors produce[s]
an ex-afferance…. The same receptor can serve both the ex- and re-
afferance. The CNS [central nervous system], must, however, possess
the ability to distinguish one from the other” (p. 89). His solution
was the efference copy. The “command” leaves a copy of itself in the
motor mechanism, which is compared with reafference produced by
the animal’s movement. If the feedback from the movements of the
animal (reafference) matches the expectation of what the feedback
should be (the efference copy) the animal perceives the world as
stable and perceives itself as having moved. If there is no efference
copy (i.e., there is no expectation of movement) stimulus input
(afference) is perceived as the world moving. The concept of
efference copy has been experimentally shown to be applicable to
animals from insects to humans and the comparison principle, or
expectation, is important in most fields of behavior studies.
Oscillators or central pattern generators are another class of central
behavior mechanisms. At a neural level, oscillators are neurons or
groups of neurons (neural systems) that fire in a rhythmic pattern in
the absence of any rhythmic input. Oscillators are also called
pacemakers. Oscillators can be found throughout the brain and are
generally thought to be responsible for rhythmic activity in many
systems. Their rhythms range from milliseconds to days and perhaps
even years. It was von Holst (1937) who showed that fin movements
in fish are controlled by central pattern generators and D. Wilson
(1966) postulated oscillators as controlling factors in insect
locomotion. Lorenz’ (1937) concept of Erbkoordination also invokes
the operation of central pattern generators in many types of actions.
Gallistel (1980) provides a general discussion of the role of
oscillators in the organization of action. Beyond their role in
determining the form of behavior patterns, oscillators are also
involved in the timing of most behavioral events. They are important
for our perception of time and play an essential role in biological
rhythms as discussed in Chapter 4. As with most basic comparator
mechanisms, so also with oscillators, both are central behavior
mechanisms that generally operate in the background of
consciousness or awareness.
Representations are the mental (neural) correlates of objects, ideas,
concepts, memories, feelings, and the like. Because these entities are
difficult to specify empirically, there have been many different
approaches to studying them. We have seen one method of studying
the representation of an object (an egg for a gull). But there are many
approaches, often specific to the kind of representation being studied
and the kind of question being asked. We will look at some studies of
memory and concepts.
Memory
Memory is the representation of past experience and can be
considered a process leading to the formation of behavior
mechanisms (representations) as well as the outcome of the process.
Cognitive psychologists who study memory are interested in the
relations among the acquisition, retention, and retrieval mechanisms
of memory. These are actually three different kinds of questions
about memory: acquisition is a problem of development or change in
structure; retention is a problem of structure—how (in what form)
and where are memories stored; and retrieval is a problem of
motivation. Psychologists have also noted that there are different
kinds of memory, though there is no consensus as to what those
kinds are. That is because distinctions among kinds of memory
depend on which aspect of memory a researcher is considering: Are
there different modes of acquisition? Are there different forms of
memory, and different locations in which memories are stored? Are
there different kinds of retrieval? Do memories serve different
functions? One distinction, discussed in detail in Chapter 8, is
between working memory (short-term) and reference memory (long-
term). Another distinction, made by Endel Tulving (1972), is between
semantic memory and episodic memory, two forms of reference
memory. Semantic memory, sometimes called conceptual
knowledge, is the aspect of memory that corresponds to general
knowledge of objects, word meaning, and facts without connection to
any particular time or place. Episodic memory, as the name suggests,
is memory for specific events in time and place. Work on these forms
of memory has concentrated on humans, but the results are
applicable to much work on memory in other animals.
In 2007, Karalyn Patterson, Peter Nestor, and Timothy Rogers
published a paper entitled “Where do you know what you know? The
representation of semantic knowledge in the human brain.”
Conceiving of how an object, an egg for example, might be
represented in the brain is a problem because any object has many
attributes, and representations of those attributes (color, shape, size,
etc.) must be located in different appropriate locations. For any
particular object (or idea or concept or word) it is not too difficult to
imagine how it might be represented, but all objects share some
attributes, and representations interact with each other. Patterson et
al. proposed the scheme depicted in Figure 9.4 as a solution to the
problem: the hub-and-spoke model. The model is based on decades
of research with brain-damaged patients suffering from semantic
dementia, neuroimaging studies on normal individuals, and
computational modeling. The details of this model are beyond the
purview of this chapter, but one can see that the representation of an
object is widely distributed throughout the brain (the spokes), but
that the representation comes together in the anterior temporal lobe
(the hub). Representations of different objects, ideas, concepts, etc.
“mingle” in the hub and in that way can interact with each other. The
scheme of visual processing presented in Figure 2.11 is, in principle,
a simplified version of the hub-and-spoke model. I later discuss how
this model relates to representations in other animals.
Figure 9.4 (a) Computational framework for the hub-and-spoke
model. (b) A neuroanatomical sketch of the location of the hub and
spokes is presented. The hub is located within the anterior temporal
lobe (ATL) region, whereas the modality-specific spokes are
distributed across different neocortical regions (the same color
coding is used as for the computational model). Each spoke
communicates bidirectionally with the ATL hub through short- and
long-range white-matter connections (arrows). From Ralph et al.
(2017).
The concept of episodic memory has been a source of controversy
among many cognitive scientists. Tulving (1983) believed that
episodic memory was characteristic of humans and was not present
in other species. As we have seen in Chapter 8 (Figure 8.5), however,
scrub jays (Aphelocoma californica) also exhibit episodic-like
memory (Clayton & Dickinson 1998) as do other species. The digger
wasp female inspects one of her three active nests, spends the night
resting in the fallen needles of a pine tree some distance from the
nest, and returns the next morning with a caterpillar to provision the
nest she inspected the night before. Unsurprisingly, there is still
debate about whether similar behavior implies equivalent cognitive
mechanisms (Clayton 2015). This question is explored further later
in this chapter.
Neuroscientists are also actively studying memory: “Memories are
thought to be encoded as enduring physical changes in the brain, or
engrams” (Josselyn et al. 2015, p. 521). A cartoon of the development
of a memory (engram) is shown in Figure 9.5. There has been
considerable progress in recent years in unravelling the neural
mechanisms involved in these structural changes, and Josselyn et al.
(2015, 2017) review the neurophysiological evidence for these
mechanisms. Of special note is the fact that the neural ensembles
that encode the memory (engram) are widely distributed in the
brain, which is in accord with the hub-and-spoke model of memory
above. A behavioral example of the consolidation and
reconsolidation processes in engram development is the
development of the partner recognition mechanism (sexual
imprinting) in zebra finches discussed in Chapter 7.
Figure 9.5 The lifetime of an engram. The formation of an engram
(encoding) involves strengthening of connections between
collections of neurons (neuronal ensembles) that are active (red)
during an event. Consolidation further strengthens the connections
between these neurons, which increases the likelihood that the same
activity pattern can be recreated at a later time, allowing for
successful memory retrieval. During consolidation, the engram
enters a mainly dormant state. Memory retrieval returns the engram
back to an active state and transiently destabilizes this pattern of
connections. The engram may be restabilized through a process of
reconsolidation and re-enter a more dormant state. Therefore, an
engram may exist in a dormant state between the active process of
encoding and retrieval required to form and recover the memory. In
this way, an engram is not yet a memory, but provides the necessary
conditions for a memory to emerge. From Josselyn et al. (2015)
Concepts
The American Heritage Dictionary defines a concept as “a general
idea or understanding, especially one derived from specific instances
or occurrences.” This is a rather vague definition, but in most cases,
it refers to an abstract feature common to a group of objects that can
differ from each other in many or all of their other features. “Red” is
a concept. The sky can be red, a flower can be red, a fire engine can
be red, the belly of a male stickleback can be red. The hub-and-spoke
model of semantic knowledge discussed above can provide a
framework for understanding a concept as a mental structure:
overlapping spokes. Concepts and concept formation in humans
have been studied in experimental psychology for many years (e.g.,
Bruner et al. 1956), but Chittka & Niven (2009) have argued that
insects can also form concepts such as same or different.
Recently, Avargues-Weber et al. (2012) have provided evidence that
honeybees are even able to learn two abstract concepts
simultaneously: a spatial relationship (above/below vs right/left)
and a same/different relationship. The bees were trained in a Y-maze
with stimuli presented vertically on the back wall of each arm. A
small nipple in the center of each wall contained either a drop of
sucrose solution (a reward) or a drop of quinine (an aversive
substance). The correct stimulus always had two components that
could be either the same or different (in color and pattern) and could
be arranged either one above the other or next to each other. Bees
were trained on the spatial arrangement and reached a level of 80%
correct in 30 trials. During training, all the stimulus components
were different. On transfer tests after training, the bees chose the
stimulus with different components when the spatial arrangement
no longer provided discriminant information. The authors
concluded: “…bees learned that they had to choose stimuli arranged
in a specific spatial relationship and that all stimuli were composed
of different visual elements” (p. 7484).
Orientation
Orientation is generally considered to be a change of an organism’s
position in space as a response to an external stimulus. It is therefore
one category of the consequences of activating behavior mechanisms.
Orientation reactions range from simple reflexes to highly integrated
sequences of behavior. Three types of orientation reactions are
considered here: taxes, navigation, and migration.
Taxes
Taxes are movements defined by the fact that their form is
continuously determined by stimuli from the external environment.
When the greylag goose is retrieving her egg, she continuously makes
sideways movements of her bill that keep the egg from rolling away.
However, if the egg does roll away, the sideways movements stop
even though the retrieval movement itself continues (Figure 9.2).
Most behavior patterns have a taxis component, and there is also a
large older literature on taxes in various invertebrates. One of the
most influential figures in this field was the German/American
physiologist Jacques Loeb (1918), who was active at the end of the
nineteenth and the beginning of the twentieth centuries. He led a
crusade against the anthropomorphic and teleological explanations
of invertebrate behavior then current in the writings of men such as
Romanes (1883) and attempted to understand all behavior in
physical and chemical terms. Although many of his ideas were
oversimplified or incorrect, his work stimulated a great deal of
experimental work on the behavior of invertebrates, much of it
summarized in the book by Fraenkel & Gunn (1940/1961).
Movement toward, away from, or with a fixed relation to a stimulus
is probably the simplest form of orientation. The behavior
mechanisms responsible for the movement, however, can range from
simple to highly complex. The negative klinotaxis to light in the
blowfly maggot (Calliphora erythrocephala), for example, depends
on a comparison of the light intensities on the two sides of its
foreregion. As it moves, it slowly waves its foreregion from side to
side. If the light intensity on one side is higher than on the other, it
turns away from the light (see Tinbergen 1951, pp. 92–93). Much
more complex is the rheotaxis of the larval zebrafish (Danio rerio).
Most aquatic species orient toward a current and swim to hold their
position. This rheotaxic behavior is known to involve the lateral line
and visual systems. Olive et al. (2016) developed an assay to study
freely swimming larvae and were able to show that there is a clear
transition from exploratory to counterflow swimming. By changing
the sensory modalities accessible to the fish (visual only, lateral line
only, or both) and comparing the swim patterns at different ages,
they were able to detect and characterize two different mechanisms
for position holding, one mediated by the lateral line and one
mediated by the visual system. When both sensory modalities were
accessible, the visual system overshadowed the lateral line. Oteiza et
al. (2017), in other experiments, showed that, in the absence of visual
cues, larval zebrafish perform rheotaxis by using flow velocity
gradients as navigational cues. The fish use their mechanosensory
lateral line to first sense the curl (or vorticity) of the local velocity
vector field to detect the presence of flow and, second, to measure its
temporal change after swim bouts to deduce flow direction. Their
results reveal an elegant navigational strategy that generalizes to a
wide range of animal behaviors in moving fluids. Florian Engert and
his group are currently investigating the neural circuits involved in
this behavior.
Navigation
Our ability to easily find our way about in space raises many
additional questions about the mechanisms of orientation. In
everyday life, we subjectively take a stable representation of space for
granted. But how the nervous system might accomplish such a
representation poses huge problems. Further, other species from
insects to birds and other mammals also behave in ways that support
the idea that they too have a stable representation of space. Three
lines of evidence speak to this issue: spatial memory, path
integration, and cognitive maps.
Spatial Memory
Place memory, that is, remembering where something is located, is a
basic requirement for view-based navigation. There is abundant
evidence that species from insects to humans use view-based
navigation, but what is actually being remembered? In early studies
of digger wasps, Tinbergen (1932/1972) and Baerends (1941) saw
that the wasps made an orientation flight above the nest before
departing on a foraging trip. Experiments using displacement of
landmark arrays near the nest (see Figure 17.4) showed that the
wasps relied on visual local landmarks to relocate their nests. Black-
capped chickadees (Parus atricapillus) store seeds and invertebrate
prey in concealed locations scattered throughout their home range.
Experiments, similar to the wasp studies, showed that the birds rely
on visual information from nearby landmarks to locate concealed
caches. The appearance of the cache sites themselves seemed to be
relatively unimportant in cache retrieval (Sherry & Duff 1996).
Sherry and Vaccarino (1989), in a laboratory study, removed
(aspirated) the hippocampus of black-capped chickadees after the
birds had had an opportunity to cache sunflower seeds and found
that recovery of stored seeds was reduced to the chance rate, even
though the rate of searching behavior was not affected. The results of
a second experiment showed that both memory for places and
working memory were disrupted by hippocampal damage, and that
both these memory capacities were essential for cache recovery.
Spatial memory has been studied in a wide variety of species, using
many different tasks. Richard Morris (1981) observed rats swimming
in a circular pool of water. A platform, on which the animals could
remain dry, was submerged just below the surface. The platform was
not visible due to milk being added to the water. The rats quickly
learned the location of the platform. By altering the location of the
platform, it was determined that the rats were using distal cues in the
room as landmarks. Interestingly, rats that were tested when the
platform was not submerged and was visible did not learn
substantially faster. Ken Cheng (1986) observed rats in a large
rectangular sandbox. The rats learned that food was buried in a
particular location and then were tested when no food was present.
Analysis of the errors made by the rats while learning and when
being tested with no food present showed that the animals were
encoding the location of the food in relation to the geometry of the
enclosure, local cues. What cues are used when both distal and local
cues are available varies with the species and situation.
How the landmark memories are used is another question. In a study
of landmark learning in bees, Cartwright & Collett (1982) suggested
that bees trained to forage at a place specified by landmarks do not
construct a Cartesian map of the arrangement of landmarks at the
food source. Instead, they proposed that the bees store something
like a two-dimensional snapshot of their surroundings at the food
source. To return there, the bees move so as to reduce discrepancies
between the snapshot and their current retinal image. Some
variation of image matching is likely to be a general mechanism used
in spatial navigation. Gallistel (1990), Shettleworth (2010), and
Collett et al. (2013) discuss these issues in detail.
Path Integration
“It is often assumed that navigation implies the use, by animals, of
landmarks indicating the location of the goal. However, many
animals (including humans), are able to return to the starting point
of a journey, or to other goal sites, by relying on self-motion cues
only. This process is known as path integration, and it allows an
agent to calculate a route without making use of landmarks” (Etienne
& Jeffery 2004, p. 180). The term “path integration” was first used by
Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt (1980) with respect to pup retrieval in
the gerbil (Meriones unguiculatus), but the principle was already
suggested by Darwin (1873) with respect to humans and derived
from “dead reckoning” as used by mariners in navigating across open
seas with no visible landmarks. The path integration mechanism is
often thought to be a neural accumulator that continuously monitors
directional cues and distances traveled and that integrates them so
that the animal always “knows” the direction from its current
position to its home or other starting position. Such a mechanism
implies the existence of some sort of neural representation of space
(Gallistel 1990; Gallistel & Matzel 2013).
There have been many experiments studying navigation of insects,
especially ants and honeybees, and many of these experiments have
demonstrated the use of path integration. Karl Von Frisch (1955), for
example, showed that honeybees (Apis mellifera) communicate the
distance and direction of a food source to other bees by means of the
“wagging dance” (see Chapter 14). In one experiment, he
demonstrated that the subject bee communicated the straight-line
distance from the hive to the food source even though the subject bee
had only visited the food source by detouring around a large rock and
never by flying directly herself; this information could only have
been acquired through path integration. Other experiments by
Wehner and his colleagues (e.g., Wehner & Menzel 1990) on the
desert ant (Cataglyphis fortis) also demonstrate the use of path
integration in navigation. Collett and Collett (2000) reviewed the
results from desert ants and honeybees and discuss three models of
how an accumulator might work. They also provide new
experimental results that show that insects can use both path
integration and landmark navigation, and which is employed
depends on conditions in the specific case.
As mentioned above, path integration is also used by birds and
mammals. In a series of very careful experiments, Ariane Etienne
and her colleagues (1996) demonstrated that foraging golden
hamsters (Mesocricetus auratus) can return to their home using
only information derived from path integration. Her results also
showed that the return home need not even be direct. Nonetheless,
under normal environmental conditions, path integration
information is combined with landmark information in navigation.
Cognitive Maps
Tolman (1948) introduced the term “cognitive map” into psychology
to interpret the results of his experiments on maze learning in rats.
He suggested “that in the course of learning, something like a field
map of the environment gets established in the rat’s brain” (p. 192).
Such a map would be an internal representation of the geometric
relations among noticeable points in the animal’s environment.
Evidence for such a map came from a number of sources, but
especially from observations that, when physical barriers were
removed, a rat would run directly to the source of food. Thirty years
later, O’Keefe and Nadel (1978) presented neurophysiological
evidence for such a view in their book, The Hippocampus as a
Cognitive Map.
Since then, there has been an explosion of experimental work, both
behavioral and neurophysiological, exploring the characteristics of
such maps. It soon became apparent, however, that investigators had
differing views of what was meant by the concept of a cognitive map
and whether insects, for example, did or did not have such a map.
Sara Shettleworth (2010, pp. 296–310) provides a thoughtful and
comprehensive review of the behavioral evidence for and against the
idea of a cognitive map. She concludes that “there is little if any
unambiguous evidence that any creature gets around using a
representation that corresponds to an overall metric survey map of
its environment” and that mapping-like behavior is “better explained
by reference to what cues the animals are actually using, how they
are using them, and how they come to do so than to the ill-defined
notion of a cognitive map.”
The reality of the hypothesized existence of a cognitive map has been
supported by the recent discovery of spatial grid cells in the
entorhinal cortex (a neighboring structure of, and with direct
connections to, the hippocampus) of the rat that encode both
distance and direction information independent of the animal’s
immediate location (Moser & Moser 2016). Together with
information from “place cells” in the hippocampus, this system could
be used by the animal to find its way about in space. (John O’Keefe,
May-Britt Moser, and Edvard Moser were awarded the Nobel Prize
for physiology in 2014 for this work.) However, as Redish (2001)
pointed out, there are different kinds of maps: a local map of one’s
surroundings; a map of the city in which one resides; a map of the
world. How are these maps related? And how is space represented in
animals such as birds, fish, insects, and cephalopods that do not have
the same brain structures as mammals? Humans have an internal
model of the outside world, but whether “cognitive map” is the best
metaphor for how the outside world is represented is moot. It is
perhaps better to follow Shettleworth’s advice and look for the
mechanisms each species is actually using to find its way about in
space.
Migration
Migration refers to movement from one place to another, usually in
groups, and often seasonally. The cognitive mechanisms used by
human migrants from Afghanistan to Europe are clearly different
from those used by wildebeest moving across the African plains or
from birds migrating from the Arctic to the Antarctic. In this chapter,
I will only be considering some aspects of bird migration.
The phenomenon of bird migration has been known since ancient
times, although explanations of it have radically changed since then
(Wiltschko & Wiltschko 2003). Bird migration can vary in distance
from a few hundred to several thousand kilometers. Many species
interrupt their migratory flights in places where they can rest and
refuel, but at least one species, the bar-tailed godwit (Limosa
lapponica), has been tracked making an 11,000 km-long nonstop
flight from Alaska to New Zealand and eastern Australia (Battley et
al. 2012). However, regardless of distance, there are three questions
all migrants face with respect to orientation: In which direction do I
go? How far do I go? How do I know I have arrived in the right
place? Another question, “When do I go?”, is a question of
motivation and is not considered in detail here. Most of these
questions have been investigated using birds kept in aviaries,
although some studies have observed free-flying birds.
“In which direction do I go?” is the aspect of migration that has been
most studied. During the migratory season, most aviary birds show
an increase in activity (Zugunruhe or migratory restlessness). This
Zugunruhe has been shown to be due to physiological changes
controlled by the photoperiod and a circannual rhythm (Gwinner
1986, 1996). Early experiments by Kramer (1952) on starlings
(Sturnus vulgarus) showed that the birds were able to orient their
flights using a sun-compass (see Chapter 4), but since most birds,
including starlings, migrate at night, later experiments have
concentrated on other means of orientation. Emlen (1967) tested
captive indigo buntings (Passerina cyanea) for celestial orientation
under the natural night sky and inside a planetarium and showed
that the birds displayed a consistent tendency to orient in the
direction appropriate for the migration season in question (i.e., fall
or spring migration). Outside periods of Zugunruhe, the birds
oriented in random directions. Other experiments by the Wiltschkos
and their colleagues (review in 2003) provide convincing evidence
that most birds can also use the earth’s magnetic fields for
orientation.
The sun-compass, the starry sky, and magnetic fields are all tools
that birds can use for orientation, but they do not actually answer the
question of which direction is correct. Emlen (1969) provided
evidence that changes in the internal physiological state of the bird
are responsible for the seasonal reversal of preferred migration
direction, and experiments with birds of various species that were
migrating for the first time, demonstrate that they set off in the
correct direction. These results all suggest that migratory direction
can develop prefunctionally, but social interaction of some sort with
experienced conspecifics is probably the determining factor in most
cases.
“How far should I fly?” is a question that has not been much studied,
but there are some data that suggest possible answers. Berthold
(1973) found, in various species of migratory warblers that he and his
colleagues were studying, that the amount of Zugunruhe shown by
aviary birds during the migratory period correlated highly with the
distance that each species flew on its migratory trips. Gwinner (1986,
1996) proposed that a circannual rhythm produced timing programs
that could play a major role in determining migratory distance.
Another possible mechanism is related to the magnitude of the
energy stores built up prior to migration (see Piersma & Van Gils
2011). The bird would fly until its store was used up. In experienced
birds, memory of previous flights would be sufficient to determine
distance.
“How do I know I have arrived?” has also not been extensively
addressed experimentally. One study of habitat preference in the
dark-eyed junco (Junco hyemalis) suggests a possible general
mechanism. Roberts and Weigl (1984) recorded the time juncos
spent in front of pictures of their summer and winter habitats.
Juncos kept on winter or summer photoperiods preferred winter or
summer habitat pictures, respectively. Insofar as habitat preference
is based on visual features of the environment, birds would know
that they have arrived when the actual habitat matches their mental
picture of the appropriate habitat. An experiment with red knots
(Calidris canutus), a long-distance migratory shorebird, has
provided suggestive evidence: the birds’ visual preference for
projected habitat pictures of wintering mudflats and breeding tundra
did change as the birds went from winter to summer physiological
condition in the lab (Kok et al. 2020).
Social Learning
Social learning refers to any learning that is influenced by interaction
with, or observation of, another animal or its products (Heyes 1994).
What makes it different from the types of learning discussed in
Chapter 8? With respect to the mechanisms of learning, probably
nothing! Nonetheless, it has been studied as a separate field for
many years for at least two major reasons. The first is that many
investigators have been interested in comparing human and
nonhuman intelligence: the presence or absence of social learning in
various species might make it possible to differentiate humans from
nonhumans. The second reason is that social learning provides a
mechanism for transmission of behavior between generations and
could thus provide insight into the evolution of behavior. I will
present some examples of social learning and then discuss possible
mechanisms.
Observational Learning
When a broody hen, in the presence of young chicks, finds a morsel
of food such as a mealworm, she picks it up and makes a “food call.”
This attracts the chicks. She then drops the food and one of them
picks it up and swallows it. Subsequently, all the chicks will show a
preference for similar foods (Kruijt 1964). Young kittens provide a
somewhat similar example. Young kittens are often seen “playing”
with small moveable objects, which is also seen with a live mouse.
When the mother cat joins the kittens and catches the mouse, opens
it up, and eats it, the kittens subsequently treat mice as food (Berry
1908). Another more complex example concerns foraging behavior in
pigeons (Columbia livia) and doves (Zenaida macroura). There have
been several reports that pigeons and doves can perform relatively
complex novel food-finding behavior after observing the actions of
an experienced conspecific. The most convincing evidence comes
from a well-designed series of experiments by Palameta and Lefebvre
(1985). These investigators were able to show that a pigeon, merely
by observing another pigeon performing a learned response for food,
can learn both where to direct its feeding behavior and what motor
act to use. The experimental set-up used in their experiments is
shown in Figure 9.6.
Figure 9.6 Observational learning in doves. The dove on the left is
watching the dove on the right lift a cover off a source of food.
Courtesy of Louis Lefebvre.
In a review of studies of social learning in insects, Elli Leadbeater &
Lars Chittka (2007) concluded that there are many well-
substantiated cases of observational learning. In a recent example,
Leadbeater (2015) studied observational learning in bumblebees
(Bombus terrestris). In the experiment, “subject” bumblebees were
initially trained to associate conspecific presence with either a
sucrose reward or an aversive substance. They were then permitted
to watch conspecific “demonstrators” choosing a particular color of
an artificial flower through a screen. The set-up was analogous to
that in Figure 9.5, adapted for bees, of course. When later allowed to
forage alone, bees that had learned to associate conspecifics with
sucrose preferred the flower color the demonstrators chose, while the
aversive group actively avoided the same colors. A control group of
naïve bees was not influenced by the demonstrators’ choices. In
another study (Alem et al. 2016), investigators trained bumblebees to
obtain a sucrose reward from an artificial flower lying under a
transparent cover using a string-pulling task (see Figure 9.7).
Observer bees were first allowed to obtain the sucrose reward from
exposed flowers. They then were allowed, individually in a small
transparent chamber nearby, to watch a demonstrator bee retrieve
the flower and obtain the reward. After the demonstrator bee had
been removed and the flower replenished, the observer bee was
allowed to enter the flight arena. Sixty percent (15 of 25) of the
observer bees tested managed to pull the string (a tool) and obtain
the reward on the first trial after having observed the demonstration.
Control bees, without a demonstration, never solved the problem.
Perceptual Learning
As we have seen in Chapter 7, social interaction is essential for the
development of species’ recognition mechanisms through filial and
sexual imprinting. It is also essential for the development of a
template (perceptual mechanism) in bird song learning: the bird
stores a memory of the song it heard while very young that it uses
when learning to sing the song itself later. Social influences are in
fact ubiquitous in many aspects of vocal development (Snowdon &
Hausberger 1997). An important example is the development of
alarm calling in vervet monkeys (Cercopithecus aethiops, now
Chlorocebus aethiops) living in Amboseli National Park, Kenya.
Struhsaker (1967) noted that these monkeys gave acoustically
different alarm calls in response to different types of predators and
that each call evoked a different and seemingly adaptive response.
His suggestions were followed up in a 14-month field study by
Seyfarth et al. (1980) who observed the responses of vervet moneys
to predators in natural encounters and to playbacks of recorded
alarm calls. Their results confirmed the observations of Struhsaker:
“animals on the ground respond to leopard alarms by running into
trees, to eagle alarms by looking up, and to snake alarms by looking
down” (p. 1070).
These findings started a conversation about the problem of meaning
in alarm calls (Macedonia & Evans 1993). Do nonhuman animal
vocalizations have “functional reference”: do the callers only give the
leopard alarm when they spot a leopard, or do they give the leopard
alarm when they spot any ground predator or nonpredator; do the
receivers always behave appropriately when they hear the alarm for a
predator they cannot see? Do the monkeys have representations of
the predator analogous to human representations? The question of
meaning is logically an aspect of the search for the adequate (sign)
stimulus. Subsequent studies of the development of alarm calling
and responses to alarm calls in young vervet monkeys from 3 to 7
months of age found that both the motor mechanism of the sender
and the perceptual mechanism of the receiver require functional
experience (i.e., learning) in order to attain adult form (Seyfarth &
Cheney 1997). Their results suggest that the alarm calls of these
monkeys do indeed have functional reference.
Figure 9.9 (a) Female Portia fimbriata. This is the posture Portia
adopts when stalking other jumping spiders. Courtesy of Robert
Jackson. (b) Example of apparatus used in detour-choice
experiments. Trial began with a test spider walking out of the pit and
on top of the tower where it could view two boxes. One box contained
four lures made from Oecobius amboseli (another species of spider)
and the other box contained lures made from four green-leaf pieces.
Which box contained prey was determined at random. After the test
spider left the pit and walked down from the top of the tower, all of
the lures were removed from the apparatus. To complete a successful
trial, the test spider chose a walkway after it left the tower and then
walked across the platform. The thick arrows indicate the path the
test spider took from the tower to the beginning of the correct
walkway and then to the end of that walkway. The apparatus sat in a
shallow pan filled with water (not shown). Drawing modified from
Cross and Jackson (2016)
Planning is sometimes characterized as “thinking before acting,” and
Portia’s hunting behavior and Ammophila’s provisioning behavior fit
that definition, as does going to the grocery store with a shopping
list. But thinking ranges from simple to complex, and many scientists
are interested in studying more complex thinking in animals.
Güntürkün and Bugynar (2016) reviewed studies on bird and
primate cognition looking at these cognitive “skills”: object
permanence, delay of gratification, mental time travel, reasoning,
meta-cognition, mirror self-recognition, theory of mind, and vocal
learning. The purpose of the review was to show that many birds,
primarily corvids and parrots, have these skills at the same level as
many primates, especially chimpanzees and apes. Such a result
supports the hypothesis that mammal and bird cognition (brain
structures) evolved independently and that birds and mammals have
evolved similar cognitive abilities convergently. Implications of this
conclusion are considered below. But first I want to consider a study
investigating learning and cognitive processes in rats using advanced
neurophysiological methods as well as behavioral observation.
Steiner and Redish (2014) studied “regret” in rats using the
Restaurant Row apparatus seen in Figure 9.10. The economic
foraging task required a rat to run counterclockwise around the loop,
making stay or skip decisions as it passed each spoke (restaurant).
Upon entering the zone around each spoke, the rat encountered
different offers of delays ranging from 1 to 30 seconds, indicated by
the frequency of the tone. If the rat stayed the allotted time, it
received a flavored pellet from a feeder at the end of the spoke. If it
left the zone early, the offer was rescinded, and the rat moved on to
the next zone. Each restaurant offered a different flavor, and the rat
had a total of 60 minutes in each session. Because the session was
time-limited, the decision to stay or skip a zone was not independent
of the other zones: waiting at one zone was time that could have been
spent at another zone. An economically maximizing rat should
distribute its time among the offers, waiting for valuable offers but
skipping expensive offers. Assuming that an animal likes some
flavors more than others, the economic value of an offer should
depend on the delay offered and the animal’s preferences.
Figure 9.10 Neural encoding of regret in orbitofrontal cortex
(OFC) and ventral striatum in rats performing the Restaurant Row
task. (a) Rats run counterclockwise in an economic foraging task in
which there were four reward zones (restaurants). If rats waited long
enough in each zone, a flavored pellet was delivered at the end of the
zone’s arm. The length of the wait time was signaled by the frequency
of a tone presented on entering that zone. Two zones, banana and
cherry, are shown in this example. The rat likes both of these flavors.
The plots at the bottom represent single cell activity seen in OFC
during performance of this task. In this example, activity is high
when the rat considers cherry and low when it considers banana.
Thus, this neuron is selective for cherry. Other neurons are selective
for other flavors. (b) The rat skips the cherry zone because the delay
to reward exceeds the rat’s threshold of willingness to wait for
cherry. However, once the rat gets to the banana zone, the new delay
for banana far exceeds the rat’s willingness to wait for banana. At
that instant the rat looks back with regret. During this look back,
activity in OFC and ventral striatum is similar to that observed
previously when the rat considered the cherry zone. From Bissonette
et al. (2014) (after Steiner & Redish 2014).
There are clearly many decisions the rat must make in order to
maximize receiving the most preferred pellets, but I will only
consider one here. “Regret” entails recognition that an alternative
action would have produced a more valued outcome. In humans, the
orbitofrontal cortex (OFC) is active during expressions of regret, and
humans with damage to the OFC do not express regret. In rats and
nonhuman primates, both the OFC and the ventral striatum have
been implicated in reward computations. In this study, neural
ensembles from OFC and ventral striatum were recorded as the rat
traversed the Restaurant Row. Some results are shown in Figure
9.10. The results described give strong support to the supposition
that the rat is engaged in deliberative thinking and is perhaps feeling
“regret”; but whether the rat “feels” anything and how such a feeling
compares to a human feeling remain matters of conjecture.
FURTHER READING
Cognition, Evolution, and Behavior by Sara Shettleworth (2010) is
the authoritative source for details on most of the topics discussed in
this chapter. The Study of Behavior (Hogan 2017) puts cognitive
issues in a broader perspective. Wynne and Udell (2020), Animal
Cognition: Evolution, Behavior, and Cognition, present a wide
range of facts and examples of animal cognition suitable for the
general reader.
REFERENCES
Alem, S., Perry, F.J., Zhu, X. et al. 2016. Associative mechanisms
allow for social learning and cultural transmission of string
pulling in an insect. PLoS Biology, 14, 10.
Avargues-Weber, A., Dyer, A.G., Combe, M. & Giufa, M. 2012.
Simultaneous mastering of two abstract concepts by the miniature
brain of bees. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
USA, 109, 7481–6.
Baerends, G.P. 1941. Fortpflanzungsverhalten und Orientierung der
Grabwespe Ammophila campestris. Jur. Tijdschrift voor
Entomologie, 84, 71–275.
Baerends, G.P. & Drent, R.H. (eds.). 1982. The herring gull and its
eggs. Behaviour, 82, 1–416.
Battley, P.F. et al. 2012. Contrasting extreme long-distance migration
patterns in bar-tailed godwits. Limosa lapponica. Journal of
Avian Biology, 43, 1–12.
Berry, C.S. 1908. An experimental study of imitation in cats. Journal
of Comparative Neurology and Physiology, 18, 1–12.
Berthold, P. 1973. Relationships between migratory restlessness and
migration distance in six Sylvia species. Ibis, 115, 594–9.
Bissonette, G.B., Bryden, D.W. & Roesch, M.R. 2014. You won’t
regret reading this. Nature Neuroscience, 17, 892–3.
Bruner, J.S., Goodnow, J.J. & Austin, G.A. 1956. A Study of
Thinking. New York: Wiley.
Cartwright, B.A. & Collett, T.S. 1982. How honeybees use landmarks
to guide their return to a food source. Nature, 295, 56–564.
Cheng, K. 1986. A purely geometric module in the rat’s spatial
representation. Cognition, 23, 149–78.
Chittka, L. & Niven, J. 2009. Are bigger brains better? Current
Biology, 19, R995-R1008.
Clayton, N.S. 2015. Ways of thinking: from crows to children and
back again. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 28,
209–41.
Clayton, N.S. & Dickinson, A. 1998. Episodic-like memory during
cache recovery by scrub jays. Nature, 395, 272–4.
Collett, M., Chittka, L. & Collett, T.S. 2013. Spatial memory in insect
navigation. Current Biology, 23, R789-R800.
Collett, M. & Collett, T.S. 2000. How do insects use path integration
for their navigation? Biological Cybernetics, 83, 245–59.
Cross, E.R. 2020. Arthropod intelligence? The case for Portia.
Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 568049.
Cross, E.R. & Jackson, R.R. 2016. The execution of planned detours
by spider-eating predators. Journal of the Experimental Analysis
of Behavior, 105, 194–210.
Darwin, C. 1973. Origin of certain instincts. Nature, 7, 417–8.
Diedrichsen, J. & Kornysheva, K. 2015. Motor skill learning between
selection and execution. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 19, 227–33.
Emlen, S.T. 1967. Migratory orientation in the indigo bunting.
Passerina cyanea. Auk, 84(309-342), 463–89.
Emlen, S.T. 1969. Bird migration: influence of physiological state
upon celestial orientation. Science, 165, 716–8.
Etienne, A.S. & Jeffery, K.J. 2004. Path integration in mammals.
Hippocampus, 14, 180–92.
Etienne, A.S., Maurer, R. & Séguinot, V. 1996. Path integration in
mammals and its integration with visual landmarks. Journal of
Experimental Biology, 199, 201–9.
Ewert, J.-P. 1997. Neural correlates of key stimulus and releasing
mechanism. Trends in Neurosciences, 20, 332–39.
Falótico, T. & Ottoni, E.B. 2014. Sexual bias in probe tool
manufacture and use by wild bearded capuchin monkeys.
Behavioural Processes, 108, 117–22.
Falótico, T. & Ottoni, E.B. 2016. The manifold use of pounding tools
by wild capuchin monkeys of Serra da Capivara National Park,
Brazil. Behaviour, 153, 421–42.
Fraenkel, G.S. & Gunn, D.L. 1940/1961. The Orientation of Animals.
New York: Dover.
Galef, B.G., Jr. 1988. Imitation in animals: history, definition and
interpretation of data from the psychological laboratory. In T.R.
Zentall & B.G. Galef Jr. (eds.), Social Learning: Psychological
and Biological Perspectives, pp. 3–28. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Galef, B.G., Jr. 2013. Imitation and local enhancement: detrimental
effects of consensus definitions on analyses of social learning in
animals. Behavioural Processes, 100, 123–30.
Gallistel, C.R. 1980. The Organization of Action. Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Gallistel, C.R. 1990. The Organization of Learning. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Gallistel, C.R. & Matzel, L.D. 2013. The neuroscience of learning:
beyond the Hebbian synapse. Annual Review of Psychology, 63,
169–200.
Güntürkün, O. 2020. The surprising power of the avian mind.
Scientific American, 322, 48–55.
Güntürkün, O. & Bugynar, T. 2016. Cognition without cortex. Trends
in Cognitive Sciences, 20, 291–303.
Gwinner, E. 1986. Circannual rhythms in the control of avian
migration. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 16, 191–228.
Gwinner, E. 1996. Circadian and circannual programmes in avian
migration. Journal of Experimental Biology, 199, 39–48.
Haslam, M., Luncz, L.V. & Falótico, T. 2016. Pre-Columbian monkey
tools. Current Biology, 26, R515-R522.
Heyes, C.M. 1994. Social learning in animals: categories and
mechanisms. Biological Reviews, 69, 207–31.
Hogan, J.A. 2017. The Study of Behavior. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Jackson, R.R. & Cross, E.R. 2011. Spider cognition. Advances in
Insect Physiology, 41, 115–74.
Jackson, R.R. & Wilcox, R.S. 1998. Spider-eating spiders. American
Scientist, 86, 350–7.
James, W. 1890. The Principles of Psychology. New York: Henry
Holt. [Reprinted 1950 by Dover Publications.].
Josselyn, S.A., Köhler, S. & Frankland, P.W. 2015. Finding the
engram. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 16, 521–34.
Josselyn, S.A., Köhler, S. & Frankland, P.W. 2017. Heroes of the
engram. Journal of Neuroscience, 17, 4647–57.
Kok, E.M.A., Hogan, J.A. & Piersma, T. 2020. Experimental tests of a
seasonally changing visual preference for habitat in a long-
distance migratory shorebird. Ethology, 126, 681–93.
Kramer, G. 1952. Experiments on bird orientation. Ibis, 94, 265–85.
Kruijt, J.P. 1964. Ontogeny of social behaviour in Burmese red
junglefowl (Gallus gallus spadiceus). Behaviour, Suppl. 9.
Leadbeater, E. 2015. What evolves in the evolution of social learning.
Journal of Zoology, 295, 4–11.
Leadbeater, E. & Chittka, L. 2007. Social learning in insects—From
miniature brains to consensus building. Current Biology, 17,
R703–R713.
Loeb, J. 1918. Forced Movements, Tropisms and Animal Conduct.
Philadephia: Lippincott.
Lorenz, K. 1937. Über die Bildung des Instinktbegriffes.
Naturwissenschaften, vol. 25, pp. 289–300, 307–318, 324–331.
[Tr. as: The establishment of the instinct concept. In: Lorenz
1970, Studies in Animal and Human Behaviour, vol. 1, pp. 259–
315. London: Methuen].
Lorenz, K. & Tinbergen, N. 1939. Taxis und Instinkthandlung in der
Eirollbewegung der Graugans. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie,
vol. 2, pp. 1–29. [Tr. as: Taxis and instinctive behaviour pattern in
egg-rolling by the greylag goose. In: Lorenz 1970, pp. 316–50].
Macedonia, J.M. & Evans, C.S. 1993. Variation among mammalian
alarm call systems and the problem of meaning in animal signals.
Ethology, 93, 177–97.
Mittelstaedt, M.-L. & Mittelstaedt, H. 1980. Homing by path
integration in a mammal. Naturwissenschaften, 67, 566–7.
Morris, R.G.M. 1981. Spatial localization does not require the
presence of local cues. Learning and Motivation, 12, 239–60.
Moser, M.-B. & Moser, E.J. 2016. Where am I? Where am I going?
Scientific American, 314(1), 26–33.
O’Keefe, J. & Nadel, L. 1978. The Hippocampus as a Cognitive Map.
Oxford: Clarendon.
Olive, R., Wolf, S., Dubreuil, A. et al. 2016. Rheotaxis of larval
zebrafish: Behavioral study of a multi-sensory process. Frontiers
in Systems Neuroscience, 10, 14.
Oteiza, P., Odstrcil, I., Lauder, G., Portugues, R. & Engert, F. 2017. A
novel mechanism for mechanosensory-based rheotaxis in larval
zebrafish. Nature, 547, 445–8.
Palameta, B. & Lefebvre, L. 1985. The social transmission of a food-
finding technique in pigeons: what is learned? Animal Behaviour,
33, 892–6.
Patterson, K., Nestor, P. & Rogers, T.T. 2007. Where do you know
what you know? The representation of semantic knowledge in the
human brain. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 8, 976–87.
Piersma, T. & Van Gils, J. 2011. The Flexible Phenotype. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Ralph, M.A.L., Jefferies, E., Patterson, K. & Rogers, T.T. 2017. The
neural and computational bases of semantic cognition. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience, 18, 42–55.
Redish, A.D. 2001. The hippocampal debate: are we asking the right
questions? Behavioral Brain Research, 127, 81–98.
Resende, B.D., Nagy-Reis, M.B., Lacerda, F.N., Pagnotta, M. &
Savalli, C. 2014. Tufted capuchin monkeys (Sapajus sp.) learning
how to crack nuts: does variability decline throughout
development? Behavioural Processes, 109, 89–104.
Roberts, E.P. & Weigl, P.D. 1984. Habitat preference in the dark-
eyed junco (Junco hyemalis): the role of photoperiod and
dominance. Animal Behaviour, 32, 709–14.
Romanes, C.J.R. 1883. Mental Evolution in Animals. London.
Seyfarth, R.M. & Cheney, D.L. 1997. Some general features of vocal
development in nonhuman primates. In: Snowdon & Hausberger,
1997, pp. 249–73.
Seyfarth, R.M., Cheney, D.L. & Marler, P. 1980. Vervet monkey
alarm calls: semantic communication in a free-ranging primate.
Animal Behaviour, 28, 1070–94.
Sherry, D.F. & Duff, S.J. 1996. Behavioural and neural bases of
orientation in food-storing birds. Journal of Experimental
Biology, 199, 165–71.
Sherry, D.F. & Vaccarino, A.L. 1989. Hippocampus and memory for
food caches in black-capped chickadees. Behavioral
Neuroscience, 103, 308–18.
Shettleworth, S.J. 2010. Cognition, Evolution, and Behavior. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Snowdon, C.T. & Hausberger, M. 1997. Social Influences on Vocal
Development. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Sol, D., Bacher, S., Reader, S.M. & Lefebvre, L. 2008. Brain size
predicts the success of mammal species introduced into novel
environments. American Naturalist, 172, S63–S71.
Steiner, A.P. & Redish, A. 2014. Behavioral and neurophysiological
correlates of rat decision-making on a neuroeconomic task.
Nature Neuroscience, 17, 995–1002.
Struhsaker, T.T. 1967. Social structure among vervet monkeys
(Cercopithecus aethiops). Behaviour, 29, 6–121.
Thorndike, E.L. 1898. Animal intelligence. Psychological Review,
Monograph suppl. 2, 1–113.
Tinbergen, N. 1932/1972. On the orientation of the digger wasp
Philanthus triangulum Fabr. In: N. Tinbergen (ed.), The Animal
in Its World, vol. 1, pp. 103–27. London: George Allen & Unwin.
Tinbergen, N. 1951. The Study of Instinct. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Tolman, E.C. 1948. Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological
Review, 55, 189–208.
Tulving, E. 1972. Episodic and semantic memory. In: E. Tulving & W.
Donaldson (eds.), Organization of Memory, pp. 381–403. New
York: Academic Press.
Tulving, E. 1983. Elements of Episodic Memory. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Van Lawick-goodall, J. 1970. Tool using in primates and other
vertebrates. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 3, 195–249.
Von Frisch, K. 1955. The Dancing Bees. New York: Harcourt, Brace.
Von Holst, E. 1937. Von Wesen der Ordnung im
Zentralnervensystem. Naturwissenschaften, vol. 25, pp. 625-631,
641–47. [Tr. as: On the nature of order in the central nervous
system. In: von Holst 1973, The Selected Papers of Erich von
Holst, vol. 1, pp. 3–32. London: Methuen].
Von Holst, E. 1954. Relations between the central nervous system
and the peripheral organs. British Journal of Animal Behaviour,
2, 89–94.
Wehner, R. & Menzel, R. 1990. Do insects have cognitive maps?
Annual Review of Neuroscience, 13, 403–14.
Wilson, D.M. 1966. Central nervous mechanisms for the generation
of rhythmic behaviour in arthropods. Symposia of the Society for
Experimental Biology, 20, 199–228.
Wiltschko, R. & Wiltschko, W. 2003. Avian navigation: from
historical to modern concepts. Animal Behaviour, 65, 257–72.
Wynne, C.D.L. & Udell, M.A.R. 2020. Animal Cognition, 3rd ed.
London: Red Grobe Press.
10
applied animal behavior and animal welfare
DAVID FRASER AND DANIEL M. WEARY
INTRODUCTION
Why do captive tigers pace for hours, tracing and retracing the
same path in their pens? Does the presence of tourists drive
grizzly bears away from their spring feeding areas? Why do some
pigs chew the tails off their pen-mates? Why is it so hard to get
wild rats to eat poisoned bait? Is it frustrating for a hen to live in
a cage with no secluded place to lay her eggs? Why do certain
dogs never become fully socialized with their human families?
Since animals can’t talk, how do we know when they are in pain?
These are a small sample of the questions that the field of applied
animal behavior has tried to answer as it grapples with practical
problems and animal welfare issues arising in the management of
wild, farmed, companion, and laboratory animals. These are the
issues discussed in this chapter.
• Society for
Veterinary
Ethology (SVE)
founded
1970s • Journal • Occasional books • Early research
Applied Animal on animal papers
Ethology ethics/advocacy
• First textbook
founded 1974 • Animal welfare chapter on farm
codes and guidelines animal welfare
• Books on written
behavior of
farm animals
and poultry
Figure 10.4 The price that caged American mink (Mustela vison)
will pay for access to various environmental features. Price is
expressed in the total weight (kg) lifted by mink over a 6-week test.
Values are means (+ S.E.) from 16 animals tested. Data are from
Mason et al. (2001)
An especially sophisticated example of this approach comes from a
study by Laura Webb and colleagues who used “cross-point” analysis
of double demand functions to test which types of forage are most
valued by calves. In one experiment Webb and colleagues trained
calves to push their muzzle against a panel and thus trigger the
release of roughage (chopped hay), and they varied the “price” using
a ratio of 7, 14, 21, 28, or 35 presses per reward (called the Fixed
Ratio or FR). This generated a classic “demand curve” with the calves
receiving fewer rewards as the price increased. However, the calves
could also switch to a second panel that released long hay at a price
of 42 minus the FR for chopped hay. Thus, when chopped hay was
available at 7 presses, long hay was available at 35 presses, and vice
versa. If the calves found the two forages equally attractive, we would
expect that the two demand curves should intersect exactly in the
middle; i.e., calves would show equal demand for the two options
when the price was the same (Fixed Ratios of 21 and 21). Instead,
however, the calves appeared to value long hay more because they
received equal proportion of long and chopped hay when the price of
long hay was higher (Figure 10.5; Webb et al. 2014).
Abnormal Behaviors
Abnormal animal behavior has provided a strong stimulus to
understand affective states of animals. In a classic article on
behavioral disturbances, psychiatrist David Levy (1944) described
the repeated rocking movements and other stereotyped behavior
shown by some emotionally disturbed children. In the same article
Levy described similar behavior in farm animals—including
repetitive weaving by horses in stables and stereotyped head
movements by caged chickens—and Levy proposed that these
abnormalities reflect the same kinds of problems seen with children
in severely deprived environments. The idea generated enormous
interest in abnormal animal behavior and its implications for animal
welfare.
A striking example is seen with pregnant sows. During pregnancy
most sows have to be limited in their food intake in order to prevent
excessive weight gain and later health problems, but the restricted
diet can lead to serious aggression if the animals are fed in groups. A
common solution is to house sows individually, often in narrow stalls
where they are sometimes tethered by a collar around the neck.
Some such sows develop stereotyped movement patterns; for
example, a sow may make three rooting movements to the left, swing
her head to the right, and bite the bar of the stall, and then repeat
that same sequence of movements for several hours every day. But
what is the significance of these bizarre movements? Various
scientists have proposed that the behavior develops from exploratory
motivation, or from attempts to escape from a confined space, or that
the behavior helps animals to “cope” with an aversive environment,
for example by causing a release of endogenous opioids (see
Lawrence & Rushen 1993).
However, research in Scotland showed that food restriction plays a
large role in the development of stereotyped behavior of sows. One
hypothesis is that food restriction causes a motivation to forage for
food, but in a barren environment where normal foraging is
impossible, elements of foraging behavior become fused together
into stereotyped sequences of behavior, and because the behavior
never leads to actual eating, it does not turn off in the normal
manner. In a critical experiment, Claudia Terlouw and coworkers
(1991) tested the food-restriction theory. They housed some sows in
narrow stalls where they were tethered by a chain while others were
loose-housed in larger pens equipped with chains hanging from the
walls. In each housing treatment, half the animals were fed a
restricted diet typical of commercial practice while the others
received nearly twice as much. In both pens and stalls, the restricted-
fed animals spent considerable time in chewing, biting, and rooting
the chain and in other seemingly functionless and stereotyped
behavior, whereas these activities were much less common among
the geneyrously fed animals. Terlouw et al. (1991) concluded that
chain-manipulation and other stereotyped behavior of sows are more
related to hunger than to restraint itself, but they noted that none of
the available theories adequately explains this bizarre behavior.
REFERENCES
Adams, G.J. & Johnson, K.G. 1994. Sleep, work, and the effects of
shift work in drug detector dogs, Canis familiaris. Applied Animal
Behaviour Sciemce, 41, 115–26.
Allee, W.C. c.1938. The Social Life of Animals. New York: W.W.
Norton & Co.
Appleby, M.C. & Hughes, B.O. (eds.). 1997. Animal Welfare.
Wallingford: CABI.
Appleby, M.C., Olsson, I.A.S. & Galindo, F. (eds.). 2018. Animal
Welfare, 3rd ed. Wallingford: CABI.
Appleby, M.C., Weary, D.M. & Sandøe, P. (eds.). 2014. Dilemmas in
Animal Welfare. Wallingford: CABI.
Boissy, A., Manteuffel, G., Jensen, M.B. et al. 2007. Assessment of
positive emotions in animals to improve their welfare. Physiology
and Behavior, 92, 375–97.
Bradshaw, J.W.S., Casey, R.A. & Brown, S.L. 2012. The Behaviour of
the Domestic Cat, 2nd ed. Wallingford: CABI.
Brambell, F.W.R. (chairman). 1965. Report of the Technical
Committee in Enquire into the Welfare of Animals kept under
Intensive Livestock Husbandry Systems. London: Her Majesty’s
Stationery Office.
Broom, D.M. & Fraser, A.F. 2015. Domestic Animal Behaviour and
Welfare, 5th ed. Wallingford: CABI.
Burkhardt, R.W., Jr. 1997. The founders of ethology and the problem
of animal subjective experience. In: M. Dol, S. Kasanmoentalib, S.
Lijmbach, E. Rivas & R. Van Den Bos (eds.), Animal
Consciousness and Animal Ethics, pp. 1–13. Assen: Van Gorcum.
Celli, M.L., Tomonaga, M., Udono, T., Teramoto, M. & Nagano, K.
2003. Tool use task as environmental enrichment for captive
chimpanzees. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 81, 171–82.
Cheng, H.-W. 2010. Breeding of tomorrow’s chickens to improve
well-being. Poultry Science, 89, 805–13.
Craig, J.V. 1981. Domestic Animal Behavior: Causes and
Implications for Animal Care and Management. Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Dalla Costa, E., Minero, M., Lebelt, D. et al. 2014. Development of
the Horse Grimace Scale (HGS) as a pain assessment tool in
horses undergoing routine castration. PLoS One, 9, e92281.
Daros, R.R., Costa, J.H.C., Von Keyserlingk, M.A.G., Hötzel, M.J. &
Weary, D.M. 2014. Separation from the dam causes negative
judgment bias in dairy calves. PLoS One, 9, e98429.
Darwin, C. 1872. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and
Animals. Reprinted 1965. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Dawkins, M.S. 1977. Do hens suffer in battery cages? Environmental
preferences and welfare. Animal Behaviour, 25, 1034–46.
Dawkins, M.S. 1980. Animal Suffering: The Science of Animal
Welfare. London: Chapman & Hall.
Dawkins, M.S. 1983. Battery hens name their price: Consumer
demand theory and the measurement of ethological “needs.”
Animal Behaviour, 31, 1195–1205.
Dawkins, M.S. 2001. Who needs consciousness? Animal Welfare,
10(Suppl.), S19–S29.
De Passillé, A.M. & Rushen, J. 1997. Motivational and physiological
analysis of the causes and consequences of non-nutritive sucking
by calves. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 53, 15–31.
Dennett, D.C. 1987. The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Duncan, I.J.H. 1970. Frustration in the fowl. In: B.M. Freeman &
R.F. Gordon (eds.), Aspects of Poultry Behaviour, pp. 15–31.
Edinburgh: British Poultry Science Ltd.
Duncan, I.J.H. 1993. Welfare is to do with what animals feel. Journal
of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 6(Suppl. 2), 8–14.
Duncan, I.J.H., Slee, G., Kettlewell, P., Berry, P. & Carlisle, A.J. 1986.
Comparison of the stressfulness of harvesting broiler chickens by
machine and by hand. British Poultry Science, 27, 109–14.
Fox, M.W. (ed.). 1968. Abnormal Behavior in Animals. Philadelphia:
Saunders.
Fraser, A.F. 1968. Reproductive Behaviour in Ungulates. London:
Academic Press.
Fraser, A.F. 1974. Farm Animal Behaviour. London: Baillière
Tindall.
Fraser, A.F. 2010. The Behaviour and Welfare of the Horse, 2nd ed.
Wallingford: CABI.
Fraser, A.F. 2012. Feline Behaviour and Welfare. Wallingford: CABI.
Fraser, D. 2008. Understanding Animal Welfare: The Science in its
Cultural Context. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Fraser, D. 2009. Animal behaviour, animal welfare and the scientific
study of affect. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 118, 108–17.
Fraser, A.F. & Broom, D.M. 1997. Farm Animal Behaviour and
Welfare, 3rd ed. Wallingford: CABI.
Fraser, D. & Nicol, C.J. 2017. Preference and motivation research. In:
M.C. Appleby, I.A.S. Olsson & F. Galindo (eds.), Animal Welfare,
3rd ed., pp. 213–231. Wallingford: CABI.
Fraser, D. & Reardon, E. 1980. Attraction of wild ungulates to
mineral-rich springs in central Canada. Holarctic Ecology, 3, 36–
40.
Gehring, J., Kerlinger, P. & Manville, A.M. 2009. Communication
towers, lights, and birds: successful methods of reducing the
frequency of avian collisions. Ecological Applications, 19, 505–14.
Goodall, J. 1971. In the Shadow of Man. London: Wm Collins.
Gordon, J.K., Matthaei, C. & Van Heezik, Y. 2010. Belled collars
reduce catch of domestic cats in New Zealand by half. Wildlife
Research, 37, 372–8.
Waring, G.H. 2003. Horse Behavior, 2nd ed. (1st edition, 1983).
Norwich (USA): Noyes.
Weary, D.M. 2014. What is suffering in animals? In: M.C. Appleby,
D.M. Weary & P. Sandøe (eds.), Dilemmas in Animal Welfare, pp.
188–202. Wallingford: CABI.
Webb, L.E., Bak Jensen, M., Engel, B. et al. 2014. Chopped or long
roughage: what do calves prefer? Using cross point analysis of
double demand functions. PLoS One, 9(2), e88778.
Webster, J. 1994. Animal Welfare: A Cool Eye towards Eden.
Oxford: Blackwell Science.
Weiss, E. 2002. Selecting shelter dogs for service dog training.
Journal of Applied Animal Welfare Science, 5, 43–62.
Wells, D.L. 2009. The effects of animals on human health and well-
being. Journal of Social Issues, 65, 523–43.
Wischner, D., Kemper, N. & Krieter, J. 2009. Nest-building
behaviour in sows and consequences for pig husbandry. Livestock
Science, 124, 1–8.
Wong, D., Von Keyserlingk, M.A.G., Richards, J.G. & Weary, D.M.
2014. Conditioned place avoidance of zebrafish (Danio rerio) to
three chemicals used for euthanasia and anaesthesia. PLoS One,
9, e88030.
Wood-Gush, D.G.M. 1971. The Behaviour of the Domestic Fowl.
London: Heinemann Educational.
Wood-Gush, D.G.M., Duncan, I.J.H. & Fraser, D. 1975. Social stress
and welfare problems in agricultural animals. In: E.S.E. Hafez
(ed.), The Behaviour of Domestic Animals, 3rd ed., pp. 182–200.
London: Baillière Tindall.
11
the function of behavior
LUC-ALAIN GIRALDEAU AND JERRY A. HOGAN
INTRODUCTION
Avian migration, the seasonal displacement of millions of birds
from one hemisphere to another is, as all mass migrations, an
astonishing phenomenon: tons of biomass moving from one
continent to another, spending enormous amounts of energy in
the process and all to what end? This remarkable sequence of
events can be approached from a purely mechanistic point of
view. Birds, for instance, respond to changing photoperiod,
which, added to signals from an internal clock, trigger a
hormonal cascade that leads to accumulation of fat reserves and
makes the bird inclined to fly off at night with a strong directional
preference based on stellar position. However, as we pointed out
in Chapter 1, no matter how hard you study this chain of events
and learn how birds migrate, no matter how detailed the
knowledge you get of the physiological processes involved in
hormone production or the way the birds use the stars as a
compass, you will be no closer to knowing why birds migrate in
the first place. Why is it that the internal machinery of some bird
species, but not others, reacts to changing photoperiod in a long
chain of events that lead to long distance migration? To answer
this type of question we must leave the realm of cause and
mechanism and enter the sphere of function and adaptation. This
chapter reviews some of the approaches and methods used to
study the adaptive function of behavior (see also Chapter 15). It
first looks at how adaptation can be studied by formulating
quantitative hypotheses about function using backward
engineering and simple optimality models. The approach will be
illustrated with two classic examples taken from foraging theory:
prey choice and patch residence times, including some results
from experimental tests of the models. Then in the next section it
introduces another version of the optimality approach,
evolutionary game theory and its solution, the Evolutionarily
Stable Strategy, using three examples: the Hawk-Dove and
Producer-Scrounger games and the Ideal Free Distribution.
Introducing Optimality
Backward Engineering
Engineers are asked to design machines that will accomplish some
function with maximal efficiency. They build the machine knowing
its purpose. Biologists, however, have the complete machine before
them and puzzle about its purpose. To figure out the purpose they
follow the reverse route, they postulate a function, and then ask
whether the details of the machine are consistent with maximal
efficiency of this function. That, in essence, is what we mean by
backward engineering. The method of backward engineering
assumes that selection has shaped traits, organs, limbs, behaviors
etc, so that after many generations of being submitted to the same
selective pressures they offer the greatest possible efficiency in the
accomplishment of their purpose. We say greatest possible because
evolution (much like the engineer) is often constrained. The design is
assumed to be maximally efficient given physical, genetic,
morphological, historical, and other constraints. So, if a trait is
thought to be adaptive, we hypothesize its function and ask: what
would be the characteristics of a trait that is optimally designed to
accomplish this hypothetical function? We use mathematical,
economic, and engineering techniques to predict these
characteristics of optimal design and compare them to observations.
If we find a quantitative fit between some feature of an organ, say its
length or width, and the precise length or width expected of an organ
optimally designed to accomplish that same function, then we would
feel more confident that selection honed the trait we are dealing with
to accomplish that purpose and can with more certainty conclude
that it is an adaptation.
1. The relative abundances of each prey type should not affect the
choice. Only the encounter rate with the most profitable prey
(prey type 1) remains in the final equation. That means that
whether prey type 2 gets included in the diet does not depend on
its own abundance but on the abundance of the other, more
profitable item. The more prey type 1 is abundant, the more
likely prey type 2 will drop out of the diet.
2. The optimal diet policy does not depend on the duration of the
search time, because the variable S falls out during
simplification. That means the same policy holds whether an
animal searches just briefly or for long foraging periods.
3. The optimal diet does not allow partial preferences; a prey type
is either always accepted or always rejected.
1. When the patch density declines and hence the average travel
time between patches increases, animals should spend longer
foraging within patches and deplete them to a greater extent.
2. When average patch quality in a habitat increases, foragers
should spend less time exploiting each patch and deplete each to
a lesser extent.
In this graph the x-axis runs in two directions from the y-axis. To
the right, patch time increases. To the left, travel time increases.
The curve gives the cumulative increase in energy intake as the
animal spends time in the average patch. Note that as the animal
spends longer and longer in the patch its instantaneous rate
declines. This is the result of patch depletion. There are two
habitats represented here, one with short travel times and the
other with long travel times, each one represented on the x-axis.
When the animal forages in the habitat with the short travel time
it can leave at any point on the exploitation curve. The problem
consists in finding the point that provides the maximal long-term
intake rate. The intake rate will have units E divided by the sum
of travel time and the chosen patch time. The slope of the line
starting at the short travel time and touching the exploitation
function will have a slope that gives the rate of intake. The slope
of any line linking a travel time to a point on the exploitation
function will give the rate of intake achieved by that patch time.
We are looking for the patch time that corresponds to a line with
the maximum slope. That line has to be the point of tangency to
the curve. Note that the point of tangency for short travel time
corresponds to a short optimal patch time, whereas the longer
travel time leads to a point of tangency at a longer optimal patch
time. This means that the optimal patch times are predicted to
increase when the average travel time between patches in an
environment increases.
placing the payoffs from the matrix in their appropriate places gives:
1. know the value of all alternative habitats (i.e., they are ideal).
2. are free to go in the best habitats (i.e., they are free).
Figure 11.6 The value of two habitats (B1 and B2) declines as the
density of competitors in them increases. Habitat B1 has a higher
initial value than habitat B2. The first ideal free individuals should go
to habitat B1. As the density of individuals in habitat B1 increases, its
value declines until the value in B1 becomes equal to the value in B2.
When this happens, all new arrivals should distribute equally to
habitats B1 and B2 until the population has been completed
distributed. The stable distribution will have individuals that
experience equal values in both habitats but there will be a higher
density of competitors in habitat B1 than in B2 (d1 > d2).
This form of the IFD has been called habitat matching (e.g.,
Pulliam & Caraco 1984). Another way to express this prediction is to
say that the proportion of individuals in a habitat should match the
proportion of resources provided by that habitat, or
FURTHER READING
Davies et al. (2012) provides an excellent and easy-to-read
introduction to behavioral ecology. More about foraging theory can
be obtained by reading Dave Stephens and John Krebs’ (1986) now
classic book and its more recent multi-authored follow-up by
Stephens et al. (2007). Those who wish to know more about games of
foraging should read Giraldeau and Dubois’ (2008) more recent
chapter on social foraging. For those interested in more general
game theory, Geof Parker’s (1984) excellent chapter as well as John
Maynard Smith’s (1982) book are two important sources while Lee
Dugatkin and Kern Reeve (1998) provide an up-to-date view of the
many applications of game theory in animal behavior. To explore the
relevance of producer–scrounger games to natural resource
havesting and public health see Giraldeau et al. (2017). For exploring
the interaction between functional and mechanistic approaches
students should consider Sara Shettleworth’s (2010) excellent book
and Reuven Dukas’ (1998) multi-authored book on cognitive ecology.
REFERENCES
Arak, A. 1988. Callers and satellites in the natterjack toad:
evolutionarily stable decision rules. Animal Behaviour, 36, 416–
32.
Barnard, C.J. 1984. Producers and Scroungers: Strategies of
Exploitation and Parasitism. London: Croom Helm.
Barnard, C.J. & Sibly, R.M. 1981. Producers and scroungers: a
general model and its application to captive flocks of house
sparrows. Animal Behaviour, 29, 543–50.
Beauchamp, G. 2000. Learning rules for social foragers: Implications
for the producer-scrounger game and ideal free distribution
theory. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 207, 21–35.
Bijleveld, A.I., Van Gils, J.A., Jouta, J.A. & Piersma, T. 2015. Benefits
of foraging in small groups: An experimental study on public
information use in red knots Calidris canutus. Behavioural
Processes, 117, 74–81.
Brockmann, H.J., Grafen, A. & Dawkins, R. 1979. Evolutionarily
stable nesting strategy in a digger wasp. Journal of Theoretical
Biology, 77, 473–96.
Cade, W. 1978. Of cricket song and sex. Natural History, 87, 64–72.
Davies, N.B., Krebs, J.R. & West, S.A. 2012. An Introduction to
Behavioural Ecology. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Dugatkin, L.A. & Reeve, H.K. 1998. Game Theory and Animal
Behavior. New York: Oxford University Press.
Dukas, R. 1998. Cognitive Ecology: The Evolutionary Ecology of
Information Processing and Decision Making. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Fretwell, S.D. 1972. Populations in a Seasonal Environment.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Getty, T. 2002. The discriminating babbler meets the optimal diet
hawk. Animal Behaviour, 63, 397–402.
Getty, T. & Krebs, J.R. 1985. Lagging partial preferences for cryptic
prey: a signal detection analysis of great tit foraging. American
Naturalist, 125, 39–60.
Giraldeau, L.-A. & Beauchamp, G. 1999. Food exploitation: searching
for the optimal joining policy. Trends in Ecolology and Evolution,
14, 102–6.
Giraldeau, L.-A. & Caraco, T. 2000. Social Foraging Theory.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Giraldeau, L.-A. & Dubois, F. 2008. Social foraging and the study of
exploitive behaviour. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 38, 59–
104.
Giraldeau, L.-A., Heeb, P. & Kosfeld, M. (eds). 2017. Investors and
Exploiters in Ecology and Economics: Principles and
Applications. Strüngmann Forum Reports Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Giraldeau, L.-A. & Kramer, D.L. 1982. The marginal value theorem: a
quantitative test using load size variation in a central place forager
the eastern chipmunk, Tamias striatus. Animal Behaviour, 30,
1036–42.
Giraldeau, L.-A., Kramer, D.L., Deslandes, I. & Lair, H. 1994. The
effect of competitors and distance on central place foraging in
eastern chipmunks, Tamias striatus. Animal Behaviour, 47, 621–
32.
Giraldeau, L.-A. & Livoreil, B. 1998. Game theory and social foraging.
In: L.A. Dugatkin & H.K. Reeve. (eds.), Game Theory and Animal
Behavior, pp. 16–37. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gould, S.J.&. & Lewontin, R.C. 1979. The spandrels of San Marco
and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist
programme. Proceeding of the Royal Society London B, 205,
581–98.
Gross, M.R. 1985. Disruptive selection for alternative life histories in
salmon. Nature, 313, 47–48.
Harper, D.G.C. 1982. Competitive foraging in mallards: “ideal free”
ducks. Animal Behaviour, 30, 575–84.
Kennedy, M. & Gray, R.D. 1993. Can ecological theory predict the
distribution of foraging animals? A critical evaluation of
experiments on the ideal free distribution. Oikos, 68, 158–66.
Krebs, J.R. 1978. Optimal foraging: Decision rules for predators. In:
J.R. Krebs & N.B. Davies. (eds.), Behavioural Ecology: An
Evolutionary Approach, pp. 23–63. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Krebs, J.R., Erichsen, J.T., Webber, M.I. & Charnov, E.L. 1977.
Optimal prey-selection by the great tit (Parus major). Animal
Behaviour, 25, 30–8.
MacArthur, R.H. & Pianka, E.R. 1966. On optimal use of a patchy
environment. American Naturalist, 100, 603–9.
Maynard Smith, J. 1982. Evolution and the Theory of Games.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Maynard Smith, J. & Price, G.R. 1973. The logic of animal conflict.
Nature, 246, 15–18.
McAleer, K. & Giraldeau, L.-A. 2006. Testing central place foraging
in eastern chimunks, Tamias striatus, by altering loading
functions. Animal Behaviour, 71, 1447–53.
Milinski, M. & Parker, G.A. 1991. Competition for resources. In: J.R.
Krebs & N.B. Davies. (eds.), Behavioural Ecology: An
Evolutionary Approach, pp. 137–68. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Morand-Ferron, J. & Giraldeau, L.-A. 2010. Learning behaviorally
stable solutions to producer-scrounger games. Behavioral
Ecology, 21, 343–8.
Nonacs, P. 2001. State dependent behavior and the Marginal Value
Theorem. Behavioral Ecology, 12, 71–83.
Oudman, T., Onrust, J., De Fouw, J., Spaans, B., Piersma, T. & Van
Gils, J.A. 2014. Digestive capacity and toxicity cause mixed diets
in red knots that maximize intake rate. American Naturalist, 183,
650–9.
Parker, G.A. 1984. Evolutionary stable strategies. In: J.R. Krebs &
N.B. Davies. (eds.), Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary
Approach, pp. 30–61. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Piersma, T. & Van Gils, J.A. 2011. The Flexible Phenotype. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Pulliam, R.H. & Caraco, T. 1984. Living in groups: Is there an
optimal group size? In: J.R. Krebs & N.B. Davies. (eds.),
Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach, pp. 122–147.
Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Schmid-Hampel, P., Kacelnik, A. & Houston, A.I. 1985. Honeybees
maximise efficiency by not filling their crop. Behavioral Ecology
and Sociobiology, 17, 61–6.
Shettleworth, S.J. 1998. Cognition, Evolution, and Behavior. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Shettleworth, S.J. 2010. Cognition, Evolution, and Behavior, 2nd ed.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Sih, A. & Christensen, B. 2001. Optimal diet theory: when does it
work, and when and why does it fail? Animal Behaviour, 61, 379–
90.
Stephens, D.W., Brown, J.S. & Ydenberg, R.C. 2007. Foraging:
Behavior and Ecology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Stephens, D.W. & Krebs, J.R. 1986. Foraging Theory. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Sutherland, W.J. 1996. Predicting the consequences of habitat loss
for migratory populations. Preceedings of the Royal Society of
London, Series B, 263, 1325–7.
Tregenza, T. 1995. Building on the ideal free distribution. Advances
in Ecological Research, 26, 253–307.
Van Gils, J.A., Spaans, B., Dekinga, A. & Piersma, T. 2006. Foraging
in a tidally structured environment by red knots (Calidris
canutus): ideal, but not free. Ecology, 87, 1189–1202.
Williams, G.C. 1966. Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
12
mate choice, mating systems, and sexual
selection
ANDERS PAPE MØLLER
INTRODUCTION
Male crickets Gryllus integer sing to attract females but thereby
run the risk of being parasitized by tachinid flies that are also
attracted to the calls (Cade 1975). Similarly, foxes Vulpes vulpes
prey on peacocks Pavo cristatus that are likely to be easier to
catch because of their cumbersome ornamentation, with
exaggerated feathers that weigh more than 1 kg and, when wet
after a shower, more than 3 kg (Petrie 1992). Why do females not
pay a similar cost? How can such apparently maladaptive traits
that reduce the probability of survival evolve and be maintained?
Charles Darwin developed the theory of sexual selection to
account specifically for the evolution and the maintenance of
exaggerated traits that do not benefit the individual in terms of
survival prospects. Many characters, such as the antlers of deer,
the train of the peacock, the calls of frogs and crickets, and the
exaggerated body size of one sex but not the other in the gorilla
Gorilla gorilla, can be attributed to the effects of sexual selection.
This chapter starts with a discussion of sexual selection followed
by a definition of mating systems and their determinants. Next, I
describe male–male competition and its consequences, analyze
female choice and the adaptive and nonadaptive bases for mate
choice, and briefly discuss evolutionary conflicts between the
sexes and their consequences. I then investigate the cost of
secondary sexual characters and its ecological and evolutionary
consequences and discuss the reasons for the presence of
multiple secondary sexual characters and their significance. In
the final part, I analyze sex ratio theory and how it relates to
sexual selection.
Sexual Selection
Sexual selection is a result of nonrandom variance in mating success
in one or both sexes. It is important to note that males (or females)
may vary in mating success for simple stochastic reasons: for
example, because of random rates of encounter with individuals of
the other sex, and because of a finite number of individuals in the
local neighborhood. Nonrandom variation in mating success
(hereafter called variation in mating success) may result in the
evolution of exaggerated traits when there is a quantitative genetic
basis (several genes with additive effects on the expression of a trait)
for such traits and when individuals with more extreme phenotypes
enjoy increased mating success.
Sexual selection differs from natural selection in terms of the kinds
of characters that can be attributed to the two processes of sexual
selection (intrasexual selection, usually male–male competition,
and intersexual selection, usually female mate choice) and,
therefore, in terms of the effects of the two kinds of processes on the
relative importance of survival and mate selection. While natural
selection results in the evolution of traits that are beneficial in terms
of survival, sexual selection is generally detrimental to the survival of
individuals. The reason for this effect is that traits that become
exaggerated by sexual selection may progress beyond the optimum
under natural selection, because of the mating advantages that they
confer. However, phenotypic traits can become immensely
exaggerated and cumbersome to the extent that males suffer
dramatic reductions in survival prospects; this process of
exaggeration will continue as long as some males are more than
compensated for the costs by advantages in terms of mating success.
Why is sexual selection important? Sexual selection accounts for
most differences in phenotype between males and females, and an
understanding of any phenomenon that can be attributed to
differences between the sexes among reproducing adults can only be
achieved by considering sexual selection. Since sexual selection
usually affects males and females differentially, ecological questions
such as the distribution of males and females can also only be
understood by considering sexual selection. Sexual selection also has
profound effects on the mortality rates of the two sexes, the
stochastic component of population fluctuations in the numbers of
individuals of the two sexes, the probability of and variance in
successful reproduction, and hence the likelihood of survival of a
population. Finally, most aspects of life among adult humans differ
between men and women, and we can only understand such
differences and the social, psychological, and medical problems that
they cause by considering sexual selection. Thus, we cannot
understand ecology, life-history theory, or human existence without
considering sex and sexual selection.
Mating Systems
Mating system is the label used for describing the way in which
males and females are distributed in reproductive units, and the
consequences of this distribution for reproductive behavior and
parental care. Why are some species polygynous (one male, several
females), whereas others are polyandrous (one female, several
males)? Why do females in most mating systems provide parental
care whereas males less frequently do so? Before answering these
questions we have to remember that a mating system is more than
meets the eye. Although a monogamous mating system is
described as a reproductive relationship between a single male and a
single female, sexual relationships between a “monogamous” female
and other males may render the term “monogamy” anomalous. Great
advances during the last 15 years in the study of parentage as a result
of the introduction of molecular genetic analyses have clearly
demonstrated that social and genetic mating systems are sometimes
not at all congruent. This superimposition of social and genetic
mating systems can most readily be resolved by considering that
sexual selection is a sequence of selection events starting from the
acquisition of a social mate, time required for acquiring and
processing these mates, followed by copulation, fertilization,
abortion, infanticide, parental care, and differential parental
investment (Figure 12.1). Intraspecific variation in each of the
variables in Figure 12.1 may be associated with the expression of
male secondary sexual characters. For example, attractive peacocks
with extravagant trains have shorter search time, take shorter time to
handle a female, and thus have a shorter mate processing time. This
results in such males having more copulation partners and hence
higher fecundity. Such attractive males cause females to invest
differentially in offspring, which increases fecundity per mate, again
increasing total fecundity. Since attractive peacocks also have lower
mortality, total fitness is presumably greater for the most attractive
males. Thus a thorough description of the mating system requires
quantification of components of sexual selection at these different
sequential stages and their interactions.
Intrasexual Selection
Multiple Ornaments
The previous sections have generally dealt with sexual signaling for a
single phenotypic character. However, in real cases of signaling,
individuals often simultaneously exhibit many different kinds of
secondary sexual characters, such as exaggerated morphological
traits, colors, and vocalizations. The evolution and maintenance of
such multiple signals need to be explained. Candolin (2005)
reviewed the literature on multiple ornamentation focusing on the
benefits of multiple choice, but also on the information content of
the mate choice of the cues. The evolution of multiple characters can
derive from the following.
Sex Ratios
Why are equally many males and females born in most species?
Ronald Fisher (1930) suggested that an equal sex ratio would be
advantageous to an individual because any deviation from this ratio
on average would result in the production of fewer grandparental
offspring. This view of Fisher’s sex ratio theory is based on the
premise that sons and daughters cost the same, whereas the sex ratio
in fact should be based on the combined cost of sons versus
daughters. Deviations from these predicted patterns of equal sex
ratios occur when siblings mate with each other, in which case sex
ratios are generally biased strongly toward daughters.
Adaptive variation in sex ratio has attracted considerable attention
recently, particularly because of its relationship with sexual
selection. If males are especially sexually attractive for genetic
reasons, male offspring of such sires should enjoy a disproportionate
mating success compared with the average male in the population.
Females mated to such attractive males should therefore produce
relatively more sons than daughters. Indeed, attractive males of
several species seem to have mates that produce more sons than
daughters. Nancy Burley (1981), in a classic study of the zebra finch,
showed that when males became more attractive by simple
experimental manipulation of the color of their plastic leg rings, this
affected the sex ratio of their offspring. Female zebra finches
preferred males with red rings and avoided males with green rings.
Females mated to red-ringed males produced significantly more sons
than did females mated to green-ringed males, as predicted by
theory (Figure 12.6). Subsequent studies of several other species
have provided similar evidence for adaptive adjustment of sex ratio
in response to the phenotype of the sire, although experimental
studies testing this prediction are still the exception.
Figure 12.6 Sex ratio of zebra finches Taeniopygia guttata in
relation to the color of plastic leg rings of their mates, where red
rings are attractive and green rings are unattractive. (Adapted from
Burley 1981).
Numerous studies have demonstrated evidence of female condition
being related to sex ratio of their offspring. If sons are more costly to
produce than daughters and if female condition changes consistently
with age, we should expect sex ratios to change similarly. Many
studies have shown a preponderance of sons being produced by
dominant females or by females in prime condition. Likewise,
senescence seems to be associated with a sex ratio bias toward
daughters.
Studies of sex ratios in humans provide equally striking effects of
environmental conditions. For example, studies at the US West Point
military academy of the sex ratio of cadets in relation to military rank
show a preponderance of sons produced by women married to high-
ranking officers. A similar result has been reported for the sex ratio
of the offspring of US presidents, vice presidents, and cabinet
secretaries. Among the US executive branch, a staggering 70% of
sons have been recorded during the first 20 presidents, falling to
53% during the following 20 presidents, compared with the null
expectation of 50% recorded in human populations in general
(Betzig & Weber 1995). Similarly, many different studies have
recorded changes in sex ratios associated with resource abundance
and other indicators of environmental conditions. For example, in
rural Portugal during the period 1671–1720 the sex ratio was 112.1
sons per 100 daughters in good harvest years but only 90.7 sons per
100 daughters in poor harvest years (Trivers 1985). Twins are more
costly to produce than two singletons, and we should thus expect the
sex ratio of twins to be biased toward daughters. In fact, the sex ratio
of human twins is 3% lower than that of singletons (Trivers 1985). If
this deviation from an equal sex ratio is adaptive, we should expect
that male twins have disproportionately lower reproductive success
than female twins. Indeed, both male and female twins have lower
reproductive success than singletons, based on data from eighteenth-
and nineteenth-century Mormons in the USA. However, the
reduction in reproductive success among male twins is twice as large
as that for female twins, consistent with the prediction (Trivers
1985). More recently, sex ratio theory has been invoked to explain
variation in sex ratios in societies with enforced family planning such
as China. Families generally favor sons over daughters when a one-
child policy is enforced, and this happens as a consequence of
selective abortion, infanticide, and other mechanisms. Surprisingly,
in families with more than a single child there are dramatic changes
in sex ratios of the second and later children, depending on the sex
ratio of the first child (Low 2000). If the first child is a son, the sex
ratio of any subsequent children is biased toward daughters; the
reverse situation occurs when the first child is a daughter. These
studies, and many others reviewed by Trivers (1985), suggest that
human sex ratios are closely linked to sexual selection and the
advantages that accrue to women in terms of future reproductive
potential through the sex of their offspring.
FURTHER READING
Andersson (1994) provides a general overview of sexual selection
theory and summarizes the empirical evidence. Monographs on
sexual selection in particular species include Houde (1997) on the
guppy, Møller (1994) on the barn swallow, and Ryan (1985) on the
túngara frog. Sex ratio theory is reviewed extensively by Trivers
(1985). Low (2000) provides an extensive treatise on the
consequences of sexual selection for humans. The consequences of
sexual selection for conservation are described by Møller (2000) and
Wilson et al. (1998).
Methodological addendum: Many model systems have been
used repeatedly in order to investigate different predictors or other
factors that may reveal novel mechanisms or functions of behavioral
traits. Such repeated investigations can be evaluated using meta-
analyses, which basically represents the quantitative assessment of
multiple studies and their synthesis. Parker (2013) investigated over
1200 relationships between the effects of coloration on signalling
and other phenotypic traits in the blue tit Cyanistes caeruleus with
only 52 studies being suited to be included in a meta-analysis.
Mainly small effects with weak relationships were the outcome of
this meta-analysis. Romano et al. (2017a) conducted a similar
analysis of barn swallow behavior that showed many more
intermediate to large effects, demonstrating differences in intensity
of sexual selection among populations, consistent with a role of
sexual selection in divergence and speciation. Romano et al. (2017b)
showed consistent and significant effects of the expression of
viability being linked to small to intermediate effects. These findings
open up novel ways to investigate behavior and to quantitatively
assess such patterns of behavior. The links between behaviour,
ecology, and evolution are all open for these novel ways of
quantitative analysis.
REFERENCES
Andersson, M. 1994. Sexual Selection. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Arak, A. 1988a. Callers and satellites in the natterjack toad:
evolutionarily stable decision rules. Animal Behaviour, 36, 416–
32.
Arak, A. 1988b. Sexual dimorphism in body size: & model and & test.
Evolution, 42, 820–5.
Arnqvist, G. 1989. Sexual selection in the water strider: the function,
mechanism of selection and heritability of & male grasping organ.
Oikos, 56, 344–50.
Arnqvist, G. 1992. Spatial variation in selective regimes: sexual
selection in the water strider. Gerris odontogaster. Evolution, 46,
914–29.
Arnqvist, G. 1998. Comparative evidence for the evolution of
genitalia by sexual selection. Nature, 393, 784–8.
Bakker, T.C.M., Kunzler, R. & Mazzi, K. 1999. Condition-related
mate choice in sticklebacks. Nature, 401, 234.
Bakker, T.C.M. & Pomiankowski, A. 1995. The genetic basis of female
mate preferences. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 8, 129–81.
Bastien, B., Farley, G., Ga, F., Malin, J.S., et al. 2019. The waiting
and mating game. Condition-dependent mate sampling in female
gray tree frogs (Hyla versicolor). Frontiers in Ecology, 2018,
00140.
Bateman, A.J. 1948. Intra-sexual selection in Drosophila. Heredity,
2, 349–68.
Bensch, S. & Hasselquist, D. 1992. Evidence for active female choice
in & polygynous warbler. Animal Behaviour, 44, 301–12.
Berglund, A., Rosenqvist, G. & Svensson, I. 1989. Reproductive
success of females limited by males in two pipefish species.
American Naturalist, 133, 506–16.
Bessa-Gomes, C., Legendre, S., Clobert, J. & Møller, A.P. 2003.
Modeling mating patterns given mutual mate choice: the
importance of individual mating preferences and mating system.
Journal of Biological Systematics, 11, 205–19.
Betzig, L.L. & Weber, S. 1995. Presidents preferred sons. Politics and
the Life Sciences, 14, 61–4.
Bro-Jørgensen, J. 2007. The intensity of sexual selection predicts
weapon size in bovids. Evolution, 61, 1316–26.
Burley, N. 1981. Sex ratio manipulation and selection for
attractiveness. Science, 211, 721–2.
Burley, N. 1986. Sexual selection for aesthetic traits in species with
biparental care. American Naturalist, 127, 415–45.
Cade, W.H. 1975. Acoustically orienting parasitoids: fly phonotaxis to
cricket song. Science, 190, 1312–3.
Candolin, U. 2005. The use of multiple cues in mate choice.
Biological Reviews, 78, 575–95.
Clutton-Brock, T.H. & Vincent, A.C.J. 1991. Sexual selection and the
potential reproductive rates of males and females. Nature, 351,
58–60.
Conner, J. 1988. Field measurements of natural and sexual selection
in the fungus beetle. Bolitotherus cornutus. Evolution, 42, 735–
49.
Conner, J. 1989. Density-dependent sexual selection in the fungus
beetle. Bolitotherus cornutus. Evolution, 43, 1378–86.
De Lope, F. & Møller, A.P. 1993. Female reproductive effort depends
on the degree of ornamentation of their mates. Evolution, 47,
1152–60.
Eberhard, W.G. 1996. Female Control: Sexual Selection by Cryptic
Female Choice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Emlen, S.T. & Oring, L.W. 1977. Ecology, sexual selection, and the
evolution of mating systems. Science, 197, 215–23.
Fisher, R.A. 1930. The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Folstad, I. & Karter, A.J. 1992. Parasites, bright males, and the
immunocompetence handicap. American Naturalist, 139, 603–
22.
Gil, D., Biard, C., Lacroix, A., Spottiswoode, C., et al. 2007. Yolk
androgens in birds: Development, coloniality and sexual
dichromatism. American Naturalist, 160, 802–19.
Gil, D., Graves, J.A., Hazon, N. & Wells, A. 1999. Male attractiveness
and differential testosterone investment in zebra finch eggs.
Science, 286, 126–8.
Hamilton, W.D. & Zuk, M. 1982. Heritable true fitness and bright
birds: a role for parasites? Science, 218, 384–87.
Hogan-Warburg, A.J. 1966. Social behavior of the ruff, Philomachus
pugnax (L.). Ardea, 54, 109–229.
Holland, B. & Rice, W.R. 1998. Chase-away sexual selection:
antagonistic seduction versus resistance. Evolution, 52, 1–7.
Holland, B. & Rice, W.R. 1999. Experimental removal of sexual
selection reverses intersexual antagonistic coevolution and
removes a reproductive load. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences USA, 96, 5083–88.
Houde, A.E. 1997. Sex, Color and Mate Choice in Guppies.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Janetos, A.C. 1980. Strategies for female mate choice: a theoretical
analysis. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 1, 107–12.
Jarman, P.J. 1989. On being thick-skinned: dermal shields in large
mammalian herbivores. Biological Journal of the Linnean
Society, 36, 169–91.
Jennions, M.D., Møller, A.P. & Petrie, M. 2001. Sexually selected
traits and adult survival: a meta-analysis of the phenotypic
relationship. Quarterly Review of Biology, 76, 3–36.
Jennions, M.D. & Petrie, M. 1997. Variation in mate choice and
mating preferences: A review of causes and consequences.
Biological Reviews, 72, 283–327.
Jennions, M.D. & Petrie, M. 2000. Why do females mate multiply? A
review of the genetic benefits. Biological Reviews, 75, 21–64.
Jukema, J. & Piersma, T. 2006. Permanent female mimics in a
lekking shorebird. Biology Letters, 2, 161–4.
Knapp, R.A. & Kovach, J.T. 1991. Courtship as an honea indicator of
male parental quality in the bicolor damselfish. Stegastes
partitus. Behavioral Ecology, 2, 295–300.
Kotiaho, J.S., Alatalo, R.V., Mappes, J. & Parri, S. 1999. Sexual
signalling and viability in & wolf spider (Hygrolycosa
rubrofasciata): measurements under laboratory and field
conditions. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 46, 123–8.
Küpper, C., Stocks, M., Risse, J.E., et al. 2016. A supergene
determines highly divergent male reproductive morphs in the ruff.
Nature Genetics, 48, 79–83.
Lamichhaney, L., Fan, G., Widemo, F., et al. 2015. Structural
genomic changes underlie alternative reproductive strategies in
the ruff (Philomachus pugnax). Nature Genetics, 48, 84–8.
Lank, D.B., Smith, C.M., Hanotte, O., Burke, T. & Cooke, F. 1995.
Genetic polymorphism for alternative mating behaviour in lekking
male ruff. Philomachus pugnax. Nature, 378, 59–62.
Little, A.C., Burt, D.M., Penton-Voak, I.S. & Perrett, D.I. 2001. Self-
perceived attractiveness influences human female preferences for
sexual dimorphism and symmetry in male faces. Proceedings of
the Royal Society of London Series B, 268, 39–44.
Low, B.S. 2000. Why Sex Matters. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Møller, A.P. 1994. Sexual Selection and the Barn Swallow. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Møller, A.P. 2000. Sexual selection and conservation. In: M. Gosling
& W.J. Sutherland (eds.), Behaviour and Conservation, pp. 172–
197. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Møller, A.P. & Alatalo, R.V. 1999. Good genes effects in sexual
selection. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London Series B,
266, 85–91.
Møller, A.P., Biard, C., Blount, J.D., et al. 2000. Carotenoid-
dependent signals: indicators of foraging efficiency,
immunocompetence or detoxification ability? Poultry and Avian
Biology Reviews, 11, 137–59.
Møller, A.P., Christe, P. & Lux, E. 1999. Parasite-mediated sexual
selection: effects of parasites and hoa immune function. Quarterly
Review of Biology, 74, 3–20.
Møller, A.P. & Cuervo, J.J. 2003. Asymmetry, size and sexual
selection: factors affecting heterogeneity in relationships between
asymmetry and sexual selection. In: M. Polak (ed.),
Developmental Instability, pp. 262–275. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Møller, A.P. & De Lope, F. 1994. Differential costs of a secondary
sexual character: an experimental tea of the handicap principle.
Evolution, 48, 1676–83.
Møller, A.P. & Jennions, M.D. 2001. How important are direct
fitness benefits of sexual selection? Naturwissenschaften, 88,
401–15.
Møller, A.P. & Legendre, S. 2001. Allee effect, sexual selection and
demographic stochasticity. Oikos, 92, 27–34.
Møller, A.P. & Pomiankowski, A. 1993. Why have birds got multiple
sexual ornaments? Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 32,
167–76.
Møller, A.P., Sorci, G. & Erritzoe, J. 1998. Sexual dimorphism in
immune defense. American Naturalist, 152, 605–19.
Møller, A.P. & Thornhill, R. 1998. Bilateral symmetry and sexual
selection: a meta-analysis. American Naturalist, 151, 174–92.
Orians, G.H. 1969. On the evolution of mating systems in birds and
mammals. American Naturalist, 103, 589–603.
Packer, C. 1983. Sexual dimorphism: the horns of African antelopes.
Science, 221, 1191–3.
Parker, T.H. 2013. What do we really know about the signalling role
of plumage colour in blue tits: A case study of impediments to
progress in evolutionary biology. Biological Reviews, 88, 511–36.
Petrie, M. 1992. Peacocks with low mating success are more likely to
suffer predation. Animal Behaviour, 44, 485–6.
Petrie, M., Schwabl, H., Brande-Lavridsen, N. & Burke, T. 2001. Sex
differences in avian yolk hormone levels. Nature, 412, 498–99.
Pribil, S. & Searcy, W.A. 2001. Experimental confirmation of the
polygyny threshold model for red-winged blackbirds. Proceedings
of the Royal Society of London Series B, 268, 1643–6.
Promislow, D.E.L., Montgomerie, R. & Martin, T.E. 1992. Mortality
costs of sexual dimorphism in birds. Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London Series B, 250, 143–50.
Promislow, D.E.L., Montgomerie, R. & Martin, T.E. 1994. Sexual
selection and survival in North American waterfowl. Evolution,
48, 2045–50.
Rice, W.R. 1996. Sexually antagonistic male adaptation triggered by
experimental arrest of female evolution. Nature, 361, 232–4.
Rice, W.R. 1998. Male fitness increases when females are eliminated
from the gene pool: Implications for the Y chromosome.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 95, 6217–
21.
Romano, A., Costanzo, A., Rubolini, D., Saino, N. & Møller, A.P.
2017a. Geographical and seasonal variation in the intensity of
sexual selection in the barn swallow Hirundo rustica: A meta-
analysis. Biological Reviews, 92, 1582–1600.
Romano, A., Saino, N. & Møller, A.P. 2017b. Viability and expression
of sexual ornaments in the barn swallow Hirundo rustica: A meta-
analysis. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 30, 1929–35.
Ryan, M.J. 1985. The Túngara Frog. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Ryan, M.J., Fox, J.H., Wilczynski, W. & Rand, A.S. 1990. Sexual
selection for sensory exploitation in the frog. Physalaemus
pustulosus. Nature, 343, 66–7.
Ryan, M.J. & Rand, A.S. 1993. Sexual selection and signal evolution:
the ghost of biases past. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society of London Series B, 340, 187–95.
Saino, N., Bolzern, A.M. & Møller, A.P. 1997. Immunocompetence,
ornamentation and viability of male barn swallows (Hirundo
rustica). Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA,
94, 549–52.
Sutherland, W.J. 1985. Chance can produce a sex difference in
variance in mating success and explain Bateman’s data. Animal
Behaviour, 33, 1349–52.
Thornhill, R. & Møller, A.P. 1998. The relative importance of size and
asymmetry in sexual selection. Behavioral Ecology, 9, 546–51.
Trivers, R.L. 1985. Social Evolution. Menlo Park, CA:
Benjamin/Cummings.
Van Rhijn, J.G. 1991. The Ruff. London: Poyser.
Verner, J. 1964. The evolution of polygamy in the long-billed marsh
wren. Evolution, 18, 252–61.
von Schants, T., Bensch, H., Grahn, M. et al.1999. Good genes,
oxidative stress and condition-dependent sexual signals.
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 266, 1–12.
Wedekind, C., Seebeck, T., Bettens, F. & Paepke, A.J. 1995. MHC-
dependent mate preferences in humans. Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London Series B, 260, 245–9.
Welch, A.M., Semlitsch, R.D. & Gerhardt, H.C. 1998. Call duration as
an indicator of genetic quality in male gray tree frogs. Science,
280, 1928–30.
Wilson, M. & Daly, M. 1985. Competitiveness, risk taking, and
violence: the young male syndrome. Ethology and Sociobiology,
6, 59–73.
Wilson, M., Daly, M. & Gordon, S. 1998. The evolved psychological
apparatus of human decision-making is one source of
environmental problems. In: T. Caro (ed.), Behavioral Ecology
and Conservation Biology, pp. 501–23. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Zuk, M. 1990. Reproductive strategies and sex differences in disease
susceptibility: an evolutionary viewpoint. Parasitology Today, 6,
231–3.
Zuk, M. & Kolluru, G.R. 1998. Exploitation of sexual signals by
predators and parasitoids. Quarterly Review of Biology, 73, 415–
438.
Zuk, M., Thornhill, R., Ligon, J.D., et al. 1990. The role of male
ornaments and courtship behavior in female mate choice of red
jungle fowl. American Naturalist, 136, 459–73.
13
Animal Personality, the Study of Individual
Behavioral Differences
DENIS RÉALE AND PIERRE-OLIVIER MONTIGLIO
INTRODUCTION
At the turn of the twenty-first century, the idea that social
networks comprise individuals has become one of the new pillars
of our contemporary societies. Every day, millions of people
commute singly listening to personalized radio programs or
engage in all-inclusive communication with their personal
electronic devices. Jogging has become one of the most popular
activities of urban populations. Some people spend hours
broadcasting their private lives on social networks, and several of
us are attracted by electronic devices whose names start with the
prefix “i.” The questions asked by scientists both reflect and
impact the trends of a society. It is thus not surprising to see the
interest that biological sciences have recently developed around
questions related to individuality. Indeed, the individual
phenomenon has started invading several fields of biology: we
speak of personalized medicine, we recognize the importance of
individuals for epidemiology, energetics, endocrinology, ecology,
and life history. Behavioral ecology has not been spared by the
trend: since the late 1990s studies on personality or temperament
have become a major topic in the field. It is now recognized that
animal personality research has built up bridges between
different fields of biology, ecology, and psychology, and is part of
the current trend in the development of integrative biology.
In this chapter we will review the main aspects related to the
recent trends in animal personality. Newcomers in animal
personality raise some questions about the field and its concepts.
Thus, we will first discuss terminological and other issues related
to personality. We then present a brief history, with an emphasis
on behavioral ecology. We next review the different sources of
consistent individual behavioral variation and describe the main
methodological advances in the field over the last few decades.
Finally, we will provide an overview of the role that animal
personality can play in several aspects of animals’ ecology.
Definition(s) of Personality
After two decades of debate, most biologists now agree with the
definition of personality as consistent individual differences in
behavioral traits over time and across situations (Dall et al. 2004;
Réale et al. 2007). In other words, it represents the repeatable
dimension of the variation of a behavioral trait in a population.
What does this mean exactly? Most traits vary, and this variation can
be explained by three main sources: differences among individuals,
differences within individuals, and measurement errors. If we
consider measurement errors to be negligible and randomly
distributed across all the measures, we are left with differences in the
measures among and within individuals. The first one constitutes
personality and can itself be decomposed into other components as
we will see below. Variation within individuals can mostly be
explained by plastic changes in the behavior resulting from changes
in internal or external conditions experienced by individuals during
the interval of our measures (Figure 13.1). Following that definition,
personality for an individual refers to how much his/her average
behavioral phenotype (or behavioral type) deviates from the
average value of that behavior in a population. For instance, some
individuals may be more aggressive, less shy, less active, more
voracious, or more impulsive than the average individual in the
population. (Figure 13.2).
Figure 13.1 Representation of personality differences or
individual behavioral consistency. Left hand side: there are
personality differences among individuals; the behavior of three
genotypes or individuals is measured in three environments (E1, E2,
E3; here environment can be replaced by time). Although each of
these genotypes exhibits some phenotypic plasticity or some
differences in the phenotype of the behavior with the environment,
the three genotypes differ consistently in the level of their
phenotypes across environments. They are said to show similar
reaction norms, and the relative value of an individual in one
environment can be predicted by its relative value in another
environment. Furthermore, each individual only shows one fraction
of the total phenotypic variation observed. Right hand side: absence
of personality differences among individuals. In this case the
phenotypic value of an individual in one environment is
unpredictable and all individuals show the whole range of variation
observed in the population for that behavior. These two examples
represent the two extreme cases and in personality differences are
observed somewhere along the gradient between these two extremes
cases. From Réale & Dingemanse 2010.
Figure 13.2 Illustration of the distribution (a) and of the range of
variation (b–f) in a trait among individuals depending on its
repeatability. Here we simulated data for 12 individuals and 50
measurements per individual for a trait with repeatability values of
0, 0.1, 0.25, 0.5, and 0.75 (b–f, respectively). When repeatability is
very low (e.g., 0.1) phenotypic values largely overlap among
individuals. In contrast, very high repeatability corresponds to no
overlap of values among individuals (high among-individual
consistent differences). Most repeatability estimates for behavioral
traits range between 0.2 and 0.5 (Bell et al. 2009), which means that
a lot of them will show significant overlap in the data points among
individuals, showing that the consistency of ranks is not as obvious
as one would expect.
The definition of personality provided above solves several questions
about the phenomenon. First, it shows that it is important to
distinguish the emergence of consistent differences in the behavior of
groups, populations, or species, from the idea that individuals are
consistent (i.e., stable) in their behavior over time, which is clearly
the property of a given individual. It is central to understanding that
these two concepts are not equivalent. Individual consistency in
behavior is not a prerequisite for the existence of consistent
differences in behavior among individuals. For example, all
individuals could plastically change their behavior in response to
changes in their environment, while still preserving their behavioral
differences (Figure 13.1). We will detail how these concepts are
linked later in this chapter.
Considering personality as the repeatable dimension of a behavioral
trait, has also the benefit of separating the notion of personality from
the notion of behavior. Hence, under this definition, personality is a
feature of a behavioral trait in a population, and there is no such
thing as a “personality trait.” Furthermore, although students of
personality have restricted their investigation to five main traits,
personality can be studied on any type of behavior (Réale et al.
2007). Also, using the term personality without reference to a
particular behavioral trait is probably too vague to be informative.
For instance, asking whether personality and cognition should be
linked does not make much sense because there could be a
personality dimension in cognitive traits. We should rather ask
whether and why some specific behavioral traits should be linked to
specific cognitive traits.
The debate over the terminology of personality has mainly been
caused by the plethora of terms that exist around the notion of
personality, such as temperament, behavioral types, coping styles, or
behavioral syndromes (Gosling 2001; Réale et al. 2007). There are a
few nuances among these terms. For example, psychologists
differentiate temperament—the inherited and biological basis for
behavioral tendencies appearing early in life and serving as a
foundation for personality—from personality itself, which is built on
the experiences (physical, cultural…) accumulated by the individual
during its whole life (Gosling 2008). However, from a biological
standpoint there is no need to separate temperament from
personality, particularly if one is interested in the evolutionary and
ecological consequences of this phenomenon. People working on the
behavioral and neurophysiological reaction of animals in response to
a stressful situation talk about coping styles (Koolhaas et al. 1999).
People interested in examining the associations among behavioral
traits at the phenotypic or genetic level mostly refer to behavioral
syndromes (Sih et al. 2004).
The definition of personality given above also shows that the
correlation among traits into a behavioral syndrome is not a
necessary condition to define personality. The notion of behavioral
syndrome is a key biological concept and is important for the study
of animal personality. However, including the notion of syndrome in
the definition of personality generates a problem if people take that
definition too strictly and reject the existence of personality based on
this criterion. Researchers should focus on whether behavioral traits
are correlated or not, and why. It is, thus, more profitable for the
study of personality to consider that personality could be found in a
set of behavioral traits, these traits being correlated to a greater or
lesser extent.
REFERENCES
Aplin, L.M., Farine, D., Morand-Ferron, J., Cole, E.F., Cockburn, A.
& Sheldon, B.C. 2013. Individual personalities predict social
behaviour in wild networks of great tits (Parus major). Ecology
Letters, 16, 1365–1372.
Armitage, K.B. 1986. Individuality, sociability, and reproductive
success in yellow-bellied marmots. Ecology, 67, 1186–1193.
Baugh, A.T., Schaper, S.V., Hau, M., Cockrem, J.F., De Goede, P. &
Van Oers, K. 2012. Corticosterone responses differ between lines
of great tits (Parus major) selected for divergent personalities.
General and Comparative Endocrinology, 175, 488–494.
Bekoff, M. 1977. Mammalian dispersal and the ontogeny of
individual behavioral phenotypes. American Naturalist, 111, 715–
732.
Bell, A.M., Hankison, S.J. & Laskowski, K.L. 2009. The repeatability
of behaviour: a meta-analysis. Animal Behaviour, 77, 771–783.
Bergmüller, R. & Taborsky, M. 2010. Animal personality due to
social niche specialisation. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 25,
504–511.
Best, E.C., Blomberg, S.P. & Goldizen, A.W. 2015. Shy female
kangaroos seek safety in numbers and have fewer preferred
friendships. Behavioral Ecology, 26, 639–646.
Biro, P.A. & Stamps, J.A. 2008. Are animal personality traits linked
to life-history productivity? Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 23,
361–368.
Boake, C.R. 1989. Repeatability: its role in evolutionary studies of
mating behavior. Evolutionary Ecology, 3, 173–182.
Bonnot, N., Verheyden, H., Blanchard, P., et al. 2015. Interindividual
variability in habitat use: evidence for a risk management
syndrome in roe deer? Behavioral Ecology, 26, 105–114.
Boon, A.K., Réale, D. & Boutin, S. 2008. Personality, habitat use, and
their consequences for survival in North American red squirrels.
Tamiasciurus hudsonicus. Oikos, 117, 1321–1328.
Boyer, N., Réale, D., Marmet, J., Pisanu, B. & Chapuis, J.-L. 2010.
Personality, space use and tick load in an introduced population
of Siberian chipmunks. Tamias sibiricus. Journal of Animal
Ecology, 79, 538–547.
Budaev, S.V. 1999. “Personality” in the guppy (Poecilia reticulata): A
correlational study of exploratory behavior and social tendency.
Journal of Comparative Psychology, 111, 399–411.
Carere, C., Drent, P.J., Koolhaas, J.M. & Groothuis, T.G.G. 2005.
Epigenetic effects on personality traits: early food provisioning
and sibling competition. Behaviour, 132, 1329–1355.
Champagne, F.A., Weaver, I.C.G., Diorio, J., Dymov, S., Szyf, M. &
Meaney, M.J. 2006. Maternal care associated with methylation of
the estrogen receptor-α1b promoter and estrogen receptor-α
expression in the medial preoptic area of female offspring.
Endocrinology, 147, 2909–2915.
Chitty, D. 1967. The natural selection of self-regulatory behaviour in
animal populations. Proceeding of the Ecological Society of
Australia, 2, 51–78.
Ciuti, S., Muhly, T.B., Paton, D.G., et al. 2012. Human selection of elk
behavioural traits in a landscape of fear Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London B, 279, 4407–4416.
Clark, A.B. & Ehlinger, T.J. 1987. Pattern and adaptation in
individual behavioral differences. Perspectives in Ethology, 7, 1–
47.
Coppens, C.M., De Boer, S.F. & Koolhaas, J.M. 2010. Coping styles
and behavioural flexibility: towards underlying mechanisms.
Philosophical transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 365,
4021–4028.
Costa, P.T., Jr. & McCrae, R.R. 1992. NEO PI-R professional
manual. Odessa, FL: Psychological Assessment Resources, Inc.
Cote, J. & Clobert, J. 2007. Social personalities influence natal
dispersal in a lizard. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London
B, 274, 383–390.
Cote, J., Clobert, J., Brodin, T., Fogarty, S. & Sih, A. 2010.
Personality-dependent dispersal: characterization, ontogeny and
consequences for spatially structured populations. Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 365, 4065–4076.
Cote, J., Fogarty, S. & Sih, A. 2012. Individual sociability and
choosiness between shoal types. Animal Behaviour, 83, 1469–
1476.
Croft, D.P., Krause, J., Darden, S.K., et al. 2009. Behavioural trait
assortment in a social network: patterns and implications.
Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 63(10), 1495–1503.
Dall, S.R.X., Houston, A.I. & McNamara, J.M. 2004. The behavioural
ecology of personality: consistent individual differences from an
adaptive perspective. Ecology Letters, 7, 734–739.
Darwin, C. 1859. On the origin of species by means of natural
selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle
for life, First ed. London: John Murray.
Dingemanse, N.J., Both, C., Van Noordwijk, A.J., Rutten, A.L. &
Drent, P.J. 2003. Natal dispersal and personalities in great tits
(Parus major). Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B,
270, 741–747.
Dingemanse, N.J. & Dochtermann, N.A. 2012. Quantifying
individual variation in behaviour: mixed-effect modelling
approaches. Journal of Animal Ecology, 82, 39–54.
Dingemanse, N.J., Dochtermann, N.A. & Nakagawa, S. 2012.
Defining behavioural syndromes and the role of “syndrome
deviation” in understanding their evolution. Behavioral Ecology
and Sociobiology, 66, 1543–1548.
Dingemanse, N.J., Kazem, A.J.N., Réale, D. & Wright, J. 2010.
Behavioural reaction norms: animal personality meets individual
plasticity. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 25, 81–89.
Dingemanse, N.J. & Réale, D. 2013. What is the evidence for natural
selection maintaining animal personality variation? In: C. Carere
& D. Maestripieri (eds.), Animal Personalities: Behavior,
Physiology and Evolution. Chicago: Univesity of Chicago Press.
Drent, P.J., Oers, K.V. & Noordwijk, A.J.V. 2003. Realized
heritability of personalities in the great tit (Parus major).
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 270, 45–51.
Duckworth, R.A. & Badyaev, A.V. 2007. Coupling of dispersal and
aggression facilitates the rapid range expansion of a passerine
bird. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, USA, 104,
15017–15022.
Dumont, F. 2010. A History of Personality Psychology: Theory,
Science, and Research from Hellenism to the Twenty-first
Century. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Gosling, S.D. 2001. From mice to men: what can we learn about
personality from animal research? Psychological Bulletin, 127,
45–86.
Gosling, S.D. 2008. Personality in non-human animals. Social and
Personality Psychology Compass, 2, 985–1001.
Groothuis, T.G.G. & Carere, C. 2005. Avian personalities:
characterization and epigenesis. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral
Reviews, 29, 137–150.
Huntingford, F.A. 1976. A comparison of the reaction of sticklebacks
in different reproductive conditions towards conspecifics and
predators. Animal Behaviour, 24, 694–697.
Johnson, K.V.A., Aplin, L., Cole, E.F., Farine, D.R., Firth, J., Patrick,
S.M. & Sheldon, B.C. 2017. Male great tits assort by personality
during the breeding season. Animal Behaviour, 128, 21–32.
Johnson, J. C. & Sih, A. 2005. Precopulatory sexual cannibalism in
fishing spiders (Dolomedes triton): a role for behavioral
syndromes. Behavior Ecology and Sociobiology, 58, 390–396.
Koolhaas, J.M., De Boer, S.F., Buwalda, B. & Van Reenen, K. 2007.
Individual variation in coping with stress: A multidimensional
approach of ultimate and proximate mechanisms. Brain,
Behavior and Evolution, 70(4), 218–226.
Koolhaas, J.M., Korte, S.M., De Boer, S.F., et al. 1999. Coping styles
in animals: current status in behavior and stress-physiology
Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 23, 925–935.
Kralj-Fišer, S., Sanguino Mostajo, G.A., Preik, O., Pekár, S. &
Schneider, J.M. 2013. Assortative mating by aggressiveness type
in orb weaving spiders. Behavioral Ecology, 24, 824–831.
Krause, J., James, R. & Croft, D.P. 2010. Personality in the context of
social networks. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society
of London B, 365, 4099–4106.
Krebs, J.R., MacRoberts, M.H. & Cullen, M. 1972. Flocking and
feeding in the great tit Parus major – an experimental study. Ibis,
114, 507–530.
Lucon-Xiccatoa, T., Bisazz, A. & Pilastro, A. 2019. Exploratory
behaviour covaries with preference for unfamiliar males in female
guppies. Animal Behaviour, 155, 217–224.
Martin, J.G.A., Nussey, D.H., Wilson, A.J. & Réale, D. 2011.
Measuring individual differences in reaction norms in field and
experimental studies: a power analysis of random regression
models. Methods in Ecology and Evolution, 2, 362–374.
McDonald, G.C., Spurgin, L.G., Fairfield, E.A., Richardson, D.S. &
Pizzari, T. 2017. Pre‐and postcopulatory sexual selection favor
aggressive, young males in polyandrous groups of red junglefowl.
Evolution, 71, 1653–1669.
Meffert, L.M., Hicks, S.K. & Regan, J.L. 2002. Nonadditive genetic
effects in animal behavior. American Naturalist, 160, S198 – 213.
Michelena, P., Sibbald, A.M., Erhard, H.W. & McLeod, J.E. 2009.
Effects of group size and personality on social foraging: the
distribution of sheep across patches. Behavioral Ecology, 20,
145–152.
Moiron, M., Laskowski, K.L. & Niemelä, P.T. 2019. Individual
differences in behaviour explain variation in survival: a meta-
analysis. Ecology Letters, 23, 399–408.
Montiglio, P.-O., Dammhahn, M., Messier, G.D. & Réale, D. 2018a.
The pace-of-life syndrome revisited: the role of ecological
conditions and natural history on the slow-fast continuum.
Behavioral Ecologyt Sociobiology, 72, 116.
Montiglio, P.O., Ferrari, C. & Réale, D. 2013. Social niche
specialization under constraints: personality, social interactions
and environmental heterogeneity. Philosophical Transactions of
the Royal Society of London B, 368, 20120343–20120343.
Montiglio, P.O., Garant, D., Pelletier, F. & Réale, D. 2014. Intra-
individual variability in fecal cortisol metabolites varies with
lifetime exploration and reproductive life history in eastern
chipmunks (Tamias striatus). Behavioral Ecology and
Sociobiology, 69, 1–11.
Montiglio, P.O., McGlothlin, J.W. & Farine, D.R. 2018b. Social
structure modulates the evolutionary consequences of social
plasticity: a social network perspective on interacting phenotypes.
Ecology and evolution, 8, 1451–1464.
Montiglio, P.-O., Wey, T., Chang, A.T., Fogarty, S. & Sih, A. 2016.
Multiple mating reveals complex patterns of assortative mating by
personality and body size. Journal of Animal Ecology, 85, 125–
135.
Mutzel, A., Dingemanse, N.J., Araya-Ajoy, Y.G. & Kempenaers, B.
2013. Parental provisioning behaviour plays a key role in linking
personality with reproductive success. Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London B, 280, 20131019.
Myers, J.H. & Krebs, C.J. 1971. Genetic, behavioral, and reproductive
attributes of dispersing field voles Microtus pennsylvanicus and.
Microtus ochrogaster. Ecological Monographs, 41, 53–78.
Nakagawa, S., Gillespie, D.O.S., Hatchwell, B.J. & Burke, T. 2007.
Predictable males and unpredictable females: sex difference in
repeatability of parental care in a wild bird population. Journal of
Evolutionary Biology, 20, 1674–1681.
Niemelä, P. T., Vainikka, A., Hedrick, A. V. & Kortet, R. 2012.
Integrating behaviour with life history: boldness of the field
cricket, Gryllus integer, during ontogeny. Functional Ecology, 26,
450–456.
Nunnally, J.C. & Bernstein, I.H. 1994. Psychometric Theory, 3rd ed.
New York: McGraw-Hill.
Oliveira, R.F., Taborsky, M. & Brockmann, H.J. 2008. Alternative
Reproductive Strategies: An Integrative Approach. Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press.
Øverli, Ø., Sørensen, C., Pulman, K.G.T., et al. 2007. Evolutionary
background for stress-coping styles: relationships between
physiological, behavioral, and cognitive traits in non-mammalian
vertebrates Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 31, 396–
412.
Patrick, S.C., Chapman, J.R., Dugdale, H.L., Quinn, J.L. & Sheldon,
B.C. 2012. Promiscuity, paternity and personality in the great tit.
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 279, 1724–1730.
Patterson, L.D. & Schulte-Hostedde, A. 2011. Behavioural correlates
of parasitism and reproductive success in male eastern chipmunk.
Tamias striatus. Animal Behaviour, 81, 1129–1137.
Pike, T.W., Samanta, M., Lindström, J. & Royle, N. 2008.
Behavioural phenotype affects social interactions in an animal
network. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 275,
2515–2520.
Rabaneda‐Bueno, R., Aguado, S., Fernández‐Montraveta, C. & Moya‐
Laraño, J. 2014. Does female personality determine mate choice
through sexual cannibalism? Ethology, 120, 238–248.
Räsänen, K. & Kruuk, L.E.B. 2007. Maternal effects and evolution at
ecological time-scales. Functional Ecology, 21, 408–421.
While, G.M., Isaksson, C., McEvoy, J., et al. 2010. Repeatable intra-
individual variation in plasma testosterone concentration and its
sex-specific link to aggression in a social lizard Hormones and
Behavior, 58, 208–213.
Wilson, D.S., Clark, A.B., Coleman, K. & Dearstyne, T. 1994. Shyness
and boldness in humans and other animals. Trends in Ecology
and Evolution, 9, 442–446.
Wilson, D.S., Coleman, K., Clark, A.B. & Biederman, L. 1993. Shy-
bold continuum in pumpkinseed sunfish (Lepomis gibbosus): An
ecological study of a psychological trait. Journal of Comparative
Psychology, 107, 250.
Wolf, M., Van Doorn, G.S., Leimar, O. & Weissing, F.J. 2007. Life-
history trade-offs favour the evolution of animal personalities.
Nature, 447, 581–584.
14
animal communication
WILLIAM A. SEARCY AND STEPHEN NOWICKI
INTRODUCTION
Many of the most spectacular and beautiful traits of animals
function in communication. Especially striking to humans are
certain visual signals, such as the vivid color patterns of coral reef
fish and arrow poison frogs and the exaggerated feather
ornaments of birds of paradise, egrets, and peafowl. Also obvious
and beautiful to humans are the auditory signals of some
animals, such as the songs of humpback whales, nightingales, and
wood thrushes. Other animal signals tend to pass us by because
of our sensory limitations; we miss out, for example, on most of
the olfactory signals of insects such as butterflies and ants, and
we are entirely oblivious to the electrical signals produced by
some groups of fishes. Whether we are personally aware of them
or not, animal signals pose interesting evolutionary questions.
Natural selection should favor the evolution of signaling
behaviors that benefit the signaler rather than the receiver, but
then why do receivers pay attention to signals that have evolved
to benefit others? Is it because signals contain information
valuable to receivers? But why should such information be
reliable (honest) enough to be worth attending to? Such
evolutionary questions will be one focus of this chapter. A second
focus will be the relationship between animal communication and
human language. Human language is far more complex and
cognitively sophisticated than the communication system of any
non-human animal. Nonetheless we still can ask about specific
ways in which human language is more advanced than animal
communication, and about the nature of commonalities between
the two. Before we get to any of these questions, however, we
define communication and its relationship to information.
Signal Reliability
Constrained Signals
Within the category of signals given between individuals with
opposing interests, a distinction is made between signals that can be
made by any individual and those whose production is somehow
constrained (Figure 14.2). Two types of constraints are considered,
physical and informational. A physical constraint means that some
individuals are unable to produce certain types of signals or certain
signal features because of the physical limitations of their signal
production mechanisms, whereas an informational constraint means
that some individuals cannot produce certain signals because they
lack the necessary information.
Signals subject to a physical constraint are termed index signals
and are often considered to be inherently honest because of an
inescapable relationship between a signal feature and the physical
characteristics of the signaler (Maynard Smith & Harper 2003). A
now-classic example involves formant frequencies in red deer
(Cervus elaphus). Male red deer produce loud roaring vocalizations
during the fall breeding season. As in other mammals, the sound of
any vocalization is initially produced by vibrations of vocal folds in
the larynx, and then passes to the outside through the vocal tract,
which in red deer is essentially a tube formed by the throat and oral
cavity. Passage through this tube emphasizes certain frequencies,
those whose wave lengths correspond to the acoustic resonances of
the tube. These emphasized frequencies are termed formants, with
the frequency of successive formants and the spacing between them
being inversely related to the tube’s length. Because the length of the
vocal tract is likely to be greater in larger animals, one would expect
these formant characteristics to be inversely correlated with body
size (Fitch & Reby 2001). In red deer, as expected, body mass is
strongly correlated with certain formant traits, especially with the
minimum spacing between formants. These correlations are not
perfect, but are nevertheless informative; variation in formant
spacing, for example, predicts about 40% of the variation among
males in body mass (Reby & McComb 2003). Both sexes of red deer
respond to such information: females prefer to approach playback of
roars with low formant spacing, while males vocalize more
themselves in reply to such roars (Reby et al. 2005; Charlton et al.
2007).
The responses of other red deer suggest that it would be
advantageous for a male to produce roars with lower formant
spacing in order to exaggerate his apparent size. In theory, cheating
on the roar in this way should not be possible, because only a truly
large individual can have the long vocal tract needed to produce the
formant attributes indicative of large size. Nevertheless, evidence
exists of both past and present exaggeration of this signal (Fitch &
Reby 2001). The larynx of most mammals is situated high in the
throat, but has descended deeper in the throat in the evolution of
humans. The “descended larynx” was long thought to be a uniquely
human characteristic, until it was shown that the larynx of red deer is
also found in a similar descended position. One explanation for the
descended larynx of red deer is that natural selection has favored
lowering the larynx because doing so elongates the vocal tract, thus
changing formant characteristics in a way that exaggerates apparent
size. Natural selection for size exaggeration thus would have led to
the gradual evolution of the larynx’s descended position. In addition
to this evolutionary exaggeration of apparent size, red deer
manipulate apparent size behaviorally by using muscles to pull the
larynx even lower when they roar. Despite the evidence for cheating
on the signal on both evolutionary and behavioral time scales, it can
still be argued that if all males have the descended laryngeal position
and all pull down on the larynx when roaring, then any remaining
variance in vocal tract length and thus in formant characteristics is
still constrained to reflect body size.
An example of an informational constraint is provided by song type
matching in songbirds. In many species of songbirds, each male
sings multiple versions of the species song; the different versions are
termed “song types.” Song type matching is a behavior in which one
individual replies to another with the same song type that the other
has just sung. Matching has been suggested to be a signal of
attention, demonstrating that the matcher is paying attention to the
bird that it matches. The signal is constrained to be honest, because
matching at above chance levels is only possible if the matcher is
indeed paying attention to the other, so that it knows what the other
has just sung. In this sense, having information about what song type
was sung and the ability to match it functions as a kind of “password”
in the signaling interaction. The constraint is an informational one
because it is information on what the other male has sung that limits
ability to match, rather than physical ability to produce the signal.
Handicaps
Signals that are not subject to constraints are sometimes said to
represent a free strategic choice (Hurd & Enquist 2005) (Figure
14.2): “free” because all individuals are able to produce such signals,
and a “strategic choice” because each individual chooses whether or
not to produce the signals based on the costs and benefits of doing
so. It is then the relationships between costs and benefits together
with individual attributes or environmental circumstances that can
combine to make such signals reliable.
The best known hypothesis for how signal costs can produce signal
reliability is the handicap principle of Amotz Zahavi. Zahavi
(1975) proposed that display characters used in mate choice will be
honest about signaler quality if they lower the signaler’s survival.
Those individuals that survive despite the costly display have passed
a test that individuals of lower quality cannot pass. Possession of the
trait thus conclusively demonstrates an individual’s quality. Zahavi
(1977) later amended the idea to allow the development of the
display to be adjusted to individual quality within the lifetime of a
signaler, removing the assumption that death must act to cull
through the signalers in order to produce reliability. A costly signal
whose development depends on individual quality is referred to as a
condition dependent handicap. Such traits are handicaps not in
the sense of a physical disability but rather in the sense of the extra
weight that an especially fast racehorse is made to carry.
Particularly important in convincing scientists of the validity of the
handicap principle were mathematical models by Grafen (1990),
which demonstrated that the assumptions of the handicap principle
can lead to signals that are both evolutionarily stable and reliable.
The models are complex, but their essentials are easily grasped from
a graphical version proposed by Johnstone (1997) and illustrated in
Figure 14.4. The model graphs the fitness costs and benefits of a
signal against a measure of its intensity, which might be size or color
for a visual display, or amplitude or production rate for an auditory
display. The model shows the fitness benefit of the display increasing
with signal intensity. If, for example, the display is a male courtship
signal, this relationship would arise because the higher a male’s
signal intensity, the more females he attracts, leading to more
offspring and thus higher fitness. The benefit curve reaches an
asymptote, based on the reasonable assumption in this mating signal
example that there is some upper limit to the number of females a
male can mate with. Two costs curves are shown, both having fitness
costs that increase linearly with increasing signal intensity. The
reason there are two cost curves is that the model assumes that
fitness costs increase more steeply for low quality signalers than for
high quality ones, another reasonable assumption. Suppose that the
signal is a call used in mate attraction, such as a frog call, and that
calling takes considerable energy, as is indeed true for calling in
frogs. In this system, a low quality signaler would be one with poor
energy reserves, and a high quality signaler ones with good energy
reserves. The fitness costs of expending energy by calling would then
increase more rapidly with calling rate for a low quality signaler than
for a high quality one. Only a single benefit curve is drawn because
we assume that receivers cannot judge signaler quality independent
of the signal, making the fitness benefit of a signal solely dependent
on its intensity.
Figure 14.4 A graphical version of the handicap mechanism. The
fitness costs of giving the signal increase linearly with signal
intensity, with a greater slope for low quality than for high quality
signalers. Fitness benefits increase in the same curve for both
categories of signalers. The optimum signaling level is found where
the difference between benefit and cost is maximized; that level is
greater for a high quality signaler than for a low quality one. Model
based on Johnstone (1997) and Grafen (1990).
The optimal signaling level is that value of signal intensity at which
the difference between signal benefit and signal costs is greatest.
Because of the difference in cost curves, the optimum level is higher
for signalers of good quality than for signalers of poor quality (Figure
14.4). Therefore, if all individuals signal at their optimum levels,
signal intensity reveals signaler quality. Cheating is not favored,
because signalers of poor quality that raise their signal intensity
beyond their equilibrium level experience a greater increase in signal
costs than in signal benefits. The signal is reliable, however, only
along the dimension in which it is costly. A fitness cost that arises
from an energy cost, for example, makes the signal reliable about
energy balance, but not about other attributes such as age or agility.
An example of a signal that illustrates the assumptions of the
handicap model is courtship drumming in the wolf spider
Hygrolycosa rubrofasciata. In this species, males court females by
drumming their abdomens against dry leaves, producing both
substrate vibrations and an air-borne sound. Females respond
preferentially to higher drumming rates both when choosing among
live males (Kotiaho et al. 1996) and when responding to playback of
drumming presented in the absence of males (Parri et al. 1997).
Captive males provisioned at higher levels drum more than males
provisioned at lower levels, demonstrating that drumming is
condition-dependent (Kotiaho 2000). As assumed in the handicap
model, the signal has a fitness cost: males induced to drum at a high
rate (by proximity to females) lose weight more rapidly and suffer
higher mortality than males drumming less (Mappes et al. 1996). In
an experiment in which both food level and drumming rate were
manipulated simultaneously, the two factors interacted in their
effects on survival (Kotiaho 2000), supporting the assumption that
the fitness costs of signaling are greater for males in poor condition
than for males in good condition.
In the wolf spider case, it is the energy cost of producing the signal
that leads to a fitness cost that maintains signal reliability, as we
suggested in laying out the general logic of the handicap theory.
Other types of costs are also possible. In some species of birds, such
as the barn swallow, females prefer males with longer tails (Møller
1988a; Vortman et al. 2011), and tail length is a predictor of aspects
of male quality (Møller 1994). Producing longer tail feathers may
impose a trivial energy cost in many cases; the major cost of this
signal instead appears to be that tail elongation reduces flight
performance (Rowe et al. 2001). In certain species of fish, such as
three-spined sticklebacks (Gasterosteus aculeatus) (Millinksi &
Bakker 1990), and birds, such as house finches (Haemorhous
mexicanus) (Hill 1991), females prefer males that are redder in color.
The red color is typically produced by carotenoid pigments, which
vertebrates are unable to synthesize, and which consequently must
be obtained in food. One cost to red coloration is that carotenoids
allocated to producing color are taken away from their alternative
functions in promoting health (Lozano 1994). Finally, some signals
have costs that are not experienced when the signals are used in
communication, but instead are experienced earlier in life, when the
signals are developing. For example, learned aspects of bird song
may have a developmental cost because song learning requires
considerable investment in the brain regions that support song
during a period of early life when resources are limited (Nowicki et
al. 1998, 2002).
Differential Benefits
In many species of birds, offspring remain in the nest and are fed by
their parents for some days or weeks after hatching. When a parent
visits the nest with food, the young produce a mix of signals:
stretching their necks upwards, opening their mouths widely, and
producing shrill calls. The common sense interpretation of these
signals, that they function to beg food from the parents, turns out to
be well justified. Young are fed more the more intensely they beg
(Krauss & Yasukawa 2013) and experimental enhancement of
begging calls via playback results in an increase in feeding by the
parents (Burford et al. 1998). Begging intensity increases with
increasing time since the last feeding (Kilner et al. 1999), so the
signal contains reliable information about the hunger (or need) of
the nestlings. Begging signals that communicate need from offspring
to parents are also found in mammals such as seals (Smiseth &
Lorentsen 2001) and meerkats (Manser et al. 2008).
Begging has some costs, as would be expected under a handicap
interpretation. Begging requires energy expenditure (McCarty 1996;
Leech & Leonard 1996), which, though slight, appears to be enough
to lower growth (Kilner 2001). Lower growth should have negative
effects on fitness. Begging also may attract predators (Haff &
Magrath 2011), which again has negative fitness consequences.
Furthermore, the energy cost of begging seems likely to act
differentially according to signaler quality, as assumed in the
handicap model. Nestlings that have been fed recently, and thus are
not very hungry, should pay a lower fitness cost for expending a
given amount of energy by begging than would a nestling that has
not been fed recently, and is accordingly nearer starvation. Given
that signal costs exist and that they increase with signal intensity at
different rates for high and low quality signalers, reliability of
begging seems well explained by our handicap model – except that
the predicted relationship between hunger and begging intensity is
directly opposite to that observed! Note with reference to Figure 14.4
that because the very-hungry chicks are the group for which fitness
costs increase more steeply with increasing signal intensity, and the
not-very-hungry chicks are the group for which fitness costs increase
less steeply, the handicap model predicts lower begging from the
very-hungry chicks than from the not-very-hungry ones, which is the
reverse of what is observed.
Although the reliability of begging cannot be explained by our
handicap model (Figure 14.4), it can be explained by an alternative
version of Grafen’s general model (Grafen 1990). In this second
version (Johnstone 1997), illustrated in Figure 14.5, a single cost line
is assumed to apply to all signalers. Two different benefit curves are
assumed, one for signalers of high need and the other for signalers of
low need. The benefit curve rises more steeply for signalers of high
need than for those of low need because the delivery of a given
amount of food has a greater impact on the fitness of a starving chick
than on the fitness of a well-fed chick. The equilibrium signaling
level is again the signal intensity at which the difference between
signal benefit and signal cost is greatest. This model predicts a higher
signaling level for signalers of high need than for signalers of low
need, which is in accord with what is observed.
Figure 14.5 A graphical version of a differential benefits model.
The benefits of signaling are assumed to increase with increasing
signal intensity more rapidly for signalers of high need than for those
of low need, while costs follow the same line for both categories of
signaler. The optimum signaling level is found where the difference
between benefit and cost is maximized; that level is greater to
signalers of high need. Model based on Johnstone (1997) and Grafen
(1990)
This alternative model may or may not be considered a handicap
model, depending on one’s perspective. Signal costs are needed to
stabilize the signaling system, but it is really the differential benefits
experienced by different categories of signalers that create the
predicted relationship between signal intensity and signaler
attributes. We therefore refer to this as a differential benefits model
(Figure 14.2).
Conventional Signals
The final category of explanations for signal reliability invokes
receiver dependent costs (Figure 14.2). These are costs that are
not intrinsic to the production or development of the signal but are
instead generated by the response of receivers. When signals are
subject to a physical constraint (like red deer roars) or a production
cost (like wolf spider drumming), the meaning of the signal, in the
sense of its information content, is determined by the signal’s
physical makeup. Signals that are not subject to physical constraints
or production costs, but only to receiver-dependent costs, have
meanings that are arbitrary with respect to their physical makeup,
and that are instead determined only by convention. For this reason,
signals that are of this type are often referred to as conventional
signals (Guilford & Dawkins 1995).
One possible example of a conventional signal is soft song in song
sparrows (Melospiza melodia) and other songbirds. Songs are long,
elaborate vocalizations produced in the context of mate attraction
and territory defense. Soft songs are simply low amplitude versions
of these vocalizations. Although in some species soft songs are
produced mainly during courtship (Dabelsteen et al. 1998), in song
sparrows they are produced only during aggression. In fact, of the
array of signals that song sparrows use during aggressive
interactions, soft song is the one best predictor of aggressive
escalation, more specifically of an actual attack (Searcy et al. 2006;
Akçay et al. 2013). The physical attribute that separates soft song
from normal, broadcast song is its low amplitude, a physical feature
that is neither costly to produce nor constrained to be associated
with aggression. At the same time, as a highly aggressive signal soft
song does appear to provoke aggressive retaliation from rivals and
thus to be subject to a receiver dependent cost (Anderson et al.
2012).
As emphasized earlier, aggression is a context in which conflicts of
interest are most extreme, and in which unreliable signaling seems
most likely to be advantageous. Can receiver-dependent costs
actually produce reliable signaling in such cases? An answer to this
question was first provided by Enquist’s (1985) game theoretical
model. The model assumes there are two possible signals: a signal of
strength that we will call A and a signal of weakness that we will call
B. An honest signaling strategy is to give A if strong and B if weak.
Individuals giving B concede defeat if their opponent gives A and
fight if their opponent gives B. Individuals giving A wait for their
opponent to concede if it gives B and fight if it gives A. Given these
assumptions, there is a temptation for weak individuals to cheat by
giving the signal of strength: a weak individual giving A will cause
honest weak individuals to concede, thus winning contests it might
otherwise lose. This benefit of cheating is balanced by a cost: weak
individuals that give the signal of strength will be attacked by strong
opponents, thus getting into fights that they will necessarily lose, and
which honest weak individuals can avoid. Game theory analysis
shows that if the cost of fighting a stronger opponent is high relative
to the value of winning contests, then cheating will not have a net
advantage, and reliability will prevail. Thus, reliable signaling is not
inevitable in such a system, but can be a stable outcome with the
right parameter values. Note that in such a conventional signaling
system, honest individuals do not actually pay a signal cost, so
honesty can be thought of as being maintained by the potential costs
of cheating rather than by realized costs (Számadó 2011).
Deception
Thus far we have laid out a number of hypotheses to explain why
animal signals are often reliable, but we have not considered the
opposite possibility: that animal signals are sometimes deceptive.
When applied to humans, the term deception implies that one
individual has an intention to cause another to form a false belief.
Intentions and beliefs are mental states that are difficult, if not
impossible, to assess in nonhuman animals. Accordingly, scientists
have adopted a definition of deception in animal communication that
does not stipulate such mental states. Here deception is defined as
occurring when a signaler produces a signal Y that is usually
associated with condition X; a receiver gives a response to Y that is
appropriate under condition X and that benefits the signaler; and
condition X does not actually hold (Searcy & Nowicki 2005). An
example helps to clarify this definition. Suppose that signal Y is an
alarm call that is usually given when a predator is present (condition
X), that receivers usually respond to the alarm by freezing, and that
freezing is appropriate in that it makes the freezing individual less
likely to be observed and attacked by the predator. Alarming would
be considered to be deceptive when the alarm is given in a context in
which no predator is actually present and the signaler benefits from
the receiver’s freezing response.
Instances that meet this definition of deception have long been
known from interspecific communication. Batesian mimicry, in
which a harmless prey species evolves a resemblance to a dangerous
one, provides many examples. Such examples typically involve visual
resemblance, as when a non-poisonous king snake evolves a pattern
of red, yellow, and black rings similar to that of a highly poisonous
coral snake, and visual predators such as birds are thereby deterred
from attacking the king snake (Greene & McDiarmid 1981; Brodie
1993). Because the visual signals provided by the king snake have
evolved in order to influence the behavior of the predators, such a
case meets our definition of communication. Mimicry can also occur
with respect to other sensory modalities, as when palatable moths
mimic the ultrasonic clicks that noxious moths use to warn off
predatory bats (Barber & Conner 2007).
Evidence has also been found for intraspecific deception. A
particularly clear example is provided by topi (Damaliscus lunatus),
a species of savannah antelope (Bro-Jørgensen & Pringle 2010). In
topi, both males and females give alarm snorts when they detect a
predator such as a lion or cheetah, and then stand staring at the
predator with ears pricked. Male topi give false alarms, that is alarms
in the absence of any predator, in one particular circumstance: when
a sexually receptive female is on the male’s territory and is starting to
leave it. A female is sexually receptive for one day, and during that
day she typically visits about 10 male territories, mating with about
four of the owners. Territory owners are much more likely to give
false alarms when a receptive female is on their territory than when
no females are present, and they are especially likely to give false
alarms when the receptive female attempts to leave. False alarms are
acoustically indistinguishable from true alarms, and males giving
them prick their ears and stare into the distance, just as they do
when giving true alarms. Females respond to playback of both true
and false alarms by first standing still briefly and then walking away
from the source of the sound. Because males give false alarms when
positioned between the female and the nearest boundary, the
walking away response usually brings the female back toward the
center of the male’s territory, thus delaying her departure. Males on
average achieve about three extra matings by using this false alarm
tactic. Males thus give a false signal and benefit from doing so, as
required by our definition of deception. Such a system can remain at
evolutionary equilibrium despite the occurrence of deception if a
sufficient proportion of the signals are reliable to make response
advantageous on average. Thus, female topi may be selected to
continue to respond to alarm calls despite the occurrence of false
alarms because the fitness consequences of failing to respond to an
honest alarm are potentially disastrous.
False alarms are used for other purposes in other species, for
example to draw competitors away from food in birds (Møller 1988b)
and monkeys (Wheeler 2009) and to cause sexual rivals to cease
moving in squirrels (Tamura 1995). Deception is also known in non-
alarm systems, for example in threat displays in stomatopod
crustaceans (Steger & Caldwell 1983) and in food calls in domestic
chickens (Gyger & Marler 1988).
Eavesdropping
Eavesdropping refers to the use of signals by unintended receivers
and represents another way that signaling systems can be diverted
from the functions for which they originally evolved. That receivers
are actually unintended is clearest in cases in which the receivers are
predators or parasites that use the signals of their victims to locate
individuals to attack. A case in point is provided by the túngara frog
(Engystomops pustulosus), whose mate attraction calls are exploited
by both predators and parasites. Male túngara frogs can produce
either simple calls, consisting of a frequency-modulated whine, or
complex calls, consisting of a whine plus one or more broad-band
chucks. The calls function in mate attraction; female túngara frogs
approach calling males or playback of calls and prefer to approach
complex calls over simple ones (Rand & Ryan 1981). A frog-eating
bat, Trachops cirrhosus, is also attracted to the male calls (Tuttle &
Ryan 1981), and like the female frogs the predatory bat is more likely
to approach complex calls than simple ones (Ryan et al. 1982).
Several species of blood-sucking flies of the genus Corethrella are
also attracted to the calls, and again respond more to complex calls
to simple ones (Bernal et al. 2006). Complex calls appear to be easier
for the bats to localize (Page & Ryan 2008), but this does not seem to
be true for the flies (Bernal et al. 2006). Although it is not always
clear why these natural enemies prefer complex calls, the existence of
this preference helps explain why the male frogs sometimes produce
simple calls even though complex calls are more effective mating
signals.
Eavesdropping has also been suggested to occur within species.
When a territorial male songbird countersings with an intruder on
his territory, or with song playback simulating an intruder,
information derived from the exchange of signals may be acted on by
other, neighboring territory owners (Peake et al. 2005) or by nearby
females (Otter et al. 1999). Such third party receivers probably
should not be classified as “unintended” in the sense that predators
and parasites are, in that influencing these other conspecifics may
have been one of the selective advantages that originally led to the
evolution of the signaling behavior and that still favors its
maintenance. Nevertheless, the perspective that communication
often occurs in extended “networks” (McGregor & Dabelsteen 1996),
rather than exclusively in signaler/receiver dyads, is an important
one and should be kept in mind when analyzing signaling systems.
The animal signals discussed thus far have for the most part been
capable of communicating only rather simple information: the body
size of the signaler, for example, or its aggressive intentions or level
of hunger. The simplicity of these signaling systems contrasts greatly
with human language, as well as with the way that animals are
imagined to communicate in works of literature such as Watership
Down and The Jungle Book. In this section we consider whether
non-human animals are capable of greater sophistication in
communication than we have thus far seen, using human language as
a point of comparison.
Vocal Learning
Another design feature that Hockett ascribed to all human languages
is “traditional transmission,” by which he meant that the “detailed
conventions” of any particular language are acquired through
learning. Because human languages are primarily vocal, language
transmission is typically through “vocal learning,” though humans
also have the capacity to acquire fully functional sign languages
through “gestural learning.” Most animals, including many that rely
heavily on vocal communication, are incapable of vocal learning; in
particular, primates other than humans have relatively little capacity
in this regard (Egnor & Hauser 2004). This generalization applies
specifically to vocal production learning, in which animals learn how
to form their vocalizations by imitating others. Other aspects of vocal
learning, such as learning how to respond to vocalizations, are more
widespread (Janik & Slater 2000).
Among animals other than humans, vocal production learning has
been most thoroughly studied in songbirds. All songbirds appear to
learn their songs, but as there are over 4000 songbird species, there
is a great deal of scope for variation in patterns of learning (Beecher
& Brenowitz 2005). One common pattern is illustrated by song
sparrows. Male song sparrows prevented in early life from hearing
the songs of adults grow up to produce songs that are obviously
abnormal (Kroodsma 1977), but which nevertheless preserve some
species-typical features (Marler & Sherman 1985). Isolated males
tutored with recorded songs learn the details of those songs and
show a strong preference for learning own-species songs rather than
songs of a closely related species (Marler & Peters 1988). Young male
song sparrows are particularly likely to learn from recorded models
that they hear during a “critical learning period” that spans
approximately 10 to 100 days post-hatching (Marler & Peters 1987).
The existence of a critical learning period provides one striking
parallel with human language development; a second parallel is that
song sparrows and other songbirds pass through a subsong phase in
which they sing relatively unformed versions of their song, similar to
the babbling stage shown in human infants (Marler & Peters 1982).
In the wild, young male song sparrows do not learn songs from their
own fathers (Cassidy 1993), and instead learn from males they
encounter after dispersing from their natal territories and that are
likely to become their territorial neighbors (Nordby et al. 1999).
Vocal production learning occurs in two groups of birds other than
songbirds, hummingbirds and parrots, and in a few groups of
mammals other than humans, such as whales, dolphins, and bats
(Searcy & Nowicki 2019). Why vocal learning has evolved in these
various groups and not others is not well established, but one idea is
that the selective advantage of vocal learning lies in allowing the
expansion of the repertoire of vocal signals (Nowicki & Searcy 2014).
In humans, expansion of the vocal repertoire may have originally
been advantageous mainly in allowing information sharing among
kin (Fitch 2010) through increases in numbers of referential signals.
In the other vocal learners, however, signals subject to learning are
not referential, but instead are most often sexual signals used in
mate choice and aggressive competition, as is true of songbird song.
Increases in the vocal repertoire in such cases do not lead to greater
information sharing in the same way as seen in humans. Because
vocal production learning involves learning new referential signals in
humans but not in other animals, non-human animals can be
considered at most to approximate this design feature of human
language.
Syntax
Syntax refers to rules governing how smaller signal elements, such
as words, are assembled into longer strings, such as sentences.
Syntax in this simple sense is fairly common among animals. Many
species of songbirds, for example, sing multiple song types, each of
which conveys the same two messages: an aggressive, keep-away
message directed at same sex conspecifics, and a courtship, mate-
attraction message directed at opposite-sex conspecifics. Some
species sing such song types with “eventual variety,” meaning that a
singer produces a series of renditions of one song type before
switching to a bout of a second song type, while other species sing
with “immediate variety,” continually switching song types after a
single rendition of each. Although a species may follow one of these
syntactical rules faithfully, syntax in these songbirds is
fundamentally different than in human language in that how signal
elements are combined has little or no effect on meaning (Berwick et
al. 2011).
Some nonhuman primates show a more complex level of syntax, in
which signal elements have meanings that change when those
elements are combined. In Campbell’s monkey (Cercophithecus
campbelli), for example, two boom calls mean that a male is
separated from his group, two booms followed by a series of krak-oo
calls mean that a tree is falling, and a pair of booms plus krak-oo
calls interspersed with hok-oo calls mean that another group of
monkeys is approaching (Ouattara et al. 2009). Note that in this
example, meaning is affected by what calls are combined, and there
seems to be regularity in the order in which call types are given, but
it is not explicitly shown that order affects meaning. Syntax of this
order of complexity is known for several nonhuman primates
(Zuberbühler 2019).
The most complex level of syntax known for a nonhuman
communication system occurs not in a primate but in a bird, the
Japanese tit (Suzuki et al. 2019). Japanese tits produce A, B, and C
notes as alert calls when they perceive a nearby predator and
produce D notes to recruit others to social contexts that are not
threatening. Playback of ABC notes causes listening birds to scan
their surroundings, while playback of D notes causes listening birds
to approach. Playback of ABC-D combinations causes listeners to
approach while scanning. Crucially, ABC-D sequences are much
more effective in causing the approach while scanning response than
are D-ABC sequences (Suzuki et al. 2016), demonstrating that
element order affects response and suggesting that order affects
meaning. Japanese tits also respond to tää recruitment calls
produced by willow tits (Poecile montanus), a species that they often
flock with (Suzuki et al. 2017). Japanese tits again respond with both
approach and scanning to playback of completely novel ABC-tää
combinations, while showing very little response to equally novel
tää-ABC combinations (Suzuki et al. 2017). Thus, novel sequences
are also interpreted with respect to their element order.
Although Japanese tit syntax is surprisingly complex, it is still far
simpler than the widely varying syntactical rules of human
languages. What the essential differences are between human and
nonhuman syntax has been much debated. One proposal is that the
one truly distinguishing feature of the human “faculty of language” is
that only humans have a “capacity of recursion” (Hauser et al. 2002),
where recursion refers to the sequential placement of components
inside other components of the same type. An example is provided
by the sentence “the car the doctor drove broke down,” in which the
phrase that describes what the car did (the car broke down) has
embedded within it a specification of what car we are talking about
(the one the doctor drove). Humans are sometimes said to have an
infinite capacity of recursion, but in fact adding one more level of
recursion is more than we typically attempt in speaking and is almost
more than we can comprehend, as in “the car the doctor Sally knew
drove broke down.”
Although there is currently no clear evidence that any non-human
animal uses recursion in its natural signaling system, studies have
asked whether animals can learn to recognize recursive structures in
human-imposed systems. In one such study, Gentner et al. (2006)
trained European starlings (Sturnus vulgaris) to discriminate
between two categories of sequences made up of two types of starling
phrases, rattles (R) and warbles (W). One category included strings
such as RRWW and RRRWWW, with a general form that can be
written as RnWn. These strings have a recursive structure, with RW
pairs embedded within other RW pairs. The second category
consisted of sequences such as RWRW and RWRWRW; these can be
written as (RW)n and do not have a recursive structure. Starlings
proved capable of discriminating between the two categories of
training sequences and of generalizing this discrimination to new
examples of the sequence types. Probe stimuli were used to show
that the starlings were not using simple rules-of-thumb, such as
classifying based on whether the first two phrases were the same (RR
= recursive) or different (RW = non-recursive). One classification
strategy that was not eliminated was counting: starlings might have
counted the number of R’s given first and then the number of W’s
given subsequently, and accepted the sequence as recursive when
those numbers were equal (Corballis 2007). Ironically, counting is a
strategy that humans often follow to solve this discrimination
problem. Another even simpler possibility is that the starlings used
overall acoustic similarity (i.e. which strings sounded similar) to
classify sequences, without doing any kind of syntactic analysis at all
(Van Heijningen et al. 2009). Acoustic similarity may also explain
the results of other studies in which non-human animals appear to
discriminate stimuli based on artificial syntactical rules (Beckers et
al. 2017).
Although it is still debated whether birds and other non-human
animals can be taught to judge whether strings of signals have a
proper recursive structure, no one has suggested that non-human
animals can recover meaning from such structures. It is after all both
much easier (and less useful) to discern that the sentence “the car the
doctor Sally knew drove broke down” has the correct number of
verbs relative to subjects than to figure out that the car broke down,
the doctor drove, and Sally knew. Once again, the communication
capabilities of other animals fall short of those shown in human
language.
Pragmatics
In the study of human language, pragmatics concerns how context
influences communication in general and meaning in particular.
Context definitely has important effects on meaning in human
speech, effects that are traditionally illustrated using statements that
are ambiguous without knowledge of the context in which they are
given. As one example, the statement “the missionaries are ready to
eat” (Mey 2001) has a different meaning if given when a group of
religious workers are sitting down to dinner than if given after the
same individuals have been captured by cannibals. Context also
affects communication acts in humans, with speakers altering their
speech with respect to the composition of the audience they are
addressing, the presumed state of knowledge of the individuals in
that audience, and so forth.
Context has been demonstrated to affect the interpretation of signals
in non-human animals just as in humans. In song sparrows, for
example, territory owners are normally less aggressive towards
playback of a neighbor’s song than towards playback of a stranger’s
song, as long as the neighbor’s song is played from the correct
boundary, that is the one shared with the neighbor in question
(Stoddard et al. 1991). If, however, playback is first used to simulate
the intrusion of a neighbor onto a male’s territory, that male is
subsequently much more aggressive towards boundary playback of
the song of this “bad neighbor” than towards song of an unoffending
“good neighbor” (Akçay et al. 2009). Moreover, if playback is first
used to simulate the intrusion of one neighbor (the “defector”) onto
the territory of another neighbor (the “victim”), subjects are
subsequently more aggressive towards boundary playback of the
defector’s songs than of the victim’s songs (Akçay et al. 2010). Song
sparrows thus modulate their aggressive response to song not just
with respect to the presumed signaler’s past behavior towards
themselves, but also with respect to the presumed signaler’s past
behavior towards others.
Context in non-human animals can affect signaler behavior as well as
receiver response. In audience effects, for example, the presence
and identity of potential receivers affects patterns of signaling. One
of the first demonstrations of such effects was in chickens: roosters
that encountered food were found to be very likely to give a food call
when a female was present, less likely to call when no audience was
present, and not at all likely to call when only a rival male was
present (Marler et al. 1986). Audience effects have also been found in
non-human primates: for example, the latency with which capuchin
monkeys (Cebus apella) give food calls in response to the discovery
of bananas was found to decrease as the number of nearby monkeys
increased (Di Bitetti 2005). More subtle audience effects have been
demonstrated in chimpanzees: in experiments in which playback was
used to simulate the approach of another individual to a silently
feeding chimpanzee, subjects were more likely to give food calls for
the approach of a closely associated individual (a “friend”) than for
less closely associated individuals (Schel et al. 2013).
Altogether, non-human animals have been shown to exhibit
considerable abilities with respect to pragmatics aspects of
communication. Humans undoubtedly do far more, in particular in
terms of adjusting signaling with respect to the state of knowledge of
their receivers. Nevertheless, pragmatics may be the aspect of
communication in which animal signaling systems most closely
resemble human language.
SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS
Communication is defined as the production of acts or structures
that affect the behavior of others and that have evolved because
of such effects. Signals often contain information of value to
receivers, and this value explains the maintenance of receiver
response over evolutionary time. The vulnerability of such
systems is that signalers may be selected to manipulate receiver
response by providing false information; most communication
systems can be evolutionarily stable only if such deception is
somehow held in check. One way that deception can be limited is
for signaling to be constrained by inescapable relationships
between signal features and physical characteristics of the
signaler, producing what are termed index signals. Another
possibility, which applies especially to signals of quality, is for
signals to have a fitness cost that is higher for low quality than for
high quality signalers, so that optimal signaling levels are higher
for those of high quality. A third possibility, which applies
especially to signals of need, is for the fitness benefits of signaling
to be higher for individuals of high need than for those of low
need. Finally, conventional signals are signals that are not
physically constrained and that have negligible intrinsic costs and
are instead stabilized by costs imposed by receiver responses.
Although some animal signaling systems are impressively
complex, none approaches the complexity of human language. A
subset of animal signals have some of the properties of symbols,
such as the ability to refer to things external to the signaler, but
none are accepted as being fully symbolic. A few animal groups
learn to produce their signals, but none are known to learn to
produce new referential signals with new meanings, as do
humans. Some animals follow rules about signal order, but it
seems to be very rare for signal order to affect meaning, as occurs
pervasively in human language. Animal signals approach human
language most closely with respect to pragmatics, the effects of
context on meaning and on signaling behavior, but even here
non-human animals seem not to adjust their signals with respect
to the state of knowledge of their audience.
FURTHER READING
Principles of Animal Communication by Bradbury and Vehrencamp
(2011) provides comprehensive coverage of all aspects of animal
communication. Those interested specifically in issues relating to
signal reliability and deception might consult the books by Maynard
Smith and Harper (2003) and Searcy and Nowicki (2005), while
those interested in the relationship of animal communication to
human language will find much of value in The Evolution of
Language by Fitch (2010). Monographs on specific systems of
animal communication that are both authoritative and entertaining
include Von Frisch (1967) on the dance language of honeybees, the
two books by Cheney and Seyfarth (1990, 2007) on communication
in non-human primates, and Catchpole and Slater (2008) on
birdsong.
REFERENCES
Akçay, C., Reed, V.A., Campbell, S.E., Templeton, C.N. & Beecher,
M.D. 2010. Indirect reciprocity: song sparrows distrust aggressive
neighbours based on eavesdropping. Animal Behaviour, 80,
1041–7.
Akçay, C., Tom, M.E., Campbell, S.E. & Beecher, M.D. 2013. Song
type matching is an honest early threat signal in a hierarchical
animal communication system. Proceedings of the Royal Society
of London B, 280, 20122517.
Akçay, C., Wood, W.E., Searcy, W.A., et al. 2009. Good neighbour,
bad neighbour: song sparrows retaliate against aggressive rivals.
Animal Behaviour, 78, 97–102.
Anderson, R.C., Searcy, W.A., Hughes, M. & Nowicki, S. 2012. The
receiver-dependent cost of soft song: a signal of aggressive intent
in songbirds. Animal Behaviour, 83, 1443–8.
Barber, J.R. & Conner, W.E. 2007. Acoustic mimicry in a predator-
prey interaction. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences USA, 104, 9331–4.
Beckers, G.J.L., Berwick, R.C., Okanoya, K. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2017.
What do animals learn in artificial grammar studies?
Neurosicence and Biobehavioral Reviews, 81, 238–46.
Beecher, M.D. & Brenowitz, E.A. 2005. Functional aspects of song
learning in songbirds. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 20, 143–
9.
Bernal, X.E., Rand, A.S. & Ryan, M.J. 2006. Acoustic preferences
and localization performance of blood-sucking flies (Corethrella
Coquillett) to túngara frog calls. Behavioral Ecology, 17, 709–15.
Berwick, R.C., Okanoya, K., Beckers, G.J.L. & Bolhuis, J.J. 2011.
Songs to syntax: the linguistics of birdsong. Trends in Cognitive
Science, 15, 113–21.
Bradbury, J.W. & Vehrencamp, S.L. 2011. Principles of Animal
Communication, 2nd ed. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Brodie, E.D. 1993. Differential avoidance of coral snake banded
patterns by free-ranging avian predators in Costa Rica. Evolution,
47, 227–35.
Bro-Jørgensen, J. & Pangle, W.M. 2010. Male topi antelopes snort
deceptively to retain females for mating. American Naturalist,
176, e33-e39.
Burford, J.E., Friedrich, T.J. & Yasukawa, K. 1998. Response to
playback of nestling begging in the red-winged blackbird,
Agelaius phoeniceus. Animal Behaviour, 56, 555–61.
Cassidy, A.L.E.V. 1993. Song variation and learning in island
populations of song sparrows. PhD Dissertation, University of
British Columbia, Vancouver.
Catchpole, C.K. & Slater, P.J.B. 2008. Bird Song: Biological Themes
and Variations, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Charlton, B.D., Reby, D. & McComb, K. 2007. Female red deer prefer
the roars of larger males. Biology Letters, 3, 382–5.
Cheney, D.L. & Seyfarth, R.M. 1990. How Monkeys See the World:
Inside the Mind of Another Species. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Cheney, D.L. & Seyfarth, R.M. 2007. Baboon Metaphysics: The
Evolution of a Social Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Corballis, M.C. 2007. Recursion, language, and starlings. Cognitive
Science, 31, 697–704.
Crespi, B.J. & Yanega, D. 1995. The definition of eusociality.
Behavioral Ecology, 6, 109–15.
Dabelsteen, T., McGregor, P.K., Lampe, H.M., Langmore, N.E. &
Holland, J. 1998. Quiet song in song birds: an overlooked
phenomenon, Bioacoustics, 9, 89–105.
Di Bitetti, M.S. 2005. Food-associated calls and audience effects in
tufted capuchin monkeys. Cebus apella nigritus. Animal
Behaviour, 69, 911–9.
Egnor, S.E.R. & Hauser, M.D. 2004. A paradox in the evolution of
primate vocal learning. Trends in Neuroscience, 27, 649–54.
Enquist, M. 1985. Communication during aggressive interactions
with particular reference to variation in choice of behaviour.
Animal Behaviour, 33, 1152–61.
Fitch, W.T. 2010. The Evolution of Language. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Fitch, W.T. & Reby, D. 2001. The descended larynx is not uniquely
human. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 268,
1669–75.
Gentner, T.Q., Fenn, K.M., Margoliash, D. & Nusbaum, H.C. 2006.
Recursive syntactic pattern learning by songbirds. Nature, 440,
1204–12.
Gould, J.L. 1976. The dance-language controversy. Quarterly Review
of Biology, 51, 211–44.
Grafen, A. 1990. Biological signals as handicaps. Journal of
Theoretical Biology, 144, 517–46.
Greene, H.W. & McDiarmid, R.W. 1981. Coral snake mimicry: does it
occur? Science, 213, 1207–12.
Guilford, T. & Dawkins, M.S. 1995. What are conventional signals?
Animal Behaviour, 49, 1689–95.
Gyger, M. & Marler, P. 1988. Food calling in the domestic fowl,
Gallus gallus: the role of external referents and deception. Animal
Behaviour, 36, 358–65.
Haff, T.M. & Magrath, R.D. 2011. Calling at a cost: elevated nestling
calling attracts predators to active nests. Biology Letters, 7, 493–
5.
Hallem, E.A., Fox, A.N., Zwiebel, L.J. & Carlson, J.R. 2004.
Mosquito receptor for human-sweat odorant. Nature, 427, 212–3.
Hauser, M.D., Chomsky, N. & Fitch, W.T. 2002. The faculty of
language: what is it, who has it, and how did it evolve? Science,
298, 1569–79.
Hill, G.E. 1991. Plumage coloration is a sexually selected indicator of
male quality. Nature, 350, 337–9.
Hockett, C.F. 1960. The origin of speech. Scientific American, 203,
88–96.
Hurd, P.L. & Enquist, M. 2005. A strategic taxonomy of biological
communication. Animal Behaviour, 70, 1155–70.
Janik, V.M. & Slater, P.J.B. 2000. The different roles of social
learning in vocal communication. Animal Behaviour, 60, 1–11.
Johnstone, R.A. 1997. The evolution of animal signals. In: J.R. Krebs
& N.B. Davies (eds.), Behavioural Ecology, pp. 155–178. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Kilner, R.M. 2001. A growth cost of begging in captive canary chicks.
Proceedings of the National Acadamy of Sciences USA, 98,
11394–8.
Kilner, R.M., Noble, D.G. & Davies, N.B. 1999. Signals of need in
parent-offspring communication and their exploitation by the
common cuckoo. Nature, 397, 667–72.
Kotiaho, J.S. 2000. Testing the assumptions of conditional handicap
theory: costs and condition dependence of a sexually selected
trait. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 48, 188–94.
Kotiaho, J.S., Alatalo, R.V., Mappes, J. & Parri, S. 1996. Sexual
selection in a wolf spider: male drumming activity, body size and
viability. Evolution, 50, 1977–81.
Krauss, N. & Yasukawa, K. 2013. How do female red-winged
blackbirds allocate food within broods? Condor, 115, 198–208.
Kroodsma, D.E. 1977. A re-evaluation of song development in the
song sparrow. Animal Behaviour, 25, 390–9.
Leech, S.M. & Leonard, M.L. 1996. Is there an energetic cost to
begging in nestling tree swallows (Tachycineta bicolor)?
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 263, 983–7.
Lozano, G.A. 1994. Carotenoids, parasites, and sexual selection.
Oikos, 70, 309–11.
Macedonia, J.M. & Evans, C.S. 1993. Variation among mammalian
alarm call systems and the problem of meaning in animal signals.
Ethology, 93, 177–97.
Manser, M.B. 2001. The acoustic structure of suricates’ alarm calls
varies with predator type and the level of response urgency.
Proceedings of the Royal Society London B, 268, 2315–24.
Manser, M.B., Madden, J.R., Kunc, H.P., English, S. & Clutton-
Brock, T. 2008. Signals of need in a cooperatively breeding
mammal with mobile offspring. Animal Behaviour, 76, 1805–13.
Mappes, J., Alatalo, R.V., Kotiaho, J. & Parri, S. 1996. Viability costs
of condition-dependent sexual male display in a drumming wolf
spider. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 263, 785–
9.
Marler, P., Dufty, A. & Pickert, R. 1986. Vocal communication in the
domestic chicken: II. Is a sender sensitive to the presence and
nature of a receiver? Animal Behaviour, 34, 194–8.
Marler, P. & Peters, S. 1982. Subsong and plastic song: their role in
the vocal learning process. In: D.E. Kroodsma & E.H. Miller
(eds.), Acoustic Communication in Birds, Vol. 2, pp. 25–50. New
York: Academic Press.
Marler, P. & Peters, S. 1987. A sensitive period for song acquisition in
the song sparrow, Melsopiza melodia: A case of age-limited
learning. Ethology, 76, 89–100.
Marler, P. & Peters, S. 1988. The role of song phonology and syntax
in vocal learning preferences in the song sparrow. Melospiza
melodia. Ethology, 77, 125–49.
Marler, P. & Sherman, V. 1985. Innate differences in singing
behaviour of sparrows reared in isolation from adult conspecific
song. Animal Behaviour, 33, 57–71.
Maynard Smith, J. & Harper, D. 2003. Animal Signals. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
McCarty, J.P. 1996. The energetic cost of begging in nestling
passerines. Auk, 113, 178–188.
McGregor, P.K. & Dabelsteen, T. 1996. Communication networks. In:
D.E. Kroodsma & E.H. Miller (eds.), Ecology and Evolution of
Acoustic Communication in Birds, pp. 409–25. Ithaca, New York:
Cornell University Press.
Mey, J.L. 2001. Pragmatics: An Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.
Milinski, M. & Bakker, T.C.M. 1990. Female sticklebacks use male
coloration in mate choice and hence avoid parasitized males.
Nature, 344, 330–3.
Møller, A.P. 1988a. Female choice selects for male sexual tail
ornaments in the monogamous swallow. Nature, 332, 640–2.
Møller, A.P. 1988b. False alarm calls as a means of resource
usurpation in the great tit. Parus major. Ethology, 79, 25–30.
Møller, A.P. 1994. Male ornament size as a reliable cue to enhanced
offspring viability in the barn swallow. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences USA, 91, 6929–32.
Nordby, J.C., Campbell, S.E. & Beecher, M.D. 1999. Ecological
correlates of song learning in song sparrows. Behavioral Ecology,
10, 287–97.
Nowicki, S., Peters, S. & Podos, J. 1998. Song learning, early
nutrition and sexual selection in songbirds. American Zoologist,
38, 179–90.
Nowicki, S. & Searcy, W.A. 2014. The evolution of vocal learning.
Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 28, 48–53.
Nowicki, S., Searcy, W.A. & Peters, S. 2002. Brain development, song
learning and mate choice in birds: a review and experimental test
of the “nutritional stress hypothesis”. Journal of Comparative
Physiology A, 188, 1003–14.
Otter, K., McGregor, P.K., Terry, A.M.R., et al. 1999. Do female great
tits (Parus major) assess males by eavesdropping? A field study
using interactive song playback. Proceedings of the Royal Society
of London B, 266, 1305–9.
Ouattara, K., Lemasson, A. & Zuberbühler, K. 2009. Campbell’s
monkeys concatenate vocalizations into context-specific call
sequences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
USA, 106, 22026–31.
Page, R.A. & Ryan, M.J. 2008. The effect of signal complexity on
localization performance in bats that localize frog calls. Animal
Behaviour, 76, 761–9.
Parri, S., Alatalo, R.V., Kotiaho, J. & Mappes, J. 1997. Female choice
for male drumming in the wolf spider. Hygrolycosa
rubrofasciata. Animal Behaviour, 53, 305–12.
Peake, T.M., Matessi, G., McGregor, P.K. & Dabelsteen, T. 2005.
Song type matching, song type switching and eavesdropping in
male great tits. Animal Behaviour, 69, 1063–8.
Proctor, H.C. 1991. Courtship in the water mite Neumania
papillator: males capitalize on female adaptations for predation.
Animal Behaviour, 42, 589–98.
Proctor, H.C. 1992. Sensory exploitation and the evolution of male
mating behaviour: a cladistic test using water mites (Acari:
Parasitengona). Animal Behaviour, 44, 745–52.
Rand, A.S. & Ryan, M.J. 1981. The adaptive significance of a complex
vocal repertoire in a neotropical frog. Zeitschrift für
Tierpsychologie, 57, 209–14.
Ratnieks, F.L.W. 1988. Reproductive harmony via mutual policing by
workers in eusocial Hymenoptera. American Naturalist, 132,
217–36.
Reby, D. & McComb, K. 2003. Anatomical constraints generate
honesty: acoustic cues to age and weight in the roars of red deer
stags. Animal Behaviour, 65, 519–30.
Reby, D., McComb, K., Cargnelutti, B., et al. 2005. Red deer stags
use formants as assessment cues during intrasexual agonistic
interactions. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 272,
941–7.
Riley, J.R., Greggers, U., Smith, A.D., Reynolds, D.R. & Menzel, R.
2005. The flight paths of honeybees recruited by the waggle
dance. Nature, 435, 205–7.
Rowe, L.V., Evans, M.R. & Buchanan, K.L. 2001. The function and
evolution of the tail streamer in hirundines. Behavioral Ecology,
12, 157–63.
Ryan, M.J., Fox, J.H., Wilczynski, W. & Rand, A.S. 1990. Sexual
selection for sensory exploitation in the frog. Physalaemus
pustulosus. Nature, 343, 66–7.
Ryan, M.J., Tuttle, M.D. & Rand, A.S. 1982. Bat predation and sexual
advertisement in a neotropical anuran. American Naturalist, 119,
136–9.
Schel, A.M., Machanda, Z., Townsend, S.W., Zuberbühler, K. &
Slocombe, K.E. 2013. Chimpanzee food calls are directed at
specific individuals. Animal Behaviour, 86, 955–65.
Searcy, W.A., Anderson, R.C. & Nowicki, S. 2006. Bird song as a
signal of aggressive intent. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology,
60, 234–241.
Searcy, W.A. & Nowicki, S. 2005. The Evolution of Animal
Communication: Reliability and Deception in Signaling Systems.
Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Searcy, W.A. & Nowicki, S. 2019. Birdsong learning, avian cogntion
and the evolution of language. Animal Behaviour, 151, 217–27.
Seeley, T.D. 1997. Honey bee colonies are group-level adaptive units.
American Naturalist, 150, S22-S41.
Seeley, T.D., Mikheyev, A.S. & Pagano, G.J. 2000. Dancing bees tune
both duration and rate of waggle-run production in relation to
nectar-source profitability. Journal of Compative Physiology A,
186, 813–819.
Seyfarth, R.M., Cheney, D.L. & Marler, P. 1980a. Monkey responses
to three different alarm calls: evidence of predator classification
and semantic communication. Science, 210, 801–803.
Seyfarth, R.M., Cheney, D.L. & Marler, P. 1980b. Vervet monkey
alarm calls: Semantic communication in a free-ranging primate.
Animal Behaviour, 28, 1070–1094.
Slocombe, K.E. & Zuberbühler, K. 2006. Food-associated calls in
chimpanzees: responses to food types or food preferences?
Animal Behaviour, 72, 989–999.
Smiseth, P.T. & Lorentsen, S.H. 2001. Begging and parent-offspring
conflict in grey seals. Animal Behaviour, 62, 273–279.
Steger, R. & Caldwell, R.L. 1983. Intraspecific deception by bluffing:
a defense strategy of newly molted stomatopods (Arthropoda:
Crustacea). Science, 221, 558–560.
Stoddard, P.K., Beecher, M.D., Horning, C.L. & Campbell, S.E. 1991.
Recognition of individual neighbors by song in the song sparrow,
a species with song repertoires. Behavioral Ecology and
Sociobiology, 29, 211–215.
Struhsaker, T.T. 1967. Auditory communication among vervet
monkeys (Cercopithecus aethiops). In: S.A. Altman (ed.), Social
Communication Among Primates, pp. 281–324. Chicago: Univ. of
Chicago Press.
Suzuki, T.N. 2020. Other species’ alarm calls evoke a predator-
specific search image in birds. Current Biology, 30, 1–5.
Suzuki, T.N., Griesser, M. & Wheatcroft, D. 2019. Syntactic rules in
avian vocal sequences as a window into the evolution of
compositionality. Animal Behaviour, 151, 267–274.
Suzuki, T.N., Wheatcroft, D. & Griesser, M. 2016. Experimental
evidence for compositional syntax in bird calls. Nature
Communications, 7, 10986.
Suzuki, T.N., Wheatcroft, D. & Griesser, M. 2017. Wild birds use an
ordering rule to decode novel call sequences. Current Biology, 27,
2331–2336.
Számadó, S. 2011. The cost of honesty and the fallacy of the handicap
principle. Animal Behaviour, 81, 3–10.
Tamura, M. 1995. Postcopulatory mate guarding by vocalization in
the Formosan squirrel. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 36,
377–386.
Tuttle, M.D. & Ryan, M.J. 1981. Bat predation and the evolution of
frog vocalizations in the neotropics. Science, 214, 677–678.
Van Heijningen, C.A.A., De Visser, J., Zuidema, W. & Ten Cate, C.
2009. Simple rules can explain discrimination of putative
recursive syntactic structures by a songbird species. Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 106, 20538–20543.
Von Frisch, K. 1967. The Dance Language and Orientation of Bees.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Vortman, Y., Lotem, A., Dor, R., Lovette, I.J. & Safran, R.J. 2011. The
sexual signals of the East-Mediterranean barn swallow: a different
swallow tale. Behavioral Ecology, 22, 1344–1352.
Wenner, A.M. 2002. The elusive honey bee dance “language”
hypothesis. Journal of Insect Behavior, 15, 859–878.
Wenner, A.M., Wells, P.H. & Johnson, D.L. 1969. Honey bee
recruitment to food sources: olfaction or language? Science, 164,
84–86.
Wheeler, B.C. 2009. Monkeys crying wolf? Tufted capuchin monkeys
use anti-predator calls to usurp resources from conspecifics.
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 276, 3013–3018.
Wheeler, B.C., Searcy, W.A., Christiansen, M.H., et al. 2011.
Communication. In: R. Menzel & J. Fischer (eds.), Animal
Thinking: Contemporary Issues in Comparative Cognition, pp.
187–205. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Zahavi, A. 1975. Mate selection - a selection for a handicap. Journal
of Theoretical Biology, 53, 205–214.
Zahavi, A. 1977. The cost of honesty (further remarks on the
handicap principle). Journal of Theoretical Biology, 67, 603–605.
Zuberbühler, K. 2019. Evolutionary roads to syntax. Animal
Behaviour, 151, 259–265.
15
evolution of behavior
MICHAEL J. RYAN
INTRODUCTION
Darwin often referred to his theory of evolution by natural
selection as descent with modification. Descent refers to the
existence of traits because they were passed down from a
previous ancestor; modification refers to variation in such traits
shaped by selection. As we have seen in Chapter 1, Tinbergen
(1963) summarized the four main “questions” of ethology as
causation, ontogeny, evolution, and survival value. The latter two
map quite well onto “descent with modification.” In this chapter
we focus on the historical components of behavior, which is what
Tinbergen meant by “evolution” and what Darwin meant by
“descent”: How many of the details of an animal’s behavior were
inherited from its previous ancestor, and what are the general
historical patterns by which behaviors emerge? But we also
explore the inextricable links between history and selection. How
can we parse the dual influences of history and selection on
behaviors of extant species? Toward this end we will discuss
various approaches that are used to infer historical patterns of
behavioral evolution and apply some of these approaches to aid
us in understanding adaptations in a historical context.
Coevolution
When selection favors the evolution of traits needed to face
environmental challenges, such as survival in harsh temperatures,
there could be the evolution of an optimal solution that would be
stable over time. For example, animals in Arctic climes might evolve
an optimal degree of fat and fur given the various tradeoffs of such
an adaptation. The fact that the animal evolves an adaption to be
warmer does not feedback on the environmental temperature. In this
example there is one independent variable (the agent of selection,
environmental temperature) and one dependent variable (the target
of selection, the animal’s phenotype).
There are situations in which an individual can be both an agent and
a target of selection. This occurs when one individual influences the
evolution of a second and this then causes feedback on the evolution
of the first individual, a process referred to as coevolution.
Coevolution can occur between species, such as when a predator
evolves more efficient hunting tactics and a prey evolves a greater
ability to evade those tactics, or when bacteria evolve drug resistance
to the development of new antibiotics by pharmaceutical companies
(Bull & Wichman 2001). These situations can also occur within
species, such as when male courtship traits drive preferences for
those traits and vice versa (Kirkpatrick & Ryan 1991). We often refer
to these cycles as arms races (Dawkins & Krebs 1978).
A particular type of coevolution that has seen widespread interest is
that of “cospeciation.” A well-considered example is provided by
studies of figs and the wasps that pollinate them. In general, each
species of fig is pollinated by a single species of wasp, and each fig-
pollinating wasp will pollinate only that species of fig. This is one of
the most extreme cases of obligate pollination known. A female wasp
will enter a fig, which has its flowers enclosed within the fruit. The
female will pollinate some of the flowers, lay eggs in others, and then
die inside the fig. After her offspring hatch, the male and female
offspring mate, the females gather pollen from some of the flowers,
and leave to find another fig in which they can oviposit, die, and thus
continue the life cycle (Machado et al. 2001). Previous studies have
argued for strong patterns of cospeciation (e.g., Machado et al.
2001), but a more recent analysis suggests that groups of genetically
well-defined wasp species coevolve along with frequently hybridizing
groups of figs (Machado et al. 2005).
Sexual selection and sensory exploitation
Coevolution can also occur within a species, especially in sexual
communication systems.
In many sexually reproducing species, males produce advertisement
signals that are specific to the species, and females are attracted
preferentially to males producing the conspecific signal in contrast to
males that would produce signals of other species. The evolution of
such mate recognition systems is a critical part of the speciation
process. In one simple scenario of how speciation comes about,
imagine that the range of an ancestral species becomes split by a
geographic barrier resulting in two isolated populations.
Reproductive interactions are constrained to individuals on either
side of the barrier. These populations become different in various
aspects of their phenotype, including the mate recognition system,
due to random genetic drift or local adaptation. Eventually the
populations differ to a degree that they no longer recognize their
former conspecifics as appropriate mates. Speciation has occurred
(Mayr 1942).
During the process of speciation there is often evolution of a new
communication system that recognizes mates. For this to happen, it
is thought there must be a change not only in the signal used by
males but also in the females’ perception of that signal. Many studies
have shown that various aspects of the receivers’ neural systems are
tuned or biased to properties of the species-specific signal, whether it
be in the auditory, visual, chemosensory or electrical-reception
modality (Ryan & Wilczynski 2011).
Sexual selection is responsible for the evolution of exaggerated male,
and sometimes female, traits that enhance an individual’s ability to
acquire mates even if the exaggerated traits reduce survivorship.
Sometimes the exaggerated traits give the bearer armaments that are
used in combat, but in many cases the elaboration involves
ornaments that males use to attract females. Although sexual
selection can be important in driving evolution of traits used in
species recognition (Lande 1982; West Eberhard 1983), much of the
interest in sexual selection is in trying to explain the evolution of
exaggerated traits within a lineage.
A central focus in the study of sexual selection is understanding why
females would prefer males with traits that reduce survivorship,
especially in mating systems in which males offer no resources to
females but their sperm (see also Chapter 12). Two hypotheses have
received most of the attention: the good genes theory and
Fisher’s theory of runaway sexual selection. Both hypotheses
posit that the variation in the genes underlying the male trait and the
female preference become correlated, and that evolution of the male
trait in response to female preference generates correlated evolution
of the preference itself. Thus, tight coevolution of the trait and
preference should be apparent. A third hypothesis is sensory
exploitation. This hypothesis states that females will have general
sensory or perceptual biases, as detailed by the more general theory
of sensory drive, and that males who evolve traits that exploit these
biases will be favored by sexual selection.
The two hypotheses of coevolution can be distinguished from that of
sensory exploitation if one can reconstruct the evolution of sexual
selected traits and female preferences for those traits. If the trait is
restricted to one lineage but the preference for that trait
encompasses not only the lineage with the trait but others without it,
then the most logical interpretation is that the preference existed
prior to the trait. If the preference, however, is restricted to the
lineage in which the trait is present, then the coevolution hypotheses
are more tenable (Ryan 1990, 1998).
This approach to sexual selection was initially taken in two groups of
animals, swordtail fishes (Xiphophorus helleri, Basolo 1990) and
túngara frogs (Physalaemus pustulosus, Ryan et al. 1990). Female
swordtails prefer males with longer swords, an elaboration of the
bottom rays of the caudal fin. At the time of the experiments,
swordtails were thought to be a monophyletic group consisting of
two smaller groups, northern swordtails and southern swordtails. A
third group, the platyfish, is a monophyletic group belonging to the
same genus. Male platys lack swords, but Basolo showed that if she
appended a plastic sword to a male platyfish his own females found
him more attractive. Experiments with another fish, Priapella
olmacae, added further support to this hypothesis. This fish is in a
genus closely related to Xiphophorus but which, like platyfish, has
swordless males. And like platyfish, they have females that prefer
swords (Basolo 1995).
A similar result was found in a very different mating system that
relies on acoustic rather than visual cues. Male túngara frogs
produce a call consisting of a whine and from 0–6 chucks. Females
prefer males with chucks and the larger males that make lower
frequency chucks. Except for its sister species P. petersi, all other
Physalaemus species (> 30 known species) lack chucks, so the chuck
seems to have been derived from the ancestor of these two species.
But females of a closely related species, P. coloradorum, prefer the
whines of their own species when a three-chuck component of the
túngara frog is appended to the normal chuckless call more so than
their own normal, chuckless whines. But the preference for chucks is
not apparent in response to a whine with one chuck (Ron 2008).
Thus, it appears that among some Physalaemus there is a
preexisting bias for chucks and male túngara frogs evolved chucks to
exploit that bias (Ryan & Rand 1993). There is also a more subtle
exploitation going on. The relationship between the tuning of one of
the frog’s two inner ear organs and the frequencies in the chuck
results in female túngara frogs preferring the lower-frequency chucks
of larger males. Other species of Physalaemus in the same species
group, however, all have similar tuning properties (Ryan et al. 1990;
Wilczynski et al. 2001). Thus, it seems that the properties of the
chuck evolved to match what is a very conservative feature of this
animal’s neurobiology. Again, this is an example in which the
importance of phylogenetic inference in providing a deep
understanding of behavioral evolution should be clear. But it also
highlights the integrative nature of animal behavior in which
proximate and historical analyses are cross-illuminating (Ryan &
Wilczynski 2011).
Not only does the brain modulate the expression of behavior, it can
also drive its evolution. Furthermore, the brain evolves under a
variety of constraints and under selection in a variety of domains.
Sensory, perceptual, and cognitive biases in the brain should not be
expected to be optimal for all tasks in which it is involved (Ryan
2011). For example, the wavelengths of light to which an animal is
most sensitive is influenced to a great degree by the sensitivity of its
photopigments. Light sensitivity influences performance in many
tasks but optimal performance in each task might require different
wavelength sensitivity. It is not possible to know a priori if
photopigment sensitivities are optimized for one of several tasks or a
compromise among competing demands. Cummings (2007) showed,
for example, that photopigment sensitivity in surfperch is optimal for
discriminating foraging targets in the ambient light environment,
and this sensitivity, in turn, has driven the evolution of male
courtship colors. Numerous other examples of similar phenomena
are reviewed in Ryan and Cummings (2013).
It has long been known that the neural and cognitive mechanisms by
which signals are processed by a receiver can lead to the evolution of
elaborate or exaggerated signals without concomitant change in the
receiver. As noted above, this can happen to some extent in sexual
selection by sensory exploitation. This is best illustrated by
Tinbergen’s notion of the supernormal stimulus, which occurs when
a stimulus has some properties exaggerated relative to the normal
stimulus and because of this elicits a greater response from the
receiver (see also Chapter 2). Two examples from the early
ethological literature include male sticklebacks and their bright red
nuptial coloration rushing toward a large red postal van driving past
their aquarium (Tinbergen 1952), and oystercatchers preferentially
retrieving a large model of an egg back to their nests in preference to
the smaller, real egg that has been removed (Tinbergen 1951). There
are other types of stimulus–response patterns that suggest that
internal biases of animals can drive evolution in certain directions.
In a more artificial setting, pigeons can exhibit a well-known
psychological phenomenon called peak shift displacement
(Hanson 1959; Hogan et al. 1975; Staddon 1975). In these situations,
an animal is trained to a positive stimulus and a negative stimulus,
such as wavelength. Peak shift displacement occurs when in
subsequent trials the subject shows a greater positive response to a
novel stimulus that is less similar to the original negative stimulus
than one that is more similar to the positive stimulus. Analogous
situations occur in nature, as in some birds in which individuals
prefer to mate with those conspecifics who appear most different
from heterospecifics in order to avoid the costs of mating with
heterospecifics (Grant & Grant 2010). In another example, zebra
finches learn to discriminate sexes from experience with the different
beak colors of their mother and father, and later when mature males
prefer females as mates that are more extreme in their beak color
than their own mothers (Ten Cate et al. 2006). Ten Cate and Rowe
(2007) review many other natural tasks in which animal responses
involve peak shift displacement.
There are also biases in how animals perceive stimuli in relation to
that of others, such as in comparisons of quantity. For example,
Weber’s Law predicts that stimuli are compared based on
proportional rather than absolute differences, such that: ∆I/I = K,
where ∆I is the minimum difference required to discriminate two
stimuli of magnitude I, and K is a constant (Stevens 1975). Weber’s
Law could impose important limitations on the evolution of signal
elaboration as an ever-increasing magnitude of traits must evolve for
them to be perceived as different from the norm. This seems to be
true in preferences for call complexity in túngara frogs. As noted
above, females prefer males who produce chucks and the more
chucks the better. But female preference does not increase linearly
with chuck number. The differences in the strength of preference for
two chucks versus one, for example, is much stronger than the
preference for six chucks over five chucks. This pattern of preference
strength scales with chuck number as predicted by Weber’s Law
(Akre et al. 2011). Furthermore, this mode of preference does not
appear to be an adaptation for mate choice per se in túngara frogs.
Call complexity is under counterselection by predation by the frog-
eating bat, Trachops cirrhosus. The bats are able to locate calling
frogs passively by listening to the frog’s call, and the bats like the
female frogs also prefer calls with more chucks to fewer chucks. The
pattern of the bat’s preference for chuck number also follows a
Weber-like pattern that is indistinguishable from that of the female
frogs. Weber’s law has not been investigated extensively in
naturalistic settings, but Akre & Johansen (2014; Figure 15.7) argue
how it could play an important role in other domains besides sexual
selection, such as species recognition and host–parasite evolution in
cowbirds.
Figure 15.7 (top) Weber’s Law predicts that comparisons are
based on proportional rather than absolute differences. When this is
the case, the magnitude of the difference between two stimuli needed
for them to be perceived as different (just noticeable difference,
JND) is greater when the overall stimulus magnitude is greater, and
the JND is smaller when the overall magnitude of the stimuli are
smaller. (bottom) Weber’s Law could have important effects on the
evolution of sexually selected traits. In this hypothetical example,
female peahens prefer male peacocks with longer tails. But the same
increase in tail length that made a male more attractive when tails
were short does not endow a male with an attractiveness advantage
when tails are long. If genetic variation for tail length is exhausted or
the costs of increasing tail length are not sustainable, selection might
then favor other innovations, such as eye spots, that increase the
male’s attractiveness in another dimension (from Akre & Johnsen
2014).
Another biased transformation of nature into our perceptions occurs
with perceptual illusions. Kelley and Kelley (2014) make a strong
case for the importance of visual illusions driving the evolution of a
variety of animal phenotypes. The most convincing example deals
with how male bowerbirds arrange decorations around their bower.
Using stones, snails and a variety of other objects, males create an
avenue leading up to the bower, the male’s lair where he courts a
willing female. The objects are not arranged randomly, but the larger
objects are at the front of the avenue and the smaller ones closer to
the bower. The males are very particular about this; when
researchers rearrange the objects the males put them back where
they belong. This particular arrangement creates what is called
forced perspective. Any object at the far end of the bower will be
perceived as relatively larger than it is due to the smaller size of the
decorations at the avenue’s end near the bower.
Humans readily exploit forced perspective to manipulate what we
think we see. Hobbits and dwarves in a movie seem to be standing
with other characters but are actually some distance away to make
them appear smaller. The Cinderella Castle at Disney’s Magic
Kingdom looks larger because the proportion of structures get
smaller as the Castle becomes taller, thus they appear farther away
than they really are, the building taller than it really is. It seems
bowerbirds have cashed in on this same trick.
FURTHER READING
Lorenz (1958 (1967)) provides some instructive examples of how the
early ethologist explored patterns of evolution of homologous
behavior, while Greene (1994) offers a more recent as well as
insightful synopsis of the general issue of establishing behavioral
homology. Felsenstein’s (1985) independent contrast method was
critical for promoting the use of phylogenetic data to test hypotheses
of adaptation, while Thornton et al. (2003) reviews the use of
phylogenetic information to reconstruct ancestral characters of
hormone receptors and test the functionality of the ancestral
receptor. Ryan and Cummings (2013) review evidence for the role of
perceptual biases in driving signal evolution, and the textbook by
Ryan and Wilczynski (2011) emphasizes the importance of
integrative analyses in studies of animal behavior.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I thank Dave Hillis for discussion and Sofia Rodriguez and Alex
Jordan for comments on the manuscript.
REFERENCES
Akre, K.L., Farris, H.E., Lea, A.M., Page, R.A. & Ryan, M.J. 2011.
Signal perception in frogs and bats and the evolution of mating
signals. Science, 333, 752–3.
Akre, K.L. & Johnsen, S. 2014. Psychophysics and the evolution of
behavior. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 29, 291–300.
Archibald, J.K., Mort, M.E. & Crawford, D.J. 2003. Bayesian
inference of phylogeny: a non-technical primer. Taxon, 52, 87–
191.
Atz, J.W. 1970. The application of the idea of homology to behavior.
In: L.R. Aronson, E. Tobach, D.S. Lehrman & J.S. Rosenblatt
(eds.), Development and Evolution of Behavior, pp. 53–74. San
Francisco: Freeman.
Autumn, K., Ryan, M.J. & Wake, D.B. 2002. Integrating historical
and organismal biology enhances the study of adaptation.
Quarterly Review of Biology, 77, 383–408.
Baldwin, M.W., Toda, Y., Nakagita, T., et al. 2014. Evolution of sweet
taste perception in hummingbirds by transformation of the
ancestral umami receptor. Science, 345, 929–33.
Basolo, A.L. 1990. Female preference predates the evolution of the
sword in swordtail fish. Science, 250, 808–10.
Basolo, A.L. 1995. A further examination of a pre-existing bias
favouring a sword in the genus Xiphophorus. Animal Behaviour,
50, 365–75.
Blair, W.F. 1962. Non-morphological data in anuran classification.
Systematic Zoology, 11, 72–84.
Brennan, S.E. 1985. The caricature generator. Leonardo, 18, 170–8.
Bull, J.J. & Wichman, H.A. 2001. Applied evolution. Annual Review
of Ecology and Systematics, 32, 183–217.
Cooper, I.A., Brown, J.M. & Getty, T. 2016. A role for ecology in the
evolution of colour variation and sexual dimorphism in Hawaiian
damselflies. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 29, 418–27.
Cumming, J.M. 1994. Sexual selection and the evolution of dance fly
mating systems (Diptera: Empdidae: Empidinae). Canadian
Entomologist, 126, 907–20.
Cummings, M.E. 2007. Sensory trade‐offs predict signal divergence
in surfperch. Evolution, 61, 530–45.
Darwin, C. 1862. On the Various Contrivances by which Orchids are
Fertilized by Insects. London: John Murray.
Darwin, C. 1872. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and the
Animals. London: John Murray.
Dawkins, R. 1996. Climbing Mount Improbable. New York: Norton.
Dawkins, R. & Krebs, J.R. 1978. Animal signals: Information or
manipulation? In: J.R. Krebs & N.B. Davies (eds.), Behavioural
Ecology, An Evolutionary Approach, pp. 282–309. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Day, J.J., Upchurch, P., Norman, D.B., Gale, A.S. & Powell, H.P.
2002. Sauropod trackways, evolution, and behavior. Science, 296,
1659.
Dean, A.M. & Thornton, J.W. 2007. Mechanistic approaches to the
study of evolution: the functional synthesis. Nature Reviews
Genetics, 8, 675–88.
Drickamer, L.C. 2010. Animal behavior: The seventeenth to the
twentieth centuries. In: M.D. Breed & J. Moore (eds.),
Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior, volume 3, pp. 453–461.
Oxford: Academic Press.
Enquist, M. & Arak, A. 1993. Selection of exaggerated male traits by
female aesthetic senses. Nature, 361, 446–8.
Enquist, M. & Arak, A. 1998. Neural representation and the evolution
of signal form. In: R. Dukas (ed.), Cognitive Ecology, pp. 21–87.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Felsenstein, J. 1985. Phylogenies and the comparative method.
American Naturalist, 125, 1–15.
Fitch, W.M. 1971. Toward defining the course of evolution: minimum
change for a specific tree topology. Systematic Biology, 20, 406–
416.
Grant, B.R. & Grant, P.R. 2010. Songs of Darwin’s finches diverge
when a new species enters the community. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences USA, 107, 20156–63.
Greene, H.W. 1994. Homology and behavioral repertoires. In: B.K.
Hall (ed.), Homology: The Hierarchical Basis of Comparative
Biology, pp. 369–392. San Diego: Academic Press.
Hamilton, W.D. & Zuk, M. 1982. Heritable true fitness and bright
birds: a role for parasites? Science, 218, 384–7.
Hanson, H.M. 1959. Effects of discrimination training on stimulus
generalization. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 58, 321–34.
Harcourt, A.H., Harvey, P.H., Larson, S.G. & Short, R.V. 1981. Testis
weight, body weight and breeding system in primates. Nature,
293, 55–7.
Harvey, P.H. & May, R.M. 1989. Out for the sperm count. Nature,
337, 508–9.
Hauser, M.D., Yang, C., Berwick, R., et al. 2014. The mystery of
language evolution. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, Article 401.
Hogan, J.A., Kruijt, J.P. & Frijlink, J.A. 1975. Supernormality in a
learning situation. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 38, 212–8.
Horner, J.R. & Makela, R. 1979. Nest of juveniles provides evidence
of family structure among dinosaurs. Nature, 282, 296–8.
Houck, M., Gauthier, J.A. & Strauss, R.E. 1990. Allometric scaling in
the earliest. Archaeopteryx lithographica. Science, 247, 195–8.
Huxley, J. 1914. The courtship habits of the great crested grebe.
Porpodiceps cristatus. Proceeding of the Zoological Society,
London, 2, 491–562.
Johnson, K.P., McKinney, F., Wilson, R. & Sorenson, M.D. 2000.
The evolution of postcopulatory displays in dabbling ducks
(Anatini): a phylogenetic perspective. Animal Behaviour, 59,
953–63.
Kelley, L.A. & Kelley, J.L. 2014. Animal visual illusion and confusion:
the importance of a perceptual perspective. Behavioral Ecology,
25, 450–63.
Kessel, E.L. 1955. The mating activities of balloon flies. Systematic
Zoology, 4, 97–104.
Kirkpatrick, M. & Ryan, M.J. 1991. The evolution of mating
preferences and the paradox of the lek. Nature, 350, 33–8.
Lande, R. 1982. Rapid origin of sexual isolation and character
divergence in a cline. Evolution, 36, 213–23.
LeBas, N.R. & Hockham, L.R. 2005. An invasion of cheats: the
evolution of worthless nuptial gifts. Current Biology, 15, 64–7.
Lloyd, J.E. 1984. On deception, a way of all flesh, and firefly
signalling and systematics. Oxford Surveys in Evolutionary
Biology, 1, 48–84.
Lorenz, K. 1941 (1971). Comparative studies of the motor patterns of
Anatinae. In: R. Martin (ed.), Studies on Animal and Human
Behavior, vol. 2, pp. 14–114. London: Methuen.
Lorenz, K. 1958 (1967). The evolution of behavior. In: J.L. McGaugh,
N.M. Weinberger & R.E. Whalen (eds.), Psychobiology, The
Biological Bases of Behavior, Readings from Scientific American,
pp. 33–42. San Francisco: Freeman.
Machado, C., Robbins, N., Gilbert, T.P. & Herre, E.A. 2005. Critical
review of host specificity and its coevolutionary implications in
the fig/fig-wasp mutualism. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences USA, 102, 6558–65.
Machado, C.A., Jousselin, E., Kjellberg, F., Comptom, S.G. & Herre,
E.A. 2001. Phylogenetic relationships, historical biogeography
and character evolution of fig-pollinating wasps. Proceedings of
the Royal Society, London B, 268, 685–94.
Martins, E. (ed.) 1996. Phylogenies and the Comparative Method in
Animal Behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Max, D.T. 2008. A man of taste. The New Yorker, May 12.
Mayr, E. 1942. Systematics and the Origin of Species. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Muchhala, N. 2006. Nectar bat stows huge tongue in its rib cage.
Nature, 444, 701–2.
Nicholson, K.E., Harmon, L.J. & Losos, J.B. 2007. Evolution of
Anolis lizard dewlap diversity. PLoS One, 2, e274.
Odom, K.J., Hall, M.L., Riebel, K., Omland, K.E. & Langmore, N.E.
2014. Female song is widespread and ancestral in songbirds.
Nature Communications, 5, Article 3379.
Oliveira, R.F., Taborsky, M. & Brockmann, H.J. (eds.) 2008.
Alternative Reproductive Tactics: An Integrative Approach.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Padian, K. 2001. Cross-testing adaptive hypotheses: phylogenetic
analysis and the origin of bird flight. American Zoologist, 41,
598–607.
Pagel, M. 1999. The maximum likelihood approach to reconstructing
ancestral character states of discrete characters on phylogenies.
Systematic Biology, 48, 612–22.
Paradis, E. 2011. Analysis of Phylogenetics and Evolution with R.
New York: Springer.
Phelps, S.M. & Ryan, M.J. 2000. History influences signal
recognition: Neural network models of túngara frogs. Proceedings
of the Royal Society, London, B, 267, 1633–9.
Platt, J.R. 1964. Strong inference. Science, 46, 347–53.
Price, T. 1997. Correlated evolution and independent contrasts.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B, 352, 519–29.
Read, A.F. & Harvey, P.H. 1989. Reassessment of comparative
evidence for Hamilton and Zuk theory on the evolution of
secondary sexual characters. Nature, 339, 618–20.
Ron, S.R. 2008. The evolution of female mate choice for complex
calls in túngara frogs. Animal Behaviour, 76, 1783–94.
Ryan, M.J. 1990. Sensory systems, sexual selection, and sensory
exploitation. Oxford Surveys in Evolutionary Biology, 7, 157–95.
Ryan, M.J. 1996. Phylogenetics and behavior: some cautions and
expectations. In: E. Martins (ed.), Phylogenies and the
Comparative Method in Animal Behavior, pp. 1–21. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Ryan, M.J. 1998. Receiver biases, sexual selection and the evolution
of sex differences. Science, 281, 1999–2003.
Ryan, M.J. 2011. The brain as a source of selection on the social
niche: Examples from the psychophysics of mate choice in
túngara frogs. Integrative and Comparative Biology.
doi:10.1093/icb/icr065.
Ryan, M.J. & Cummings, M.E. 2013. Perceptual biases and mate
choice. Annual Review of Ecology, Evolution and Systematics,
44, 437–59.
Ryan, M.J., Fox, J.H., Wilczynski, W. & Rand, A.S. 1990. Sexual
selection for sensory exploitation in the frog. Physalaemus
pustulosus. Nature, 343, 66–7.
Ryan, M.J. & Rand, A.S. 1993. Sexual selection and signal evolution:
the ghost of biases past. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society, B, 340, 187–95.
Ryan, M.J. & Rand, A.S. 1995. Female responses to ancestral
advertisement calls in the túngara frog. Science, 269, 390–2.
Ryan, M.J. & Rand, A.S. 1999. Phylogenetic influences on mating call
preferences in female túngara frogs (Physalaemus pustulosus).
Animal Behaviour, 57, 945–56.
Ryan, M.J. & Wilczynski, W. 2011. An Introduction to Animal
Behavior, An Integrative Approach. Cold Spring Harbor, New
York: Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press.
Sakaluk, S.K. 2000. Sensory exploitation as an evolutionary origin to
nuptial food gifts in insects. Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London, B, 267, 339–43.
Schluter, D. & McPhail, J.D. 1992. Ecological character displacement
and speciation in sticklebacks. American Naturalist, 140, 85–108.
Staddon, J.E.R. 1975. A note on the evolutionary significance of
‘supernormal’ stimuli. The American Naturalist, 109, 541–5.
Stevens, S.S. 1975. Psychophysics. Transaction Publishers.
Ten Cate, C. & Rowe, C. 2007. Biases in signal evolution: learning
makes a difference. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 22, 380–7.
Ten Cate, C., Verzijden, M.N. & Etman, E. 2006. Sexual imprinting
can induce sexual preferences for exaggerated parental traits.
Current Biology, 16, 1128–32.
Thornton, J.W. 2004. Resurrecting ancient genes: experimental
analysis of extinct molecules. Nature Reviews Genetics, 5, 366–
75.
Thornton, J.W., Need, E. & Crews, D. 2003. Resurrecting the
ancestral steroid receptor: ancient origin of estrogen signaling.
Science, 301, 1714–7.
Tinbergen, N. 1951. The Study of Instinct. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Tinbergen, N. 1952. The curious behavior of the stickleback.
Scientific American, 187, 2–6.
Tinbergen, N. 1963. On aims and methods in ethology. Zeitschrift für
Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–33.
Tobias, J.A., Cornwallis, C.K., Derryberry, E.P., et al. 2014. Species
coexistence and the dynamics of phenotypic evolution in adaptive
radiation. Nature, 506, 359–63.
Weishampel, D.B. 1981. Acoustic analyses of potential vocalization in
lambeosaurine dinosaurs (Reptilia: Ornithischia). Paleobiology,
7, 252–61.
Wenzel, J.W. 1992. Behavioral homology and phylogeny. Annual
Review of Ecology and Systematics, 7, 361–81.
West Eberhard, M.J. 1983. Sexual selection, social competition and
speciation. Quarterly Review of Biology, 58, 155–83.
Wilczysnki, W., Rand, A.S. & Ryan, M.J. 2001. Evolution of calls and
auditory tuning in the Physalaemus pustulosus species group.
Brain, Behavior and Evolution, 58, 137–51.
Wiley, E.O. & Lieberman, B.S. 2011. Phylogenetics: Theory and
Practice of Phylogenetic Systematics. New York: Wiley.
Williams, G.C. 1966. Adaptation and Natural Selection: A Critique
of Some Current Evolutionary Thoughts. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Wimberger, P.H. & De Queiroz, A. 1996. Comparing behavioral and
morphological characters as indicators of phylogeny. In: E.
Martins (ed.), Phylogenies and the Comparative Method in
Animal Behavior, pp. 206–33. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
16
the evolution of hominin behavior
IAN TATTERSALL
INTRODUCTION
Human beings are very unusual creatures. Not only is their
upright bipedality a very unusual form of locomotion, with
enormous structural ramifications throughout the body, but they
process information about their exterior and interior
environments in an utterly unique way. Among all of the many
evolutionary alterations that occurred along the way to Homo
sapiens it is this latter acquisition that is the most astonishing,
and that was least predicted by anything that had gone before. In
this chapter, I look at what can be said about how a specialized
but otherwise unremarkable lineage of higher primates became
transformed into the altogether unprecedented cognitive entity
that our species is today. Using the modern African great apes as
a very approximate yardstick for gauging where the story begins,
the chapter surveys what can be gleaned of behavioral and
cognitive change over the seven- to eight-million-year history of
the subfamily Homininae to which our species Homo sapiens
belongs.
Primate Phylogeny
Australopithecus afarensis
The new body form was almost certainly implicated in the first
movement by hominins beyond the African continent. During the
australopith period hominins, while diversifying vigorously, had
remained confined to the continent of their birth. But by 1.8 myr ago
they had already penetrated as far as Dmanisi, a site in Georgia, just
to the east of the Black Sea (Lordkipanidze et al. 2013). And by not
long after that, they had reached all the way to eastern Asia, where
the iconic form Homo erectus is documented on the island of Java as
far back as 1.3 myr ago. Exactly what made hominins so
unprecedentedly mobile at this point is not known for sure, although
all hominins known from outside Africa have been attributed (rightly
or wrongly) to the genus Homo. This attribution is certainly not the
result of notably enlarged brains: the Dmanisi hominins, now known
from five skulls and two partial skeletons, all have brains in the
australopith-like 600 ml range (Figure 16.8). What’s more, brain size
is the main thing all the Dmanisi specimens have in common,
because in other respects quite diverse morphologies are
represented. Nonetheless, the entire assemblage has most recently
been attributed to a single “paleodeme” of the ubiquitous Homo
erectus (Lordkipanidze et al. 2013). Alternatively, the name Homo
georgicus is also available for them, in the unlikely event that all
belong to the same species.
Figure 16.8 Three-quarter view of the most distinctive hominid
cranium from Dmanisi, in the Republic of Georgia, holotype of
Homo georgicus. Approximately 1.8 million years old. Photo by
Jeffrey H. Schwartz.
Numerous stone artifacts are known from Dmanisi, and all are of the
ancient Oldowan kind. Improved technology thus does not seem to
be implicated in these hominins’ ability to leave the tropics and
penetrate the cooler temperate zone. And, to judge by the small brain
sizes of the hominins involved, neither does higher intelligence—if
indeed this quality maps efficiently onto brain size. Physically, this
leaves us only with the structure of the locomotor apparatus as a
potential explanation of the Dmanisi hominins’ remarkable mobility
—which will, it seems, remain the default explanation for the time
being. For, while the Dmanisi hominins all appear to have been of
rather short stature, their limb skeletons have been described as
more modern- than australopith-like. It is worth noting that an
external event such as a climatic amelioration might also have
permitted the ancestors of the Dmanisi hominins to expand beyond
Africa for the first time; but, however this colonization of new
environments was achieved, it is difficult based on the little we know
to find a specific behavioral explanation—either for the colonization
itself, or for the remarkable hominin adaptability it clearly implies.
The fossil and archaeological records both now suggest that
hominins had penetrated Europe, notably the Italian and Iberian
peninsulas, by about 1.4 myr ago (Bermudez de Castro et al. 2011)—
still in an Oldowan technological context. The Acheulean came late
to Europe, and barely managed to penetrate eastern Asia at all. As
might have been expected, both Europe and eastern Asia hosted
indigenous developments on the biological front, with Homo erectus
documented early on as a regional phenomenon in eastern China
and on Java, while the lineage leading to Homo neanderthalensis
was established in Europe well over 400 kyr ago.
FURTHER READING
Recent books on the subject by Ian Tattersall are Masters of the
Planet: The Search for Our Human Origins (2012), The Strange
Case of the Rickety Cossack and Other Cautionary Tales from
Human Evolution (2015), and (with Rob DeSalle) The Accidental
Homo sapiens: Genetics, Behavior, and Free Will (2019).
REFERENCES
Aiello, L. & Wheeler, P. 1995. The expensive-tissue hypothesis: The
brain and the digestive system in human and primate evolution.
Current Anthropology, 36, 199–221.
Aubert, M., Brumm, A., Ramli, M., et al. 2014. Pleistocene cave art
from Sulawesi, Indonesia. Nature, 514, 223–7.
Aubert, M., Setiawan, P., Oktaviana, A.A., et al. 2018. Palaeolithic
cave art in Borneo. Nature, 564, 254–7.
Bermúdez De Castro, J.M., Martinon-Torres, M., Gómez-Robles, A.,
et al. 2011. Early Pleistocene human mandible from Sima del
Elefante (TE) cave site in Sierra de Atapuerca (Spain): A
comparative morphological study. Journal of Human Evolution,
61, 12–25.
Berna, F., Goldberg, P., Horwitz, L.K., et al. 2012. Microstratigraphic
evidence of in situ fire in the Acheulean strata of Wonderwerk
Cave, Northern Cape province, South Africa. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences, USA, 109(20), 1215–20.
Bouzouggar, A., Barton, N., Vanhaeren, M., et al. 2007. 82,000-year-
old shell beads from North Africa and implications for the origins
of modern human behavior. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA, 104, 9964–9.
Brown, K.S., Marean, C.W., Herries, A.I.R., et al 2009. Fire as an
engineering tool of early modern humans. Science, 325, 859–62.
Chan, E.K.F., Timmermann, A., Baldi, B.F., Moore, A.E., et al. 2019.
Human origins in a southern African palaeo-wetland and first
migrations. Nature, 575, 185–189. 10.1038/s41586-019-1714-1.
Cohen, J. 2010. Almost Chimpanzee: Searching for What Makes Us
Human in Rainforests, Labs, Sanctuaries, and Zoos. New York:
Times Books/Henry Holt.
d’Errico, F. & Nowel, A. 2000. A new look at the Berekhat Ram
figurine: implications for the origins of symbolism. Cambridge
Archaeological Journal, 10, 123–67.
d’Errico, F., Salomon, H., Vignaud, C. & Stringer, C. 2010. Pigments
from Middle Paleolithic levels of es-Skhūl (Mount Carmel, Israel).
Journal of Archaeological Science, 37, 3099–3110.
De Lumley, H. & Boone, Y. 1976. Les structures d’habitat au
Paléolithique inférieur. In: H. De Lumley (ed.), La Préhistoire
française, vol. 1, pp. 635–43. Paris: CNRS.
Dean, M.C. & Smith, H. 2009. Growth and development of the
Nariokotome Youth, KNM-WT 15000. In: F.E. Grine (ed.), Origin
and Early Evolution of the Genus Homo, pp. 101–20. Heidelberg:
Springer.
Eldredge, N. 1995. Dominion. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Fleagle, J.G. 2013. Primate Adaptation and Evolution, 3rd ed. San
Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Gibbons, A. 2006. The First Human: The Race to Discover Our
Earliest Ancestors. New York: Doubleday.
Graves, R.R., Lupo, A.C., McCarthy, R.C., Wescott, D.J. &
Cunningham, D.L. 2010. Just how strapping was KNM-
WT15000? Journal of Human Evolution, 59, 542–54.
Green, R.E., Krause, J., Briggs, A.W., et al. 2010. A draft sequence of
the Neandertal genome. Science, 328, 710–22.
Harcourt-Smith, W.E.H. 2014. Origin of bipedal locomotion. In: W.
Henke & I. Tattersall (eds.), Handbook of Paleoanthropology, vol.
3, pp. 1919–60. Heidelberg and New York: Springer.
Harmand, S., Lewis, J.E., Feibel, C.S., Lepre, C.J., et al. 2015. 3.3-
million-year-old stone tools from Lomekwi 3, West Turkana,
Kenya. Nature, 521, 310–6.
Hart, D. & Sussman, R.W. 2009. Man the Hunted: Primates,
Predators, and Human Evolution, Expanded Edition ed. Boulder,
CO: Westview Press.
Henshilwood, C.S., d’Errico, F., Yates, R., et al. 2002. Emergence of
modern human behavior: Middle Stone Age engravings from
South Africa. Science, 295, 1278–80.
Hoffmann, D.L., Standish, C.D., Pettitt, P.B., et al. 2018. U-Th dating
of carbonate crusts reveals Neandertal origin of Iberian cave art.
Science, 359, 912–5.
Holloway, R.L., Broadfield, D.C. & Yuan, M.S. 2004. The Human
Fossil Record, Vol. 3: Hominid Endocasts, The Paleoneurological
Evidence. New York: Wiley-Liss.
Johanson, D.J. & Edgar, B. 2006. From Lucy to Language, 2nd ed.
New York: Simon and Schuster.
Kano, F., Krupenye, C., Satoshi Hirata, S., Tomonaga, N. & Call, J.
2019. Great apes use self-experience to anticipate an agent’s
action in a false-belief test. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences USA, 116, 20904–9.
Klein, R. 2009. The Human Career: Human Biological and Cultural
Origins, 3rd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Krause, J., Fu, Q., Good, J.M., Viola, B., Shunkov, M.V., Derevianko,
A.P. & Pääbo, S. 2010. The complete mitochondrial DNA genome
of an unknown hominin from southern Siberia. Nature,
464(7290), 894–7.
Krupenye, C., Kano, F., Hirata, S., Call, J. & Tomasello, C. 2016.
Great apes anticipate that other individuals will act according to
false beliefs. Science, 354, 110–4.
Lepre, C.J., Roche, H., Kent, D.V., et al. 2011. An earlier origin for
the Acheulian. Nature, 477, 82–5.
Lordkipanidze, D., Ponce De León, M.S., Margvelashvili, A., et al.
2013. A complete skull from Dmanisi, Georgia, and the
evolutionary biology of early Homo. Science, 342, 326–31.
McDougall, I., Brown, F.H. & Fleagle, J.G. 2005. Stratigraphic
placement and age of modern humans from Kibish, Ethiopia.
Nature, 433, 733–6.
McPherron, S., Alemseged, Z., Marean, C.W., et al. 2010. Evidence
for stone-tool-assisted consumption of animal tissues before 3.39
million years ago at Dikika, Ethiopia. Nature, 466, 857–60.
Newton-Fisher, N.E. 2014. The hunting behavior and carnivory of
wild chimpanzees. In: W. Henke & I. Tattersall (eds.), Handbook
of Paleoanthropology, 2nd ed., vol. 2, pp. 1661–92. Heidelberg
and New York: Springer.
Ohnuma, K., Aoki, K. & Akazawa, T. 1997. Transmission of tool-
making through verbal and non-verbal communication:
Preliminary experiments in Levallois flake production.
Anthropological Science, 105(3), 159–68.
Plummer, T. 2004. Flaked stones and old bones: Biological and
cultural evolution at the dawn of technology. Yearbook of
Physical Anthropology, 47, 118–64.
Povinelli, D.J. 2004. Behind the ape’s appearance: Escaping
anthropocentrism in the study of other minds. Daedalus, 133(1),
29–41.
Radovčić, D., Sršen, A.O., Radovčić, J. & Frayer, D.W. 2015.
Evidence for Neandertal jewelry: Modified White-tailed Eagle
claws at Krapina. PLoS One, 10(3), e0119802.
Roebroeks, W. & Villa, P. 2011. On the earliest evidence for habitual
use of fire in Europe. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences USA, 108(13), 5209–14.
Roth, G. & Dicke, U. 2005. Evolution of the brain and intelligence.
Trends in Cognitive Science, 9(5), 250–7.
Semaw, S. 2000. The world’s earliest stone artifacts from Gona,
Ethiopia: Their implications for understanding stone technology
and patterns of human evolution between 2.6-1.5 million years
ago. Journal of Archaeological Science, 27, 1197–1214.
Senghas, A. & Coppola, M. 2001. Children creating sign language.
Psychological Science, 12(4), 323–8.
Slimak, L., Fietzke, J., Geneste, J.-M. & Ontanon, R. 2018. Comment
on “U-Th dating of carbonate crusts reveals Neandertal origin of
Iberian cave art.” Science, 361, 912–5.
Sponheimer, M. & Lee-Thorp, J. 2014. Hominin paleodiets: The
contribution of stable isotopes. In: W. Henke & I. Tattersall (eds.),
Handbook of Paleoanthropology, 2nd ed., vol. 1, pp. 671–702.
Heidelberg: Springer.
Tattersall, I. 1998. The origin of the human capacity. New York:
American Museum of Natural History (James Arthur Lecture
series).
Tattersall, I. 2012. Masters of the Planet: In Search of Our Human
Origins. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Tattersall, I. 2018. Brain size and the emergence of modern human
cognition. In: J.H. Schwartz (ed.), Rethinking Human Evolution,
pp. 319–34. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Texier, P.J., Porraz, G., Parkington, J., et al. 2010. A Howiesons
Poort tradition of engraving ostrich eggshell containers dated to
60,000 years ago at Diepkloof Rock Shelter, South Africa.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 107,
6180–5.
Thieme, H. 1997. Lower Palaeolithic hunting spears from Germany.
Nature, 385, 807–10.
Toth, N., Schick, K.D., Savage-Rumbaugh, E.S., Sevcik, R.A. &
Rumbaugh, D.M. 1993. Pan the toolmaker: Investigations into the
stone tool-making and tool-using capabilities of a bonobo (Pan
paniscus). Journal of Archaeological Science, 20, 81–91.
Van Couvering, J.A. 2014. Quaternary geology and
paleoenvironment. In: W. Henke & I. Tattersall (eds.), Handbook
of Paleoanthropology, 2nd ed., vol. 1, pp. 537–56. Heidelberg and
New York: Springer.
Vanhaeren, M., d’Errico, F., Stringer, C., et al. 2006. Middle
Paleolithic shell beads in Israel and Algeria. Science, 312, 1785–8.
Walker, A.C. & Leakey, R.E.F. 1993. The Nariokotome Homo erectus
skeleton. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
White, T.D., Asfaw, B., DeGusta, D., et al. 2003. Pleistocene Homo
sapiens from Middle Awash, Ethiopia. Nature, 423, 742–7.
Wrangham, R. 2009. Catching Fire: How Cooking Made Us
Human. New York: Basic Books.
Wu, L., Martinon-Torres, M., Cai, Y.-J. & Xing, S. 10 others. 2015.
The earliest unequivocally modern humans in southern China.
Nature, 526, 596–600.
Zink, K.D. & Lieberman, D.E. 2016. Impact of meat and Lower
Paleolithic food processing techniques on chewing in humans.
Nature, 531, 139–44.
17
evolutionary approaches to human behavior
GILLIAN R. BROWN, CATHARINE P. CROSS, AND KEVIN N.
LALAND
INTRODUCTION
In this chapter, we overview how evolutionary theory has been
applied to investigate human behavior and cognition, examining
whether human beings can be studied in the same way as any
other species of animal. Charles Darwin proposed that natural
selection and sexual selection could act on our behavioral traits,
just as on our physical traits, and argued that human beings
should not be considered as separate from the rest of the animal
kingdom. In the first half of this chapter, we briefly review the
history of applying evolutionary theory to human behavior from
Darwin to the present day, highlighting recurrent controversies
such as the “nature versus nurture” debate. During the 1950s,
ethologists applied their methodologies to human behavioral
traits, and the advent of sociobiology in the 1970s prompted a
further rush of evolutionary hypotheses for human behavior,
leading to vocal criticism from some opponents. Subsequently, a
number of modern sub-fields have emerged, including Human
Behavioral Ecology, Evolutionary Psychology, and Cultural
Evolution. We provide examples of research within these sub-
fields and evaluate the strengths and weaknesses of each
approach, before examining whether the core assumptions of
these sub-fields are complementary or contradictory. In the
second half of this chapter, we critically evaluate the assumption
that human beings can be studied as if they were any other
animal species. Human beings are potentially different from
other animals in terms of (i) their reliance on culture and the
extent to which human beings modify their selective
environments, and (ii) the fidelity, efficiency, and breadth of
information transfer, which is enhanced by language and
teaching. Other animal species modify their environments and
exhibit social learning, but not to the same extent as human
beings, and we provide examples of how our cultural traits have
altered selection pressures on the human genome. Language and
teaching capacities of human beings are clearly more potent than
related systems in other species, and human beings exhibit high
levels of cooperation, with potential implications for the
evolutionary trajectory of our species. We conclude that human
behavior is often on a continuum with other animals but is also
distinctive in some important respects, and that certain aspects of
our cognition have dramatically affected the selection pressures
acting on the human mind. Finally, we argue that the resolution
of current debates surrounding the evolution of human behavior
will enhance our understanding of the behavior of nonhuman
animals.
FURTHER READING
Laland, K. N. & Brown, G. R. 2011. Sense and Nonsense:
Evolutionary Perspectives on Human Behaviour, 2nd ed.
REFERENCES
Archer, J. 2009. Does sexual selection explain human sex differences
in aggression? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 249–66.
Avital, E. & Jablonka, E. 2000. Animal Traditions: Behavioural
Inheritance in Evolution. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press.
Basalla, G. 1988. The Evolution of Technology. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Bateman, A.J. 1948. Intra-sexual selection in Drosophila. Heredity,
2, 349–68.
Bickerton, D. 2010. Adam’s Tongue: How Humans Made Language,
How Language Made Humans. New York: Hill and Wang.
Bjorklund, D.F. & Kipp, K. 1996. Parental investment theory and
gender differences in the evolution of inhibition mechanisms.
Psychological Bulletin, 120, 163–88.
Blackmore, S. 1999. The Meme Machine. Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press.
Blackwell, E.B. 1875. The Sexes throughout Nature. New York: G.P.
Putnam’s Sons.
Boakes, R. 1984. From Darwin to Behaviourism: Psychology and
the Minds of Animals. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press.
Boogert, N.J., Madden, J.R., Morand-Ferron, J. & Thornton, A.
2018. Measuring and understanding individual differences in
cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 373,
20170280.
Bowlby, J. 1969. Attachment and Loss: Volume 1 Attachment.
London: Hogarth Press.
Boyd, R. 2017. A Different Kind of Animal. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Boyd, R., Gintis, H., Bowles, S. & Richerson, P.J. 2003. The evolution
of altruistic punishment. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences USA, 100, 3531–5.
Brown, G.R., Dickins, T., Sear, R. & Laland, K.N. 2011. Evolutionary
accounts of human behavioural diversity. Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society B, 366, 313–24.
Brown, G.R., Laland, K.N. & Borgerhoff Mulder, M. 2009. Bateman’s
principles and human sex roles. Trends in Ecology and Evolution,
24, 297–304.
Brown, G.R. & Richerson, P. 2014. Applying evolutionary theory to
human behaviour: past differences and current debates. Journal
of Bioeconomics, 16, 105–28.
Brüne, M. & Schiefenhövel, W. (eds.) 2019. The Oxford Handbook of
Evolutionary Medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bshary, R., Gingins, S. & Vail, A.L. 2014. Social cognition in fishes.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18, 465–71.
Buller, D.J. 2006. Adapting Minds: Evolutionary Psychology and
the Persistent Quest for Human Nature. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Buss, D.M. (ed.) 2015. The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology,
2nd ed., 2 vols. New York: Wiley.
Campbell, A. 1999. Staying alive: Evolution, culture, and women’s
intrasexual aggression. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 203–
52.
Caro, T. M. & Hauser, M. D. 1992. Is there teaching in nonhuman
animals? Quarterly Review of Biology, 67, 151–174.
Chudek, M. & Henrich, J. 2011. Culture-gene coevolution, norm-
psychology and the emergence of human prosociality. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, 15, 218–26.
Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. 1987. From evolution to behavior:
evolutionary psychology as the missing link. In: J. Dupré (ed.),
The Latest on the Best: Essays on Evolution and Optimality.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cronk, L. 1991. Human behavioral ecology. Annual Review of
Anthropology, 20, 25–53.
Cross, C.P., Copping, L.T. & Campbell, A. 2011. Sex differences in
impulsivity: a meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 137, 97–130.
Cross, C.P., Cyrenne, D.L.M. & Brown, G.R. 2013. Sex differences in
sensation-seeking: a meta-analysis. Scientific Reports, 3, 2486.
Daly, M. & Wilson, M. 1985. Child abuse and other risks of not living
with both parents. Ethology and Sociobiology, 6, 197–210.
Daly, M. & Wilson, M. 2005. The ‘Cinderella effect' is no fairy tale.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9, 507–508.
Damasio, A. & Carvalho, G.B. 2013. The nature of feelings:
evolutionary and neurobiological origins. Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 14, 143–52.
Darwin, C. 1859. The Origin of Species by Means of Natural
Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle
for Life. London: John Murray. (1st edition reprint, London:
Penguin Books, 1968).
Darwin, C. 1871. The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to
Sex. John Murray; London (1st edition reprint, Princeton NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1981).
Darwin, C. 1872. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and
Animals. London: John Murray. (3rd edition reprint, London:
Harper-Collins, 1998).
Dawkins, R. 1976. The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dean, L., Vale, G., Laland, K., Flynn, E. & Kendal, R. 2014. Human
cumulative culture: a comparative perspective. Biological
Reviews, 89, 284–301.
Dean, L.G., Kendal, R.L., Schapiro, S.J., Thierry, B. & Laland, K.N.
2012. Identification of the social and cognitive processes
underlying human cumulative culture. Science, 335, 1114–8.
Dennett, D. 1995. Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the
Meanings of Life. London: Penguin Books.
Desmond, A. & Moore, J. 2009. Darwin’s Sacred Cause: Race,
Slavery and the Quest for Human Origins. London: Penguin
Books.
Dindo, M., Whiten, A. & De Waal, F.B.M. 2009. In-group conformity
sustains different foraging traditions in capuchin monkeys (Cebus
apella). PLoS ONE, 4, e7858.
Dunbar, 1997. Grooming, Gossip, and the Evolution of Language.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Durham, W.H. 1991. Coevolution: Genes, Culture and Human
Diversity. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Durrant, R. & Ward, T. 2015. Evolutionary Criminology: Towards a
Comprehensive Explanation of Crime. London: Academic Press.
Ekman, P. 1994. Strong evidence for universals in facial expressions:
a reply to Russell’s mistaken critique. Psychological Bulletin, 115,
268–87.
Elfenbein, H.A. & Ambady, N. 2002. On the universality and cultural
specificity of emotion recognition: a meta-analysis. Psychological
Bulletin, 128, 203–35.
Ellegren, H. 2005. Natural selection in the evolution of humans and
chimps. Current Biology, 15, R919–922.
Emery, N.J. & Clayton, N.S. 2004. The mentality of crows:
convergent evolution of intelligence in corvids and apes. Science,
306, 1903–7.
Fehr, E. & Rockenbach, B. 2004. Human altruism: economic, neural,
and evolutionary perspectives. Current Opinion in Neurobiology,
14, 784–90.
Fitch, W.T. 2010. The Evolution of Language. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Flynn, E.G., Laland, K.N., Kendal, R.L. & Kendal, J.R. 2013.
Developmental niche construction. Developmental Science, 16,
296–313.
Fogarty, L., Strimling, P. & Laland, K.N. 2011. The evolution of
teaching. Evolution, 65, 2760–70.
Foley, R. 1995. The adaptive legacy of human evolution: a search for
the environment of evolutionary adaptedness. Evolutionary
Anthropology, 6, 194–203.
Fragaszy, D.M. & Perry, S. (eds.) 2003. The Biology of Traditions:
Models and Evidence. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press.
Gangestad, S.W. & Simpson, J.A. 2000. The evolution of human
mating: trade-offs and strategic pluralism. Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 23, 573–644.
Gerbault, P., Liebert, A., Itan, Y. et al. 2011. Evolution of lactase
persistence: an example of human niche construction.
hilosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 366, 863–77.
Gerbault, P., Roffet-Salque, M., Evershed, R.P. & Thomas, M.G.
2013. How long have adult humans been consuming milk?
IUBMB Life, 65, 983–90.
Gluckman, P.D., Hanson, M.A. & Spencer, H.G. 2005. Predictive
adaptive responses and human evolution. Trends in Ecology and
Evolution, 20, 527–33.
Goodman, M. 1999. The genomic record of humankind’s
evolutionary roots. American Journal of Human Genetics, 64, 31–
9.
Güntürkün, O. & Bugnyar, T. 2016. Cognition without cortex. Trends
in Cognitive Sciences, 20, 291–303.
amlin, K.A. 2014. From Eve to Evolution: Darwin, Science, and
Women’s Rights in Gilded Age America. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Henrich, J. 2016. The Secret of Our Success: How Culture is Driving
Human Evolution, Domesticating our Species, and Making us
Smarter. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S. et al. 2001. In search of Homo
economicus: behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale societies.
American Economic Review, 91, 73–7.
Herrmann, E., Call, J., Hernàndez-Lloreda, M.V., Hare, B. &
Tomasello, M. 2007. Humans have evolved specialized skills of
social cognition: the cultural intelligence hypothesis. Science, 317,
1360–6.
Hinde, R.A. 1966. Animal Behaviour: a Synthesis of Ethology and
Comparative Psychology. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Hinde, R.A. 1974. Biological Bases of Human Social Behaviour. New
York: McGraw-Hill.
Hoppitt, W.J.E., Brown, G.R., Kendal, R. et al. 2008. Lessons from
animal teaching. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 23, 486–93.
Hoppitt, W.J.E. & Laland, K.N. 2013. Social Learning: Mechanisms,
Methods and Models. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hrdy, S.B. 1981. The Woman that Never Evolved. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Hrdy, S.B. 1999. Mother Nature: Natural Selection and the Female
of the Species. London: Chatto and Windus.
Hull, D.L., Langman, R.E. & Glenn, S.S. 2001. A general account of
selection: biology, immunology, and behavior. Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 24, 511–73.
Huxley, T.H. 1863. Evidence as to Man’s Place in Nature. London:
Williams and Norgate.
Ingold, T. 2007. The trouble with ‘evolutionary biology’.
Anthropology Today, 23, 13–7.
Jensen, K., Call, J. & Tomasello, M. 2007. Chimapnzees are rational
maximizers in an ultimatum game. Science, 318, 107–9.
Kingsolver, J.G., Hoekstra, H.E., Hoekstra, J.M. et al. 2001. The
strength of phenotypic selection in natural populations. American
Naturalist, 157, 245–61.
Kokko, H. & Monaghan, P. 2001. Predicting the direction of sexual
selection. Ecology Letters, 4, 159–65.
Kossinets, G. & Watts, D.J. 2006. Empirical analysis of an evolving
social network. Science, 311, 88–90.
Laland, K.N. 2017. Darwin’s Unfinished Symphony: How Culture
Made the Human Mind. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Laland, K.N. & Brown, G.R. 2006. Niche construction, human
behaviour and the adaptive-lag hypothesis. Evolutionary
Anthropology, 15, 95–104.
Laland, K.N., Odling-Smee, F.J. & Feldman, M.W. 2001. Cultural
niche construction and human evolution. Journal of Evolutionary
Biology, 14, 22–33.
Laland, K.N., Odling-Smee, F.J. & Myles, S. 2010. How culture has
shaped the human genome: bringing genetics and the human
sciences together. Nature Reviews: Genetics, 11, 137–48.
Laland, K.N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, J., Hoppitt, W. & Uller, T.
2011. Cause and effect in biology revisited: Is Mayr’s proximate-
ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science, 334, 1512–6.
Lewis, H.M. & Laland, K.N. 2012. Transmission fidelity is the key to
the build-up of complex culture. Philosophical Transaction of the
Royal Society B, 367, 2171–80.
Li, N.P., Van Vugt, M. & Colarelli, S.M. 2018. The evolutionary
mismatch hypothesis: implications for psychological science.
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 27, 38–44.
Lorenz, K. 1935. Der Kumpan in der umwelt des vogels: der
artgenosse als auslösendes moment sozialer verhaltungsweisen.
[The companion in the bird’s world: fellow members of the
species as releasers of social behaviour]. Journal für Ornithologie,
83, 137–213.
Lorenz, K. 1966. On Aggression. London: Methuen (reprinted in
1996 by Routledge).
Mathew, S. & Perreault, C. 2016. Cultural history, not ecological
environment, is the main determinant of human behavior.
Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 283, 1826.
Mayr, E. 1961. Cause and effect in biology. Science, 134, 1501–6.
Mesoudi, A. 2011. Cultural Evolution: How Darwinian Theory Can
Explain Human Culture and Synthesize the Social Sciences.
Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Mesoudi, A. & Thornton, A. 2018. What is cumulative cultural
evolution? Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 285, 20180712.
Monaghan, P. & Birkhead, T. 2001. Spot the difference. Trends in
Ecology and Evolution, 16, 527.
Morgan, T.J.H., Uomini, N.T., Rendell, L.E. et al. 2015. Experimental
evidence for the co-evolution of hominin tool-making, teaching
and language. Nature Communications, 6, 6029.
Morris, D. 1967. The Naked Ape. London: Vintage.
Nettle, D. 2009. Ecological influences on human behavioural
diversity: a review of recent findings. Trends in Ecology and
Evolution, 24, 618–24.
Nettle, D., Gibson, M.A., Lawson, D.W. & Sear, R. 2013. Human
behavioral ecology: current research and future prospects.
Behavioral Ecology, 24, 1031–1340.
Nowak, M. & Highfield, R. 2011. Supercooperators: Evolution,
Altruism and Human Behaviour or, Why We Need Each Other to
Succeed. New York: Canongate Books.
Nowak, M.A., Tarnita, C.E. & Wilson, E.O. 2010. The evolution of
eusociality. Nature, 466, 1057–62.
Odling-Smee, F.J., Laland, K.N. & Feldman, M.W. 2003. Niche
Construction: The Neglected Process in Evolution. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Owens, I.P.F. 2006. Where is behavioural ecology going? Trends in
Ecology and Evolution, 21, 356–61.
Pagel, M. 2012. Wired for Culture: The Natural History of Human
Cooperation. London: Allen Lang.
Pagel, M., Atkinson, W.D. & Meade, A. 2007. Frequency of word-use
predicts rates of lexical evolution throughout Indo-European
history. Nature, 449, 717–20.
Panksepp, J. 2011. The basic emotional circuits of mammalian
brains: do animals have affective lives? Neuroscience and
Biobehavioral Reviews, 35, 1791–1804.
Plotkin, H. 1994. Darwin Machines and the Nature of Knowledge.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rapaport, L.M. & Brown, G.R. 2008. Social influences on foraging
behaviour in young non-human primates: learning what, where,
and how to eat. Evolutionary Anthropology, 17, 189–201.
Rendell, L. & Whitehead, H. 2001. Culture in whales and dolphins.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 309–24.
Richerson, P.J. & Boyd, R. 2005. Not by Genes Alone: How Culture
Transformed Human Evolution. Chicago: Chicago University
Press.
Richerson, P.J., Boyd, R. & Henrich, J. 2010. Gene-culture
coevolution in the age of genomics. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences USA, 107, 8985–92.
Ridley, M. 2010. The Rational Optimist: How Prosperity Evolves.
New York: Harper.
Rose, S., Lewontin, R.C. & Kamin, L.J. 1984. Not in Our Genes:
Biology, Ideology, and Human Nature. London: Penguin Books.
Roth, A.E., Prasnikar, V., Okuno-Fujiwara, M. & Zamir, S. 1991.
Bargaining and market behavior in Jerusalem, Ljubljana,
Pittsburgh, and Tokyo: an experimental study. American
Economic Review, 81, 1068–95.
Searcy, W.A. & Nowicki, S. 2005. The Evolution of Animal
Communication. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Seed, A. & Byrne, R. 2010. Animal tool-use. Current Biology, 20,
R1032–9.
Seed, A.M. & Mayer, C. 2017 Problem-solving in animals. In J. Call,
G.M. Burghardt, I.M. Pepperberg, C.T. Snowdon & T.R. Zentall
(eds.), APA Handbook of Comparative Psychology, pp. 601–25.
Washington: American Psychological Association.
Segerstråle, U.S. 2000. Defenders of the Truth: The Sociobiology
Debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Seyfarth, R.M., Cheney, D.L. & Marler, P. 1980. Vervet monkey
alarm calls: semantic communication in a free-ranging primate.
Animal Behaviour, 28, 1070–94.
Siepielski, A.M., DiBattista, J.D., Evans, J.A. & Carlson, S.M. 2011.
Differences in the temporal dynamics of phenotypic selection
among fitness components in the wild. Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London B, 278, 1572–80.
Smith, B. 2007. Human niche construction and the behavioural
context of plant and animal domestication. Evolutionary
Anthropology, 16, 188–99.
Smith, E.A., Bliege Bird, R. & Bird, D.W. 2003. The benefits of costly
signaling: Meriam turtle hunters. Behavioral Ecology, 14, 116–26.
Somel, M., Liu, X. & Khaitovich, P. 2013. Human brain evolution:
transcripts, metabolites and their regulators. Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 14, 112–27.
Spencer, H. 1855, 1870. Principles of Psychology. (1st edn., 2nd
edn.) London: Longman.
Symons, D. 1989. A critique of Darwinian anthropology. Ethology
and Sociobiology, 10, 131–44.
Thornton, A. & McAuliffe, K. 2006. Teaching in wild meerkats.
Nature, 313, 227–9.
Tinbergen, N. 1951. The Study of Instinct. Oxford: Oxford University
Press (reprinted 1989).
Tinbergen, N. & Kruyt, W. 1932. Über die orientierung des
bienenwolfes (Philanthus triangulum Fabr.). [On the orientation
of the bee wolf] Zeitschrift für vergleichende Physiologie, 25, 292–
344.
Tomasello, M. 1994. The question of chimpanzee culture. In: R.
Wrangham, W. McGrew, F. De Waal & P. Heltne (eds.),
Chimpanzee Cultures, pp. 301–17. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Tomasello, M. 1999. The Cultural Origins of Human Cognitions.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Tomasello, M. & Call, J. 1997. Primate Cognition. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. 1990. The past explains the present:
emotional adaptations and the structure of ancestral
environments. Ethology and Sociobiology, 11, 375–424.
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. 2005. Conceptual foundations of
evolutionary psychology. In: D. Buss. (ed.), The Handbook of
Evolutionary Psychology, pp. 5–67. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Toren, C. 2018. Human ontogenies as historical processes: lessons
from ethnography. In: E. Hannon & T. Lewens (eds.), Why we
Disagree about Human Nature, pp. 170–85. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Trivers, R.L. 1972. Parental investment and sexual selection. In: B.
Campbell (ed.), Sexual Selection and the Descent of Man, 1871–
1971, pp. 136–70. Chicago: Aldine.
Voight, B. F., Kudaravalli, S., Wen, X. & Pritchard, J. K. 2006. A map
of recent positive selection in the human genome. PLoS Biology,
4, e72.
Watson, J.B. 1913. Psychology as the behaviorist views it.
Psychological Review, 20, 158–77.
Watson, J.B. 1924. Behaviorism. New York: Norton.
heeler, B.C. & Fischer, J. 2012. Functionally referential signals: a
promising paradigm whose time has passed. Evolutionary
Anthropology, 21, 195–205.
Whitehead, H. & Rendell, L.R. 2015. The Cultural Lives of Whales
and Dolphins. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Whiten, A. 2005. The second inheritance system of chimpanzees and
humans. Nature, 437, 52–5.
Whiten, A. 2017. Culture extends the scope of evolutionary biology in
the great apes. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science
USA, 114, 7790–7.
Whiten, A., Ayala, F., Feldman, M.W. & Laland, K.N. 2017. The
extension of biology through culture. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Science USA, 114, 7775–81.
Whiten, A., Goodall, J., McGrew, W.C. et al. 1999. Culture in
chimpanzees. Nature, 399, 682–5.
Whiten, A. & Van De Waal, E. 2017. Social learning, culture and the
‘socio-cultural brain’ of human and non-human primates.
Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 82, 58–75.
Williams, G.C. 1966. Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Wilson, D.S. & Gowdy, J.M. 2013. Evolution as a general theoretical
framework for economics and public policy. Journal of Economic
Behavior and Organization 90S, S3–S10.
Wilson, E.O. 1975. Sociobiology: the New Synthesis. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Zuberbühler, K. 2000. Referential labelling in Diana monkeys.
Animal Behaviour, 59, 917–27.
name index
Adams, C.D., 205
Adams, G.J., 255
Adams, M.J., 352
Adli, M., 152
Adrian, E.D., 58
Agate, R.J., 151
Aiello, L., 440
Ainsworth, M.D.S., 179
Akçay, C., 380, 389
Akre, K.L., 420–421
Alatalo, R.V., 327, 331
Alem, S., 240
Alexander, B., 163
Alexander, J., 332
Alexander, R.D., 321
Allee, W.C., 254
Altman, J., 126
Alvarez-Buylla, A., 128
Ambady, N., 462
Anderson, R.C., 380
Andersson, M., 119
Aplin, L.M., 358
Appleby, M.C., 254, 276
Arak, A., 303, 321
Archer, J., 461
Archibald, J.K., 403
Armitage, K.B., 346, 358
Arnold, A.P., 151
Arnqvist, G., 318, 330
Ashida, G., 132
Atz, J.W., 402
Aubert, M., 451
Avargues-Weber, A., 123F, 233
Avital, E., 479
Eaton, R.C., 27
Eberhard, W.G., 330
Edgar, R.S., 85
Egnor, S.E.R., 386
Ehlinger, T.J., 346
Eilam, D., 118
Ekman, P., 68, 462
Elbert, T., 40
Eldredge, N., 451
Elfenbein, H.A., 462
Ellegren, H., 459
Emery, N.J., 463
Emlen, S.T., 238, 318
Enquist, M., 74, 371, 372F, 375, 380
Etgen, A.M., 140
Etienne, A.S., 236
Evans, C.S., 242, 385
Everaert, M.B.H., 180, 182
Ewert, J.-P., 7, 16, 18–20, 25, 26, 30–37, 227
Kaas, J.H., 37
Kabelik, D., 140
Kafka, W.A., 28
Kaissling, K.-E., 14, 21, 27, 29
Kamin, L.J., 206
Karter, A.J., 328, 332, 333
Kee, N., 129
Kelley, J.L., 421
Kelley, L.A., 421
Kendrick, K.M., 38
Kennedy, M., 308–310
Kessel, E.L., 400, 401
Kettler, L., 114F, 118
Kilgour, R., 253
Kilner, R.M., 378
Kingsolver, J.G., 469
Kipp, K., 461
Kirkpatrick, M., 416
Klein, D.C., 99
Klein, R., 445, 448
Kleitman, N., 106
Klem, D., 260
Knapp, R.A., 325
Koelling, R.A., 218
Koffka, K., 17
Kok, E.M.A., 239
Kokko, H., 461
Kolluru, G.R., 332
Konishi, M., 14, 113–115, 117–119
Koolhaas, J.M., 345, 349
Kornysheva, K., 227
Kortlandt, A., 65
Kossinets, G., 457
Kotiaho, J.S., 331, 377
Kovach, J.T., 325
Kralj-Fišer, S., 357
Kramer, D.L., 293, 294F
Kramer, G., 103, 238
Krause, J., 358, 447
Krauss, N., 378
Krebs, C.J., 347
Krebs, J.R., 7, 285, 289, 290, 290F, 292, 416
Kriegsfeld, L.J., 163
Kroodsma, D.E., 386
Kruijt, J.P., 63, 63F, 64, 166, 167, 178, 190, 239
Krupenye, C., 429
Kruuk, L.E.B., 349
Kruyt, W., 464, 464F
Kuenen, D.J., 18
Kuhl, P.K., 180, 181
Kupfermann, I., 27
Kupper, C., 320
Kutschera, U., 19
Labhart, T., 14
Lagerspetz, K., 170
Laland, K.N., 9, 467–469, 472, 474, 476, 479, 480, 482
Lamichhaney, L., 320
Lande, R., 417
Langford, D.J., 268
Langley, C.M., 25
Lank, D.B., 320
Lara, R., 37
Larkin, R.P., 260
Lashley, K.S., 50, 57, 111
later, P.J.B., 126, 180
Lawrence, A.B., 266
Leadbeater, E., 239
Leakey, R.E.F., 437, 438, 440
LeBas, N.R., 401
LeDoux, J., 70, 71
Leech, S.M., 378
Lee-Thorp, J., 433
Lefebvre, L., 239
Legendre, S., 333
Lehman, M.N., 98
Lehrman, D.S., 2, 57, 58, 166, 171, 172, 172F, 173
Leonard, M.L., 378
Leong, C.Y., 23
Lepre, C.J., 439
Lesku, J.A., 103
Lettvin, J.Y., 31
Levitan, R.D., 104
Levy, D.M., 266
Lewis, D.J., 217
Lewis, H.M., 479
Lewontin, R.C., 284
Li, N.P., 468
Lieberman, D.E., 441
Little, A.C., 323
Livingstone, M.S., 37, 38
Livoreil, B., 306
Lloyd, J.E., 401
Loeb, J., 234
Lomo, T., 124
Lordkipanidze, D., 442, 443
Lorentsen, S.H., 378
Lorenz, K., 51, 52F, 54, 58, 59, 64, 65, 67, 71, 72F, 73, 74, 166,
171–179, 226, 226F, 227, 228, 230, 398, 402, 464, 465
Low, B.S., 326
Lozano, G.A., 378
Lu, W., 85
Macaluso, E., 40
MacArthur, R.H., 285
Macedonia, J.M., 242, 385
Machado, C.A., 416
Macphail, E.M., 5, 8, 218–219
Magrath, R.D., 382
Makela, R., 407
Maki, W.S., 213
Malmkvist, J., 265
Manser, M.B., 378, 385
Mappes, J., 377
Marchant, E.G., 91
Markl, H., 22
Markowitz, H., 261
Marler, P., 180, 182, 183, 382, 386, 390
Martin, J.G.A., 350
Martins, E., 398
Mason, G.J., 263F, 264, 271
Masson, J.M., 272
Mathew, S., 480
Matzel, L.D., 236
Max, D.T., 409
May, R.M., 416
Mayer, C., 459
Maynard Smith, J., 7, 297, 299, 374
Mayr, E., 4, 417, 482
McAleer, K., 294
McAuliffe, K., 476
McCabe, B.J., 175, 188
McCarthy, S., 272
McCarty, J.P., 378
McComb, K., 374
McDiarmid, R.W., 381
McDonald, G.C., 357
McDougall, I., 448
McDougall, W., 50
McEwen, B.S., 146, 150
McFarland, D.J., 52, 67
McGregor, P.K., 383
McPhail, J.D., 412
McPherron, S., 436
McRae, R.R., 352
Meagher, R.K., 271
Meck, W.H., 60
Meeuwissen, G.B., 178
Meffert, L.M., 349
Mello, C.V., 189
Menaker, M., 102
Mendl, M., 73, 269
Menzel, R., 121, 236
Mesoudi, A., 470, 471
Mey, J.L., 389
Meyer, C.C., 178
Meyer, E.P., 14
Michelena, P., 359
Micic, G., 93
Midgley, M., 253
Milinski, M., 310, 378
Miller, G.A., 212
Miller, N.E., 60
Mishkin, M., 37, 38
Mistlberger, R.E., 87, 91, 94, 95, 101
Mittelstaedt, H., 236
Mittelstaedt, M. L., 236
Mohawk, J., 99
Moiron, M., 348
Moiseff, A., 113–115
Møller, A.P., 325–329, 331, 332F, 333, 334, 377, 382
Monaghan, P., 457, 461
Montiglio, P.O., 349, 355, 356, 358, 360
Montminy, M.R., 125
Moore, J., 462
Moore-Ede, C.A., 95
Moore-Ede, M.C., 88
Moorman, S., 126, 127F, 188F, 189
Morand-Ferron, J., 306
Morgan, T.J.H., 477, 477F, 479
Morris, D., 465
Morris, R.G.M., 202, 235
Morton, J., 182, 186, 187
Moser, E.J., 237
Moser, M.-B., 237
Mrosovsky, N., 81
Mueller, J.C., 349
Mulder, C.K., 87
Muller, U., 121
Mutzel, A., 359
Myers, J.H., 347
Sagi, D., 39
Saino, N., 327
Saldanha, C.J., 158
Salzen, E.A., 178
Schachter, S., 69, 70
Schacter, D.L., 120
Scheibler, E., 96
Schel, A.M., 390
Schibler, U., 99
Schiefenhövel, W., 457
Schleidt, W., 25
Schluter, D., 412
Schmid-Hampel, P., 295
Schneider, H., 36
Schneirla, T.C., 61
Schuett, W., 357, 358
Schulte-Hostedde, A., 357
Schürg-Pfeiffer, E., 35
Schwippert, W.W., 36
Searcy, W.A., 119, 319, 370, 380–381, 386, 387, 480
Seed, A.M., 459, 474
Seeley, T.D., 372
Segerstråle, U.S., 466
Seidl, A.H., 115, 117F
Seitz, A., 23
Semaw, S., 436
Senghas, A., 450
Sevenster, P., 65
Sevenster-Bol, A.C.A., 55
Seyfarth, R.M., 242, 384, 385, 475
Shaaya, M., 130
Sherman, V., 386
Sherry, D.F., 67, 235
Shettleworth, A.J., 8
Shettleworth, S.J., 219, 235, 237, 242, 309F
Sibly, R.M., 304
Siepielski, A.M., 469
Sih, A., 285, 290, 345, 349, 357, 359
Simpson, J.A., 468
Singer, J.E., 69, 70
Singer, P., 253
Singer, W., 37
Skene, D.J., 94
Skinner, B.F., 3, 4, 58, 200, 201, 205
Slater, P.C., 216
Slater, P.J.B., 180, 181F, 386
Slimak, L., 447
Slocombe, K.E., 385
Sluckin, W., 175
Smiseth, P.T., 378
Smith, E.A., 472, 481
Smith, H., 438
Snowdon, C.T., 242
Sol, D., 246
Somel, M., 469, 469F
Spalding, D.A., 2, 174
Spear, N.E., 217
Spencer, H., 462
Sponheimer, M., 433
Spreckelsen, C., 35
Squire, L.R., 216
Staddon, J.E.R., 419
Stamps, J.A., 349, 354, 360
Steger, R., 382
Stein, L.R., 359
Steiner, A.P., 244, 245F
Stephens, D.W., 285, 292
Stevens, S.S., 419
Stimson, W.H., 332
Stoddard, P.K., 389
Stratmann, M., 99
Straub, J.J., 204, 205
Strausfeld, N.J., 122
Struhsaker, T.T., 242, 384
Suga, N., 14
Sussman, R.W., 435
Sutherland, W.J., 310, 318
Suzuki, T.N., 385, 387
Symons, D., 467, 468
Számadó, S., 381
Yamada, N., 80
Yamazaki, S., 93
Yanega, D., 371
Yang, C., 4
Yasukawa, K., 378
Yoshida, N., 37
Young, L.J., 140, 163
Zahavi, A., 375
Zhao, W.C., 130, 131F
Zink, K.D., 441
Zuberbühler, K., 385, 387, 475
Zuk, M., 326, 327, 332, 334, 416
Zupanc, G.H., 26
subject index
Acheulean implements, 440f
acoustic display, 331
acrophase, 83–84
action-specific energy, 51, 54
activating effects, 156
adaptations, 172–174, 214, 219, 281–285, 398, 399, 402, 413–
417, 433, 434, 438, 465, 467, 468, 472
affective quality, 70
affective states, 274
abnormal behaviors, 266–267
and animal welfare science, 266–271
assessing, 267–271
animal experimentation, 8
animals
better environments, designing, 260–264
environmental preferences, testing, 262
handling, improving, 259
mitigating harm to, 259–260
motivation strength, testing, 262–264
natural behavior, accommodating, 261–262
undesirable behavior, preventing, 257–258
using the abilities, 255–257
verses human beings, 471
auditory processing
barn owl (Tyto alba), 112
cognition, 120
honeybee learning, 120–125
perception and sexual selection, 119–120
streams, 113–117
behavioral ecology, 6–8, 306, 310, 342, 343, 346, 456, 458, 467
mechanism to function, 6–7
birdsong
learning, 180–182
speech and language, human infants, 180–182
circalunar, 79
circannual, 79
circatidal, 79
classical conditioning, 175, 199, 203–205, 220, 254, 257
clock genes, 98–100
closest living relatives, 429–430
cochlea, 114, 116
coevolution, 360, 416–418, 479, 480
cognition, 223–247
central mechanisms, 228–233
concepts, 233
knowledge, basic mechanisms, 225–233
memory, 230–232
mental structure and processes, 245–246
mental structures, knowledge, 233–245
motor and perceptual mechanisms, 226–228
wasp, 223–225
comparative psychology, 2, 3
comparator mechanisms, 228
competence, 169, 274, 328
complex conditioning procedures, 201–202
conditional control, 201–202
discrimination learning, 202
evolution, 4, 397–402
ancestral states, uncovering, 407
brain and, 418–421
divergence time, assessing, 411–413
patterns of, 405–406
phylogenetics and, 402–405
strong inference, 398–399
infradian rhythms, 79
inhibition, 35, 40, 59, 61, 65–67, 157, 158
innate, 2, 26, 71, 169–173, 183, 227, 228
innate releasing mechanism (IRM), 12, 26–29, 36, 227, 228
neuronal correlates, releasing systems, 27
scent-coding, 27–29
specialized receptor cells, insects, 27–29
jet lag, 93
Junco hyemalis, 238
limits of science
Animal Welfare, Science, and Ethics, 273–275
mental experience of animals, 271–273
probing, 271–275
maintenance, 48, 184, 213, 315, 322, 325, 326, 334, 357, 383,
390
male junglefowl (Gallus gallus spadiceus), 63
male praying mantis (Mantis religiosa), 59
male sexual behavior
appetitive vs. consummatory sexual behavior, 155–156
endocrine controls, 156
Japanese quail, 155–158
neural circuits, 156–157
rapid effects of estrogens, 158
role of dopamine, 158
Mantis religiosa, 59
Marmota flaviventris, 346
marmots (Marmota flaviventris), 346
masculinization, 147, 148
mate choice benefits, 324–329
maternal effects, 329, 356
mating success, 316, 318, 319, 321, 322, 326–329, 331, 335, 357,
358
mating systems, 316–320, 398, 414–416, 418
maximum parsimony, 403
Melospiza georgiana, 183
Melospiza melodia, 5
memetics, 470–471
memory, 197, 209–217
general and special processes, 217–220
oscillator, 59, 60, 82, 85, 98, 99, 101, 105, 228
mechanisms, 228
overflow theory, 65, 66
oviposition, 145
phase, 82, 84, 87, 89, 90, 92–96, 105, 115–118, 128, 174, 178,
180
advance shift, 90
angle, 115
delay shift, 90
shift, 90, 95
phase-locked, 115–118
phase-locked cells, 115
phase-response curve (PRC), 90, 92–95
phenotypic variance, 350
pheromone, 14, 22, 27–29
Philomachus pugnax, 320
phylogenetic reconstruction, 402–404, 408
phylogenetics, 398, 402–405
phylogenetic tree, 403, 405, 415
phylogeny, 97, 99–101, 398, 402–405, 416, 427
Physalaemus pustulosus, 418
pigeons (Columbia livia), 239
Poecile atricapillus, 285
Poecile montanus, 388
polecat (Mustela putorius), 186
polyandrous species, 317
polyandry, 318–320
polygynous species, 317
polygyny, 318–321
threshold model, 319
pons, 117
Porichthys notatus, 143, 159
Porpodiceps cristatus, 400
pragmatics, 389–390
predispositions, 173, 179, 182–187, 191, 480
in chicks and human infants, 183–186
preformation, 168
primacy effect, 211
primate phylogeny, 427–429
priming, 55–57
principle of parsimony, 22, 403
proactive interference, 212, 213
proboscis, 120
producer-scrounger game, 304–305
psychological construction, 70
punishment, 201
selective attention, 39
sensitive periods, 186–187
sensory bias, 368
sensory exploitation, 417
sensory maps, 40
sensory modalities, 21–22
sensory preconditioning, 204
sensory receptors, 14
sensory substitution, 37, 40, 41
sensory systems, 12, 14, 41, 119, 227, 245, 368
sequential prey encounter model, 287
serial position curve, 211
servals (Felis serval), 261f, 262
sex ratios, 334–336
sexual conflict, 330
sexual differentiation
birds, 148–149
brain correlates, behavior, 150
epigenetic mechanisms, brain, 152
genetic effects, 150–151
in human behavior, 460–461
mammals, 147–148
other vertebrate classes, 149–150
steroid action, 146–147
sign-tracking, 199
simultaneous ambivalence, 62
singing crickets (Gryllus integer), 303
Social Darwinism, 462
social learning, 239–242
observational learning, 239–242
sociobiology, 463–467
soft-shelled shrimp (Crangon crangon), 295
songbirds (oscines)
multiple brain sites, steroid action, 159–160
singing in, 159–160
stimulus recognition, 25
stimulus selection
behavioral meaning on motivation, 25–26
behavioral ways of, 24–26
vacuum activity, 58
Vandenbergh effect, 153
variable interval schedule, 201
variable ratio schedule, 201
variables correlations, 413–416
ventral processing stream, 38
vervet monkeys (Cercopithecus aethiops), 242
visual cortex, 40, 187
visual feature detection, 29–37
in amphibians, 29–37
brain structures, feature detection, 32–33
configurational object perception, 33–34
eye and brain, 31–32
features-relating-algorithm, configurational perception, 30–
31
multimethodological analysis, 29–37
sensorimotor codes, 36–37
size constancy phenomenon, 34–35
species-specific feature detection, learning, 36
toad’s visual system, 37
visuomotor access, 35