COOTER, R. - The Falcon's Gyre
COOTER, R. - The Falcon's Gyre
2014
Recommended Citation
Cooter, Robert, "The Falcon's Gyre: Legal Foundations of Economic Innovation and Growth" (2014). Berkeley Law Books. Book 1.
http://scholarship.law.berkeley.edu/books/1
This Book is brought to you for free and open access by Berkeley Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Berkeley Law Books
by an authorized administrator of Berkeley Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected].
The Falcon’s Gyre
Legal Foundations of Economic Innovation and Growth
Version 1.4
The Falcon’s Gyre
Legal Foundations of Economic Innovation and Growth
Robert Cooter
with Aaron Edlin
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/legalcode
http://works.bepress.com/robert_cooter/
This book available electronically through the Berkeley Law Scholarship Repository
http://scholarship.law.berkeley.edu/books/1/
Contents
viii Acknowledgements
ix Preface
Chapter 1. Overtaking
1.6 Innovation
1.9 Depletion
1.11 Freedom
1.13 Welfare
1.16 Conclusion
Chapter 2. Ventures
2.2 Life-Cycle of a Business Venture
2.4 Imitators or Enthusiasts?
2.8 Rate of Innovation
2.9 Conclusion
2.11 Appendix
Chapter 3. The Double Trust Dilemma
3.5 Relationships
3.7 Private Law
3.9 Public Law
3.11 Three Stages of Finance in Silicon Valley
3.13 Small and Large Firms
3.15 Ontogeny Recapitulates Philogeny
3.17 Conclusion
Chapter 4. Separation
4.2 Paradox of Growth
4.4 Producer’s Market Power
4.6 Innovator’s Market Power
4.8 Conclusion
Chapter 5. Fertility
5.5 Applying the Fertility Principle
5.7 Bargaining and Transaction Costs
5.10 Conclusion
5.11 Appendix: Welfare Triangles
Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
6.2 Strength
6.5 How Strong?
6.7 Applications
6.8 Reach: Invention or Discovery
6.10 Breadth
6.13 Duration
6.16 Optimal Remedy
6.20 Thickets and Holdup
6.23 Middlemen and Trolls
6.24 Conclusion
Acknowledgements
For the best feast, the host who supplies the main course should ask each
guest to contribute a dish. I have supplied the main course to the table of
my scholarship and many others have contributed their ideas. Most im-
portant, Aaron Edlin provided fundamental ideas and criticism, especially
to the initial chapters of this book where he is credited. I would also like
to thank Blair Dean Cooter, Robert Litan, Brian Broughman, Merritt Fox,
Robert Atiah, George Geis, Steve Maurer, Patrick Goold, and Tal Niv. Tech-
nical support was proved by the Berkeley Law School library and the Berke-
ley Electronic Press. Financial support and encouragement were provided
by The Kauffman Foundation, The Humboldt Prize, the Mercatus Center
and the Law and Economics Program at George Mason University, and the
Berkeley Law School
Preface
After years of parish work, a Catholic priest sat up in bed one morning and
thought, “Maybe the Pope is wrong and Buddha is right.” After years of
teaching and writing about economic efficiency and the law, I sat up in bed
one morning and thought, “Maybe efficiency is wrong and innovation is
right.” The effects on human welfare from inventing the tractor far exceed
the effects from more efficient allocation of horses. Innovation causes com-
pound growth that swamps static inefficiency like a tsunami swamps a scow.
These facts compelled me to rethink previous work on law and economics,
including my own.
The state provides infrastructure on which the economy runs. The materi-
al infrastructure includes roads and the institutional infrastructure includes
laws. Smooth roads and good laws sustain the economy. Law and efficien-
cy economics explains how law improves resource allocations. Its practical
usefulness, systematic consistency, and even its intellectual beauty, have in-
fluenced America legal scholarship. By contrast, law and growth economics
must explain how law increases economic innovation. Its potential useful-
ness potentially exceeds law and static economics, but, in its current state of
underdevelopment, it lacks systematic consistency or intellectual beauty.
Chapter 1. Overtaking1
Robert Cooter and Aaron Edlin
Robert Lucas, the economist who won the Nobel prize in 1995, famously
commented, “Once one starts to think about economic growth, it is hard to
think about anything else.” Compared to sustained growth, other sources of
national wealth are insignificant. Compounded over a century, 2% annual
growth (roughly the growth rate of the US economy in the last century) in-
creases wealth by more than 7 times, and 10% annual growth (roughly the
growth rate of the Chinese economy from 1980 to 2010) increases wealth
by almost 14,000 times.2 People systematically underestimate the effects of
compound growth, like thinking that a 5% increase in height is the same for
a teenager and a toddler.
1 This chapter draws on Robert Cooter and Aaron Edlin, “Overtaking,” in The American Illness:
Essays on the Rule of Law, ed. Frank Buckley (Yale University Press, forthcoming), and “Maximizing
Growth vs. Static Efficiency or Redistribution,” working paper, Berkeley Economics Department.
2 Here’s a table of size reached by an economy that starts at 1 and grows at various rates and years.*
Growth
1 year 5 years 10 years 25 years 50 years 100 years
rate
0% 1.00 1.00 1.00 1.00 1.00 1.00
0.5% 1.005 1.01 1.05 1.13 1.28 1.65
1% 1.01 1.05 1.10 1.25 1.64 2.70
2% 1.02 1.10 1.22 1.64 2.69 7.24
5% 1.05 1.28 1.63 3.39 11.47 131.50
10% 1.10 1.61 2.59 10.83 117.39 13,780.61
*size of economy = (1+r/100)t, where r=percentage growth rate, and t=years of growth
1.1
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 1: Overtaking
than Sweden’s, yet by 2004 Argentina’s per capita income had dropped to 43
percent of Sweden’s.
3
1.2
Robert Cooter
4 Joke: “Economists need a graph to reach the wrong conclusions with certainty, whereas lawyer
can do so immediately.
1.3
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 1: Overtaking
An economy produces different goods like houses, clothes, books, and clean
water. The usual measure of economic growth is the increase in wealth (a
stock) or income (a flow). To measure wealth or income, economists com-
bine different goods into comprehensive aggregates, such as gross national
product (GNP). To combine heterogeneous goods, economists first weight
quantities of goods by their market prices. Economists ideally adjust market
prices for unpriced externalities such as the social cost of pollution. Com-
prehensive measures of wealth or income include externalities, and also pub-
lic goods such as national security and air quality. To get closer to human
welfare, economists measure consumption instead of wealth or income, and
they divide the total by the number of people.5 Later we consider more con-
troversial measures, specifically utility and social welfare.
The vertical axis in Figure 1.2 is unlabeled because the measure of growth
-- total or per capita wealth, income, consumption, utility, or welfare – mat-
ters little to our conclusions. For all economic measures, exponential growth
1.4
Robert Cooter
Besides prioritizing dynamic over static effects, the overtaking principle pri-
oritizes some dynamic paths over others. Thus in Figure 1.3, the growth-
path of income or wealth represented by D is unambiguously better than
the growth-path represented by E, because D starts higher and grows faster
than E. The analysis is different, however, when comparing E and F. F starts
lower than E, grows faster, and overtakes E at t*. If overtaking occurs rapidly,
then t* is small and nothing matters except growth. If, however, overtaking
occurs slowly, then t* is large and static effects of efficiency and redistribution
matter. Thus F is better or worse than E depending on the rate of growth.
The measure of growth seldom changes these conclusions because different
measures have similar overtaking times.
In contrast, the overtaking principle loses much of its normative appeal when
growth and overtaking is slow. Thus interpret E and F as two sequences of
consumption in an infinite number of generations. In the first sequence E,
1.5
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 1: Overtaking
Innovation
Economic theory ascribes long run growth to three broad factors: physical
capital (buildings and machines), human capital (work adjusted for the skills
people bring to their jobs), and “innovation”. An increase in these factors
increases income and wealth. MIT economist Robert Solow won the Nobel
Prize partly for showing that innovation was more important to growth in
the 1950s in the United States than increased physical or human capital.
Subsequent empirical work by Edward Denison, Robert Barro, and others
confirmed this finding for other developed economies.7 In the last 100 years,
innovation caused more economic growth than anything else, including us-
ing more resources.
Innovations use new ideas to produce goods cheaper or to make better goods.
The supply curve shows the cost of making a good,8 so a cost-reducing inno-
6 Utilitarians often hold that future utility should not be discounted, whereas future income
should be discounted by its marginal utility. In this view, utility is what discounts money, but there
is nothing to discount utility. For a justification of not discounting future utility or welfare, see
Derek Parfit & Tyler Cowen, Against the Social Discount Rate, in Justice Between Age Groups and
Generations (Peter Laslett & Fishkin eds., 1992).
7 Add citations.
8 The supply curve is a monotonic relationship between price and quantity. Inferring from a
price to a quantity, the supply curve shows the quantity that a firm or industry will supply at a given
price. Conversely, inferring from a quantity to a price, the supply curve shows the cost for a firm or
industry to supply a given quantity.
1.6
Robert Cooter
vation shifts the supply curve down, as when the tractor replaced the horse
for plowing. In Figure 1.4, innovation shifts the supply curve from S to S`,
and the shaded area indicates the social value of the savings in cost from pro-
ducing the quantity x of the good.
9 Like the supply curve, the demand curve is a monotonic relationship between price and quan-
tity. Inferring from a price to a quantity, the demand curve shows the quantity that consumers will
buy at a given price. Conversely, inferring from a quantity to a price, the demand curve shows the
price that consumers are willing to pay for a given quantity.
1.7
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 1: Overtaking
from D to D`, and the shaded area indicates the social value of the improve-
ment in quality from producing the quantity x of the good.
When one person uses a scarce resource, others cannot use it, like taking a
bite from a sandwich. Scarce resources like capital and labor have rival uses.
In contrast, when one person uses an idea, just as much remains for someone
else to use. Thus architects have used the Pythagorean Theorem for over two
millennia and just as much remains as before. Using theorems, principles,
natural laws, designs, discoveries, expressions, and compositions does not use
them up. Economists call this property “nonrivalry”. Furthermore, when
one person uses an idea, preventing others from doing so is difficult, more
difficult than preventing someone from trespassing on your land or taking a
bite from your sandwich. Ideas spread like gossip in Puddletown. Econo-
mists call this property “non-exclusion.”10
10 In economics, non-rivalry and non-exclusion define “public goods” like national security and
air quality, which resemble ideas in these two traits.
1.8
Robert Cooter
“Nonrivalry” and “non-exclusion” are good news about ideas, and here is
even better news: ideas are fertile like seeds, not dead like coal. 2,500 years
after its proof, generalizations of the Pythagorean Theorem continue to ex-
pand geometry’s power.11 Similarly, the number of transistors that can be
placed inexpensively on an integrated circuit has doubled approximately ev-
ery two years for the past fifty years (Moore’s law). Ideas about transistors are
so fertile that innovation grows exponentially.
Depletion
Although the signs are good, the future remains in doubt until it arrives. A
worrisome doubt concerns resource exhaustion and environmental degrada-
tion. Must depletion of resources eventually end growth? Some resources
renew like a forest, river, or wheat. Use does not necessarily reduce their stock
permanently because we replenish it. Instead of renewing, however, other re-
sources deplete, like oil and iron. Use depletes their stock because we do not
11 The theorem says, “The square of the hypotenuse of a right triangle is equal to the sum of the
squares on the other two sides.” The fascinating story of the proof of its generalization in n-dimen-
sions is told in Simon Singh’s book, Fermat’s Enigma: The Epic Quest to Solve the World’s Greatest
Mathematical Problem (New York, etc.: Doubleday, Anchor Book, 1998).
12 For a survey of technologies where that great abundance is the future, see Peter H. Diaman-
dis & Steven Kotler, Abundance: The Future Is Better Than You Think (2012).
1.9
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 1: Overtaking
know how to replenish it. Whereas fertile ideas increase with use, depletable
resources diminish with use.
1.10
Robert Cooter
Freedom
Every youth who watches the Olympics fantasizes standing on the central
platform with a gold medal while the national anthem plays. In wealth as
in sports, individuals and nations hope to surpass others and fear being sur-
passed by them. Like the Olympics, the value of winning the race for wealth
or income is self-evident to many people. If you are one of them, facts cited
above provide ample motivation to study law and growth economics.
Other readers of this book, however, will want moral or political justification
for focusing on the growth of wealth. Wealth and income are means for buy-
ing goods, not ends in themselves like beauty, love, holiness, knowledge, or
self-fulfillment.13 Accumulating wealth only to misuse it is a labor of shame.
Is the nation that wins the growth race like the winner of the pie-eating
contest whose prize is another pie? Does studying growth turn wealth into a
fetish like falling in love with a shoe?
13 The champion of this view in development economics is Amartya Sen, as two quotes suggest.
“Economic growth cannot be sensibly treated as an end in itself. Development has to be more con-
cerned with enhancing the lives we lead and the freedoms we enjoy.” Development as Freedom
(New York: Knopf, 1999), 14. “The challenge of development . . . is to improve the quality of life.
Especially in the world’s poor countries, a better quality of life generally calls for higher incomes—
but it involves much more. It encompasses as ends in themselves better education, higher standards
of health and nutrition, less poverty, a cleaner environment, more quality of opportunity, greater
individual freedom, and a richer cultural life.” World Bank, World Development Report 1991
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1991). Note that governments supply many non-market
goods, and GDP measures their value by their cost (e.g. salaries paid to civil servants), not by their
benefits to the citizens. Cost-benefit analysis can measure some of these non-market values more
convincingly. To measure the value of non-market goods, economists try to find out how much peo-
ple would pay for them if they had to pay, given that they don’t have to pay. This can be a measure-
ment maelstrom, so national accounting limits its use of cost-benefit analysis. For the relationships
between happiness and money, see B. S.Frey and A. Stutter (2002), “What Can Economists Learn
from Happiness Research?” Journal of Economic Literature.
1.11
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 1: Overtaking
One justification for focusing on wealth and income concerns freedom. Like
driving a car, most people think that they are good at spending money, in
spite of occasional lapses such as purchasing uncomfortable shoes. People
know what they want to buy, and they criticize what others buy. A liberal
education should help you to think critically about what is worth buying. To
critique the uses of wealth, intellectuals draw on traditions in philosophy and
religion concerning what is really good, as opposed to what seems good. Thus
intellectuals in the university often carp about strip malls, popular movies,
fried food, ostentatious furniture, pay-day loans, and television preachers.
Most economists, however, refrain from debate about what people ought to
want. By doing so, economists cultivate neutrality in controversies about the
values of consumers. Instead of embracing a particular conception of good-
ness, economists often accept “consumer sovereignty” – the right of consum-
ers to buy what they want. Consumer sovereignty implies the right to buy
things that are good or bad, just as free speech implies the right to say things
that are true or false. I may disagree with what you buy and defend your right
to buy it, just as I may disagree with what you say and defend your right to
say it.14
1.12
Robert Cooter
Welfare
Increasing negative and positive freedom is an appropriate goal for econo-
mists in a democratic state. Increasing freedom, however, is not the usual
justification given by economists for increasing wealth. Economists usually
justify increasing wealth as the means to increase the welfare of people. The
normative branch of economics connects wealth to welfare, rather than con-
necting wealth to freedom. In the history of economics, the philosophy of
utilitarianism was central to connecting wealth to welfare, especially in 19th
and early 20th century England.16 Utilitarians equate individual welfare with
a person’s utility, and they equate social welfare with the sum of individual
utilities. In notation, SW= u1+u2+…+un. Instead of thinking of social welfare
as a sum of individual utilities, however, modern economists think of it as an
increasing function of individual utilities: SW = f(u1, u2,…, un).17 The func-
tion may be additive as with utilitarianism, or it may be non-additive, such as
multiplicative (SW= u1×u2×…×un) or logarithmic (SW= log u1 + log u2+…+
log un). From a mathematical viewpoint, the social welfare function general-
izes utilitarianism,18 and different forms of the function have different ethical
consequences for equality.19
16 Economic theory assumed its recognizably modern mathematical form when theorists
understood that equating marginal benefits and marginal costs maximizes utility. This recognition
joined Newton’s calculus and the philosophy of utilitarianism and. See the “marginalist revolution”
in economics as discussed in the classic by Joseph A. Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis
(1986).
17 “Utility” is a notoriously elusive concept that pervades economic theory. For a discussion of its
various meanings, see…
18 The concept of social welfare as a function of individual utility was introduced by Abram Berg-
son, A Reformulation of Certain Aspects of Welfare Economics, Quarterly Journal of Economics
310–34 (1938). All forms of the social welfare function, additive or non-additive, assume that social
welfare increase with individual utility. For a recent discussion of social welfare that is deep but
challenging to read, see Matthew Adler, Well Being and Fair Distribution (2012).
19 Summing utilities gives the same weight to utility regardless of its distribution among persons.
Thus, in a society of 5 people, social welfare is the same as measured by the sum of utilities if 5
people each enjoy 10 utils, or if one person enjoys 50 utils and the other 4 get 0 utils. In contrast,
social welfare is higher for the multiplicative or logarithmic social welfare functions if 5 people enjoy
10 utils than if one person enjoys 50 utils and the other 4 get 0 utils. In general, the additive form
of SWF is indifferent about the distribution of a fixed amount of utility across people, whereas the
multiplicative and logarithmic forms favor its equal distribution across people. Note, however, that
all three forms of SWF favor a more equal distribution of a fixed amount of income across people, so
long as the marginal utility of money is decreasing for all individuals. The most sophisticated treat-
ment of this problem, which is also challenging to read, is found in Matthew Adler, Well Being
and Fair Distribution (2012).
1.13
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 1: Overtaking
People agree about some connections between wealth and welfare. Thus life
expectancy at birth is 83 years in Japan and 66 years in Bangladesh,20 and
enrollment in secondary school is 98 percent among Japanese children of the
appropriate age and 42 percent in Bangladesh.21 Facts like these make almost
everyone agree that welfare is higher in Japan than Bangladesh. The poor in
Bangladesh need extra money to buy basic health care and primary education
more than the rich in Japan need extra money to buy cosmetic surgery and
theater tickets. In general, the poor need extra money for necessities more
than the rich need extra money for luxuries.
Perhaps comparing the marginal utility of income of rich and poor is like
distinguishing between your face and the back of your head: the difference
is real but the boundary is imprecise. In this respect, “social welfare” may
be like other values that social scientists measure in controversial ways, such
as “happiness”23. If so, economists can talk meaningful about the declining
marginal utility of income, but they will never find a uniquely correct mea-
sure of it. According to this view, economics must encompass controversial
20 Life expectancy at birth, total (years)) in 2008, World Bank. http://data.worldbank.org/
indicator/SP.DYN.LE00.IN. Note that life expectancy is in the 40s in many African countries.
21 Data & Statistics on Education for 2007 and 2008, World Bank, http://web.worldbank.
org/WBSITE/EXTERNAL/TOPICS/EXTEDUCATION/0,,contentMDK:20573961~menuP-
K:282404~pagePK:148956~piPK:216618~theSitePK:282386,00.html.
22 The utility of a poor person increases more from an increase in wealth than the utility of a rich
person (decreasing marginal utility of money. Social welfare increases in the utility of individuals.
Therefore, redistribution of wealth from rich to poor (with no loss in the amount of wealth) increases
social welfare. In Adler’s theory (see preceding footnote), social welfare increases with individual
wealth, and social welfare increases with a more equal distribution of wealth or utility across individ-
uals.
23 See Bruno S. Frey & Alois Stutzer, What Can Economists Learn from Happiness Research?,
Journal of Economic Literature (2002). Also see Daniel Kahneman & Richard Thaler, Utility
Maximization and Experienced Utility, 20 Journal of Economic Perspectives 221–234 (2006).
1.14
Robert Cooter
measures of imprecise facts. Thus the “material welfare” school of the early
20th century held that additional money benefits the poor more than the
rich, which can be shown by measures of the causes of welfare like health and
education that are reasonable, pragmatic, and incomplete.24
In any case, measuring social welfare and the declining marginal utility of
money is less important to growth economics than to static economics.
When progressive taxation and state spending shift consumption from lux-
uries to necessities, the static effects – whether measured in wealth, income,
utility, or welfare for the poor or everyone in society – correspond to the shift
in Figure 1.2 from A to B, or from B to C. The static effects are small relative
to the dynamic effects represented by D, regardless of how they are mea-
sured. When growth is exponential, the mathematics of overtaking applies,
regardless of the function’s interpretation in Figure 1.2. Measuring utility or
welfare is unimportant to policy conclusions when fast growth causes rapid
overtaking, whereas the measure is important when sluggish growth causes
slow overtaking.
To illustrate, assume that redistributive policies improve the health and edu-
cation of the poor, which directly increase their welfare. In addition, health-
ier workers with better education are more creative, so they may increase
economic growth. Economists who believe that better education and health
of poor Americans would increase U.S. growth point to Denmark and Korea
as examples where good education and health have contributed to robust
24 For an account of the material welfare school and its tension with scarcity economics, see Rob-
ert Cooter & Peter Rappoport, Were the Ordinalists Wrong About Welfare Economics?, 22 J.Economic
Literature 507 (1984).
1.15
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 1: Overtaking
economic growth, whereas poor education and health of workers may partly
explains the economic struggles of the Philippines.
Conclusion
The first question of law and growth economics is, “Which laws increase the
pace of economic innovation?” Increasing the pace of innovation can lead
to sustained growth in wealth, income, utility, and welfare. When growth is
rapid, overtaking is the only normative standard required to choose among
many laws and policies. Balancing growth against static efficiency or equality
is unnecessary when growth is fast, which simplifies the analysis of many laws
and policies such as patents. Isaac Newton invented calculus and discovered
the laws of motion associated with gravity in 1666, which historians of sci-
ence call the “miracle year” (“annus mirabilis”). Civil engineers still use New-
tonian physics for ordinary objects, although it fails for very large objects
(the cosmos) and very small objects (sub-atomic particles). Similarly, rapid
growth is the domain of the overtaking principle, which is good for making
1.16
Robert Cooter
The overtaking principle also challenges ethical theories concerning the re-
distribution of wealth. Controversies about fair distribution, social welfare,
the marginal utility of income, and time-discounting do not matter when
growth is rapid. In much of political philosophy, fairness concerns distrib-
uting shares of fixed income, and economic equality is an end in itself. With
rapid growth, however, putative ends turn out to be only valuable as means.
Economic equality mostly affects welfare through growth, not in its own
right. When rapid growth is possible, progressive taxes and state expendi-
tures increase the welfare of the poor if they cause faster growth in wages and
subsidies.
Perhaps you think that static efficiency and growth align, with more efficien-
cy causing faster growth. This view is roughly two-thirds right and one-third
wrong. Efficiency and growth have a common cause: competition. To
maximize innovation, the law must create a framework of open competition
so innovators can develop their ideas. The core of economic growth comes
from entrepreneurs. Only the possibility of extraordinary profits can induce
entrepreneurs to bet big on risky ideas. However, extraordinary profits re-
quire market power, not competition. Thus patent law creates open compe-
tition to innovate and rewards the winners by giving them temporary market
power. As told in this book, the story of law and growth economics is open
competition to innovate and extra-ordinary profits for the winners.
Astronomers from the time of Aristotle saw the earth as the center of the
universe and the sun revolving around it, until the Copernican Revolution
put the sun at the center. In general, a revolution rearranges the central
1.17
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 1: Overtaking
25 This is the thesis of the classic by Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolu-
tions (1st ed. 1962).
26 Lionel Robbins, An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. (London:
McMillan, 1932),page 16.
27 For a discussion of the paradigm shift, see Robert Cooter and Peter Rappoport, “Were the
Ordinalists Wrong About Welfare Economics?,” J.Economic Literature 22 (1984): 507.
1.18
Robert Cooter
Chapter 2. Ventures1
Robert Cooter and Aaron Edlin
Similarly, an engineer in Silicon Valley in 1985 has an idea for a new com-
puter technology. The engineer cannot patent the idea until he develops it.
Developing it requires more money than the engineer can risk personally. He
drafts a business plan, meets with a small group of investors, and explains
his idea to them. Developing the idea is inherently risky— someone might
steal the idea before it is patented, an unknown competitor might patent the
invention first, the invention might not work, or it might work but not sell.
If the plan succeeds, however, the innovators will make a fortune. The inves-
tors agree to form a company and develop the product. Unlike so many oth-
er start-ups, this one succeeds after two years and the firm acquires a valuable
patent. The company sells the product to an established firm and divides the
proceeds between the engineer and the investors. The success of the venture
attracts imitators. Production and sale of the invention eventually becomes
a normal business with moderate risk and ordinary profits.
2.1
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 2: Ventures
3 A production function determines outputs from inputs, such as y=f(k,l) where the output is y
and the inputs are capital k and labor l. In a competitive equilibrium, the price of output y equals its
marginal social value. So the marginal value product of an input, say capital k, equals pf1. A business
venture at time t in its life-cycle has an expected profit function πt determined by the probable payoffs
as a function of future investment of k and l. As explain in Chapter 1, the social value of alternative
business ventures is compared by the contributions to growth. According to the overtaking principle,
one business venture that increases the sustained rate of growth relative to another business venture
is much more socially valuable, perhaps infinitely so.
4 Perfect competition drives the prices of all goods to their cost of production. Profits are zero
after including the cost of capital in the other costs of production. The cost of capital equals the
ordinary rate of profit in alternative uses.
2.2
Robert Cooter
2.3
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 2: Ventures
Figure 2.1 indicates the benefits and cost of the venture to its owners. What
about its benefits and costs to society? As conventionally measured, the net
social benefits from a successful business ventures equal the sum of innova-
tor’s profits, profits of other firms such as imitators’, and the consumer’s sur-
plus.5 The innovator’s profits are a small fraction of the net social benefits.
The richest innovators get less wealth for themselves than the value that their
innovations convey to consumers and other producers. Thus the wealth that
Apple investors obtained from the iPhone is less than the value of the iPhone
to consumers and other firms that imitate it or create applications for it. In
the appendix to this chapter, Tables 2.1 and 2.1 use numbers to illustrate the
venture depicted in Figure 2.1,
Production of the improved widget will continue beyond time 4 under con-
ditions approximating perfect competition until the product becomes obso-
lete. The product becomes obsolete when a new innovation destroys the old
one’s value and the industry begins a new cycle of innovation. When ventures
like the one in Figure 2.1 repeat themselves, one innovation follows another,
and the path of net social benefits traces a gyre like the falcon on this book’s
cover. In the appendix, Figure 2.4 traces the gyre of net social benefits from
a numerical example.
Imitators or Enthusiasts?
Figure 2.1 depicts a profitable venture, but most ventures fail and lose mon-
ey. Recent U.S. data suggests that 40% of new businesses survive and 60%
disappear within four years.6 Figure 2.3 depicts a losing venture. The in-
novator in Figure 2.2 spends 8 in period 1 to develop the product. Many
innovations fail before completing development and beginning production,
without recouping any development costs. The innovator in Figure 2.3,
however, is a little more successful and brings the product to market. When
the innovation is launched in period 2, the innovator has no competitors and
enjoys profits of 7. The only difference between Figures 2.1 and 2.3 is in pe-
5 See appendix to Chapter 1. Recall that the consumer surplus equals the difference between what
the good is worth to consumers and what they must pay for it, or the difference between the wili-
ness-to-pay and the market price.
6 44% of U.S. businesses started in the 1990s still existed 4 years afterwards. See Knap, A. E. (2005).
“Survival and longevity in the Business Employment Dynamics data.” Bureau of Labor Statistics of
the U.S. Department of Labor. The number given by Dun and Bradstreet is 37% as cited in “Some of
the Reasons Why Business Fail and How to Avoid Them,” Entrepreneur Weekly, Issue 36, 3-10-96.
2.4
Robert Cooter
2.5
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 2: Ventures
The innovator sometimes has the advantage as in Figure 2.1, and the imitator
sometimes has the advantage as in Figure 2.2. If the innovator in period 0
can foresee that the venture will have a net payoff of +3 as in Figure 2.1, it
will launch the venture. The expectation of positive venture profits causes the
development of innovations. If the innovator in period 0 can foresee that
the venture will have a net payoff of -1 as in Figure 2.2, it will not launch the
venture. The expectation of negative venture profits prevents the develop-
ment of innovations.
The law of trade secrets helps innovators to keep their secrets private. A per-
son who violates these laws by distributing proprietary information is liable
for the harm done to the firm with the secret. When firms in Silicon Valley
hire employees or discuss collaboration with other firms, they routinely sign
non-disclosure agreements (NDAs) in which they promise not to reveal any
secrets that they learn about the company. Sometimes trade secrets laws
work -- the recipe for Coca Cola has remained a secret for decades. More
2.6
Robert Cooter
often, trade secret law is ineffective. Trade secrets laws are hard to enforce in
Silicon Valley and they are unenforced in much of the world.7
An invention is likely to become a standard if its value for each user increases
as the number of its users increases. The uncompensated benefit that one
user conveys to another is a “positive externality.” The joint operation of the
positive externalities is a “network effect.”
The three sources of extraordinary profits for innovators are secrecy, intellec-
tual property, and natural monopoly. Some innovators enjoy extraordinary
profits from all three sources. Thus Microsoft cloaks the core code of Win-
7 Yuval Feldman, Confidential Know-how Sharing and Trade-secrets Laws: Studying the Interac-
tion Between Legality, Social Norms and Justice Among High-tech Employees in Silicon Valley (PhD
Thesis, Law School, University of California at Berkeley, 2004.
In addition, patents and copyright give innovators a temporary monopoly by law. An effective patent
gives the inventor monopoly profits until the patent expires or new inventions undermines its value.
To illustrate numerically, consider how A’s profits in Figure 1.5 might change if A holds an effective
patent to its innovation that lasts for periods 1 and 2. If A refuses to license the innovation to anyone,
it enjoys monopoly profits of 10 in time 1 as indicated in Figure 1.5. Assume that the patent extends
through time 2 and that competitors make little progress circumventing the patent by their own inno-
vations. In time 2, A enjoys profits much like in time 1, say, profits of 9. Thus the patent increases A’s
earnings net of development costs for all periods from 6 to 13. Later chapters contain more details
about intellectual property, including patents and copyright.
2.7
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 2: Ventures
Rate of Innovation
The expectation of positive profits launches innovative ventures, and the ex-
pectation of negative prevents innovative ventures. Law affects the profit-
ability of all phases of a venture -- finance, development, marketing, and
competition. When better law makes innovations more profitable, the num-
ber of innovations increases. To see why, think of an array of new ideas that
differ according to the expected profitability of developing them. Innovators
develop the ideas that they expect to yield positive profits, and they do not
develop the ideas that they expect to yield negative profits. If better law
increases the expected profits for innovations, some ventures will tip from
negative to positive expected profits, so innovators will develop more ideas.
Figure 2.3 depicts this fact. The horizontal axis indicates an industry’s array
of possible innovations in order of profitability, with higher profit ventures
farther to the left and lower profit ventures farther to the right. Figure 2.3
distinguishes between profits under bad and good law. An innovation’s prof-
itability under bad law equals the difference between its revenues R and costs
C over the venture’s life. To the left of I, revenues R exceed costs C, so the
innovations will be developed. To the right of I, costs C exceed revenues R,
so the innovations will not be developed. The revenue curve R intersects
the cost curve C at point I where venture profits are zero (development costs
before launch equal profits after launch). I is the tipping point that indicates
the number of developed innovations under bad law.
2.8
Robert Cooter
Conclusion
Chapter 1 posed the first question of law and growth economics: “Which
laws increase the pace of economic innovation?” Chapter 2 simply answers,
“The laws that increase venture profits.” Fleshing out this answer requires the
rest of this book. First we must look inside the business venture. The next
2.9
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 2: Ventures
chapter explains how law enables individuals with different interests to give
their ideas and money to innovative ventures with shared goals.
2.10
Robert Cooter
Appendix
Table 2.1 uses numbers to illustrate the business venture in Figure 2.1. As-
sume that the innovator develops an innovation that lowers the cost and
improves the quality of a particular consumer good – say, a better widget.
At time 0, before development of a better widget, widget makers earn zero
profit and consumers enjoy a surplus of So. At time 1, development of the
improved widget costs the innovator -8. At time 2 when the improved wid-
get is launched, the innovator has lower production costs, so the innovator
enjoys extraordinary profits of 7 temporarily. Informed consumers buy the
improved widget and enjoy its higher quality, so the consumer’s surplus rises
to So+10. At time 3, some imitators partially succeed in replicating the in-
novation. This competition drives the price down, the innovator’s profits fall
to 4 at time 3, and the imitators enjoy profits of 2. The fall in price causes
the consumer’s surplus to increase by 30, and the rise in average quality of
widgets causes the consumer’s surplus to increase by 3. At time 4, compe-
tition drives the price down to the cost of production, so the innovator and
imitators receive zero profits. The fall in price causes the consumer’s surplus
to increase by 70, and the rise in average quality causes the consumer’s sur-
plus to increase by 10. Summing over the life cycle in Table 2.1, the venture
profits are 3 and the consumer’s surplus increases by 123. Consequently, the
innovator enjoys less that 3% of the innovation’s total benefit to society.
2.11
The explanation of the following table shows that these numbers are reason-
able.
So -8+So +7+So +6+So+30 + 3 So+70 + 10
2.12
consumer’s surplus
Robert Cooter
The industry consists of, say, 10 firms and each of them supplies 100 units
of the good for total production of 1,000. The unit cost of production un-
der the original technology is 1, the market price of the good is originally 1
under perfect competition, and the consumer’s surplus is So. The innovator
spends 8 to develop a new production method that reduces the cost to .93.
Since the good’s price is 1, the innovator earns .7 per item for 100 items in
the monopoly stage when the innovation is launched. The innovation also
improves the good’s quality. 100 consumers know that the innovator’s good
has higher quality, so their surplus increases by .1 x 100.
In the final phase of perfect competition, all firms learn the new production
technique, the price falls to the cost of production .93, and all firms earn
zero profits. Consumers buy 100 units from each of 10 firms. The original
consumer surplus is So. When the price falls to .93, the consumer surplus
increases by 1,000 x .07. In addition, the consumer surplus increases from
the higher quality of the good by 1,000 x .01.
Notice that these calculations assume fixed market shares and perfectly in-
elastic demand, which eliminates the “welfare triangles” in a standard effi-
ciency analysis. A more complete analysis that relaxed these assumptions
would have larger total net benefits.
The product becomes obsolete when a new innovation destroys the old one’s
value and the industry begins a new cycle of innovation. The graph of the
net social benefits forms a gyre as depicted in Figure 2.4. The first cycle of
innovation begins at time 0 when social benefits equal So and ends at time 4
when social benefits equal So+80. The curve beyond time 4 suggests what the
next cycle of innovation looks like.
2.13
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 2: Ventures
2.14
Robert Cooter
3.1
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 3: The Double Trust Dilemma
A new idea collides with capital in Silicon Valley when an innovator presents
a business plan to potential investors. Here is a simple example of how such
a presentation might go:
“I have a new idea. I can use my time to develop it and sell it for $1 mil-
lion, or I can explain it to you. I have no effective legal protection for my
idea. Once you know it, you can use your capital of $3 million to develop it
yourself and sell it for $5 million, and I will gain nothing. However, once you
know the idea, I think that you will see that we can make a lot more money
by working together. If you supply me with $3 million in capital, I can use
my expertise to develop the innovation and sell it for $15 million. With $15
million, we can give you $5 million for not developing it yourself, and we can
split the remaining $10 million.”
Figure 3.1 depicts this proposal as a decision tree. In step 1 the innovator can
develop his idea without capital and earn 1, in which case the financier keeps
her capital of 3. Alternatively, in step 1 the innovator can explain his idea to
the financier and go to step 2. The innovator has no effective legal protection
of his idea. In step 2 the financier can use capital of 3 to develop the idea her-
self and sell it for 5. Alternatively, in step 2 the financier can supply capital to
develop the innovation in cooperation with the innovator and they can earn
15, with the innovator getting 5 and the financier getting 10. Each receives
what he could get without cooperation plus an equal share of the surplus
from cooperation. (This is the “Nash bargaining solution” in game theory.3)
3 The Nash Bargaining Solution is named after its inventor, John Nash, whose genius and insanity
inspired the popular Hollywood film, “A Beautiful Mind.” It is an axiomatic account of coopera-
tion. The Nash bargaining solution corresponds to the outcome of a non-cooperative game repeated
indefinitely. See Ariel Rubinstein,. “Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model”. Econometrica 50
(1): 97–109. doi:10.2307/1912531..
3.2
Robert Cooter
Many business ventures begin with plans resembling this one. The plan in
Figure 3.1 proposes payoffs of 5 to the innovator and 10 to the financier. To
implement this proposal, the innovator and financier must make 5 and 10
into the actual payoffs from cooperating. Successful implementation implies
that the innovator and financier will get the payoffs in Figure 2.1 if they
make the decisions depicted in the figure. If the plan can be implemented,
self-interest will motivate the parties to cooperate as envisioned in the pro-
posals. The financier will decide in stage 2 to supply capital to the innovator
to develop the idea, because the payoff from cooperation exceeds the payoff
from non-cooperation: F2>F1. Foreseeing this fact, the innovator will decide
to cooperate in stage 1, because the payoff from explaining his idea exceeds
the payoff from developing it on his own: I2>I0. These two inequalities ex-
press the conditions for cooperating in a venture structured like Figure 3.1.
Successful implementation of the plan satisfies these two conditions.
3.3
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 3: The Double Trust Dilemma
If the innovator and financier are protected against outsiders, they still need
to trust each other. At the final stage when the firm’s has 15, the plan calls
for the financier to receive 10 and the innovator to receive 5. What prevents
the innovator from grabbing all 15? Perhaps the innovator will take all 15 as
salary and leave nothing for paying dividends to shareholders. Many busi-
ness ventures never launch because the financier cannot trust the innovator
to distribute the profits as promised.
If the final stage of Figure 3.1 cannot be implemented, then the whole pro-
posal collapses. Assume that if venture were to reach the final stage, the
innovator would grab all 15, as depicted in Figure 3.2. Foreseeing this fact,
if the venture reaches stage 2, the financier will develop the innovation her-
self, so the financier’s payoff will be 5 and the innovator’s payoff will be 0.
Foreseeing this fact, in stage 1 the innovator will develop the idea himself
and receive a payoff of 1, instead of explaining the idea to the financier. The
payoffs in Figure 3.2 fail to implement the plan in Figure 3.1 for sharing the
gains from cooperation, so cooperation unwinds and noncooperation stifles
an innovative business venture. (Notice that the payoffs in Figure 3.2 violate
the two conditions for cooperation: F2>F1 and I2>I0.)
3.4
Robert Cooter
Relationships
How can the innovator and financier implement a business plan as depicted
in Figure 3.1, rather than collapsing as depicted in Figure 3.2? One way is
to deal with trusted relatives. Loyalty within families is partly irrational and
partly rational. Here’s how rationality prompts family members to cooperate
with each other. Kinship is ascribed, not chosen. Your uncle is your uncle
until death. Ascription provides a framework for repeat dealings. Through
repeat dealings, people come to know whom to trust and whom to distrust.
One reason to be trustworthy is fact that your relatives will find out if you
are not trustworthy.
3.5
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 3: The Double Trust Dilemma
in the next round, and likewise for subsequent rounds.4 With cooperation,
the innovator receives 5 in each round of the game. Alternatively, if the inno-
vator appropriates 15 in any round, then the financier refuses future dealings
with him, so the innovator will have to develop his ideas without capital in
each subsequent round and earn 1.
Compare the payoffs from the two strategies. In round t, “appropriate” pays
the innovator 15 and the innovator gains 1 in each subsequent round. In
contrast, “cooperate” pays 5 in every round. Summing payoffs from round
t to round t+3, “cooperate” pays 20 and “appropriate” pays 19. Thus “coop-
erate” overtakes “appropriate” in round t+3, and the gap widens with each
subsequent round. A rational player who values future payoffs will cooperate
and not appropriate.5 Conversely, a rational player who highly discounts
future payoffs will appropriate rather than cooperate. Specifically, the inno-
vator in Figure 3.3 will cooperate who discounts payoffs by less than 40%
per round, and the innovator will appropriate who discounts payoffs by more
than 40% per round.6
4 The financier’s strategy is called “grim” or “grim trigger.” Once the innovator cheats the finan-
cier treats him as untrustworthy forever. Another possible strategy with similar implications for
cooperation is a variant of “tit-for-tat, in which the financier punishes an innovator for cheating and
then resumes cooperating. The payoff matrix looks like this:
round t t+1 t+2 t+3 t+3 t+5 t+6 t+…
appropriate 15 1 1 1 15 1 1 1
Experimental evidence indicates that tit for tat comes close to maximizing the party’s payoffs in a
variety of circumstances.
5 To be precise, the discounted sum across rounds is the game’s “present value” to the player. The
present value of “cooperate” exceeds the present value of “appropriate” if the game repeats itself
enough times and the discount.
6 Cooperation yields
3.6
Robert Cooter
Private Law
Family members can cooperate even if law cannot effectively enforce their
promises to each other. However, entrepreneurs do not have enough family
and friends to conduct business exclusively with them on the most profitable
scale. Successful entrepreneurs look beyond relationships to strangers for
money and ideas. Whereas kinship endures, strangers come and go. In busi-
ness, friendships are often chosen for particular needs, not ascribed. The pos-
sibility that a business relationship will end poses an obstacle to cooperation.
3.7
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 3: The Double Trust Dilemma
The payoffs in Figure 3.4, however, do not reflect what each player will do if
he foresees what the other player will do (“Nash equilibrium”). If the finan-
cier foresees that the innovator will appropriate in round t+3, she will change
her strategy and not cooperate in round t+3. If the innovator foresees the
financier’s behavior in round t+3, he will change his strategy and appropriate
in round t+2. If the financier foresees the innovator’s behavior in round t+2,
she will change her strategy and not cooperate in round t+2. By repeating
this reasoning, cooperation unwinds all the way to the game’s beginning. 7
With a definite end in sight, repeating the game provides no basis for cooper-
ation. Every round looks like Figure 3.2, where the innovator and financier
do not launch a joint venture. This is the “end-game” problem.
In a game with a definite end, cooperation may unwind back to the begin-
ning. In a game with a likely end, cooperation may stop if uncertainty causes
high discounting of future payoffs. Unlike relatives, strangers have more dif-
ficulty solving the problem of non-cooperation by repeating the double trust
dilemma because they foresee an end to their relationship, or they discount
future payoffs by the probability that the relationship will end. If the inno-
vator and financier cannot cooperate, the business venture does not launch,
the innovation is undeveloped, and the economy does not grow.
Where repetition fails, private law may succeed in solving the double trust
dilemma. Here is one legal implementation often used in business ventures
like Figure 3.1. The innovator and financier form a corporation to develop
the idea. The financier loans the firm 3 for development (debt), and the
innovator contributes his expertise to the firm. The firm issues 7 shares (eq-
uity) to the innovator and 5 shares (equity) to the financier. Shares are claims
on profits left over after paying the firm’s debt. To implement the proposal,
the law must effectively enforce the firm’s repayment of debt and an equal
7 Experimental data shows that people are not so rational. In a repeated game with a definite
end, experiments often find that players cooperate in the beginning and they stop cooperating near
the end. Apparently people are partly logical and partly psychological.
3.8
Robert Cooter
Here is one way that weak corporate law could allow the innovator to ap-
propriate all profits. Assume that the innovator is the corporation’s chief
executive officer (CEO) who controls the company without effective legal
constraints. After the firm earns 15, the innovator/CEO repays the firm’s
debts of 3 to the financier, and then the innovator/CEO pays himself a salary
of 12. Since all 15 go to pay debts and salary, no profits remain to distribute
as dividends to shareholders. The financier gets nothing beyond the repay-
ment of her debt of 3, and the innovator gets everything else. If the financier
foresees this ploy by the entrepreneur, cooperation will unwind.8 (Similarly,
another ploy transfers all profits to the financier instead of the innovator,
which also causes cooperation to unwind.9)
Public Law
In private finance of a business venture, the innovator and financier nego-
tiate with each other over price and non-price terms and then use contracts
and corporate law to implement their plans. In contrast, traders in public
markets like the New York Stock exchange buy and sell stocks and bonds at
8 In stage 2, the financier foresees that lending capital of 3 for the firm to develop the innovation
will result in repayment of the loan and nothing more for her. Foreseeing this fact, the financier
will choose to develop the idea without the innovator in stage 2, which pays the financier 5 and the
innovator 0. Foreseeing this fact, the innovator will choose to develop the idea at stage 1 and earn 1,
rather than explaining the idea to the financier and earning 0. Unless law can prevent the innovator’s
chicanery at the end of stage 2, cooperation will unwind.
9 Assume that the financier is the Chairman of the Board who controls the company without ef-
fective legal constraints. After the firm develops the idea, the financier/chairman fires the innovator/
CEO and sells the innovation for 15 to another firm that she owns. The selling firm uses 3 to repay
its debts, and the buying firm distributes its profits of 12 to the financier/owner.
3.9
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 3: The Double Trust Dilemma
The ability to sell securities to the public presupposes compliance with secu-
rities regulations that ideally protect buyers from chicanery. Members of the
public who buy stocks or bonds have no direct control over how the firm uses
their money. Instead, the firm’s managers and board of directors control it.
Insiders have many opportunities to appropriate outsiders’ investments. For
example, insiders may use accounting tricks to convert profits into salaries,
thus depriving stockholders of their dividends. Protecting outsiders from
insiders in public companies requires more than securing property and en-
forcing contracts. For public finance, the additional protection comes espe-
cially from corporate law and the law of securities. These laws ideally assure
that outside investors get their share of a firm’s profits, rather than insiders
appropriating all of it. Conversely, if these laws are ineffective, insiders will
appropriate all of a firm’s profits, and outsiders who foresee this fact will be
unwilling to invest.
If the firm gets 15 by selling itself to another firm or by selling its stock in an
initial public offering, the founders often take the cash from the initial public
offering and exit the business soon thereafter. A timely exit by the founders
makes a business venture more profitable, which increases innovative activ-
3.10
Robert Cooter
10 For a recent application, see Bernard Black and Ronald Gilson, “Does Venture Capital Require
an Active Stock Market?” Journal of Applied Corporate Finance 11 (winter 1999): 35–38.
11 The three stages of finance in Silicon Valley are distinguished and related to stages in the de-
velopment of financial markets in The phrase “double trust dilemma” was introduced by Cooter and
Schaefer in Chapter 3, “The Double Trust Dilemma of Development,” Solomon’s Knot: How Law
Can End the Poverty of Nations. Contemporary (Princeton University Press, 2012).
3.11
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 3: The Double Trust Dilemma
Innovators and entrepreneurs have goods reasons to distrust each other. Sil-
icon Valley innovators sometimes expropriate the investments of their finan-
ciers. John P. Rogers convinced some prominent California investors to give
him $330 million for a high-tech start-up named Pay By Touch that would
“transform how America pays its bills” by using “biometric authentication
technology” (e.g., fingerprints). In 2008 the company went bankrupt, and
investors contend in lawsuits that Rogers burned through $8 million per
month without producing anything of value.12
Similarly, the creative people who found a company often manage it badly.
When the founders prove to be bad managers, the venture capitalists must
replace them with good managers. In these circumstances, the venture cap-
italists seize the firm to increase its profitability. Alternatively, where the
founders prove to be competent managers, venture capitalists may seize the
firm to avoid sharing profits with the founders. Venture capitalists sometimes
want to remove good managers with large claims to the firm’s future profits.
The initials “v.c.” stand for “venture capitalists” and also “vulture capitalists.”
Innovators and venture capitalists use various legal devices to overcome their
mutual distrust. The founders of the firm commit to performance goals
implicitly or explicitly. If they fail to meet their goals, they may lose their
investments and their jobs. Specifically, the venture capitalists often hold
preferred shares of stock, unlike the common shares held by the founders.
Preferred shareholders may have special powers of governance that common
shareholders lack, as well as other advantages. The financing contract may say
12 Lance Williams, “How a ‘Visionary’ Raised—and Lost—a Fortune,” San Francisco Chroni-
cle, December 7, 2008, available at http://www.sfgate.com/cgi-bin/article.cgi?f=/c/a/2008/12/07/
MNIK137QU3.DTL.
3.12
Robert Cooter
Corporate governance provides another device to solve the double trust prob-
lem in Silicon Valley. The firm’s bylaws may stipulate that common share-
holders (founders) and preferred shareholders (venture capitalists) appoint
an equal number of directors to the company’s board, plus an independent
director accepted by both sides. If the founders and venture capitalists dis-
agree, the independent director holds the decisive vote. Thus the indepen-
dent director will decide whether or not the venture capitalists can replace
the founders with new management.
In the third stage of finance in Silicon Valley, a successful start-up sells itself
to the public, either directly through an initial public offering of its stock,
or indirectly when a publicly traded company acquires it. In order to sell
stock to the public in the United States, a firm must comply with disclosure
rules of the Securities Exchange Commission. Brokers disseminate the firm’s
disclosed information to potential investors. After disclosures, many people
understand the innovation sufficiently to decide whether or not to invest in
its further development. The investors in stock markets are a large group of
people – the “public.” Regulatory law, which belongs to “public law,” espe-
cially controls finance by a large group of investors.
3.13
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 3: The Double Trust Dilemma
promising ones, and order the finance division to pay the research division to
develop the innovations. Perhaps you think that hierarchical authority solves
the problems of trust that afflict negotiations between individual innovators
and financiers.
If that is what you think, consider the following. When an employee has a
new idea, he understands its worth better than others. If he gives a valuable
idea to his employer, he may get a bonus and the firm may get richer. A typi-
cal employee, however, would rather enrich himself than his firm. Instead of
giving the idea to his firm, the employee may quit, form a startup company,
develop the idea on his own, and try to get rich. Various contracts and laws
restrain employees from quitting firms and taking creative ideas with them.14
The more large firms can claim legal ownership of employees’ discoveries, the
less people who are creative will work for them. Large firms often cannot
prevent employees from quitting and taking creative ideas with them, and
large firms often cannot hire the most creative innovators to work for them.
That is why many innovations in Silicon Valley begin in small, startup firms,
where innovators own a significant share of the firm.
The double trust dilemma persists in large firms. The employee in the re-
search division asks, “Can I trust the firm to reward me if I give it my in-
novative idea?” The employee in the finance division asks, “Can I trust the
research division to develop this innovative idea as planned?” Each one fears
that the other party is withholding crucial information. Perhaps the inno-
vator-employee keeps secret a potentially fatal obstacle to development, or
perhaps the financier-employee keeps secret his intention not to pay a bonus
to the innovator-employee.
The problem of trust favors innovation in small firms. Why do large firms
innovate? The amount of money required to develop an innovation often ex-
ceeds the innovator’s wealth. The innovator is reluctant to risk all his wealth
on an innovation with an uncertain future. In a startup firm, the innovator
shifts much of the financial risk to the financier. If they form a business
venture with the innovator in charge, the innovator risks another’s money,
not his own. This fact creates incentive problems that we discuss later. To
improve incentives, the innovator usually retains substantial risk of failure.
14 See Chapter __ trade secrets law and Chapter __ on non-competition clauses in employment
contracts.
3.14
Robert Cooter
Creative people differ in their appetite for risk taking. Creative people who
are risk-lover form startup firms, and creative people who are risk-averse find
employment in the research division of large firms. The main advantage of
developing innovations in large firms is risk spreading. Different tastes for
risk contribute to the distribution of innovations by firm size.
Like 18th century England, the poorest countries today have weak capital
markets, so businessmen mostly borrow from family and friends. Starting
from a condition of lawlessness, imposition of secure property rights can
cause a spurt of growth based mostly on relational finance, as in China’s new
industries after the 1980s. Some peoples, notably the Chinese and the Jews,
have family networks that extend business relationships beyond the usual
boundaries. However, the conditions of trust among relatives do not reach
the scale of modern businesses. Relational finance keeps business small and
local. No modern country became wealthy by relying exclusively on relation-
al finance.
15 See P. M. Deane, The First Industrial Revolution (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1955), summary on 155–157. For financing of key eighteenth-century inventions by name, see 155.
3.15
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 3: The Double Trust Dilemma
16 See Chapter 8, pages 115-120 of Cooter and Schaefer, “The Double Trust Dilemma of Devel-
opment,” Solomon’s Knot: How Law Can End the Poverty of Nations. Contemporary (Princeton
University Press, 2012)
17 Each animal begins life as a single cell containing genetic instructions for how to grow into a
complex organism. For animals in different species with a common evolutionary ancestor, the path
of individual growth suggests the older, evolutionary forms found in the fossil record. While the pat-
tern of individual growth does not strictly recapitulate the evolution of the species, comparing them
provides useful clues about the genes that control the development of individuals and species. For a
book that finds the origin of the human fetus in fish, see Neil Shubin, Your Inner Fish: A Journey
into the 3.5-Billion-Year History of the Human Body (New York: Pantheon Books, 2008).
3.16
Robert Cooter
States and Great Britain rely mostly on public finance for mature industries.
Germany appears to be shifting from the former to the latter.18
Expanding the basis of finance requires effective law that controls behavior,
not aspirational law that expresses lofty ideals. What makes a law effective?
Not just writing it down. Written law in a poor country often resembles
written law in a rich country. Property and contract law-on-the-books in
India and Nigeria resemble English common law, and property and contract
law-on-the-books in Peru resemble the Spanish civil code. Writing down a
law, however, does not make it effective. The written laws are less effective in
Nigeria or Peru than in England or Spain.
Conclusion
New business ventures begin with secrecy, risk, and high profit expectations.
All three decrease as the venture matures. Sea routes from Europe to Asia
were eventually mapped and secured, trade between them became common-
place, and middle-class Europeans could buy spices. In Silicon Valley, com-
petitors work around patents and ferret out secrets, thus converting today’s
technological breakthroughs into tomorrow’s commodities. However, an in-
novative economy never settles into a permanent condition without secrecy,
risk, or extraordinary profits. For economic growth, new business ventures
must repeatedly confront and solve the double trust dilemma. To solve the
double trust dilemma, entrepreneurs, financiers, courts, and regulators have
worked out contracts, laws, and institutions over years and centuries. One
cannot understand these creations without studying them as legal scholars
do. That is how law dispels some mysteries of growth that baffle economists.
Where law is weak, innovators and financiers cannot rely on formal law for
much more than protecting property from predators. They must deal mostly
through relationships. This is true for most business in some undeveloped
countries, and it is true for startup firms in developed countries where no law
can protect fragile secrets and implicit financial agreements. In developing
countries and startup firms, good law cannot do all of the work of creating
trust. When the effective law of contracts and corporations improves, fi-
nance expands from relational to private. This is true in undeveloped coun-
tries that improve their legal institutions, and it is true in startup firms after
18 For details on finance in different countries, see...
3.17
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 3: The Double Trust Dilemma
3.18
Robert Cooter
Chapter 4. Separation
Robert Cooter and Aaron Edlin
To increase innovation, law and policy should increase its profitability. Fig-
ure 4.1 expresses this idea. (It is essentially the same as Figure 2.4 in Chapter
2.). The vertical axis represents venture profits, which equal the discounted
present value of the stream of revenues from the innovation’s sales, minus
the discounted present value of its development and production costs. The
horizontal axis arrays ventures by profitability from high on the left to low
on the right. With open competition, investors will finance ventures until
profits fall to zero. Development stops when the present discounted value of
revenues equals the present discounted value of development and production
costs.
Figure 4.1 contrasts venture profits under two different legal regimes. Un-
der the original law, venture profits reach 0 at innovation I. Improved law
changes the situation by shifting the venture profit curve up as indicated by
the arrows, so venture profits reach 0 at innovation I*. Thus improved law
increases the number of innovations that get developed from I to I*. The fig-
ure depicts the increase in one period of time. If better law increases innova-
tions in every future period of time, then the sustained growth rate increases.
(Figure 4.1 depicts one of several ways that improved law increases growth by
increasing the profitability of innovation.2)
1 By definition, the consumer’s surplus equals the difference between the price that a consumer
would be willing to pay for a good and the price that he actually pays.
2 Figure 4.1 does not depict the speed with which an innovation is developed. In a race to in-
novate, the expectation of higher profits may cause an entrepreneur to develop an innovation faster.
Faster development affects infra-marginal innovations, not just the marginal innovation I*.
4.1
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 4. Separation
Figure 4.1. Laws that Increase Venture Profits Cause More Innovations
How much should law ideally increase the profits of innovative ventures?
To maximize social welfare, according to the overtaking principle, law and
policy should increase venture profits as much as possible. You might doubt
the overtaking principle or the conditions that make it true, but when you
consider the historical record you cannot doubt that sustained growth in a
comprehensive measure of consumption dramatically improves social wel-
fare. Nor can you doubt that faster sustained growth would increase social
welfare faster. In any case, this book is playing the intellectual game of law
and growth economics whose objective is to maximize sustained growth.
Paradox of Growth
Law and policy rests on a paradox, like “This statement is false.” The paradox
of growth is that rapid innovation requires competition for extraordinary
profits. This is a paradox because “perfect competition” in economic theory
implies that all firms earn ordinary profits. If some firms earn extraordinary
profits, competition must be imperfect.
How can law and policy combine intense competition and extraordinary
profits for innovators? Patent law illustrates the solution. Chapter 2 distin-
guished a venture’s phases into development, launch, and imitation. Patent
4.2
Robert Cooter
This is not the conventional approach in the economic analysis of law. The
conventional approach first observes that a venture incurs losses in develop-
ment, so overall profitability requires extra profits after development. How
much extra? The usual words are “sufficient,” “adequate,” “cost-recovery,” or
“break-even.” Second, the conventional approach notes that market power
for a firm increases the price of its product to consumers. The words are
“excessive,” “inefficient,” or “distorting.” Third, the conventional logic con-
cludes that law affecting market power should balance the gain from faster
innovation and the loss from higher prices for consumers. The words are
“tradeoff” and “optimal.” Unlike the conventional approach, our words are
“maximize innovation.”
3 A patent cycle begins with competition for a market, and ends with competition in a market.
The phrase “competition for a market” was used by Bill Baxter to analyze antitrust law.
4.3
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 4. Separation
When a firm uses market power to increase its price, part of the buyers’ losses
transfers to the seller as higher profits, and part of the buyers’ losses does not
transfer to the seller. “Deadweight” describes a loss without an offsetting
gain.4 To illustrate numerically, assume that a seller earns 0 profits under
perfect competition and 100 under monopoly. A change from competition
to monopoly transfers 100 from buyers to the seller. According to standard
economics, the seller gains less from monopoly than the buyers lose. Thus
if monopoly causes the seller to gain 100, buyers may lose, say, 130. The
difference of 30 is the deadweight loss.5 (Behind this problem of monopoly
lies a deeper theoretical problem of transaction costs.6) Firms with market
4 The deadweight loss occurs because the higher price causes buyers to purchase less of the good.
When buyers forego some purchases, the buyers lose the gains that they would have enjoyed from
these foregone goods, and the seller gains nothing from goods that buyers do not buy.
5 The standard analysis is somewhat more complicated than these remarks suggest because of the
difference between long run and short run effects. In the long run, all of the deadweight loss falls
on buyers, but in the short run sellers can also bear part of the deadweight loss. Note that in the
standard graphical analysis, the transfer is a rectangle and the deadweight burden is a triangle.
6 If there were no obstacles to bargaining, the monopolist and the buyers could write contracts
that eliminate the deadweight lost. The contracts would charge according to a price schedule, not a
single price. The schedule discriminates according to how many units of the good the buyer buys,
charging a higher price for the first unit and a lower price for the last unit. By definition, a perfectly
discriminating monopoly charges the reservation price to each buyer, so the marginal rate of substi-
tution equals the marginal rate of transformation as required for static efficiency. With zero transac-
tion costs, perfect discrimination eliminates the deadweight loss of monopoly. The deadweight loss
4.4
Robert Cooter
power can raise prices to buyers and enjoy extraordinary profits. Static eco-
nomics condemns market power as inefficient because the deadweight loss
reduces wealth.
Market power slows growth when a producer who does not innovate raises
prices to innovators, so the cost of developing innovations increases and the
profitability of innovation decreases. When profitability decreases, the mar-
ginal venture in Figure 4.1 shifts to the left as depicted by a move from I* to
I. To prevent this slowing of innovation and growth, law and policy should
suppress market power by non-innovating producers against innovators.
To illustrate, a cartel that controls diamond mines and raises diamond prices
spurs the development of manufactured diamonds. Manufacturers will prof-
it from developing diamonds so long as the cost does not exceed the cartel’s
price. Since mined and manufactured diamonds virtually indistinguishable,
the only gain to society from manufacturing diamonds is to undermine the
cartel’s price. The cartel’s price could be undermined directly by laws and
policies aimed at reducing the market power of the diamond monopoly,
without the cost of developing manufactured diamonds.
4.5
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 4. Separation
exceed the price of α. Since the price of β exceeds the price of α, innovators
might foresee higher profits from developing substitutes for β rather than α,
even though society benefits more from the opposite.
When market power raises a good’s price, more innovators try to invent sub-
stitutes for it. The invention of a perfect substitute is costly. However, a per-
fect substitute is no better than the original good. The only consequence of
inventing the substitute is to reduce the distortion from monopoly pricing.
Law and policy could reduce market power without the expense of develop-
ing the substitute.
4.6
Robert Cooter
vations price, which transfers wealth from producers and consumers to the
innovator. The transfer increases the average profits of innovative ventures,
which causes the marginal venture in Figure 4.1 to shift to the right as de-
picted by the move from I to I*. More resources are devoted to innovation
and fewer resources are devoted to production and consumption. Thus mar-
ket power for innovators against producers and consumers enhances growth
The three effects of market power are transfer, deadweight loss, and mistar-
getting. Analyzing these effects on growth implies a simple conclusion for
law and policy. Growth economics proscribes market power for (non-in-
novating) production against innovation and consumption, and growth
economics prescribes market power for innovations against consuming and
(non-innovating) producing. In both cases, the aim is the same: to increase
4.7
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 4. Separation
Conclusion
In static economics, monopoly causes buyers to pay more than the marginal
cost of goods, so too little is consumed and produced. The remedy is to abol-
ish market power and to restore competition whenever possible. In growth
economics, however, market power is necessary to increase the profitability
of ventures competing to innovate. Crossing the boundary between static ef-
ficiency and growth changes economics, like crossing the border from France
to Germany changes languages.
7 Note that the three effects of monopoly align in static and growth economics to reinforce the
proscription of producer monopolies against innovators. The three effects do not align with respect
to the prescription for innovator’s monopolies against producers. The prescription for innovator’s
monopolies against producers rests on the transfers to innovators overtaking deadweight loss and
mistargeting.
4.8
Robert Cooter
These facts imply the separation principle: to maximize growth, law and pol-
icy should separate innovation and (non-innovating) production. Growth
economics proscribes market power for non-innovating production, and
it prescribes market power for innovating against consuming and produc-
ing. The next chapter will analyze the effect of market power by innovators
against each other.
4.9
Robert Cooter
Chapter 5. Fertility
Robert Cooter and Aaron Edlin
The social value of an innovation far exceeds the innovator’s profits. To in-
crease innovation, law and policy should increase the profitability of business
ventures in open competition with each other. Profitability increases when
the venture that wins the competition enjoys market power. A successful
venture obtains temporary market power by innovating first. Imitators even-
tually enter the industry and erode the venture’s market power. Law and
policy that slows imitators will extend the innovator’s market power, thus in-
creasing the venture’s profits. Chapters 4 and 5 concern general principles for
extending the innovator’s temporary market power, and subsequent chapters
discuss specific legal instruments such as intellectual property, secrecy, and
collusion.
5.1
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 5. Fertility
What about market power of innovators against each other? Besides selling
to consumers and producers, innovators sell to other innovators. Today’s
new pharmaceutical molecule is discovered from yesterday’s new molecule;
today’s new operating system is discovered from yesterday’s new operating
system; today’s new power cell is discovered from yesterday’s new power cell.1
The subject of this chapter is redistribution within the dynamic economy.
The question is, “Should law and policy enhance market power of some in-
novators against other innovators?” Thus in Figure 5.1, A creates innovation
α and sells it to innovator B, who uses α to create innovation β and to sell β
to consumer C.
When one innovator has market power in the sale of an innovation to anoth-
er innovator, the seller raises the price to the buyer and profits transfer from
one innovator to another. In Figure 5.1, assume that A has market power
against B, so A can capture some of B’s profits from sales to C. Market power
for A against B redistributes within the dynamic economic, whereas market
power of B against C redistributes from the static economy to the dynamic
economy.
To increase growth, A’s innovation α must be more fertile than innovator B’s
innovation β. An innovation is fertile like a breeding horse if it can be used
to create another innovation. In Figure 5.1, innovation α is used to create
1 Brian Arthur describes technology as “self-creating” (autopoietic). ”…if new technologies were
constructed from existing ones, then considered collectively, technology created itself.” W. Brian
Arthur, The Nature of Technology (2009), page 2.
5.2
Robert Cooter
A costless transfer occurs without loss. Imagine that oasis Y in the desert fills
a one liter container with ice cream and sends it across the hot sands to oasis
X. Costless transfer implies that X receives one liter of ice cream. None of
it melts. Conversely, a costly transfer between oases implies that some ice
cream melts and X receives less than one liter. Similarly, a costless transfer
from B to A in Figure 5.1 means that B’s loss from the transfer equals A’s
gain. The burden of the transfer on B equals the benefit of the transfer to
A. If law and policy can transfer profits costlessly, then maximizing growth
requires redistributing profits from less to more fertile innovations. Redis-
tribution should proceed until all developed innovations are equally fertile.
This fact can be explained in terms of spillovers. The value of a fertile innova-
tion spills over to other innovations with large effects on growth, whereas the
value of an sterile innovation spills over to consumers and non-innovating
producers with small effects on growth. To maximize growth, some prof-
its from selling sterile innovations to consumers and producers should pass
through to fertile innovations. To pass profits through, the seller of a fertile
innovation like α should have market power against the buyer who uses it for
sterile innovation like β. (A footnote contains an example.4)
2 cite Tim Bresnahan, General Purpose Technolgies).cite Scotchmer
3 In notation, let i denote an innovation. The winner of an open competition to make innovation
i enjoys profits denoted πi. The sustainable growth rate g is a function of the distribution of profits:
g=g(π0,π1,π2,…,πI). By definition, if j is “economically more fertile” than i, then a costless transfer of
profits δ from i to j increases the growth rate:
The characteristics of an innovation that make it economically fertile concern the way one idea
prompts the discovery of other profitable ideas.
4 Innovator A in Figure 5.1 creates innovation α and sells it to B. Assume that A’s only income
comes from selling α to B. If law and market structure deny A market power, then A must sell α
5.3
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 5. Fertility
When innovators buy and sell innovations to each other, however, the trans-
fer is usually costly, not costless. Market power imposes a deadweight loss on
most transactions, including transactions between innovators. In Figure 5.1,
market power for A might cause an increase in the price of α that benefits A
by, say, 100 and burdens B by, say, 130. The difference of 30 is the “dead-
weight loss” as explained in Chapter 4. Whereas the transfer from less fertile
innovations to more fertile innovations causes growth to increase, the dead-
weight loss causes growth to decrease. The net effect determines whether or
not the overall growth rate increases. These considerations imply a general
principle. To maximize growth, law and policy should transfer profits from
less to more fertile innovations until the increase in growth from higher fertility
equals the decrease from a heavier deadweight loss. This is the fertility principle.
(The mathematical expression is in a footnote.5)
Figure 5.1 can illustrate this principle. Recall that A must develop α in order
for B to develop β. If A develops α and sells it to B at the cost of production,
then A suffers a loss equal to the cost of developing α. Foreseeing this fact,
A will not develop α. Alternatively, if A develops α and uses market power
to sell it to B at more than the cost of development and production, then A
makes a profit. Foreseeing this fact, A will develop α. Thus market power
of fertile innovators can benefit all innovators. (A footnote illustrates with
numbers.6)
at its production cost, so A cannot recover α’s development costs. If A foresees this fact, it will not
develop α, which B needs to develop β. To induce A to create α, B could pass some profits back to A
obtained from selling β to C. To increase the rate of innovation, law should facilitate the pass-back
of profits from sterile innovators like B to fertile innovators like A.
5 In footnote 2, if j is a “economically more fertile” innovation than i, then a costless transfer of
profits δ from i to j increases the growth rate:
However, an actual transfer caused by law and policy creates a deadweight loss. The burden on i is
δ, the transfer to j is γδ, and the deadweight loss is (1-γ)δ. At the optimum as given by the fertility
principle, the benefit from the transfer to a more fertile innovation exactly offsets the cost from the
deadweight loss, so the growth rate does not increase or decrease:
g(π0,π1,π2,…,πI) = g(π0,π1,π2,πi-δ,...,πj+γδ,..πI).
6 Assume that A invests 75 to develop α and A spends 25 to produce α. If B buys α at 25, which
is the cost of production, then A loses 75. Foreseeing these facts, A will not develop α. If A does not
develop α, then B cannot develop β, and their joint profits are 0.
5.4
Robert Cooter
Instead of the fertility principle, court cases refer to other principles such
as the principle of cost recovery (innovators should enjoy enough profits to
recover their development costs) and the principle of proportionality (suc-
cessful innovators should receive profits in proportion to their development
costs). The next chapter discusses the connection between the fertility prin-
ciple and the principles actually invoked by courts.
There is, however, a deadweight loss caused by A’s market power against B, which we also illustrate.
As noted, when B buys α for 200, A and B each earn profits of 100. We assume that the state pays a
subsidy to A to develop α and then requires A to sell α to B at the cost of production. Specifically,
the state imposes a tax of 175 on B, which the state pays to A for developing α, and the state requires
A to sell α to B at 25, which is the cost of production. In sum, A receives a subsidy of 175, spend 75
to develop α, spends 25 to produce α, and sells α to B at a price of 25, for a net profit of 100 for A.
A’s profits remain constant at 100, and B’s profits rise, say to 130, because B does not have to econo-
mize on the use of α when it develops β. The replacement of market power with a subsidy eliminates
a deadweight loss of 30 and increases joint profits of A and B from 200 to 230.
5.5
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 5. Fertility
Besides the elasticity, the pattern of transactions among innovators affects the
deadweight loss. Circular transactions among innovators cause an especially
large deadweight loss. Much that a venture buys to develop an innovation
was originally an innovation by another venture. When innovators sell inno-
vations to each other, some transactions circle within the dynamic economy,
instead of proceeding straight from innovators to consumers as in Figure 5.1.
In Figure 5.2 venture A makes innovation α and sells it to venture B, who
uses it to develop innovation β and sells it to venture A for the next round of
innovations, and so on. (In Figure 5.2, innovators A and B also sell innova-
tions to consumers C.)
5.6
Robert Cooter
to raise the price of the innovations that it sells to B. This use of market
power gains profits of 100 for A and imposes costs of 130 on B. Similarly,
assume that innovator B uses market power to raise the price of the innova-
tions that it sells to A. This use of market power gains profits of 100 for B
and imposes costs of 130 on A. The deadweight loss of monopoly in this cy-
cle of transactions between A and B is 60. If market power were eliminated,
the increase in profits of A and B would total 60, with each one gaining 30.
Their profits would increase because each gains more from lower costs than
it loses from lower revenues.
The more innovators deal in circular transactions with each other, the larger
is the increase in growth from reducing their market power. Eliminating
market power in circular transactions is relatively easy when everyone gains.
For example, if patents were the source of market power between A and B,
then both of them would enjoy higher profits if neither had patents that
were good against the other. Later we explain how firms achieve this result
by pooling their patents.
5.7
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 5. Fertility
a football stadium sets the price of a glass of beer. In the standard model of
monopoly, the monopolist maximizes profits by setting a firm price where
the marginal revenue from a small increase in production equals the marginal
cost.9
Second, instead of a firm price, the seller may name a flexible price, and each
buyer may make a counter-offer. With price flexibility, the parties bargain
with each other to reach an exact price. Bargaining takes time and effort.
In addition to time and effort, bargaining sometimes fails to reach an agree-
ment. Three major costs of transacting by bargaining are time, effort, and
the loss from failure to agree.
To illustrate, assume that a football player is willing to play for 100 and a
team values the player at 120. When they bargain over salary, the player
will not accept less than 100 and the team will not pay more than 120. If
bargaining succeeds, they will agree on a price in between 100 and 120, de-
pending on their bargaining power.10 Say they agree on the price 112, so the
player gains 12 and the team gains 8. Bargaining takes time and effort that
costs, say, 1 for the team and 1 for the player. The gain net of bargaining
costs thus equals 7 for the team and 11 for the player. In addition to the
time and effort, bargaining involves uncertainty about the result. When the
parties begin bargaining, they do not know whether or not they will reach an
agreement. If the probability of success in our example is, say, 90%, then the
probability of failure is 10%. Rational parties discount the expected value
9 A seller’s revenue equals the price p multiplied by the quantity q that he sells. For a monopolist,
the quantity is a decreasing function of the price. So the monopolist’s revenue R can be written
R=pq(p) where q`<0. The monopolists cost of production C increase with the quantity, which
decreases with the price, so C=C(p) where C`<0. Profits, which equal revenues R- C, are maximized
when marginal revenues equal the marginal cost: q+pq`= C`.
10 When two parties bargain with each other, their bargaining power depends on their alterna-
tives. In perfect competition, each party to a bargain has a perfect substitute. The buyer can buy
the same good from another seller at the market price, and the seller can sell the good to another
buyer at the market price. With perfect substitutes, neither party has any bargaining power against
the other. That is why they are price takers. Alternatively, in monopoly, the buyer cannot buy the
same good from anyone except the single seller, whereas the seller can sell to another buyer. With
close substitutes for the buyer and no substitutes for the seller, the seller has all of the bargaining
power and the buyer has none of it. Law and policy increases the market power of the seller of an
innovation by reducing the substitutes available to buyers. For example, a patent that effectively
stops infringements reduces the substitutes available to its buyers. A remarkably simple formulation
of the relationship between bargaining power and negotiated prices is the Nash Bargaining Solution,
which Chapter __ discusses.
5.8
Robert Cooter
of the bargain by its probability of failure. The net gain discounted for the
probability of failure is .9(7) for the team and .9(11) for the player, which
sum to 16.2. The difference between the gross gain of 20 for the team and
player, and the discounted net gain of 16.2, is 3.8.
This number, 3.8, can be called the bargain’s “transaction costs,” and it can
also be called the bargain’s “deadweight loss.” The equivalence of “transac-
tion costs” and “deadweight burden” yields two formulations of the fertility
principle. According to the original formulation, to maximize growth, law
and policy should transfer profits from less to more fertile innovations until
the increase in growth from higher fertility equals the decrease from a heavier
deadweight loss. Equivalently, law and policy should transfer profits from
less to more fertile innovations until the increase in growth from higher fer-
tility equals the decrease from higher transaction costs.
To apply this principle, contrast bargaining between two parties and many
parties. When only two people must agree to a bargain (say, the buyer and
the seller), negotiation often takes little time or effort, and the parties can
usually reach an agreement. With two parties, transaction costs are low,
especially when the law enforces contracts between them.11 Thus the dead-
weight loss is negligible if A sells α to a single buyer B. Conversely, with
many individuals involved, negotiation takes more time and effort, and the
parties may not reach an agreement. Thus the deadweight loss is likely to be
high if A sells α to B where “B” stands for many individuals who must agree.
5.9
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 5. Fertility
Conclusion
Maximizing growth requires an open competition among innovators with
extraordinary profits as the prize. Innovators enjoy extraordinary profits
when law and policy allows them to exercise the market power that they have
or gives them market power that they lack. According to the separation prin-
ciple in the preceding chapter, law and policy should strengthen the market
power of innovators against consumers and producers who do not innovate.
According to the principle of fertility in this chapter, law and policy should
strengthen the market power of fertile innovators against sterile innovators.
Market power within the dynamic economy has two effects on growth:
transfer and deadweight loss. Transfers from less to more fertile innovations
increase growth, and deadweight loss in transactions among innovators de-
creases growth. Redistribution from less to more fertile innovators should
proceed until the decrease in growth from deadweight loss equals the in-
crease in growth from fertility. Intellectual property, which is the subject of
the next chapter, is one bodies of law for implementing the separation and
fertility principles.
5.10
Robert Cooter
In the numerical discussed in this chapter, T equals 100. However, the loss
to B of paying the higher price pm is more than the transfer T. Besides paying
more for the qm units of α that B buys, the higher price causes B to forego
the purchase of qc-qm units of α. The loss to B from foregoing this purchase
equals the difference between the amount B was willing to pay for them, as
given by B’s demand curve, and their cost of production c. In Figure 5.2, L
denotes this loss. B’s loss from A’s market power equals T+L, which is the
burden on B. A’s gain from its market power equals T. The difference L be-
tween B’s burden and A’s gain is the deadweight loss L.
12 Ramsey first worked out the mathematics for taxation, and he concluded that optimal taxes are
inversely proportional to the elasticity of demand. See Frank P. Ramsey, A Contribution to the Theory
of Taxation, 37 Economic Journal 47–61 (1927).
5.11
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 5. Fertility
Figure 5.4 shows the increase in the deadweight loss when demand becomes
more elastic. Figure 5.4 holds demand constant at the point (pm,qm) and
rotates the demand curve from Dinelastic up to Delastic. This change holds
A’s gain of T constant, but the deadweight loss increase from L to L+L’. The
deadweight loss increases because B responds to the price increase by making
a larger reduction in the good’s use. The larger reduction in use involves
more costly adjustments to get by with less of the good.
5.12
Robert Cooter
5.13
Robert Cooter
1 Section 101 [2] sets out subject matter that can be patented; section 102 [3] defines novelty and
loss of right to patent; section 103 [4] lists what constitutes non-obvious subject matter.
6.1
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
This chapter applies the separation and fertility principles to innovations that
can grow exponentially, so the effects of growth on human welfare overtake
other effects. Patented inventions can grow exponentially. So can some
copyrighted expressions such as computer programs, as well as some innova-
tions covered by special statutes.2 In contrast, cultural expressions (novels,
songs, plays) evolve and develop, but these changes do not constitute expo-
nential growth on a generally accepted measure such as cost-benefit analysis
or market value. Compared to economic growth, any attempt to measure
progress in artistic expression immediately encounters deep disagreements
over cultural values.
Strength
We will develop the theory and application of the optimal strength of intel-
lectual property law. The strength of intellectual property rights depends on
three attributes: duration, breadth, and remedy. The duration of a patent can
be measured in years. Thus U.S. patent duration is 20 years from the date
of filing the patent application.3 When filing, the applicant and her patent
attorney make claims about the innovation’s breadth. The patent office and
2 The Semiconductor Chip Protection Act of 1984, which legally protects the layouts of integrat-
ed circuits, exemplifies such special statues.
3 Before 1995, U.S. patent duration was 17 years from the date the patent issued.
6.2
Robert Cooter
the courts ultimately decide the validity of these claims. Breadth is easier to
order than to measure. Thus a patent covering rain gear is broader than a
patent covering umbrellas, and a patent covering umbrellas is broader than a
patent covering automatically opening umbrellas. While one patent can be
broader or narrower than another, there is no natural measure of the differ-
ence in breadth.4
4 Patent breadth resembles the alphabet. Letters A through N encompasses more letters than A
through M, but there is no natural measure of the distance between M and N. Similarly, no natural
measure exists to answer the question, “Is the difference in breadth between a patent on rain gear and
a patent on umbrellas larger or smaller the difference in breadth between a patent on umbrellas and
a patent on automatically opening umbrellas?” In this respect, patent breadth contrasts with height.
One person is taller than another and the difference can be measured in centimeters.
Fortunately, an ordering without a measure can support the mathematics of maximization. This
fact makes modern utility theory possible in economics. Economic models often maximize utility
functions that order states of the world by preference (“ordinal utility”), but do not measure differ-
ences in utility levels. Similarly, finding the breadth of patent that maximizes growth only requires
an ordering by breadth, not a measure.
5 Note that money measures damages like years measure duration, whereas breadth orders (but
does not measure) injunctions like patent claims order their breadth.
6.3
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
6 This is a picture, not a graph, because the breadth of innovations has no natural measure. See
the discussion in this chapter of the difference between an ordering and an index.
7 Increases in the scope of a particular patent do not necessarily increase the scope of patents as a
whole. Rather, the scope of a particular patent can increase by decreasing the scope of another pat-
ent. Instead of fencing more of the common land of innovation, the fence between patent holders
moves to the advantage of one of them and to the disadvantage of the other, as with the boundary
between α and β in Figure 6.1.
6.4
Robert Cooter
How Strong?
What reach and strength (breadth, duration, and remedy) of intellectual
property rights maximizes innovation? The answer is remarkably simple.
Maximizing innovation requires transferring resources from consumption
and production to innovating. According to the separation principle (Chap-
ter 4), an innovator should have a strong patent against others copying the
innovation to sell to consumers, such as a smart phone application. An in-
novator should also have a strong patent against others producing consumer
goods by using the innovation, such as industrial robots that manufacture
cars. Applied to the strength of intellectual property, the separation principle
asserts that the innovator’s rights against others consuming it or producing with
it should be strong -- broad and long with a generous remedy for infringement. 9
6.5
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
to use it. Market power of innovators against each other imposes a dead-
weight loss on all of them, which slows innovation and growth. This fact
argues that innovators should have weak intellectual property rights against
each other, or none at all.
Chapter 4 described four forms of deadweight loss and their likely extent.
Creating market power for an innovator causes a large deadweight loss when
the patented good has close substitutes (high elasticity of demand),10 few
obstacles to resale (no price discrimination),11 the innovation is complex and
opaque (incomplete information for buyers),12 and many buyers purchase
small amounts of the good.13 These conditions argue that innovators should
have weak intellectual property rights against each other, or none at all.
To apply the separation principle, lawmakers and courts must distinguish the
uses of an innovation into consuming, producing, and innovating. In many
cases, the distinction requires non-technical judgments of the kind that
courts routinely make without statistics or mathematical theories. Common
sense usually suffices, but difficulties arise at the boundaries of these three ac-
tivities. In hard cases, economists can assist by drawing on their long history
of distinguishing these three activities. Economists can also assist by predict-
ing the effect of different distinctions on the goal underlying the separation
principle: maximizing innovation.
10 Goods are substitutes when having more of one makes a person demand less of the other.
When a good has close substitutes, raising its price (while keeping other prices constant) causes
buyers to switch to the substitute. Switching costs are a deadweight loss.
11 With few obstacles to resale, the owner cannot charge different prices to different buyers for
the same innovation. Price discrimination is impossible. The more the seller can discriminate
among buyers, the less the buyers will switch in response to a price increase, so the deadweight loss of
switching falls. This is an application of the proposition found in microeconomics textbooks that a
perfectly discriminating monopolist is efficient.
12 As a good becomes more complicated and opaque, the amount of bargaining increases, and so
do the search costs of determining whether an innovation is already patented.
13 Transactions costs of purchases often have economies of scale. Consequently, the transaction
cost of market exchange is higher with many buyers make small purchases than when few buyers
make large purchases.
6.6
Robert Cooter
ing and strong rights against consuming. Similarly, Sun Microsystems devel-
oped the Java programming language in the 1990s and made it available for
free to developers under a general-purpose license.14 Developers use Java to
write programs that they sell to consumers.15 Thus Java is free for innovators
and costly for consumers of its applications.
As explained, the overtaking principle and the deadweight loss from mo-
nopoly argue for weak intellectual property rights of innovators against each
other. However, an argument in the opposite direction applies when in-
novations differ significantly in fertility. By definition, costless transfers (no
deadweight loss) from less to more fertile innovations increase the rate of
innovation and growth. Stronger intellectual property rights for more fertile
innovations transfer wealth away from less fertile innovations. In transac-
tions among innovators, relatively greater fertility favors relatively stronger
intellectual property rights.
Applications
To maximize progress in the useful arts, intellectual property law should ap-
ply the separation and fertility principles. The separation principle favors
giving innovators strong rights – broad, long, and with a generous remedy
for infringement -- against others consuming the innovation or producing
14 A reverse of this pattern sometimes occurs. Thus when the owner of a platform for running
computer games allows consumers to use it for free and charges developers who want to use it to
create new games to sell to consumers.
15 Legal disputes subsequently arose when Microsoft modified java to run exclusively on its
Windows program, thus necessitating the use of Windows to run programs written in the modified
java language.
6.7
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
with it. The fertility principle usually favors giving innovators weak rights or
no rights against others using the innovation to make subsequent innova-
tions. In unusual case of especially fertile innovations, an innovator’s rights
against others using the innovation to make subsequent innovations should
balance incentives for fertile innovations and the deadweight loss from stron-
ger property rights. We will apply this general theory to intellectual proper-
ty’s strength as indicated by reach, breadth, duration, and remedy
How does this legal distinction square with the separation and fertility prin-
ciples? The separation principle favors strong patent protection over static
activities (consuming and producing) and weak or no patent protection over
dynamic activities (innovating). The telegraph was the first device to use the
electromagnetic spectrum to transmit messages, and many others followed,
including telephones and computers. The patent for the telegraph gave its
inventor’s temporary market power over transmitting messages by using the
16 The court recently sustained this view in Bilski (2010).
6.8
Robert Cooter
The separation and fertility principles broadly favor the patentability of in-
ventions and the non-patentability of discoveries of natural laws and facts.
Easy cases can follow common-sense distinctions, and hard cases can look to
evidence about locating the boundary to maximize economic growth. An
example of a hard case concerns whether diagnostic devices in medicine are
inventions or observations of nature. Diagnostic devices are used to treat
patients (consumption) and to conduct medical research (innovation). The
separation and fertility principles commend a different standard of “infringe-
ment” for medical treatment and medical research.
To speed innovation, the separation and fertility principles argue for patent
coverage of patient treatments, which implies that unlicensed use of a diag-
nostic device to treat a patient infringes the patent. The patent will increase
the cost of treatment, and patients will lose from higher prices in the short
run, but, according to the overtaking theorem in Chapter 1, patients will
gain more from faster innovation in diagnostic devices. The conclusion is
different for research as opposed to treatment. To speed innovation, the
fertility principle argues against patent coverage for research, which implies
that unlicensed us of a diagnostic devices to make medical innovations does
not infringe the patent. The law follows these prescriptions imperfectly. In
Prometheus (2012) the U.S. Supreme Court disallowed the patenting of di-
agnostic devices (and also surgical methods) without distinguishing between
treatment and research. In pharmaceuticals, however, the law follows the
separation principle and allows a “research exemption,” as we will discuss
shortly.
6.9
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
that weigh the arguments, some commentators doubt that an invention has
utility if its only use is to generate more inventions. This reasoning is con-
fused. A fertile innovation promotes “progress” in the “useful arts” even if
it is not used in consumption or production. Progress in the useful arts is
the constitutionally recognized purpose of intellectual property law. Thus
fertility is a constitutionally recognized form of utility, not a suspect category.
Breadth
In Figure 6.1 the patent authorities could issue one broad patent to A that
encompasses both α and β, or a narrow patent to A for α and a narrow patent
to B for β. Are α and β sufficiently similar to justify one patent, or are they
sufficiently different to require two patents? Common sense understanding
of it and engineering facts give the answer in most cases, but not in the hard
ones. Resolving hard cases requires connecting legal rules to their purposes.
The constitutional purpose of intellectual property law in the U.S. is promot-
ing progress in the useful arts, which economic innovation measures.
6.10
Robert Cooter
much wealth from buyers to the owner A as two narrow patents transfer to
the owners A and B.
When goods are substitutes, their use determines whether transferring wealth
from buyers to sellers increases or decreases incentives for innovation. If in-
novations α and β mostly have static uses (consuming and producing), then
one broad patent will transfer more wealth from static to dynamic activities
than two narrow patents, which increases the incentive to innovate. Thus
the separation principle favors broad patents for innovations that substitute
in consumption or production. Conversely, if innovations α and β are sub-
stitutes and they mostly have dynamic uses (innovating), issuing two narrow
patents will impose less deadweight loss on innovating, which increases the
incentive to innovate.
Demand for two goods is independent if the price of one does not affect
how much people will pay for the other (zero cross price elasticity). Inde-
pendent goods are dissimilar economically. Intellectual property law cannot
increase the market power or profitability of innovating by issuing broad
patents encompassing independent inventions. Thus when demand for α is
independent of demand for β, owning the patent on β does not increase the
profitability of owning the patent on α. Since independent goods are dissim-
ilar, broad patents do not increase the incentive to innovate. The breadth of
intellectual property makes little difference to market power created by pat-
ents for independent innovations. The patent authorities should issue narrow
parents for inventions of independent goods.
Table 6.1 summarizes these conclusions about use, substitution, and pre-
ferred patent breadth.
6.11
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
This reasoning applies to a series of suits that Apple brought against Samsung
beginning in 2011 for infringement of design patents for the iPhone and
iPad. For smart phones and tablets, Apple was the original innovator and
Samsung was the imitator. Samsung’s strategy was to build close substitutes
to the originals and to make small improvements. By imitating, Samsung
saved development costs, so Samsung built substitutes at lower cost and sold
them to consumers at lower prices. Consequently, Samsung’s share of the
smartphone market increased at Apple’s expense.18
The legal question is whether Samsung infringed Apple’s patents. Table 6.1
provides an answer by relating preferred patent breadth of substitutes to their
use. In so far as Samsung mostly used Apple’s innovations to make consumer
goods, the separation principle favors strong protection. Strong protection
will reward innovation and speed progress in the useful arts. In so far as
Apple’s innovations were fundamental and Samsung’s innovations were de-
rivative, the fertility principle also favors strong protection of Apple’s patents
against Samsung. Again, strong protection will reward fertile innovation
and speed progress in the useful arts. However, in so far as Samsung mostly
used Apple’s innovation to make its own innovations of similar fertility, the
fertility principle favors weak protection of Apple’s patents against Samsung.
Weak protection will reduce the deadweight loss on innovation and speed
progress in the useful arts.
18 Sang-Hun Choe, After Verdict, Assessing the Samsung Strategy in South Korea By CHOE
SANG-HUN ``, New York Times, Summer, 2012, http://www.nytimes.com/2012/09/03/
technology/companies/south-korea-reassesses-samsung-after-battle-with-apple.html?_
r=1.
6.12
Robert Cooter
vices appear to use Apple’s designs mostly to increase consumer sales, and
Samsung’s innovations appear to be derivative. If these appearances are the
deeper truth, then Apple’s patent protection should be strong against Sam-
sung. Liability of Samsung to Apple will promote faster growth in the future
by causing Samsung to devote more of its formidable technological prowess
to fundamental inventions and less to imitations.
We have discussed the alignment between patent breath and the separation
principle. For the pharmaceutical industry, an important exception to U.S.
patent law aligns them closely. Firms that develop a new drug need regula-
tory approval before marketing it in the U.S. To gain regulatory approval,
the drug’s owner must prove that it is effective and safe. Proof often requires
research on other chemically related drugs, including rivals for the same mar-
ket. The owner of a drug has reason to refuse to license its use by a rival. A
legal exemption (“Hatch-Waxman”) allows firms to use patented drugs for
research on regulatory compliance without a license from the patent’s own-
er. Instead of obtaining permission to license the patented drug at the price
demanded by the owner, the innovator can use the drug and pay a royalty
set by legal authorities. In the language of property rights, the innovator
can “take” the patentee’s property right by paying an “objective price” set by
the court, rather than having to pay the “subjective price” demanded by the
patent’s owner.
Duration
Next, apply the separation and fertility principles to the duration of a patent.
The horizontal axis in Figure 6.2 indicates the length of patents in years, and
the vertical axis indicates the rate of innovation. The curves in Figure 6.2
depict some possible relationships between the rate of innovation and pat-
ent length. For curve A, the rate of innovation is an increasing function of
19 Universities were traditionally exempted from the legal requirement to license patented inven-
tions for use in research in laboratories. This traditional research exemption was eliminated in …
6.13
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
Curve B depicts the intermediate case in between the pure cases of Curve
A and Curve C. In the intermediate case, strengthening weak intellectual
property rights increase the rate of innovation at first, but a point is reached
where further strengthening decreases innovation. In Figure 6.2, the optimal
patent duration of patents is internal, not infinite as for curve A or zero as
for curve C. In the intermediate case, moderately strong intellectual property
rights maximize the rate of innovation.
20 Landes and Posner advocate patents of infinite length, which we favor for patents against con-
suming and producing, but not for patents against innovating. CITE;
6.14
Robert Cooter
The ideal patent system grants patents of different length according to the
product’s growth profile as in Figure 6.2. German patent authorities issue
“petty” patents of short duration for minor inventions, and “full” patents
of longer duration for major inventions. In contrast, American patent law
issues full patents for all patented inventions. Does the German or Ameri-
can patent regime come closer to this ideal? For inventions mostly sold for
producing and consuming, full patents will transfer more wealth from static
to the dynamic uses. Consequently, American patent law is closer to the
ideal than German patent law for innovations mostly used for consuming
and producing. In contrast, for innovations mostly sold for innovating, the
ideal law issues strong patents to fertile inventions and weak patents to sterile
21 Curve B is a concave function with a unique maximum. Another possibility is a convex func-
tion with two local maxima, one for weak intellectual property rights and one for strong intellectual
property rights. Another possibility is multiple equilibria. For analyzing many activities, economists
assume a concave function with a unique maximum.
6.15
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
inventions. A stronger patent for fertile innovations and a weaker patent for
sterile innovations transfer wealth from the latter to the former in accordance
with the fertility principle. In so far as German patent authorities issue “full”
patents to fertile inventions and “petty” patents to sterile inventions, German
patent law is closer to the ideal than American law for innovations mostly
used for innovating.
The international default standard for patent duration, which the U.S. has
adopted, is twenty years from the date of the application for a patent. Quan-
titative research on the optimal duration of intellectual property rights has
barely begun. No compelling evidence indicates whether the pace of inno-
vation would increase from lengthening or shortening the duration, or from
distinguishing between petty patents and full patents. According to U.S. law,
copyright endures for the creator’s life plus 70 years.22 Many scholars be-
lieve that this is far too long. The shadow of dead writings apparently inhib-
its creativity. A U.S. statute on semiconductor protection possibly has a bet-
ter rule. The Semiconductor Chip Protection Act of 1984 (or SCPA) legally
protects the layouts of integrated circuits for 10 years from registration.23
Optimal Remedy
Patent law provides damages for past infringements. Three benchmarks for
damages are compensation, disgorgement, and treble damages. Compensa-
tion ideally puts the victim in the same position as if the infringement had
not occurred. For firms, this requires transferring profits from the injurer to
the victim until the victim’s profits equal what they would have been but for
the infringement. Disgorgement ideally puts the injurer in the same position
as if the infringement had not occurred. For firms this requires transfer-
22 In October, 1998, Congress passed the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, which
lengthens copy- right protection for works created on or after January 1, 1978, to the life of the
author plus 70 years, and extends existing copyrights “created for hire and owned by corporations” to
95 years. Before the change, the 1976 Copyright Act had given protection for the author’s life plus
50 years. Whatever other reasons there may be for the Copyright Term Extension Act, one justifica-
tion is that it brings U.S. practice into conformity with Western European practice.
23 The three dimensions of strength of intellectual property protection for the layouts of integrat-
ed circuits, which the law calls a chip’s “mask”, mix standards from patents and copyright. Breadth
is determined by the substantial similarity” test of copyright law, duration is 10 years from registra-
tion, and the available remedies correspond generally to copyright and patent law. Protection covers
all embodiments of the chip’s layout, but does not cover the chip’s functionality that patents law
protects or the information on chips that copyright law protects (if they are protected at all). If the
defendant asserts reverse engineering as a defense and provides “probative evidence” of it, then the
standard shifts from “substantially similar” to “substantially identical.”
6.16
Robert Cooter
ring profits from the injurer to the victim until the injurer’s profits equal
what they would have been but for the infringement. Treble damages simply
mean three times compensation.
The following inequalities order these remedies by the usual size of damages,
or, equivalently, by their strength:
In addition to damages for past harm, the owner can often obtain an injunc-
tion against future infringements.24 This possibility gives the owner a choice:
either prevents future infringements by enjoining them before they occur,
or deter future infringements by obtaining damages after they occur. If the
law allows the owner to defend his patent with an effective injunction, then
others must desist from using it or pay the owner’s asking fee for a license.
However, the law does not always give the owner a choice between injunc-
tion and damages. Sometimes the law allows damages but not injunction. If
the owner defends his patent by suing for damages, then, instead of licensing,
others may infringe and pay a price set by the court, not the owner’s asking
price.25 Thus in eBay v. Merc, the U.S. Supreme Court held that when a
24 In addition to patent law, U.S. firms have an additional remedy against infringing imports.
The U.S. firm can bring a case before the U.S. International Trade Commission asking it to ban the
import of all infringing goods. This powerful remedy against foreign infringement allegedly leads
to abuse by firms shielding themselves from foreign competition. See K. William Watson, Still a
Protectionist Trade Remedy: The Case for Repealing Section 337, No. 708 Policy Analysis (Cato
Institute) (2012).
25 Legal scholars say that property rights cannot be taken without paying the owner’s subjective
price, whereas the law allows other rights to be taken by paying an objective price. An implication of
this fact is that sellers will not sell property for less than it is worth to them, and buyers will not buy
property for more than it is worth them. Consequently, voluntary sales move property from people
who value it less to people who value it more, which yields a surplus that can benefit buyer and seller.
By creating surpluses, sales allocate resources to their most productive uses and reward innovators.
6.17
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
The fertility principle distinguishes between the usual innovations and very
fertile innovations. Infringements for dynamic uses involving the usual in-
novations should have weak remedies in order to reduce the excess burden on
innovators. Consequently, the fertility principle usually ranks remedies the
opposite of the separation principle. For past infringements by innovators,
compensation without a choice is preferred to a choice between disgorge-
ment or compensation, and a choice between disgorgement or compensation
is preferred to treble damages. For future infringements by innovators, the
fertility principle favors compensation without a choice instead of the choice
of compensation or an injunction. In contrast to the usual cases, unusual
cases concern infringements of patents for fundamental innovations that are
6.18
Robert Cooter
very fertile. Here the fertility principle ranks remedies the same as the sepa-
ration principle.
Table 6.2 summarizes these conclusions about the preferred remedy for eco-
nomic growth.
Table 6.2 compares compensatory damages to the strength of two other rem-
edies. Compensatory damages also differ in strength according to their basis
of computation. Production costs and development costs often figure as
elements in compensation for infringement. Compensation can include the
cost of the invention’s production and development, which suggests this or-
dering of compensatory damage measures for patent infringement:
The same reasoning as in Table 6.2 motivates the relationship between the
infringing use and the preferred measure of compensatory damages that Ta-
ble 6.3 depicts.
6.19
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
To illustrate the use of the tables, return to the case of eBay v. Merc, where
the court held that compensatory damages can compensate sufficiently for
infringing a patent on a small component in a large product. This decision
is apparently consistent with Table 6.2, which indicates that a patent owner
should receive compensatory damages for infringement by innovators in the
usual case. The “usual case” involves an innovator’s infringement of a patent
with low or average fertility, and a “small component in a large product”
presumably has low or average fertility. Furthermore, Table 6.3 indicates
that compensatory damages should preferably exclude development costs or
extraordinary profits. (Notice that the rule of compensatory damages repli-
cates the cost structure in a patent pool, which eliminates market power and
deadweight loss.26) In the exceptional case where one patented innovation is
much more fertile than others, however, Table 6.2 requires a strong remedy
– injunction or high damages.
Unix is “unowned” or “open access” or “in the public domain.” Its users are
unrestricted by patent or copyright, although it is trademarked.27 Since no
one privately owns Unix, using it does not require negotiating with anyone.
If someone owned Unix, however, anyone who wanted to improve it would
have to license its use. Negotiating a license takes time and effort, which re-
duces profits and slows innovation. An innovation thicket contains so many
circular transactions that bargaining over property rights slows growth. In-
novations in a thicket ideally remain in the public domain where anyone can
use them freely, like Unix. If not in the public domain, then innovations in a
26 In a patent pool, anyone is free to produce and use another’s patented good, without paying a
license fee. So anyone selling its patented good to another member of the pool must charge a price
that does not exceed the good’s production cost. If courts award compensation for production and
not development among innovators in a patent pool, costs replicate a patent pool.
27 Only users conforming to certain specifications can apply the name “Unix”.
6.20
Robert Cooter
thicket should, according to the fertility principle, receive weak patent rights
(narrow breadth in Table 6.1, weak remedy in Table 6.2, low damages in Ta-
ble 6.3). In the unusual case of a pioneering patent in a thicket, however, its
high fertility warrants strong patent rights (wide breadth in Table 6.1, strong
remedy in Table 6.2, high damages in Table 6.3).
Each of these solutions – cross licensing, pools, and mergers -- has limited
success in solving the patent hold out problem. 30 In practice, firms cross
license or pool a small fraction of patents, and small firms often resist merg-
ing for fear that size will impede creativity.31 Private transactions among
individuals often fail so solve the challenge of innovation thickets because of
problem that game theory explains. If innovations in a thicket are patented,
then each venture to develop an innovation needs licenses from several other
innovators. When several patent owners have the power to withhold licenses
that are necessary to develop an innovation, then the each of them can ef-
fectively veto the venture. Given multiple vetoes over a venture, every veto
holder must consent for the venture to proceed. If everyone with veto power
consents except for one, the last hold out can demand most of the venture’s
value in exchange for his consent. Since a patent holder gains by consenting
last, no one wants to consent first. As the number of patent-holders with
veto power increases, the probability increases that someone will hold out for
a higher license fee.
6.21
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
Behind this bargaining story lies a technical fact. When distributing the
value of a joint product, the usual rule in economics is for each participant
to receive his marginal product. The marginal product of a participant in a
cooperative venture equals the increase in the venture’s value when he par-
ticipates in it (holding the participation of others constant).32 In a patent
thicket, many people own essential patents for further innovation. Conse-
quently, the holdout’s marginal product is large, possibly equal to the ven-
ture’s entire value or nearly so. Furthermore, anyone can hold out who owns
an essential patent for the venture. In these circumstances, the sum of the
marginal products of the contributors to the venture exceeds the venture’s
total value. The venture does not have enough value for each contributor
to receive his marginal product. Demands that are reasonable individually
are unreasonable collectively. If the participants negotiate and each one de-
mands his marginal product, the venture is doomed.33 (For the same reason,
marginal product provides no basis for computing compensatory damages or
reasonable fees.34)
Given its intractability, private actors need law’s help to solve the hold out
problem. Law can help by weakening patents among innovators in a thicket.
Narrowing a patent’s breadth weakens its market power and lowers the price
that a license commands. In Apple v. Motorola, Judge Posner recently fol-
lowed this prescription by dismissing Apple’s infringement claims. Law can
also help to solve the holdout problem by weakening the remedy for patent
infringement. As mentioned above, in eBay v. Merc, the U.S. Supreme Court
held that the weaker remedy – damages instead of injunctions – applies to
small components in a complex innovation.
32 This is usually equivalent to the decrease in the venture’s value when he stops participating in it
(holding the participation of others constant).
33 In more technical language, increasing returns to the scale of a coalition implies that the sum of
the marginal contributions of each member exceeds the coalition’s total product, and the game’s “core
is empty”.
34 Damages for using another’s property often equal the marginal product that the owner lost
when the infringer used his property (compensatory damages), or else damages equal the marginal
product that the trespasser got from using another’s property (disgorgement damages). In a thicket,
“compensatory damages” or a “reasonable fee” for using a patented good without a license cannot
refer to its marginal product, because the sum of the marginal products exceeds the total product.
Marginal productivity theory is unreasonable for computing damages from infringement or negotiat-
ing shares in cross-licenses.
6.22
Robert Cooter
Name calling aside, law requires analysis of patent middlemen. After a busi-
ness venture develops and patents an innovation, the innovation must be
marketed to users and enforced against infringers. Innovating, marketing,
and enforcing are different specialties that different people can perform.
With respect to enforcement, the innovator can directly defend her patent or
she can indirectly defend by selling the right to collect damages to someone
else. Thus firm A invents and patents α. A can enforce the patent on α, or
A can sell α to B, or A can sell to B only the right to sue and collect damages
from infringers of α.
6.23
Ver. 1.4 - Chapter 6. Separation and Fertility in Intellectual Property Law
Conclusion
Intellectual property law, which includes patents and copyright law, establish-
es the ownership of innovations by people. It conveys a bundle of rights to
creators as determined by rules. The normative question of growth econom-
ics is, “Which ownership rules maximize innovation?” In order to increase
the pace of innovation, ownership rules should open competition to innovate
and increase the winner’s profits. This chapter poses the question, “Which
ownership rules maximize profits among ventures in open competition to
innovate?” Answering the normative question of growth economics requires
comparing two opposite effects of stronger intellectual property rights. The
first effect is a transfer from static activities (consumption and production)
to dynamic activities (innovation), which increases the profitability and pace
of innovation. According to the overtaking theorem explained in Chapter
1, transfers from static activities to dynamic activities increase the welfare of
people. So the first effect favors strong intellectual property against infringe-
ment by consumers and producers. The second effect is the dead-weight
loss of licensing dynamic activities, which decrease the profitability and pace
of innovation. So the second effect favors weak intellectual property rights
against infringement by innovators.
6.24