0% found this document useful (0 votes)
47 views10 pages

Introduction To Minimalist Program

This document introduces the Minimalist Program (MP) and discusses how it differs from Principles and Parameters (P&P) in its conception of Universal Grammar (UG). The MP pursues both methodological and substantive minimalism. Methodological minimalism aims to simplify linguistic theory, while substantive minimalism examines if properties satisfy the Strongest Minimalist Thesis. The MP views UG as consisting mainly of general principles that are rewirings of third factor principles, whereas P&P viewed UG as a highly specified set of parameters. The MP also sees linguistic variation as derived from the articulatory-perceptual system, rather than different parameter settings.

Uploaded by

Jordana Naves
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
47 views10 pages

Introduction To Minimalist Program

This document introduces the Minimalist Program (MP) and discusses how it differs from Principles and Parameters (P&P) in its conception of Universal Grammar (UG). The MP pursues both methodological and substantive minimalism. Methodological minimalism aims to simplify linguistic theory, while substantive minimalism examines if properties satisfy the Strongest Minimalist Thesis. The MP views UG as consisting mainly of general principles that are rewirings of third factor principles, whereas P&P viewed UG as a highly specified set of parameters. The MP also sees linguistic variation as derived from the articulatory-perceptual system, rather than different parameter settings.

Uploaded by

Jordana Naves
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 10

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/41313143

Introduction. The Minimalist Program and the concept of Universal Grammar

Article in Catalan Journal of Linguistics · December 2009


DOI: 10.5565/rev/catjl.139 · Source: OAI

CITATIONS READS

2 11,261

2 authors:

Jordi Fortuny Ángel J. Gallego


University of Barcelona Autonomous University of Barcelona
21 PUBLICATIONS 204 CITATIONS 92 PUBLICATIONS 796 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Physics of language View project

Ambiguity at the grammar-pragmatics interface: structural and pragmatic factors View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Jordi Fortuny on 09 March 2016.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


CatJourLing 8 001-189:CatJL 11/1/10 13:18 Página 7

Catalan Journal of Linguistics 8, 2009 7-15

Introduction
The Minimalist Program and the concept
of Universal Grammar
Jordi Fortuny Andreu
University of Groningen. Center for Language and Cognition Groningen
[email protected]

Ángel J. Gallego
Centre de Lingüística Teòrica
Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona. Departament de Filologia Espanyola
[email protected]

This volume offers a collection of brief and orginal articles that aim at developing
the minimalist approach to language. In this introduction, we would like to discuss
certain issues concerning the Minimalist Program and the concept of Universal
Grammar as well as to present the contributions of the volume.
The term minimalism is typically associated to certain artistic tendencies whose
work is said to be stripped down to its most fundamental features. In the linguistic
agenda developed by Noam Chomsky and others since the early nineties, this term
is endowed with the same aesthetic concern of searching for the most fundamen-
tal features of grammatical theory, but it crucially adds a substantive commitment
to investigate to what extent language is—in a sense we clarify below—a perfect
system.
In Martin & Uriagereka (2000) this bifurcated path to pursue the Minimalist
Program (MP) is emphasized by establishing a distinction between methodologi-
cal minimalism and substantive minimalism. The methodological facet is con-
cerned with the “theory of language” under construction, whereas the substantive
facet is concerned with how well designed “language itself” is. Methodological
minimalism seeks those components of a linguistic theory that are redundant, stip-
ulative, and idiosyncratic, in order to eliminate or reformulate them in the form of
parsimonius, well-grounded, and general principles. Substantive minimalism
explores whether an alleged property of language is a genuine property or an appar-
ent property, and if genuine, whether it satisfies the Strongest Minimalist Thesis
—SMT (see Chomsky 2000)—, i.e., whether it is an optimal solution to the require-
ments imposed by the external systems.
There are different case studies of methodological minimalism that have con-
tributed to determine what the fundamental elements of the theory of Universal
Grammar are. The most representative concerns are the reduction of the levels of
CatJourLing 8 001-189:CatJL 11/1/10 13:18 Página 8

8 CatJL 8, 2009 Jordi Fortuny Andreu; Ángel J. Gallego

representation (D-Structure, S-Structure, and Logical Form; see Chomsky 1993;


2000), the elimination of Agr(eement) nodes (see Chomsky 1995), and the sim-
plification of phrase structure and transformational theory.1 Typically, almost any
grammatical observation offers a case study for substantive miminalism. Just to
mention a few questions for the SMT: What would the legibility conditions be for
the existence of parasitic gaps in a language like English? Why is it that certain
languages have grammatical functions? Would it not be enough to have thematic
roles and illocutionary force and informational relations? In virtue of what legi-
bility conditions different languages have different basic word orders or different
Case patterns? Can cartographic effects be derived from semantic factors? Why
are natural languages ambiguous? The list could go on and on.
We would like to emphasize that methodological and substantive minimalism
are not to be confused. For instance, it is conceivable to construct a theory of how
linguistic properties derive from external principles that postulates a multitude of
idiosyncratic principles, instead of a relatively small set of general and fundamental
principles. Although this would be an impressive achievement, it would not satis-
fy the usual scientific ideals of simplicity and solidness. However, the method-
ological and substantive facets may not be independent: quite plausibly, it is by
struggling for an elegant and parsimonious theory of an object that one can trully
understand to what extent such an object is an optimal solution to the external con-
ditions it must face. We also stress the truism that these two facets are not exclusive
of the MP or the generative tradition, but they are characteristic attitudes of any
rational inquiry that is not merely descriptive or cumulative but searches for a ‘prin-
cipled account’—the substantive facet—that satisfies the usual ‘simplicity desider-
ata’—the methodological facet—.
Clearly, the MP leads minimalist researchers to a view of Universal Grammar
(UG) that is essentially different from the view in Principles and Parameters (P&P),
from which the MP orginated. We can express the sharp contrast between the con-
ceptions of UG in the MP and the P&P by reflecting about their opposite views on
the logical problem of language growth and linguistic variation.
As to the logical problem of language growth (how can a child develop a nat-
ural language just by being exposed to some linguistic data for a relatively short
period?), the P&P model would claim that UG is a very highly specified structure
of exclusively linguistic principles with their respective parameters. Language
growth would consist in setting a value for the parameters given by UG. The MP
would investigate to what extent the principles belonging to UG, a virtually necessary
cognitive component of humans, would belong to general principles, or in terms
of Chomsky’s (2005) factors, to what extent Factor I is a rewiring of Factor III; the
process of language growth would consist in the interaction of linguistic princi-
ples (which should, ideally, be derived from general principles) and principles of

1. See Chomsky & Lasnik (1995) for a brief historical overiew of the simplification of phrase struc-
ture and Chomsky (1995) for the introduction of bare phrase structure. See Lasnik & Saito (1992)
for an important simplification of the transformational component in terms of the single operation
‘move α’ which allowed much further work.
CatJourLing 8 001-189:CatJL 11/1/10 13:18 Página 9

Introduction. The Minimalist Program and the concept of Universal Grammar CatJL 8, 2009 9

analysis (see Yang 2002; 2004, Gambell & Yang 2003) that apply to linguistic data
(Factor II).
As to linguistic variation, the minimalist reasoning would invite us to investi-
gate to what extent linguistic variation can be derived from the Articulatory-
Perceptual (A-P) system (which includes phonetics, morphology and phonology),
in opposition to the P&P view, according to which variation between two languages
would reflect different parameter settings in the process of language growth.
According to the minimalist working hypothesis, linguistic variation would be no
more than the effect of the relative freedom allowed by the A-P system, and the
important question would be to determine the principles governing variation and
their relationship to the principles of the A-P system.
This new perspective is better captured in the following quote, which summa-
rizes the reductionist—or, to use Chomsky’s words, ‘from below’—twist of min-
imalism:

Throughout the modern history of generative grammar, the problem of determining the
character of FL [Faculty of Language] has been approached “from top down”: How
much must be attributed to UG to account for language acquisition? The MP seeks to
approach the problem “from bottom up”: How little can be attributed to UG while still
accounting for the variety of I-languages attained, relying on third factor principles?
The two approaches should, of course, converge, and should interact in the course of
pursuing a common goal. [from Chomsky 2007:4]

What Chomsky suggests here is that most devices and properties that were
attributed to UG in the GB era—Factor I—should be recast as economy and effi-
cient computation principles—Factor III—. In a nutshell: “UG is what remains
when the gap has been reduced to the minimum, when all third factor effects have
been identified. UG [only] consists of the mechanisms specific to [the faculty of
language]” (Chomsky 2007:5). The goal of the present volume is precisely to help
reduce the gap by considering what properties can truly be adscribed to UG, and
what properties cannot. If the SMT is seriously entertained, then the faculty of lan-
guage boils down to a computational system and the interface systems, and the
crucial question is to determine what features of the computational system and the
interfaces are primitive elements of language belonging to Factor I or derivative
from general principles belonging to Factor III.
Before introducing the contents of the papers of this volume, we shall sketch
Chomsky’s (2007; 2008) most recent essentialist view of UG. Chomsky’s very
restrictive conception of the computational system focuses on Merge, “the most
elementary property of language [...] [giving rise to] a system of discrete infinity con-
sisting of hierarchically organized objects” (Chomsky 2008:137). Much literature
has been dedicated to investigate the properties of this operation, and discuss its
triggers, its consequences, and its subcomponents (see Boeckx 2008, Hornstein
2009, and references therein). Although there have been proposals to motivate
Merge, attributing some Agree-like nature to it, the defining property of this oper-
ation concerns the hypothesis that it is ‘unbounded’ and feature-free, an idea that
has been expressed by means of a special property of lexical items: their edge fea-
CatJourLing 8 001-189:CatJL 11/1/10 13:18 Página 10

10 CatJL 8, 2009 Jordi Fortuny Andreu; Ángel J. Gallego

ture (EF).2 As Chomsky puts it: “The fact that Merge operates without limit is a
property of LIs [...] EF articulates the fact that Merge is unbounded, that language
is a recursive infinite system.” Chomsky (2008:139). Merge therefore operates by
combining two syntactic objects, α and β—either simple or complex—. If α and
β are independent—not having participated in previous applications of Merge, or
being directly taken from the lexicon—, Merge is external; if they are not, Merge
is internal. Or in different terms,

(1) a. External Merge: Merge (α, β) when α is an outcome of a previous appli-


cation of Merge (or selected from the lexicon) and β is selected from the
lexicon
b. Internal Merge: Merge (α, β) when α is an outcome of a previous applica-
tion of Merge and β is selected from the domain of α3

A further characteristic attributed to Merge in some recent literature (see Boeckx


2008; 2009, Chomsky 2005; 2007; 2008) is its symmetric nature. Typically, this
is represented by using sets, which do not—by definition—impose any asymmetry
to their members. The only exception appears to come from adjuncts, which have
been approached by invoking a pair-creating version of Merge—pair Merge—,
which establishes an asymmetry between Merge-mates. The reason for this dou-
ble treatment appears to have, in Chomsky’s (2004) account, an empirical moti-
vation: adjuncts do not have an impact on the syntactic computation—they do not
participate in theta-role configurations, do not receive Case, are potentially unbound-
ed, etc.—, but they make an interpretive contribution. It is, according to Chomsky
(2004), as if adjuncts were not there, apart from semantic interpretation—where
the ‘were not there’ part has been taken to suggest that adjuncts occupy a parallel
plane or are late-merged into the derivation (see Chametzky 2000, Lebeaux 1991).
In Chomsky’s (2004) treatment, the parallel plane metaphor has been implement-
ed by invoking (ordered) pairs for adjuncts, because only pairs establish asymme-
tries between Merge-mates. This can be seen in (2).

(2) a. Set Merge: {α, β} = {β, α}


b. Pair Merge: <α, β> ⬆ <β, α>

Along with edge features that trigger Merge, it is a fact—against the SMT, at
first glance—that UG has uninterpretable features, the so-called ϕ-features. If UG
has ϕ-features, then it will optimally activate some valuation procedure—which

2. Chomsky’s (2007; 2008) EF must be seen as a Merge-inducing property, not a bona fide feature.
There are at least three traits that distinguish EFs from other features: they do not involve feature-
Match, they have no values, and they do not delete. For these reasons, EFs should not be treated like
other features.
3. See Chametzky (2000), Boeckx (2008), Fortuny & Corominas-Murtra (this volume), and refer-
ences therein for an accurate definition of the distinction between internal and external Merge.
CatJourLing 8 001-189:CatJL 11/1/10 13:18 Página 11

Introduction. The Minimalist Program and the concept of Universal Grammar CatJL 8, 2009 11

is referred to as Agree—, and a deletion mechanism. Chomsky (2007; 2008) argues


that deletion is part of a transfer operation, which is responsible for reducing com-
putational load by ‘periodically forgetting’ chunks of the derivation. On this view,
ϕ-features are not an imperfection, but a way to signal what the transfer points are.
Chomsky calls the relevant transfer units phases, and claims that ϕ-features are
located in the functional heads C and v* (see Gallego 2007, Fortuny 2008, and
Richards 2004 for discussion).

(3) Transfer points are signaled by ϕ-features.

Once transfer has applied, the syntactic objects generated by Merge are cashed
out to the external systems—through the SEM and PHON interfaces—, which are
supposed to incorporate Factor III conditions that UG must meet. The following
conditions have been explored in the minimalist literature:

(4) Factor III Conditions


a. Inclusiveness Condition
b. Extension Condition / No Tampering Condition
c. Full Interpretation
d. Phase Impenetrability Condition
e. Minimal Link Condition

First of all, it is worth noting that it is at the interfaces that asymmetries emerge.
So, whereas Merge treats α and β as equal, in a symmetric fashion, the interfaces
seem to reinterpret the syntactic outputs, providing asymmetry. This is so with dif-
ferent interface phenomena: if α binds β, then β does not bind α; if α is an argu-
ment of β, then β is not an argument of α; if α precedes β, then β cannot precede
α; etc. A further relevant issue about the interfaces and their conditions can be for-
mulated as follows: are these principles ‘substantive’ or ‘methodological’? In other
words: are the conditions in (4) genuine conditions of UG that can be derived from
Factor III or mere aesthetic devices? Putting aside Full Interpretation, which gen-
uinely appears to fall within Factor III, it is rather plausible that (4a) and (4b) are
just methodological, as they restrict the number of formatives and operations that
one can invoke in order to approach the faculty of language. (4d) and (4e) are, on
the other hand, not obviously just methodological: they are not especially con-
cerned with the minimal elements or conditions that must be assumed in the theo-
ry, but they are principles that attempt to account for the locality of movement, a
property that has always been related to economy conditions (see Chomsky 1973;
1986; 1995 for different illustrations). A different and important issue is to what
extent these two principles attributed to Factor I can be derived from Factor III,
thereby showing that they (i.e., the principles that constraint/regulate locality effects)
are an optimal solution to some external requirement, in which case (4d) and (4e)
offer a case study for substantive minimalism.
On the basis of the above given essentialist considerations about Factor I, one
may be tempted to go a step further and claim that the content of UG is solely
CatJourLing 8 001-189:CatJL 11/1/10 13:18 Página 12

12 CatJL 8, 2009 Jordi Fortuny Andreu; Ángel J. Gallego

Merge and those features that trigger its applications (namely, EFs and ϕ-fea-
tures)—all other linguistic properties being a byproduct of the external systems.
There may be, though, several qualms for such a claim. Note, for instance, that it
would confuse the syntactic component and UG (Factor I), i.e., the set of innate
elements of grammar which are necessary to interpret some given external data as
linguistic experience and constrain the set of possible growing paths. For these rea-
sons, one could envisage the possibility that UG be composed of several components
other than Merge, such as the knowledge of phonological structure (which seems
necessary for statistical learning to be successful in a realistic setting; see Yang
2002, 2004, Gambell & Yang 2003) or, quite likely, the coarticulation mechanisms
that transform a sequence of discrete phonological units into a continuous acoustic
sign (see Harcastle & Hewlett 2000 for a broad discussion and illustration), along-
side those mechanisms that reconstruct a sequence of discrete phonological units
from a received continuous acoustic sign, and the interpretative mechanisms that
allow humans to refer to displaced events (see Hockett 1960), i.e., to events tak-
ing place at a time different from the present one and in a world different from the
actual one. All this, and quite likely much more, may be necessary if one wants to
characterize what allows humans to develop the knowledge of grammar and how.4

After this brief sketch of the current minimalist approach to language and some
critical remarks about the concept of UG in the MP and the P&P, we shall finally
present the contributions of this volume to the development of the MP. In the first
paper, Abels and Bentzen discuss the nature of successive cyclic movement. These
authors defend the hypothesis that movement has a punctuated (i.e., non-uniform)
nature, only targeting the so-called phase edges: SPEC-v* and SPEC-C. Apart
from data from wh-movement effects, Abels and Bentzen investigate the interac-
tion of quantifier phrases and adverbs in Norwegian and ellipsis licensing, pro-
viding new evidence in favor of their claim.
Boeckx argues for a system that sticks to an architecture in the spirit of what we have
discussed so far. According to this author, the asymmetries that prominently appear
in the language faculty can be seen as a consequence of the phase-based transfer that
Chomsky (2000 and subsequent work) advocates for. Assuming that Merge is inher-
ently symmetric, the distinctions that were established by invoking the notion
head/label are recast by a label-free algorithm that takes the second application of
Merge to be the key factor to establish Probe-Goal dependencies, cyclic transfer, the
internal-external argument cut, and the nature of phenomena such as ellipsis, pied-
piping, or islands.
Richards’ paper addresses the possibility that, just like there is external and inter-
nal Set Merge, there is an analogous duality affecting Pair Merge. Richards pro-
vides interesting pieces of evidence that this missing mode of movement, which

4. Plausibly, this would correspond to a broad interpretation of UG (in the sense of Hauser et al.
2002).
CatJourLing 8 001-189:CatJL 11/1/10 13:18 Página 13

Introduction. The Minimalist Program and the concept of Universal Grammar CatJL 8, 2009 13

he calls internal Pair Merge, may well be behind a number of operations (e.g.,
focalization, scrambling, successive cyclicity) that are usually addressed by pos-
tulating dedicated features that are not of the agreement type—criterial or EPP fea-
tures—. In brief, internal Pair Merge is the variety of movement that is feature-
less—or pure-EPP driven—according to Richards.
Vicente’s contribution focuses on A-bar chains—paying special attention to its
quantificational nature—, discussing how the Copy Theory of Movement and
Multidominance approaches deal with them. As Vicente observes, the distinctions
are not particularly notorious empirically, as there is no evidence favoring one of
the approaches over the other. What this investigation does show is that the device
one adopts does have an effect on the mapping between the computational com-
ponent and the external systems, with specific consequences for domains like lin-
earization and the composition of logical forms.
Fortuny and Corominas-Murtra propose to construct the core of the transfor-
mational generative syntactic theory of language on the basis of the set-theoreti-
cal concept of ‘nest’, on which Kuratowski’s (1921) general theory of order is
based. Accordingly, one does not need to appeal to idiosyncratic linguistic con-
structs (such as X’-theory) to represent hierarchical properties of linguistic expres-
sions, but elementary set-theoretical notions are sufficient.
Hornstein and Pietroski articulate a minimalist conception of syntactic and seman-
tic composition by identifying fundamental operations of language. They take as a
starting point the operation COMBINE(A, B), which is claimed to be responsible
for combining expressions in an I-language. COMBINE is decomposed into two sim-
pler operations, CONCATENATE and LABEL. Each application of COMBINE(A,
B) is argued to be a semantic instruction in such a way that the meaning of a com-
plex structure is the meaning of a labelled concatenation.
Irurtzun is concerned with the general design of grammar, and more precisely,
with the comparison of two different views of how syntax is related to the external
systems: the classic inverted-Y model, according to which syntax is responsible
for creating structures interpreted by the Articulatory-Perceptual (A-P) system and
the Conceptual-Intentional (C-I) system with no further connection between A-P
and C-I, and the more articulated alternative proposed by Jackendoff (1997), which
postulates a non-syntactic stretch A-P → C-I. On the basis of the particular case
study of the grammar of focus, Irurtzun argues for the superiority of the simpler
inverted-Y model.
Zwart explores a top-down model of syntactic computations that yields, at each
step of the computation, an ordered pair of elements relevant to the expression of
order, information and grammatical features. A crucial feature of Zwart’s propos-
als is that the output of a previous derivation appears as an atom in the resource
for the next derivation. Zwart suggests that the existence of layered derivations,
and not conditions on movement, would be the source of opacity effects.
CatJourLing 8 001-189:CatJL 11/1/10 13:18 Página 14

14 CatJL 8, 2009 Jordi Fortuny Andreu; Ángel J. Gallego

References
Boeckx, Cedric (2008). Bare Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Boeckx, Cedric (2009). “Aspects of a Theory of Phases”. Ms., ICREA / CLT-UAB.
Chametzky, Robert (2000). Phrase structure. From GB to minimalism. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Chomsky, Noam (1973). “Conditions on Transformations”. In A festschrift for Morris
Halle, S. Anderson and P. Kiparsky (eds.), 232-286. New York: Holt, Renehart and
Winston.
Chomsky, Noam (1986). Barriers. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam (1993). “A minimalist program for linguistic theory”. In The view from
Building 20: essays in linguistics in honor of Sylvain Bromberger, K. Hale and S.
J. Keyser (eds), 1-52. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press. [Reprinted in Chomsky, N.
1995. The Minimalist Program, 167-217. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press].
Chomsky, Noam (1995). “Categories and Transformations”. In The Minimalist Program,
219-394. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam (2000). “Minimalist Inquiries: The Framework”. In Step by Step.
Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik, R. Martin et al. (eds.),
89-155. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam (2004). “Beyond Explanatory Adequacy”. In Structures and Beyond.
The Cartography of Syntactic Structures (vol. 3), A. Belletti (ed.), 104-131. Oxford,
NY: Oxford University Press.
Chomsky, Noam (2005). “Three factors in language design”. Linguistic Inquiry 36: 1-22.
Chomsky, Noam (2007). “Approaching UG from below”. In Interfaces + Recursion =
Language? Chomsky’s minimalism and the view from syntax-semantics, U. Sauerland
and H-M. Gärtner (eds.), 1-30. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Chomsky, Noam (2008). “On Phases”. In Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory.
Essays in Honor of Jean-Roger Vergnaud, C. Otero et al. (eds.), 134-166. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam; Lasnik, Howard (1995). “The Theory of Principles and Parameters”.
In The Minimalist Program, 13-127. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Epstein, Samuel; Seely, Daniel (2002). Derivation and Explanation in the Minimalist
Program. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Fortuny, Jordi (2008). The Emergence of Order in Syntax. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Gallego, Ángel J. (2007). Phase Theory and Parametric Variation. PhD dissertation,
UAB.
Gambell, Timothy; Yang, Charles D. (2003). “Scope and limits of statistical learning in
word segmentation”. Ms., Yale University.
Hardcastle, William J.; Hewlett, Nigel (2000). Coarticulation: Theory, data and tech-
niques. Edited by. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hauser, Marc D.; Chomsky, Noam; Fitch, Tecumseh (2002). “The faculty of language:
What is it, who has it, and how did it evolve?”. Science 298: 1569-1579.
Hockett, Charles F. (1960). “The orgin of speech”. Scientific American 203: 88-101.
Hornstein, Norbert (2009). A Theory of Syntax: Basic Operations and the Minimalist
Program. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jackendoff, Ray (1997). The Architecture of the Language Faculty. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
CatJourLing 8 001-189:CatJL 11/1/10 13:18 Página 15

Introduction. The Minimalist Program and the concept of Universal Grammar CatJL 8, 2009 15

Kuratowski, Kazimierz (1921). “Sur la notion de l’ordre dans la théorie des ensem-
bles”. Fundamenta Mathematicae 2: 161-171.
Lasnik, Howard; Saito, Mamoru (1992). Move Alpha: Conditions on Its Application
and Output. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lebeaux, David (1991). “Relative clauses, licensing, and the nature of the derivation”.
In Perspectives on phrase structure: heads and licensing, S. Rothstein (ed.), 209-
239. San Diego: Academic Press.
Martin, Roger; Uriagereka, Juan (2000). “Some Possible Foundations of the Minimalist
Program”. In Step by Step. Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik,
R. Martin et al. (eds.), 1-29. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Richards, Marc D. (2004). Object Shift and Scrambling in North and West Germanic:
A Case Study in Symmetrical Syntax. PhD dissertation, University of Cambridge.
Yang, Charles D. (2002). Knowledge and learning in natural language. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Yang, Charles D. (2004). “Universal Grammar, Statistics or both?”. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences 8: 451-456.

View publication stats

You might also like