Bucovetsky, S. (2017) Externalities-Introduction
Bucovetsky, S. (2017) Externalities-Introduction
1
an externality if the firm has negotiated an agreement with the owner of the neighbouring property.
Affecting someone else, and neglecting this effect, is the externality problem.
Another aspect of the above definition which is worth repeating is that an externality can
occur among people, or among firms, or between people and firms. That is, if one person’s playing
loud music bothers the person’s neighbours, that’s an externality, between two people. If one firm’s
training of its workers benefits other firms who might later hire some of those workers, that’s an
externality between firms. If one person’s holding a yard sale affects a firm trying to film a movie
on the same street, then that’s an externality between the person and the firm.
So the party (or parties) causing the externality could be a person, or a firm, and the party
or parties affected by the externality could be a firm or people (or both). But be warned :
classifying parties involved in an externality as “causing” on the one side, and “affected by” on the
other side, is very misleading as well, in many circumstances. That is, the behaviour of the victim
of an externality may matter here, as well as the behaviour of the perpetrator.
Two paragraphs above, one of the examples of an externality was a firm’s training of workers
benefitting some other firms. That’s an example of a positive externality : the more training
the first firm undertakes, the higher the profits of the other firms will be. So externalities can
be negative or positive. There still is an externality problem when the externality is beneficial :
as long as one firm’s (or person’s) actions affect another firm or person, and these effects are not
internalized, then there will be an externality problem, and the overall allocation of resources in
the economy will be inefficient.
Externalities could be reciprocal : the effluents emitted from firm 1’s production might lower
the profits of firm 2, at the same time as the effluents emitted from firm 2’s production lower the
profits of firm 1. Reciprocal externalities do not “cancel” : there will be an externality problem
here if these effects are not internalized, even if the damage done by firm 1 to firm 2 is exactly the
same magnitude as the damage done by firm 2 to firm 1.
A classic example of an externality is pollution. This of course is a negative externality. The
effects of the polluting firm’s production are a reduction in the utility of people subject to the
pollution. But there are many other examples of positive externalities, in addition to the one
mentioned above ; many involve a firm or person providing goods which have some public good
aspects, so that other firms or people can free–ride. [For example, skills learned by workers at one
firm may be like public goods, in that other firms cannot be excluded from the benefits of these
skills.]
If a firm producing a negative externality is not charged for the harm its activities impose
on others, then it will undertake those activities at a higher level than is efficient. On the other
hand, if a firm producing the positive externality is not paid for the benefit its activities impose
on others, then it will undertake those activities at a lower level than is efficient.
The two main theoretical points about externalities : One, there is an efficiency problem,
that the competitive equilibrium is not Pareto optimal, whether the externality is positive or
negative, if it is not internalized properly. Two, the problem stems from the fact that the agent
2
(firm or person) producing the externality does not face prices that reflect all the consequences
of its actions at the margin. R. H. Coase, whose work will be considered shortly, might modify
that second point to make it “the agents” rather than “the agent”, to take account of this (valid)
argument : when noise from an airport annoys nearby residents, the externality results from the
actions of the airplanes landing at the airport, and as well from the residents choosing to locate
near the airport.
An important category of externality in which several agents cause the damage to each other
is the common property resource. Classic examples are fisheries, and oil pools. The externality
in the latter case arises if several firms can drill on land they own over the same underground oil
pool. Then one firm’s well can remove oil from the whole pool, thus reducing the potential yield
of any other firm’s well. If no arrangement is made to internalize this externality, then excessive
drilling activity takes place, as each firm drills and pumps as fast as it can, to prevent its rivals
from pumping up the entire pool. Similarly, the level of fishing activity off both of Canada’s coasts
is inefficient, as boats from different countries attempt to harvest fish from the same biomass,
reducing the future yield in an attempt to get the fish before the next boat does.
The problem in those examples is that there is a resource to which many firms have access,
but which no single firm owns. If a single firm owned the entire oil field, or the entire fishing
area, then that firm would have incentives to exploit the resource is the most efficient manner. For
instance, if I owned a lake full of fish, there would be no incentive to over–fish, to kill off the entire
stock of fish for the sake of my profits. By doing so I reduce the value of future profits, which also
belong to me if I own the lake. Alternatively, inefficiently fast extermination of the fish will reduce
the resale value of the lake. On the other hand, if no individual owns the lake, but many firms can
fish there, then each has an incentive to over–fish, since if they do not then someone else will.
Actually, air and water pollution can also be viewed as well as common property resource
problems. The air or water I pollute does not belong to me, so that I have no direct incentive to
take into account the implications of my pollution for the value of that air or water. Of course,
having the entire resource under the ownership of a single firm is not always a practical solution
to the common property resource problem. With pollutants carried by high atmospheric winds all
over the continent and the planet, assigning ownership to the air is not sensible. Nor is it practical
for pollution of the ocean, or over–fishing of the Atlantic fisheries. But framing the problem this
way is often useful.