Conceptual Analysis A Method For Understanding Inf
Conceptual Analysis A Method For Understanding Inf
net/publication/228953426
CITATIONS READS
116 20,337
1 author:
Jonathan Furner
University of California, Los Angeles
73 PUBLICATIONS 2,119 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Jonathan Furner on 17 March 2014.
JONATHAN FURNER
OCLC Online Computer Library Center, Inc., 6565 Frantz Road., Dublin, OH 43017-
3395, USA (E-mail: [email protected])
Abstract. The utility of conceptual analysis for archival science is assessed by means
of an exploratory evaluation in which the concept of evidence is analyzed. Usage of
the term ‘‘evidence’’ in the philosophies of science, law, and history is briefly
reviewed; candidates for necessary conditions of evidentiariness are identified and
examined; and taxonomies are built of evidentiariness and of archival inference.
Correspondences are shown to exist between the concepts of evidentiariness and
relevance, and between the domains of archival science and social epistemology,
thereby pointing in promising directions for further research. The tentative conclusion
is reached that conceptual analysis may profitably be used to improve understanding
of archival concepts.
Introduction
1
Jeremy Bentham, An Introductory View of the Rationale of Evidence for the Use of Non-lawyers
as well as Lawyers (ed. James Mill, 1812; first published in vol. 6 of The Works of Jeremy Bentham,
ed. John Bowring, Edinburgh and London, 1843), p. 2.
234 JONATHAN FURNER
particular concepts are (or could be) used for communicating ideas
about that field.2
Information science is one field in which important contributions have
recently been made through the application (sometimes on a relatively
informal basis) of conceptual analysis. Questions such as ‘‘What is infor-
mation?’’ and ‘‘What is a document?’’ received close attention in the
1990s, and the various suggested answers to these questions continue to
be treated as candidate cornerstones of emergent theoretical frameworks
in the field.3 In archival science, similarly, the ongoing debate about the
nature of the record received renewed impetus in the 1990s with the wide-
spread recognition that (what are called) electronic records may not share
as many of the properties of physical records as might be thought at first
glance.4 This paper seeks to demonstrate what kinds of advances might be
made possible through the application of the method of conceptual analy-
sis to key archival concepts. It does this by addressing the question ‘‘What
is evidence?’’
Two of the assumptions that underlie any positive expectation of
the utility of conceptual analysis are (i) the belief that it is at least
possible for concept-users to reach some level of agreement as to the
nature of the uses to which concepts are put, and (ii) the belief that to
reach some agreement of that kind is a prerequisite for the develop-
ment of useful (and/or interesting) knowledge (and/or theory). These
are among the assumptions that are made in the present paper. In
addition, it is assumed that any ‘‘proof’’ of the utility of the method
lies ‘‘in the pudding’’ – in other words, that it is possible to demon-
strate the utility of the method through the production of a result
that is perceived to be provocative of original or interesting ideas for
directions in which future research may be pushed. In that spirit, the
2
The body of method known simply as analysis, and deriving from the work of Frege, Moore,
and Russell, lay at the core of much twentieth-century anglophone philosophy, and its adherents
continue to exert a huge influence: see, e.g., Brian Leiter, ‘‘Introduction’’, in Leiter (ed.), The Future
for Philosophy (Oxford, 2004); and Frank Jackson, From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of
Conceptual Analysis (Oxford, 1998). Analytic philosophy has a broad scope and there is no single
technique that could be claimed as the analytic method. One distinctive characteristic that is
nonetheless shared by most philosophers in the analytic tradition is the belief that many philo-
sophical problems can be illuminated by clarifying the meanings of the concepts that we use to
think about and to express those problems. This is the context in which ‘‘conceptual analysis’’ is to
be understood in this paper.
3
See, e.g., Michael Buckland, ‘‘Information as Thing’’, Journal of the American Society for
Information Science 42(5) (1991): 351–360; Buckland, ‘‘What is a ‘Document’?’’, Journal of the
American Society for Information Science 48(9) (1997): 804–809; and Michèle Tourney ‘‘Caging
Virtual Antelopes: Suzanne Briet’s Definition of Documents in the Context of the Digital Age’’,
Archival Science 3 (2003): 291–311.
4
See, e.g., Luciana Duranti et al., Preservation of the Integrity of Electronic Records (Dordrecht
and Boston, 2002).
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS 235
paper concludes with two specific suggestions of lines of work that
may potentially prove productive: a collaboration among archival sci-
entists and information scientists with the aim of clarifying the nature
of the relationship between evidentiariness and relevance; and an
exploration of social epistemology as a theoretical foundation for
archival science.
Conceptual analysis, of course, is not the only method available for
clarifying or establishing evolution in archival concepts. Another plau-
sible approach to the analysis of the nature of evidence would involve
conducting a close examination of the arguments and conclusions of
others who have written about the properties, functions, and role of
evidence in archival, historical, legal, scientific, and other contexts. In
the historical context, for instance, an empirical survey could be
undertaken of the ways in which ‘‘evidence’’ has been used in the past
both by practicing historians, and by philosophers of history. Simi-
larly, in the archival context, we might wish to investigate how archi-
val practitioners and/or archival theorists have employed the concept,
and how such usage has reflected or influenced wider archival practice.
There is little doubt that studies of these kinds would be helpful in
enabling present-day theorists to reach a better understanding of what
it means for us to call certain things ‘‘evidence.’’ A preliminary effort
is made below to identify some of the more important ideas about evi-
dence that are characteristic of different fields of inquiry. The present
paper, however, is not intended as a review of prior analyses of the
concept (such as they exist), and thus no attempt is made to provide a
comprehensive set of citations to previous work.
5
See, e.g., Peter Achinstein (ed.), The Concept of Evidence (Oxford, 1983); and Achinstein, The
Book of Evidence (Oxford, 2001).
236 JONATHAN FURNER
13
See, e.g., Peter Lipton, Inference to the Best Explanation (London and New York, 2nd edn.,
2004).
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS 239
reliability of the methods by which individual hypotheses are reached.
If, after examining past performance, we were to find that, given a
choice between the explanation that posits the existence of the fewest
new or unobserved classes of object and the explanation that covers
the largest number of cases, selection of the explanation of the former
kind appears to reflect reality more frequently, then on the reliabilist
account we would be justified in using that method of deciding
among competing hypotheses. Of course, that smoking causes lung
disease is widely considered among health professionals as the ‘‘best’’
explanation of the unhealthy condition of many smokers: it may be
no coincidence that it is also the simplest.
If it is to be persuasive, any model of IBE needs also to provide
an account of the process of explanation itself; typically, in this
context, a causal account of explanation is given that equates expla-
nation with specification of a historical sequence of cause and effect.
Such an account serves as an alternative to the well-known
deductive-nomological (D-N) model, whereby to explain any given
event is to deduce it from a ‘‘covering law’’ or generalization.14
According to the D-N model, explaining the incidence of lung dis-
ease in a smoker is a matter of stating the ‘‘law’’ that long-term
smoking is always accompanied or followed by lung disease, and
then deducing the facts of the particular case from that law. The
D-N model has been criticized for its inadequacy on several fronts,
not least for its underdetermination of the class of acceptable expla-
nations for any given event. The particular ‘‘law’’ stated above,
much like the proposition that all swans are white, is not empiri-
cally true, of course; yet it is another feature of the D-N model that
any putative law can be modified by adding exception clauses (such
as ‘‘... except in cases where patients have condition x’’) as neces-
sary to cover all cases that arise. It is notable that historiographers
and philosophers of social science who have considered the D-N
model as it has been developed by their colleagues in philosophy of
natural science have widely rejected it in favour of accounts of
explanation that do not require deterministic covering laws to be
specified for human behavior, but that allow for the effects of
human intentionality, individuality, and the exercise of free will, and
that require the explainer to engage in imaginative interpretation of
the meanings events have for human actors.15
14
See, e.g., Carl G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy
of Science (New York, 1965).
15
See, e.g., William H. Dray, Philosophy of History (Englewood Cliffs, N. J., 1964).
240 JONATHAN FURNER
16
See, e.g., Christopher B. Mueller and Laird C. Kirkpatrick, Evidence under the Rules: Text,
Cases, and Problems (New York, 1996).
17
Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832), British philosopher, economist, and jurist.
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS 241
Judicial Evidence (1827)18 and Wigmore’s19 Science of Judicial Proof
(1937).20 Twining21 and Shapiro22 trace the history of the develop-
ment of legal notions of evidence; Binder & Bergman23 and Anderson
and Twining24 provide accounts of the process of establishing legal
proof; Tillers and Green25 and Schum26 use the framework provided
by Bayesian probability theory to model this process.
30
Brian Fay, ‘‘The Linguistic Turn and Beyond in Contemporary Theory of History’’, in Fay
et al. (eds.), History and Theory: Contemporary Readings (Malden, Mass., and Oxford, 1998),
pp. 1–12.
31
See, e.g., Heather MacNeil, Trusting Records: Legal, Historical, and Diplomatic Perspectives
(Dordrecht and Boston, 2000); and Brien Brothman, ‘‘Afterglow: Conceptions of Record and
Evidence in Archival Discourse’’, Archival Science 2(3/4) (2002): 311–342.
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS 245
Twentieth-century thought on the nature of archival evidence
demonstrates the distinctive influence of the two doyens of modern
archival practice, the Briton Hilary Jenkinson (1882–1961), and the
American Theodore R. Schellenberg (1903–1970).32 Jenkinson popu-
larized the idea that evidentiariness is the essence of archival
records, and insisted on the universal, objective strength of the link
between premise (the existence of the record) and conclusion (the
occurrence of the events that produced the record); Schellenberg
articulated a much-repeated distinction between the evidential and
the informational value of a record that continues to inform contem-
porary archival theory and education. For Schellenberg, a record’s
evidential value is an index of its utility in documenting the circum-
stances of its creation, whereas its informational value reflects the
importance of its symbolic content. The possibility of confusion is
thus introduced by Schellenberg’s use of the term ‘‘evidential’’ to
refer only to evidence of a real (rather than documentary) kind. In
historical scholarship and in the law, Schellenberg’s distinction is an
important one, but it is one that is drawn between different kinds
of evidence (i.e., between real evidence-as-trace and documentary
evidence-as-testimony) rather than between evidential and non-
evidential values.
It is well appreciated that Jenkinson’s views on the essential objec-
tivity and truthfulness of the archives as a record of ‘‘what really
happened’’ in the past reflects the positivist, Rankean historiography
that was dominant in his time.33 For Jenkinson, appraisal of records’
long-term value was a task that should be undertaken only by
records creators, and that should involve consideration only of the
functions of records as originally intended. Schellenberg’s supporters
argued, in contrast, that appraisal decisions should take into account
any expectations as to the future use of records for purposes other
than those for which they were created, and that archivists rather
than records creators should bear responsibility for decisions of that
kind.
In the late twentieth century, and primarily in Australia and Can-
ada, a neo-Jenkinsonian perspective on archival best-practice emerged
that retained Schellenberg’s emphasis on appraisal, but that restored
to primacy Jenkinson’s principle that selection decisions are to be
based on evaluations of the strength of the relationships between
32
See, e.g., Terry Cook, ‘‘What Is Past Is Prologue: A History of Archival Ideas Since 1898, and
the Future Paradigm Shift’’, Archivaria 43 (Spring 1997).
33
Leopold von Ranke (1795–1886), German historian renowned for his dictum that history
should be recorded ‘‘wie es eigentlich gewesen.’’
246 JONATHAN FURNER
records and the contexts in which they were originally created. The
scope of a record’s contextuality is now more broadly defined than
Jenkinson allowed. In Canada, Hugh Taylor and Terry Cook are
among those who have promoted a new focus on the ‘‘macro,’’ socie-
tal contexts that give records their meaning.34 One result of this trend
is for the primary role of the archivist to now be more commonly
perceived as one of determining the provenance of records as a means
of understanding the social structures and processes by whose com-
plex combination records are generated. In Australia, Sue McKem-
mish and Frank Upward have been concerned to emphasize the
importance of archives as the primary means by which societies main-
tain the accountability of their institutions.35 In this sense, the process
by which records of demonstrable authenticity provide evidence of
public and private institutions’ actions is an essential component of
any functioning democracy.
More recently, McKemmish and her colleagues have begun more
explicitly to explore the similarities and differences between corporate
recordkeeping, where records are captured as evidence of business
functions and activities, and personal recordkeeping, where records are
captured as evidence of the roles and activities of individuals.36 Just as
archivists have long appreciated the importance of establishing record-
keeping and preservation systems that can capture, manage and
maintain complete and accurate records of business activities for busi-
ness purposes, McKemmish is concerned to emphasize the active role
of archivists in institutionalizing personal recordkeeping systems as a
means of preserving the collective memory (and thus the identity) of
societies and cultures. No redefinition of ‘‘record’’ is required or
implied in this work: the recordness of a document such as a personal
letter is still conceived as consisting in its transactional origin (as the
product of some human interactivity), and its evidential potential (as
the object of a recordkeeping process that maintains the document’s
links to the context in which it was generated); and the functional
requirements of any recordkeeping system are still conceived as
including the means to guarantee the authenticity and reliability of
documents captured as evidence.
34
See, e.g., Tom Nesmith, ‘‘Hugh Taylor’s Contextual Idea for Archives and the Foundation of
Graduate Education in Archival Studies’’, in Barbara L. Craig (ed.), The Archival Imagination:
Essays in Honour of Hugh A. Taylor (Ottawa, 1992), pp. 13–37; and Terry Cook, ‘‘Mind Over
Matter: Towards a New Theory of Archival Appraisal’’, in Craig (ed.), The Archival Imagination,
pp. 38–70.
35
See, e.g., Sue McKemmish and Frank Upward (eds.), Archival Documents: Providing
Accountability Through Recordkeeping (Melbourne, 1993).
36
See, e.g., Sue McKemmish, ‘‘Evidence of Me ...’’, Archives and Manuscripts 24(1) (1996): 28–45.
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS 247
General Characteristics of Evidence
Evidence is relational
38
The existence of a distinction between ‘‘reality’’ and any representation of reality is denied by
the rigorous postmodernist, who would treat all entities as thoughts (in the sense used here).
39
In a legal context, the conclusion might be referred to as ‘‘the point in question;’’ in history, as
‘‘the facts;’’ and in science, as a hypothesis.
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS 249
How are conclusions derived from premises? What methods are
used in the inferential analysis of premises? We may distinguish
broadly between two kinds of inferential method: deduction and
induction. A simple example of a deductive inference is provided by
the following argument, represented in three systems of notation. In
this example and the next one, the proposition listed below the line is
the conclusion; the propositions listed above the line are the premises.
Evidence is probabilistic
evidence on the one hand, and the physical sources of that evidence
on the other. We might, for instance, talk of our vase as being the
physical source of an idea that we have about the context in which it
was produced. In recognition of this distinction, we should be pre-
pared also to acknowledge that the word ‘‘evidence’’ may sometimes
be used loosely to denote a source or sources, rather than to refer to
that which we might more properly conceive as the evidence itself.
What is more common is the description of sources as ‘‘evidentiary,’’
i.e., as supplying evidence.
Some events and objects in the real world may be identified as human
artifacts in that they are generated as a result of human activity.
Some of these artifacts may be treated as documents in virtue of their
having (symbolic) content as well as (physical) form. Sometimes such
documents are treated as evidence (or sources of evidence) in virtue of
their form; sometimes documents are treated as evidence in virtue of
their content. In this sense, content is conceived as anything that
serves as the physical expression or representation of human ideas or
thoughts. The relationship of content to thought is that of meaning.
In any given case, this relationship is complex, not least because any
instance of content (i.e., an utterance) may have multiple potentially-
associated thoughts, including at least (i) a meaning intended by the
speaker or writer, (ii) a conventional meaning emergent from prior
usage, and (iii) a meaning assigned by the hearer or reader, none of
which may coincide.
It should be clear, for example, that vases of the kind observed in
our hypothetical case can be treated as sources of evidence in virtue
of their form. We have already seen how an argument may be con-
structed in which the known origins of previously-examined vases are
used as evidence in support of a conclusion about the origins of a
newly-discovered vase. This kind of argument, in which propositions
about the form of other vases are marshaled as evidence in support of
an answer to a question about the context in which the vase in ques-
tion was produced, is (as we shall see) just one of the kinds of infer-
ence in which evidence-of-form may play a part. Another is that in
which the very existence of an artifact is invoked as evidence of the
occurrence of the act that produced it.
But our vase and others like it can also be treated as sources of
evidence in virtue of their content. The series of symbols inscribed
on Vase 1’s outer surface comprise an utterance, or speech act, carried
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS 253
out by an author or inscriber. Such an utterance expresses a
thought or particular idea of the author’s (its intentional meaning),
and may also be assigned meaning by individual readers or through
inter-subjective consensus or convention. Documents – i.e., artifacts
that, like our vase, have symbolic content – supply evidence not just
of the occurrence of the acts that produced them, but of the occur-
rence of the acts that they document. Suppose that, on interpreting
the inscription on our vase, we were to discover a story about an
ancient battle. Not only would we then have evidence of the occur-
rence of the speech act of which this document is a result, but we
would have evidence of the occurrence of the battle described. The
need to evaluate both the authenticity of the document and the reli-
ability of the author if we are to quantify the weight of the evidence
in support of these conclusions is discussed in a separate section
below.
41
The act of inferential analysis, carried out with a view to deriving conclusions from premises,
should perhaps be conceived as distinct from the act of interpretation that is undertaken in order to
derive premises from primary sources. Nevertheless, it should also be clear that the results of
inductive inference are also strongly dependent on individuals’ personal interpretations of the
concepts and categories that are manipulated in argument.
256 JONATHAN FURNER
Having considered the kinds of thing that evidence can be, I shall
now turn to a presentation of a taxonomy of the kinds of conclusion
that may be drawn as a result of the interpretation of a primary
source. What kinds of conclusion or inferences may we potentially
draw (or wish to draw) from our analysis of any evidential premises
that may be derived from a primary source such as our inscribed
vase, beyond simple reports of our perception of its existence and
physical attributes? To answer this question, first it should be recog-
nized that the premises that we derive from the vase itself are far
from the only premises that may be used in deriving a conclusion
about the vase. We have access, of course, to whatever set of proposi-
tions (and whatever set of evaluations of the truth of those proposi-
tions) that have been amassed from previous interpretations of objects
similar (in various ways) to the vase under current examination.
1. Inferences to context
– Deductive inferences to particular context – about the circumstances
and/or conditions of this particular object’s creation, including (specifi-
cally) the identity and nature of its creator(s). For example, we might
know from prior interpretation of the available evidence that vases made
of a particular kind of stone were made in Ireland (Premise 1: p fi q);
observe that our vase is made of that kind of stone (Premise 2: p); and
deduce that our vase was made in Ireland (Conclusion: q).
– Inductive inferences to general context – about the circumstances and/or
conditions of the creation of other members of any class of which this
particular object is understood to be a member, including (specifically)
the identity and nature of their creator(s). For example, we might know
that another vase was made of the same kind of stone and that that vase
was made in Ireland (Premise 1: p q); observe that our vase was made
of that kind of stone and know from prior interpretation of the avail-
able evidence that it was made in Ireland (Premise 2: p q); and infer by
induction that vases made of that kind of stone were made in Ireland
(Conclusion: p fi q).
2. Inferences to function
– Inferences to intentional function
Deductive inferences to particular intentional function – about the functions
or uses to which the creator(s) intended to put this particular object, and thus
about the reasons the creator(s) had for creating it.
Inductive inferences to general intentional function – about the functions
or uses to which the creator(s) intended to put other members of any
258 JONATHAN FURNER
42
See, e.g., Rafael Capurro and Birger Hjørland, ‘‘The Concept of Information’’, Annual Review
of Information Science and Technology 37 (2003): 343–411.
260 JONATHAN FURNER
C2 Document X1 is authentic. q.
C1 Event Y1 occurred. q.
Evidentiariness as Relevance
43
See Jonathan Furner, ‘‘Information Studies without Information’’, Library Trends 52(3)
(2004): 427–446.
262 JONATHAN FURNER
even within the relatively narrow scope of the library and information
sciences. The same can be said of conceptions of evidence in the con-
text of the archival sciences.
It is possible, nevertheless, to compare individual pairs of concep-
tions of evidence and information with a view to establishing the
extent and nature of any overlap. One of the more promising approa-
ches might be to focus on the shared propositional nature of two
conceptions of relatively wide acceptance and application, viz., docu-
ments as the sources of potentially relevant ideas (i.e., information),
and records as the sources of potentially evidentiary ideas. Taking
this approach might have the interesting effect of revising the motiva-
tion for the initial comparison, so that the objective is recast as one
of relating not evidence to information, but evidentiariness to
relevance. Just as evidentiariness is a property of the relationship
between one set of propositions (i.e., premises) to another (a conclu-
sion), relevance is a property of the relationship between one set of
propositions (i.e., a document) to another (a query). Sets of premises
are evaluated in order to measure the weight of evidence they supply
for conclusions; documents are evaluated in order to measure the
degree of relevance they have to queries. Both evidentiariness and rel-
evance are matters of degree; both are probabilistic. On this reading,
to seek to define the link between evidence and information is per-
haps to set oneself the less interesting challenge.
As was stated at the outset, the aim of the present paper has been
to assess the utility of a particular method – namely, conceptual
analysis – when applied in addressing a particular problem – that of
improving understanding of the nature, scope, and function of the
phenomena that are commonly grouped by archival scientists under
the heading of ‘‘evidence.’’ It was assumed that, if such understanding
were to turn out to be enhanced as a result of the application of such
a method, then not only would we be enabled to generate interesting
ideas for future research, but we would also thereby be justified in
evaluating that application as successful, and in evaluating the
method as potentially of more-general utility in archival science.
In the paper, the meaning of the concept labelled ‘‘evidence’’ was
defined as a class of phenomena – viz., those things that we consider in
order to infer a conclusion. Several candidates for necessary conditions
of evidentiariness – relationality, measurability, physicality, substanti-
ality, meaningfulness, objectivity – were identified and examined, and
47
See Don Fallis, ‘‘Veritistic Social Epistemology and Information Science’’, Social Episte-
mology 14 (2000): 305–316; and Fallis, ‘‘Social Epistemology and Information Science’’, Annual
Review of Information Science and Technology 40 (forthcoming).
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS 265
taxonomies were presented (i) of multiple kinds of evidentiariness,
varying in the appropriateness with which they are attributable to situ-
ations, events, utterances, and ideas, and (ii) of multiple kinds of infer-
ence, varying in their purpose, in their level of generality, and in the
extent to which they capture intentionality and conventionality. On
the basis of this conceptual framework, a correspondence was shown
to exist between the use of the concept of evidentiariness in archival
science and the use of the concept of relevance in information science;
and an analogy was drawn between the purpose of archival science
and that of social epistemology. It is asserted that these correspon-
dences are worthy of further investigation, and that their identification
allows for innovative thinking about the nature and purpose of archi-
val processes and the function and design of archival systems. On the
basis of the evidence thereby provided, we may tentatively infer that
conceptual analysis may profitably be used to improve understanding
not just of the concept of evidence (central as it is to archivists’ con-
cerns), but of other concepts germane to archival science.