A. Premise Vs Conclusion Notes
A. Premise Vs Conclusion Notes
Conclusion Notes
When you think of the word 'argument,' you probably imagine two people yelling at one another
or having some sort of a fight. However, when we're discussing critical thinking, an argument is
a term used to describe something that can be far less dramatic than that. An argument, in this
context, is simply a statement, or set of statements, that includes at least one premise and a
conclusion. A premise includes the reasons and evidence behind a conclusion.
A conclusion is the statement that the premise supports and is a way of promoting a certain
belief or point of view. To help us better identify the premise and conclusion of an argument, we
can take a look at indicator words.
Introduction to Logic
Basic Definitions
An inference is a process of reasoning in which a new belief is formed on the basis of or in
virtue of evidence or proof supposedly provided by other beliefs.
The premises of an argument are those statements or propositions in it that are intended to
provide the support or evidence.
The conclusion of an argument is that statement or proposition for which the premises are
intended to provide support. (In short, it is the point the argument is trying to make.)
(Important note: premises are always intended to provide support or evidence for the
conclusion, but they don't always succeed! It's still an argument, and there are still premises
and a conclusion, even if the premises don't really provide any support at all.)
God is defined as the most perfect being. A perfect being must have every trait or property
that it's better to have than not to have. It is better to exist than not to exist. Therefore, God
exists.
Hillary Clinton must be a communist spy. She supports socialized health care, and everyone
who supports socialized health care is a communist spy.
It has rained more than 15 inches per year in Amherst every year for the past 30 years. So you
can safely bet it will rain more than 15 inches in Amherst this year.
Professor Chappell said that the ratio of female to male students in the class was exactly 3:1.
This means that there are 112 female students in the class, because there are 148 students in
the class total.
The Encyclopaedia Britannica has an article on symbiosis. It stands to reason that the
Encyclopaedia Americana has an article on symbiosis as well, since the two reference works
tend to cover the same topics.
Jason isn't an NRA member. Almost 90% of NRA members are republicans, and Jason isn't a
republican.
This can be a tricky subject. Many people think deduction is reasoning from the general to the
specific, and induction is reasoning from the specific to general. This is NOT how these
words are actually used by most logicians, nor in this course.
The distinction actually has to do with how strong the author of an argument intends the
evidence or support to be.
An argument is deductive if the author intends it to be so strong that it is impossible for the
premises to be true and the conclusion to be false, or in other words, that the conclusion
follows necessarily from the premises. A deductive argument attempts (successfully or
unsuccessfully) to provide full proof of the conclusion.
An argument is inductive if the author intends it only to be so strong that it is improbable that
the premises could be true and the conclusion false, or in other words, that the conclusion is
likely if the premises are true. An inductive argument only attempts (successfully or
unsuccessfully) to provide evidence for the likely truth of the conclusion, rather than
outright proof.
A deductive argument is valid if it has a form that would make it impossible for the premises
to be true and the conclusion false, or if the conclusion follows necessarily from the premises.
To test whether an argument is valid, you should first imagine that the premises are true—
whether or not they actually are—and then ask yourself, without appealing to
any other knowledge you have, could you still imagine the conclusion being false? If you can,
the argument is invalid. If you can't, then the argument is valid.
Note that validity does not have to do with the actual truth or falsity of the premises. It only
has to do with what would follow from them if they were true. A valid argument can have
false premises. For example:
It may be hard to imagine these premises as true, but it is not hard to recognize that if they
were true, the conclusion would also be true.
So there's more to an argument's being a good one than validity. To be a good argument, an
argument must also have true premises. An argument with true premises is called factually
correct.
An invalid argument may have true or false premises, and a true or false conclusion. A valid
argument may have false premises with either a true or a false conclusion. The only
combination that is ruled out is a valid argument with true premises and a false conclusion.
Sound arguments always have true conclusions.
Argument Form
The validity of a deductive argument is determined entirely by its form. Consider these
arguments.
These arguments share the same form: All A are B, No B are C, Therefore, No A are C. All
arguments with this form are valid. So the examples above are valid. (What is wrong with
#2?)
Now consider:
These arguments also have the same form. All A are F. X is F. Therefore, X is an A. All
arguments with this form are invalid. #4 may seem like a good argument because all the
premises and the conclusion are true (at least in fiction), but note that the conclusion isn't
made true by the premises. It could be possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion
false. #4 is invalid, and all invalid arguments are unsound. #4 is not a good argument.
1) If God existed, then J. Lo and Puffy would still be dating. But J. Lo and Puffy are not
dating anymore. Therefore, God does not exist.
2) If Minnie Driver has agreed to go on date with Kevin, then God exists. Minnie Driver has
not agreed to go on a date with Kevin. Therefore, God does not exist.
3) Either materialism is false or all emotions are physical processes in the brain. If all
emotions are physical processes in the brain, then it is possible to know what love feels like
simply by studying brain chemistry. It is not possible to know what love feels like simply by
studying brain chemistry. Therefore, materialism is false.
NOTE: An argument may still have a true conclusion even if it is invalid or factually
incorrect (or both). Consider:
Christina Aguilera loves all of Eminem's lyrics. The Eifel tower is made of cheese. Therefore,
Atlanta is the capital of Georgia.
The real upshot of this, however, is that just because you believe a certain conclusion, you do
not logically have to accept the soundness of every argument for that conclusion.
https://people.umass.edu/klement/100/logic.html
What IS an argument?
Example:
Self defense is a basic human right. - premise
Therefore, everyone should carry a handgun. - conclusion
NOTE:
Necessary condition - If you were not exposed to the influenza virus, you
will not get sick.
http://www.mesacc.edu/~barsp59601/text/103/notes/1.html