Rousseau
Rousseau
Biography
Émile
Rousseau wrote Émile in 1762, shortly after which it was banned. The book
challenged the dominion of the clergy in education as well as their methods in providing
instruction. Émile imparts Rousseau’s philosophy of education through the experiences
of the title character, a young boy. Tellingly, the boy’s tutor is named Jean-Jacques
who, at the end of the book, declares himself to be the boy’s “true” father because of his
role in educating Émile. Despite the book’s initial difficulties with French authorities,
Rousseau nonetheless reached a large audience by having the book printed in the
Netherlands. Eventually, Rousseau won a small victory over the ancien regime; Émile
became the basis for the new French education system after the French Revolution in
1789. However, Rousseau’s work still attracted much criticism, in particular from
women who were angered by his belief that women should merely be educated for a life
in the home.
Rousseau was not the only Enlightenment philosophe to propose changes to the
French system of education, but the changes he proposed were the most radical and
far-reaching. Rousseau articulated a philosophy of education that imagined the
transformative potential of education for society: properly educated pupils would be able
to create a new society that eliminated the centuries-long cycle of poverty, inequality,
and exploitation against which Rousseau wrote. The changes that other eighteenth-
century thinkers proposed, in contrast, merely changed the focus of education: rather
than imparting aristocratic values, such changes imparted bourgeois values.
Philosophes like Priestly in England and Helvétius in France, relying on Locke, argued
that a child’s mind was a blank slate on which should be printed the skills and values
necessary to succeed in society. Rousseau also adopted Locke’s blank slate—or
tabula rasa— theory, but he believed that contemporary values must be left behind
entirely.
Rousseau developed his political philosophy over the course of decades. The
principle means in which he did so was through several books written between 1750
and 1762, of which The Social Contract is the most famous. Over the next few pages,
we will outline Rousseau’s political philosophy through his major works.
Rousseau’s Discourse on the Arts and Sciences was his first major work and
brought him to the attention of the French and European public. Shortly after his
“conversion experience” in 1749, Rousseau decided to enter an essay-writing
competition given by the Academy of Dijon. The competition stipulated that writers
must answer “whether the re-establishment of the arts and sciences has contributed to
purifying morals.” Rousseau sent his answer to the Academy in 1750, and in 1751 he
was announced as the winner. Rousseau gained extensive notoriety as a result of his
answer; the competition was watched widely, and his victory received responses from
numerous dignitaries, including the king of Poland.
Rousseau’s essay began his engagement with a theme that would be the focus
of the rest of his major writings: the corruptive influence of civilization on human beings.
He argued, first of all, that progress and civilization were eroding the soul’s virtue, and
that the sciences and the arts were the main influence on this devolution. Rousseau’s
proposal ran counter to Enlightenment beliefs that progress in the sciences and the arts
were good for individuals and for humanity.
Rousseau began by arguing that whenever the arts and the sciences flourished
in a society, the society crumbled soon after. He drew on historical examples for those
arguments: when art had flourished in China, ancient Egypt and, especially, ancient
Greece, it marked a period of decline for those civilizations. He compared the decline of
Athens, which had thoroughly embraced an artistic culture, with Sparta. Rousseau
believed that the Spartans, with their military and utilitarian outlook on life, had
embodied the proper sensibilities for the enrichment of the soul. Because the Spartans
had purged artists and scientists from society, they had prospered. (He did not,
however, put much stress on the fact that the Spartan civilization also perished.)
In the second half of his discourse, Rousseau attacked the nature of the arts and
sciences themselves as degenerate. Neither, he argued, do anything to make people
better citizens. One who understands the sciences is not necessarily a more virtuous
person, merely a more knowledgeable person. Moreover, Rousseau argued that
enjoyment of the arts creates a society in which people strive to be recognized and no
longer value courage, temperance, or fraternity. In both cases, Rousseau argued that
the arts and sciences do nothing to make someone a better citizen or a more virtuous
person.
1
The development of this section on Rousseau’s political philosophy draws in particular on James Delaney,
“Rousseau, Jean-Jacques,” Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2005), http://www.iep.utm.edu/rousseau.
Rousseau’s Discourse on the Origin and Basis of Inequality among Men, better
known by the shorter title above or as Rousseau’s Second Discourse, was again written
in response to a question given by the Academy of Dijon. The Academy’s question in
1754 was “what is the origin of inequality among men, and is it authorized by natural
law?” This time Rousseau did not win first prize, partly because his essay was longer
than the specified length, but he still published his text in 1755. It has become better
known than his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences.
Rousseau began his project along much the same lines as John Locke’s Two
Treatises of Government. Like Locke (and Thomas Hobbes), he argues that society is
constructed, not natural. Rousseau’s understanding of the natural state of man,
however, differed from what Locke and Hobbes had argued. Rousseau argued against
Hobbes’s idea that life in a natural state was “nasty, brutish, and short.” Such a belief,
Rousseau argued, defined humans by only their negative characteristics. Rather, if
humans were truly without all the structures and organizations of civilization, they would
be shy and peaceful. Humans were not only capable of acting in their own self-interest
(their self-love, or amour de soi), as Hobbes argued; rather, they also had a powerful
capacity for pity and mercy. Other creatures share these qualities, but humans have
evolved, Rousseau argued, because their capacity for reason exceeds that of any other
creature. Since human nature includes this powerful capacity for mercy and reason,
Rousseau optimistically proposed that cooperation, not conflict, was the natural state of
human society.
Rousseau went on to articulate his theory of the development of civilization. The
first stage involved temporary group organization, with attempts at developing language.
Next came more permanent relationships, especially marriage and family relationships,
which also brought with them rudimentary understandings of property and pride. While
humans would still be basically happy at this stage, developments in the arts and
sciences at the next stage created the setting for humanity’s dissatisfaction. Here,
Rousseau’s Second Discourse hearkens back to his Discourse on the Arts and
Sciences and its argument about the degenerate nature of civilization. With the
introduction of the arts and sciences, people developed different skills, and a division of
labor evolved: those with more valuable skills acquired more power in the society.
Eventually, citizens who rise to the top of the division agree that everyone must be
bound by a social contract; that all aspects of the society work together to reinforce the
whole. Rousseau asserted, however, that this is a self-interested argument on the part
of the new elites to secure their power. The people, failing to recognize that the social
contract is a trap, accept it willingly.
Legacy
Summary
Jean-Jacques Rousseau was a traveler; he rarely remained in one place for more
than two decades of his life. The reasons for this varied: his family abandoned him;
his friends abjured him for his paranoid conduct; and the French state sought his
arrest for subversion, forcing him to flee.
Rousseau’s Émile attempted to establish a new standard of education based on a
natural, self-directed style of learning. Rousseau believed that children should be