Principles and Practice of Criminalistics
Principles and Practice of Criminalistics
CRIMINALISTICS
The Profession of
Forensic Science
A Volume in the
Protocols in Forensic Science Series
CRC Press
Boca Raton London New York Washington, D.C.
8127/frame/fm Page iv Monday, July 24, 2000 11:17 AM
HV8073.I443 2000
363.25--dc21 00-034316
This book contains information obtained from authentic and highly regarded sources. Reprinted material
is quoted with permission, and sources are indicated. A wide variety of references are listed. Reasonable
efforts have been made to publish reliable data and information, but the author and the publisher cannot
assume responsibility for the validity of all materials or for the consequences of their use.
Neither this book nor any part may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic
or mechanical, including photocopying, microfilming, and recording, or by any information storage or
retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publisher.
The consent of CRC Press LLC does not extend to copying for general distribution, for promotion, for
creating new works, or for resale. Specific permission must be obtained in writing from CRC Press LLC
for such copying.
Direct all inquiries to CRC Press LLC, 2000 N.W. Corporate Blvd., Boca Raton, Florida 33431.
Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are
used only for identification and explanation, without intent to infringe.
v
Thinking is Allowed. This is one of the major themes of the book. Critical thinking is the first skill to be
invoked at the beginning of a case, and continues through every phase of an analysis and interpretation. Too
often, our thinking is constricted by what we believe is true, by what we expect to be true, or by commands
from the god of productivity. The competent analyst will not sacrifice thoughtfulness at any stage of his work.
8127/frame/fm Page vii Monday, July 24, 2000 11:17 AM
Series Introduction
vii
8127/frame/fm Page ix Monday, July 24, 2000 11:17 AM
Preface
Thinking is allowed
Unknown
Why do we need another book about criminalistics? Many books have been
written on this subject over the last century, and several are currently in print
(Kirk, 1953, 1974; Saferstein, 1981, 1988, 1993, 1998; DeForest, 1983; Fisher,
2000). The majority of writings addressing subjects relating to science and
crime have been aimed at the police investigator or the lay public. This is
perhaps not surprising. The investigator or detective plays the unquestionably
critical role of identifying and collecting evidence from the crime scene. These
actions profoundly influence any subsequent analysis and interpretation, so
it is imperative that those duties are performed with knowledge and expertise.
Although investigators are usually not trained scientists, they must under-
stand enough about the analytical procedures to avoid confounding them by
their actions at the scene. Thus many books have been written with this goal
in mind.
The lay public, including crime and mystery writers, has always had a
morbid obsession with criminals, crime, and its detection. Many of the
fascinating tales recounting both the commission of crimes and their solution
have been recorded in various volumes directed toward the interested lay-
person. As technology has advanced and more-sophisticated methods have
been applied to the analysis of physical evidence, the interested public wants
to know not only about the criminal and the crime, but also about the various
analytical techniques and what they can contribute to the solution of the
crime (Ragle, 1995; Houde, 1999).
This book is not aimed at the investigator, attorney, crime or mystery
writer, career switcher, or beginning student. Although all of these groups
may find the information presented here both useful and interesting, they
may have to employ other resources to fill in gaps in scientific or forensic
knowledge. Rather, this volume is by and for forensic scientists; it is directed
toward the practicing or soon to be practicing criminalist. It is not introduc-
tory in nature and assumes a strong background and familiarity with the
physical and forensic sciences.
ix
8127/frame/fm Page x Monday, July 24, 2000 11:17 AM
Strangely, few volumes have been written for the forensic science profes-
sional, and the majority of those tend to be simply compilations of laboratory
methods and techniques (Kirk, 1953, 1974; Saferstein, 1981, 1988, 1993;
DeForest et al., 1983). While detailed and standardized procedures are obvi-
ously indispensable to quality laboratory work, without the proper cognitive
framework the laboratory results may be worse than useless. Therefore, we
do not present here yet another overview of forensic science or introduction
to laboratory techniques. Rather, we concentrate on topics that are discussed
in lunchrooms, around watercoolers, and on electronic mail lists by practic-
ing forensic scientists.
We outline here a logical framework for a forensic investigation, an
approach rather than a compendium of methods, a way of thinking rather
than a set of instructions. We most definitely emphasize the role of physical
evidence in providing information about criminal actions. However, as we
will stress throughout the book, physical evidence does not exist in a vacuum
and, to maximize its value, it must be considered in the total context of the
circumstances of the case. The technician who only pushes buttons and
twiddles dials, even on the most-sophisticated instrument, remains just
that — a technician. The criminalist must synthesize and interpret laboratory
results in the greater context of the crime, or risk misinterpreting them.
Thinking is allowed — consider this a framework on which to hang your
thoughts.
THINKING IS ALLOWED
References
DeForest, P., Lee, H., and Gaensslen, R., Forensic Science: An Introduction to Crimi-
nalistics, McGraw-Hill, New York, 1983.
Fisher, B. J., Techniques of Crime Scene Investigation, 6th ed., CRC Press, Boca Raton,
FL, 2000.
Houde, J. Crime Lab: A Guide for Nonscientists, Calico Press, Ventura, CA, 1999.
Kirk, P. L., Crime Investigation, Interscience, John Wiley & Sons, New York, 1953.
Kirk, P. L., Crime Investigation, 2nd ed., Krieger Publishing Co. (by arrangement with
John Wiley & Sons), Malabar, FL, 1974.
Ragle, L., Crime Scene, Avon Books, New York, 1995.
Saferstein, R., Forensic Science Handbook, Vol. 1, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ,
1981.
Saferstein, R., Forensic Science Handbook, Vol. 2, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ,
1988.
Saferstein, R., Forensic Science Handbook, Vol. 3, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ,
1993.
Saferstein, R., Criminalistics: An Introduction to Forensic Science, 6th ed., Prentice-
Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1998.
8127/frame/fm Page xiii Monday, July 24, 2000 11:17 AM
The Authors
Keith Inman holds a B.S. and M. Crim., both from the University of California
at Berkeley. He is a fellow of the American Board of Criminalistics. In his
professional career he has been employed as a criminalist by the Orange County
Sheriff’s Department, the Los Angeles County Sheriff’s Department, the Los
Angeles County Chief Medical Examiner-Coroner, and the Oakland Police
Department. He was in private practice for 6 years at Forensic Science Services
of California, Inc., a private crime laboratory that undertook both prosecution
and defense work. Mr. Inman is currently employed as a senior criminalist by
the California Department of Justice DNA Laboratory. He has coauthored An
Introduction to Forensic DNA Analysis, a book that has become the preeminent
reference for both attorneys and crime laboratories. He has taught in the Crim-
inal Justice Administration Department at California State University, Hayward,
and currently teaches a variety of general forensic science and forensic DNA
courses for the University of California at Berkeley Extension and online.
Norah Rudin holds a B.A. from Pomona College and a Ph.D. from Brandeis
University. She is a diplomate of the American Board of Criminalistics. After
completing a postdoctoral fellowship at Lawrence Berkeley Laboratory, she
worked for 3 years as a full-time consultant for the California Department
of Justice DNA Laboratory and has also served as consulting technical leader
for the DNA programs at the Idaho Department of Law Enforcement DNA
Laboratory, the San Francisco Crime Laboratory, and the San Diego County
Sheriff ’s Department. Dr. Rudin divides her time among consulting, writing,
and teaching about forensic DNA and forensic science as well as more general
topics in biology. Dr. Rudin has co-authored An Introduction to DNA Forensic
Analysis, a book that has become the preeminent reference for both attorneys
and crime laboratories. She is also the author of the Dictionary of Modern
Biology, Barron’s Educational, 1997. Dr. Rudin teaches a variety of general
forensic and forensic DNA courses for the University of California at Berkeley
Extension and online. She is active as a consultant and expert witness in
forensic DNA for both prosecution and defense.
Please visit the Forensic Education and Consulting Web page at
www.forensicdna.com.
xiii
8127/frame/fm Page xv Monday, July 24, 2000 11:17 AM
Acknowledgments
The seed for this book was planted during the first class we taught at the
University of California at Berkeley Extension when a student asked us how
the principle of transfer applied to physical match evidence. Our search for an
answer to her question led us to propose the new principle of divisible matter,
and subsequently to reexamine the prevailing ideas and conventional wisdom
in forensic science. The constant challenges and critical thinking from our
students comprised the major driving force behind the writing of this book.
We are eternally grateful to Harvey Kane who rescued the proposal for
this book from apparent oblivion and insisted that it was a worthwhile
project. He remains our “Godfather.” Becky McEldowney, who inherited the
responsibility of editor for two demanding and high-maintenance authors,
helped bring the book to fruition. Her patience with our missed deadlines
and at times odd requests is appreciated. Likewise, Andrea Demby, our
project editor, maintained both a sense of perspective and a sense of humor
while expertly guiding us through the details of the publishing process. We
also would like to acknowledge the folks, many of whom we have never even
met, who labor behind the scenes in the CRC production department.
A number of individuals provided material or assistance with specific
items. E.J. Wagner and Peter Martin contributed to the Birmingham Six
sidebar; John Houde provided us with one of the original Locard quotes, and
Sharon Kruzic assisted us with the translation; Elliot Beckleman gave us
permission to reproduce the results chart from one of his cases; Jeff Silvia
and Roger Moore provided us with case transcripts; Ron Linhart and Mark
Stolorow reviewed the Fred Zain sidebar; Duayne Dillon provided assistance
in checking various historical details; John Buckleton gave us permission to
use his “absence of evidence” example previously posted to a mailing list.
Carl Selavka, Greg Matheson, Hiram Evans, Jay Henry, Peter Striupaitis,
Frank Hicks, and Joe Polski assisted us in obtaining permission for the logos
used to illustrate Chapter 12.
Finally, we are especially grateful to Peter Barnett, Ann Bradley, and Ray
Davis who provided both encouragement and a number of suggestions which
significantly improved the manuscript. Any remaining errors are our respon-
sibility alone.
xv
8127/frame/fm Page xvii Monday, July 24, 2000 11:17 AM
Dedication
KPI
NR
xvii
8127/frame/fm Page xix Monday, July 24, 2000 11:17 AM
Table of Contents
1 Introduction 3
xix
8127/frame/fm Page xx Monday, July 24, 2000 11:17 AM
Index 361
8127/frame/ch01 Page 1 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
Section I
Background and History
of Forensic Science
8127/frame/ch01 Page 2 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
Figure 1.1 Physical evidence. Any bit of physical matter can become evidence,
including a puff of smoke, a Mack truck, or a dab of peanut butter. Certain items
are frequently encountered in violent crimes; some are represented in this collage.
8127/frame/ch01 Page 3 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
Introduction
1
Contents
A. Scope and Definitions .............................................................................. 3
1. What Is Forensic Science; Who Is a Forensic Scientist? ................. 4
2. The Science in Forensic Science ....................................................... 5
a. What Is Science?......................................................................... 5
b. Science Is Dynamic .................................................................... 6
c. Science Is Durable...................................................................... 7
d. Forensic Science Is an Applied Science .................................... 7
3. Science Lessons from History........................................................... 8
4. Forensic Science and Criminalistics............................................... 10
5. Physical Evidence: From Art to Science......................................... 12
B. Forensic Science and the Law ................................................................ 15
1. What Is the Question?..................................................................... 15
a. Translating the Legal Question into the Scientific
Question.................................................................................... 15
b. Physical Evidence and Circumstantial Evidence.................... 17
C. Summary ................................................................................................. 18
References ........................................................................................................ 18
I have no data yet. It is a capital mistake to theorize before one has data.
Insensibly one begins to twist facts to suit theories, instead of theories to suit
facts.
Arthur Conan Doyle
—A Scandal in Bohemia
3
8127/frame/ch01 Page 4 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
becomes more litigious, it is not unusual for the court to call upon experts
in the most esoteric of pursuits to provide testimony. While acknowledging
the diversity of expertise that may impinge on legal matters, we will direct
our commentary according to our own area of expertise, the application of
the physical sciences to the solution of crime. Even so, there remains a
discussion of semantics, intent, and, to no small extent, integration of all the
various disciplines that may be called upon in any investigation. Many of the
ideas that we present here most certainly apply to areas beyond strict science,
if for no other reason than the science must integrate with the greater effort
of an investigation. But to begin, we will tackle the classic struggle to define
our territory. Even if you do not agree with the following definitions, at least
you will be able to read the rest of this book without ambiguity.
Introduction 5
a. What Is Science?
Science is the method of study we use in our attempts to understand and
describe the physical universe. We do this by identifying repeating patterns,
either spatial or temporal, and using the pattern data to try to establish
general rules. This is called inductive reasoning — extrapolating from the
specific to the general. If we think we have established a general principle,
we attempt to test that principle by predicting what will happen in a specific
situation. This is an example of deductive reasoning. The scientist obtains
qualitative data by observation and quantitative data by measurement, all in
the attempt to understand and categorize the universe. Although the quan-
titative description of data increasingly dominates our view of science, in no
small part due to advances in measuring instruments, it is important to
understand that both qualitative and quantitative descriptions of data are
useful tools — it all depends on the question (Houck, 1999).
Classical science is defined by the notion of hypothesis testing. In very
simple terms, the scientist proposes a hypothesis, performs experiments to
test the hypothesis, and obtains results that either tend to confirm or inval-
idate the hypothesis. To classify an endeavor as science, one must be able not
only to state a hypothesis, but to imagine a way to test the hypothesis (Popper,
1962). The scientific method provides a framework for hypothesis testing.
In reality, we can never prove that an idea, concept, or theory is true — we
can only fail to prove that it is false. In the absence of information that a
theory is untrue or incorrect, we accept it as correct until new information
is obtained that demonstrates otherwise. Both in science and forensic science,
we frequently have an idea in mind — this bullet came from that gun. This
8127/frame/ch01 Page 6 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
b. Science Is Dynamic
Another common misconception about science is that it embraces immutable
truths. In fact, nothing could be further from reality. At any point in time,
* Much confusion and misunderstanding exists around the idea of the null hypothesis. The
most useful working definition is that the null hypothesis must be falsifiable (Stark, 2000).
When the null hypothesis is disproved by experimentation, we must accept one or more
alternative hypotheses.
8127/frame/ch01 Page 7 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
Introduction 7
science provides us with our best estimate of how the universe works. But
soon enough, an idea or discovery comes along either to refine or to refute
what we once “knew to be true.” This is simply the nature of scientific
discovery; our understanding changes with new information. This revelation
can be somewhat disconcerting to the layperson who perceives that science
can provide hard and fast, black and white, irrefutable answers to questions
about the physical realm. All science can provide is the best answer based on
all the information available at that point in time. This concept becomes
excruciatingly clear in forensic science when newer, more discriminating
techniques are able to distinguish between two items that were previously
indistinguishable using older techniques. One of the best examples of this
concept at work is that of convictions that have been overturned with the
advent of DNA testing. Barring the exceptional case in which an accidental
or malicious error has been committed, the previous work would not be
considered wrong; it is simply that two individuals with, for example, blood
type “O” will likely show different DNA profiles.
c. Science Is Durable
In spite of some well-known historical exceptions (the world is flat, the Earth
is the center of the solar system), most ideas in science tend to change rather
slowly and in small increments. The newer idea is usually a small variation
on the old one and tends to add rather than discard information. Our current
understanding is simply a refinement of the previous concept; one can follow
the evolution of the idea along a logical path. This idea is demonstrated in
forensic science by exactly the same example we used above to demonstrate
that science is dynamic. The methods that were originally used to include
each of these people in a class of individuals who could have perpetrated a
crime did not produce “wrong” results; repeated today (again barring cases
of intentional misrepresentation), they would provide exactly the same
answers. Rather, increasingly discriminating methods of detection enable us
to add knowledge to the previous results, allowing us to refine rather than
refute the answer. The two individuals with blood type “O” would still be
indistinguishable using that test; only with a more discriminating DNA test
are they differentiated. The critical distinction between these two kinds of
tests resides in the limitations inherent in each one. Qualified by the appro-
priate limitations, each conclusion remains valid.
Introduction 9
Sidestepping, for our limited purpose, the larger debate in the scientific
community over Wilson’s sociobiological meaning of consilience (Naess,
1998), we can certainly apply the concept to the interpretation of facts and
analyses in a case investigation. In fact, it is the goal of a criminal inquiry to
provide a reconstruction consistent with all known facts and stated assump-
tions. Additionally, the concept that the simplest explanation is often the best
is not lost in attempting crime reconstruction.*,**
Perhaps, in the end, a more flexible notion of the definition of science
will provide a stronger framework upon which to hang our notion of forensic
science. Although we will be concentrating on the natural sciences, certainly
the ideas we will present may be adopted by any branch of learning willing
to systematize its knowledge and use it to generate fundamental, testable laws
and principles.
* In the 14th century, the British monk and philosopher, William of Occam, argued that
the best explanation of a given phenomenon is generally the simplest, the one with the
fewest assumptions. This principle, called Occam’s razor, was the downfall of the Ptolemaic
model of the solar system in the Middle Ages (Horgan, 1996).
** On the other hand, we have all had the experience that truth is stranger than fiction,
particularly in the context of a criminal case.
8127/frame/ch01 Page 10 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
* In Europe, where the term criminalistics originated, the laboratory’s work may be less
restricted.
8127/frame/ch01 Page 11 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
Introduction 11
* In an interview with John Horgan for The End of Science, Karl Popper insisted that a
scientific theory is an invention, an act of creation as profoundly mysterious as anything
in the arts (Horgan, 1996).
8127/frame/ch01 Page 13 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
Introduction 13
and fibers, and print and impression evidence. Rarely will an analyst be asked
about the fingerprint database on which a conclusion of common source has
been based (Cole, 1998; 1999), or the number or proportion of microscopic
striae that must concord between an evidence and test bullet for the analyst
to conclude that they were fired from the same gun. Some argue that inherent
differences in the nature of each type of evidence preclude a universal statistical
or interpretational model for all physical evidence (Houck, 1999).
An evolving standard for the legal admissibility of scientific evidence has
prompted a review and closer scrutiny of all methods, some of which have
been accepted without question for the last century (Cole, 1998; 1999). While
DNA analysts (recent FBI pronouncements notwithstanding) are expected
to provide an estimated frequency of a genetic profile in the relevant popu-
lation, the print or firearms analyst simply renders an opinion that the
association between evidence and reference is unique. It has been suggested
that comparison evidence might fall within the purview of an acquired skill
or expert opinion. Therefore, examiners should be able to express opinions
of identity without having to provide numeric estimates or systematic scien-
tific justification (Ashbaugh, 1996; Murdock and Biasotti, 1997). Recent court
decisions (Daubert, 1993; Kumho, 1999) that comment directly on the admis-
sibility and definition of scientific evidence, and to what standard it should
be held, have provoked this discussion anew among the forensic community.
Certainly, defining the elements of a valid shoe print or glass fracture
comparison presents a greater challenge than defining the elements of sim-
ilarity necessary for a DNA or solid dose drug analysis. This follows directly
from the nature of the evidence. Shoe wear and breaking glass generate highly
random and complex patterns that may actually require greater expertise, or
at least more experience, to interpret than the much simpler and more
constrained patterns found in a spectrum or autoradiograph. Certainly, some
criminalists debate whether any useful purpose would be served by demand-
ing a more scientific treatment of disciplines that have traditionally relied on
the experience and expertise of each individual examiner (Ashbaugh, 1996;
Murdock and Biasotti, 1997). In a 1997 editorial, John Thornton, one of the
leading forensic minds of our day, wrote, “To master statistical models to
explain much of our evidence may be a slow, reluctant march through enemy
territory, but we must begin to plan for that campaign” (Thornton, 1997).
We agree that, at least for physical evidence, providing a statistical justifica-
tion for the analyst’s opinion should be a goal. This may take different forms
for different evidence; it may be limited for certain types of evidence until
further work is done, and remain limited for some kinds of evidence due to
its nature. However, in our opinion, it is an objective that we should be
actively pursuing. The discussion within the forensic community remains
heated and current.
8127/frame/ch01 Page 15 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
Introduction 15
to proceed. In this setting, the only germane questions are the legal questions.
The role of the forensic scientist is to translate the relevant legal question
into a scientific question. If this cannot be done, then forensic science has
no role to play.
One way the criminalist can assist law enforcement and legal profession-
als is by helping them to translate a legal question correctly (Did O. J.
Simpson kill Ron Goldman and Nicole Brown Simpson?) into a question
that science can answer (What genetic types are found in the bloodstains
from the scene?). The answer to the scientific question will then assist in
answering the legal question. Conversely, one of the most effective counters
to the presentation of physical evidence is to show that the wrong question
was asked. For instance, finding the suspect’s blood on the suspect’s shoes
is irrelevant to whether he attacked the victim. Similarly, the finding of an
unusual collection of fibers on the murder weapon becomes meaningless if
both the suspect and the victim were wearing uniforms composed of the
rare fiber set. Analysis of physical evidence in a crime laboratory is best
suited to answering who, what, where, and how; it is less adept at answering
when and can almost never answer why. Because the design or selection of
appropriate tests depends completely on the initial hypothesis, it must be
carefully framed at the beginning of the investigation rather than on the
witness stand.
It is crucial to note that the moment the question is translated into
science, the component of guilt or innocence is lost. Forensic science seeks
to establish connections (or lack thereof) between evidence and its source,
and secondarily, between items that may be associated by the evidence. Said
in another way, we consider the probability of the evidence in light of com-
peting hypotheses, often the prosecution’s allegation and the defense prop-
osition. Guilt or innocence may only be considered by the legal system and
decided by a judge or jury.
The focus of an analysis and its interpretation are dictated by the cir-
cumstances of the case and the question(s) facing the criminal justice system.
This is the reason the most common and useful answer to any general crim-
inalistics question is, “it depends.” The analysis of a sexual assault case serves
as a good example of this point. Sexual assault, and rape in particular, is
distinguished from other crimes in that it is not necessarily evident by mere
observation that a crime has occurred. We know that if we come home, the
window has been forced open, and our stereo is missing, that a burglary has
taken place. This is generally obvious to any other observer as well. It is rarely
possible to look at a woman or man and determine that she or he has been
raped. The crime of rape can be summarized as the act of sexual intercourse
accomplished through fear or force. Science can assist in substantiating one
of the elements (that of sexual intercourse) by determining that sperm are
8127/frame/ch01 Page 17 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
Introduction 17
present. This, of course, says nothing about the fear or force part. The mean-
ing of the scientific finding may change dramatically depending on the cir-
cumstances of the case.
The use of science in the arena of civil law has grown as pioneering and
developing societies have achieved the economic stability necessary to sup-
port elective activities. Civil litigation almost always concerns money; to
argue about it, one must have both the time and means to do so. Many of
the common areas of civil litigation, such as medical malpractice, money
fraud, and engineering, are outside the scope of this volume. Of the areas of
inquiry shared by criminal and civil investigations, the legal standards obvi-
ously differ, leading to, among other things, different questions, but the
scientific analyses remain the same.
C. Summary
In writing this book, we found that our subject area logically divided itself
into three sections. In Section 1, Background and History of Forensic Science,
we introduce you to definitions and concepts to that we will refer throughout
the book. We also spend some time looking backward to see how the evolu-
tion of forensic science can help us understand the issues we face today. In
Section 2, The Principles of Forensic Science, we introduce you to a unifying
paradigm for thinking about forensic science. Included in this paradigm is
a new principle, divisible matter, that we propose is necessary to invoke the
well-known principle of transfer, attributed to the great forensic scientist
Edmund Locard (Locard, 1920). We also discuss at length the forensic prin-
ciples of identification, classification, individualization, association, and recon-
struction. In Section 3, The Practice of Forensic Science, we address some of
the pragmatic issues facing the criminalist today. We start with recognizing
an item as evidence, progress through analysis and interpretation guidelines,
and finish with a discussion of ethics and accountability. We hope we have
at least intrigued you to read further.
References
Ashbaugh, D. R., Quantitative–Qualitative Friction Ridge Analysis: An Introduction to
Basic and Advanced Ridgeology, CRC Press, Boca Raton, FL, 2000.
Bacon, F., The Great Instauration. Originally published 1620, The Great Instauration
and the New Atlantis, Weinberger, J., Ed. AMH Publishing Co., Arlington
Heights, IL, 1980.
Ceccaldi, P. F., From crime to evidence, Int. Police J., 1974.
Cole, S., Witnessing identification: latent fingerprinting evidence and expert knowl-
edge, Soc. Stud. Sci., 28(5–6), 687, 1998.
Cole, S., What counts for identity? The historical origins of the methodology of latent
fingerprint identification, Sci. Context, 12(1), 139, 1999.
Daubert v. Merrill Dow Pharmaceuticals, 509 U. S., 1993.
Decartes, R. Discourse on Method, 1637.
Doyle, A. C., The Adventures of Sherlock Holmes: A Scandal in Bohemia, The Strand
Magazine, 1891.
Evett, I., What is the probability that this blood came from that person? A meaningful
question? J. Forensic. Sci. Soc., 23, 35, 1983.
Fisher, R. A., The Design of Experiments, Oliver and Boyd, London, 1949.
Hofstadter, D. R., Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid, Basic Books, New
York, 1979.
Horgan, J., The End of Science, Addison-Wesley, New York, 1996.
8127/frame/ch01 Page 19 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
Introduction 19
Houck, M., Statistics and Trace Evidence: The Tyranny of Numbers, Forensic Science
Communications, Federal Bureau of Investigation, Virginia 1(3), 1999, available
at http://www.fbi.gov/programs/lab/fsc/current/houck.htm.
Jones, L. V. and Gabard, C., Scientific Investigation and Physical Evidence; Handbook
for Investigators, Charles C Thomas, Springfield, MA, 1959.
Kumho Tire Co., Ltd., et al. v. Carmichael. 97-1709 U.S., 1999.
Locard, E., L’enquete Criminelle et Les Methodes Scientifique, Ernest Flammarion,
Paris, 1920.
Loftus, E. F., Eyewitness Testimony, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1996.
Maddock, J., No evidence for cold fusion neutrons, Nature, 340, 1989.
Murdock, J. E. and Biasotti, A. A., The scientific basis of firearms and toolmark
identification, in Firearms and Toolmark Identification, in Modern Scientific
Evidence, Faigman, D. L., et al., Eds., West Law, San Francisco, 1997.
Naess, A., Book review, New Scientist, August, 1998.
Neyman, J. and Pearson, E. S. On the use and interpretation of certain test criteria
for purposes of statistical inference, Part I and II, Biometrika, 20, 174–240,
263–294, 1928.
Popper, K. R., Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, Basic
Books, New York, 1962.
Stark, P. B., SticiGui© Glossary of Statistical Terms, 2000, available at
http://www.stat.berkeley.edu/~stark/SticiGui/Text/gloss.htm#n.
Taroni, F., Champod, C., and Margot, P., Forerunners of Bayesianism in early forensic
science, Jurimetrics J., 38, 183–200, 1998.
Thornton, J., The DNA statistical paradigm vs. everything else, correspondence,
J. Forensic Sci., 42(4), 758, 1997.
Van Heerden, T. J., Criminalistics, University of South Africa, Muakleneuk, Pretoria,
1982.
Webster’s Encyclopedic Unabridged Dictionary of the English Language, Gramercy
Books, New York, 1996.
Williams, E. W., Modern Law Enforcement and Police Science. Charles C. Thomas,
Springfield, MA, 1967.
Wilson, E.O., Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge, Knopf, New York, 1998.
8127/frame/ch01 Page 20 Friday, July 21, 2000 11:32 AM
References
Preface
even along the same hair, and that hairs from different
people can look
ize.* This was not true when the first few single-locus
RFLP probes came
b. Nonbiological Evidence
3. Identification
would be it.
4. Association
is the man who smashed window X); (3) offense (e.g., Mr. A
committed the
broken glass item; Mr. A did not smash the window; another
person com
5. Reconstruction
Sidebar 3
engine and the first few cars emerged from the south side
of the tunnel; the mail car was halfway out,
and the passenger and baggage cars remained in the tunnel.
The bomb, planted in the mail car and
just outside the southern end of the tunnel, they found the
remains of a detonator with two batteries
a tree (his right side would be facing the tree, and the
wood chips would fly in), the wear on the left
side pockets, and his observation that the overall had been
buttoned exclusively from the left side.
sons, Roy and Ray (who were twins), and Hugh. The elder
D’Autrement recounted that his sons had
vanished the day before the train was held up. His
description of Roy appeared to coincide with
Ohio steel mill where they had been working under false
names. Hugh was tried first, and convicted,
1. Continuing Themes
these concerns.
Fisher, 1992.
2. Marking it correctly.
4. Preventing contamination.
c. Is Criminalistics a Profession?
E. Summary
Locard, E., Dust and its analysis, Police J., 1, 177, 1928.
Section 2
The Principles of
Forensic Science c r i m
c r
i m
e c r i m e c r i m e c r i m e c r i m e c r i m e c r i m
e c r i m e c r i m e c r i m e C R I M E G e n e r a t i o
n o f E v i d e n c e P r a c t i c e o f F o r e n s i c S
c i e n c e D i v i s i b l e M a t t e r T r a n s f e r T
r a n s f e r A P P E A R A N C E C O M P O S I T I O N S O
U R C E E V E N T C O N T A C T S u s p e c t V i c t i m W
i t n e s s e s S c e n e e v i d e n c e c o l l e c t i o
n ( m a t t e r ) ( t r a i t s ) A s s o c i a t i o n C l
a s s i f i c a t i o n R e c o n s t r u c t i o n I n d i
v i d u a l i z a t i o n I d e n t i f i c a t i o n R e c
o g n i t i o n
3 3. Overview — A Unifying
Paradigm of Forensic Science
Section III
The Practice of
Forensic Science
not. Which rows have matching shapes and which rows have no
repeated figures?
9 9. Good Laboratory Practice
—Establishing Validity and
Reliability
Reproduced from:
16. Regard and respect their peers with the same standards
that they hold for themselves.
17. Set a reasonable fee for services if it is appropriate
do so however, no services shall ever be rendered on a
contingency fee basis.
Appendix D
Preamble
P E