Denial, Negation, and The Forces of The Negative
Denial, Negation, and The Forces of The Negative
W ILFR IE D V ER E E C K E
N o part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without
written permission. N o part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or
transm itted in any form or by any m eans including electronic, electrostatic,
magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the
prior permission in writing of the publisher.
BF175.V465 2005
121'.5— dc22
2004029291
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
F o r Josian e,
with whom I crossed an ocean
to start a fam ily in the prom ised land.
Contents
A ckn o w led g m en ts ix
In t r o d u c t i o n 1
C o n c l u s io n 123
N o tes 127
B ib l io g r a p h y 155
A u t h o r In d e x 167
S u b j e c t In d e x 173
Acknowledgments
T his book would not have been possible without the editorial assistance of
Lynn Poss and David O ’M ara, supported by a Georgetow n University U nder
graduate Research Opportunity grant, and Lacy Baugher and Eupil Muhn,
supported by the Departm ent o f Philosophy. I want to give special thanks to
D evra Sim iu for helping to improve the style of the whole manuscript.
Several chapters have appeared before as separate articles. A ll have been
adapted to the interdisciplinary nature of this book. Often, I have added
extensive references to the treatm ent of the problem in other disciplines, in
particular, psychoanalysis, psychology, linguistics, and philosophy. I wish to
thank the following publishers for their permission to use articles in writing
some o f the chapters o f this book.
I made use of: Ver Eecke, W. “Ontology o f D enial.” Rereading Freud: Psy
choanalysis through Philosophy. Ed. J. M ills (Albany, NY: State U niversity of
N ew York Press, 2004). 103-25, in writing chapter 1, “T h e C om plex Phe
nom enon o f D enial,” with the kind permission o f State U niversity o f N ew
York Press.
I made use of: Ver Eecke, W. “Epistem ological Consequences o f Freud’s
Theory o f N egation.” M an and World 14 (1981): 111-25, in writing chapter
2, “T he Epistem ological Problem of Self-description in Freudian Psycho
analysis,” with the kind permission of Kluwer A cadem ic Publishers, copyright
owner of M an and World.
I made use of: Ver Eecke, W. “N egation and Desire in Freud and H egel.”
Owi of Minerva 15 (1983): 11-22, in writing chapter 3, “D enial and H egel’s
Philosophical Anthropology,” with the kind permission of Owl o f Minerva.
I made use of: Ver Eecke, W. “Seein g and Saying ‘N o ’ W ithin the T h e o
ries o f Spitz and Lacan ,” Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought 12:3
(1989): 383-431, in writing chapter 5, “A C h ild ’s N o-Saying: A Step towards
Independence,” with the kind permission o f International U niversities Press,
based upon: Copyright 1989 Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought, pub
lished by International U niversities Press, Inc., M adison, CT.
ix
Introduction
T h is is a book about denial, negation, and the forces of the negative. A denial
is a paradoxical phenom enon. In a denial, such as “this woman in my dream
is not my mother,” a truth is revealed, but the revelation is done in such a way
that the revelation is explicitly denied. A denial thus appears as a m isleading
statem ent. A s presented, it is not true, but false. N evertheless, the falsity o f a
denial does not make it worthless. A denial reveals two things to a good lis
tener. It reveals a truth that the patient him or herself cannot yet accept. S e c
ondly, it reveals that the patient is caught in a conflict and thus cannot see
reality truthfully. O ne can say, therefore, that a denial is much more reveal
ing than a sim ple affirmative statem ent. It labels the truth, while in its denial
o f what it labels, it gives a hint o f the paralysis o f the speaking subject.
Freud’s therapeutic attitude towards denials and his intellectual conclu
sions about them give us two entirely different paths on which to evaluate the
phenom enon of denial. From a therapeutic perspective, Freud suggests steps to
help the patient overcome the lim itations resulting from his or her conflicted
situation. These steps should help the patient become a more free individual.
T he first step, the easiest, is the one which consists o f helping the patient to
intellectually accept the true revelation hidden in the denial. T he therapist
can let the patient reveal information which accumulatively provides evi
dence for the truth of what was previously denied. T h e patient is then forced,
often reluctantly, to confess that that which was previously denied is true.
Freud points out that such an intellectual acceptance of the truth, hidden in
a denial, does not mean that the truth is emotionally accepted. Freud writes,
“T h e outcom e o f this is a kind o f intellectual acceptance o f the repressed,
while at the same time what is essential to the repression persists” (Freud,
S .E ., XIX, 236). Therefore, a second therapeutic step needs to be undertaken.
The therapist must help the patient emotionally accept the truth hidden in
the denial. To accept som ething em otionally m eans to accept the conse
quences o f that truth and to undertake the rational actions implied by the
1
2 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
accepted truth. Overcom ing the negative forces hidden behind the formation
of a denial can thus be expected to be an arduous process.
In his theoretical reflections on denial, Freud follows a different line of
reasoning. Indeed, Freud accepts the conflicted nature o f a hum an being. He
then takes this acceptance a step further by affirming that a conflicted being
must have at its disposal m echanism s to bridge the conflict. M astering a con
flict requires that one first expresses the conflict. Freud points to the linguis
tic expression of negation as such a m echanism . Indeed, Freud writes, “But
the performance o f the function o f judgm ent [acknowledging the truth] is not
m ade possible until the creation o f the symbol o f negation has endowed
thinking with a first measure o f freedom from the consequences of repression
and, with it, from the com pulsion of the pleasure principle” (Ibid. 239).
T he above-m entioned puzzling dim ensions o f a denial are presented in
detail in the first chapter o f this book. O ne im portant im plication o f the phe
nom enon o f denial is then analyzed in chapter 2. There I argue that it is not
possible to classify all false self-descriptions as lies, because such a move
locates a denial in the moral dom ain. Classifying a statem ent as a lie supposes
that the speaker has achieved a level of agency that is simply not achieved by
som eone who utters a denial. Such a person is in conflict and is thus not m as
ter in her own home. She is subject to negative forces that she does not con
trol. A denial can therefore be better classified as a sign o f deficiency in
agency. It shows an anthropological weakness and not a moral failure. T his
ends the first part o f the book, in which the text o f Freud is clarified.
In chapters 3 and 4 o f the book, I exam ine the conflicted forces that are
behind the creation o f negations and denials. I do so by employing H egel’s
philosophy. In chapter 3, I make use o f H egel’s anthropology in order to the
orize about denial, making philosophical generalizations where Freud makes
astute observations. In H egel’s analysis o f the master-slave dialectic, Hegel
demonstrates that the relationship between the body and the mind involves
contradictory requirements which unavoidably lead to denial. I make that
argument more general by using H egel’s claim that the road to truth is not
solely a path o f doubt, but more properly a highway o f despair. T h e road
towards truth changes doubt into despair whenever doubt involves on e’s self
conception. If doubt undermines one’s self-conception, it destroys the possi
bility of being a desiring subject. Such a doubt makes one lose on e’s bearings
and creates despair. Denial can thus be understood as a desiring being’s
defense against despair.
In chapter 4, I start from the view that a denial is a misguided effort to
sustain life by avoiding despair. I try to clarify the misguided effort to sustain
life, present in a denial, by appealing to H egel’s analysis of the hum an will.
T h e appeal to H egel is prom ising in that H egel defines the free will as a will
that relates negatively to the object o f its own willing. T h e student, whose
summer job consists of washing dishes, rem ains free in so far as he relates neg
IN T R O D U C T IO N 3
atively to what he does by saying that he is earning his college tuition. Thus,
the student is able to m aintain that washing dishes is only a byproduct o f his
effort to earn his tuition. I then argue that in uttering a denial, a person tries
to exercise the negativity, required for the will to be free, by denying an epis-
tem ological connection rather than by putting distance between the ob jec
tively given and the volition o f the will.
Hegel calls the eudemonic will the will which is able to create distance
between itself and the objectively given without denying epistem ologically
that given. It succeeds in doing so because it is able to create a norm, h appi
ness, to which it subjects any thing that is objectively given. A ll that is objec
tively given is epistem ologically recognized, but no given is allowed to make
a decisive influence on what the will intends to decide. T h e given that is ch o
sen as object of the will is the given that contributes to the goal of the will,
say, happiness. T h e eudemonic will thus succeeds both in being open to the
given and keeping its distance from the given when making a decision.
W here the eudem onic will succeeds, the arbitrary will fails. It is a will
which exercises the necessary distance dem anded by a free will by not giving
enough consideration to the given. Instead, the arbitrary will is a will that
reserves for itself the right to decide without having to give a reason beyond
the claim: I so decided. For the arbitrary will, the given is disregarded as a
legitim ate input in the decision.
It looks as if som eone who utters a denial tries to create the distance to
the given, required to be a free will, by disregarding the epistem ologically
given, as does the arbitrary will, instead o f creating that distance by evalu
ating the given in terms of its contribution to a personal goal, as does the
eudem onic will. S uch a H egelian interpretation o f denial allows us to
understand why the therapeutic effort of patients uttering a denial consists
o f two steps. First, it must address the epistem ological error used m istakenly
to create the illusionary distance required by the logic o f the will. Secondly,
it must provide the will with the ability to accept the objectively given
while m ain tain ing the possibility o f evaluating th at given in light o f on e’s
chosen goals.
In chapters 5, 6, and 7 o f the book, I address three im plications of
Freud’s theory o f denial. In chapter 5, I exam ine Freud’s claim that the
acquisition o f the linguistic symbol o f negation is the prerequisite for free
dom of the will. I find Spitz’s work to be a useful framework in which to
address that question. Spitz argues that hum an beings, particularly children,
do not show a linear developm ent. Rather, he argues, multiple parallel
developm ents lead to the creation o f new possibilities. A s exam ples he gives
the appearance o f the social sm ile at about two m onths, the eight-m onth
anxiety— som etim es also called separation anxiety, and the no-saying at
about fifteen m onths o f age. T h ese phenom ena are indicators of the new
psychic possibilities o f the child. Thus, the eight-m onth anxiety indicates
4 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
that the child establishes a deeper relationship with its caregivers. I argue
that the anxiety indicates that the child is dealing with the alienating
dim ensions o f having appropriated its body in the mirror stage. T h e no-say
ing is, according to Spitz, the first unequivocal concept used by the child. I
argue that the no-saying o f the child shows an irrational dim ension in that
the child seems to refuse that which it manifestly wants. T h at irrational
dim ension becom es supremely rational if one understands that the no-say
ing aims at cutting the em otional ties with the caregiver. I interpret the n o
saying of the fifteen-m onth-old infant as her effort to establish the right to
decide on her own, even if th at m eans losing what she wants. I also argue
that the use o f the linguistic symbol of negation (no-saying), by itself, affirms
the right to autonomy. It is not only an indicator o f the autonom y of the
child, it is the organizer of that autonomy. I argue that the eight-m onth an x
iety is only an indicator, and not an organizer, of the new psychic achieve
ments o f the child at eight m onths. T h e new psychic achievem ent is the
establishm ent o f a deeper attachm ent to caregivers in order to overcom e the
alienating dim ension of having appropriated the body.
In chapter 6, I analyze more closely the process of undoing a denial as it
happens in Sophocles’ tragedy Oedipus, the King. Freud warned us that such
a process is difficult and arduous. Sop h ocles’ tragedy allows us to illustrate
the idea that a denial is connected with situations in which the self-image
o f a person is threatened in such a way that the possibility o f desire is
destroyed. Oedipus, the King shows how and how not to help som eone undo
a denial.
In chapter 7 , 1 analyze the autobiography of A ntony M oore in which the
author reveals the many com plex psychic acts he has undertaken to over
com e a profound denial. Indeed, M oore, who lost his father in the Second
W orld War when he was only two m onths old, developed unconsciously a
deep identification with his dead and idealized father. A t the same time,
when asked if he missed his father, he replied, when growing up: “O ne can
not miss what one never had.” H e com bined this primary denial with the idea
that he had learned to be his own father and thus needed no substitute father,
certainly not in the figure o f his m aternal grandfather. Finally, in his childish
grandiosity, he made him self unconsciously responsible for the death of his
father by the argument that his father died shortly after he was born. T h ere
fore, there was no room in the world for both of them. Moore thus felt that
in fathering a son, his father wrote his own death warrant and that if he were
to father a child it would m ean his own death as well. In the autobiography
o f M oore, more than in the article by Freud, we see that a denial is, as it were,
the tip o f an iceberg, covering deep tragic experiences. In that same autobi
ography we find a description o f all the psychic work that is required to undo,
not just intellectually but also emotionally, a denial. I will dem onstrate that
it is by m eans of appropriate help from others and by m eans of m etaphoric
IN T R O D U C T IO N 5
work by him self that M oore was able to acknowledge that he deeply missed
his father but could also start feeling that he was not responsible for the death
of his father. Furthermore, he could start experiencing him self as the fulfill
m ent o f the promise of life, which did not com e to fruition in his father but
which did come to fruition in the son.
ONE
The Complex
Phenomenon of Denial
abstract: Freud drew attention to the puzzling phenom enon o f denial in many
passages of his work. He focused on some o f the contradictory aspects o f the
phenom enon in an article published in 1925. In that same article Freud theo
rized about a num ber o f characteristics in hum an beings that one must postu
late in order to do justice to these many puzzling and contradictory aspects of
denial. O ne o f the strongest conclusions that Freud made was the claim that
n egation is a precondition for hum an freedom. I will present Freud’s ideas, but
I will also dem onstrate that his analysis is incom plete. In particular, Freud, in
his crucial article on denial (“N egatio n ” 1925), did not analyze the arduous
work required to undo fully a denial and its consequences. In particular Freud
did not draw atten tion to the need for acts o f separation from primary care
givers and for the creation o f m etaphoric m oves in order to free oneself from
the contradictions inherent in denials.
IN T R O D U C T IO N
In this chapter I will present Freud’s analysis o f the puzzling phenom enon of
denial, which consists o f simultaneously denying and revealing the truth.
Thus, when a patient answers that the female figure in his dream is not his
mother, Freud interprets the answer as revealing that it really is his mother
(Freud, S .E ., XIX , 2 3 5 ).1 Or when a patient boasts that it is pleasant not to
have had her headaches for so long, Freud interprets this as signaling that the
attack is not far off (Ibid. 236).
I will start by delineating the problem as Freud treated it. N ext, I will
show that the phenom enon o f denial is part of a larger process. I will also
7
8 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
point out that Freud refrains from fully analyzing that whole process, leaving
a prom ising task for readers of this chapter. Third, I will describe and elabo
rate on three m etapsychological insights of Freud, one of which, I will show,
implies that realizing the truth hidden in a denial is more than an epistemo-
logical problem: it involves hard em otional work. Fourth, I will show some
lim itations in Freud’s analysis of the phenom enon o f denial. In particular, I
will show that realizing the truth hidden in a denial requires more than epis-
tem ological work; it requires also acts o f separation from intim ate others and
the mobilization o f powerful aspects o f language. Finally, I will briefly present
and analyze an autobiography in which the author describes the undoing of a
profound denial related to the death of his father on the battlefield when the
author was a two-month old infant. T h is case will illustrate my theoretical
claim that undoing a denial requires acts o f separation and skillful usages of
m etaphors.2
1. D E M A R C A T I O N O F T H E P R O B L E M
By the exam ples he gives, Freud demarcates the problem he intends to dis
cuss by m eans of the concept o f Vememung, translated in the the Standard
Edition of Freud’s works as “negation,” but which I prefer to translate as
“denial.”’ Freud’s dem arcation is at the same time restrictive and expansive.
Let us first look at the restrictions imposed by Freud’s exam ples on the
dom ain of the concept Vemeinung. In the first exam ple, a patient rejects an
em otion that might be imputed to her, given what she intends to say. Freud
presents the case in this way: “N ow you’ll think I m ean to say som ething
insulting, but really I’ve no such intention” (Ibid. 235). Freud continues by
presenting what he thinks goes on in the patient: “We realize that this is a
rejection, by projection, o f an idea that has just com e up” (Ibid.). Typical for
a denial is the fact that the patient labels a phenom enon— in this case an
em otion— but that the labeling is incorrectly rejected as untrue.
T he second exam ple concerns a patient who has told Freud about a
dream in which there is a female figure. Freud reports the case as follows:
‘“You ask who this person in the dream can be. It is not my mother.’” Freud
then continues: “We emend this to: ‘S o it is his m other.’ In our interpreta
tion, we take the liberty o f disregarding the negation and o f picking out the
subject-m atter alone o f the association. It is as though the patient had said:
‘It’s true that my mother cam e into my mind as I thought of this person, but
I don’t feel inclined to let the association count’” (Ibid.). In his com m ents on
this second exam ple Freud is very explicit about the two dim ensions he seems
to consider constitutive o f the phenom enon o f denial. O n the one hand,
there is an activity of labeling. Freud describes it as an act o f associating a
known figure (m other) with the unknown figure in the dream. Describing
what happens in the first constitutive m om ent o f denial as an association
TH E COM PLEX PH ENO M EN O N OF D EN IA L 9
accepts the face-saving device and describes what he thinks is furthest from
his mind, he almost always describes the unconscious correctly. In one o f the
next paragraphs, Freud calls the negation in a denial “the hall-mark o f repres
sion, a certificate o f origin— like, let us say, ‘Made in G erm any’” (Ibid. 23 6 ).5
Som e authors have expanded the m eaning o f denial to include non-ver
bal activities.6 Thus Edith Jacobson uses the label ‘denial’ for such phenom
ena as am nesia (Jacobson 63, 64), disavowal or undoing of castration (Ibid.
74, 77, 83), avoidance (Ibid. 75), and wishful fantasies distorting reality when
they are a m eans o f defending against fearful objects (Ibid. 78). Such an
expansion o f the concept o f denial omits, in my opinion, a crucial elem ent in
the phenom enon Freud wants to study: that is, a denial correctly labels the
repressed phenomenon, even though a denial denies the correctness o f the
labeling. Labeling and correctly labeling that which is repressed are crucial
aspects o f the puzzle which Freud wants to study under the phenom enon
called ‘denial.’7
T here is, however, an expanded m eaning of denial which does corre
spond to Freud’s interpretation of denial. I believe that I can argue for that
expansion because Freud provided a fourth exam ple o f the kind o f ph e
nom ena he was going to study. T h e fact that the exam ple is m entioned not
in the m ain text, but in a footnote, m ight indicate th at Freud, too, felt that
this exam ple is a form o f extension o f the core phenom enon. H e actually
claim s that the fourth exam ple is using the sam e process; he does not claim
that the process is identical with the process at work in the first three exam
ples. Here is how Freud describes the new exam ple, which he calls boasting:
“‘How nice n ot to have had one o f my headaches for so long.’ But this is in
fact the first announcem ent o f an attack, o f whose approach the subject is
already sensible, although he is as yet unwilling to believe it” (Freud, S .E .,
X IX , 236). A t first, one could argue th at the patient in this new exam ple
does not make a false statem ent. It seems to be correct for the patient to say
that he has not had the headaches for a long time. Therefore, this exam ple
could be said to be a misfit. It is not a proper exam ple o f the phenom enon
Freud is studying, for in it nothing is falsely denied. However, when one
looks in the rest o f Freud’s oeuvre one can notice additional sim ilar exam
ples.8 Freud’s explanation o f these exam ples provides argum ents for seeing
the sim ilarity between the fourth exam ple and the other three. In the
process, Freud also forces us to accept a fourth not-so-visible constituent
elem ent in the phenom enon o f denial.
Freud discusses the danger o f boasting in his study o f Frau Emmy von N .
H e does so in a long footnote, having warned his readers at the beginning of
his study that he will reproduce the notes that he made at night during the
beginning o f the treatm ent and will put insights acquired later in footnotes
(Freud, S .E ., II, 48). Emmy von N . regularly had “neck-cram ps.” Freud
describes them as consisting “in an ‘icy grip’ on the back o f the neck, together
TH E COM PLEX PH EN O M EN O N OF D ENIA L 11
with an onset o f rigidity and a painful coldness in all her extrem ities, an in ca
pacity to speak and com plete prostration. They last from six to twelve hours”
(Ibid. 71). In the evening session o f May 17, 1889,9 Emmy von N . “expressed
her astonishm ent that it was such a long time since she had had any neck-
cramps, though they usually cam e on before every thunderstorm ” (Ibid. 75).
T h e morning o f M ay 18, Emmy von N . “com plained o f cold at the back of
her neck, tightness and pains in the face, hands and feet. Her features were
strained and her hands clenched” (Ibid. 7 5-76). In a footnote which may
have been written up to five years after the treatment, Freud writes that
Emmy von N .’s “astonishm ent the evening before at its being so long since
she had had a neck-cramp . . . [can be understood as] a prem onition o f an
approaching condition which was already in preparation at the time and was
perceived in the unconscious” (Ibid. 76, n. 1). T he patient disregards the true
premonition.
Freud describes a second patient, Frau C acilie M ., who regularly had sim
ilar premonitions. Thus, Freud writes, “while she was in the best of health,
she said to me ‘It’s a long time since I’ve been frightened of witches at night,’
or, ‘how glad I am that I’ve not had pains in my eyes for such a long tim e,’ I
could feel sure that the following night a severe onset of her fear o f witches
would be making extra work for her nurse or that her next attack o f pains in
the eyes was on the point of beginning” (Ibid. 76, n. 1). Freud provides a
beginning o f a conceptualization of these phenom ena. H e says it this way:
“O n each occasion what was already present as a finished product in the
unconscious was beginning to show through indistinctly. T h is idea, which
emerged as a sudden notion, was worked over by the unsuspecting ‘official’
consciousness (to use C h arcot’s term ) into a feeling of satisfaction, which
swiftly and invariably turned out to be unjustified” (Ibid. 76, n. 1). These
exam ples o f boasting are therefore not, strictly speaking, like the other three
exam ples o f denial. In boasting the patient does not utter a falsity. It is indeed
true that the patient has not had neck-cramp, been frightened o f witches, or
had pain in the eyes. However, what the patient is reporting is naive because
it does not report the most interesting thing that could be reported. T he
patient does not say that he feels that an attack, or witches, or pain in the
eyes is coming. Here we com e to the essence o f Freud’s new insight. Freud
claim s that the unconscious has a wisdom that consciousness does not have.
Freud claim s that the cause for the boasting o f his patients is the wisdom of
the unconscious which feels that the attack or the painful crisis is coming.
Consciousness, in its limited inform ation capabilities, does not see the attack
on the horizon. A ll that consciousness can report is that it is aware that these
attacks have not occurred for some time. Freud thus tells us, on the one hand,
that the unconscious takes the initiative and formulates the truth, but that,
on the other hand, consciousness does not know what the unconscious
already knows. Freud says as much when he explains the popular warning
12 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
2. P H E N O M E N O L O G I C A L A N A L Y S I S
O F T H E P R O C E S S O F D E N IA L
H aving delineated the phenom enon that he wants to analyze (verbal denial),
Freud then proceeds to unpack the background o f that phenom enon. Freud
teaches us that a verbal denial is part of a larger process.
First, there is a postulated prior phase: repression. Freud points out that
a Vemeinung (den ial) has the effect o f “taking cognizance o f what is
repressed” (Ibid. 235). T h is idea is so im portant to Freud th at he form ulates
it three more tim es. H e writes: “T hus the conten t o f a repressed im age or
idea can m ake its way into consciousness, on condition that it is negated"
(Ibid.). Or: “ it [Vemeinung (a denial)] is already a lifting o f the repression”
(Ibid.). O r finally: “ [by Vemeinung (a denial)] one consequence o f the
process of repression is undone— the fact, namely, o f the ideational content
o f what is repressed not reaching consciousness” (Ibid.). A s already pointed
TH E CO M PLEX PH EN O M EN O N OF D EN IA L 13
out in the analysis of the exam ples given by Freud, a necessary precondition
for a denial thus seem s to be the existence o f repression. W hen the m ech
anism o f repression is successful then consciousness is faced with a blank.
For the patient who dream ed about a fem ale figure, a successful repression
would have resulted in her saying: “You ask me who that figure is in my
dream ? I do not know.” We have an exam ple in Freud’s patien t Emmy von
N ., when Freud asks her “what the stam m er cam e from ” ( S .E ., II, 61).
Freud reports th at the patient reacted by silence, by giving no reply. W hen
Freud insisted and asked: “D on’t you know?” she replied “N o .” W hen Freud
pressed her by asking “W hy not?” the patient angrily replied: “Because I
mayn’t” (Ibid.).
Second, there is the actual phase o f denial. By contrasting the phenom
enon o f denial with the postulated state that preceded it, Freud is able to
emphasize the novelty in the phenom enon o f denial. T h e novelty is that
consciousness is now aware of a phenom enon that it was not aware o f before.
Further on in his reflections, Freud describes denial as contributing to free
dom o f thinking because it provides consciousness with conten t that it
lacked, insofar as consciousness is now aware of that which it previously was
not. Furthermore, repressed thoughts are im portant— Freud even claim s that
they are indispensable— to the patient. Freud puts it this way: “W ith the
help o f the symbol of negation [in a denial], thinking frees itself from the
restrictions o f repression and enriches itself with m aterial that is indispens
able for its proper functioning” (S .E ., X IX , 236). A gain: “But the perfor
m ance o f the function o f judgm ent is not m ade possible until the creation of
the symbol of negation has endowed thinking with a first measure o f free
dom from the consequences o f repression and, with it, from the com pulsion
of the pleasure principle” (Ibid. 239).
Freud, however, points out that one should not be too enthusiastic about
the presumed victory o f denial over repression. H e describes that victory in a
variety o f ways. He writes that a denial is “a way o f taking cognizance o f what
is repressed . . . though not, o f course an acceptance of what is repressed”
(Ibid. 23 5 -3 6 ). Or: “W ith the help o f negation only one consequence of
repression is undone” (Ibid. 236). O r finally: “T h e outcom e o f this is a kind
o f intellectual acceptance of the repressed, while at the same time what is
essential to the repression persists” (Ibid.). A denial is thus a very ambiguous
perform ance.12 It undoes one crucial aspect o f repression in that a denial
labels the repressed. A denial lets a careful listener know precisely what the
object of an effort o f repression is. O n the other hand, a denial makes it clear
to any listener that the patient does not accept the truth as it is labeled and
thus revealed in a denial. Freud knows that the female figure represented—
let us suppose as dom ineering— in the patient’s dream is in truth the patient’s
mother. But the patien t’s denial states the contrary: that female figure is not
my mother. Freud describes the ambiguity o f this denial quite well when he
14 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
writes: “It is as though the patient had said: ‘It’s true that my mother cam e
into my mind as I thought o f this person, but I don ’t feel inclined to let the
association count’” (Ibid. 235). In a denial, a patient thus rejects or refuses to
accept a true proposition.
Third, Freud informs us that therapy can prom ote further progress. Freud
reports that it is possible to conquer “the negation as well and [bring] about
a full intellectual acceptance o f the repressed” (Ibid. 236). He adds, however,
that in this new phase “the repressive process itself is not yet rem oved”
(Ibid.). O ne can im agine that Freud asked the patient who dreamt about the
female figure what eyes the female figure had, what hair, what clothes, what
shoes, and so forth. If the patient was forced to recognize each time that the
eyes, the hair, the clothes and the shoes o f the figure all resembled those of
his mother, he m ight then have concluded: “I guess it then must be my
mother.” Such an intellectual acknowledgm ent is clearly not a full em otional
acknow ledgm ent.13 A s in the case of denial, here too there is a split between
the intellectual and the affective processes.14
Clearly, this latter situation suggests the expected existence o f a fourth
stage in the process of denial wherein that which is repressed is overcome
both intellectually and affectively.15 O ne can imagine that the patient who
dreamt about a dom ineering lady and who subsequently identified her as his
mother is now able to solve the em otional conflict arising from the fact that
the female figure is simultaneously a dom ineering figure and his mother.
Freud does not provide us, in his article, with any hints o f the steps that will
have to be taken to achieve that fourth stage.16 In the rest o f this chapter I
will articulate insights derived from studying that fourth stage.17
3. F R E U D ’S M E T A -P S Y C H O L O G IC A L R E F L E C T IO N S
H aving observed a difference between the em otional reaction and the intel
lectual attitude towards a repressed phenom enon as revealed in a denial, one
would have expected that Freud would have reflected on that difference.
Instead, Freud uses m ost o f the rest o f the article on denial to explain how the
intellectual function, that is, judging, is similar to and possibly emerges out of
the affective life.18 He makes use of the generally accepted distinction
between an attributive and an existential judgm ent. In an attributive judg
m ent one is concerned with whether an object— in Freud’s exam ples, the
ego— has a particular quality. A m I a person who insults people, has bad ideas
about my mother, and so forth? A n existential judgm ent must decide whether
a representation exists only in my memory or in my mind or, on the contrary,
also exists in reality. Freud gives as exam ple the child who imagines the
m other’s breast. A n existential judgm ent must make the distinction between
a representation to which nothing corresponds in reality and a representation
that fits the reality.
TH E COM PLEX PH EN O M EN O N OF D ENIA L 15
ego itself. T h is insight destroyed the opposition between the libido (a force
for reproduction) and the “ego-force.” In Beyond the Pleasure Principle, Freud
explicitly accepts this conclusion and therefore reduces both the ego-
instincts and the libido to one force, Eros (Freud, S .E ., XV III, 4 4 -6 1 ). T h e
force opposing the libido (or love-force) is the instinct of destruction (which
in its ultim ate form is the death-instinct). Thus, Freud reintroduces psycho
logical duality.
T h e second pair, substitute for uniting and successor to expulsion, is a
strange one. T h e way Freud labels them indicates that the two elements of
the pair are not co-equal; there is no symmetry between the two. T h e G er
man word Nachfolge (successor) indicates that a prior action has taken
place— referred to as expulsion. Freud’s understanding of the way the original
narcissistic ego constructs itself is consonant with the idea that it is a “suc
cessor.” Indeed, Freud claim s that the narcissistic ego is the result of—
m etaphorically— ‘spitting out o f itself’ what is considered bad (Freud, S .E .,
X IX , 237). T he G erm an word Ersatz (substitute), on the other hand, is used
for an object or a situation. T he idea that som ething is a substitute presup
poses that som ething precedes the substitute either in time or in thought.
T he idea o f unity does not include that same suggestion of a prior state as sug
gested by the idea o f substitute. C ould this m ean that, according to Freud,
unity is the primary situation o f the child, whereas rejection (spitting out) is
a secondary reaction?23
T h e asymmetry signaled in the choice of labels for the second of the
three pairs o f words relating judgm ents and affective forces can be clarified
further by reflecting on the central problem of this article: negation-denial.
A denial presupposes, first, a connection between two facts, that is, a form of
unity. A denial also presupposes that this connection was repressed. A nega
tive judgm ent— particularly a denial— is then the expression of an original
connection and of a trace of a prior repression, that is, a negation. A n affir
m ative judgm ent expresses only a relation between the two contents.
W hether or not there was a split between them is not expressed in an affir
m ative judgm ent. Thus, an affirmative judgm ent has less expressive potential
than a negative judgm ent. In an affirmative judgm ent one only affirms a con
nection or a unity. W hat preceded the connection cannot be expressed by an
affirmative judgment.
T h is leads us to the first pair m entioned by Freud: the affirmative and the
negative judgm ent. T his pair too must consist o f parts that are not equally
important. T h e negative judgm ent has more expressive potential. Thus, it is
understandable that Freud finishes the paragraph by underlining the central
function o f the symbol o f negation. N egation expresses both a connection
between two concepts and a rejection of that connection. W hen the n ega
tive sentence is a denial, then the negation is a sign o f a repression which is
sim ultaneously overcome and m aintained at a new level.
18 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
4. S P E C I F I C A T I O N S A N D C O R R E C T I O N S
O F F R E U D ’S R E F L E C T IO N S
adult who prohibits and does what the adult wants— for exam ple, not touch
ing an electric outlet (Ibid. 56). However, such a reaction leads to unaccept
able frustrations for the child. Furthermore, the passivity forced upon the
child provokes an aggressive reaction from the unconscious. T h e child is thus
put in a paradoxical situation: he/she is still in a very dependent relation with
the m aternal figure while also feeling aggression towards that same figure.
Spitz believes that the child resolves this tension by identifying with its
m other as an aggressor (Ibid. 56, 133).28 By such a m ove the child dynam i
cally satisfies both contradictory feelings. In consequence, the child acquires
no-saying and is now able to use the word or gesture with all the frustration
and aggression attached to it. Finally, the child can make use of the newly
acquired word (or gesture) either against him or herself or against the mother.
In using the no-saying against him or herself the child creates a cleavage
within between him or herself as an object observed and as an observer (Ibid.
130, 133). In using the no-saying against a person with whom the child has
“primary narcissistic dependent relations” (Ibid. 56), the child severs his/her
dependency relations with that person (Ibid. 52) and establishes separateness
(Ibid. 57). From then on the child will have to establish new kinds of rela
tions with that person. Spitz calls those new relations “highly enriched” (Ibid.
57, 129, 131).29 By means of a case I will study in the next section, I will
dem onstrate that the acts of separation and severing involved in no-saying
introduce a need for m etaphorical relations. T h e linguistic form o f negation
will thus lead us by m eans o f the idea o f separation and the idea of aggression
hidden in acts of separation to the appearance of the phenom enon of
metaphor.30
5. C O M P L E T IN G F R E U D ’S R E F L E C T I O N S
In his study on denial, Freud greatly stressed the im portance for the hum an
being of acquiring the linguistic symbol o f negation. However, I claim that,
in laying this stress, Freud was also undervaluing the many other functions
o f language, as well as undervaluing the act of separation, with its implied
aggression, that is behind the no-saying. I will now illustrate my claim with
a concrete case o f denial and the person’s successful efforts at overcom ing
the denial.
In Father, Son, and Healing Ghosts, the author, A nthony M oore, provides
us with an autobiographical account of dealing with his father’s death. W hen
M oore was two m onths old, his father died on a battlefield in the Second
World War. A s a young boy, M oore developed several strategies to deal with
this traum atic event. H e identified with his father, the dead marine officer, so
strongly and im itated him so much that the young M oore at one point felt
that “he was unable to be [himself] (M oore 4 ).31 A t the same time, when
asked about his feelings about the loss o f his father, M oore had the habit,
TH E COM PLEX PH EN O M EN O N OF D EN IA L 21
from his childhood on, o f answering: “You can ’t miss what you never had”
(Ibid. 1). Clearly this is a denial. We can see the pain o f losing his father in
his attem pts to erase it via suffocating im itation and identification. We also
find traces o f young M oore’s pain— some o f it self-inflicted— in two fantasies
related to his father’s death. A s he was born A pril 16, 1944, and his father
died June 15, 1944, young M oore developed the fantasy that there must not
have been space enough in the world for both of them together and that thus
he was the cause o f his father’s death. H e further fantasized that if he were to
father a child that would be his own death warrant (Ibid. 3, 98).
W ith the help of a therapist, as in Freud’s own reported examples, Moore
was able to undo intellectually the denial that he did not miss his father. In
the case o f Moore, the therapist said: “You can also miss what you never had
but know you had every right to have” (Ibid. 4). Emotionally undoing the con
flict and healing the wound behind the denial is a more com plicated story.
M oore’s efforts at distancing him self from the idealization of his father
were crucial. A fter years as a dedicated and enthusiastic student in a military
high school, the young M oore avoided R O T C in college. H e gives as his rea
son that he felt he “had had enough o f the military” (Ibid. 2). By his senior
year, M oore returned to his love for the M arines and took the entrance exam
for the M arine C orps Officer C andidate School (Ibid. 2). His first attem pt at
separating from his idealized father had not stuck. A second and new form of
separation was initiated when he told his m other and grandm other of his
plans to enroll in the M arine Officer School while the Vietnam War was tak
ing place. W hat the young M oore saw in their eyes was either their fear o f his
death or their disapproval o f his risking his life. His mother (and grand
m other) had put a wedge between the young M oore and his father by appeal
ing to his own wish to live (Ibid. 2). T h e young M oore accepted their invi
tation to make the separation from his idealized father.
M oore him self tells us that once he had separated him self from his
father’s identity he felt the need “to reconnect to the energy and m eaning
that continued to flow from the image of [his] father” (Ibid. 5). M oore thus
found him self in the contradictory situation that he wanted to be both sepa
rate from and rem ain connected with his father. He found a solution to this
challenge in what in Lacanian terminology is called a m etaphoric m ove.32
H aving refused to becom e a M arine because that might lead to death, the
young M oore lost an important connection with his father. M oore recovered
that connection with his father by becom ing a Jesuit. M oore writes about this
decision: “Being a Jesuit was like being a M arine. Som etim es the Jesuits were
even referred to as the Pope’s Marines. Furthermore, the idea o f joining a reli
gious order carried with it an image of dying, dying to the world, particularly
the world o f m arital love” (Ibid. 3 ).33 By the m etaphorical power of the words
“M arine” and “dying” the younger M oore was able to reconnect with his
father after having separated him self from him .34
22 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
C O N C L U S IO N
T h e analysis o f M oore’s undoing of his denial can help us clarify the concept
o f self-deception. O ne is right in saying that the younger M oore deceived
him self when he was telling him self and others during his adolescence that
he could not miss his father since he never had one. O ne is also right in say
ing that the younger M oore did not know that he was deceiving himself. He
only knew that he had been deceiving him self after he was helped by his psy-
chiatrist-psychoanalyst, who told him that one can also miss what one never
had but knows one had every right to have.35 A t that m om ent the younger
M oore knew that he had been deceiving himself; he knew that his claim that
one cannot miss a father one never had was a denial. O ne can therefore claim
that it is possible to deceive oneself without knowing that one is deceiving
oneself. Self-deception is thus, strictly speaking, not a lie.36 It becom es a lie
only after the m om ent in which a denial has been intellectually undone and
the person refuses to do the em otional work involved in taking the steps
implied by the intellectual undoing.
Freud praised the linguistic symbol o f negation as a great instrum ent of
freedom. It would be wrong, however, to attribute the healing o f Tony
M oore simply to the m agic power o f the symbol o f negation in his funda
m ental denial. T h e healing was also based on several acts of cutting him self
loose from his father and on the great m etaphor o f being a Jesuit. I believe
th at I have been able to show that Freud’s analysis o f the function of n ega
tion is but the tip o f an iceberg in the process of healing. T h e iceberg
includes at least the idea that one has to cut on eself loose from others with
all the aggression (and guilt) that this involves and the idea that the rich
ness o f language must be used in its many dim ensions, including the
m etaphoric dim ension m ade available by the cultural tradition in which
one lives. I was able to rely on Spitz for pointing out the negative acts
required for personal growth. I was able to rely on L acan and H egel to point
to the requirem ent that the totality o f hum an life needs to be elevated to
the level o f language. Clearly, correcting the epistem ological m istake pre
sent in a denial requires addressing the great anthropological puzzle of
hum an growth with its dem and for aggressive separation from and creative
(m etaphorical) conn ection with our original caregivers. N o t properly d eal
ing with the dem and for separation and conn ection with his father was for
M oore a form o f self-deception even before he form ulated a denial. W hen
M oore form ulated his denial, it was possible for others to see the self-decep
tion at work. O nly when he was able to intellectually undo his denial was
M oore confronted with the choice o f lying to him self or being authentic.
A s I see it, M oore avoided lying to him self because he was w illing to face
the difficult em otional dem ands m ade on him self in order to deal in a dif
TH E COM PLEX PH ENO M EN O N OF D EN IA L 23
ferent way with the need to separate him self from his father while satisfy
ing his need to rem ain connected with him . T hus, although the concepts
o f denial, self-deception, and lying about on eself partially overlap, they are
not identical and should be carefully distinguished. I will devote the next
chapter to this problem atic.
TW O
abstract. Freud’s theory o f denial (negation ) implies several theses about hum an
self-knowledge. T h e first thesis is that self-knowledge is not identical to self
revelation; hum an beings reveal more about the self than they are able to
acknowledge consciously. T h e second thesis is that self-knowledge can be con
tradicted by self-revelation and can therefore be proven false. T h e third thesis
is that unacknow ledged self-revelation can be used to correct or broaden one’s
self-knowledge. T h e fourth thesis is that hum an beings encounter lim its to self
knowledge. Therefore errors in the description of the self are not necessarily
lies or expressions o f bad faith. T h e fifth thesis is that the lim its to self-knowl
edge are n ot fixed; they can be changed. T h ese limits can be altered n ot only
by personal effort, but also by appropriate h elp from others. In this chapter I
concentrate on the ethical im plications of Freud’s theory o f self-knowledge as
implied by his study on denial (negation): m istakes in self-description, when
put into the terms o f ethical language, should n ot always be called lies.
IN T R O D U C T IO N
In this chapter, I will develop five points. First, I will briefly map out the
Freudian concepts that point to erroneous self-expressions or self-descriptions
such as: lies, hypocrisy, mistakes, illusions, and disavowals. Second, I will draw
attention to the phenom ena (the use of denial and negation as first revelations
of painful truths) that Freud wants to explain with his theory of negation.
Third, I will demonstrate that these phenom ena are crucial in psychotherapy
25
26 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
and that Freud gradually cam e to perceive their central function. In Freud’s
oeuvre, one can find vestiges of his emerging awareness of the importance of
facts and events. Fourth, I will show the far-reaching epistem ological im plica
tions of Freud’s theory of negation for a theory of self-knowledge. Fifth, I will
ponder about some apparent contradictions.
1. A M A P O F F R E U D ’ S C O N C E P T S O F
E R R O N E O U S FO R M S O F SE L F -D E S C R IP T IO N S
self-confident” (Ibid. 305). Afterwards, she was “shy and tim id” (Ibid.). Freud
discovered that, for the girl, taking money from her father was associated with
an incident in which the nursemaid gave the girl money to remain silent
about the nursem aid’s erotic relations with a doctor. Through this associa
tion, taking money was unconsciously associated with an offer o f tenderness,
with “a declaration o f love” (Ibid. 307). T h e anger o f the father m eant that
her offer was rejected.
In the second case, Freud discovered that, when his patient was a young
girl, she could not deal with the fact that her father was less powerful than
she had thought. She adored and identified with her idealized father. O ne of
the talents the girl admired very much in her father was his drawing talent.
Her attem pt to draw a perfect circle was thus an attem pt to show not only
how she could draw, but also how well her father could. Sh e could therefore
not acknowledge anything that would dim inish the achievem ent.
In his introductory and concluding remarks, Freud writes that such lies
should not be interpreted morally; rather, educators should becom e con
cerned about the child’s unconscious problems. In the m ain text, Freud links
children’s lies to the lie’s hidden m eaning. A bout the first case, Freud writes:
“She could not admit, however, that she had appropriated the money; she
was obliged to disavow it, because her m otive for the deed which was uncon
scious to herself, could not be adm itted” (Ibid. 307). T h e reason why it could
not be adm itted becom es clear when Freud summarizes the two cases at the
end o f his paper: “an adm ission was impossible for the same reason that was
given in the first o f the observations: it would inevitably have been an adm is
sion o f her hidden incestuous love” (Ibid. 3 0 8 -309).
Clearly, Freud intends to argue in this article that a lie is to be inter
preted in some cases as the impossibility of self-knowledge when self-knowl
edge would be incom patible with self-love based on identification with an
idealized person.
Hypocrisy too is interpreted not so much as a conscious lie as it is a fail
ure to live up to an ideal. Freud infers such a failure from mistakes that patients
often unconsciously make. Thus, in his article “Thoughts for the Times on
War and D eath,” (S .E ., XIV, 273-300) Freud defines hypocrisy as that attitude
which tries to follow cultural prescriptions even if one’s own drives are really
desiring som ething different. Hypocrisy is then described as follows:
2. F R E U D ’ S E M E R G I N G A W A R E N E S S
O F T H E F U N C T IO N O F N E G A T IO N
Freud’s theory o f negation first attem pts to explain the appearance of a lin
guistic expression (i.e., a negation) which fallaciously changes the meaning
o f statem ents. Freud already observed this phenom enon in the treatm ent of
Emmy v. N . (1 8 88-89) (1 893).2 Thus, Freud suggests, in a footnote, a rela
tionship between a negative statem ent and repression. (S .E ., II, 57, n. 2)
In his analysis o f the Rat-m an (1907) (1909), and again in a footnote,
Freud shows that he is already fam iliar with the curious phenom enon of
denial. Indeed, he writes: “T h is is a com m on type o f reaction to repressed
m aterial which has becom e conscious: the ‘N o ’ with which the fact is first
denied is immediately followed by a confirm ation o f it, though, to begin with,
only an indirect on e” (S .E ., X , 183, n. 2). T h is leads Freud to make, some ten
pages later, a distinction between two forms of knowing:
It m ust therefore be adm itted that . . . there are two kinds o f knowledge,
and it is reasonable to hold that the patien t ‘know s’ his traum as as that he
does not ‘know ’ them . For he knows them in that he has not forgotten
them , and he does n ot know them in that he is unaware of their sign ifi
cance. (Ibid. 196, n. 1)
In his study of Judge Schreber (1911), Freud mentions the use of negation
as one of the techniques by which the patient indirectly reveals the truth.
Finally, Freud again discusses the problem o f negation twelve years after
his article on “N egation ,” in his study “Construction in A nalysis” (1937).
Here Freud adds a further idea: A denial is an indication that the labor of
SE LF-D E SC R IPT IO N IN FREU D IA N P SY C H O A N A LY SIS 29
Finally, in his 1915 publication “Thoughts for the Times on War and
D eath,” Freud writes:
W h at we call our ‘unconscious’— the deepest strata o f our minds, m ade up
o f instinctual impulses— knows n othin g that is negative, and no negation;
in it, contradictions coincide. For that reason it does not know its own
death, for to that we can give only a negative content. (S .E ., XIV, 296)
30 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
In 1916 Freud writes more precisely: “T h is connects with the further fact
that a representation o f ‘N o ’— or at any rate an unambiguous one— is not to
be found in dream s” (S .E ., XV, 178).
3. FR O M E P IS T E M O L O G Y T O
AN TH RO PO LO G Y AN D O N TO LO GY
Freud’s theory o f negation stresses the fact that negation can only be
explained within a dual framework: an archeology and a teleology.
T he archeological aspect comes through clearly in the following sentence:
To negate som ething in a judgm ent is, at bottom , to say: ‘T h is is som ething
which I should prefer to repress.’ A negative judgm ent is the intellectual
substitute for repression; its ‘n o’ is the hall-m ark of repression, a certificate
of origin— like, let us say, ‘M ade in G erm any.’ (Freud, S .E ., X IX , 236)
But the perform ance of the function of judgm ent is n ot made possible until
the creation of the symbol of negation has endowed thinking with a first
measure o f freedom from the consequences of repression and, with it, from
the com pulsion o f the pleasure principle. (Ibid. 239)
A ccording to this line o f reasoning, negation is a creation that has the pur
pose o f freeing thought or, alternatively, the purpose of enriching thought
with previously repressed unconscious content.
SE LF-D E SC R IPT IO N IN FR EU D IA N PSY C H O A N A LY SIS 31
anthropological thesis is that the self experiences unity with the world prior
to experiencing differences with the world. W ithin such a view, the anthro
pological prerequisites for the epistem ological possibility o f existential judg
ments are that “objects shall have been lost,” and that the self has the
strength and tools to overcome the dictates of the pleasure principle. In the
second period o f the self's self-constitution, the pleasure principle demands
that all good objects— be they lost or not— be im aginatively classified as part
o f the ego. In this period— the period o f the pleasure-ego’s pre-dom inance—
the loss of an object is countered by an effort to create an illusionary presence
o f the object and furthermore by an effort to identify with that object. In that
period, objects can not subjectively be experienced as lost.
Towards the end of his paper, Freud complements his epistemological and
anthropological claims with an ontological one. He uses three parallel pairs of
concepts to present his argument for an ontology of the human person. (Ibid.
239). The three pairs o f concepts are: the epistemological actions o f affirmation
and negation; the ontological entities Eros and the instinct of destruction; and
the concepts serving to relate the epistemological pair to the ontological pair.
I would like to make the tentative claim that in the asymmetry o f the
concepts Freud uses to relate the epistem ological pair to the ontological pair,
we may find a possible key to Freud’s ontology. Indeed, Freud says that affir
m ation is a substitute for unity, whereas negation is a successor to expulsion.
T h e word expulsion presupposes a prior unity, and an action that breaks this
unity. N egation is a successor to that action. T he word substitute (Ersatz) is
more often used to point to a thing replacing another thing than to an action
following another action. Therefore, affirmation is said to be a substitute for
another non-action, that is, the primal situation o f unity. U nity must, there
fore, be thought o f as ontologically primary.
T his tentative claim regarding Freud’s ontology is supported by its abil
ity to explain the sentence immediately following the introduction o f the
parallelism o f the three pairs of concepts. T he sentence it helps explain is:
4. IM P L IC A T IO N S
IN T R O D U C T IO N
37
38 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
1. D E N I A L ’ S P E R V A S I V E P R E S E N C E IN S E L F - K N O W L E D G E
I had to bear it for my little boy’s sake. But when the last insult was added;
when my own servant m aid— ; then I swore to myself: this shall com e to an
end! A n d so I took the reins into my own h and— the w hole control— over
him and everything else. For now I had a weapon against him, you see; he
dared not oppose me. It was then 1 sent Osw ald [her child] away from hom e.
He was nearly seven years old, and was beginning to observe and ask ques
tions, as children do. T h at I could not bear. It seem ed to me the child must
be poisoned by merely breathing the air o f this polluted house. T h a t was
why I sent him away. A n d now you can see, too, why he was never allowed
to set foot inside his hom e so long as his father lived. N o one knows what
that cost me. (Ibsen 1908, 2 0 9 -1 0 )
W hen her grown-up son returns in despair from Paris and com plains that
“the joy o f life, M other— th at’s a thing you don’t know much about in these
parts o f the world” (Ibid. 259), Mrs. A lvin g changes her self-understanding
and says:
A little while ago you spoke o f the joy of life; and at that word a new light
burst for me over my life and everything connected with it. . . . You ought
to have known your father w hen he was a young lieutenant. He was brim
D EN IA L A N D HEGEL’S P H ILO SO P H IC A L A N TH R O P O LO G Y 39
m ing over w ith the joy of life. . . . It was like a breezy day only to look at
him . A n d w hat exuberant strength and vitality there was in him . . . . W ell
then, child o f joy as he was— for he was like a child in those days— he had
to live at hom e here in a half-grown town, w hich had no joys to offer him —
only dissipations. H e had no o b ject in life— only an official position. H e had
n o work into w hich he could throw h im self heart and soul; he had only busi
ness. H e had not a single com rade that could realize what the joy o f life
m eant— only loungers and b oon -com p an io n s.. . . Your poor father found no
outlet for the overpow ering joy o f life that was in him. And I brought no
brightness into his home. (Ibid.; em phasis m ine)
T h ey had taught me a great deal about duties and so forth, w hich I went on
obstinately believing in. Everything was marked out into duties— into my
duties, and his duties, and— I am afraid I made h is hom e intolerable for your
poor father, Osw ald. (Ibid. 277 -7 8 )
Both Sophocles and Ibsen present tragedies in which the m ain character
(Oedipus/M rs. A lving) radically change their self-conception. These charac
ters may help prove the general validity of Freud’s theory; both Oedipus and
Mrs. A lving knew, on some level, the truth about them selves before they
cam e to pronounce that truth.
T h e novelty of Freud’s thesis is that a change of self-conception is based
on an unconscious and true self-understanding and that the change o f con
scious self-conception begins with a denial. M ore precisely, Freud writes that
the ego’s recognition o f the unconscious is expressed in a negative formula.
T he force o f the article’s argument, however, is that the ego’s recognition of
the unconscious must be expressed in a negative formula. T h is is evident from
the following sentence in Freud’s article:
But the perform ance o f the function o f judgm ent is not made possible until
the creation o f the symbol o f n egation has endowed thinking with the first
measure of freedom from the consequences o f repression and, with it, from
the com pulsion o f the pleasure principle. (S .E ., X IX , 239)
2. T H E F O R C E S O F T H E N E G A T IO N IM P L IE D BY D E N IA L S
It is useful to restrict the domain of the puzzle. Indeed, Freud’s exam ples all
refer to knowledge about the self. Perhaps the same thesis holds for knowledge
40 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
of the external world.5 However, here I will address only the puzzle o f knowl
edge about the self.
A t the beginning o f our analysis it is useful to remember that Freud’s the
sis about self-knowledge is diam etrically opposed to the C artesian tradition,
which stresses the them e o f the self-presence of consciousness. Several 19th-
century philosophers presented a view of mankind, that radically departed
from this C artesian tradition. A m ong them are Hegel, M arx, and Nietzsche.
It might be useful to rely on H egel to elucidate Freud’s thesis.
I hope to make progress by analyzing a famous passage of H egel’s Phe
nomenology; “Lordship and Bondage” (H egel 1977 b, 229—40). In that pas
sage, H egel describes the emergence of self-consciousness. Consciousness is
ready to becom e self-consciousness when it discovers its essential contribu
tion to perception. Perception is not just passive registration o f the outside
world. Perception involves activity on the subject’s part. A t first, however,
consciousness is not aware o f its active participation in perception, and there
fore does not know itself. H egel claim s that it is the encounter with another
consciousness that allows it to becom e aware of itself and to differentiate
itself from the object of perception.6 W hen becom ing self-aware, conscious
ness first experiences that it is different from objectivity (self-consciousness is
not one’s knowledge o f one’s own weight, height, grades, etc.). T h is experi
ence, however, is a subjective conviction, not a proven truth. T he proof that
a particular consciousness is not som ething objective lies in the fact that this
consciousness is willing to risk its very objectivity, that is, its life.7 There must
be another consciousness, however, for whom one can prove one’s conviction
and who can then recognize the truth of this conviction. T his other con
sciousness must have the same purpose. Jointly, these two consciousnesses
can now prove to each other that they are as consciousnesses som ething
other than objectivity because in a life and death struggle both are risking
their lives.
Only if one consciousness experiences the fear of death shall this strug
gle end in som ething other than actual death. A ctual death must be avoided
because the death of either consciousness prevents the other consciousness
from recognizing the truth of what consciousness is. Fear o f death, however,
implies that one consciousness is changing its self-conception. Fear o f death
entails em otionally accepting that life, the body, food, shelter, and so on, are
all essential for consciousness. T h e life and death struggle, however, does not
allow for one consciousness to affirm the two characteristics that conscious
ness discovered to be essential for consciousness: that is, on the one hand,
that consciousness is not objectivity and thus that objectivity is worthless to
it while, on the other hand, that objectivity (life, the body, etc.) is essential
for consciousness.
T he two characteristics cannot be affirmed simultaneously, because in a
life and death struggle, one either continues the struggle— thereby dem on
D EN IA L A N D HEGEL’S P H ILO SP H IC A L A N TH R O P O LO G Y 41
strating that life is a secondary value— or gives up the struggle— thus indi
cating that life is crucial to consciousness. O ne cannot do both at the same
time. We thus discover that consciousness cannot make the transition to self
consciousness alone.8 It needs another consciousness. Two consciousnesses
can make that transition because each can prove one o f the two necessary but
contradictory or m utually exclusive features o f consciousness. T h e conscious
ness that is willing to continue to fight proves that objectivity is secondary
for consciousness. T h e consciousness that fears death proves that objectivity
is essential for consciousness. T h e first is called the master. T he second is
called the slave.
Both the master and the slave have opted for a specific self-conception.
Both hope to realize a self by m eans o f a self-image. In his analysis, Hegel
explains the disappointm ent of the master by showing how his self-image
cannot possibly be a reliable guide towards self-fulfillment. Hegel offers two
arguments as to why the m aster’s self-image is or will be a disappointm ent.
T he first argument is a general, and thus an abstract, argument: the m aster’s
ultim ate desire, H egel reminds us, was the will to be recognized as a co n
sciousness that is beyond objectivity and is thus unique. T h e master must
receive that recognition from the slave. T he master, however, is not able to
value the slave because the slave has opted to identify him self with life and
objectivity— the very things that the master considered secondary. Thus, by
looking down on the slave, the master has deprived him self o f the possibility
o f receiving worthwhile recognition, even though the slave may hasten to
give the master recognition.
T h e second argument that H egel gives is based on the m aster’s descrip
tion o f the actual experience of pursuing the realization o f his self-concep
tion. T he master in effect acts according to his self-conception and lets the
slave fulfill his objective needs. H e also reserves for him self the right to think
when he and the slave are together. Thus, he can give orders9 while the slave
is supposed to execute them. In both cases, though, the slave is forced to work
and to transform the external world; he thus develops skills10 that the master
does not possess. T he master, however, needs the slave’s skills to pursue the
actualization of his self-conception. T h e master therefore becom es dependent
on the slave. T h is part o f H egel’s dialectic shows that the master actualizes
the opposite of his self-conception in the process o f pursuing his self-concep
tion. Indeed, the m aster’s self-conception denied the validity of one o f the
two basic principles of consciousness: that is, the fact that life and objectiv
ity are essential for consciousness. T h e realization o f the m aster’s self-con
ception is therefore possible only if som eone else (the slave) takes care o f this
neglected (or repressed) principle. Thus, the m aster must becom e the slave of
the slave. T his outcom e is not at all what the m aster had intended.
T h e analysis of “Lordship and Bondage” teaches us a crucial lesson about
the becom ing o f self-consciousness. A n individual must discover who he or
42 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
she is and then try to becom e that person. In “Lordship and Bondage,” how
ever, Hegel dem onstrated that hum an consciousness possesses contradictory
characteristics. O nly one o f them can be affirmed at any one time by con
sciousness. T h e other aspect must then be affirmed by another conscious
n ess." H egel writes in his Philosophy of Right (#7):
It [the will] is the self-determ ination of the ego, w hich m eans that at one
and the same tim e the ego posits itself as its own negative, i.e., as restricted
and determ inate, and yet rem ains by itself, i.e., in its self-identity and uni
versality. It determ ines itself and yet at the sam e tim e binds itself together
with itself. T h e ego determ ines itself in so far as it is the relating o f n ega
tivity to itself.
fore n ot w hat it chose to b e.13 C on sciou sness will therefore have to relate
negatively to what it decided to be.
It m ight be useful to draw attention to the fact that this process is closely
related to Freud’s description o f what happens in the process o f denial. Freud
writes about denial: “W ith the help o f negation only one consequence of the
process o f repression is u n d o n e .. . . T h e outcom e o f this is a kind o f intellec
tual acceptance o f the repressed, while at the sam e time what is essential to
the repression persists” (S .E ., X IX , 236). R elating negatively to the repressed
through denial allows an unacceptable state of affairs to continue, similar to
the case of the student who continues to do what he does not want to be
identified with (i.e. dishwashing), or to the case o f emperor M arcus Aurelius
who continued to reign even though being on the throne had become
unessential for him as a stoic.
There is, however, a crucial difference between the master-slave situa
tion analyzed by H egel and the process o f denial described by Freud. In the
case of the situation analyzed by Hegel, one has a desirable and constructive
outcom e. In the process described by Freud, one has an undesirable and
regressive outcome. We do not yet have the conceptual framework to under
stand the difference.
H egel’s second general statem ent applicable to our problem can be found
in the introduction to the Phenomenology:
Because o f that, the road can be looked on as a path o f doubt, or more prop
erly a highway o f despair. For what happens there is not w hat is usually
understood by doubting, a jostling against this or that supposed truth, the
outcom e of w hich is again a disappearance in due course o f the doubt and a
return to the former truth, so th at at the end the m atter is taken as it was
before. O n the contrary, the pathw ay is the conscious insight in the untruth
o f the phenom enal knowledge. (1977 b, 135-36)
despair is that despair involves a loss o f hope. H ope is defined in the same dic
tionary as “to desire with expectation o f fulfillm ent.”15
T he dictionary definition allows us to point to some precise differences
between doubt and despair. A lthough both states question a previously held
truth, despair also involves elim inating the possibility of desire, for despair is
losing the expectation of desire’s fulfillment.
W hen we now returns to the m aster-slave dialectic, we must rem ember
that in th at passage, H egel describes a m om ent in the self-constitution of
consciousness. T h is m om ent requires that desire find an ego-m odel (ego
ideal) by which it hopes to be recognized. T h e first consciousness’s hope
was to find self-fulfillm ent and recognition in the role o f master. T h e sec
ond consciousness’s hope was to retain its essence in the role o f the slave.
A n im portant step in consciousness’s developm ent is thus the m om ent of
choosing the ego-m odel (ego-ideal) by which consciousness hopes to real
ize itself. T h at choice indeed determ ines what consciousness will take as a
valid object o f desire. T h at choice determ ines to what consciousness, as
desire, will attach itself in order to find itself back in th at object or that
ego-m odel.
Hegel, however, stresses the fact that consciousness is not guiding the
choice o f ego-model (ego-ideal). T he choice is determ ined by the state of
desire. T h at state is radically different for the two consciousnesses. Indeed,
the desire o f the consciousness that will accept the role of the slave is a desire
that has been radically transformed. T h e desire of the consciousness that will
choose the role o f master is non-transformed desire. T h e transform ation of
the desire of the future slave is the result o f a fear of death. Hegel describes
that transform ation as follows: “It (consciousness) has been in that experi
ence (fear o f death) melted to its inmost soul, has trembled throughout its
every fiber, and all that was fixed and steadfast has quaked within it” (Ibid.
237). G iven that the desire of the consciousness that will choose the role of
the master has not been transformed because that consciousness does not
know the fear o f death, one must therefore conclude that the m aster cannot
find a true object for its desire in the slave’s role.
We are now ready to discover the full consequence o f the m aster’s expe
rience and life project. H egel makes it clear that it will not be the m aster’s
consciousness that discovers the falsehood o f its own ego-model. If that were
the case, the master would have knowledge o f his falsehood. T he falsehood
o f the m aster’s role will be dem onstrated for the reader who is willing to fol
low H egel’s description and reasoning. Through Hegel, the falsehood o f the
m aster’s ego-model becom es evident for the outsider.
Informed by Hegel, we know that it is logically impossible for desire to
find recognition by m eans of the m aster’s ego-model. Like all desires, the m as
ter’s desire is intentional. It must have an object. Furthermore, that object
must be found to be a valid or true object for desire. G iven, however, that the
D EN IA L A N D HEGEL’S P H ILO SP H IC A L A N T H R O P O LO G Y 45
desire o f the master is not a transformed desire, the master cannot accept an
ego-model other than its own as a true or valid object o f its desire. If the m as
ter recognizes his ego-model’s falsehood, he will be without an object of
desire. H egel calls this state despair. If the state o f being without an object of
desire must be avoided, the figure o f the m aster has no other choice but to try
to justify the truth and validity o f the only object his desire can choose. The
master must therefore try to defend the validity o f the role of master, even
though Hegel has taught us the falsity of that role.16 Clearly, this is a defen
sive and incorrect strategy. Freud’s case studies reveal similar faulty strategies.
These strategies lead to Freud’s exam ples o f denials. Rem ember Freud saying
that the statem ent: “It is not my mother,” m eans “It is my mother.” Freud
gave us em pirical exam ples o f denials.17 A close reading o f H egel gives us an
insight into the inevitability o f such denials.
T he constructive solution for the master is to becom e a stoic. A stoic
integrates the truth o f the role o f both the m aster and the slave by modifying
or negating some aspect o f each role. T his is precisely what Hegel says when
he writes:
C O N C L U S IO N
abstract. In his analysis o f the will, H egel teaches us th at hum an beings can
solve the paradox of the hum an will in different ways. A will that is true to its
essential form must negate the objectively given. Instead, the w ill informed by
consciousness m ust take responsibility for its decisions. T h is is H egel’s arbi
trary will. However, in order to be true to its con ten t, the will can n ot simply
disregard the objectively given, it m ust evaluate the given and subm it it to its
ow n chosen norm . T h is is H egel’s eudem onic will. Clearly, the eudem onic will
is a more subtle form o f negating the authority o f the objectively given than
the one used in arbitrary will. I will argue th at a denial can be understood as
a m isapplication o f the forces o f the negative necessary for freedom — a m isap
plication borrowed from the arbitrary will. T h erapeutic intervention, 1 will
argue, seem s to aim to bring the patien t to a position in w hich the strategy of
the eudem onic will can be used. T h e ob jective conn ection s can n ot be denied
by the patient. Instead, these con n ection s need to be intellectually recognized.
T h e force o f the negative must then be introduced as the power to evaluate
the objectively recognized facts and con n ection s in light of a freely chosen
norm o f consciousness.
IN T R O D U C T IO N
47
48 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
insights for understanding the puzzling phenom enon of denial.2 In his Philos
ophy of Right, H egel provides the key to understanding his theory o f freedom
by analyzing the concept of the will. T he kernel of that analysis is to be found
in ##5, 6, and 7 of that book.3 Pedagogically, the best approach to explain
these difficult and poorly written paragraphs is to start with three exam ples
from everyday life. T he first two exam ples allow us to see that the will is
caught in a paradox. Typical of Hegel, the paradox is formulated in dialecti
cal form. T h e will is said to aim at one thing (thesis, # 5 ). T h e will must, how
ever, also aim at the opposite (antithesis, # 6 ). T h e third exam ple attem pts to
illustrate the way out o f the paradox. It tries to illustrate the path o f synthe
sis (#7).4 These exam ples and their explanations will take up the first part of
this chapter. In the second part, I will show how H egel uses his idea o f the
will as free will to classify and to criticize conceptions of the will offered by
the philosophical tradition. A s these conceptions o f the will imply necessar
ily specific views of morality, H egel’s criticism can also be read as a criticism
o f alternative views of morality. In the conclusion I will clarify the phenom
enon of denial by m eans o f insights derived from H egel’s study of freedom and
the will.
1. T H E P A R A D O X O F T H E W I L L
A s our first exam ple let us imagine a person who is in personal difficulties
and who wants to talk. Suppose I have am ple time and I start the conversa
tion by asking my visitor how old he is, how tall, and how much he weighs.
A fter listening to the answers I say, “N ow I understand you” (in the sense of:
I am able to grasp your essential identity). My visitor would be accurate in
saying, “N o you do not.” Suppose I continue my quest for objective infor
m ation about my visitor by asking him how many brothers and sisters he has,
whether he is married, if he has children, and how many he has. A fter h ear
ing the answers, I restate my conviction, “But surely I now understand you.”
My visitor would be right in again saying, “N o you do n o t.” Suppose that I
once again continue my inquiry and ask my visitor whether he went to co l
lege and if he did, where and what grades he obtained. Would my visitor not
be right every time he rejected my claim that I understood him based on
objective inform ation? C ould we then not say that my visitor declines to be
identified with an objective content? T h is is precisely H egel’s statem ent
about the will: “T h e w ill. . . involves the dissipation o f every restriction and
every content . . .” (# 5 ).5 O n e can call this dissipation the first m om ent in
the drama o f the will. It is the thesis.6
Let us now turn to a second exam ple. Consider the situation o f late ado
lescents and early adults. Students at that age face a difficulty inherent in
the act o f willing. Students at that age have to make many choices. They
have to m ake decisions about careers and relationships, am ong other things.
D EN IA L A N D HEGEL’S TH EO RY OF TH E WILL 49
Let us concentrate on the choice o f a future job. Clearly, there are many
things one desires from a job. O n e expects a job to be interesting and ful
filling. O ne expects a job to be socially useful, so that one can contribute to
society. O n e expects the job to pay well, so that one can provide for oneself
and for on e’s family. A fter one is clear about all the desirable characteristics
o f a potential job, it is necessary to take a look at the available jobs. Som e
jobs pay well but are boring or morally com prom ising, other jobs are inter
esting (for exam ple, artistic careers) but are low-paying. So, late adolescents
or young adults som etim es adopt the attitude that there is no job good
enough for them. S uch an attitude lacks an essential m om ent o f willing
according to H egel. T h e lacking m om ent in such an attitude is that such
persons are unable to decide. To will, however, is to be able to decide. To
decide is to becom e som ething specific, som ething determ inate. In H egel’s
words: “the ego is also the transition from undifferentiated indeterm inacy to
the differentiation, determ ination, and positing o f a determ inacy as a co n
tent and ob ject” (# 6 ).7 O ne can call this the second m om ent in the dram a
of the will. It is the antithesis, because it requires the will to do the opposite
of the first requirem ent (which required the will to refuse to identify itself
with anything o b jective.)8 T he will is thus caught in a paradox because it has
to satisfy two opposite demands.
Let us now turn to our third exam ple in which I will illustrate how Hegel
tries to solve the paradox of the will. During the summer, one can m eet stu
dents who are working in hotels, in offices, on construction jobs, and in many
other places. Suppose one talks to a student who does typing work in an office
and asks, “are you a secretary?” It is very likely one will hear the following
answer, “N o, I am earning money to pay for college.” T h is student has been
able to decide. H e has accepted a position as an office secretary. His reply that
he is not an office secretary, however, m eans that he relates negatively to his
own choice.
T h e above negation could be thought of as a denial. It is not a denial,
however, because the negation, unlike a denial, does not prevent action.
Rather, the student’s negation prom otes action, that is, com m itm ent to a
task. T h e negation prom otes action because it is a negation o f an unaccept
able aspect of a situation, which would have undermined the student’s com
m itm ent to his task. T h is negation transforms a hum ble task into a prom is
ing endeavor. H egel calls this negation a “negation of a negation” (#104).
In H egelian language, the student who denies being an office secretary
has becom e other than he wishes to be by accepting to becom e an office sec
retary. T he solution to this predicam ent is not for the student to give up his
job. If the student were to do so, he would end up without a job and he would
not be a will because to be a will m eans to settle upon some content. T he real
solution is for the student to find a m otivation for performing his job that
transcends the particularity o f the job itself. Such a solution could be the
50 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
claim that the student is earning tuition money by m eans o f his summer job.
Clearly such a m otivation does not specify that the student must take an
office job; such a m otivation only says that the student has to take some job.
Let us now reflect upon the consequences o f sticking it out with the
summer job and justifying it with the m otivation o f earning tuition money.
T h e first consequence is th at the student denies that he is stuck with the
secretarial job. Indeed, he does not take the job because o f the job itself but
because o f some other goal. T h e student can claim that perform ing secre
tarial tasks is incidental, while earning tuition is essential. T h e student can
say that while perform ing secretarial services, he is not really performing
secretarial services but earning tuition. H e can thus deny that he is doing
secretarial work. Instead, he is really earning tuition (in the sense o f ex is
tentially intending that aspect o f his act to be the essential aspect o f the
act). T h e second consequence is that the student can continue to do his
job, because it earns m oney for tuition. T h e third consequence is that the
student can sim ultaneously deny that he is doing a secretarial job and c o n
tinue to work at the job in actuality. H e distances h im self from the p artic
ular job, while accepting the job as a particular instance to reach a (m ore)
general goal.
Denying that he is doing the particular job is holding on to the moment
described in #5. Continuing to do the job is obeying the imperative of #6.
U sing the m otivation to do the job while at the same time claim ing that per
forming the job is not what one is doing is achieving the synthesis described
in #7. In that synthesis the student accepts doing som ething which is deter
m inate (being an office secretary) and does som ething that the will as such
cannot will, because it does not fulfill the will. Thus, the will of the student
accepts becom ing other than itself; it accepts externalizing itself. I take this
to be an illustration o f the will as negativity, as a force com pelled and cap a
ble o f transcending itself, o f going outside itself. T h e student does not, how
ever, surrender to this alienating situation.
T h e student, as it were, recaptures his own loss. H e takes back his deci
sion, but he does so in an ideal way, not in a m aterial way. Thus, while m ate
rially continuing to perform the office secretary job, he says that he does not
perform this job, but rather, that he earns tuition. Clearly, this m ove involves
a negation (not a denial). It is by this negation that the student undoes that
alienating aspect of accepting and performing a particular job. H egel calls
that undoing, that act of negation, an act o f negativity. We are now ready to
understand the crucial part o f #7: “it [the will] is the relating of negativity to
itself.”9 O ne can call this the synthesis. Indeed, in negating the particular that
the will has accepted, the will preserves the demand o f #5. However, the
demand o f #5 is not preserved in its unm ediated form. It is preserved in a
transformed way in the synthesis. Hegel specifies this act of transform ation as
“idealizing” the determ ination dem anded in #6 (remark to #7).
D EN IA L A N D HEGEL’S TH EO RY OF TH E WILL 51
2. C L A S S IF IC A T IO N OF
D IF F E R E N T C O N C E P T I O N S O F T H E W IL L
In his Introduction to the Philosophy of Right, Hegel further analyzes four gen
eral strategies that m ankind has developed to deal with the paradox of the
will. H egel labels the four strategies: the natural will, the arbitrary will, the
search for happiness (the eudem onic will), and the free will. Let us analyze
each of these strategies in turn. I will try to reconstruct these four strategies
in a dialectic fashion.
T h e first strategy is the one referred to as the strategy o f “the natural will”
(# # 1 1 -1 4 ). T h is will needs to be determined. It allows itself to be determined
by inclination— by whatever it happens to feel an impulse or a passion for
doing. It thus abandons the need to decide by allowing itself to be determined
by what nature happens to make attractive to it. Thus, when such a will feels
an impulse to drink, it is bound to look for a drink. O ne can call this the th e
sis in the dram a o f the experience o f the natural will (#11).
T he difficulty with such a will is that there could be many impulses
which emerge at the same time. T h e will could simultaneously feel inclined
52 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
to drink, eat, read K ant, and listen to C hopin. In such a situation the natural
will does not know what to do. In addition, when one is thirsty, one can drink
coffee, tea, coke, or milk, am ong other beverages. T h e principle adopted by
the natural will does not provide a guideline to solve this second impasse
either. T his failure is the antithesis in the dram a of the natural will (#12).
More abstractly, H egel summarizes the impasse o f the natural will as fol
lows: the natural will acts as if it has rules for deciding and thus has the for
mal characteristic o f being a free will. However, the natural will allows the
content of its decisions to be determ ined by som ething other than its own
will. T he content o f the will’s decision will be decided by the emerging incli
nations or impulses. T he form and content of the natural will are therefore
not identical (#13). A person accepting the strategy o f the natural will can
say, “ I decided” or, “It is my decision.” T he “m ineness” of the decision is
rather superficial; it does not reach into the decision’s content. Rather, it
resembles the act o f som eone who receives a gift and stam ps his nam e on the
gift. It is his gift, but som eone else selected it.
One may say that the natural will does not possess enough negativity. It
is not able or not willing to deny natural desires the right to autom atically
decide the will’s actions. T h e natural will is not free because it does not exer
cise the power to negate the right o f natural desires to autom atically deter
mine the will.
T h e second strategy is the one o f the “arbitrary will” (# # 1 5 -1 9 ). T h is
will appears as the synthesis that solves the problem o f the natural will.
Indeed, the natural will’s im passe occurs because it does not possess a rule on
how to decide when faced with the presence o f m ultiple impulses or with the
m ultiplicity o f objects th at could satisfy one impulse. A noth er way of for
m ulating a criticism of the natural will is to recall that this will does not
itself decide the conten t o f its decisions. It does not have the capability to
negate natural desires’ autom atic push to determ ine the outcom e o f the will’s
decision. T h e arbitrary w ill’s strategy is to accept the duty o f having to
decide, as well as to decide the specific conten t o f available choices. T he
arbitrary will accepts as rule for its decisions: I have to decide and I have to
decide in all m atters. I do not surrender the right and the duty to decide to
my natural inclinations. Furthermore, it has a second rule: one does not need
to follow rules when deciding; one simply has to decide. T h is form of the will
is the arbitrary will (#15). C onfronted by two or three impulses, or two or
more possibilities to satisfy an impulse, the arbitrary will is not immobilized.
It will decide this way one time and that way another time. W hen asked
why, the arbitrary will can answer, “because I will it so.” 11 T h e arbitrary will
is not required under its own strategy to give a reason. T h is is the m om ent
o f the thesis.
T he antithesis emerges when one realizes that decisions have conse
quences. If a student decides in the beginning of the year to use his pocket
D EN IA L A N D HEGEL’S TH EO RY OF TH E WILL 53
money to visit France, he m ight not have future opportunities to make finan
cial decisions (# # 1 6 -1 7 ). Thus, the strategy of the arbitrary will finds its lim
its in the restrictions that reality imposes on the acting will.
Philosophically, H egel puts his criticism as follows: the arbitrary will
decides without binding itself to its decisions. Because they are arbitrary they
could have been replaced by other decisions. Thus, the content o f the arbi
trary will’s decisions is not worth defending because it could have been dif
ferent (#16). T h e content of the arbitrary will’s decisions is thus always con
tingent; it is never necessary.
T h e third strategy is the one used by the “eudemonic will,” or the will in
search of happiness (#20). T h is strategy emerges as a solution to the difficul
ties of the arbitrary will. T h e eudem onic will has accepted that the will needs
to coordinate its decisions. For that purpose it needs a norm. Particular d eci
sions of the will which are made in accordance with a norm cease to be con
tingent. They receive the form o f necessity and are coordinated with other
particular decisions.
Happiness is a norm which has often been proposed in the history of
mankind. T h e strategy o f the eudem onic will is that it sees the need to eval
uate all possible decisions in light o f one norm: what decisions will bring the
most happiness? T he great contribution of this strategy is that it accepts the
interconnection o f thought and will in order to bring about freedom of the
w ill.12 A further contribution of this strategy is that it introduces the need to
coordinate and thus the need to to refine, to transform, and to educate the
different hum an impulses.
Freud points to two im portant achievem ents in the therapeutic work
with som eone who has uttered a denial (Ver Eecke 1984, 14). Both seem
related to the positive contribution made by the eudemonic will.
T h e first achievem ent is that the person uttering a denial becom es able
to undo the intellectual negation embedded in a denial. T h e symbolic con
nections are intellectually acknowledged and respected. T h is first achieve
m ent parallels the achievem ent o f the eudem onic will which, in its decision
procedure, respects connections between, for exam ple, decisions and
expected results. T h is is progress com pared to the arbitrary will, which
decided on its own authority without necessarily having recourse to ob jec
tively observed (or expected) connections.
T h e second achievem ent in the work with a person uttering a denial is
that such a person also accepts the im plications for action dem anded by the
intellectual acknow ledgm ent. A ccep tin g im plications for action often
requires dealing with em otional wishes and fears. It requires th at the
p atien t be capable o f becom ing m aster o f his or her em otions. T h is is a
dem and sim ilar to the one faced by the eudem onic will, which, for its exer
cise, requires the refinem ent and education (i.e., rational control) of
wishes, impulses, and em otions.
54 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
T he fatal flaw in the eudem onic strateg, which will allow the emergence
o f its antithesis, is the fact that the eudem onic will pursues a strategy it can
not guarantee. Indeed, a person can do many things in order to make h appi
ness possible. H e cannot, however, guarantee his own happiness by what he
does. Suppose, for exam ple, that one has worked on e’s whole life for good
grades, in order to go to a good school, in order to have a good job, in order
to have a good income, in order to be able to provide for on e’s family. S u p
pose one has succeeded in accom plishing all o f the above but then discovers
that one has cancer. T h is would undoubtedly make one very unhappy. T h e
purpose of on e’s whole life would thus be lost. A strategy which leaves open
the possibility that the m eaning o f on e’s life project could be destroyed is a
strategy that is rationally defective.
T h e fourth strategy, the one used by the free will, is a successful and
open-ended strategy (#-#21-28). T h is fourth strategy is the solution to the
previous strategy’s problem . T h e problem was th at the eudem onic will was
pursuing a goal it could not guarantee. T h e strategy o f the free will is to
will its own freedom (# 2 1 ). T h e free will has to involve thinking to a
higher degree than even the eudem onic will is prepared to d o .13 T h e free
will has to ask from thought w hat is required to be and to rem ain free. S u p
pose th at an adolescent plans to have a family, but decides that he does not
like school. If he drops out o f school, he will not acquire the skills n eces
sary to earn a d ecen t salary in today’s society. W hen he later starts a fam
ily, he m ight realize th at he can n ot afford what he w anted to provide for
his family. H e becom es disillusioned and thus, in som e sense, unfree. To
aim at freedom m eans one is required to think what one has to do in order
to be, as well as to rem ain, free. In addition, one m ust accept w hat one has
thought.
T hinking has a crucial function for the free will. It tells a person what
choices to make. Philosophy, in particular H egel’s The Philosophy of Right,
presents us with a rough sketch o f what is required to m aintain freedom.
H egel writes that what thinking discovers as freedom ’s requirem ents are:
“the principle o f right, morality, and all ethical life” (# 2 1 ). N ow these three
principles are the three parts o f The Philosophy of Right. Ethical life itself c o n
tains three substrata: the family, civil society, and the state. I understand
H egel to be saying that in order to be and to rem ain free one needs property
rights, morality, and the ethical institutions of the family, the free market,
and the state. T hese different dom ains are not just preconditions for free
dom; they are em bodim ents o f freedom as well. By willing all the em bodi
ments o f freedom, the will makes its existence correspond to its concept
(#23). In other words, for H egel, to be free m eans that two totally different
requirem ents need to be fulfilled. First, “freedom shall be the rational system
o f m ind” (#27). Second, “the rational system o f m ind . . . shall be the world
o f im m ediate actuality” (#27).
D EN IA L A N D HEGEL’S THEORY OF TH E WILL 55
the arbitrary will, hum an beings have reached a developm ent in which some
essential characteristic o f the will is realized. T h at characteristic is the fact
that the will has the power to refuse any objective datum the capability to
determ ine its decision.
A denial has a progressive and a regressive aspect. It is progressive in
that it reveals a content. It is regressive in that the revealed content is not
acknowledged. Rem em ber Freud’s exam ple o f a p atien t’s reply to his ques
tion as to the identity o f a woman in her dream: “T h at (dom ineering)
woman in my dream is not my mother.” U nderstanding the nature o f the
arbitrary will gives us an additional way o f presenting the progressive aspect
o f a denial. It looks as if, in the negation o f a denial, the will tries to realize
the essential achievem ent o f the arbitrary will: I do not grant anything the
power to decide for me; I decide and in this case I decide that I am not a per
son who would present such a negative picture o f my mother. Unfortunately,
as I argue later, this is a m isapplication o f the progressive dim ension of the
arbitrary will.
T he eudemonie will corresponds to the judgm ent o f necessity. Hegel
gives as exam ples: “the rose is a plant,” (H egel 1989, 651) “ If A is, then B is;
or the being of A is not its own being, but the being o f another, B ” (Ibid. 652)
or “Colour is either violet, indigo, blue, green, yellow, orange or red” (Ibid.
656). In a judgm ent of necessity the subject and the predicate are connected
by m eans of a thoughtful understanding of a conceptual connection. T h e
eudemonie will too is characterized by the use of thoughtful understanding of
conceptual connections. T h e eudemonie will must relate a concrete option
with the conceptual norm it has chosen for judging the desirability o f alter
natives. U tility or happiness are such norms. T h e eudemonie will does not
deny the given; it does subject it, though, to a norm. T h is is a more con
structive use of the negative than the m ethod used by the arbitrary will.
I will argue that therapeutic intervention with a person uttering a
denial can be understood as aim ing at the constructive usage o f the n eg a
tive’s force as it is present in the eudem onie will. R eal freedom is n ot the
intellectual negation o f what is given; it is the subm ission o f the given to a
reasonable norm.
T he fourth form o f the will, the free will, corresponds to the judgm ent of
the notion. H egel gives the following exam ples: “T h is house is bad, this
action is good” (H egel 1989, 659). H e stresses that the essential characteris
tic of a predicate in a judgm ent of the notion is that it includes an “ought-to-
be,” that is, how the house ought to be (Ibid.657). T h e will which corre
sponds to the judgm ent o f the notion therefore must include an
“ought-to-be,” that is, the idea o f having to be free and to be able to remain
free. A s this interpretation o f the will includes an “ought-to-be,” there is
room for philosophy to try to determine what the will “ought-to-be” in order
to be a free will. H egel schem atically announces what this “ought-to-be”
D EN IA L A N D HEGEL’S TH EO RY OF TH E WILL 57
needs to include: “the principle o f right, o f morality, and o f all ethical life”
(H egel 1967b, #21 ). H egel then uses these three principles to structure his
The Philosophy of Right into three parts. These three principles correspond log
ically to the three forms o f syllogism discussed in the Logic.14
C O N C L U S IO N
I now want to use H egel’s analyses o f the will, in particular his analyses o f the
arbitrary will and the eudemonic will, to better understand both the progres
sive and the regressive aspects of a denial.
1. In order to proceed, we first need to understand the difference and
similarity between an act o f the will and a denial. T h e difference between the
two is that the will relates to deciding whereas denial relates to acknow ledg
ing or, more precisely, refusing to acknowledge symbolic connections as they
are presented to consciousness (e.g., in dreams or slips o f the tongue). Thus,
the will operates in the dom ain o f doing whereas a denial takes place in the
dom ain o f knowledge. Therefore we can conclude that the performance o f an
act of the will and a denial take place in two different ontological domains.
T h e similarity between an act o f the will and the performance of a denial
consists in the fact that they both ultimately aim to be operative in the same
ontological dom ain. A s already stated, the will explicitly relates to deciding.
I will now dem onstrate that a denial is implicitly about deciding as well. Take
our classic exam ple of the statem ent: “T his (domineering) woman in my
dream is not my mother.” T h at statem ent does not just intend to deny a sym
bolic connection. It is also about avoiding having to make certain decisions.
Indeed, the sem iotic statem ent that the person in the dream is dom ineering
demands certain actions, for exam ple: avoiding such a person or standing up
to him or her. H aving denied the connection, the reason for such action is
nullified. A denial can thus be understood as grounds for avoiding certain
actions.
2. We are now in a position to use H egel’s analysis o f the will for the
purpose o f clarifying the process o f denial. M y thesis will be that, in a denial,
a hum an being tries to exercise freedom by incorrectly applying som ething
to the dom ain o f knowledge that can be applied legitim ately only to the
dom ain o f action. If my thesis is accurate then correction of the m istake will
have to address errors in the two dom ains. T hus changes will have to occur
in both the dom ain o f symbolic connections (epistem ology) and the dom ain
o f action.
A D e n ia l a s a C a t e g o r y M ist a k e o f t h e U r g e t o F reedo m
C o r r e c t in g t h e C a te g o r y M ist a k e in D en ia l
lar to those of my mother; she has the hair and the eyes o f my mother. Thus,
it must be my mother. Freud states that such a recognition on the patient’s
part does not m ean that the unconscious connection has been em otionally
accepted. If that is the case then therapy needs to prom ote a second move:
the em otional acceptance o f the unconscious connection.
T h e first task o f the therapist dealing with a denial is to correct the ille
gitim ate m ove at the epistem ological level using the force for freedom in the
subject. T he second task is to search for a correct expression o f freedom.
I now wish to describe that double therapeutic task, described by Freud,
as helping the patient to m ove from an arbitrary form o f the will to a eude-
m onic form o f the will.
T h e great difference between the arbitrary and the eudem onic forms of
the will is the fact that the eudem onic will gives great weight to thought
whereas the arbitrary will does not. Indeed, the arbitrary will affirmed its
freedom without paying attention to intellectual arguments. O bjective
givens did not matter. T he eudem onic will, on the other hand, pays atten
tion to the objectively given without allowing the given to becom e author
itative for decisions o f the will. Instead, the eudem onic will acknowledges
the objectively given and submits it to a calculation aim ed at achieving a
freely chosen goal (happiness). A s the essential m ove o f the eudem onic will
is subm ission o f the objectively given to a calculation, the eudem onic will
can use the force of the negative, not to deny the objective data, but to sub
mit them to a goal. T h e eudem onic will thus gives the forces o f the negative,
inherent in freedom, a new object. Instead o f falsely denying objective con
nections, the goal is now to evaluate truthfully those connections (weigh
their relative im portance; put them in a hierarchical order; etc.) in order to
justify concrete actions.
H egel hints at the great efforts required to succeed in subm itting ob jec
tive givens to a goal. He points out that this requires education in the double
sense o f having formal education (prom oting the exercise o f thought) and in
the sense o f personality form ation (reaching the maturity to be able to sub
mit impulses to thought) (H egel 1967b, ##20, 187). N o wonder Freud
laments the difficulty o f the therapeutic process dealing with a person utter
ing a denial. H e writes: “We succeed . . . in bringing about the full intellec
tual acceptance o f the repressed; but the repressive process itself is not yet
removed by this” (Freud, S .E ., XIX, 236). Indeed, the therapeutic process
must both enlighten the patient about true objective givens and educate her
towards em otional maturity. T h is is a tall order.
3. A fter com paring the process o f denial with H egel’s analysis o f the will
and its freedom we can now formulate the progressive and regressive moments
in the act o f denial.15 T he progressive dim ension in a denial is the negation, a
sign o f the presence of the force of the negative required in the exercise o f free
dom. T h e regressive dimension in a denial is the m isapplication of the force of
60 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
the negative. Instead of being properly used in the dom ain of action, it is
improperly used in the epistem ological domain. We can therefore first expect
therapeutic work to make a correction in the epistem ological attitude o f the
patient. Second, we can expect the work to lead the patient towards the em o
tional maturity required to take the reasonable action that was avoided, by
defective means, in the denial. T h at is exactly what Freud describes the ther
apeutic work as consisting of in the case of a denial.
FIVE
A Child’s N oSaying
A Step toward Independence
abstract. Spitz uses the two concepts of indicator and organizer to point to a
new behavior in the child’s developm ent. I distinguish betw een a weak and a
strong sense of organizer. T h e weak sense of organizer m eans that the indicator
o f a new behavior is not a necessary condition for the new and higher level of
activity reached by the child. T h e new and higher level o f activity can be
assumed to be present even if the specifically studied indicator does not appear.
T h e strong sense of organizer m eans that the indicator o f the new behavior cre
ates the new and higher level o f activity reached by the child. I argue that
stranger anxiety at eight m onths is a weak organizer for a deeper form o f the
ch ild’s attachm ent to fam iliar persons. A bsence o f m anifest signs o f that an xi
ety does not m ean that this deeper form of attachm ent is n ot taking place. I
argue that the no-saying, w hich occurs around 15 m onths o f age, is a strong
organizer. By its mere presence, it creates a higher level o f activity in the child.
Spitz argues that it creates the first unequivocal concept. I argue th at it creates
a new degree of em otional independence for the child. M y thesis can thus be
taken as a confirm ation o f the Freudian claim th at the acquisition (and effec
tive usage) of the linguistic form o f negation is a precondition for freedom.
IN T R O D U C T IO N
A ccording to Spitz, it is incorrect to look upon the first few years of the child’s
developm ent as a simple linear development. Instead, Spitz believes that there
are multiple lines of developm ent which come together to make a new form
of behavior possible for the child. T his new behavior is so different from the
child’s previous behavior that Spitz claim s the new behavior indicates a higher
61
62 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
level of psychic structure. He calls the moment when such new behavior
appears a critical period. Since these critical periods function to synthesize
several developments into a new form of behavior that is in turn the begin
ning of a new psychological development, Spitz also calls these indicators
organizers o f psychic structures (Spitz 1965, 177).
Spitz lists three such critical periods during the first twenty m onths of
the child’s life. T h e indicators o f these critical periods are: the smile at about
three m onths of age; stranger anxiety at about eight m onths; and the no-say
ing after about fifteen m onths (Ibid. VI, VIII, XI).
T he first two critical periods are related in a special way to the function
o f seeing. T h e child smiles at about three m onths of age in response to see
ing the hum an face. A nxiety at eight m onths is a reaction triggered by see
ing a stranger— or, correcting Spitz, I will argue that anxiety at eight m onths
is a reaction to being seen by a stranger.1 T h e third critical period concerns
the child’s no-saying. It is this latter phenom enon that interests us, but its
subtle m eaning can only be understood after understanding the two chrono
logically prior phenom ena.
In this chapter, I will present Spitz’s theory of these three critical periods
and dem onstrate that, in several crucial areas, Spitz’s description o f these
periods is richer than his theory. I will com plem ent or correct Spitz’s theory
with my own theory, often relying on a Lacanian framework. I will distinguish
between weak and strong organizers. T his will help to prevent inaccurate pre
dictions about the future m ental health o f a child in whom an organizer is
absent.2 In my conclusion, finally, I will appeal to H egel in order to dem on
strate that my strategy o f giving no-saying and negativity such a central role
in philosophical anthropology falls well in line with what we know about
hum an beings from speculative philosophy.
1. T H E F I R S T O R G A N I Z E R : T H E S M I L E
Typically, between the ages o f two and six m onths, the child smiles even
at strangers. Aptly, Spitz calls it “indiscrim inate sm iling” (Ibid. 88), implying
that the sm iling response cannot be interpreted as a sign that the child has
already established em otional ties with a particular person. In psychoanalytic
language, this m eans that the sm iling response is not a sign that true object
relations have been established. A gain, Spitz’s view is generally confirmed by
K onner’s survey article on the m other-infant bonds. Thus Konner, summariz
ing the existing research, writes:
social sm iling is well established but relatively undiscriminating. It appears to
the observer to be associated w ith positive em otion, but the em otion seems
impersonal; alm ost anyone can elicit it and, despite subtle signs o f discrim i
nation o f primary caretakers, strong emotional bonds do not appear to exist
[em phasis mine]. (149)
Spitz’s claim about the absence o f true object relations or o f the absence
of em otional ties to a particular person runs counter to the view o f a group
o f authors (e.g., the H ungarian school o f psychoanalysis; the attachm ent
theorists)5 who argue that the child is attached to a specific person from very
early on. Even Konner, in the text just quoted, writes that there are, “subtle
signs o f discrim ination o f primary caretakers.” To add support to Spitz’s
detractors, let us present a case from a psychoanalyst’s consultation. T his
psychoanalyst was consulted because an infant refused the bottle after her
m other had died. T h e psychoanalyst asked if any o f the deceased m other’s
unwashed undergarm ents rem ained. Sh e further advised winding this under
wear around the bottle before giving the bottle to the infant. W hen this
m ethod was followed, the infant accepted the bottle. Such a case does
indeed confirm the attachm ent theorists’ theoretical claim and seem s to
invalidate Spitz’s conclusion that the infant cannot be said to have true
object relations.
My position is that the attachm ent theorists are correct and that Spitz
overstated his conclusion. I believe, however, that there is a truth to Spitz’s
claim. T he challenge is to acknowledge Spitz’s observation about indiscrim i
nate sm iling without overstating the conclusion drawn from the observation.
T he fact that, at first, the child smiles at everybody— and even smiles at
masks— whereas, at eight m onths o f age, the child starts to show anxiety
64 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
between their respective theories. Spitz talks about indicators and organizers
(Ibid. 117). H e explicitly calls the sm iling response an indicator, and, in order
not to be misunderstood, he writes:
I repeat: the sm iling response as such is merely the visible sym ptom o f the
convergence o f several different developm ental currents w ithin the psychic
apparatus. T h e establishm ent o f the sm iling response signals that these
trends have now been integrated, organized, and will thenceforward operate
as a discrete unit w ithin the psychic system. T h e em ergence o f the smiling
response marks a new era in the ch ild’s way o f life; a new way o f being has
begun, basically different from the previous one. (Ibid. 119)
Lacan concentrates on seeing and talks about the recognition that occurs
in the mirror image. H e too points to the joy and the smile that is produced
in the child when recognizing her image, her G estalt, in the mirror or in the
figure o f a real person, mostly the mother. In contrast to Spitz, Lacan does not
describe the child’s sm iling response to seeing her G estalt as an indicator for
marking the child’s new level o f psychic organization. Rather, Lacan will
intepret seeing as a psychological faculty which must be called an organizer
o f the child’s psychic life.7 For Lacan, seeing at this age will be understood as
producing an effect rather than merely indicating an effect’s presence. Lacan
will go so far as to claim that seeing is a faculty that bridges the physiological
and the psychological dim ensions in hum an beings, so that he will be able to
claim that there may even be physiological effects produced by the psycho
logical act o f seeing. (Ver Eecke 198 a, 115-16) Spitz, on the other hand,
only claim s that seeing a specific sign G estalt triggers an innate mechanism.
Interestingly enough, in Spitz one can find a number o f remarks which
show that the sm iling response o f the three-month-old baby has more m yste
rious aspects to it than Spitz’s theory explains. We can use these remarks to
justify the Lacanian radicalization o f the interpretation o f the baby’s seeing
and smiling.
Indeed, Spitz reports that the child does not only smile, but also becomes
active and starts wriggling when she sees a hum an face (Spitz 1965, 89). The
smile is thus but one o f the reactions a child has to seeing a hum an face. The
full reaction spreads over the whole body.
Spitz cautions the reader against m isunderstanding his theory of “sign
G estalten, releaser m echanism triggering innate responses,” warning us not
to conclude from the theory that “a m echanical doll, fitted with the sign
G estalt can rear our children . . .” (Ibid. 95).
Spitz further explains this warning by elaborating on his theoretical
interpretation o f the infant’s smile. He argues that “although the innate
equipment is available to the baby from the first m inute o f life, it (the innate
equipm ent) has to be quickened” (Ibid. 95). T his could m ean that a certain
time is required for the innate m echanism to becom e operative. Such an
66 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
interpretation would rem ain consonant with the theory o f innate m echa
nisms. However, Spitz interprets the need to quicken the innate equipment
by saying:
It is the m utual give and take, its single elem ents constantly changing and
shifting (though its sum total rem ains the dyadic relation), w hich represents
the essence of what we are trying to describe and to convey to the reader.
T h e reciprocal feedback w ithin the dyad betw een m other and baby, and
baby and mother, is in continuous flux. T h e dyad, however, is basically
asymmetric. W hat the m other contributes to the relation is com pletely dif
ferent from what the baby contributes. E ach of them is the com plem ent of
the other, and while the m other provides w hat the baby needs, in h[er] turn
(though this is less generally acknow ledged) the baby provides w hat the
m other needs. (Ibid. 96)
sm iling response. I take this to be a warning about the broad context neces
sary for the sm iling response to take place. In order to explain the sm iling
response, Spitz uses a theory where a sign G estalt functions as a releaser
m echanism triggering an innate response (Ibid. 95). My difficulty with Spitz’s
theory is that he, in effect, uses a two-part theory to explain the sm iling
response. H e has a theory proper: releaser m echanism triggering an innate
response. H e also has a requirement about the context necessary for the sm il
ing response. In Spitz’s writings, the connection between the explanation of
the event and the requirem ent about context is only an observed connection.
Spitz in no way presents a theoretical frame that would make the connection
between his theory of innate m echanism and his requirement about the gen
eral context a necessary connection. O ne purpose I have will be to work
towards a theoretical framework that will make it possible to see the above
connection as a necessary connection. I will work out this claim for the two
other indicators.
2. T H E S E C O N D O R G A N I Z E R : E I G H T - M O N T H - A N X I E T Y
behaviors” such as follow ing, clinging, and cuddling becom e frequent in dis
tinctive relation to the primary caretaker(s), especially in strange situations
or in the presence o f strange persons. . . . (149)
A ll the above m easures have been made in at least som e non-W estern cul
tures, with the result that the underlying con cepts now have considerable
cross-cultural validity. . . . T h e growth of the social fears and the concom -
m ittan t growth o f attachm ent, as defined by these and related measures, is
a putative universal o f the second half-year o f hum an life (with m uch indi
vidual variation in the degree of overt expression). (149)
Konner reports that children are not only showing anxiety with
strangers, but are “crying when left by the m other in a strange situation, with
or without a strange person.” Second, Konner reports that ‘“ attachm ent
behaviors’ such as following, clinging, and cuddling becom e frequent in dis
tinctive relation to the primary caretaker(s), especially . . . in the presence of
strange persons” (Ibid. 149). Third, there is great variability in the age of
onset of the fear o f strangers, but m ost researchers put the onset after the first
six m onths. However, in a graph Konner borrowed from Kagan, it looks as if
fear o f strangers— the so-called eight-m onth-anxiety— could start as early as
the age of five m onths in some children.
My theoretical explanation of the eight-month-anxiety will not explain a
child’s fear o f strange situations. N either will it try to explain a fear o f strangers
in general. My explanation will apply only to a child’s fear of a stranger who
looks at the child. A s I now see it, my theory would be falsified if the child’s
fear o f a stranger’s look were to occur prior to the child’s jubilation before the
mirror. However, I was unable to find any empirical studies about the relative
timing o f these two phenom ena. My theory would not be falsified if a child
feared strangers who did not look at the child or if a child feared strange situ
ations. T he child’s fear in these two situations involves matters beyond the
scope of my theory. In particular, it is possible to argue that seeing is a privi
leged sense in humans even though other senses can at least partially replace
some of seeing’s functions. T his line of reasoning might find support in
Fraiberg’s and Freedman’s research as reported by Konner: “blind infants
develop social smiling . . . a m onth or two later than sighted infants.” Konner
may overstate his interpretation of this research when he writes: “a crucial role
for visual perception in the growth o f the behavior can be ruled out” (Ibid.
146). If the social smile, on average, starts between two and three m onths of
age and blind children need one or two months more to begin smiling socially,
then blind children need between thirty percent and fifty percent more time
to achieve the social smile. I consider that a significant difference. Still, it does
m ean that, at least for some functions, seeing can be replaced by other senses.
A C H IL D ’S N O -SA Y IN G 69
Clearly, Spitz has good arguments to back his claim that the child’s eight-
m onth-anxiety reaction is an indicator o f a higher level of psychic structure,
but this new affect still remains to be explained. Spitz explicitly rejects the
hypothesis o f Szekely, which supposes that the G estalt “eyes-forehead” acts as
an innate “releaser stimulus” representing the phylogenetic survivor o f the
enemy in the anim al world. T h e infant’s smile at three m onths would be,
according to that theory, an indication o f an early attem pt at m astering this
archaic anxiety (Ibid. 157). T h e eight-m onth-anxiety would be an indication
that the child has regressed and that the “eyes-forehead” G estalt again func
tions as a stimulus for the archaic fear.
Spitz rejects Szekely’s hypothesis because the eye configuration does not
function as an innate releaser. Som e m aturation o f the ch ild’s nervous system
is required. Furthermore, the eyes do not provoke fear but rather a smile, as
we saw in the analysis of the three-month-old infant’s smile. Finally, if eyes
actually provoke fear, the child should be relieved when the observer’s face is
changed to a profile. O n the contrary, however, in such circum stances the
infant shows bewilderment and it becom es quite difficult to reestablish em o
tional contact with the child so as to calm him down (Ibid. 159).
Spitz’s own explanation is based upon the following interpretation of
anxiety: “W hat he reacts to when confronted with a stranger is that this is
not his mother; his m other ‘has left’ him ” (Ibid. 155). W hen form ulating his
explanation, though, Spitz can only explain the affect disappointm ent:
T h e child produces first a scanning behavior, nam ely the seeking for the lost
love object, the mother. A decision is now made by the function o f judg
m ent “w hether som ething w hich is present in the ego as an image, can also
be re-discovered in perception.” (Freud 1925 [N egation]) (Spitz 1957, 54)
Thus, Spitz’s argument am ounts to claim ing that the child at eight
m onths is unable to see the face o f a stranger without feeling a strong long
ing for the mother. Furthermore, the stranger not only provokes that longing
(because the child m ight have been happily playing before), but she also fails
to fulfill the longing that she provoked in the child. T h e resulting disap
pointm ent, finally, is said to produce the so-called eight-month-anxiety.
I have two m ain objections to this more detailed reading o f Spitz’s text.
First, Spitz’s theory is incom plete inasm uch as he does not talk about the dan
ger that appears to be present at eight m onths but not at six months, when
most babies smile at any human person approaching them. My theory could
then be seen as com plem entary to Spitz’s, in that it dem onstrates the specific
danger with which an eight-m onth-old has to deal, which has not yet pre
sented itself to the typical six-m onth-old child.
Second, Spitz’s theory can be said to be wrong in that his theory would
have to predict a behavior different from what is actually observed. Spitz
observes: “. . . the child looks back at the stranger again and again. [S]he
peeks between h[er] fingers, [s]he lifts h[er] face from the blanket-and hides it
again” (Spitz 1957, 55). Now, even if the child is in the arms of her mother,
the child continues to look, from time to time, at the stranger. It is this last
behavior which I believe Spitz’s theory cannot explain and would probably
72 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
predict differently. If the face of the stranger provokes a longing for the
mother and disappoints that longing, why would the child continue to peek
at the stranger while she is still in the arms of her mother? Spitz suggests that
the actions of the baby (covering eyes, hiding his head in the pillow, pulling
his shirt over his eyes, etc.) are actions intended to make the stranger disap
pear. H e writes: “ [the child] tries in a wishful way to make the stranger dis
appear” (Ibid. 55). But if the child’s wish for the mother is satisfied because
the child is in the arms o f the mother, why would the child still want to peek
at the stranger? My theory will suggest that the stranger’s look is a m ajor cause
o f the child’s anxiety.11 T h at cause remains even if the mother is present.
However, the presence o f the mother helps the child to deal with the look of
the stranger. My objection to Spitz’s disappointm ent theory thus stands even
after a close reading of Spitz’s argument.
W ith the help o f L acan’s theory o f “the mirror stage” and Sartre’s theory
o f “the look,” the eight-m onth-anxiety shall be explained without recourse to
the concept of disappointm ent. T h e explanation will, however, claim that
being seen, rather than seeing, is the cause o f the anxiety o f the eight-month-
old baby.12 Furthermore, the explanation will specify the new danger that the
child faces at about eight m onths of age.
Sartre’s analysis of the look can be found in Being and Nothingness. In the
French edition it covers 58 pages out o f a total of 722. T h e passage on the
look is, therefore, not unimportant, and its im portance increases once one
understands its crucial function within Sartre’s philosophical anthropology.
By analyzing the function of the look, Sartre wants to clarify two problems at
the same time: the existence of others and on e’s own bodily existence. (This
purpose is reinforced by the titles o f the three chapters of Part T h ree). In
Sartre’s theory, the close relationship between the existence o f others and
on e’s own bodily existence culm inates in his concept o f the body as being-
for-others. It is that concept that Sartre has chosen as the title o f Part Three
which contains the section on the look.
C rucial to an understanding o f Sartre’s insights about the look is his
description o f a person who hears footsteps as he is looking through a key
hole in a hall (Sartre 1966, 317). If I were in such circum stances I can eas
ily im agine, so Sartre argues, that I would becom e asham ed. I becom e
asham ed about m yself for another when I think that another m ight be look
ing at me. T h e thought th at another m ight be looking at me is the occasion
for my sham e. In th at sham e I becom e aware of a dim ension o f m yself of
which, w ithout sham e, I am not aware. For Sartre, the sham e I experience
at the im agined look o f the other “reveals to me th at I am this being . . .
[that] I have an outside, [that] I have a nature” (Ibid. 3 2 1 -2 2 ). H e goes on
to claim that “ Sham e . . . is the apprehension o f m yself as a nature although
that very nature escapes me and is unknowable as such” (Ibid. 3 2 2 ). O r fur
ther, “T h us in the shock which seizes me when I apprehend the O th er’s
A C H IL D ’S N O -SA Y IN G 73
look, this happens— that suddenly I experience a subtle alien ation of all my
possibilities . . (Ibid. 324). O r “T h e appearance o f the Other, on the c o n
trary, causes the appearance in the situation o f an aspect which I did not
wish, o f w hich I am not master, and which on principle escapes me since it
is for the O th er” (Ibid. 325). O r “For in sham e . . . I do n ot cease to assume
m yself as such. Yet I assume m yself in blindness since I do not know w hat I
assum e. I simply am it” (Ibid. 325). In his rhetorical style Sartre calls this
assum ption o f o n e’s determ inate character, o f o n e’s bodily being, “my orig
inal fall” (Ibid. 322).
Interpreting Sartre, one can say that, for Sartre, consciousness becomes
aware o f its bodily dim ension by im agining the look of the other. C on scious
ness thus becom es aware that as body it is determ inate and for-others. T he
fact that I am determ inate accounts for the possibility that I might be som e
thing I do not wish to be. I take this to be the source o f what Sartre calls the
“alienation of myself, which is the act of being-looked-at” (Ibid. 323). T he
fact that I am this determ inate being for-others before I am aware o f it makes
me vulnerable to the look of the other. For Sartre, this is an ontological alien
ation and an ontological vulnerability. I believe that Sartre has discovered an
im portant aspect o f the hum an condition and of the look o f others. Indeed,
people report that they feel very uncom fortable when, for instance, while sit
ting in a train, they sense that they are being looked at.
T h at which is an ontological alienation or an ontological vulnerability
is o f course a perm anent problem for a hum an being. It is my general hypoth
esis that there is a m om ent in the child’s developm ent when the child is
explicitly confronting each of the ontological problems o f the hum an condi
tion. Freud’s theory o f the Oedipus com plex illustrates my general hypothesis
insofar as, during the Oedipus com plex, according to Freud, the child con
fronts the problem o f sexual differentiation in an acute way.
My claim then is that, at around eight m onths of age, the child confronts
the ontological problems Sartre described as being connected with the body.
My claim has the advantage o f supplying the specific problem that is
addressed in the eight-month-anxiety.
My specific hypothesis is thus both consistent with and com plem entary
to the genetic view typical for psychoanalysis. It is consistent with the
framework Freud assumed in presenting his theory o f the O edipus com plex
(a perm anent problem in hum an psychology, such as sexual difference, is
specifically confronted at a definite point in a child’s developm ent). My spe
cific hypothesis is com plem entary to the existing body of psychoanalytic lit
erature in that I claim that there is an additional problem that hum an beings
must face. T h at additional problem is the assum ption, the appropriation, of
the body. Logically, I need to then also postulate that every child explicitly
faces that problem at some point in her developm ent. A lso, I logically must
accept that the problem o f appropriating the body should be prior to the
74 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
problem o f facing sexual difference, because sexual difference is, am ong other
things, a m atter o f bodily differentiation. These two logical requirements are
satisfied in my specific hypothesis that the child faces the problem o f appro
priating, of assuming, his body at about eight m onths o f age. My hypothesis
therefore locates the problem of appropriating the body prior to the problem
o f facing sexual difference.
In applying Sartre’s insights to the interpretation o f children’s behavior,
I will criticize his interpretation o f the look. I will argue that the look can be
supportive (the m other’s look) as well as alienating (the look o f the stranger).
T h e look has either one of these roles, depending upon the em otional con
text (Ver Eecke 1975, 241 -4 3 ). T h e supportive look requires a m aternal em o
tional context, as Spitz’s study on hospitalism demonstrated.
3. L A C A N 'S T H E O R Y O F T H E M IR R O R S T A G E
Lacan first presented his theory of the mirror stage in 1936 and published a
revised version o f it in 1949 (Lacan 1977, 7ff.). In that paper, Lacan makes
seeing, not just an indicator o f a higher psychic structure, but the organizer
and creator of that higher structure. Lacan depends on Hegel and two em pir
ical studies to support his basic claim about the function of seeing.
From K ojève’s interpretation o f H egel (1969), Lacan borrows the idea
that an ego needs another ego in order to exist as an ego. Kojève puts it
roughly this way: an ego is what it desires. A n ego who desires only food is
not really an ego but a stom ach. Only an ego who desires another ego is an
ego in the full sense of the word. O f course, desiring another ego involves the
risk o f conflict, even deadly conflict. T h is H egelian conclusion gave Lacan
the opportunity to see the close connection between the mirror stage and
narcissism on the one hand and aggressivity on the other hand.
Later in his career, Lacan argued that such a deadly conflict— w hich is
present in H egel’s text o f the m aster-slave dialectic (H egel 1977 b,
1 1 1 -1 9 )— can be avoided if the sym bolic order m ediates the relation
between the egos. T h e power and efficacy o f the sym bolic order, in partic
ular o f words, was brought hom e to L acan by L évi-Strau ss’s text on the effi
cacy o f rituals, words, and symbols for difficult childbirths in prim itive cu l
tures (Lévi-Strauss 1949). L acan then turned to de Saussure (1959) and
Jakobson (Jakobson and H alle, 1956) in order to discover what m echanism s
language m akes available for m ediating interpersonal relations and for
structuring our desires. From de Saussure L acan borrowed the idea o f the
opposition between signifier and signified. From Jak obson L acan learned
that language’s two crucial m echanism s are m etonym y and metaphor.
Jakobson him self docum ented that deficiencies in each of these two func
tions lead to different deficits in the linguistic ability of the speaker. A t the
tim e that L acan first presented his theory o f the mirror stage he had n ot yet
A C H IL D ’S N O -SA Y IN G 75
created his linguistic theory o f the unconscious nor had he introduced the
concept o f the sym bolic.13
From L.H . M atthew s’s em pirical study o f pigeons and C h au vin’s study of
locusts, Lacan learned that the visual faculty performs a pivotal function in
connecting the psychological and physiological dim ensions (Ver Eecke
1983a, 113-26).
M atthews concludes: “the stimulus which causes ovulation in the pigeon
is a visual one” (1938-39, 558, my em phasis). For ovulation to take place, the
presence of a male pigeon is not necessary; the female pigeon need only see
herself in a mirror. T h e sexual activity o f ovulation thus requires a psychic act
which is not obviously sexual: seeing on e’s own body. From this study of cer
tain physiological functions activated only through seeing, Lacan derives the
insight that seeing on e’s own body transforms the body.
T h e crucial result of C h au v in ’s study o f locusts is that transition from a
solitary to a gregarious form is possible if nymphs o f the solitary locust have
contact with members o f their own species during early phases o f their
developm ent. T h e gregarious and the solitary form o f locust differ in beh av
ior, color, m etabolic activity (oxygen and food intake), and physiology
(C h auvin 258). Thus, again, contact— be it visual or tactile— has physio
logical consequences.
Lacan uses the ontological function of the other ego, learned from Hegel,
and the pivotal function o f seeing, learned from the experim ental research of
M atthews and C hauvin, to correlate two totally different phenom ena. T he
first phenom enon deals with a hum an being’s im agination and fantasy life, in
particular a fascination with dism emberment as evidenced in such cultural
habits as “tattooing, incision, and circum cision” or dreams about “castration,
m utilation, dismemberment, dislocation, evisceration, devouring and burst
ing open o f the body,” or in the historically docum ented preoccupation “with
the cruel refinement o f weapons” and torture-tools, or finally, the im agina
tion of an individual as it is objectified in the painting of dismembered bod
ies, particularly those o f Hieronymus Bosch (Lacan 1977, 11, 12, 4; Ver Eecke
1983a, 117). T he second phenom enon is what embryologists have called the
foetalization of a hum an being at birth. T h is refers to the anatom ical incom
pleteness o f the hum an brain and neurological system that results in “signs of
uneasiness and m otor uncoordination o f the neo-natal m onths” (Lacan 1977,
4; Ver Eecke 1983a, 117).
L acan’s mirror stage theory claim s that in seeing him self in the mirror or
in recognizing his own G estalt in the G estalt o f another person at about six
months of age the child discovers a (bodily) unity and a com pleteness he did
not experience before. Prior to the mirror stage, Lacan postulates that the
child’s image of him self is one of separate body parts: a hand, an arm, a foot, a
leg, a thumb. If for any reason the child or, for that matter, an adult, must give
up his attachm ent to that image, Lacan claims that fear of dismemberment
76 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
and/or body disintegration will be experienced. Thus, one’s own image dis
covered in another is the protection against the hallucinatory experience of
dismemberment and/or bodily disintegration.
A s proof o f his m irror stage theory, which is uniquely applicable to
hum ans, L acan points to the difference in the behaviors o f a hum an baby
and a baby chim panzee at about six to eight m onths o f age. O n the one
hand, the chim panzee has a greater problem -solving ability than the hum an
baby. O n the other hand, the chim panzee does not grasp the m eaning o f the
mirror im age, while the hum an baby can. W hen the chim panzee sees h im
self in the mirror, he tries to look behind it in order to locate the “other
chim p.” W hen he realizes that there is nothing behind the image, he loses
interest in it. Either the chim panzee does not recognize him self in the m ir
ror or he has no interest in a mere reflection. T h e hum an baby’s reaction is
totally different. H e responds with great interest, even excitem ent, to see
ing his own image. In L acan ’s words, the excitem ent is so intense that it
m anifests itself in: “a flutter o f jubilan t activity” (L acan 1977, 1; Ver Eecke
1983a, 115).
There is a second advantage that the child gains from the mirror stage.
In the mirror stage, the baby discovers him self as a possible object o f his own
libido. Therefore, in L acan ’s theory, the mirror stage is the beginning o f nar
cissism (Lacan 1984, 44). Lacan summarizes the gains that the baby experi
ences in the mirror stage as follows:
W hat the subject welcom es in it is its inherent m ental unity. W hat he rec
ognizes in it is the ideal o f the imago o f the double. W h at he acclaim s in it
is the trium ph o f a tendency towards salvation. (L acan 1984, 44) [transla
tion mine]
period. L acan ’s analysis, however, lacks any description o f the m other’s pos
itive contribution as it relates to the intrusion com plex or the mirror stage.
Spitz writes:
[I]t [the innate equipment] has to be quickened; the vital spark has to be
conferred on the equipm ent through exchanges with another hum an being,
with a partner, with the mother. N oth in g less than a reciprocal relation will
do. O nly a reciprocal relation can provide the experiential factor in the
infant’s developm ent, consisting as it does o f an ongoing circular exchange,
in w hich affects play a m ajor role. (Spitz 1965, 95)
It is the m utual give and take, its single elem ents constantly ch an gin g and
shifting (though its sum total rem ains the dyadic relation ), w hich repre
sents the essence o f w hat we are trying to describe and to convey to the
reader. (Ibid. 96)
W hat exactly does the child get from this mutual, dyadic relation?
A gain, Spitz’s study o f hospitalism is helpful in providing an answer (Ibid.
277). Briefly, hospitalism is a symptom present in young children who are
brought to a hospital and given hygienic and physical care that is better than
the care they received at home. Spitz’s amazing discovery was that these ch il
dren— separated for three m onths or more from their mothers at the age of
three m onths— did not develop as well as children who stayed home with
their mothers. In som e cases, their developm ent regressed or even stopped.
Sym ptom s o f increasingly serious deterioration appeared and were at least
partially irreversible (Ibid. 277). Som e o f the results observed were retarda
tion in m otor developm ent and progressive passivity. These children would
lie supine in their beds and would not achieve the m otor control necessary to
turn into the prone position. T heir faces would becom e vacuous, their eye
coordination defective, and their expressions often imbecilic. Som e would
show bizarre finger m ovem ents rem iniscent o f decerebrate or athetotic m ove
m ents (Ibid. 278). Finally, these children had a shockingly high mortality
rate. By the end of the second year, thirty-four of the ninety-one children
observed had died. Spitz summarizes:
changes. In the next stage this leads to increased infection liability and
eventually, when the em otional deprivation continues into the second year
o f life, to a spectacularly increased rate of mortality. (Ibid. 281)
the new nam e for Spitz’s eight-m onth-anxiety). I will first present K agan’s
theory and then argue that his theory does not necessarily com pete with
mine. Rather, my theory is com plem entary to K agan’s, which in fact requires
such a com plem entary specification.
K agan’s theory is based upon a general view o f child developm ent in
which the author argues that the nine-to twelve-month-old child has the
com petence to activate relational structures. By that com petence Kagan
m eans that the roughly one-year-old is “capable of actively generating rep
resentations o f previously experienced absent events . . . and com paring
these representations with the perceptions generated by the situation he is
in at the m om ent” (K agan 1976, 188). Kagan further states that: “T h e one-
year-old shows prolonged attention to events that are discrepant transfor
m ations o f his knowledge, com pared with the m inim al attentiveness at
seven m onths” (Ibid.)
K agan’s explanation of separation anxiety then takes the following form:
“distress to [sic] separation is the result of the new ability to generate a ques
tion or representation concerning the discrepant quality o f the separation
experience coupled with the temporary inability to resolve it” (Ibid. 189). A s
em pirical confirm ation for his theory, Kagan reports several cross-sectional
and cross-cultural experim ents that drew the following conclusions:
T h e m ain result was that there was no significant decrease in play, a sensi
tive sign o f apprehension, or occurrence o f crying follow ing the departure of
either parent until the child was about nine to twelve m onths old. T h ese
two signs of apprehension or distress increased linearly until eighteen
m onths and then declined at twenty-one months. (Ibid. 188)
T h e probability that the child would touch his nose was very low at 9
m onths but increased linearly through the second year— paralleling the
A C H IL D ’S N O -SA Y IN G 81
grow th curve for separation protest. . . . We believe that the older but not
the younger children were relating the discrepant inform ation in the mirror
to their schema of selfhood. (Ibid. 190, em phasis mine)
Separation distress occurs when the child is m ature enough to ask questions
about the parental departure and his response to it— W here is mother? W ill
she return? W h at should I do? W h at will the stranger do?— but not mature
enough to answer those queries. . . . W hen he is mature enough to resolve
those questions, his distress disappears. (Ibid. 190)
He [the child] may lower his eyes “shyly,” he may cover them with his
hands, lift his dress to cover his face, throw him self prone on his cot and
hide his face in the blankets, he may weep or scream. T h e com m on denom
inator is a refusal o f contact, a turning away, w ith a shading, more or less
pronounced, of anxiety. (Spitz 1965, 150)
82 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
Kagan is right in claim ing that there is a specific m aturational factor play
ing a role in separation anxiety. Separation anxiety requires what Kagan calls
the capability of activating relational structures. But the capability is not
exclusively used to create comparisons about others; it can also be used to cre
ate, in Kagan’s words, “a schema of selfhood.” Even if Kagan does not inter
pret “schema of selfhood” the same way I do, I believe that nothing in K agan’s
theory prevents me from claim ing that the child’s m aturation includes the use
of his “capability o f activating relational structures” for the creation of a body
image that allows him to actively inhabit his body. T h is is what I claim hap
pens in the mirror stage, creating an unforeseen vulnerability for the child that
becomes manifest as separation anxiety. My claim gains plausibility when one
considers the crucial results reported by Selm a Fraiberg and Edna A delson
(1973). These authors claim that: “A m ong children blind from birth there is
typically a delay in the acquisition o f ‘I’ as a stable pronoun” (Fraiberg et al.
1973,539). They further claim “that the acquisition o f personal pronouns goes
beyond practice with gram matical tools” and that “T h e blind child’s delay in
the acquisition o f ‘I’ as a concept and a stable form appears to be related to the
extraordinary problems o f constructing a self-image in the absence of vision”
(Ibid. 559). Or: “ It is vision that gives unity to the disparate forms and aspects
of hands and brings about an elementary sense of ‘me-ness’ for hands. Body
image is constructed by means of the discovery o f parts, and a progressive orga
nization of these parts into coherent pictures” (Ibid.). A nd finally: “K athie’s
[the blind child] achievem ent o f a stable T at the age of four years, ten months
corresponds exactly with her capacity to represent herself in doll play and to
invent an imaginary com panion” (Ibid. 561). Thus, seeing can be said to be
crucial for the construction of a self-image, which in turn is required for being
able to consistently use the pronoun ‘I.’ Seeing can thus be credited with a spe
cial function in the achievem ent of what one could vaguely call ‘selfhood.’
4. T H IR D O R G A N IZ E R : S A Y IN G “N O ”
In his analyses o f “saying “n o”” Spitz gives equal consideration to shaking the
head in a refusal gesture and using a verbal “no.” His thesis is that, from the
point o f view of the adult com m unicating with the child, no-saying is the first
sem antic sign or gesture (Spitz 1965, 182). Saying “no,” according to Spitz,
implies that the child possesses a concept o f refusal; saying “n o” is not just a
signal, it is a sign. T his distinguishes “n o” from other words already used at
that age, such as “m am a” and “dada.” Children use these words to represent
different wishes at different times. They could m ean “mother,” “father,” “
food,” “I am bored,” or “I am happy” (Ibid. 183). Therefore, the child uses
these words more as a signal than as a linguistic sign. Spitz clearly expresses
this theory in the title o f one o f his books: N o and Yes. On the Genesis of
Human Communication.
A C H IL D ’S N O -SA Y IN G 83
Spitz proves his thesis by showing how the child uses no-saying to extri
cate him self from situations that pose a dilem m a. O n the one hand, the
child has created a libidinal bond with his mother. Spitz dem onstrates this
through his analysis o f the second organizer: the eight-m onth-anxiety at see
ing strangers. I believe that his study o f hospitalism shows the ch ild’s depen
dence on its m other in even greater depth. L acan ’s mirror stage theory can
be used to explain the specific problem for which m aternal support is h elp
ful for the child.
O n the other hand, the child is pushed towards aggressivity, provoked by
the many frustrations imposed upon him. These include, am ong others, those
the child’s mother imposes when the child’s surges o f activity start to replace
the passivity of the previous stage.
Since the reader is already fam iliar with Spitz’s theory of the child’s libid
inal bond to his mother, I will now concentrate on the frustration in the
mother-child relationship. A s the child starts to walk, the relationship
between mother and child changes drastically. Prior to that event, “infantile
passivity and m aternal endearm ent and supportive action constituted the
m ajor part o f ’ (Ibid. 181) their relationship. Now, “the exchanges between
mother and child wi l l . . . center around bursts of infantile activity and m ater
nal com m ands and prohibition” (Ibid.). T he child, however, does not realize
that his activity often damages things or that he is doing som ething danger
ous. Therefore, mother is “forced to curb and to prevent the child’s in itia
tives” (Ibid. 181). Furthermore, the child’s locom otion puts distance between
the mother and the child. T h e mother, therefore, must increasingly rely on
“gesture and word” (Ibid.).
In explaining why the mother does this, Spitz advances the proposition:
that the m other is the child’s external ego. U n til an organized structural ego
is developed by the child the m other takes over the function o f the child’s
ego. Sh e controls the child’s access to directed motility. Sh e cares for the
child and protects him , she provides food, hygiene, entertainm ent, the sat
isfaction of the ch ild’s curiosity; she determ ines the choice o f avenues lead
ing into the various sectors o f developm ent; . . . the m other must act as the
representative o f the child both in respect to the outer world and to the
c h ild’s inner world. (Ibid. 181-82)
this negative affective cathexis ensures the perm anence o f the memory trace
o f both the gesture and of the word “n o” (Ibid. 185).
Furthermore, the frustration imposed by the m aternal prohibitions forces
the child back towards passivity. A ccording to Spitz, this provokes, “an
aggressive thrust from the id” (Ibid. 183).
Thus, the child’s dilem m a is that he experiences aggressive impulses
toward his mother to whom he also has libidinal ties. Spitz suggests that the
child solves this dilemm a by a well-known defense m echanism discussed by
A n n a Freud: identification with the aggressor. Aggressivity thus becom es the
em otional force which makes the refusal gesture available to the child.
A ccording to Spitz, his explanation o f the m echanism by which the
refusal gesture (or the word “n o” ) becom es available to the child proves that
the child has access to the abstract concept o f refusal. T h e child is not just
im itating the mother. Indeed, the m other’s “n o” is mostly, if not always, a pro
hibition o f an action the child initiated on his own. T h e child, however, uses
his newly acquired “n o ,” not only to impose a prohibition upon his mother,
but also, to refuse demands or even to refuse offers made by the mother.
“Johnny, do you want a piece o f cake; do you want candy?”— ”N o ” is often
the reply.
Spitz believes that the child has acquired the capacity to com m unicate
because he can now, by m eans of a linguistic sign, convey an unequivocal
meaning: the m eaning defined by the concept of refusal.18 Let me quote
Spitz’s com ments regarding his own explanation:
In the fifteen-m onth-old infant, this attack takes the form of the “n o” (ges
ture first, and word later), w hich the child has taken over from the libidinal
object. Because o f numerous unpleasurable experiences, the “no” is invested
with aggressive cathexis. T h is makes the “n o ” suitable for expressing aggres
A C H IL D ’S N O -SA Y IN G 85
sion, and this is the reason why the “n o” is used in the defense m echanism
o f identification w ith the aggressor and turned against the libidinal object.
O n ce this step has been accom plished, the phase o f stubbornness (with
w hich we are so fam iliar in the second year o f life) can begin. (Ibid. 187)
the m other is the ch ild’s external ego. U n til an organized structural ego is
developed by the child the m other takes over the functions o f the child’s
ego . . . the m other must act as the representative of the child both in
respect to the outer world and to the child’s inner world. (Ibid. 181-82)
from her by essentially telling her: If you think you know what I want, you
are wrong; I want what I want, even if that means that I need to forego the
cake I want.24
T h e second exam ple concerns a three-year-old who had fully mastered
the use of “n o” as the victorious battle cry Spitz described. In the late after
noon the child saw that his siblings had eaten several bags o f Doritos. He
asked one of his parents if he could have some Doritos. T h e parent first said
“no,” but, after the child repeatedly requested chips, the parent acceded to
the request and said, “If your brothers have eaten some, we cannot refuse your
request.” T he child went to the cabinet where the chips were and com
mented to him self in a self-satisfied manner, “I asked and they said yes.”
A bout two hours later, five minutes before dinner was to start, the same child
took two more bags o f chips out o f the kitchen cabinet. T he father asked the
child to put them back and explained that he had to eat dinner. T h e child
said “n o” he would not put them back and “n o” he would not eat dinner. T he
m other reinforced the prohibition and added that the chips were needed the
next day as snacks for lunch and that he could put one in his lunchbox. A t
first, the child said “n o” and com m ented that he was not going to put one in
his lunchbox. Suddenly, the child put one bag o f chips back in the kitchen
cabinet and said that only one bag o f chips was needed for his snack the next
day and asked if he could eat the one rem aining bag. T h e mother and father
repeated their prohibition and their various arguments, to which the child
replied each time with a forceful “n o .” A fter some mild coaching, the child
took his seat . . . and suddenly produced a contented face, put the one
rem aining bag o f chips next to his soup plate and said, more to him self than
to anybody else, “I did not open the bag.” (W hen he finished his soup, the
child asked if he could now eat his chips. A fter a second’s hesitation the par
ents let him have them .)
A gain, it was clear that the child understood the intellectual context of
no-saying. It was also clear that there was an aggressive com ponent to the
child’s ‘‘nos.” But twice the child’s own com m ents illustrated that no-saying
was a process by which he resisted but also slowly and partially allowed lan
guage to interfere with his demand for im m ediate gratification.
C O N C L U S IO N
that one supplem ents his theory with the insight that the m other’s em otional
relation to the child is crucial for that appropriation. Thus, the eight-month-
anxiety, as I understand it, includes the mirror stage as one of its moments.
2. In interpreting the three indicators, Spitz has a reductionist ten
dency which he corrects by including a richer contextu al description o f the
three indicators than his own explanation and theory incorporate. Each
tim e, his corrections concern the em otional significance o f the m other fig
ure for the child. T h is leads m e to argue that Spitz’s explanation o f the
function o f seeing in the period of the eight-m onth-anxiety is unsatisfac
tory because it can only explain disappointm ent and not anxiety. L acan ’s
mirror stage theory leads me to argue that the eight-m onth-anxiety is
caused by the look o f a stranger who rem inds the child o f the alienating
aspect of his appropriated body.
W hen it com es to no-saying, I disagree with Spitz’s interpretation o f this
achievem ent as being, at most, the acquisition of language as a m ethod of
intellectual com m unication. A gain, I find in Spitz’s own descriptions ele
m ents which go beyond the explanatory power of Spitz’s theory. I argue
instead that saying “n o” is a victorious slogan for the child because it estab
lishes the child’s will for his own point o f view, even if that point of view is
irrational. It is this irrational aspect o f the child’s no-saying which is the deci
sive elem ent in my argument that no-saying is more than a beginning o f com
m unication, as Spitz claims. Furthermore, I argue that no-saying also func
tions as a tool through which the child uses language to control his needs for
immediate gratification. W hile these two interpretations are not to be found
in Lacan, I am indebted to the Lacanian framework in formulating them.
3. Spitz makes no clear differentiation between the concepts o f indica
tor and organizer. By calling the social smile, the eight-m onth-anxiety, and
no-saying indicators and organizers, Spitz stresses that those three ph enom
ena organize past achievem ents and prepare the child for a higher level of
future psychic activity. I argued that these are organizers in the weak form.
T h e strong form o f organizer would be one in which a behavior is not just an
indicator o f a higher psychic activity but one in which it is, by itself, the
cause of that higher activity. It is, in my opinion, wrong to argue that a child
who does not show eight-m onth-anxiety has not established true object rela
tions and is thus em otionally deficient. Eight-m onth-anxiety is but an indi
cator o f true object relations. It is not that alone by which object relations
are established. T h e real organizer behind the eight-m onth-anxiety is,
according to my theory, the creation o f the body image (in the mirror stage)
by which the child appropriates its body. O f Spitz’s three indicators, only n o
saying would qualify as an organizer in the strong sense. A m ong other
things, the no-saying by itself creates the separation o f m other and child.
W ithout the aggressive act o f no-saying the separation of m other and child
is not achieved. T his conclusion clarifies and justifies the Freudian claim in
A C H IL D ’S N O -SA Y IN G 89
abstract: In this chapter I make use o f Sop h ocles’ piece Oedipus, the King in
order to answer a num ber o f questions about denials such as: can undoing a
denial avoid the tragedy experienced by O edipus? W hy was Teiresias’ inter
ven tion unhelpful? W hy was O edipus able to make use o f the inform ation
given by Jocasta, the messenger, and the shepherd? I will further argue that
Sop h ocles’ Oedipus, the King invites us to make a distinction betw een truth and
m eaning. For truth to becom e m eaningful, a person must integrate actively the
forgotten and repressed events. It is no help for others to tell som eone the truth
about him self. Truth about on eself thus possesses a characteristic w hich is dif
ferent from truth about the objective world, where telling the truth and pre
senting argum ents for it are effective ways to prom ote the truth.
IN T R O D U C T IO N
91
92 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C E S OF TH E N EG A TIV E
Sophocles ends the drama when Oedipus has accepted the truth and thus sees
his life in a totally new light. T h e whole dram a is nothing but the description
o f the path leading to O edipus’s discovery and acceptance of the truth. I will
pursue two questions: Why does Oedipus deny the truth about him self when
Teiresias presents it? A nd how is he ultim ately able to overcom e his denial of
the truth? T he answers to these two questions will first necessitate an analy
sis o f O edipus’s self-image at the beginning of the drama.
1. O E D I P U S ’ S E L F - I M A G E A T T H E
B E G IN N IN G O F T H E T R A G E D Y
O ne could object to the value of using this tragedy for m aking general con
clusions about people, by pointing out that the tragedy is based on an oracle,
and the oracle almost seems to be a contingent event, a kind o f deus ex machina,
which dominates the life of Oedipus, not from the inside, but from the outside.
For the Greeks, however, an oracle was no more contingent and no more exter
nal than, for example, the sudden death of a child in our civilization. Indeed,
the sudden death of a child from an incurable disease is, in our civilization, an
event that often promotes soul searching and self-accusations. T h e mourning
parents almost naturally look for events in the past which could have been
warnings about the illness. In both Greece and our own civilization an event
that is external to a person— an oracle in Greece, the biologically caused death
of a child— can set in motion a process of self-interrogation. Thus, even from
this angle, the case of Oedipus is not exceptional.
O edipus’s attitude towards the prehistorical events is one o f flight. He
runs away from C orinth. These prehistorical events are left out or repressed
in O edipus’s self-image as king. They have no m eaning for the present.
2. D E N IA L A N D R E JE C T IO N O F T H E E M E R G IN G T R U T H
In order to fulfill his royal promise of purifying the city o f injustice, Oedipus
calls upon the divinely-endowed prophet Teiresias. A fter m uch prevaricating,
O edipus forces Teiresias to tell him what caused the plague and who the mur
derer of Laius is. In verse 353, the prophet answers: “You are the land’s pol
lution.” In verse 362, Teiresias explains him self by bluntly affirming: “I say
you are the murderer o f the king whose murderer you seek.” A n d in verses
366—67 Teiresias adds: “I say that with those you love best you live in foulest
shame unconsciously and do not see where you are in calam ity.” Shortly
before he leaves, the prophet speaks without hesitation in clear and non-
m etaphorical terms:
H e shall be proved a father and a brother both to his own children and in
his house; to her that gave him birth, a son and husband both; a fellow
sower in his father’s bed with that sam e father that he murdered. (4 5 7 -5 9 )
3. F R O M D E N IA L T O A C C E P T A N C E O F T H E T R U T H
T h ere was an oracle that once cam e to Laius, . . . and it told him that it was
fate that he should die a victim at the h ands o f his own son, a son to be born
of Laius and me. But, see now, he the king, was killed by foreign highway
O ED IPU S, TH E KIN G 95
robbers at a place where three roads m eet— so goes the story: and for the
son— before three days were out after his birth K ing Laius pierced his
ankles. . . . (711 ff.)
T h is inform ation about King Laius’s death reminds Oedipus of the mur
der he com m itted. It too occurred at the crossing of three roads. O edipus’s
questioning reveals that the two murderers— first thought of as different peo
ple— are in fact one and the sam e murderer. Verses 82 1 -2 2 formulate this
insight dram atically: “A n d I pollute the bed o f him I killed by the hands that
killed him . . .”
These verses indicate that O edipus’s former self-image has eroded. It will
be further eroded as a consequence o f a second attem pt to free Oedipus from
his anxieties. T he oracle not only predicted that Oedipus would kill his
father, but also that he would marry his mother. A s long as Oedipus believes
that his parents are the King and Q ueen o f C orinth, he is protected against
this prediction of the oracle. A messenger from Corinth, however, shatters
this belief when he announces the death o f Polybus, asks Oedipus to return
to C orinth as king, and in an attem pt to brush aside an objection, tells O edi
pus that Polybus and M erope are not his parents (1016). T h is radically
changes O edipus’s horizon. W hat Oedipus formerly feared as only a distant
possibility, he must now consider as highly probable. T h e truth of his self
image is severely shaken once more.
T h e definitive turning point com es with the revelations o f the shepherd
o f Thebes. Oedipus has questions about his pierced ankles and about being
rejected at birth. H aving been told by the messenger from C orinth that he
received the young Oedipus from a T heban shepherd, Oedipus orders to bring
him that shepherd and he forces the shepherd to reveal who his parents were.
T he elem ent that links all of the inform ation into a coherent whole are the
wounds on O edipus’s ankles. Thus, Oedipus com es to recognize him self as
responsible for the plague in the city.
In the three steps that brought about the total decom position o f his self
image, O edipus played an active role. In each case, it is O edipus who puts
his self-image to a test. T h e circum stances in which the facts and events
emerged prevent O edipus from denying them , as he had with Teiresias’s
assertions. O edipus was able to deny Teiresias’s interpretation o f the events
by accusing him o f inventing the interpretation for the purpose o f plotting
against him. T h is form o f self-defense— aggressive accusation o f the oppo
nent— is made extrem ely plausible in the play because a dispute between
O edipus and Teiresias precedes Teiresias’s devastating interpretation. Such
an aggressive self-defense, however, prevented O edipus from facing the issue
on its own merit and honestly asking the question o f whether he could be
responsible for the plague in Thebes. O edipus cannot use the sam e tech
nique o f aggressive accusation to falsify the inform ation uncovered in the
96 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
dialogues with Jocasta or the m essenger or the shepherd, since they give
their inform ation in order to help him. O edipus does not reject the ques
tions about his past that emerge from the inform ation they give him.
Instead, he transforms these questions into self-interrogation. In his
encounter with the messenger, O edipus is so possessed by the process o f self
interrogation that he forces the m essenger to speak.
W hen the self-interrogation leads to insight, O edipus turns his aggres
siveness against himself. In an act of self-condem nation Oedipus pokes his
eyes out. Instead of a regal Oedipus, there is a broken m an (1360ff.). T h e for
gotten and neglected events have done their job. They have forced their way
into O edipus’s field of consciousness. Oedipus accepts them painfully, but
actively, as part of his new self-image.
4. C O U L D T H E U N D O IN G O F T H E
D E N IA L H A V E U N F O L D E D D IF F E R E N T L Y ?
I want to address two questions. T he first is: Could Oedipus have done any
thing to avoid the tragedy that forced the change in his self-image? T h e sec
ond is: W hy did Oedipus refuse to believe Teiresias? Put more positively:
C ould Teiresias have told the truth in a way that would have warded off
O edipus’s angry rejection? Both questions intend to clarify one concern: How
can denial be more effectively overcome?
A s to the first question, O edipus’s original self-image did not integrate
certain facts or events. Such non-integration is typical in cases o f denial.
Reality, however, is harsh and demanding. Unrecognized events do even
tually avenge themselves. King Oedipus finds his city afflicted by the plague.
In Sophocles’ drama, the unrecognized events are not yet powerful enough to
avenge them selves. T h e consequences o f the prehistoric events do not
emerge autom atically or independently; they get the support o f angry gods.
However, I wish to stress that in Greek culture, as in many ancient cultures,
people saw a close connection between affliction (e.g., the plague) and moral
evil. H aving com m itted evil— even if unconsciously— Oedipus had to be
punished according to the Greek vision o f the world. O ne can translate this
Greek m oralistic view into the secular vision o f contem porary psychoanalytic
theory which asserts that “the repressed necessarily returns.”4
This secular interpretation o f the king’s fall gives us a clue as to how
Oedipus could have dim inished the tragic results of the reemergence o f the
repressed events. Indeed, psychoanalysis sees the restoration of a healthy per
sonality in the undoing o f am nesia. Thus, the only creative solution available
for Oedipus would have been to actively search for the significance o f the
prehistoric events in an effort to give them a place in his conscious self
image, instead of trying to forget them .5 H ad he then found the penitence
necessary to expiate his personal guilt, he could have accepted it. Such a
O ED IPU S, TH E KIN G 97
course o f action would have given the dram a a totally different turn. T he city
would have been spared the plague and Oedipus would not have been forced
to publicize his crime. T h e tragedy thus illustrates one of life’s demands: A
hum an being must broaden his self-image so that as few events as possible are
repressed, forgotten, or considered unimportant. A n individual must regularly
recreate his or her self-image and integrate the past with the present instead
o f forgetting the past and allowing it to becom e a perm anent part of prehis
tory. In O edipus’s refusal to com ply with this hum an “duty” lies the origin of
the tragedy accom panying his change o f self-image.
The second point concerns Teiresias’s role. It contains something of a gen
eral application. Many people— similar to Teiresias— have little difficulty in
perceiving the one-sidedness and narrowness of others’ self-images. The tem p
tation, then, to present this insight as a logical and thus a necessary conclusion
is great. Such a move represents an aggressive intervention in the life of
another, who in turn must experience it as an untruth. Teiresias followed this
course exactly. Oedipus’s response was, understandably, an explosion of rage.
Was another outcome possible, given the imperious intervention of Teiresias?
T he role of king was a crucial part of O edipus’s self-image. T h e aware
ness of his royalty was the pillar of his life.6 It determ ined his attitudes and his
efforts towards other people. O ne could therefore say that O edipus’s identifi
cation with the role o f king was a primary way by which he supported and
directed his existence. Oedipus dedicated all of his energy to this role. How
could Oedipus have tolerated the underm ining o f his identification with this
regal role? It would have m eant the annihilation of the m eaning he pursued
in his life. N o one can tolerate such annihilation.
N evertheless, Oedipus had to change his self-image. Teiresias did not
bring this change about, whereas Jocasta, the messenger, and the shepherd,
unwittingly but effectively, contributed to O edipus’s transformation. They
did it unknowingly because their primary purpose was to reassure Oedipus
and thus to prevent him from looking further. In contrast, Teiresias, by trying
to broaden the king’s self-image, forced Oedipus to reaffirm his narrow self
image. T h is ironic relationship between intentions and results brought about
by the execution of those intentions requires further analysis.
C an we find in the attitudes o f Jocasta, the messenger, and the shepherd
som ething positive that we do not find in that o f Teiresias? T h e crucial dif
ference seems to be that Jocasta, the messenger, and the shepherd accepted
and supported O edipus’s initial self-image, whereas Teiresias the prophet was
concerned primarily with the truth, without considering whether this truth
would be psychologically destructive.7 Indeed, Jocasta, the messenger, and the
shepherd present O edipus with facts unknown to him in the hope that these
will confirm his self-image. Oedipus begins to broaden his views. T h is expan
sion becom es tragic for him only because the new awareness progressively
confronts him with his m assive guilt.
98 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
C O N C L U S IO N
Denial, Metaphor,
the Symbolic, and Freedom
abstract. In the previous chapter, I analyzed the case o f Oedipus. O edipus, until
forced to do so by circum stances, did not actively seek to broaden his view of
him self to include such denied facts as his pierced ankles. O edipus’ failure to
actively search out his truth led to tragic consequences. In this chapter, I will
analyze the autobiographical account of A nth ony Moore, who describes one
profound denial and the many steps, he undertook voluntarily, to undo such a
denial and its consequences.1 I will first present a careful phenom enological
description of that profound denial. I will then draw a number o f philosophical
(ontological) conclusions that I intend as correctives to the claim that hum an
beings are autonom ous creatures. T h e conclusions include the thesis that denial
is an unconscious form o f self-deception, that the achievem ent of personal free
dom depends upon the creation o f m etaphors, the usage of m etonym ic sim ilari
ties, the availability of a cultural system rich in symbols, and the ability of em o
tionally im portant persons to say “n o” to deep forms of identification.
1. P H E N O M E N O L O G I C A L D E S C R I P T I O N
O F A D E N IA L A N D IT S U N D O IN G
A n O verview
In Father, Son, and Healing Ghosts, the author, A nthony M oore, provides us
with an autobiographical account o f dealing with his father’s death, which
occurred during the author’s infancy and his fatherless childhood.1 T h e book
101
102 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
is the story of undoing a fundam ental denial. It is much more detailed than
Freud’s exam ples of denial. In particular, Freud does not tell us how denials
are undone. W hat he does tell us is that merely acknowledging the truth
behind a denial— the intellectual undoing o f a denial— is but a meager begin
ning to the work o f a com plete undoing.2 T h e m ajor work involves em otion
ally incorporating the denied truth and the world hidden behind that denial
into one’s daily life. T he book by M oore fills this gap in the Freudian litera
ture. M oore describes the many steps he took to undo the fundam ental denial
o f his formative years, which had consisted in denying that he missed his
father while at the same time deeply identifying with him.
In chapter 1 of this book I argued that Freud helps us to distinguish four
steps in the history of denial and its undoing. Denial— so Freud reasons— is a
partial lifting of the repression.3 H ence, I postulated a first m oment in which
repression was not lifted but was, on the contrary, successful. In that stage a
patient typically answers her therapist’s question by saying that she does not
know. T h e patien t’s consciousness is confronted by a blank. A second step
announces itself when the patient answers the therapist’s question with a
negative sentence. Freud claim s that such negative answers include the per
tinent inform ation in the form of a denial. T he truth thus appears but as
denied. In a third step, the therapist can help the patient see that her denial
contains the truth. T he recognition o f the truth is done reluctantly or purely
intellectually, as in the statem ent: “I guess that figure in my dream must be
my mother.” In the fourth step, the therapist helps the patient accept em o
tionally the im plications o f the denied truth, for instance: “If that bossy fig
ure in my dream is my mother, then I have to learn to stand up to her or to
avoid m eeting her.”
In my presentation o f M oore’s autobiographical description o f his
denial and its undoing I will follow the four steps discovered in Freud’s
analysis. M oore’s first step was the m om ent o f repressing his painful experi
ence, a process Freud postulated. In M oore’s case we see an unusually deep
attachm ent to his dead father. T here are indications o f deep pain and evi
dence o f sem i or unconscious m otives influencing his life decisions. M oore’s
second step was to deal with the pain o f losing his father with a well-crafted
denial. T h at denial was operative in spite o f his deep attachm ent to his
father. He needed the help o f a psychiatrist to m ove to the next phase.
Through his psychiatrist’s effective response to his well-formulated denial,
M oore took the third step, making the intellectual m ove o f undoing the
denial. M oore’s fourth step, dealing em otionally with the truth hidden in the
denial, had two stages. T h e first stage can be described as a gift to the young
M oore for his willingness to acknowledge the truth. Indeed, the acknow l
edged truth allowed M oore to recognize im portant dim ensions o f life that his
original denial prevented him from appreciating. T h e second stage consisted
o f the work that M oore performed to undo several unconscious interpreta
D EN IA L, M ETAPH OR, TH E SY M BO LIC, A N D FREEDOM 103
tions o f his father’s death: his unconscious over-idealization o f his father and
his unconscious belief that his birth was the cause of his father’s death.
T h e first step in all denial is, according to Freud, a deep pain that the
subject deals with by repressing and not accepting it. Because of the repres
sion, the pain that will be the cause o f the denial is not visible. A ll we can
expect from the reports o f a subject performing a repression are indications of
a paradox and a form o f self-deception used to deal with that paradox. In
M oore’s case we have reports that indicate his deep attachm ent to his father.
T h e attachm ent to his dead father seems to have been deeply established in
his unconscious from early infancy and leads M oore, as an adolescent, to
claim that “Som e separation from my father’s identity was necessary . . . to be
free to lead my own life” (M oore 5). T h e paradox in M oore’s life thus seems
to be connected with the young M oore’s will to over-identify with his dead
father to the point where he is unable to live his own life. I thus take the
over-identification to be the young M oore’s m ethod o f covering over an
unacceptable pain. I will describe that over-identification in its unconscious
depths and its overarching effects.
Let us first take a look at the depth of unconscious m otives present in
M oore’s over-identification with his father. M oore knows the story his
m other told him about how he threw up the first time she breastfed him after
she received the telegram announcing her husband’s death (Ibid. 1). He also
remembers, as a young child, the sad whispers o f grown-up voices creeping
into his safe haven under the table and the deep sense of sadness that would
com e over him (Ibid.). Furthermore, he writes that sharing his father’s first
nam e and his middle initial increased his identification with him (Ibid. 3)
Reverence for his dead father was silently reinforced by his mother not
remarrying. W hen M oore read with his mother, fifty years or so after the
death o f the husband/father, the love letters to his mother, both were sur
prised at the intensity o f the feelings expressed. Through her tears, M oore’s
m other said, “N ow you know why I never remarried” (Ibid. 104). In addition,
M oore’s m other had placed a portrait o f the dead father in a M arine’s green
uniform on her dresser; this must have nourished M oore’s attachm ent to his
absent father. M oore stresses that his father’s portrait was on his m other’s
dresser throughout his childhood. He even calls the portrait “a sacred icon
w atching over [his] childhood” (Ibid. 1). Furthermore, his mother encour
aged his “wearing tie clasps and carrying handkerchiefs that bore his [father’s
and his own] initials” (Ibid. 4), increasing his identification with his father to
the point that A nthony felt he had to live his life “in a way that was worthy
o f being the continuation of his” (Ibid. 4).
Second, let us look at M oore’s behaviors in which we can see the far-
reaching effects o f his identification with his father. A s a child, he was fasci
nated with Marines: uniforms, movies, even the M arine C orps Hymn. W hen
he had nothing else to do, the young M oore dressed up “wearing [the] green
104 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C E S OF TH E N EG A TIV E
garrison cap with a bronze 2nd lieutenant’s bar on it” (Ibid. 1). Later,
A nthony M oore describes him self at that time in his life as being fascinated
by “anything that reminded [him] of [his] father” (Ibid. 1). T he young Moore
“went to military high school in part to im itate [his] father’s life in uniform”
(Ibid.2). Introspectively, M oore writes, “I wanted to do it as well as my father,
so o f course I had to be an officer” (Ibid.). M oore lets us glimpse the degree
o f enthusiasm required to m aintain the denial (or repression) when he
describes that, “I com pletely immersed myself in the spit and polish o f a
cadet’s life” (Ibid.). A s a senior in college he took the entrance exam for the
M arine Corps Officer C andidate School, just as his father had. C om m enting
further on his decision to take the entrance exam , M oore writes: “Joinin g the
M arines was also one more way to im itate my father who had enlisted in the
spring o f his senior year in college, 1942” (Ibid.).
We can also see how images o f his father influenced important decisions.
Let me elaborate on the brief analysis I made in chapter one. A fter giving up
his dream o f becom ing a M arine, M oore decided to enter the N ovitiate o f the
Society of Jesus. M oore explains the decision to becom e a Jesuit on multiple
levels. H e recounts that his decision to becom e a Jesuit was connected with
the image o f his dying father. T h e young M oore “wanted to be worthy o f the
sacrifice [his] father had m ade” (Ibid. 3). H e felt that joining the Jesuits was
“dying to the world, particularly the world o f m arital love” (Ibid.). Moore
summarizes his motives to becom e a Jesuit priest as follows: “I believed that
becom ing a priest was a debt I owed my father for the sacrifice he made in
giving up his life for m e” (Ibid. 3).
W ith the images o f becom ing a Jesuit and thus “dying to the world of
m arital love” and of “sacrifice,” we enter the dom ain of the unconscious
processes that tie M oore’s conscious decision to becom e a Jesuit priest to his
father’s death. M oore informs us o f two more unconscious motives connected
with his father’s death. M oore’s awareness that his father’s death closely fol
lowed his own birth led him to the unconscious belief that the world had no
place for both o f them and that, in some way, he was responsible for his
father’s death. T h is irrational belief led to another irrational belief: that, just
as his father induced his death by fathering a child, so the young Moore
would induce his death by fathering a child (Ibid. 3). M oore developed a fur
ther unconscious fantasy when relating to his m aternal grandfather, who de
facto played the role o f a substitute father. A ffection for this substitute father
was tempered by negative feelings because his grandfather was not an intel
lectual and was tem peramentally unpredictable. Furthermore, the young
M oore’s whole affective relationship with his m aternal grandfather was
infected by denial of the pain connected with his father’s death. If M oore did
not miss his father, how could he feel that he had a substitute father in his
grandfather? Instead, M oore writes that “he preferred to pretend that [he] did
not need a father, that he had learned to be his own father” (Ibid. 4).
D EN IA L, M ETA PH O R, TH E SY M BO LIC, A N D FREEDOM 105
W o r k T o w a r d s In c r e a s in g F reedo m
B efo r e t h e U n m a s k in g o f D e n ia l
A first indication of the young M oore’s lim ited freedom from com plete iden
tification with his father was his decision to avoid R O T C in college. Moore
describes the m otivation for this decision in the following sim ple terms: “A t
the end of four years [of military high school], I felt I had had enough o f the
m ilitary” (Ibid. 2). T h is decision to avoid the military in college had been
preceded and followed by intense em otional com m itm ent to the military.
A bout his decision to go to military high school, M oore writes: “I went to a
military high school in part to imitate my father’s life in uniform ---- I wanted
to do it as well as my father, so of course I had to be an officer” (Ibid. 2). A nd
at the end o f his senior year in college, M oore again becam e interested in the
military. H e writes: “I took the entrance exam for the M arine C orps Officer
C andidate School, just as my father h ad ---- Joining the M arines was also one
more way to imitate my father who had enlisted in the spring o f his senior
year in college, 1942” (Ibid. 2). W hat m otivated M oore to interrupt his love
of the M arines and the military for three years in college? M oore gives us the
laconic answer: “I felt I had had enough o f the military” (Ibid. 2). T h is is a
reasonable enough m otivation when we remember that just prior he had
com pletely immersed him self “in the spit and polish o f a cadet’s life” (Ibid. 2).
D EN IA L, M ETA PH O R, TH E SY M BO LIC, A N D FREEDOM 107
But the m otivation to say “n o” to the military had no depth. For, at that time,
M oore had not yet created a positive alternative, such as dream ing o f becom
ing a teacher, a lawyer, or a doctor. Still, we do see that the young M oore is
more than the ego created by a deep identification and attachm ent to his
father. M oore is also a subject, who can allow him self to feel that he has had
enough of trying to be an ideal ego.
A second indication that M oore was not totally imprisoned in his
attachm ent to his father was his decision not to becom e a M arine after co l
lege. M oore describes the context o f his decision this way: “But when I told
my mother and grandm other w hat I was contem plating [becoming a Marine],
I realized that the sim ilarities to my father’s situation, which inspired me,
were more than they could handle. A s I looked into their eyes, I realized that
I could also be killed just as my father had been” (Ibid. 2). M oore transformed
his m other’s and grandm other’s wishes into his own by the following consid
eration: “ I wanted to do som ething significant with my life, dedicate myself
com pletely to a worthy cause [like his father], but I also wanted to live” (Ibid.
2). T h is second “n o” to the military and the M arines stuck. T h is “n o” origi
nated in his m other’s “n o .” U nlike the case of his first “n o ,” M oore went in
search of an alternative course o f action. H e transformed his m other’s m oti
vation into one o f his own by the statem ent: “but I also wanted to live” (Ibid.
2). However, that “n o” required further work.
In 1966, during the Vietnam War, becom ing a M arine carried the risk of
death. M oore made his m other’s fear his own m otivation by realizing that he
wanted to live. N o t becom ing a M arine and being unwilling to die entailed
that the young M oore cut two im portant ties with his father. T h e young
M oore’s psychic work consisted o f finding a way to cut yet preserve these two
im portant ties. A realistic solution seemed impossible given his decision not
to becom e a M arine and thereby avoid the risk o f death. Nevertheless, what
cannot be done realistically can be done in im agination or, better, in the
technical language of Lacanian psychoanalysis, via m etaphorical moves.
T h e young M oore re-established psychic contact with his father, the
M arine who died for his country, through a m etaphorical move in two steps.
First, M oore reports his fascination with the priesthood. O ne point stands out
for the young M oore: the prayer for the dead. T he rubrics request the faithful
to m ention the nam e o f any dead person they want to be remembered. W hen
he whispered “my father,” M oore reports that he was with his father and his
father with him (Ibid. 3). T he young M oore reports “that in the liturgy o f the
M ass I experienced a unique m om ent o f contact with my father. A t M ass I
discovered a mystery that transcended the power o f death. Being a priest was
a way to enter more fully into the power o f that mystery” (Ibid. 3).
Second, M oore enriched his adm iration for the priesthood, developed in
his childhood, by a number of m etaphors. We already saw that becom ing a
Jesuit was, for the young Moore, becom ing like his father because it entailed
108 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
a deadly sacrifice in the form o f “dying to the world o f m arital love” (Ibid. 3)
and because Jesuits were som etim es called “the Pope’s M arines” (Ibid. 3).
T h at the m etaphorical work done by the young M oore was not purely ratio
nal is evident in the inform ation M oore provided, inform ation which M oore
discovered only years after his decision to becom e a Jesuit. “W hen I entered
the Jesuits, I was twenty-three years old . . . the same age my father was when
he died” (Ibid, 3). A t age twenty-three, M oore’s father died physically; M oore
“died” metaphorically.
T h e young Moore, in refusing to be a M arine who would be in danger of
being killed in Vietnam , cut two im portant ties with his father. In becom ing
a Jesuit he m etaphorically reconnected with these two em inent characteris
tics o f his father: he becam e a M arine o f the Pope and he was prepared to die
to the world of m arital love.
A s M oore reports it, the m etaphorical m ove of becom ing a Jesuit, not a
M arine, was helpful, but ultim ately deficient. It was helpful insofar as the
Spiritual Exercises of Sain t Ignatius teach a m ethod of reflection and prayer
that engages the im agination in an inner dialogue with the characters o f on e’s
own life and the life o f Christ (Ibid. 3). M oore reports that this form o f prayer
and reflection initiated a healing process which stalled, however, around
issues related to his father (Ibid. 3). A s M oore describes it: “A key m editation
involves an intim ate dialogue with G o d the Father. Surprisingly, I was unable
to develop any real feeling around this conversation except one of frustration.
For all my fascination with things pertaining to my father, he remained som e
how affectively unreal and em otionally unavailable to me. These spiritual
exercises clarified areas of my inner life in which I needed healing” (Ibid. 3).
M oore provides a description of the difficulty in his life that needed h eal
ing. He writes that psychoanalysis, in particular analysis o f his dreams, clari
fied “many o f the psychological distortions that inhibited my freedom. I real
ized that I identified with my father so com pletely that I was unable to be
m yself’ (Ibid. 4). T h is self-description accords with L acan’s and De Wael-
hens’s theoretical claim that distance in an identificatory relation is required
in order to have the feeling of being a self. These two authors make their
claim with reference to the identification with the mother (De W aelhens
1978, 81, 90,126; Lacan 1984, 57). But their claim , I wish to argue, is made
with reference to identification in general, so that it can clarify the vicissi
tudes of the identification with either the m other or the father.
W o r k T o w a r d s In c r e a s in g F r eed o m A f t e r U n m a s k in g D e n ia l
A s described before, the young M oore was given the opportunity to psycho
logically separate him self from his father after his psychoanalyst helped him
to acknowledge the pain o f not having a father. Indeed, acknowledging the
pain of being fatherless allowed A nthony M oore to accept that his grandfa
D EN IA L, M ETA PH O R, TH E SYM BO LIC, A N D FREEDOM 109
Im p o r t a n c e o f H elp fro m O t h e r s in M o o r e ’s P s y c h ic W o r k
M oore’s further work towards freedom required the help of others. First, four
women played an im portant role in the steps that A nthony M oore took
towards freedom. They were: his mother and grandmother, who helped him
break away from his com plete and unconscious identification with his father;
his fem ale psychiatrist, who helped him acknowledge the pain of missing a
father; and finally M ichelle, who becam e his wife and who made it possible
for him to em otionally break down at his father’s grave (M oore 6 -7 ).
T h e Jungian-inspired movie Field of Dreams also had a role in helping
A nthony Moore. It provided the conviction that recovering a lost father is
110 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
possible. It also provided him with guideposts for such a recovery. It taught
A nthony M oore that one needs to listen to calls from within; that one needs
to respond to those calls with symbolic action; that one needs to wait atten
tively; that one needs to make an inward journey; and that, at the appropri
ate time, a connection with ancestors is possible. In accepting the need to lis
ten to an inner voice, M oore was aware that his personal identity was broader
than his current conscious ego or the “I” that is “presently organizing and
directing [his] life” (Ibid. 40). He now conceived o f his personal identity as
involving an inner dialogue with an “I” other than his current conscious ego.
H e accepted that his current conscious ego is not “the center o f all experi
ence and the source of all knowledge” (Ibid. 40). Som ething in him tran
scended his conscious ego. M oore called it a mystery. He personally believed
it to be an encounter with G od, but m ade it clear that this was his subjective
interpretation o f the experienced transcendence of the inner voice (Ibid. 40).
To connect em otionally with the journey prescribed for him by his trust
in the story o f Field of Dreams, M oore, at several turns, used metonymic
m oves supported by others’ words. Thus, whereas the protagonist o f Field of
Dreams heard the call to make a baseball field, A nthony M oore heard the call
to write a book about his search for his father. However, he entertained two
other possibilities: visiting the M arine C orps A rchives in Suitland, Maryland
to study his father’s military career or traveling to Saipan where his father
died. M oore wondered whether writing a book would require sufficient phys
ical activity to satisfy his conscious wish to take the call seriously. Recalling
Seam us H eaney’s poem com paring “the symbolic action of writing with the
physical labor o f digging” (Ibid. 41), M oore was able to accept the call to
write a book about his search for his father. Still, the work o f writing was slow.
It is true that Field of Dreams recom mended patience and attentive waiting;
but doubts arose in Moore. He repeatedly dealt with these doubts by rem em
bering a letter Teilhard de Chardin wrote to his im patient niece Marguerite
when he was a stretcher-bearer in the French army during World War I.
M oore felt that his father was using a condensed form of de C hardin’s letter
to adm onish his son: “Trust in the slow work o f G od. Your ideas mature grad
ually. Let them grow. Let them shape them selves. D on’t try to force them on”
(Ibid. 43). T h e m etonymic connection between the message o f Field of
Dreams, the words o f Theilhard de Chardin, and his own father made M oore
feel that the “unconscious would not fail to do its part” (Ibid. 44) in the heal
ing work o f writing his book.
M oore’s inner journey took a step forward when he and M ichelle visited
a replica o f the labyrinth in the C athedral at Chartres. Both, but A nthony in
particular, took several m editative walks through the labyrinth. During the
third day’s m editative walk, M oore “found [himself] thinking about [his]
mother and her difficulties with the early stages of Alzheim er’s disease” (Ibid.
46). M oore felt “a deep sense o f sadness well up inside [himself]” (Ibid. 46).
D EN IA L, M ETA PH O R, TH E SY M BO LIC, A N D FREEDOM 111
M oore was puzzled because he had always felt happy when thinking about his
mother. She “symbolizes all the security and love I knew as a child” and “pro
vided the safe container within which I was able to weather the loss o f my
father” (Ibid. 46). T h e feelings o f sadness he now felt were normally associ
ated with “those rare moments when [he] allowed [himself] to feel the sorrow
o f [his] father’s absence” (Ibid. 46). M oore discerned sadness for “the suffer
ing [his] mother would encounter as she moved through the various stages of
this cruel disease” (Ibid. 46), but also his “father’s sadness as he experienced
[his] m other’s illness. [He] could feel inside o f [himself his] father’s abiding
love and solicitude for the once-young bride he left so long ago” (Ibid. 46).
In his sadness, M oore “realized that [his] father and [he] were joined together
in [their] concern for [his] m other” (Ibid. 46).
In Field of Dreams, the protagonist, Ray Kinsella, ultimately meets and
bonds with his father. R ecalling the passage from Virgil’s Aeneid when A eneas
meets his father A nchises, M oore experiences “the yearning o f mortals down
through the ages to rem ain connected to those from whom they receive life
and those to whom they give life” (Ibid. 48). M oore sees in both Field of
Dreams and the Aeneid the same message: “this world and the next are more
closely woven together than usually imagined. T he separation between these
two realm s is less real than the continuity between them. Therefore, the
longing o f the hum an heart for connection between the generations is not a
futile yearning based on illusion, but a consoling truth grounded in reality”
(Ibid. 49). T his time it is the metonym ic fusion o f the m ovie and a passage
from the Aeneid that allows M oore to take his next step: “ [He] decided to fol
low the path o f [his] own ‘filial devotion’” (Ibid. 49). M oore started to collect
photographs of his father in his “dress green lieutenant’s uniform” and placed
them on his desk and the shelves o f the room where he was writing his book.
M oore followed up on a memory that his father’s uniform was in an old trunk
in the basem ent o f his m other’s house. In the trunk, he found his father’s uni
form next to his m other’s wedding gown. H e brought his father’s uniform to
his study and felt that his father “was actually in the room with [him]” (Ibid.
51). Som e weeks later, driving back from Richm ond to W ashington, M oore
followed the exit sign for Q uantico M arine Base, where his father had done
his officer’s training. H e walked around the one building that was old enough
to have been there in the 1940s. W hen he cam e hom e he confirmed from his
father’s graduation book that the building he had toured was indeed the
Reserve Officers’ Barracks, where his father had been trained. T hese two
encounters gave A nthony M oore the trust that “there was a realm beyond the
barriers o f time and death where [his] father and [he] could m eet” (Ibid. 52).
He even “felt his healing touch” (Ibid. 52).
M oore was also helped by soldiers who knew his father. A t this point in
his life, M oore was ready to leave what he calls “the inner soul work” and
make the pilgrimage to find people who knew his father. Following leads,
112 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C E S OF TH E N EG A TIV E
In fo r m a t io n A b o u t H is F a t h er
I could feel my father com ing to life. H is h um an shortcom ings made him
more alive, more real for me. H e was no longer a perfect, idealized hero, but
a m an o f flesh and blood who could be foolish, make m istakes and get into
the kind of trouble from w hich his wife had to rescue him.
Learning about my father’s peccadillos was a liberating experience. Try
ing to be the perfect son o f an ideal father was a burden that often got in the
way of my being myself. I w ondered w hether I inherited my incom petence
as a gam bler from my father. T h en I thought about some o f my other short
com ings and w ondered w hether they m ight also be a gift from him , and
therefore som ething to be prized. Just thinking about my father in this way
created a more balanced hero archetype for me to follow. A n oth er gap in my
fatherless childhood was being filled. (Ibid. 6 7 -6 8 )
For Moore, the effect of learning about his father’s gam bling was totally
different than it had been for Freud’s patient the “R atm an.” For the Ratm an,
his father’s gam bling was one more reason for great am bivalence towards his
father, as it was connected with stealing money from friends to pay off gam
bling debts (Freud, S .E ., X, 151-319). For the younger M oore, his father’s
gam bling led to a family embarrassment which was relieved by family friends.
Furthermore, the story had been lovingly told by his father’s friend, trans
forming a gam bling fiasco into a charm ing peccadillo. T h is story allowed
A nthony M oore to deidealize his father, without losing respect for him. W al
ter R idlon’s story was an exceptional gift to A nthony M oore who successfully
used it to reconstruct his psychic world.
Speaking with some o f his father’s fellow soldiers, M oore gathered a sec
ond kind o f inform ation consisting o f a series o f revelations about his father’s
character and his interactions with other people. From C harlie Eaton, a
member of his father’s platoon, A nthony M oore learned that his father could
114 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
joke with his friends. Eaton, who could barely speak because of his strokes,
told the younger Moore: “Your father was a real m an” (Ibid. 69). Burke
Dixon, another soldier friend, told A nthony M oore that his “father was his
favorite officer” (Ibid. 72). Burke continued by telling the younger Moore:
“Your father was a great listener. . . . You could always go to him with your
problem. We were just young kids away from home for the first time so you
can imagine how many problems we had. Your father would always listen and
try to help. A fter he was killed things were never quite the same for me.
W hen the war was over, I told my wife if we ever had a son I wanted to name
him A nthony after Lt. M oore” (Ibid. 72). T h e younger M oore felt “proud of
his father. H e was the kind o f m an other men respected and even loved. He
was down-to-earth, a regular guy, som eone who cared about his men and tried
to help them. He was a role m odel who could have inspired [Anthony]” (Ibid.
73). A nthony M oore felt sad that he had missed such a father to whom he
could have gone for counsel. However, at a deeper level the younger Moore
recognized som ething. H e wrote:
Som e m onths later, discovering an Indian belief that when a father dies, his
vitality is carried over into the son, A nthony M oore made a further step in
creating a dialogical identity when he writes: “I recognized in my own unique
personality the secret vitality of my father’s ongoing life within me. W hat
others loved in me and what I m ost enjoyed about m yself were gifts of his
presence. If I wanted to be with my father, I only needed to live the life I had
been given and to do it with enthusiasm and gratitude” (Ibid. 74).
T h e third type of inform ation concerned the worries and actions taken
by Lt. M oore during the last m onths o f his life. T h e younger M oore becam e
deeply engaged in his father’s experience of the battle of Roi-Namur, the bat
tle he survived. O ne o f the facts that stood out in Lt. M oore’s Roi-N am ur
experience was how the battle ended. Lt. M oore’s m ortar platoon was posi
D EN IA L, M ETA PH O R, TH E SY M BO LIC, A N D FREEDOM 115
tioned 125 yards from the end of the island with the rem aining enemy force
in between (Ibid. 94). M oore possessed a firing table for the 60 mm mortar
guns indicating the angle of elevation for shooting various distances. U nfor
tunately, the firing table did not provide the angles for distances less than two
hundred yards and thus was com pletely useless in the final hours o f the bat
tle for Roi-N am ur (Ibid. 94). T h is fact must have been very disturbing to Lt.
M oore, as it put his men in m ortal danger. W hen resting in M aui after the
battle of Roi-Namur, Lt. M oore took corrective action. “Lt. M oore and Burke
D ixon spent the afternoon o f Easter Sunday firing a m ortar and calculating
the approxim ate angle o f elevation for distances o f 100, 125, 150, and 175
yards. T h e lieutenant then wrote the corresponding ranges and settings in
blue ink at the top o f the firing table” (Ibid. 97). Easter Sunday was the last
day about which the younger M oore was able to get inform ation about his
father before he was killed in the first day o f attack on Saipan. Consulting his
calendar, the younger M oore dated Easter in 1944 as A pril 9. M oore him self
was b o m the next Sunday, A pril 16, 1944- Lt. M oore died June 15, 1944. T h e
younger M oore had always known the dates o f his birth and his father’s death.
We know that he unconsciously interpreted the closeness o f the two dates as
m eaning that there was no room in the world for both him and his father.
T h e younger M oore also “felt [unconsciously] that [his] birth had caused his
[father’s] death” (Ibid. 98). M oore furthermore confessed that he believed
fathering a child would lead to his own death (Ibid. 3). T he younger M oore
thus says that “the temporal sequence of A pril 16 and June 15, the dates
respectively of my birth and my father’s death [was] an inevitability that held
me captive” (Ibid. 98). T h at tem poral sequence made the younger M oore feel
guilty about his existence and fear that fatherhood, for him, would entail an
unconsciously announced death sentence. T he younger M oore was able to
use the inform ation about his father’s activity on Easter 1944, a week before
his own birth, to undo the deadly grip of his own unconscious beliefs about
the relationship between his birth and his father’s death. M oore describes the
transform ation o f his unconscious beliefs as follows:
T h e sacred time o f Easter calls upon Christians to have hope. W hat was the
hope that the younger M oore experienced and created that could counter
balance the deadly belief that his birth caused his father’s death? M oore him
self gives us the answer. M editating on his father’s love letters to his mother,
the younger M oore writes: “Reading about his hopes and dreams for the
future— dreams that had appeared to die on the beach o f Saipan— I saw
clearly that the heart o f those dreams had come true in my own life. I had
been privileged and blessed to live the life he had dreamed of living” (Ibid.
105). T h e younger M oore was now able to experience him self as the realiza
tion o f his father’s dreams, not the cause of their destruction. He thereby lib
erated him self from the tyranny of the unconscious fantasy that his birth had
caused the death o f his father whom he missed so much.
Reflecting on the psychic work he did, M oore writes: “Telling my father’s
story healed the fracture that ran through my psyche at my father’s death. I
have now com e to understand how, with simple fragments like a cardboard
firing table . . . we can weave together a pattern of m eaning to heal our psy
chic wounds. Following the guidance of the deeper self, I have learned how
to re-weave the fabric o f my soul and ‘com e hom e’ to the wholeness I lost at
my father’s death” (Ibid. 101). T he younger M oore understood that his deep
est gifts and com m itm ents were both his own attributes and the fulfilment of
his father’s dreams. M oore understood him self to be both him self and him self
as a gift for his father. By the m etaphor o f being a gift to his father, the
younger M oore was able to overcom e the unconscious feeling that he had
killed his father because there wasn’t room in the world for the two o f them.
Now he feels that he is his father’s dream com e true. H e has, at the same time,
overcome the unconscious identification that was at work during his denial
o f the pain caused by his father’s absence. M oore is now able to appreciate
and com m it him self to the talents and values that he feels are uniquely his
D EN IA L, M ETA PH O R, TH E SY M BO LIC, A N D FREEDOM 117
own. U ndoing the denial allowed the younger M oore to make the
m etaphoric m ove that set him free. From M oore’s story, we learn that the
tragedy o f denial is that it blocks the m etaphoric work necessary to becom e
an individuated self.
2. P H I L O S O P H I C A L C O N C L U S I O N S
B u il d in g B l o c k s T o w a r d s E m o t io n a lly
O v e r c o m in g t h e E f fe c t s o f D e n ia l
inner journey. The writings o f Saint Ignatius provided Moore with, among other
things, the techniques for using imagination to make progress in one’s inner soul
work. Jung provided Moore with a psychological frame for his journey.
T he symbolic system that M oore inhabited provided yet another form of
help. His experience with the Jesuits gave him the opportunity to separate
him self from his father by declining to becom e a M arine and instead to
m etaphorically unite him self with his father. Becom ing a Jesuit was, in the
symbolic system o f Catholicism , becom ing a “M arine of the Pope” and was
also dying to “worldly life,” in particularly to “m arital love.” T he symbolic
system of Catholicism provided M oore great help in another effort. Indeed,
success in undoing his deadly interpretation o f a causal relationship between
his birth and his father’s death depended heavily upon the younger M oore’s
belief in the symbolic system o f Christianity, in particular: the hope em pha
sized by the them e o f Easter .
The crucial importance of saying “n o.” M oore does not delineate the pain he
experienced growing up without a father. But he does describe the suffocating
identification with his father to the point that he felt he was not himself. I
therefore take his over-identification to be closely connected to the pain cov
ered over by his denial. A t first glance, it is puzzling that A nthony Moore
would find a solution to his unconscious belief about the cause of his father’s
death by way o f closely identifying his life with that of his father. Indeed, the
younger Moore ends his journey when he sees his life as more similar to his
father’s than he had realized. Why would such a realization bring healing
rather than alienation? T his question can be answered if we provide a more
detailed phenom enological description o f the end of young M oore’s journey.
M oore writes: “I was amazed to discover how much of my father lives in me.
It felt as though the core of his soul lived on in my soul. We were so alike in
the things that really m attered to us” (M oore 104); or “if I ever want to be
with my father, all I have to do is look deeply in my own soul” (Ibid. 105); or
“I realized that the resemblance ran down to the depth of my being” (Ibid.
104-105). I interpret these statem ents to m ean that the younger M oore expe
rienced a self o f his own that he then discovered bore a great resemblance to
his father. Rather than feeling alienated, the younger M oore feels that he
received a gift. H e feels that he is the fulfillment o f the dreams of his father.
He is that by being himself. I wish to call the double identity that M oore cre
ates at the end o f his journey a metaphor. T he younger Moore experiences
him self as his own person but at the same time as the gift to his father with
whom he discovers that he has so many similarities. T h e younger Moore is
him self and he is also som ething other than himself. He is both at the same
time. It is this identity in nonidentity that provides M oore the healing he
sought. For this healing to take place there must be a nonidentity in the iden
tity with his father. W hen Moore describes his adolescent experience, he
D EN IA L, M ETA PH O R, TH E SY M BO LIC, A N D FREEDOM 119
writes that he identified so deeply with his father that he felt he was not him
self. Between his adolescence and the healing end of his journey we have a
great similarity and a great difference. T he similarity is that in both cases the
younger M oore deeply identifies with his father. T h e obvious difference is that
in his adolescence M oore felt threatened and alienated by the close identifi
cation, whereas at the end o f his journey the similarity he discovers with his
father is experienced as a welcome gift. A less obvious difference is that
Moore, as an adolescent, feels that he identifies too deeply with his father,
whereas the mature M oore discovers that his deeper self is surprisingly similar
to that of his father. T h e mature M oore thus has lived a life o f his own that he
discovers resembles his father’s life. In the mature M oore we do not have a felt
identity between the younger M oore and his father, we have a discovered sim
ilarity. Between M oore’s youth and maturity som ething happened that allowed
M oore to feel that his life was his own, not his father’s. I think that the mature
M oore’s belief that he has lived his own life goes back to the two “no”s that
he expressed toward the identification with his father. The first “n o ” did not
stick. It was the time when he did not join the R O T C in college because he
had had enough of the military. T h is “n o” had no foundation and in time was
overruled by M oore’s desire to becom e a M arine officer. A t that point a sec
ond “n o” appeared. It was a “n o” introduced by M oore’s mother and grand
mother who feared that in becom ing a M arine, he might also die. Som ehow
the younger Moore made the “n o” of his mother and grandmother his own by
m eans of his own wish to live; he did not want to die. From then on, the young
M oore had to make his own life. A s we saw, the younger M oore created a life
for him self in which he metaphorically incorporated the image o f his father.
He became a Jesuit. Even if a Jesuit is a “M arine of the Pope” and dies to mar
ital love, it is also true that a Jesuit is not a real M arine and does not take the
risk o f real death. In becom ing a Jesuit, the younger M oore took distance from
total identification with his father and started the process o f finding an iden
tity for him self which was not a total identification with his father.
deadly unconscious belief that he— the younger M oore— was the cause of his
father’s death. M oore was able to do so by recognizing that there was a secu
lar time with two im portant dates: his birth and his father’s death. There was
also a sacred time with a new date: Easter Sunday, the last day o f his father’s
life, about which the younger M oore had information. His own birthday
becam e associated with Easter, because it was the Sunday after Easter. T he
sacred time connection— between Easter Sunday, when Lt. M oore used his
free time to act to protect his soldiers’ futures, and the Sunday after Easter,
when the younger M oore was bom — is at first only a new connection in time
without real weight. However, in the C hristian calendar, the eight days
between Easter Sunday and the Sunday after Easter comprise a week in which
the dom inant them e is one o f hope, whereby life overcom es death. W hen the
younger M oore started to realize that his father had made an effort on Easter
Sunday to better protect his soldiers, he could then begin to understand his
birth as a sign o f hope as well. T h e younger M oore began to realize that what
he liked in his life, such as listening to others and loving his wife, were also
the things that his father was good at. Slowly, the younger M oore was able to
realize that he was the gift to his father in which the “hopes and the dreams
for the future— dreams that had appeared to die on the beach of Saipan —
. . . had com e true in [his] own life” (M oore 105). T h e m etaphor of gift and
o f hope, based around the them e o f Easter hope, is the m etaphor by which
the younger M oore was able to override his unconscious belief that he was
the cause o f his father’s death. T he work of healing his soul ended when
M oore could experience himself, not just as the son of Lt. M oore, but also as
the gift to the dead Lt. M oore, a gift by which the dead father could com plete
his own life. It is worth noticing that the healing work relied heavily upon
the younger M oore’s deep belief in the symbolic system o f his C hristian cul
ture. M oore did not create his m etaphoric solution out of nothing. H e cre
ated it with the help of and in continuity with his culture.
P h il o s o p h ic a l I m p l ic a t io n s
The idea of a rational autonomous individual. Som e authors argue that human
beings are rational and autonom ous. T h e analysis o f denial and its overcom
ing in the case of A nthony M oore teaches us that we need to am end this th e
ory o f hum an beings.
Part o f the denial in A nthony M oore’s early life was his belief that he did
not miss his father and, furthermore, that his grandfather did not have an
im portant role, because he felt he was his own father. Rather than being a
sign of autonom y in the face o f a great loss, this affirmation of autonom y was
an instance of self-deceit. It prevented M oore from psychological growth.
Real growth depended upon M oore being able to acknowledge the truth of
his deep hurt that he missed a father while growing up. A s we have shown
D EN IA L, M ETA PH O R, TH E SY M BO LIC, A N D FREEDOM 121
before, healing the wound o f the lost father, including healing the uncon
scious guilt about the loss o f his father, cam e about when the young Moore
was able to feel that he was not just his father’s son but also a gift to his father.
T h e young M oore healed him self by accepting that he was not only an
autonom ous being but also connected with som eone. T he young M oore fur
ther healed him self by learning to live his life as a gift to his dead father.
R ational arguments could not override M oore’s unconscious belief in
him self as the cause o f his father’s death. N o rational argument could undo
his feeling that the short time between his birth and his father’s death m eant
that there was no room for both o f them. T h e younger M oore was able to
neutralize his dam aging unconscious belief but not by m eans o f clever ratio
nal arguments. T h e younger M oore’s healing work was not the work of ratio
nal analysis and argument; it was m etaphoric work, the patient work o f m ak
ing a m etaphor stick. Intergenerational connection and m etaphoric work are
therefore ideas that must com plem ent the claim that hum an beings are ratio
nal and autonom ous.
two layers at work. There is first the ego which ostensibly organizes M oore’s
life. M oore’s ego decides to go to the military school, not to enter R O T C in
college, and to take the entrance exam for the M arine C orps Officer C an d i
date School. However, another layer of M oore— let us use the Freudian label,
the unconscious— performed its own intentional acts. Long before the con
scious ego made its adolescent decisions, M oore’s unconscious had already
interpreted the death of his father and had deeply identified with his dead
father. T h is unconscious layer makes interpretations with a logic which is
referred to by Freud as primary process. O ne crucial feature o f the logic of
unconscious interpretation is that the child gives itself a form of om nipo
tence. In an illusionary way, the child feels that it causes all im portant events
around himself. Thus, when M oore’s father dies a short time after he is born,
the younger M oore feels, unconsciously, that he caused the death o f his
father. He also feels that fathering a child will guarantee im m inent death for
himself. Similarly, the younger M oore unconsciously idealizes and identifies
with the dead father, who was so beloved by his wife. M oore’s conscious ego
deals with the paradox o f unconscious ideations (unconscious guilt for the
father’s death and idealization and identification with the dead father) by, on
the one hand, making decisions that allow him to be like his father and, on
the other hand, by publicly denying that he misses his dead father. T h e heal
ing work M oore performed starts the m om ent when M oore accepts that he is
a multi-layered person in whom the conscious ego needs to listen to a voice
beyond the ego. Furthermore, the conscious ego accepts the humility entailed
in listening to that other voice. T he conscious ego thereby accepts that it has
to change.
A n outsider may correctly ascribe self-deception to a person when he can
see several forms o f interpretation at work that contradict each other. A scrib
ing self-deception to a person at a m om ent when that person is not aware of
self-deception is a teleological move. T h e expectation is that a person with
multiple layers is also called upon to act as a unified person.7 A idin g that
teleological m ove requires that one be artful. To accuse another of self-deceit
is not helpful. Rather, one should say the appropriate words so that the other
can intellectually undo his own denial and thereby accept an invitation to
differently address the paradox behind the self-deceit. A s we have seen, that
requires psychic work and the creation o f appropriate metaphors.
Conclusion
1. A person who utters a denial reveals m uch to som eone who can listen.
In a denial, one reveals som ething that one also tries to hide. A denial is thus
not just any kind o f self-revelation. It is a revelation about a fault or a frac
ture in on e’s own personality. A person “in denial” is unable to deal with an
emerging truth. A denial, thus, reveals not only content, but also personality
structure, a kind o f fracture in the person in question.
2. The revelation that occurs in a denial testifies to the fact that the per
son is growing in ability to name and face the truth. T he need to hide what has
been revealed in a denial points to a weakness in the individual. He has not
been able to face the truth he is in the process of revealing. T h e inability to
have faced the truth is not trickery. It indicates a deficiency in agency. But
where there is a deficiency in agency, one needs to be careful in assigning moral
blame. I argue that Freudian forms of denials should not be called lies. They
should not be classified as moral failures, but rather as human deficiencies.
3. Freud teaches us that denials are frequently occurring phenom ena.
A ppealing to H egel’s thought, I dem onstrated that denials do not just occur
frequently, but are unavoidable, even necessary. For Hegel, truth is not just
an epistem ological task. It is also an anthropological adventure. T h e anthro
pological adventure is such that em otions becom e involved because truth is
about the m eaning o f on e’s own existence. Doubt, therefore, can become
despair. Hegel also teaches us that hum an beings face paradoxes that can be
solved only by several hum an beings acting jointly. In some cases the
approach o f no one person is satisfactory, even though it appears to the per
son acting that his/her approach is the only possible solution to a given prob
lem. Facing the deficiency of on e’s own solution is not just a m atter of doubt.
It is also a m atter o f despair. Denials are a defensive, and thus defective way,
to deal with truths that may cause one despair.
4. Even though denials are defensive moves, they are also m oves towards
greater freedom. Towards the end o f his article on negation, Freud explicitly
123
124 D EN IA L, N E G A T IO N , A N D TH E FO R C ES OF TH E N EG A TIV E
connects the use o f denial with the quest for freedom. H e credits the use of
negation with the ability to create “a first measure of freedom from . . . the
com pulsion o f the pleasure principle” (S .E ., X IX , 239). H egel’s study o f the
will in his Philosophy of Right provides a view o f the different m ethods used by
the will to create distance, and thus a degree of freedom from desires and
impulses— that is, from the given. T he arbitrary will creates distance from the
given by denying it any importance. T h e arbitrary will takes as its grounds for
deciding simply: “I decide.” T h e eudem onic will, according to Hegel, creates
distance and freedom from the given by subm itting any given to the calculus
of its contribution to a self-chosen goal, for exam ple, happiness. H egel argues
that the m ethod used by the eudemonic will is superior to the one used by the
arbitrary will. H egel forcefully dem onstrates the deficiency of the m ethod
used by the arbitrary will. I argue that a denial can be understood as an
attem pt to establish distance and freedom from a given by the deficient
m ethod of the arbitrary will, that is, by an epistem ological m ove that denies
the objectively given. From Hegel, one can learn that denying the objective
is not the only way to affirm one’s freedom. A better and more constructive
way to demonstrate one’s freedom from the objectively given is to acknow l
edge the truth o f the given, but submit the given to a calculation. M oving
beyond a denial will therefore involve the two steps of, firstly, epistemologi-
cally acknowledging the given and, secondly, acquiring the em otional and
intellectual capacity to submit the given to a rational evaluation o f its possi
ble contribution to on e’s goals. These two steps, which Freud observed and
described in his article, are hereby given a logical necessity.
5. Freud describes the acquisition o f the linguistic symbol of negation as
the mastery of a miraculous tool. It produces the necessary distance and neg
ativity to create freedom. T h e idea that hum an developm ent is not linear, but
proceeds by sudden spurts, is defended by Spitz. Children reach new plateaus
o f developm ent because several developing areas suddenly allow the child to
perform a series o f previously impossible tasks. T h e social smile, the eight-
month-anxiety, and the no-saying at fifteen m onths are indicators o f such
new spurts in developm ent. I argue that no-saying is more than simply an
indicator o f that higher level of developm ent. No-saying is the organizer, the
creator o f that higher level of developm ent. Spitz recognized that no-saying
creates the first unequivocal concept. I argue that no-saying creates, by itself,
the distance from the caretaker required for the child’s affirmation o f its
emerging autonomy, affirming the right to the child’s own point o f view, even
if that point o f view appears som etim es to be manifestly irrational.
6. Freud points out that undoing a denial is often a com plicated and
arduous task. In his article on denial he did not specify the contribution that
an interlocutor can make in the overcom ing o f a denial. By analyzing O edi
pus, we learn that Teiresias fails, while Jocasta, the messenger, and the shep
herd succeed in helping Oedipus find the truth. I argue that in order to be
C O N C L U SIO N 125
helpful, the interlocutor must accept that establishing the other’s subjective
truth is different from establishing the truth about som ething with which the
other is not or is only marginally involved, that is, objective truth. In help
ing another find the truth about himself, the interlocutor must rem ain aware
that it is the other as discourse partner who creates the m eaning of his life.
T he interlocutor must accept that he, therefore, cannot impose a new m ean
ing upon another. A ll the interlocutor can do is provide evidence that the
other will be able to use in order to create a new m eaning for himself. To be
helpful in undoing a denial, the interlocutor must first accept the fact that
truth cannot be provided to his discourse partner. T h e truth about oneself
can only be discovered by the self. T h e life stories o f O edipus and A nthony
M oore vividly illustrate this claim.
Notes
C H A P T E R O N E . T H E C O M P L E X P H E N O M E N O N O F D E N IA L
1. Freud’s text does allow one to identify the gender of the patient.
3. A s I see it the term ‘n egation ’ refers both to the linguistic sign o f negation
and to the negative judgm ent that uses the linguistic sign o f negation. T h e term
‘den ial’ refers to a negative judgm ent that wrongly denies the truth presented in a n eg
ative judgm ent. A sim ilar distin ction is made in the French translation o f Verneinung
as négation and dénégation. See H yppolite (L acan 1988, 290), and L aplanche & Pon-
talis, 262.
A s the m eaning o f the two terms “n egation ’ and ‘den ial’ is different in psycho
analytic theory, in contem porary linguistics, in sociology, and in logic I w ant to give
a brief overview o f the different m eanings o f these two terms in the different sciences.
In psychoanalysis, negation refers to the logical operation in a proposition whereby
one affirms that a con n ection in the proposition “He is not tall” does not hold. A
denial refers to the use o f a linguistic negation in order to affirm that a con nection
does n ot hold, whereas in fact the con n ection exists: “T h is figure in my dream is not
127
128 N O T E S TO C H A P T E R ONE
4. Wurmser, using the research o f Basch and D orpat provides useful distinctions
betw een denial (Verneinung), repression (Verdrängung), and a third term closely
related to the previous two: disavow al (Verleugnung). He writes that denial deals with
a factual reality that m ight evoke painful m eanings; repression with instincts whose
dem ands are unacceptable, and disavow al with unacceptable m eanings o f the per
ceived reality. Th us, denial refuses to acknow ledge factual reality; repression refuses to
acknowledge instinctual dem ands; disavow al refuses to acknowledge em otional m ean
ings (W urmser 1989, 17 7 -7 8 ). A th anassiou m akes a sim ilar distin ction between
repression and denial (1988).
By negating, a hum an being is able to articulate and thus to know som ething that is
undesirable. T h is is m uch better than simply turning away from the danger. In a n ega
tion, one takes sym bolic distance from disappointed desires while taking cognisance
o f them. Two other techniques to deal w ith disappointm ents are that o f the pervert
who uses a fetish to deny the absence o f the phallus in the m other and that of the psy
chotic who can believe th at as a m an he is becom ing a w om an (Sch reber). A n ega
tion is thus a creative (sym bolic) way of dealing with disappointed desire. A different
view was held by Frege.
In his article, Benm akhlouf points out that for Frege a negation is only a m ethod
o f creating anoth er thought. O ne can have the idea: red. A negation is nothing but
the creation o f another idea: non-red. Frege tries to elim inate the judgm ent present
in negative sentences.
In her article, Joseleyn Benoist dem onstrates th at Husserl sees that som ething
unique is happenin g in a negation. H usserl claim s th at in n egation we express a
deception, a deceit, even a disappointm ent. We expected som ething but it is n ot so.
In his later years, Husserl refers to perception as the positive basis for both a positive
and a negative judgm ent. I can expect the color o f a ball to be the same on its back
as it is on its front. T h is expected perception can be either confirm ed or denied.
Ben oist points out th at by grounding the act o f n egation in perception H usserl is
unable to understand the con tribution o f the symbol o f n egation to the act o f n ega
tion. Freud, on the contrary, saw very clearly the sym bolic elem ent in the negative
judgm ent.
Finally, in her article, A n ton ia Soulez points out that W ittgenstein is puzzled
about the m eaning o f a negation. W ittgenstein refuses to relate the m eaning o f a
n egation to an object because he denies the existence of negative facts. W ittgenstein
then points out th at the m eaning of language and thus also of a negation is that it is
a sym bolic game. O n e can then claim that Freud understood, as W ittgenstein did, that
n egation is a linguistic gam e; he understood, as Husserl did, that negation is dealing
w ith a disappointm ent. C om b in ing the insights o f W ittgenstein and Husserl, one
could claim that, for Freud, negation offers the opportunity to use deceit to deal sym
bolically with a disappointm ent. It is a creative repression.
Less relevant for our study o f Freud’s theory o f negation but still con tain in g inter
esting studies about the phenom enon of negation is the special issue of Argumentation,
6, 1992, no. 1, 1-130, resulting from a research project at the C entre de Recherches
Sém iologiques de l’U niversité de N euch âtel (D enis M iéville, G u est Editor).
6. In my opinion, Freud’s trick to let patients label the repressed and his later
exam ple about boasting show that Freud’s usage o f the con cept o f denial is restricted
to linguistic denials. T h is is also observed by Litowitz (1998, 123). In G erm an the
label for denial is “Vemeinung," w hich m eans both denial and negation. T h e G erm an
label for den ial thus explicitly ties denial to a linguistic act.
By com paring Freud with Frege, G . M yerson too affirms that Freud’s concern
was with negation in its linguistic form. H e does poin t out correctly, however, that
Freud tries to link n egation “to the fundam ental dynam ics of the psyche” (M yerson
1995, 10).
Edith Jacobson , on the other hand, expands the m eaning of denial to include
nonlinguistic forms of denying the reality, such as the cancer patien t who starts pro
130 N O T E S T O C H A P T E R ONE
jects that m anifestly will last beyond his expected survival time. Jacobson seem s to
look for nonlinguistic forms of behavior expressing the fundam ental dynam ics o f the
hum an psyche.
7. Freud’s artifice and his exam ples show that his usage of the concept o f denial
is restricted to linguistic denials. In G erm an the word for denial is “Vemeinung,” which
m eans both denial and negation. T h e G erm an word for denial thus explicitly ties
denial to a linguistic act. However, Jacobson is not alone in expanding the m eaning of
the concept of denial. In the current psychological literature, denial is used both for
linguistic and nonlinguistic forms o f denial. Th us, a cancer patien t who starts projects
that are expected to last beyond his expected survival time is said to deny his com ing
death, not by a linguistic statem ent, but by his acts (W eism an). Dorpat, on the other
hand, in his im portant book on denial, considers denial to be a “defensive process [that]
occurs at a presymbolic or prelinguistic level” (D orpat 1985, 3). O ne crucial contribu
tion of D orpat’s work is his thesis that a presymbolic denial “prevents the form ation of
verbal ideas” (Ibid; also 42, 247, 251, 253, 265, 267) about the denied reality. H e calls
this the “cognitive arrest theory o f denial” (Ibid. chapter 1). D orpat objects to Freud’s
usage of the word "Vemeinung” for the defense m echanism o f denial (117) because Dor
pat wants to distinguish sharply between negation as a logical or gram m atical concept
and denial or disavowal as a defense m echanism . N otw ithstanding his disagreem ent
with Freud, I see D orpat as providing a crucial insight for clarifying the puzzle that
Freud saw in linguistic denials. T h e puzzle for Freud was that a linguistic denial labels
that w hich it denies. T h e creative contribution of a linguistic denial is not the telling
o f a truth. Its creative contribution is the preparatory step o f labeling the problem. Dor
p at’s insight is that a presymbolic denial prevents the subject from paying enough
attention to the denied reality to be in a position to form the concepts necessary to
properly label the denied reality. In a linguistic denial, the patient succeeds, at least
partially, in overcom ing the deficit pointed to by Dorpat: what was previously
unknown has now been labeled (Ibid. 48, 236). G iven D orpat’s clarification of the
defense m echanism o f denial, it makes sense that Freud pays attention to the difficulty
that patients have in giving inform ation about the unconscious. Rem em ber that Freud
reports with some pride that he invented a trap to help them describe a portion o f the
unconscious material (Freud, “N egation ,” S .E ., X IX , 133).
8. Further exam ples of boasting can be found in Freud’s study o f Emmy v. N . and
o f C acilie M . (S .E ., II, 76).
11. For an exam ple see Ver Eecke (1984, 145). T h e patient deeply desires to be
hom e when her son visits town. Yet she does not dare to ask from the nun who is
director o f the asylum for the perm ission to leave— a perm ission regularly granted—
because: “W h at would that nun think o f m e?”
N O T E S T O C H A PT ER ONE 131
12. Som e authors go further and argue that a denial dem onstrates that the hum an
being is split (Ver Eecke 1984, 19; W urmser 1985; W urmser 1989, 177ff).
13. C urrent literature often explicitly distinguishes these two phases. A uthors
distinguish betw een denial o f facts or o f cognition and denial o f affects, responsibility,
or blam e (Jackson & Thom as-Peter; Levine at al.; H oke et al.; Brenitz; K ennedy &
G rubin; W inn; W ool & G oldberg). T h a t distinction is often referred to as the dis
tin ction betw een a denial o f the facts and the denial o f the m eaning of the facts. O ne
author points to several layers hidden behind the denial of the m eaning o f facts. He
distinguishes betw een the im plications of facts, changes dem anded if the facts are
faced, and feelings related to the facts (Kearney 1996, 13-14, 4 3 -4 4 ). Finally, another
author distinguishes three forms o f intensity of denial, w hich he labels disbelief, defer
ral, and dism issal (Lubinsky).
14. Freud writes that this intellectual acknow ledgm ent w ithout em otional accep
tance is “a very im portant and som ew hat strange variant” of that sam e split in a denial
(Freud, S .E ., X IX , 236). I understand the rest of the article to be an attem pt by Freud
to ponder the relation and the split betw een the intellectual and the affective. H is
m ain argum ent and contribution is the claim that, notw ithstanding the split betw een
the intellectual and the affective, it is possible to dem onstrate the dependence o f the
intellectual upon the affective.
15. T h e crucial work that needs to be done in the fourth phase is well described
by Dorpat: “W h at is denied is disavowed, whereas working through some denied c o n
tent includes an avowal as part of the self o f what has previously been rejected” (D or
p at 1985, 238).
16. T h e third and fourth phases o f denial illustrate the fact th at there is an inter
subjective dim ension to denial. G iven the appropriate attitude of a partner, denial
becom es unnecessary. Th us, several authors argue that a safe and accepting environ
m ent is helpful for alcoholics (Rugel & Barry), incestuous fathers (G eller et al.) and
other sexual offenders to overcom e their denial (Laflen & Sturm ; M arshall;). T h e
same argum ent is presented for overcom ing denial of death (de H ennezel 1989). A t
the sam e time, certain attitudes of others prom ote denial. Thus, one researcher found
that “T h e patien t’s need for denial . . . was in direct proportion to the doctor’s need
for den ial” (D orpat 1989, 19). D orpat calls this the “interactional perspective” of
denial. I will explicitly address this puzzle in chapter 6 w hen I ask the question o f why
Teiresias provokes a denial in O edipus, whereas Jo casta, the shepherd, and the m es
senger h elp O edipus undo his previous denial. I will address the problem of helping
others undo a denial in my analysis o f A . M oore autobiography, in w hich he describes
overcom ing a profound denial.
17. H yppolite indicates the com plexity o f such undoing by using H egel’s con cept
o f aufheben, ‘to overcom e,’ as a m atrix for such undoing (Ver Eecke 1984, 2 5 -2 7 ).
L ater on I will be able to do more than indicate the com plexity o f undoing a denial.
I will provide a careful phenom enological description o f that process as a basis for a
number o f anthropological conclusions.
18. In cognitive science, one would call that an em ergent property.
19. I therefore agree with A .O . Rorty w hen she stresses that hum an beings orga
nize their psychic life at different levels. Sh e makes that claim a precondition for the
132 N O T E S T O C H A PT ER ONE
21. It is curious th at Freud draws e x p licit atte n tio n to the great im portance of
the acq u isitio n o f the linguistic fu n ction o f n egatio n but does n ot further c o n c e p
tualize the n egative m om en t postulated by h is claim that the o b ject o f a judgm en t
o f existen ce m ust first h ave b een lost. In the follow in g pages, I w ill argue th a t acts
o f separation and the ob vious or h id den form s o f aggression accom p an y ing such
acts o f separation w ill h ave to play an im portan t role in the developm en t o f a p er
son and thus also in un doin g a d en ial and thereby restorin g w h olesom eness in that
person.
N O T E S T O C H A PT ER ONE 133
22. Freud h im self has given a survey of the developm ent o f his theory about this
problem (Freud, S .E ., X X I, 117-22). For an extensive discussion o f this same prob
lem, see S .E ., XIV, 113-16.
24. Elsewhere Freud refers to two authors who studied this phenom enon: Bleuler
and G ross (Freud, S .E ., V III, 175, n .2).
25. O ne can find texts in Freud’s “N egatio n ” where Freud seem s to touch on the
two dim ensions I discuss below. But touching on a subject m atter is n ot the sam e as
highlighting its im portance.
26. T h ese and other o f H egel’s ideas will be used in chapters 3 and 4 to further
clarify the phenom enon o f denial.
27. I am , o f course, not arguing that H egel already discovered the L acanian
understanding that all m ental illnesses can be articulated in their structure by their
relative success or failure with respect to the paternal metaphor. I am arguing that
H egel’s requirem ent o f elevating feelings and needs to ‘ideality’ has great sim ilarities
with L acan ’s requirem ent that hum an beings must accept their insertion into the
world o f language or into the sym bolic system. H egel gives us an exam ple of a m en
tally derailed person who was not able to elevate his desire to ‘ideality’; “an English
m an who had hanged him self, on being cut down by his servant n ot only regained the
desire to live but also the disease of avarice; for w hen discharging the servant, he
deducted twopence from his wages because the m an had acted w ithout instructions in
cutting the rope w ith w hich his m aster had h anged h im se lf’ (H egel, Philosophy of
Mind, 134).
28. Spitz acknow ledges his debt to A n n a Freud’s work, The Ego and the Mecha
nisms of Defense, for this idea (Spitz, 4 5 -4 8 ).
29. I will use Spitz’s ideas more abundantly in chapter 5 to clarify the liberating
function o f negation.
30. A uthors other than Spitz have made us aware o f the constitutive function of
aggression in the developm ent of hum an infants. For instance, M elanie Klein makes
the paranoid-schizoid position a necessary phase in the ch ild’s developm ent (H an n a
134 N O T E S T O C H A P T E R TW O
Segal, Klein, 112-21) . W innicott, on the other hand, points to the function of aggres
sion in establishing the trustworthiness o f the caring person. A s m entioned before,
W innicott argues that the experience of on e’s ow n aggression and the experience of
the benign reaction of the m other allows the child to establish that the caring m other
is not subject to the effects o f its own aggression, w hich the child feels to be all-pow
erful. T h e child feels that its aggression is n ot able to destroy the good mother. Su ch
a m other acquires the status o f an independent and thus trustworthy object (i.e., a per
son) (W innicott 1971, 90).
31. T h e im portance o f this idea for the young M oore is obvious since w ithin the
space o f two pages he repeats it several times. Th us, he writes: “I needed to distinguish
my own identity from my father’s so I could live my own life” (M oore 4) and “By
allow ing my grandfather to assum e a role w ithin my conscious identity, I was able to
establish some sense o f identity distinct from my father” (Ibid. 4 - 5 ) and finally “Som e
separation from my father’s identity was necessary for me to be free to lead my own
life” (Ibid. 5).
33. M oore seems to understand that unconscious forces were at work in h is deci
sion to becom e a Jesuit w hen he writes: “W hen I entered the Jesuits, I was twenty-
three years old. O nly years later did I realize that was the same age my father was when
he died” (M oore 3).
34. T h e m etaphorical power hidden in being a Jesuit was insufficient to unify the
life of the young M oore. H e left the Jesuits and spent more than a decade creatin g a
new metaphor. I will analyze that effort in chapter 7.
35. Rorty proposes a sim ilar thesis when she writes: “We certainly think we can
recognize self-deception in others, and we strongly suspect it in ourselves, even retro
spectively attributing it to our past selves” (R orty 22, italics m ine).
36. T h e claim that self-deception and den ial are n ot lies will be further argued
for in chapters 2 and 7.
C H A P T E R T W O . T H E E P IS T E M O L O G IC A L P R O BLEM
O F S E L F - D E S C R I P T I O N IN F R E U D I A N P S Y C H O A N A L Y S I S
C H A P T E R T H R E E . D E N IA L A N D
H E G E L ’S P H IL O S O P H IC A L A N T H R O P O L O G Y
1. For Freud’s claim regarding the universality of den ial to be true, denials must
appear in m any circum stances. R esearch has in fact docum ented denial as an attitude
or as a linguistic expression in terminally ill patients reacting to their im pending
deaths (de H ennezel 1991; M orita et al.; Baider &. Edelstein; Beilin; Strelzer et al.;
C on n or); in cancer patients (W ool; Jelicic et al.; M orita et al.; W eism an); in patients
w ith Alzheim ers disease (W einstein et al.; Sevush & L eve); in patients w ith m ultiple
sclerosis (Finger); in patients with a heart disease such as m yocardinal infarction
(Fukiniski et al.; Pruneti et a l ) , or angina pectoris (Levenson et al.) and in candidates
for heart transplants (Young et al.); in patients w ith disabling diseases (Stew art); in
persons w ith eating disorders (Jackson & D avidson; Vitousek et al.); in cases o f trans
plan t failures (Streltzer et al.); in infertility resulting from H odgkin's disease (C elia &
N ajav its); in m others of children and adolescents with m alignant and term inal can
cer (Freitas); in sex offenders (Steven son et al; K ennedy & Grubin; W inn; M arshall)
and in incestuous fam ilies (H oke et al.); in drug and alcohol addiction (K restan &
Bepko; W ing; A m odea & Liftik; Liebeskind; W isem an et a l ; Kearney); in pregnant
m others (V an der H art et al.; M iller; G reen & M anohar; B em s; Finnegan et al.;
M ilden et al.; A tk in s et al.; M oyer &. Levine). W e further have descriptions o f fathers
w hose wives are in the last three m onths o f their first pregnancy who are in denial in
order to deal with their am bivalent feelings (Gerzi et al.); in w hole cultures when they
are dealing w ith a nation al defeat such as the Japanese after W W II (G ran d jean ); in
those dealing with genocide, as was the case with the H olocaust (K lein & Kogan;
D avidson; Solom on ; V idal-N aquet) or the A rm enian genocide (Boyajian & G rigo
rian). T here is thus em pirical evidence for the plausibility of denial being a wide
spread, or perhaps universal, phenom enon. To analyze that claim o f universality is a
philosophical task.
2. Philosophical theories have been helpful for the clarification o f psychody
nam ic processes. Th us, Louis Sass uses W ittgenstein’s criticism o f the solipsist and the
solipsist’s unavoidable contradictions to explain a curious phenom enon observed in
schizophrenics: Th ey experience them selves as the absolute source of their experi
ences, thereby denying the independence o f the world and the existence of other
minds. Th ey sim ultaneously experience their thoughts as being controlled by others,
sim ilar to the solipsist who needs to create another consciousness who can take his
own consciousness as an ob ject so as to give existence to his own ego (S a ss 1994,
6 7 -7 3 ; 5 1 -8 5 ). Jo h n M uller uses Peirce’s sem iotic to dem onstrate the im portance of
sem iotic activity betw een m other and child and the failure o f sem iotic activity in psy
chotics (For an analysis o f M uller’s argum ent see Ver Eecke 1997).
Several authors have used H egel specifically to clarify unconscious processes.
L acan relied on H egel’s Phenomenobgy to construct his mirror stage theory and to cre
ate the logical con n ection betw een the im aginary and aggressivity (For an exposition
o f the H egel-Lacan connection, see Ver Eecke 1983a). O patow uses H egel’s ideas
about the transition from consciousness to self-consciousness to clarify the psychoan
alytic claim that the infant needs to make a transition from h allucinating the world
to accepting reality. From H egel, O patow borrows the idea that consciousness and
self-consciousness are characterized by some form o f negativity. For Opatow, a child
N O T E S T O C H A PT ER TH REE 137
overcom es hallucin ation as a m ethod of creating the world by negating the notion
that, as consciousness, it is tied to this form o f awareness. Instead, reacting to the pain
and displeasure resulting from the lack o f satisfaction provided by hallucination, the
infant has the option to leave h allucin ation behind and accept that, first, there is an
independent reality; and second th at it— the infant— is in need of that independent
reality (O patow 1988, 6 2 2 -2 4 , 626, 6 2 8 -2 9 , 635; 1989, 6 5 1 -5 5 ; 1993, 4 4 3 -4 6 ).
A ndré G reen , in his book The Work of the Negative, devotes a whole chapter to the
fruitfulness of conn ectin g the ideas o f H egel and Freud (G reen 1999, 2 6 -4 9 ). In par
ticular, so G reen argues, both thinkers understand “the work of the negative. (Ibid. 4).
U sin g two previously published articles (G reen 1997; 1998), G reen reinterprets Win-
n ico tt’s ideas about the function o f transitional objects (G reen 1999, 7) and B ion ’s
reflections on the “fundam ental intolerance of frustration” (Ibid. 7 -1 0 ). H e sees in
the work o f these two psychoanalysts a deep understanding of the work o f the n ega
tive. Several reasons justify using H egel to clarify the logical structure o f Freudian
insights. First, there are sim ilarities in H egel’s and Freud’s conception s of m adness
(Berthold-Bond, 2 6 -2 8 , 39,54). Freud o f course provides multiple detailed analyses,
where H egel offers one general on tological structure. But H egel’s general ontological
structure is useful in preventing us from losing sight o f the overall structure o f m ental
illness. A second reason to rely on H egel for insights into psychodynam ic processes is
H egel’s insight into the sim ilarity betw een some o f consciousness’s structures and
madness. Thus, Berthold-Bond poin ts out that, for Hegel, “the healthy mind is still
grappling with the same sorts of contradictions and feelings o f alienation, the same
‘infinite pain ’ . . . w hich characterizes insanity” (Ibid. 3; see also Ibid. 5 1 -5 4 ). A third
reason to consult H egel is to deepen our understanding o f the structure of denial.
Indeed, H egel insists, as Freud does, that both the insane person and the norm al per
son have two psychic centers: the life o f feelings and the life o f rationality (Ibid. 34,
41). H aving two psychic centers in a person is the ontological con dition for the pos
sibility o f a denial. Finally, both H egel and Freud recognize the im portance o f the n eg
ative (stressed by L acan 1988, 5 2 -6 1 ; Hyppolyte 1988, 2 8 9-99; O patow op.cit). O ne
way Freud does so is through his theory of overcom ing hallucination. A n o th er way is
by introducing the con cept of the death drive, H egel stresses the n egative’s im por
tance by m aking the negative the m otor o f his ph ilosophical system and by stressing
negative experiences such as despair, contradiction, and disappointm ent (Berthold-
Bond 4 5 - 4 8 ). A s a denial is— in Freud’s mind— a defective form o f negating, it m ight
clarify m atters to look at H egel’s theory for con ceptual explanations of the expressive
form the negative takes in a denial.
4. Here and throughout this chapter we are using G rene and Lattim ore, 1959.
5. O n e could argue that L acan holds such a view w hen he writes that the
hum an world has an ontological structure sim ilar to that of paranoiac knowledge
(L acan 1977, 2)
pid painting. In this conversation these two persons discover that looking more
closely does not lead to agreem ent. T h e ob ject is not w hat divides these two persons.
It is the way they perceive the object. T h us, both people becom e aware of being dif
ferent from the other. Th ey becom e self-aware.
7. D ouglass describes his w illingness to face death and to fight Mr. Covey, the
slave breaker, as the turning poin t in his life as a slave: “Mr. C ovey entered the stable
w ith a long rope; and just as I was h alf out o f the loft, he caught hold o f my legs, and
was about tying me. . . . I resolved to fight; and, suiting my action to the resolution, I
seized C ovey hard by the throat; and as I did so, I rose. He held on to me, and I to
him . M y resistance was so entirely unexpected, that C ovey seem ed taken all aback.
He trem bled like a leaf. T h is gave me assurance, and I h eld him uneasy, causing the
blood to run where I touched with the ends o f my fingers. . . . H e asked me if I m eant
to persist in my resistance. I told him 1 did, com e what m ight; that he had used me
like a brute for six m onths, and that I was determ ined to be used so no lo n g e r.. . . This
battle with Mr. C ovey was the turning-point in my career as a slave. It rekindled the
few expiring embers of freedom, and revived w ithin me a sense o f my own m anhood.
It recalled the departed self-confidence, and inspired me again w ith a determ ination
to be free. . . . It was a glorious resurrection, from the tom b of slavery, to the heaven
o f freedom. My long-crushed spirit rose, cow ardice departed, bold defiance took its
place; and I now resolved that, however long I m ight rem ain a slave in form, the day
had passed forever when I could be a slave in fact. I did n ot hesitate to let it be known
o f me, that the white m an who expected to succeed in whipping, must also succeed in
killing me” (D ouglass 7 9 -8 1 ).
8. W hen deliberating as to w hether they would try to escape, Frederick D ou
glass and his com panions saw the alternative. Som e chose to risk death. O n e at least
is reported to have feared death too m uch to risk freedom: “Here were the difficulties,
real or im agined— the good to be sought, and the evil to be shunned. O n the one
hand, there stood slavery, a stern reality, glaring frightfully upon us,— its robes already
crim soned with the blood o f m illions, and even now feasting itself greedily upon our
own flesh. O n the other hand, away back in the dim distance, under the flickering
light of the north star, behind some craggy hill or snow-covered m ountain, stood a
doubtful freedom— h alf frozen— beckoning us to com e and share its hospitality. T h is
in itself was som etim es enough to stagger us; but when we perm itted ourselves to sur
vey the road, we were frequently appalled. U p on either side we saw grim death, assum
ing the m ost horrid shapes. N ow it was starvation, carving us to eat our own flesh;—
now we were contending with the waves, and were drowned;— now we were
overtaken, and torn to pieces by the fangs of the terrible bloodhound. . . . W ith us it
was a doubtful liberty at most, and alm ost certain death if we failed. For my part, I
should prefer death to hopeless bondage. Sandy, one of our number, gave up the
notion, but still encouraged us” (D ouglass 9 0 -9 1 ).
9. In the Narrative of the Life of Fredrick Douglass we find a beautiful description
of how far the slaveholder will go in order to enforce his right to give orders and to
m ake his slaves obey. “Very near Mr. Freeland lived the Rev. D aniel W eeden, and in
the same neighborhood lived the Rev. Rigby H opkins. T h ese were m embers and m in
isters in the Reform ed M ethodist C hurch. Mr. W eeden owned, am ong others, a
w om an slave, whose nam e I have forgotten. T h is w om an’s back, for weeks, was kept
N O T E S T O C H A PT ER TH REE 139
literally raw, made so by the lash o f this m erciless, religious wretch. He used to hire
hands. H is m axim was, behave well or behave ill, it is the duty o f a m aster occasion
ally to whip a slave, to rem ind him o f his m aster’s authority. Su ch was his theory, and
such his practice. Mr. H opkins was even worse than Mr. W eeden. H is ch ief boast was
his ability to m anage slaves. T h e peculiar feature of his governm ent was that o f w hip
ping slaves in advance o f deserving it. H e always m anaged to have one or more o f his
slaves to whip every M onday morning. H e did this to alarm their fears, and strike ter
ror into those who escaped. H is plan was to whip for the sm allest offences, to prevent
the com m ission o f large ones. Mr. H opkins could always find some excuse for w hip
ping a slave. It would astonish one, unaccustom ed to a slaveholding life, to see with
what wonderful ease a slaveholder can find things, of w hich to make occasion to whip
a slave. A mere look, a word, or m otion,— a m istake, accident, or w ant o f power,— are
all m atters for which a slave may be whipped at any time. Does a slave look dissatis
fied? It is said, he has the devil in him , and it must be whipped out. Does he speak
loudly when spoken to by his master? T h e n he is getting high-m inded, and should be
taken down a button-hole lower. D oes he forget to pull off his h at at the approach of
a white person? T h en he is w anting in reverence, and should be w hipped for it. Does
he venture to vindicate his conduct w hen censured for it? T h en he is guilty o f im pu
dence,— one o f the greatest crim es o f w hich a slave can be guilty. D oes he ever v e n
ture to suggest a different m ode o f doing things from that pointed out by his master?
He is indeed presumptuous, and getting above him self; and nothin g less than a flog
ging will do for h im ” (D ouglass 8 5 -8 6 ).
11. In other passages, too, H egel dem onstrates that a hum an being needs another
person to embody a contrary point o f view in order for him or her to discover the full
m eaning o f existence. T h is is beautifully elaborated in at least two other passages:
“T h e Law o f the H eart” and “T h e Beautiful So u l.” (H egel 1966, 3 9 0 -6 0 0 , 6 4 2 -7 9 ).
For K risteva’s rejection o f H egel’s m aster/slave paradigm and its use of binary opposi
tion see V an Buren, 1995.
12. H egel’s con cept of the will is more thoroughly analyzed in chapter 4
13. We find an indirect confirm ation for this H egelian thought in the memoirs
o f Frederick D ouglass when he points out that the life of the m aster shows puzzling
aspects. Slaveholders becom e m onsters (D ouglass 2 2 -2 3 , 27, 3 2 -3 3 , 3 6 -3 8 , 8 5 -8 6 ); a
kind-hearted w oman who marries a slaveholder becom es vicious; religious slave h old
ers turn into hypocrites (D ouglass 65, 8 4 -8 5 ). A H egelian explan ation for these
observations by D ouglass could be: slaveholders lead a life that is not giving them
140 N O T E S TO C H A P T E R TH REE
w hat they had hoped for. H ence, slaveholders becom e hum an m onsters and cann ot
but distort profound truths, including religious truths. L et me quote the description
D ouglass gives o f a decent w om an’s transform ation: “ It was at least necessary for her
to h ave some training in the exercise o f irresponsible power, to make her equal to the
task o f treating me as though I were a brute. My mistress was, as I have said, a kind
and tender-hearted w oman; and in the sim plicity o f her soul she com m enced, when I
first went to live w ith her, to treat me as she supposed one h um an being ought to treat
another. In entering upon the duties of a slaveholder, she did not seem to perceive
that I sustained to her the relation o f a mere chattel, and that for her to treat me as
hum an being was not only wrong, but dangerously so. Slavery proved as injurious to
her as it did to me. W hen I w ent there, she was a pious, warm, and tender-hearted
woman. T h ere was no sorrow or suffering for w hich she did not have a tear. Sh e had
bread for the hungry, clothes for the naked, and com fort for every mourner that cam e
w ithin her reach. Slavery soon proved its ability to divest her o f these heavenly qual
ities. U nder its influence, the tender heart becam e stone, and the lam blike disposition
gave way to one of tiger-like fierceness. T h e first step in her downward course was in
her ceasing to instruct me. Sh e now com m enced to practice her husband’s precepts.
Sh e finally becam e even more violent in her opposition than her husband him self.
Sh e was n ot satisfied with simply doing as well as he had com m anded; she seemed
anxious to do better. N oth in g seemed to make her more angry than to see me with a
newspaper. Sh e seemed to think that here lay the danger. I have had her rush at me
with a face m ade all up of fury, and snatch from me a newspaper, in a m anner that fully
revealed her apprehension. Sh e was an apt w oman; and a little experience soon
dem onstrated, to her satisfaction, that education and slavery were incom patible with
each other” (D ouglass 5 0 -5 1 ).
14. M ich ael R oth wrote a beautiful book Psycho-Analysis as History: Negation
and Freedom in Freud. T h e subtitle m akes it clear th at the book is addressing the
problem atic addressed in this book. O n e, if not the m ost im portant, thesis o f R o th ’s
b ook is closely conn ected to the idea in the text just m entioned by H egel: when
h um an beings discover the truth about them selves it is painful; it involves despair.
T h us, about transference, R oth writes: “N o t th at transference love is in itself a qual
itatively new way o f being: it certainly does n ot m anifest a radically changed way of
life. In fact, it is the very opposite of such a life, since it displays the repetitions,
defenses, and frustrations that characterize the ‘path ological’ facets of ‘n orm al’ liv
ing. It is by being this m anifestation, though, that the transference offers the
analysand the prospects of negation, that is o f freedom through the creative acknow l
edging o f o n e ’s history” (R oth 1987, 26). H e further specifies that im provem ent,
higher freedom , and greater truth dem and the acceptan ce o f sacrifice: “T h e degree of
con tradiction betw een the person ’s desires and the world th at confronts them is the
key to w hether the opportunity for negation found in the transference is to be real
ized. In o ther words, radical activity is initiated as the result o f struggle, and this only
when the person sees that the sacrifice necessary to m ake the radical chan ge is o u t
weighed by the poten tial gratification o f the change” (Ibid. 100). Finally, R oth
m akes a direct com parison betw een H egel and Freud by m eans o f the idea o f pain.
“For H egel, as for Freud, the m ind preserving itself in con tradiction is in pain. T h e
psycho-analytic in vestigation o f the con tradiction o f ‘know ing yet not know ing’ is an
N O T E S T O C H A P T E R TH REE 141
16. T h e proof that the m aster needs to defend a role that H egel has shown to be
false presents us w ith a deduction o f the unavoidability o f self-deception w ithin a
H egelian ph ilosoph ical anthropology. I will prove that denial follow s self-deception.
In a survey article, A gassi dem onstrates that classical rationalism also unavoidably
leads to self-deception. C lassical ration alism rejected the idea, com ing out of various
religious traditions, that self-deception is unavoidable, and th at therefore tradition
and authority are necessary as guides to a good life. Rather, classical rationalism
argues that self-deception should be avoided and can be avoided if one is self-reliant.
Su ch self-reliance requires n ot acceptin g any proposition except those proven by the
facts as they show them selves to a m ind w ithout preconceptions. For B acon, the
father o f classical rationalism , this m eant that science rests on “the rejection o f all
preconceived opinion s and [that] the accum u lation o f a vast collection o f item s of
factual inform ation [would] lead rapidly to the full grow th o f theoretical scien ce”
(A gassi 3 5 ). A gassi then points out th at belief in such a view is a self-deception for
two reasons. First, scientific theory requires the form ulation o f hypotheses for the
developm ent o f theories. Secon d, the G od el theorem dem onstrates th at “all effective
proof procedures are lim ited” (Ibid. 4 1 ). T h us, classical rationalism , w hich rejected
the religious idea that h um an beings are subject to self-deception, shows itself to be
a self-deception. A gassi thus dem onstrates ph ilosoph ically th at self-deception is
unavoidable, even outside a H egelian anthropology. T h e argum ent for self-deception
derived from H egel therefore seems to h ave broad general validity. We need to keep
in m ind, though, th at den ial is more than just self-deception. It is a form o f self
deception that also reveals truth.
17. Psychologists also provide us w ith such exam ples. In one case they use a co n
ceptualization close to my own to report their findings. Th ey com pare perceived risk
for con tractin g a sexually transm itted disease or becom ing pregnant with reported sex
ual behavior and divide the group into people with realistic low risk, realistic high
risk, and illusionary low risk. T h is latter group tended to avoid exposure to risk infor
m ation, deny its relevance, and experienced no increase in negative em otions when
facing contraceptive inform ation. T h e authors interpret such denial as “ego-protec
tive” (W iebe & Black).
142 N O T E S TO C H A P T E R FO UR
C H A P T E R F O U R . D E N IA L A N D
H E G E L ’ S T H E O R Y O F T H E W IL L
1. References to the Philosophy of Right will alm ost always be by numbered para
graphs (H egel 1967b; or H egel 1991).
2. I will make use o f H egel in a different way than the four authors referenced
in chapter 3. Berthold-Bond emphasizes that H egel’s theory o f consciousness has a
sim ilar structure to his theory o f mad consciousness. R ather than arguing that sim i
larity, I will presuppose such a sim ilarity and search for an explanation o f the ph e
nom enon o f denial by understanding it as a deficient solution to structural challenges
to the hum an will as articulated by H egel. Hyppolyte concentrates on overcom ing a
denial and uses H egel’s con cept o f “aufheben ” (to deny, to suppress, and to conserve)
(Hyppolyte 1988, 291) in order to clarify the process of overcom ing a denial and to
stress the presence o f negation in “the fundam ental attitude o f symbolicity rendered
explicit” (Ibid. 296). I will not concentrate, in this chapter, on explaining the over
com ing o f negation. Rather, I will try to understand why a denial itself is created.
L acan and O patow focus on the distin ction betw een perception and hallucin ation
and the function o f negativity in the em ergence o f one or the other. For Opatow, per
ception requires the force of the negative capable of rejecting h allucination (see foot
note 1 in chapter 3 ). For Lacan, adult hallucination results from a different form of
n egativity than negation and denial. It involves a rejection o f the sym bolic system
(L acan 1988, 58). M y reflections concern the function of the negative after h alluci
n ation has been overcom e and after the symbolic system has been accepted. I w ant to
clarify the difficulties faced by a person who utters a denial because he is already able
to face the reality or is already w illing to accept the sym bolic system. I further want
to clarify the deficiencies in the way such a person confronts these difficulties.
3. O ne can find a brief com m entary on these three paragraphs using H egel’s
concepts of universality, particularity, and individuality in W estphal 1992, 5 -7 . For a
book-length com m entary on the Preface of the Philosophy of Right see Peperzak 1987.
T h ere are a num ber o f useful publications on H egel’s concept of freedom or the im pli
cations of his con cept o f freedom for his views on property, morality, and different eth
ical institutions: A n g eh m 1977; Avineri 1972; C h am ley 1963; C ullen 1979; D enis
1984; D ubouchet 1995; Fleischm ann 1964; H arada 1989; H ardim on 1994; H enrich &
H orstm ann 1982; Jarczyk &. Labarrière 1986; Jerm ann 1987; Kainz 1974: Kraus
1931/1932; Lucas & Pôggeler 1986; Lukács 1973; M aker 1987; M arx 1977; Pelczynski
1984; Reyburn 1967; R iedel 1974; R oth 1989; Seeberger 1961; Sm ith 1989; S te in
berger 1988; W aszek 1988; W estphal 1992; W hitebook 1977; W infield 1988; W in
field 1990; W ood 1990.
4. I am aware that some excellent H egel scholars reject the idea th at H egel’s
thought can be m olded in a thesis-antithesis-synthesis schem a. Thus, A llen W ood
writes: “Som e of those who discourse on H egel w ith the greatest soph istication know
him only through warped, inaccurate or bowdlerized second-hand accounts (for
instance, accounts o f the H egelian dialectic as ‘thesis-antithesis-synthesis’” (H egel
1991, xxvii) or “T h is particular triadic piece of jargon was actually used by both Fichte
and Sch ellin g (each for his ow n purposes), but to my knowledge it was never used, not
even once, by H egel. We owe this way of presenting the H egelian dialectic to H ein
N O T E S T O C H A PT ER FO UR 143
6 . H egel defends a sim ilar idea in his Phenomenology when he defines self-con
sciousness as: “prim arily simple existence for self, self-identity by exclusion of every
other from itself. It takes its essential nature and absolute object to be Ego; and in this
immediacy, in this bare fact o f its self-existence, it is individual. T h a t w hich for it is
other stands as unessential object, as object w ith the impress and character o f n ega
tion ” (H egel 1 9 6 7 ,2 3 1 ).
7. T h e full text o f the paragraph reads: “ (P) A t the same time, the ego is also
the transition from undifferentiated indeterm inacy to differentiation, determ ination,
and positing o f a determ inacy as a con ten t and object. N ow further, this con tent may
either be given by nature or engendered by the con cept o f mind. Through this posit
ing o f itself as som ething determ inate, the ego steps in principle into determ inate exis
tence. T h is is the absolute m om ent, the finitude or particularization o f the ego.”
8 . A gain , H egel m akes a sim ilar claim in his Phenomenology w hen he argues that
life is essential for the life o f self-consciousness. Self-consciousness discovers that in
the fear o f death. H egel writes it this way:”In this experience [the life-and-death strug
gle w hich produces fear o f death] self-consciousness becom es aware that life is as
essential to it as pure self-consciousness. In im m ediate self-consciousness the simple
ego is absolute object, which, however, is for us or in itself absolute m ediation, and
h as as its essential m om ent substantial and solid independence” (H egel 1967, 234).
9. T h e full text of this paragraph reads: “ (y) T h e will is the unity of b oth these
mom ents. It is particularity reflected into itself and so brought back to universality, i.e.
it is individuality. It is the self-determ ination o f the ego, w hich m eans that at one and
the same time the ego posits itself as its own negative, i.e. as restricted and determ i
nate, and yet rem ains by itself, i.e. in its self-identity and universality. It determ ines
itself yet at the same time binds itself together w ith itself. T h e ego determ ines itself
144 N O T E S T O C H A P T E R FO UR
14. Ethical life in turn has three subdivisions which correspond to the three sub
divisions o f the third syllogism: the syllogism of necessity. T h e state is the third form of
ethical life and thus corresponds to the third and last form o f the syllogism of necessity:
the disjunctive syllogism. H egel’s m ethod is such that every level of the dialectic pre
pares the n ext step or that the n ext step relates to the problem s o f the previous step.
Th us, the analysis of the disjunctive syllogism ends with the concept “objectivity”
N O T E S T O C H A PT ER FIVE 145
(H egel 1989, 704), w hich is the topic of analysis in the n ext section o f H egel’s Logic,
whose first chapter is “M echanism .” Richardson uses this consideration for his m apping
o f the Logic on to the Phibsophy of Right (Richardson 1989, 65), which includes the
state relating to both the disjunctive syllogism o f necessity and m echanism .
C H A P T E R F IV E . A C H I L D ’S N O -S A Y IN G :
A S T E P T O W A R D IN D E P E N D E N C E
2. Th us, the absence o f eight-m onth-anxiety would not by itself justify the pre
diction o f a later deficiency in interpersonal relations, because eight-m onth-anxiety is
an organizer in the weak sense. T h e absence of no-saying would justify the prediction
o f later em otional deficiencies, because no-saying is, in my theory, an organizer in the
strong sense.
3. In the first part of the chapter I will refer to the child as she and in the sec
ond part as he. However, for the purpose of the argum ent, sexual difference can be
overlooked. I am simply follow ing recom m endations for gender neutral description.
4. It is worthwhile to look at the two figures m entioned in the quotation, pp. 146
and 147.
8 . In philosophical language, one can call a weak organizer a sufficient con di
tion for the presence o f a new and higher function in the child. It is n ot a necessary
condition, however. O n the contrary, a strong organizer is both a sufficient and a n ec
essary condition for the new and higher function.
10. T h e three publications and the relevant quotation s are: “However, w hen a
stranger approaches the eight-m onth-old, he is disappointed in his wish to have his
mother. T h e anxiety he displays [. . .] is a response to his perception that the
stranger’s face is n ot identical w ith the m emory traces o f the m other’s face” (Spitz
1965, 155). “ In psychoanalytic terms we say: this is a response to the intrapsychic
perception o f the reactivated wishful tension and the ensuing disappoin tm en t” (Ibid.
1 5 5 -5 6 ). A lso, “T h e realization that it can n ot be rediscovered in the given instance
provokes a response of unpleasure. In terms o f the eight-m onth anxiety, w hat we
observe can be understood as follows: the stran ger’s face is com pared to the memory
traces of the m other’s face and found w anting. T h is is not mother, she is still lost.
U npleasure is experienced and m anifested” (Spitz 1957, 55). A n d third, “W hen a
stranger approaches an infant, then the infant finds itself disappointed in its desire
to see again the mother. A n d thus the anxiety w hich the infant m anifests is not a
reaction to a perception w hich revives a memory o f a painful experience w ith the
stranger. T h e infant is concerned w ith the n on iden tity o f the stranger w ith the
mother, w hich the infant misses. H ence, we are here in the presence o f a response to
an intra-psychic perception, o f a reactivation o f a desire” (Spitz 1963, 155 [transla
tion m ine]).
11. Elsewhere, I form ulate the new problem faced by the eight-m onth-old child
as one of living with the body that he has appropriated. T h a t body has an interiority
and an exteriority. T h e child has the task of unifying those two aspects. Seein g seems
to be the privileged sense w ith w hich to do so. But hearing and touching might be
able to do so too. A s these three senses synthesize the interiority and the exteriority
of the body in different ways one could predict that persons who lack one of these
senses will literally have to live with another body in as m uch as the lived body is not
the physical body but the body as synthesized and as psychologically appropriated.
Th us, children born blind or deaf can be expected to relate differently to their bodies.
A n d indeed, deaf persons show a higher incidence of paranoic characteristics (Ver
Eecke 1984, 61ff).
12. It is im portant to reflect on the relation betw een an indicator and an organizer
and to keep in m ind the distinction betw een a weak and a strong organizer.
For Spitz, the eight-m onth-anxiety is both an indicator and an organizer. First,
the eight-m onth-anxiety is an indicator o f a higher psychic structure because it indi
cates that the child has created libidinal ob ject relations (she differentiates betw een
the mother and a stranger), that she has the capability of experiencing a new affect
N O T E S T O C H A PT ER FIVE 147
(anxiety), and that she has achieved a higher integration o f the ego (she can make
judgm ents about the external world and take, if she so decides, defensive m easures).
T h e eight-m onth-anxiety is also an organizer of developments in several areas. T h e
eight-m onth-anxiety requires a psychic developm ent w hich permits the child to dis
charge affective tensions in an intentional, directed, and volitional manner. T h e child
must also possess a m ental apparatus in w hich a number of memory traces can be
stored such that she can distinguish betw een m other and stranger. Finally, m any o f the
child’s psychic and m ental achievem ents require a som atic developm ent w hich
includes myelinization o f the neural pathways such that the diacritic function o f the
sensory apparatus and the control of groups of skeletal muscles w hich perm it directed
action are possible.
A n achievem ent in a critical period does not just organize developm ents o f the
past, it also m akes the child ready for new achievem ents. A n xiety induced by the pres
ence o f a stranger dem onstrates that the child has endowed the fam iliar person (the
mother) with unique object attributes (Spitz 1957, 161-62). T h is allows the child to
establish a kind o f secure and exclusive relation w ith the mother. A ccordin g to Spitz,
this process requires differentiation and integration or a fusion o f aggressive and libid
inal drives. Seen in this way, the anxiety at eight m onths is an indicator of a highly
com plex em otional process that leads to the creation o f a love object. T h is in turn,
Spitz claim s, will perm it the developm ent o f identification as a defense m echanism .
M ore precisely: the eight-m onth-anxiety can be seen as the organizer of a future
achievem ent: identification.
But as the eight-m onth-anxiety does n ot by itself create future achievem ent, but
only points to the presence o f the necessary preconditions for that achievem ent, it is
evident that one can call the eight-m onth-anxiety an organizer only in the weak sense
o f the term as defined above.
13. A som ew hat longer summary o f the developm ent o f L acan ’s thought can be
found in Jo h n P. M uller and W illiam J. R ichardson, Lacan and Language, 1-25.
14. By the concept o f intrusion com plex L acan refers to the fact that siblings
have difficulty tolerating other siblings. Lacan interprets sibling rivalry as a defensive
reaction of one sibling to another sibling who is experienced as intruding into the cozy
relation he or she has with the m other figure.
15. T h e difference betw een the drive m odel and the ob ject relations m odel is the
m ain concern o f Jay R. G reenberg and Stephen A . M itchell in their superb book,
Object Relations in Psychoanalytic Theory. O n e can find references to their summaries
on the mother-child relationship in various psychoanalytic theories by looking in the
index under the concepts: attachm ent; deprivation, m aternal; mother; m othering;
symbiosis; separation-individuation.
16. L acan ’s theory o f the function o f vision will allow me to explain eight-
m onth-anxiety in a more satisfactory way. O f course, that makes my explanation
dependent upon the validity o f L acan ’s theory. However, I will introduce a correction
to L acan ’s theory w hich should make my explan ation not totally dependent upon
Lacan. T h e correction I will introduce is that the child, in my reading, needs to appro
priate his body as a totality. To use other language, one could say that the child needs
to conquer his body by the construction o f a body image. Seein g is an im portant sense
148 N O T E S T O C H A P T E R FIVE
for such an image construction, but other senses can make a contribution too. W hen
seeing is not available, as in children born blind, other senses can be thought o f as
capable of replacing the function o f seeing to some extent. It is my hypothesis that the
final result for the child will be different if he constructed his body image m ainly by
the sense o f seeing, or used other senses as well, or constructed his body image by
senses other than seeing. M y hypothesis would find a tentative confirm ation in the
fact that d eaf mutes tend statistically to have more paranoiac traits than the average
population. My theory would also possibly provide a theoretical framework to think
about the fact that hyperactive children interact more physically w ith people than the
average child and thus must use the sense o f touch more than other children, even for
the construction o f their own body image.
18. Specialists in child language distinguish betw een two forms o f using “n o” :
rejection and denial. R ejection refers to what we have called refusal. “N o ” as denial is
the intellectual activity o f disagreeing w ith the truth of a statem ent: “ Is this a picture
o f a dog?” “N o , it is a picture of a c a t” (H um m er et al. 607). Specialists in child lan
guage observe that the capability to perform the rejection or refusal “n o” emerges first.
A t least one group o f authors argues for the so-called continuity thesis such that cap a
bility for using the denial “no” both benefits and depends upon the capability for using
the rejection “no” (Ibid. 616). A s a consequence, the child is better positioned to
learn to correctly use the pair yes/no than to use the pair m ore/less or the pair
before/after, and so on (Ibid. 608). Th us, one can claim that, for correctly using pairs
o f opposite terms, the child is initially helped by the em otional developm ent which
allowed him to use the refusal “no.” T h e linguistic spill-over effects of the acquisition
o f “n o” m ight therefore be greater than Spitz expected. It lays the groundwork for
intellectually understanding opposite terms just as it also lays the groundwork for the
N O T E S T O C H A PT ER FIVE 149
In my view, the ch ild’s em otional relations to others are crucial for accepting his
body around the age o f the mirror stage (about six m onths). It is an age that is
included in the ages of the children studied by Spitz in his study on hospitalism .
22. A n exam ple (Ver Eecke 1984, 7 9 -8 0 ) will be summarized in the n ext page.
23. T h is happy form ula was coined after reading M uller and R ichardson ’s sum
mary statem en t about the function of language (1982, 9ff).
24- E va Brann stresses several o f the ideas developed above w hen she writes: “But
meanw hile, in the terrible twos, there is also the no that is a mere m anifesto o f inde
pendence. It shows a cleavage in the child’s ego, for while the child is saying no, it is,
as was observed, often doing w hat the adult dem ands. T h e naysaying does n ot con
cern the objective issue but the ow nership o f the will: 'I have a will of my own and
even when it is the same as yours, it is different because it is won. I am doing this
because I w ant it and I am not doing w hat you w ant’” (B ran n 13).
25. For a more com plete treatm ent o f the problem see Ver Eecke 1984.
26. T h e parallelism betw een H egel and Freud m ight seem surprising at first.
However, H egel, as m uch as Freud and m uch more than, for instance, K ant, insisted
on the fact that desires, wishes, and even vices are forces contributing to hum an
action. In his theory o f morality, H egel will n ot insist on obedience to a universal law
as K an t did, but to the need for m utual forgiving betw een h um an beings. Freud too is
m odest with reference to the m oral dem ands he makes o f h um an beings. Th us, Freud
wrote in a letter to Putnam : “ It is therefore more hum ane to establish this principle:
‘Be as m oral as you can honestly be and do not strive for an ethical perfection for
w hich you are not destined’” (H ale 1971a, 122).
C H A P T E R S IX . O E D IP U S , T H E K IN G :
H O W A N D H O W N O T T O U N D O A D E N IA L
1. T h e translated verses throughout this chapter are from G ren e and Lattim ore
1959.
2. Telling the truth, like w arning people about preventable disasters, is often
met, not with gratitude, but w ith irritation or denial. Thus, a study, dealing with the
problem o f how to overcom e denial and n egation o f death, explicitly argues that one
must avoid taking an opposite attitude as Teiresias did (de H ennezel 1989). A noth er
author shows how argum ents betw een a helper and a denier (called a ”help ee” ) trans
form an intrapersonal struggle of denial into an interpersonal one of accusation and
rejection. T h is happens because the denier is pushed by the helper to face frightening
facts; the denier then defends herself against the threatening facts by denying them.
T h e helper robs the denier o f this defense. W h at a helper should do is provide support
so that the denier can slowly learn to face frightening facts (Kearney 1996, 9 -1 0 ). T h e
helper should join the denier “ (client) w ithin the wall o f den ial" (Ibid. 114 ff). In
short, the failure o f Teiresias w as his inability to understand th at “denial does not yield
to truth; it is a protection against it” (Ibid.).
3. M arie Kurrik prefers to underline a different role played by Jocasta. Sh e lets
the queen be the voice of w arning that a tragic hero cann ot listen to (Kurrik 1979,
N O T E S TO C H A PT ER SIX 151
243). Sh e then also describes the cruel self-punishm ent o f O edipus as an act of free
dom (Ibid. 2 5 9 -6 0 ).
4. O n e might say that O edipus repressed nothing, but simply did not know the
real m eaning of certain events. (For exam ple, he knew he com m itted a murder, but he
did not know the identity of the victim .) T h is observation could then support the
claim that w hat was needed was not “ the return o f the repressed” but a “revelation of
the truth.” I prefer to m ain tain my usage o f the idea o f repression and to counter this
objection by referring to the definition o f ‘repression’ in Je a n Laplanche and J.B. Pon-
talis 1973, 2. T h e authors claim that repression can be considered a universal ph e
nom enon in so far as it constitutes the unconscious as a dom ain that is separated from
consciousness, and that am nesia is to be understood as the result o f “the incapability
to register m eaningfully certain experiences.” U n doin g repression and am nesia would
therefore always involve an effort of interpretation in the sense o f a search for the
“real m eaning” o f past events. A ccordin g to psychoanalytic theory, the therapist is the
person who must present possible interpretative schem as and fulfill the role of revealer
o f truth. Th us, the con cept of repression still allows for “revelation o f truth.” I am
grateful to Dr. Jam es T h om asson for h aving brought this ob jection to my attention,
and for the reference to Kierkegaard (see note 7).
6 . Rem em ber the stage instructions at the beginning o f the play: “Oedipus
com es forward, m ajestic but for a telltale limp, and slowly views the condition of his peo-
pie” (em phasis m ine).
7. T here is a succinct way to form ulate this difference w ithin a L acan ian fram e
work. In order to help som eone else— for exam ple, a patient in analysis— it is n ec
essary to allow imaginary projection prior to introducing a discordant elem ent. Fur
thermore, the discordant remark must be introduced in such a way as not to
com pletely break the imaginary relationship. Jocasta, the messenger, and the shepherd
perm itted O edipus’s imaginary identification. Teiresias makes such identification
impossible (Sch em a L in L acan 1977). A non-L acan ian analyst, D orpat, h as described
two o f his interventions w hich illustrate the difference. H is first intervention was a
failure. T h e patien t threatened to stop psychotherapy in order to go to an alcohol
counselor. Dorpat, just as Teiresias, lectured his dialogue partner. H e lectured his
patien t “about the differences betw een psychoanalytic psychotherapy and alcoholism
counseling” (D orpat 1985, 232). D orpat confessed that he acted out. A n d indeed, in
the n ext session the patien t said: “you really did m anipulate me last time by the way
you talked to me about psychotherapy” (Ibid.). W ith anoth er patient, D orpat inter
vened successfully. T h e patient presented herself as helpless and asked D orpat what
she should do about her infant son: Sh ould she give up work in order to stay at hom e
with her infant or not? D orpat answered: “You are turning over to me your own abil
ities for thinking and deciding” (Ibid. 233). T h e patient answered that, as a child, she
felt that she only received attention w hen she presented a problem . H er father then
eagerly gave her advice. A fter the intervention,’’T h e patien t was relieved and grati
152 N O T E S T O C H A P T E R SIX
fied that she could use her own mind in her relations with [Dorpat] and that she did
not have to turn over the ‘good’ parts o f herself to [Dorpat] (Ibid. 233). D orpat here
did n ot position him self as opposed to the patient. Rather, he provided the patient
w ith words by w hich the patien t could redescribe to herself her own situation. Sh e
thus was given the m eans to recreate herself.
Sim ilar ideas are found in the psychological literature when addressing the ques
tion o f how to help people in denial. T h e idea that people in denial must first be allowed
imaginary identification with the interlocutor is formulated by several authors. Indeed,
we find arguments to the effect that the interlocutor should avoid adopting an attitude
opposite to that of the patient (de Hennezel 1989)— as Teiresias did; or that approaches
other than direct confrontation are needed (Forchuk & W estwell); or that a degree of
nurturance is required that creates a safe and accepting environm ent in the therapeutic
relationship (Laflen & Sturm ); or that acceptance in group therapy decreases denial
because it allows identification (Rugel & Barry); or that avoidance of rejection and
assurance o f continued support and help improves the process of overcom ing denial
(M arshall); or that em pathic understanding and a noncondem natory attitude are cru
cial for m oving from denial to acknowledgment o f the denied facts (G eller et al.).
Finally, in reviewing three m ethods for overcom ing denial, Kearney stresses that in each
method a positive clim ate has to be created. Thus, he writes that, when using the
method of “Bursting the Bubble,” “Participants must be willing and able to state their
affection for the abuser” (Kearney 1996, 119); when using the method of “Peeling the
D enial O n ion ,” “a relationship with the user behind the wall of denial” (Ibid.) needs to
be established which can become “a force of growth from w ithin” (Ibid.). Kearney calls
his third m ethod for overcom ing denial E N U F: “Empathizing N on-judgm entally and
Unconditionally, and Focusing on feelings” (Ibid. 155).
Current authors are also aware that the interlocutor must not collude with
denials and that the introduction o f a discordant note is unavoidable. Identification
and sympathy should therefore, not be the last step in o n e ’s relationship w ith deniers.
Som e argue that the underlying problem should be nam ed (Berenson & Sch rier);
another author argues that the severity of the underlying problem should not be m in
imized; rather, in the case of patients denying death, the caregivers should acknow l
edge the patien t’s situation and the tragic violence of death (de Hennezel 1989). In
the three m ethods surveyed to deal w ith denial, Kearney argues that the patient
should be confronted either forcefully (bursting the bubble), step by step (peeling the
onion ), or should be refused the false com fort of merger (Kearney 1996, 1 5 2 -5 3 ). O ne
could argue that Jocasta, the messenger, and the shepherd— by their reluctance to
speak— indirectly acknow ledged the difficulty that O edipus found him self in.
8 . T h e thesis that truth can only be com m unicated indirectly can also be found
in S 0 ren Kierkegaard (1941), particularly in the section “T h eses Possibly or A ctually
A ttributable to Lessing,” 6 7-113.
9. In L acan ian term inology one can say that the positions of Jo casta, the m es
senger, and the shepherd avoid imaginary identification w ith the discourse partner
(L acan 1977, 3 3 2 -3 3 ). A voidance o f im aginary identification with o n e ’s discourse
partner is necessary in order to be helpful to th at partner.
10. T h e therapist is not supposed to talk to the relatives o f the patient to con
firm the truth of the inform ation provided by the patient.
N O T E S T O C H A PT ER SEV EN 153
11. T h e patien t is not supposed to m ake decisions that would fundam entally alter
his/her life.
12. T h e psychoan alyst’s task is to help a p atien t find the truth about him self.
In the dram a o f Oedipus, however, we learn that Jo c asta is more helpful than Teire-
sias in bringing about O edipu s’s true self-know ledge. Sh e is m ore helpful even
though she was deceitful. D oes this suggest th at the psychoanalyst, in order to per
form h is task, m ust be deceitful? T h e answ er seem s to be affirm ative; even the tec h
n ical rules o f the therapeutic discourse suggest this answer. T h e psychoanalyst is for
bidden to gather in form ation about the real-life situation of the patien t. O n e could
argue that such a rule forces the psychoanalyst in to the p osition o f h avin g to do as
if the accou n t given by the patien t ab out his life is true. But actin g as if is the
essence o f deceitfulness.
A more constructive interpretation of the psychoanalyst’s role is that the refusal
to search for inform ation beyond the discourse of the patient is the psychoanalyst’s
expression that he trusts the word o f the patient as a tool towards discovery o f the
truth. Looking for evidence beyond the discourse would indicate that the therapist
does not believe. T h e dram a of O edipus dem onstrates that O edipus h im self must dis
cover the truth about him self. His word must bring it about.
T h is interpretation o f the role o f the psychoanalyst finds confirm ation in another
rule of the therapeutic situation: that is, the psychoanalyst should not confirm the
false beliefs of the patient. Instead, he should respond to the patien t’s story about h im
self by silence or by questions for further interpretation.
T h us we are in the presence of a crucial elem ent in the discovery o f truth about
oneself: it is that one’s own word must be respected as being capable o f finding the
truth about oneself. Sop h ocles gets this idea across by putting into opposition the atti
tudes of Teiresias and Jo casta towards O edipus’s own discourse. In telling the truth,
Teiresias shows disrespect for O edipus’s own search. Jo c asta’s m ethod of encouraging
O edipus to hold to false beliefs is a m ethod w hich repects the capability o f O edipus to
discover the truth about him self. In hindsight— th at is, by means o f a com parison with
psychoanalysis— one can argue that it is not Jo casta’s deceitfulness, but her respect for
the power o f O edipus’s own discourse, that helps O edipus discover the truth about
himself.
C H A P T E R S E V E N . D E N IA L , M E T A P H O R ,
T H E S Y M B O L IC , A N D FR E E D O M :
T H E O N T O L O G IC A L D IM E N S IO N S O F D E N IA L
A gassi, J. (1997). Self-D eception: A View from the R ation alist Perspective. In M. S.
M yslobodsky (E d.), The Mythomanias: The Nature of Deception and Self-Deception.
M ahw ah, N J: Law rence Erlbaum A ssociates.
A m adeo, M ., & Liftik, J. (1990). W orking T h rough D enial in A lcoh olism . Families in
Society, 7 1 (3 ), 131-35.
A tkins, E. L., G rim es, J. P., Gregory, W., & Liebm an, J. (1999). D enial of Pregnancy
and N eon aticide D uring A dolescence: Forensic and C lin ical Issues. American
Journal of Forensic Psychology, 17(1), 5-33.
Avineri, S . (1968). The Social and Political Thought of Karl M arx. L ondon and New
York: C am bridge U niversity Press.
Baider, L., & Edelstein, E. (1989). Beyond D enial: R eplacem ent Fantasies in Patients
with L ife-Threatening Illness. In E. Edelstein, D. L. N ath an son & A . M. Ston e
(E ds.), Denial: A Clarification of Concepts and Research. N ew York: Plenum Press.
Baum , A . S., & Burnes, D. W. (1 9 9 3 ). A Nation in Denial: The Truth about Homeless
ness. Boulder, C o : W estview Press.
Benm akhlouf, A . (2001). G . Frege sur la N égation com m e O p position sans Force.
Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale (2), 7-19.
155
156 BIBLIO G RA PH Y
Bowlby, J. (1982). A ttach m en t and Loss: R etrospect and Prospect. American Journal
of Orthopsychiatry, 52, 6 6 4-78.
Brann, E. (2001). The Ways of Naysaying. Lanham : Row m an & Littlefield Publishers.
Brenitz, S. (1988). T h e Seven K inds of D enial. In P. Defares et al. (Eds.), Stress and
Anxiety, Vol. 1 1 . The Series in Clinical and Community Psychology. W ashington,
D .C .: Hem isphere Publishing C orp/ H arper &. Row.
C elia, D. E, & N ajav its, L. (1987). D enial o f Infertility in Patients with H odgkin ’s
Disease. Psychosomatics, 2 7 (1 ), 71.
Cham ley, P. (1963). Economie politique et philosphie chez Steuart et Hegel. Paris: Dalloz.
C h oi, S. ( 1988). T h e Sem an tic D evelopm ent of N egation . Journal of Child Language,
15(3), 5 17-31.
C lose, M. M. (1983). C h ild W elfare and People of C olor: D enial of Equal A ccess.
Social Work Research and Abstracts, 19(4), 13-20.
Connor, S. R. (1988). M easurem ent o f D enial in the Term inally 111: A C ritical
Review. Hospice Journal, 2 (4 ), 5 1-68.
C ullen, B. (1979). Hegel’s Social and Political Thought: A n Introduction. N ew York: St.
M artin’s Press.
D avid-M énard, M. (2001). L a N égation com m e sortie de l’O ntologie. Revue de M éta
physique et de Morale (2 ), 59-67.
D avidson, S. (1989). A voidance and D enial in the Life C ycle o f H olocaust Survivors.
In E. Edelstein, D. L. N ath an son & A . M. Ston e (E ds.), Denial: A Clarification of
Concepts and Research. N ew York: Plenum.
Décarie, T. G ., G oulet, J., Brassard, M. D., &. Shaffran, R. (1974). The Infant’s Reaction
to Strangers (]. D iam anti, Trans.). New York: International U niversities Press.
---------. (1985). Denial and Defense in the Therapeutic Situation. N ew York: A ronson.
Finger, S. (1998). A H appy State o f M ind: A History o f M ild Elation, D enial o f D is
ability, O ptim ism , and Laughing in M ultiple Sclerosis. Archives of Neurology,
5 5 (2 ), 2 4 1-50.
Forchuk, C ., & W estwell, J. (1987). D enial. Journal of Psychosocial and Mental Health
Services, 2 5 (6 ), 9 -1 3 .
Forrester, J. (1980). Language and the Origins of Psychoanalysis. New York: C olum bia
U niversity Press.
Fraiberg, S., & A delson , E. (1973). Self-R epresentation in Language and Play: O b ser
vation s of Blind Children. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 42, 5 3 9-62.
Fukunishi, I., N um atas, Y., & H attori, M . (1994). A lexithym ia and D efense M ech a
nism s in M yocardial Infarction. Psychological Reports, 75(1), 219-23.
Gabbay, D., & M oravsick, J. (1978). N egation and D enial. In F. G uenther & C . R oher
(E ds.), Studies in Formal Semantics, 2 51-65. A m sterdam : N orth H olland.
158 BIBLIO GRAPH Y
---------. (1967). The Phenomenology of Mind (J. B. Baillie, Trans.). N ew York: H arper
Torchbooks.
---------. (1967b ). Hegel’s Phibsophy of Right (T. K nox, Trans.). O xford: O xford U n i
versity Press.
---------. (1971). Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind (W. W allace & A . Miller, Trans.). O xford:
C laren don Press.
BIBLIO G RA PH Y 159
---------. (1971). Philosophy of Mind (T. K nox, Trans.). O xford: O xford U niversity
Press.
---------. (1975). Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art. Vol. I—II (T. K nox, Trans.). O xford:
C larendon Press.
---------. (1989). Hegel’s Science of Logic (A . Miller, Trans.). A tlan tic H ighlands, N J:
H um anities Press International.
---------. (1990). The Phenomenology of Mind [M achine readable version] (]. Baillie,
Trans.). W ashington, D .C .: G eorgetow n University.
---------. (1991). Elements of the Phibsophy of Right (A . W ood, Ed.) (N . N isbet, Trans.).
Cam bridge: Cam bridge U niversity Press.
H ein, K. K., Blair, J. F., Ratzan, S . C ., & Dyson, D. E. (1993). A dolescents and HIV:
Two D ecades o f D enial. In S. C . Ratzan et al. (E ds.), A ID S : Effective Health Com -
munication for the 90s. Philadelphia: Taylor & Francis.
H enrich, D., & H orstm ann, R. (E ds.). (1982). Hegels Philosophie des Rechts: Die The
orie der Rechtsformen und ihre Logik. Stuttgart: K lett-C otta.
Hummer, P., W immer, H ., & A n tes, G . (1993). O n the O rigins o f D enial N egation.
Journal of Child Language, 2 0 (3 ), 6 0 7-18.
Jakobson, R ., & H alle, M . (1956). Two A sp ects o f Language and Two Types o f A p h a
sie D isturbances. In Fundamentals o f Language. T h e Hague: M outon.
160 BIBLIO GRAPH Y
---------. (1988). The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book I: Freud’s Papers on Technique.
1953-1954 (J. Miller, Ed.) (J. Forrester, Trans.). New York: W.W. N orton & C o.
---------. (1993). Seminar III. The Psychoses. N ew York: W.W. N orton & C o.
Lacoue-Labarthe, P., & Nancy, J. L. (1992). The Title of the Letter: A Reading of Lacan
(F. Raffoul & D. Pettigrew, Trans.). N ew York: State U niversity o f N ew York Press.
Laflen, B., & Sturm , W. R. (1994). U nderstanding and W orking with D enial in S e x
ual Offenders. Journal of Child Sexual Abuse, 3 (4 ), 19-36.
Lakoff, G ., & Johnson, M . (1980). The Metaphors We Live By. C h icago: U niversity of
C h icago Press.
---------. (1999). Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind. N ew York: Basic Books.
Levine, J., Rudy, T., & Kerns, R. (1994). A Two Factor M odel o f D enial o f Illness: A
Confirm atory Factor Analysis. Journal of Psychosomatic Research, 3 8 (2 ), 9 9 -110.
Liebeskind, A . S. (1 9 9 1 ). C h em ical D ependency and the D enial o f the N eed for Inti
macy. In A . Sm aldino et al. (E ds.), Psychoanalytic Approaches to Addiction. N ew
York: Brunner/M azel.
Maker, W. (Ed.). (1987). Hegel on Economics and Freedom. M acon: M ercer U niversity
Press.
M annoni, M. (1972). The Backward Child and his Mother (A . M. Sh eridan Sm ith,
Trans.). N ew York: Random House.
M arshall, W. (199 4). Treatm ent Effects on D enial and M inim ization in Incarcerated
S e x Offenders. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 3 2 (5 ), 559-64.
M arx, K. (1977). Critique of Hegel’s Philosphy of Right (J. O ’Malley, Trans.). Cam bridge:
C am bridge U niversity Press.
M atthew s, L. (1 9 3 8 -3 9 ). Visual Stim ulation and O vulation in Pigeons. In Proceedings
of the Royal Society of London, Series B 126, 557-60.
M cLaughlin, B. P., & Rorty, A . O . (Eds.). (1988). Perspectives on Self-Deception. Berke
ley: U niversity o f C alifornia Press.
M ilden, R., R osen th al, M ., W inegardner, ]., & Sm ith, D. (1985). D enial o f Preg
nancy: A n Exploratory Investigation. Journal of Psychosomatic Obstretrics and
Gynecology, 4 (4 ), 255-61.
M iller, L. ]. (1990). Psychotic D enial o f Pregnancy: Phenom enology and C lin ical
M anagem ent. Hospital and Community Psychiatry, 4 1 (1 1 ), 1233-37.
M oeschler, J. (1992). T h e Pragm atic A sp ects o f Linguistic N egation : Speech A ct,
A rgum en tation and Pragm atic Inference. Argumentation, 6 (1 ), 51-76.
M oore, A . (2000). Father, Son, and Healing Ghosts. G ain esville, FI: C en ter for A p p li
cations o f Psychological Type.
M orita, T., Inoue, S., & C h ih ara, S. (1997). D enial o f Term inal Patients with
A d van ced Cancer. Seishin Igaku Clinical Psychiatry, 3 9 (2 ), 173-80.
Pelczynski, Z. (Ed.). (1984). The State & Civil Society. Cam bridge: U niversity of C a m
bridge Press.
---------. (1987). Philosophy and Politics: A Commentary on the Preface to Hegel’s Philos
ophy of Right. D ordrecht: M artinus N ijhoff.
Reyburn, H. A . (1967). The Ethical Theory of Hegel: A Study of the Philosophy of Right.
Oxford: C laren don Press.
Roth, K. (1989). Freiheit und Institutionen in der politischen Philosophie Hegels. Rhein-
felden: Schäuble.
Rugel, R. P., & Barry, D. (1990). O vercom ing D enial through the G roup: A Test of
A cceptan ce Theory. Small Group Research, 2 1 (1 ), 4 5 -5 8 .
Sch m itt, M ., M ontada, L., & Dalbert, C . (1992). Struktur und Funktion der Verant-
wortlichkeitsabwher. Zeitschrift für Differentielle und Diagnostische Psychologie,
12(4), 203-14.
164 BIBLIO G RA PH Y
Seeberger, W. (1961). Hegel oder die Entwicklung des Geistes zur F reiheit. Stuttgart:
Ernst Klett.
Segal, H. (1989). Klein. London: Karnac Books.
Sevush , S., & Leve, N . (1993). D enial o f M em ory D eficit in A lzheim er’s Disease.
American Journal of Psychiatry, 150(5), 748-51.
Sh an an , ]. (1989). T h e Place o f D enial in A d ult D evelopm ent. In E. Edelstein, D. L.
N ath an son & A . M. Son e (E ds.), Denial: A Clarification of Concepts and Research,
107-18. N ew York: Plenum Press.
Sm ith, S. B. (1989). Hegel’s Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context. C h icago: U n iver
sity of C h icago Press.
Solom on, Z. (1995). From D enial to R ecognition: A ttitudes towards H olocaust Sur
vivors from World War II to the Present. Journal of Traumatic Stress, 8 (2 ),
215-28.
Sophocles. (1959). The Complete Greek Tragedies. 4 Volumes (D. G ren e & R. L atti
more, Eds.) (Vol. 1). C h icago: U niversity o f C h icago Press.
Soulez, A . (2001). D e la N égation à la D énégation chez W ittgenstein: U n e Enquête
Lim itée sur la Source de l’A veuglem ent au Sym bolism e. Revue de Métaphysique et
de Morale (2 ), 37-58.
---------. (2001). Présentation. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale (2), 3 -6 .
Stevenson , H . C ., C astillo, E., & Sefarbi, R. (1989). Treatm ent o f D enial in A d oles
cent S e x O ffenders and their Fam ilies. Journal of Offender Counseling Services and
Rehabilitation, 14(1), 3 7 -5 0 .
Stew art, J. R. (1995). D enial o f D isabling C on dition s and Specific Interventions in
the R ehabilitation C oun selin g Setting. Journal of Applied Rehabilitation Counsel-
ing, 2 5 (3 ), 7-15.
Strelzer, J., M oe, M., Yanagida, E., & Siem sen, A . (1984). C op in g with Transplant
Failure: G rie f vs. D enial. International Journal of Psychiatry in Medicine, 13(2),
9 7-106.
Tottie, G . (1982). W here D o N egative Sen ten ces C om e From? Studia Linguistica,
3 6 (1 ), 8 8 -105.
BIBLIO G RA PH Y 165
V an Buren, J. (1995). Postm odernism : Fem inism and the D econstruction of the Fem
inine: Kristeva and Irigaray. American Journal of Psychoanalysis, 5 5 (3 ), 231-43.
Van der H art, O ., Faure, H ., Van G erven, M ., & G oodw in, ]. (1991). U naw areness
and D enial o f Pregnancy in Patients with M PD . Dissociation: Progress in the D is
sociative Disorders, 4 (2 ), 6 5 -7 3 .
Ver Eecke, W. (1975). T h e Look, the Body, and the Other. In D. Ihde and R. M . Zaner
(E ds.), Selected Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy. V ol5: Dialogues
in Existential Philosophy. T h e H ague: Nyhoff.
---------. (1981). Epistem ological C on sequen ces o f Freud’s Theory o f N egation . M an
and World, 14, 111-25.
---------. (1983). H egel as L acan ’s Source for N ecessity in Psychoanalytic Theory. In
Interpreting Iuican. In J. H. Sm ith and W. K errigan (Eds.), 113-38. N ew H aven:
Yale U niversity Press.
---------. (1983). N egation and Desire in Freud and H egel. Owl of Minerva, 15, 11-22.
---------. (1984). Saying 'N o .' Pittsburgh: D uquesne U niversity Press.
---------. (1988). Sayin g ‘N o ’:The Sp ecial Status o f the Word ‘N o .’ Psychanalyse, 5,
94-97.
---------. (1989). Seein g and Saying ‘N o ’ W ithin the T h eories o f Spitz and Lacan. Psy
choanalysis and Contemporary Thought, 12(3), 3 8 3-431.
---------. (1997, Sprin g). Je an C octeau: W ord and Image. In C . A . Tsakiridou (E d.),
Bucknell Review. Vol 41: Reviewing Orpheus: Essays on the Cinema and A rt o f Jean
Cocteau (1, Vol. 41, pp. 5 7 -7 7 ). Lewisburg: Bucknell U niversity Press.
---------. (2001). L acan ’s theory, K aron ’s Psychoanalytic Treatm ent o f Schizophrenics.
Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought, 2 4 (1 ), 79-105.
---------. (2004). O ntology o f D enial. In J. M ills (E d.), Rereading Freud: Psychoanalysis
through Philosophy, 103-25. Albany, NY: State U niversity o f N ew York Press.
V idal-N aquet, P. (1992). Assassins of Memory: Essays on the Denial of the Holocaust (J.
M ehlm an, Trans.). N ew York: C olum bia U niversity Press.
Vitousek, K. B., Daly, J., & Heiser, C . (1991). R econstructing the Internal W orld of
the Eating D isordered Individual: O vercom ing D enial and D istortion in S e lf
report. International Journal of Eating Disorders, 10(6), 6 47-66.
W angh, M. (1989). T h e Evolution o f Psychoanalytic T h ough t on N egation and
D enial. In E. Edelstein, D. L. N ath an son & A . M . Ston e (E ds.), Denial: A C lar
ification of Concepts and Research. N ew York: Plenum.
Waszek, N . (1988). The Scottish Enlightment and Hegel's Account o f "Civil Society.” D or
drecht: Kluwer A cadem ic Publishers.
W estphal, K. (1991, Fall). H egel’s C ritique o f K an t’s M oral W orld View. Philosophical
Topics, 19(2), 133-76.
W estphal, M . (1992). Hegel, Freedom, and Modernity. Albany, NY: State U niversity o f
N ew York.
W hitebook, ]. (19 77). Economics and Ethical Life: A Study of Aristotle and Hegel. A n n
Arbor, M I: U niversity M icrofilms.
W iebe, D., & Black, D. (1997). Illusional Beliefs in the C o n tex t o f Risky Sexual
Behaviors. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 2 7 (1 9 ), 1727-49.
W infield, R. D. (1988). Reason and Justice. Albany, NY: State U niversity of N ew York
Press.
---------. (1990). The Just Economy. N ew York: Routledge.
W ing, D. M. (1995). Transcending A lcoh olic D enial. Image: Journal of Nursing Schol
arship, 2 ( 2 ), 121-26.
W inn, M. E. (1996). T h e Strategic and System atic M an agem en t o f D enial in the
C ogn itive/B eh avioral Treatm ent of Sexu al Offenders. Sexual Abuse: Journal of
Research and Treatment, 8 (1 ), 25-36.
W innicott, D. W. (1971). T h e U se of an O b ject and R elating through Identifications.
In Playing and Reality, 8 6 -9 4 . Lon don and N ew York: Routledge.
W isem an, E. J., Souder, E., & O ’Sullivan , P. (1996). A ge and D enial of A lcoh olism
Severity. Clinical Gerontologist, 17(1), 55-58.
W ood, A . (1990). Hegel's Ethical Thought. Cam bridge: C am bridge U niversity Press.
W ool, M. S. (1986). Extrem e D enial in Breast C an cer Patients and C ap acity for
O b ject Relations. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 4 6 (4 ), 196-204-
W ool, M. S., & G oldberg, R. ]. (1986). A ssesm ent o f D enial in C an cer Patients:
Im plications for Intervention. Journal of Psychosocial Oncology, 4 (3 ), 1-14.
Wurmser, L. (1985). D enial and Sp lit Identity: Tim ely Issues in the Psychoanalytic
Psychotherapy of Com pulsive U sers. Journal of Substance Abuse Treatment, 2 (2),
8 9-96.
---------. (1989). Blinding the Eye of the M ind: D enial, Impulsive A ction , and Split
Identity. In E. Edelstein, D. L. N ath an son & A . M. Ston e (E ds.), Denial: A C lar
ification of Concepts and Research. N ew York: Plenum.
Young, L. D ., Schweiger, J., Beitzinger, J., M cM anus, R. et al. (1991). D enial in H eart
T ransplant C an didates. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 5 5 (2 - 4 ), 141-44.
Author Index
167
168 A U T H O R INDEX
D albert, C ., 163 5 3 ,5 6 ,5 8 , 5 9 ,6 0 , 7 0 ,7 1 ,7 3 , 7 8 ,8 6 ,
Daly, ]., 165 89, 98, 102, 103, 113, 122, 123, 124,
D avid-M énard, M ., 127, 128, 156 127, 128, 129, 130, 131, 132, 133,
D avidson, G . P., 136, 159 135, 136, 137, 140, 141, 149, 150,
D avidson, S., 145, 156 153, 154, 157, 158, 159, 161, 163,
de C h ardin , T h ., 110, 117 165
de H ennezel, M ., 131, 136, 150, 152, Freud, A ., 84, 133
156 Friedland, R.P., 165
de Saussure, F., 74, 156 Fukunishi, I., 157
De W aelhens, A ., 33, 108, 134, 157
D écarie, T. G ., 146, 156 Gabbay, D „ 128, 157
Defares, P., 156 G eller, M ., 131, 152, 158
Delphi, 92 Gerzi, S., 136, 158
D enis, H ., 129, 142, 156 G eurts, B., 128, 158
D eutsch, H ., 128 G ew irth, A ., 62
D evlin, M ., 158 G ôd el, K., 141
D iam anti, ]., 156 Goldberg, R .J ., 131, 166
Dorpat, T. L., 128, 129, 130, 131, 135, G oodw in, J., 165
151, 152, 157 G ou let, ]., 146, 156
Douglass, F., 138, 139, 140, 157 G ranrose, J. T., 144, 157
D ubouchet, P., 56, 157 G reen, A ., 137, 158
G reen, C . M ., 136, 158
Edelstein, E., 136, 154, 156, 157, 160, Greenberg, J. R ., 147, 158
164, 165, 166 Greenw ald, A . G ., 135, 158
Elijah, 117 Gregory, W., 155
Emde, R., 62, 160 G rene, D., 137, 150, 158, 164
Erikson, E., 78 Grigorian, H. M ., 136, 156
Evans, D., 134, 157 Grim es, J. P., 155
Ezekiel, 117 G rubin, D., 131, 136, 160
G uenther, F., 157
Falkenberg, G ., 149, 157 Gussaroff, E., 128, 158
Faure, H., 165
Fenichel, O ., 128 H ale, N . G ., 150, 158
Fichte, J., 142, 158 H alle, M ., 74, 159
Finger, S., 136, 157 H arada, T., 142, 158
Flynn, T., 158 H ardim on, M. D., 142, 158
Forchuk, C ., 152, 157 H arm on, R ., 62, 160
Forrester, J., 157, 159, 161 H attori, M ., 157
Fraiberg, S., 68 , 82, 157 Heaney, S., 110, 117
Frankena, W., 144, 157 H egel, G ., i, iii, vii, ix, 2, 3, 18, 19, 22,
Freedm an, D. G ., 68 3 7 , 3 8 , 4 0 , 4 1 , 4 2 , 4 3 , 4 4 , 4 5 , 4 6 , 47,
Frege, G ., 129, 155 4 8 ,4 9 , 5 0 ,5 1 ,5 2 , 5 3 ,5 4 ,5 5 , 5 6 ,5 7 ,
Freitas, N . K., 136, 157 5 9 ,6 2 , 74, 7 5 ,8 9 , 98, 123, 124, 131,
Freud, S., i, iii, ix, 1, 2, 3, 4, 7, 8 , 9, 10, 133, 134, 136, 137, 139, 140, 141,
11, 12, 13, 14, 15, 16, 17, 18, 19, 20, 142, 143, 144, 145, 148, 150, 155,
2 1 ,2 2 , 2 5 ,2 6 , 27, 28, 29, 3 0 ,3 1 ,3 2 , 156, 157, 158, 159, 160, 161, 162,
33, 34, 35, 36, 37, 39, 40, 43, 45, 46, 163, 164, 165, 166
A U T H O R INDEX 169
abandon, 43, 51, 135 act, 8 , 16, 18, 19, 20, 26, 27, 28, 33, 34,
absence, 33, 63, 69, 78, 82, 86 , 106, 3 5 ,3 6 , 46, 48, 5 0 ,5 1 ,5 2 , 53, 5 7 ,5 8 ,
111, 116, 129, 145, 146 59, 64, 65, 73, 75, 83, 85, 86 , 88 , 92,
absent, 62, 69, 80, 103, 118 96, 106, 122, 123, 128, 129, 130,
absolute, 98, 136, 143 133, 144, 148, 151, 153
abuser, 152 action, xi, 17, 32, 45, 49, 52, 53, 56, 57,
acceded, 87 58, 59, 60, 72, 83, 84, 97, 107, 109,
accept, xi, 2, 3, 10, 12, 13, 14, 15, 16, 110, 112, 114, 115, 117, 120, 128,
1 7 ,2 1 ,3 3 ,4 0 , 4 2 ,4 3 ,4 4 , 4 5 ,4 6 , 49, 138, 147, 149, 150
5 0 , 5 1 ,5 2 , 5 3 ,5 4 , 5 5 ,5 8 , 59, 6 3 ,6 6 , activate, 80, 82
69, 7 3 ,7 8 , 8 6 ,9 1 ,9 2 , 9 3 ,9 6 , 9 7 ,9 9 , active, 16, 40, 65, 75, 79, 80, 82, 91, 95,
102, 103, 105, 108, 110, 117, 121, 96, 101, 135
122, 125, 131, 133, 134, 136, 137, activity, 8 , 9, 10, 15, 33, 40, 42, 45, 61,
142, 149, 150, 152, 154 69, 75, 76, 83, 88 , 110, 115, 130,
acceptance, xi, 2, 13, 14, 43, 51, 59, 86 , 136, 140, 148
92, 94, 131, 140, 152, 153, 154 actors, 123
accom plish, 35, 54, 85 acts, 4, 7 ,8 , 20, 2 2 , 3 3 ,4 1 , 4 6 ,5 2 , 70,
accord, 108, 121 122, 129, 130, 132
accusation, 38, 94, 95, 150 actualize, 41
accuse, 93, 94, 95, 122 adapted, ix
achieve, 2, 14, 30, 35, 50, 51, 59, 68 , addiction, 136
69, 77, 79, 85, 88 , 132, 147 address, 3, 9, 15, 18, 22, 35, 36, 40, 57,
achievem ent, 4, 27, 34, 53, 56, 69, 82, 7 3 ,8 1 ,8 6 , 96, 121, 122, 131, 140,
84, 8 5 ,8 8 , 101, 147 152
acknowledge, 2, 5, 25, 27, 46, 53, 56, 57, adjust, 19, 114
58, 59, 63, 66 , 77, 102, 105, 108, 109, admire, 27, 107, 117, 119
120, 121, 124, 128, 133, 140, 152 adm ission, 9, 27
acknow ledgm ent, 14, 53, 105, 117, 131, adm it, 15, 27, 28
152 adm onish, 110
acquire, 10, 18, 19, 20, 54, 84, 124, 134 adored, 27
acquisition, 3, 16, 18, 19, 61, 64, 82, 84, advice, advise, 26, 63, 117, 151
85, 88 , 124, 128, 132, 148, 149 affect, 66 , 69, 70, 77, 128, 131, 146
173
174 SU B JE C T INDEX
duty, 38, 52, 55, 97, 132, 139 experience, 4, 5, 19, 32, 40, 41, 42, 43,
dyad, 66 , 77, 85 44, 51, 69, 70, 72, 73, 75, 76, 78, 79,
dying, 21 , 104, 108, 118 80, 81, 83, 84, 91, 97, 102, 106, 107,
dynamically, 20 110, 111, 113, 114, 116, 118, 119,
dynam ics, 129 120, 132, 133, 134, 1 3 6 ,1 3 7 , 139,
140, 141, 143, 1 4 6 ,1 4 7 ,1 5 1 , 154
eight (m onths of age), 3, 4, 40, 61, 62, experiential, 66 , 77
63, 64, 67, 68 , 69, 70, 71, 72, 73, 74, expiate, 96
76, 79, 80, 83, 85, 87, 88 , 124, 145, express, 2, 11, 16, 17, 19, 29, 30, 39, 46,
146, 147 5 8 , 6 7 ,8 2 ,8 4 , 86 , 103, 119, 128,
elim inate, 44, 99, 129 129, 134, 149
em bodim ent, 19, 54, 79 expression, 2, 17, 25, 27, 28, 42, 59, 64,
embody, 139 68 , 7 7 ,9 1 , 130, 136, 145, 148, 149,
emerge, 11, 12, 14, 26, 33, 51, 52, 53, 153
6 2 ,6 4 ,8 1 , 9 3 ,9 4 , 9 5 ,9 6 , 123, 124, expressive, 17, 137
148, 149 expulsion, 16, 17, 32
em ergence, 29, 40, 54, 63, 65, 78, 91, exterior, 79
96, 142 exteriority, 79, 146
em ergent, 131 exterm ination, 145
em otion, 8 , 16, 53, 63, 78, 85, 112, 123, external, 15, 16, 19, 31, 36, 40, 41, 83,
141 84, 85, 93, 147
em otional, xi, 4, 8 , 14, 16, 22, 26, 37, externalize, 50
40, 53, 58, 59, 6 0 , 6 1 ,6 3 , 6 4 , 70, 74, extrem ities, 11
7 7 ,7 8 , 84, 86 , 88 , 101, 102, 105, extricate, 83
106, 108, 109, 110, 117, 121, 124, eye, 11, 1 4 ,2 1 ,5 8 , 59, 64, 67, 7 0 ,7 2 ,
1 2 8 ,1 3 1 , 145, 147, 1 4 8 ,1 4 9 , 150 7 7 ,8 1 ,9 6 , 107
em pathic, 152 eyes-forehead, 70
encourage, 137, 138, 153
endanger, 19 face, 9, 1 0 ,1 1 ,2 2 ,3 4 , 48, 6 2 ,6 3 ,6 4 ,
endearm ent, 83 6 5 ,6 6 , 67, 7 0 ,7 1 ,7 2 , 7 3 ,7 4 , 7 7 ,8 1 ,
endowed, 2, 13, 30, 39, 93, 147, 148 86 , 8 7 ,1 2 0 , 123, 1 3 8 ,1 4 0 , 142, 146,
endurance, 45 1 5 0 ,1 5 4
enemy, 70, 115 faced, 13, 52, 53, 131, 142, 146
epistem ic, 149 face-saving, 9, 10
epistem ological, 3, 8 , 12, 15, 18, 22, 26, fail, 3, 18, 19, 28, 3 0 ,7 1 ,8 1 ,9 9 , 110,
3 1 ,3 2 ,3 4 , 59, 60, 123, 124 124, 138
epistemology, 31, 57 failure, 2, 27, 28, 52, 64, 123, 132, 133,
equal, 1 7 ,9 8 , 140 136, 149, 150, 151
erotic, 18, 27 fallaciously, 28
ethical, 25, 54, 55, 57, 142, 144, 150 false, xi, 2, 10, 25, 29, 92, 141, 149, 152,
evisceration, 75 153
exclusion, 51, 143 falsehood, 44, 45
existential, 14, 31, 32, 50, 79 falsely, 10, 59
expect, 2, 14, 49, 5 3 ,6 0 ,6 9 , 1 0 3 ,1 2 2 , falsify, 35, 68 , 95
128, 129, 130, 132, 138, 145, 146, falsity, xi, 11, 45, 99
148, 151 family, v, 49, 54, 109, 112, 113, 136
expectation, 44 fantasized, 21
S U B JE C T INDEX 179
fantasy, 10, 21, 75, 104, 106, 116, 132 for-others, 72, 73, 79
fascinate, 75, 103, 104, 107, 108 fort-da, 33
fatal, 32, 54 for-the-other, 79
father, 4, 5, 8, 20, 21, 22, 23, 26, 27, 29, foundation, 119, 149
38, 39, 55, 82, 86, 87, 92, 93, 95, fraud, 26
101, 102, 103, 104, 105, 106, 107, free, xi, 2 , 3 , 7 , 13, 19, 30, 4 5 ,4 7 ,4 8 ,
108, 109, 110, 111, 112, 113, 114, 51, 52, 54, 56, 58, 89, 95, 103, 106,
115, 116, 117, 118, 119, 120, 121, 109, 117, 120, 134, 138, 141
122, 131, 134, 136, 141, 151, 154 freedom, 2, 3, 7, 13, 19, 22, 28, 30, 39,
fatherhood, 115 4 7 ,4 8 , 5 3 , 5 4 ,5 6 , 5 7 ,5 8 , 5 9 , 6 0 ,6 1 ,
fathering, 4, 104, 115, 122 89, 101, 106, 107, 108, 109, 119,
fatherless, 101, 108, 113 123, 124, 1 3 8 ,1 4 0 , 142, 144, 149,
fear, 11, 21, 40, 41, 44, 51, 53, 64, 66, 151
67, 68, 69, 70, 75, 80, 83, 95, 107, freehand, 26
115, 119, 133, 138, 139, 143, 145, freely, 47, 59
146 friend, 69, 113, 114, 117
fearful, 10 frighten, 11, 12, 92, 138, 150
fecundity, 144 frustration, 19, 20, 83, 84, 108, 137, 140
feel, 8, 11, 1 4 ,5 1 , 7 3 ,8 1 , 104, 107, 110, fulfill, 5 , 4 1 ,4 4 , 49, 5 0 ,5 2 , 5 4 ,5 5 ,7 1 ,
111, 113, 114, 115, 116, 118, 119, 93, 116, 118, 151
121, 122, 133, 134, 135, 137, 139,
143 generate, 80
feeling, 5, 11, 12, 18, 19, 2 0 ,3 1 , 71, 76, genital, 18
81, 105, 108, 109, 116, 118, 119, genocide, 136
121, 134 gift, 52, 102, 105, 113, 114, 116, 118,
Fehlleistung, 26 119, 120, 121
fem ale, 7, 8, 13, 14, 38, 75, 109 giving, 3, 9, 13, 62, 63, 93, 94, 98, 104,
fetish, 129 129, 130, 139
fictitious, 31 goal, 3, 50, 54, 59, 112, 124
fifteen (m onths o f age), 3, 4, 19, 62, 80, gods, 96
83, 84, 85, 87, 124 good, xi, 12, 15, 31, 32, 49, 54, 55, 56,
fight, 41, 138 70, 112, 114, 120, 121, 133, 134,
filial, 111 138, 141, 152
fixation, 33 grandchild, 33
fixed, 19, 25, 44, 98 grandfather, 4, 104, 105, 106, 109, 120,
flesh, 113, 138 121, 134
flight, 93 grandiosity, 4
flogging, 139 gratification, 33, 87, 88, 140
foetalization, 75 gratitude, 114, 150
forbidden, 153 greedily, 138
forclusion, 86 grim, 138
foreclosure, 86 grow, 4, 110, 120, 123
forego, 87 grownup, 103
forever, 138 growth, 22, 68, 81, 120, 141, 152
forget, 28, 45, 91, 92, 93, 94, 96, 97, guilt, 2 2 ,2 9 , 8 5 ,9 6 ,9 7 , 121, 122, 128,
138, 139 134, 135
forgiving, 150 guilty, 115, 139
180 S U B JE C T INDEX
liberate, 113, 116, 133 m eaning, 9, 10, 21, 26, 27, 28, 42, 51,
liberty, 8, 138 54, 62, 64, 76, 84, 86, 91, 93, 97, 98,
libidinal, 18, 32, 33, 36, 64, 69, 83, 84, 99, 115, 116, 123, 125, 127, 128,
85, 146, 147 129, 130, 131, 135, 139, 151
libido, 16, 17, 18, 33, 76 meaningful, 46, 91, 99, 151
lie, 2, 22, 25, 26, 27, 28, 33, 34, 35, 36, m eaningless, 105
40, 77, 97, 121, 123, 134, 135 m ediate, 74, 81
life, 2, 5, 14, 18, 19, 21, 22, 2 6 ,3 1 , 38, m ediation, 143
39, 4 0 ,4 1 ,4 4 , 4 8 ,5 1 ,5 4 , 5 5 ,5 7 ,6 2 , m editation, 108
64, 65, 68, 70, 75, 78, 85, 92, 93, 94, m editative, 110
97, 98, 9 9 ,1 0 2 ,1 0 3 ,1 0 4 , 105, 106, m ental, 1 9 ,3 7 ,6 2 , 76, 132, 133, 137,
107, 108, 110,111, 112, 113, 114, 147
115, 116, 118,119, 120, 121, 122, mentality, 55
125, 128, 131,134, 137, 138, 139, metaphor, 8, 20, 22, 74, 101, 107, 109,
140, 141, 143,144, 153 116, 118, 119, 120, 121, 122, 133,
life-and-death, 143 134
life-giving, 115 metaphoric, 4, 7, 17, 20, 21, 22, 107, 108,
lifeless, 45 117, 118,119, 120, 121, 132,134
life-size, 112 m etapsychological, 8
life-span, 128 metonymy, 74, 101, 110, 111, 112
mind, 2, 8, 9, 10, 14, 15, 16, 54, 94,
man, 2 9 ,5 5 ,9 6 , 105, 113, 114, 115, 137, 140, 141, 143, 146, 148, 152
129, 133, 1 3 8 ,1 4 6 minded, 139, 154
m ankind, 40, 51, 53 m indedness, 154
m arital, 21, 104, 108, 118, 119 minds, 29, 136
marriage, 92 mine, 29, 39, 70, 80, 81, 85, 116, 134,
marry, 29, 48, 92, 95, 139 149, 151
mask, 64 m ineness, 52
master, 2, 33, 37, 41, 42, 43, 44, 45, 46, mirror, 4, 65, 68, 72, 74, 75, 76, 77, 78,
51, 53, 73, 74, 7 9 ,1 3 2 , 133, 139, 141 79, 8 0 , 8 1 ,8 2 , 8 3 ,8 5 , 8 7 ,8 8 , 136,
mastered, 87 145, 148, 150
m astering, 70 mirror-image, 65
m aster-slave, 2, 37, 42, 43, 44, 74 mirror-stage, 4, 74, 78, 83, 85, 88
mastery, 124, 149 misfortune, 92
m aternal, 4, 20, 74, 78, 80, 83, 84, 85, moral, 2, 28, 89, 96, 123, 134, 135, 150
88, 104, 147 moralistic, 96
m aturation, 70, 81, 82 morality, 48, 54, 57, 142, 150
m aturational, 81, 82 morally, 26, 27, 28, 33, 49
mature, 81, 110, 119 m ortal, 55, 111
matured, 81 mortality, 77, 78
maturity, 59, 60, 119 mother, xi, 7, 8, 9, 13, 14, 15, 19, 20, 21,
mean, xi, 4, 8, 9, 10, 16, 17, 19, 20, 27, 33, 45, 56, 57, 58, 59, 63, 64, 65, 66,
3 0 ,3 1 ,3 2 ,3 3 ,3 6 ,3 7 ,3 9 ,4 1 ,4 2 , 44, 67, 68, 69, 7 0 ,7 1 ,7 2 , 74, 7 6 ,7 7 ,7 8 ,
4 5 ,4 8 , 49, 50, 54, 56, 59, 6 0 ,6 1 ,6 3 , 79, 80, 81, 82, 83, 84, 85, 86, 87, 88,
64, 65, 68, 69, 78, 80, 82, 84, 85, 86, 9 2 ,9 5 , 102, 1 0 3 ,1 0 7 ,1 0 8 , 109,110,
8 7 ,9 7 ,9 9 ,1 0 5 ,1 1 9 , 121, 127, 129, 111, 112, 113, 116,117, 119, 128,
130, 138, 1 4 0,141, 143, 149, 152, 153 129, 133, 134, 1 3 5,136, 146, 147, 149
182 S U B JE C T INDEX
129, 132, 133, 134, 136, 138, 143, 76, 79, 8 0 ,8 1 ,8 4 , 8 7 ,8 8 , 9 3 ,9 4 , 95,
144, 146, 147, 149 98, 99, 103, 104, 105, 106, 107, 108,
objecting, 135 110, 111, 112, 114, 115, 116, 117,
objection, 35, 36, 70, 71, 72, 95, 145, 118, 119, 120, 121, 122, 123, 124,
151 132, 134, 1 3 6 ,1 3 8 , 139, 141, 142,
object-relations, 78 143, 144, 1 4 7 ,1 4 8 , 150, 151, 152,
obligations, 144 153
obliged, 27 owner, ix
obsessive, 9 ownership, 150
obstinately, 39, 132
om inous, 93, 94 pain, 11, 21, 102, 103, 104, 105, 106,
om nipotence, 122 108, 109, 116, 118, 137, 140, 141,
one-sided, 66, 97 144, 149, 154
onlooker, 79 painful, 11, 25, 37, 94, 96, 102, 117,
ontological, 32, 51, 57, 73, 75, 76, 101, 128, 140
134, 135, 137 pair, 16, 17, 18, 26, 32, 148
ontology, 32 paradox, 47, 48, 49, 51, 55, 103, 105,
oppose, 17, 38, 40, 152, 153, 154 119, 122, 123
opposite, 41, 42, 48, 49, 99, 140, 148, paradoxical, xi, 20
150, 152 paralysis, xi
opposition, 15, 16, 17, 74, 139, 140, 149 paralyzing, 105
oracle, 92, 93, 94, 95 paranoiac, 137, 146, 148
oral, 18 paranoid-schizoid, 133
organ, 122, 148 parent, 80, 87, 92, 93, 95, 112, 113, 135
orphan, 112 parental, 81
other, ix, 9, 10, 11, 12, 13, 17, 18, 20, partner, 64, 66, 77, 125, 131, 151, 152
26, 28, 29, 32, 33, 34, 35, 36, 40, 42,
passion, 51
45, 48, 49, 50, 52, 53, 54, 55, 59, 65,
passive, 16, 40, 45
66, 67, 68, 69, 72, 73,74, 75, 76, 77,
passivity, 19, 20, 77, 83, 84
79, 8 2 , 8 3 ,8 5 , 8 6 , 88, 97, 98, 110, past, 12, 88, 92, 93, 94, 96, 97, 109,
112, 113, 114, 118, 122, 125, 129, 134, 147, 1 5 1 ,1 5 4
130, 131, 132, 133, 134, 135, 136, paternal, 105, 106, 121, 133
137, 1 3 8 ,1 3 9 , 140, 142, 1 4 3 ,1 4 5 , pathogenic, 35, 146
147, 148, 149, 152 pathological, 140
others, 4, 8, 22, 25, 33, 72, 73, 78, 82, patient, xi, 3, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11, 13, 14, 27,
83, 91, 97, 109, 110, 114, 117, 118, 28, 29, 34, 35, 46, 47, 53, 56, 58, 59,
120, 121, 128, 131, 134, 136, 138, 6 0 ,9 1 ,9 8 ,9 9 , 102, 113, 117, 121,
149, 150, 154 127, 129, 130, 131, 135, 136, 151,
outside, 31, 40, 50, 72, 93, 112, 141 152, 153
over-idealization, 103 peccadillo, 112, 113
over-identification, 103, 105, 118 peek, 71, 72, 79
over-identify, 103 peek-a-boo, 79
ovulation, 75 penitence, 96
owe, 104, 132, 142 perceive, 11, 15, 26, 83, 97, 128, 138,
own, 2, 4, 18, 21, 27, 29, 34, 35, 38, 40, 140, 141
42, 43, 44, 45, 46, 47, 49, 50, 52, 53, perception, 16, 31, 36, 40, 64, 68, 70,
54, 55, 56, 58, 62, 64, 66, 70,72,75, 7 1 ,8 0 , 129, 142, 146, 159
184 SU B JE C T INDEX
split, 1 4 ,1 7 , 7 9 ,8 1 ,1 3 1 sym bolic, 18, 53, 57, 58, 74, 75, 86,
spoke, 38, 154 110, 117, 118, 120, 129, 132, 133,
spoken, 139, 149 142
starvation, 77, 138 symbolicity, 142
statem ent, xi, 2, 9, 10, 12, 28, 29, 34, symbolism, 116
3 5 , 4 2 ,4 3 , 4 5 ,4 8 , 5 7 ,9 3 , 102, 107, symbolize, 111, 135
129, 130, 144, 146, 1 4 8 ,1 4 9 , 150 symbols, 74, 84, 101
statue, 112 symptom, 65, 77, 135
steadfast, 44 syntactic-m orphological, 149
stealing, 26, 113 synthesis, 46, 48, 50, 52, 142, 143
step-children, 112 synthesize, 62, 143, 146
stimulus, 36, 64, 70, 75 synthetic, 143
stoic, 43, 45 system, 9, 12, 18, 19, 29, 36, 54, 65, 70,
strange, 17, 67, 68, 131, 153 7 5 ,9 8 , 101, 118, 120, 133, 137, 142,
stranger, 61, 62, 63, 64, 66, 67, 68, 69, 149
7 0 ,7 1 ,7 2 , 74, 79, 8 0 ,8 1 ,8 3 ,8 8 ,
145, 146, 147 teleology, 30, 122
stress, 20, 30, 35, 40, 44, 51, 55, 56, 76, temporal, 115
7 8 ,8 5 ,8 8 , 96, 103, 131, 137, 142, temporary, 80
145, 150, 152 tem ptation, 97
structural, 83, 85, 142 tension, 20, 70, 146, 147
structure, 37, 46, 57, 62, 70, 74, 76, therapeutic, xi, 3, 37, 53, 56, 58, 59, 60,
80, 82, 86, 123, 133, 137, 141, 142, 98, 99, 132, 152, 153
146 therapist, xi, 21, 59, 91, 98, 99, 102,
structuring, 74 135, 151, 152, 153
struggle, 40, 41, 76, 114, 140, 143, 150 therapy, 14, 59, 135, 152
stubbornness, 85 thesis, 15, 25, 30, 31, 32, 39, 40, 42, 48,
studying, 10, 14, 135 5 1 , 5 2 ,5 7 , 6 1 ,8 2 , 8 3 ,8 6 , 1 0 1 ,1 2 9 ,
subject, xi, 2, 8, 10, 12, 19, 31, 33, 40, 130, 132, 134, 135, 140, 142, 143,
55, 56, 58, 59, 76, 78, 79, 99, 103, 148, 149, 152, 154
107, 129, 130, 133, 134, 135, 141, three (m onths o f age), 62, 64, 65, 66,
145, 154 68, 70, 77, 87, 95, 99
subjective, 15, 32, 40, 110, 125 truth, 25, 98, 123, 127, 140
subjectivity, 19, 78, 79, 99 two (m onths o f age), 3, 4, 8, 20, 62, 68,
subjects, 3 87, 117
substitute, 4, 16, 17, 29, 30, 32, 33, 104,
109 unconscious, 9, 10, 11, 12, 20, 27, 29,
substituting, 33, 119 30, 3 4 , 3 5 ,3 6 , 3 7 ,3 9 , 4 6 ,5 7 ,5 8 ,5 9 ,
suffer, 112, 154 75, 101, 102, 103, 104, 106, 109,
suffering, 92, 111, 140 110, 113, 115, 116, 118, 120, 121,
suffocating, 21, 118 122, 127, 129, 130, 134, 135, 136,
survival, 129, 130 151
survive, 114, 133 unconsciously, 4, 27, 93, 96, 104, 106,
survivor, 70 115, 119, 122
symbiosis, 86, 147 unconsciousness, 30
symbol, 2, 3, 4, 13, 17, 18, 20, 22, 30, undergo, 16, 19, 45, 96
3 9 ,6 4 , 8 9 ,1 1 2 ,1 1 6 , 124, 129, 149 underm ine, 2, 49, 94, 97
S U B JE C T INDEX 189