Linz e Stepan
Linz e Stepan
A democratic transition is complete when sufficient agreement has been reached about politi
cal procedures to produce an elected government, when a government comes to power that is
the direct result of a free and popular vote, when this government de facto has the authority to
generate new policies, and when the executive, legislative and judicial power generated by the
new democracy does not have to share power with other bodies de jure.
With this working definition, it should be clear why democratic activists and
theorists insist on distinguishing between liberalization and democratization. In
a nondemocratic setting, liberalization may entail a mix of policy and social
changes, such as less censorship of the media, somewhat greater space for the
organization of autonomous working-class activities, the introduction of some
legal safeguards for individuals such as habeas corpus, the releasing of most polit
ical prisoners, the return of exiles, perhaps measures for improving the distribu
tion of income, and most important, the toleration of opposition.
Democratization entails liberalization but is a wider and more specifically po
litical concept. Democratization requires open contestation over the right to win
control of the government, and this in turn requires free competitive elections,
the results of which determine who governs. Using these definitions, it is obvious
that there can be liberalization without democratization.1
l. Much o f the conceptual confusion about what Gorbachev was and was not doing with glasnost and
perestroika could have been avoided by a clearer understanding o f these two concepts. The above discus
sion o f the difference between liberalization and democratization is drawn from Alfred Stepan, Rethinking
Military Politics: Brazil and the Southern Cone (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988), chap. 1. Also
see Guillermo O’ Donnell and Philippe C. Schmitter, Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Tentative Con-
4 Theoretical Overview
elusions about Uncertain Democracies (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1986), 7-11, Adam Prze-
worski, Democracy and the Market: Political and Economic Reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), chap. 2, Guiseppe di Palma, To Craft Democracies: An Essay
on Democratic Transitions (Berkeley: University o f California Press, 1990), esp. 81-89, and Samuel P. Hunt
ington, The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century (Norman: University o f Oklahoma
Press, 1991),9.
2. ‘Electoralism,” or what we call the “electoralist fallacy,” figured prominently in recent debates about
Central America. See Terry Karl, “ Imposing Consent? Electoralism vs. Democratization in El Salvador,” in
Paul W. Drake and Eduardo Silva, eds., Elections and Democratization in Latin Americay 1980-1983 (San
Diego: Center for Iberian and Latin American Studies, University of California, San Diego, 1986), 9-36. See
also Abraham F. Lowenthal, ed., Exporting Democracy: The United States and Latin America (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1991) and Thomas Carothers, In the Name of Democracy: U.S. Policy toward
Latin America in the Reagan Years (Berkeley: University o f California Press, 1991).
Democracy and Its Arenas 5
opposition to point out (to their national and international allies as well as to the
nondemocratic regime) what additional, if any, indispensable changes remain to
be done. Such a standard is also extremely useful in circumstances where the old
nondemocratic regime has collapsed or been overthrown and an interim govern
ment is in power. Such moments are normally replete with elation, sweeping re
forms, and decrees. However, unless there is a rapid commitment to completing
all the steps required for a democratic transition, the “temporary” interim gov
ernment may become permanent.3
In most cases after a democratic transition has been completed, there are still
many tasks that need to be accomplished, conditions that must be established,
and attitudes and habits that must be cultivated before democracy could be con
sidered consolidated. What then are the characteristics of a consolidated democ
racy? Many scholars, in advancing definitions of consolidated democracy, enu
merate all the regime characteristics that would improve the overall quality of
democracy. We favor, instead, a narrower definition of democratic consolidation,
but one that nonetheless combines behavioral, attitudinal, and constitutional di
mensions. Essentially, we mean by a consolidated democracy a political situation
in which, in a phrase, democracy has become “the only game in town.”4
Behaviorally, democracy becomes the only game in town when no significant
political groups seriously attempt to overthrow the democratic regime or secede
from the state. When this situation obtains, the behavior of the newly elected gov
ernment that has emerged from the democratic transition is no longer dominated
by the problem of how to avoid democratic breakdown. Attitudinally, democracy
becomes the only game in town when, even in the face of severe political and eco
nomic crises, the overwhelming majority of the people believe that any further
political change must emerge from within the parameters of democratic formulas.
Constitutionally, democracy becomes the only game in town when all the actors
in the polity become habituated to the fact that political conflict will be resolved
according to the established norms and that violations of these norms are likely
to be both ineffective and costly. In short, with consolidation, democracy be
comes routinized and deeply internalized in social, institutional, and even psy
chological life, as well as in calculations for achieving success.
Our working definition of a consolidated democracy then follows:
3. We discuss interim governments in more detail in chapter 5. For an extensive discussion o f such gov
ernments, seeYossi Shain and Juan J. Linz, Between States: Interim Governments and Democratic Transitions
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995), esp. 28-40.
4. For other discussions about the concept o f democratic consolidation, see Scott Mainwaring, Guillermo
O’Donnell, and J. Samuel Valenzuela, eds., Issues in Democratic Consolidation: The New South American
Democracies in Comparative Perspective (Notre Dame, Ind.: University o f Notre Dame Press, 1992). For an
especially rigorous discussion o f the concept, see in that volume J. Samuel Valenzuela, “ Democratic Con
solidation in Post-Transitional Settings: Notion, Process, and Facilitating Conditions,” 57-104. Also see di
Palma, To Craft DemocracieSy 137-55. We owe the telling expression “only game in town” to Guiseppe di Palma.
6 Theoretical Overview
5- In essence this means that the literature on democratic breakdown, such as that found in John J. Linz
and Alfred Stepan, eds., The Breakdown o f Democratic Regimes (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
*978), would be much more directly relevant to analyzing such a phenomenon than this current book or
other books on democratic transition and consolidation. We obviously do not mean this as a criticism o f
the transition literature. Rather, our point is that the democratic transition and democratic breakdown lit
eratures need to be integrated into the overall literature on modern democratic theory. From the perspec
tive of such an integrated theory, the “ breakdown o f a consolidated democracy” is not an oxymoron.
Democracy and Its Arenas 7
much of the popular and ideological discussion of the current “wave” of democ
ratization is dominated by electoralism per se and/or the assumed democratizing
potential of market mechanisms per se. But democratic consolidation requires
much more than elections and markets.
lessors, which constitute the complex web of civil society, we should not forget
another part of society: ordinary citizens who are not a part of any organization.
Such citizens are often of critical importance in shifting the regime/opposition
balance because they turn up in the streets in protest marches, heckle the police
and the authorities, express their opposition first to specific measures, support
broader demands, and ultimately challenge the regime. Normally they are initially
small in numbers and later more numerous and can, in some cases, overwhelm
the representatives of the regime, forcing them to consider a growing liberaliza
tion and ultimately a regime change. However important, numerous, and heroic
such relatively unorganized groups may be, they would not be able to overthrow
the regime and establish a democratic regime if there were not the processes we
focus upon in this book. The fact that none of the regimes included in our work,
in the transition periods we analyze, was ready to use massive force, to give orders
to shoot on the crowds and thus provoke a massacre, as in Tiananmen Square, has
led us to give relatively little attention to the possibility that these nondemocratic
regimes could have been maintained by force. There is evidence that some lead
ers considered that possibility. They occasionally alerted their security forces for
combat readiness (e.g., in Berlin the day after the wall was breached). Ultimately,
however, such repression did not happen. The cost of that scale of repression was
too high, and the belief in the legitimacy of such a response too weak. Nondemo
cratic regimes, at least in southern Europe, the southern cone of South America,
and most of Communist Europe, did not enjoy that kind of legitimacy, and many
ordinary, unorganized people in civil society often discovered it, almost before the
rulers themselves. The most dramatic area where this was so was in parts of Com
munist Europe, such as East Germany and Czechoslovakia.
By political society in a democratizing setting we mean that arena in which the
polity specifically arranges itself to contest the legitimate right to exercise control
over public power and the state apparatus. At best, civil society can destroy a non
democratic regime. However, a full democratic transition, and especially demo
cratic consolidation, must involve political society. The composition and consol
idation of a democratic polity must entail serious thought and action concerning
the development of a normatively positive appreciation of those core institutions
of a democratic political society— political parties, elections, electoral rules,
political leadership, interparty alliances, and legislatures— by which society con
stitutes itself politically to select and monitor democratic government.6
For modern democratic theory, especially for questions about how to consol
idate democracy, it is important to stress not only the distinctiveness of civil soci
ety and political society, but also their complementarity This complementarity is
6. For an earlier discussion o f the need to distinguish between the civil society arena and the political
society arena, see Stepan, Rethinking Military Politics, chap. 1. For an adroit use o f the concepts in a concrete
historical analysis, see Paolo Farneti, “ Social Conflict, Parliamentary Fragmentation, Institutional Shift,
and the Rise of Facism: Italy,” in Linz and Stepan, eds., The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes, 3-33.
Democracy and Its Arenas 9
not always recognized. As we document throughout the book, one of these two
dimensions is frequently neglected in favor of the other. Worse, within the demo
cratic community, champions of either civil or political society all too often adopt
a discourse and a set of practices that are implicitly inimical to the normal devel
opment of the other. Since this opposition is seldom explicit, let us discuss the
forms this implicit opposition may take and how and why such discourse and
practice impede democratic consolidation.
In the recent struggles against the nondemocratic regimes of Eastern Europe
and Latin America, a discourse was constructed that emphasized “civil society
versus the state.” This dichotomy, of course, has a long philosophical genealogy.7
More importantly for our purposes, this philosophical tradition was politically
useful to those democratic movements that emerged in recent contexts where ex
plicitly political organizations were forbidden or extremely weak. A conception of
a civil society in opposition to the state was also politically useful as the opposi
tion attempted to isolate the nondemocratic regime and its state by creating an
“us” versus “them” ethical politics. Civil society in many countries was rightly
considered the celebrity of democratic resistance and transition.
The problem arises at the moment of democratic transition. Quite often dem
ocratic leaders of political society argue that civil society, having played its his
toric role, should be demobilized so as to allow for the development of normal
democratic politics.8 Such an argument is bad democratic theory and bad demo
cratic politics. A robust civil society, with the capacity to generate political alter
natives and to monitor government and state can help transitions get started, help
resist reversals, help push transitions to their completion, help consolidate, and
help deepen democracy. At all stages of the democratization process, therefore, a
lively and independent civil society is invaluable.
But we should also consider how to recognize conceptually, and thus help
overcome, the false contradictions some set up between civil society and political
society. The danger that democratic groups primarily located in civil society
7. For the contemporary revival o f civil society (especially in Eastern Europe and South America), see
the chapter by that name in Jean Cohen and Andrew Arato, Civil Society and Political Theory (Cambridge:
M IT Press, 1992), 29-82. This invaluable book adroitly combines political philosophy with comparative po
litical analysis. Also see the introduction to John Keane, ed., Civil Society and the State: New European Per
spectives (London: Verso, 1988), 1-31. The Cohen-Arato book is also valuable because it does not subsume
political society into civil society. János Kis, an important political philosopher, dissident, and former pres
ident o f the Free Democrats o f Hungary, was one o f the first thinker-activists to discuss the distinctive arenas
o f civil and political society. See Kis, Politics in Hungary: For a Democratic Alternative (Boulder, Colo.: Social
Science Monographs, 1989).
8. In some transitions the apparent crisis o f civil society merely reflects the fact that some o f the move
ments called civil society had, to a great extent, been created and directed by previously illegal political par
ties. When these political parties were able to participate legally in politics, they shifted their efforts away
from the mobilization o f civil society and, in some cases, consciously demobilized society. This phenome
non was particularly noticeable in Spain concerning those civil society organizations controlled by the
Communist Party. Many civil society movements in Chile were analogously controlled by Christian Dem
ocratic or Socialist Party leaders.
IO Theoretical Overview
might occasionally present for the development of political society is that norma
tive preferences and styles of organization, perfectly appropriate to civil society,
might be taken to be desirable or, indeed, the only legitimate style of organization
for political society. For example, many civil society leaders view with moral
antipathy “ internal conflict” and “division” within the democratic forces. Insti
tutional routinization, intermediaries, and compromise within politics are often
spoken of pejoratively.9 But each of the above terms refers to an indispensable
practice of political society in a consolidated democracy. Democratic consolida
tion requires parties, one of whose primary tasks is precisely to aggregate and rep
resent differences between democrats. Consolidation requires that habituation to
the norms and procedures of democratic conflict regulation be developed. A high
degree of institutional routinization is a key part of such a process. Intermediation
between the state and civil society and the structuring of compromise are likewise
legitimate and necessary tasks of political society. In short, political society,
informed, pressured, and periodically renewed by civil society, must somehow
achieve a workable agreement on the myriad ways in which democratic power
will be crafted and exercised.
To achieve a consolidated democracy, the necessary degree of autonomy and
independence of civil and political society must further be embedded in and sup
ported by the rule of law, our third arena. All significant actors— especially the
democratic government and the state— must respect and uphold the rule of law.
For the types of civil society and political society we have just described, a rule of
law embodied in a spirit of constitutionalism is an indispensible condition. A
spirit of constitutionalism requires more than rule by majoritarianism. It entails
a relatively strong consensus over the constitution and especially a commitment
to “self-binding” procedures of governance that require exceptional majorities to
change. It also requires a clear hierarchy of laws, interpreted by an independent
judicial system and supported by a strong legal culture in civil society.10
The above three conditions— a lively and independent civil society, a political
society with sufficient autonomy and a working consensus about procedures of
governance, and constitutionalism and a rule of law— are virtually definitional
prerequisites of a consolidated democracy. However, these conditions are much
more likely to be satisfied if a bureaucracy usable by democratic leaders and an
institutionalized economic society exist.
Democracy is a form of governance of life in a polis in which citizens have
9 - We discuss at length the question o f antipolitics in our chapter on Poland and in our discussion o f
Czechoslovakia. For an example o f how the language o f “ethical civil society” and “normal political society”
can at times emerge as normative opposites, see our chapter on Poland and especially table 15.1. Antipolitics
also created problems in post-transition Brazil.
to. For an excellent volume that discusses the relationships between constitutionalism, democracy, legal
culture, and “self-bindingness,” see Jon Elster and Rune Slagstad, eds., Constitutionalism and Democracy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), esp. 1-18.
Democracy and Its Arenas li
rights that are guaranteed and protected. To protect the rights of its citizens and
to deliver the other basic services that citizens demand, a democratic government
needs to be able to exercise effectively its claim to the monopoly of the legitimate
use of force in the territory. Even if the state had no other functions than these, it
would have to tax compulsorily in order to pay for police, judges, and basic ser
vices. Modern democracy, therefore, needs the effective capacity to command,
regulate, and extract. For this it needs a functioning state and a state bureaucracy
considered usable by the new democratic government. As we shall see in chap
ter 2, there are many reasons why in many territories of the world no such state
exists. In this book the question of state disintegration is particularly important
in parts of the former Soviet Union. But, insufficient state taxing capacity or a
weak normative and bureaucratic presence in much of the territory, such that cit
izens cannot effectively demand that their rights be respected or receive any basic
entitlements, is a great problem in many countries in Latin America, such as
Brazil. The question of the usability of the state bureaucracy by the new demo
cratic regime also emerges in countries where the outgoing, nondemocratic re
gime has given tenure (as in Chile) to many key members of the state bureaucracy
carrying out politically sensitive functions in justice and education. Important
questions about the usability of the state bureaucracy by new democrats in
evitably emerge in cases (as in much of post-Communist Europe) where the dis
tinction between the party and the state had been virtually obliterated and the
party went out of power, disintegrated, or was deligitimized.
The final supportive condition for a consolidated democracy concerns the
economy, or rather an arena we believe should be called economic society. We use
the phrase “economic society” to call attention to two claims that we believe are
theoretically and empirically sound. First, there has never been and there cannot
be a non-wartime consolidated democracy in a command economy. Second, there
has never been and almost certainly there never will be a modern consolidated
democracy in a pure market economy. If both of these claims are demonstrated to
be sound, modern consolidated democracies require a set of socio-politically
crafted and sociopolitically accepted norms, institutions, and regulations, which
we call economic society that mediates between state and market.
Empirically, no evidence has ever been adduced to indicate that a polity that
would meet our definition of a consolidated democracy has ever existed in a com
mand economy. But the question persists. Is there a theoretical reason to explain
such a universal empirical outcome? We think so. On theoretical grounds, our as
sumption is that at least a nontrivial degree of market autonomy and ownership
diversity in the economy is necessary to produce the independence and liveliness
of civil society so that it can make its contribution to a democracy. Likewise, if all
property is in the hands of the state and all price, labor, supply, and distributional
decisions are the exclusive purview of the state in control of the command econ
Theoretical Overview
First, the duty of protecting the society from the violence and invasion of other independent
societies; secondly, the duty of protecting, as far as possible, every member of the society from
the injustice or oppression of every other member of it, or the duty of establishing an exact ad
ministration of justice; and, thirdly, the duty of erecting and maintaining certain public works
and certain public institutions which it can never be for the interest of any individual, or small
number of individuals, to erect and maintain; because the profit could never repay the expense
to any individual or small number of individuals, though it may frequently do much more than
repay it to a great society.14
n. Robert A. Dahl in a similar argument talks about two arrows o f causation that produce this result.
Concerning the political arrow o f causation (e.g., in the case of Leninism in power), the party-state’s ide-
ology goes explicitly against the autonomy of civil society and political society. Or, in the case o f a state con
trolled command economy, the economic arrow o f causation goes against certain material needs o f a con
solidated democracy, such as freedom o f the press, because paper and printing materials could be denied.
See Dahl, “Why All Democratic Countries Have Mixed Economies,” in John Chapman and Ian Shapiro,
eds., Democratic Community (New York: New York University Press, 1993), 35:259-82.
12. See, for example, the ample documentation concerning fourteen advanced democracies contained
in John R. Freeman, Democracies and Market: The Politics o f Mixed Economies (Ithaca, N. Y : Cornell Uni
versity Press, 1989).
13- For an excellent analysis of inevitable market failures, see Peter Murrell, “ Can Neoclassical Economics
Underpin the Reform of Centrally Planned Economies?” Journal of Economic Perspectives'), no. 4 (1991): 59-76.
14- Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (London: J. M. Dent and Sons, Everyman’s Library Edition,
1910), 2:180-81.
Democracy and Its Arenas D
some safety net for its citizens hurt by major market swings, and some alleviation
of gross inequality, democracy would not be sustainable.15 Theoretically, of
course, it would be antidemocratic to rule such public policies off the agenda of
legitimate public contestation. Thus, even in the extreme hypothetical case of a
democracy that began with a pure market economy, the very working of a mod
ern democracy (and a modern advanced capitalist economy) would lead to the
transformation of that pure market economy into a mixed economy, or a set of
norms, regulations, policies, and institutions we have called an economic society.16
Any way we analyze the problem, democratic consolidation requires the insti
tutionalization of a socially and politically regulated market. This requires an eco
nomic society, which in turn requires an effective state. Even such a neoliberal
goal as narrowing the scope o f public ownership (privatization) in an orderly and
legal way is almost certainly carried out more effectively by a stronger state (in
terms of capacity) than by a weaker state. A severe breakdown of the existing levels
of the economy because of state incapacity to carry out any regulatory functions
greatly compounds the problems of economic reform and of democratization.17
In summary, a modern consolidated democracy can be conceived of as being
composed of five major inter-relating arenas, each of which, to function properly,
has its own primary organizing principle. Properly understood, democracy is
more than a regime; it is an interacting system. No single arena in such a system
can function properly without some support from one, or often all, of the other
15. The working of a modern democracy will normally also result in the legal exclusion o f some activi
ties from the market, such as the sale o f human organs and the sale o f children for sexual services.
16. Robert Dahl’s line of reasoning follows a similar development. “ Democracy would almost certainly
lead to the destruction of certain economic orders [including] not only a capitalist command economy but
also a strictly free market econom y.. . . If people who are harmed by the market have the freedom, power,
and opportunity to do so they will attempt to regulate the market so as to eliminate, or at least limit, the
damage they perceive . . . Political competition provides elected leaders with incentives for responding to
the views and votes of any organized or unorganized aggregate o f people.. . . One way or the other, then,
over time the victims of free markets are likely to influence the government— or some government, whether
local, state, provincial, or regional— to adopt interventionist policies intended to mitigate the harm— The
upshot is, then, that every democratic country has rejected the practice, if not always the ideology, of un
regulated competitive markets. Although it is true that a market economy exists in all democratic coun
tries, it is also true that what exists in every democratic country is a market economy modified by govern
ment intervention.” See his “Why All Democratic Countries Have Mixed Economies,” 259-82.
17. In post-Communist Europe, the Czech Republic and Hungary are well on the way to becoming in
stitutionalized economic societies. In sharp contrast, in the Ukraine and Russia the writ o f the state does
not extend far enough for us to speak o f an economic society. The consequences of the lack of an economic
society are manifest everywhere. For example Russia, with a population fifteen times larger than Hungary’s
and with vastly more raw materials, received only 3.6 billion dollars of direct foreign investment in 1992-93,
whereas Hungary received 9 billion dollars o f direct foreign investment in the same two years. Much of the
explanation for this variance was that Hungary had a strong economic society in the area o f a law, contracts,
and regulatory regime, whereas Russia had virtually no economic society and its command economy had
ceased to exist. The direct foreign investment figures are from the Wall Street Journal publication, Central
European Economic Review (Summer 1994), 6. The most cited example of market success, the Czech Re
public, is in fact one of the clearest examples of the political crafting of a new economic society. Indeed,
Stephen Holmes argues that “ Prime Minister Václav Klaus, far from being the antistatist he pretends to be,
is the most talented state-builder of postcommunist Europe.” See Holmes, “ The Politics of Economics in
the Czech Republic,” East European Constitutional Review 4, no. 2 (1995)- 52 - 55>quote from p. 52.
Table 1.1. The Five Major Arenas of a Modern Consolidated Democracy: Inter-related Principles and Mediating Fields
Civil Freedom of Rule of law which establishes legal guarantees Interests and values of civil society are the major generators of
society association and State apparatus to enforce rights of civil society to organize if political society
communication these rights are violated Civil society generates ideas and helps monitor the state
Economic society w ith sufficient pluralism to support the apparatus and econom ic society
necessary degree of autonomy and liveliness of civil society
Political Free and inclusive N eeds legitim acy in eyes of civil society Crafts constitution and major law s
society electoral contestation Needs legal guarantees anchored in rule of law and m aintained M anages state apparatus
by impartial state apparatus Produces overall regulatory fram ework for econom ic society
Rule Constitutionalism A legal culture w ith strong roots in civil society and respected Establishes a hierarchy of norms that make actions by, and
of law by political society and the state apparatus upon, other arenas legitim ate and predictable
State Rational-legal Norm ative support from civil society for rational-legal authority Imperative enforcem ent on civil, political, and econom ic societies
apparatus bureaucratic norms and its attendant monopoly of legitim ate force of dem ocratically sanctioned law s and procedures established by
Monetary support levied by political society and produced and political society
rendered to the state by a functioning econom ic society, which
has produced a sufficient taxable surplus
Economic Institutionalized Legal and regulatory framework produced by political society, Produces the indispensable surplus to allo w the state to carry
society market respected by civil society, and enforced by the state apparatus out its collective good functions and provides a m aterial base
for the pluralism and autonomy of civil and political societies
Democracy and Its Arenas 15
arenas. For example, civil society in a democracy needs the support of a rule of
law that guarantees the right of association and needs the support of a state ap
paratus that will effectively impose legal sanctions on those who would attempt
to use illegal means to stop groups from exercising their democratic right to or
ganize. Furthermore, each arena in the democratic system has an effect on other
arenas. For example, political society crafts the constitution and major laws,
manages the state apparatus, and produces the overall regulatory framework for
economic society. In a consolidated democracy, therefore, there are constant
mediations between the arenas, each of which is correctly in the “field” of forces
emanating from the other arenas (table 1.1).
5
T he In s t it u t io n a l C o m p o s it io n a n d L e a d e r s h ip
of t h e P r e c e d in g N o n d e m o c r a t ic R e g im e
Our central question here concerns the core group that is in day-by-day con
trol of the state apparatus. What is the institutional character of this state elite?
Does its character favorably or unfavorably affect democratic transition and con
solidation? The organizational base is necessarily analytically distinct from the
variable of regime type because, within some regime types (especially authoritar
ian), there can be dramatically different types of state elites, each with quite dif
ferent implications for democratic transition and consolidation. Without being
exhaustive, four different types of state elites can be distinguished: (1) a hierar
chical military, (2) a nonhierarchical military, (3) a civilian elite, and (4) the dis
tinctive category of sultanistic elites.
Hierarchical Military
As shown in chapter 4 on the consequences of prior nondemocratic regime
types, only an authoritarian regime has the possibility of being controlled by a hi
erarchical military organization. Control by such an organization is against the
logics of a totalitarian, post-totalitarian, or sultanistic regime.1 All hierarchical
1. In some cases, such as Chile and Uruguay, and especially the “dirty war” in Argentina, the military de
veloped a definition of the enemy in their national security doctrine that gave to the repression a totalitar
ian dimension. See, for example, Alexandra Barahona de Brito, “Truth or Amnesty—Human Rights and
Democratization in Latin America: Uruguay and Chile” (Ph.D. diss., University of Oxford, 1993). 28-61.
Actors and Contexts 67
2. For a more discursive argument about the analytical and historical utility o f the distinction between
military-as-government and military-as-institution, see Stepan, “ Paths toward Redemocratization, 75-78,
172-73. For the concept o f the military as a “situational elite” with a special relationship to the state, see Al
fred Stepan, “ Inclusionary and Exclusionary Military Responses to Radicalism with Special Attention to
Peru,” in Seweryn Bialer, ed., Radicalism in the Contemporary Age (Boulder: Westview Press, 1977), 3:221-39,
344-50.
68 Theoretical Overview
the hierarchical military have been involved in widespread human rights viola
tions and condition their loyalty, as a part of the state apparatus, upon not being
punished by the new democratic government. Such a legacy of human rights vi
olations presented severe problems for democratic consolidation in Argentina
and Chile.
This is not meant to imply a static situation. Power is always and everywhere
relational. We simply mean that, if a relatively unified, hierarchically led military
has just left the direct exercise of rule, the complex dialectical tasks of democratic
power creation and the reduction of the domains of nondemocratic prerogatives
of the military must become two of the most important tasks for new democratic
leaders.
Nonhierarchical Military
A nonhierarchical, military-led nondemocratic regime, on the other hand,
has some characteristics that make it less of a potential obstacle to democratic
transition and especially democratic consolidation. Concerning democratic
transition, if a nonhierarchically led military-as-government (e.g., of colonels
and majors) enters into difficulties, the incentive for the military-as-institution
to re-establish hierarchy by supporting an extrication coup is even higher than it
would be if the military-as-government were hierarchically led. The fundamen
tal political and theoretical distinction, however, concerns democratic consoli
dation. The chances that the military-as-institution will tolerate punishment
and trials of members of the outgoing nondemocratic government are signifi
cantly greater if the group being punished is not seen to be the military institu
tion itself, but a group within the military which has violated hierarchical norms.
Likewise, if the colonels have established para-state intelligence operations that
are perceived as threats even to the organizational military, the hierarchical mil
itary is much more likely to acquiesce (or even insist) that their reserve domains
of power be eliminated.
Civilian Leadership
In comparative terms, civilian-led regimes (even mature post-totalitarian
civilian-led regimes in which Communist parties are essential components) will
characteristically have greater institutional, symbolic, and absorptive capacities
than either military or sultanistic leaders to initiate, direct, and manage a demo
cratic transition. Civilian leaders are often more motivated to initiate and more
capable of negotiating a complicated reform pact than are the military. They often
have more links to society than do military or para-military sultanistic leaders.
Civilians also can see themselves as potential winners and rulers in a future dem
ocratic regime. This option is much less likely for military or sultanistic rulers.
There are, of course, potential problems for full democratic transition and
Actors and Contexts 69
Sultanistic Leadership
Last, we should briefly consider what the institutional composition of sul
tanistic rule implies for democratic transitions and consolidation. A sultanistic
regime is one in which the ruler personalizes the government and the regime and,
in an uninstitutionalized but erratically pervasive way, penetrates the state, polit
ical society, and civil society. Fused are not only the private and the public, but
also the civilian and the military. Theoretically, it is hard to classify sultanship as
either a military- or a civilian-led regime. Sultanistic regimes present an oppor
tunity for democratic transition because, should the ruler (and his or her family)
be overthrown or assassinated, the sultanistic regime collapses. However, the very
nature of a sultanistic regime means that there is very little space for the organi
zation of a democratic opposition. Therefore, short of death by natural causes,
sultanistic dictators are characteristically overthrown by quick, massive move
ments of civil society, by assassination, or by armed revolt (see table 4.2). This
manner of regime termination often leads to the dynamics of a provisional gov
ernment which, unless there is a decision to hold rapid elections, normally pre
sents dangers for democratic consolidation.4 Also, the very personalization of
power around the dictator may allow close associates of the regime to assume
power. Or, even when the group or armed movement leading the revolt eliminates
3. Pioneering work on new network formation and the associated phenomenon o f “ recombinant prop
erty” that is not really private and no longer public is being done by David Stark, “ Recombinant Property
in East European Capitalism,” Working Paper, Collegium Budapest, 1994.
4. We will discuss interim governments in our analysis o f the next variable.
Actors and Contexts 71
those most associated with the sultanistic regime, they may appoint themselves as
the “ sovereign” representatives of the people and rule in the name of democracy
without passing through the free contestation and free election phases that are
necessary for full democratic transition and consolidation.
T r a n s it io n In it ia t io n : W ho S t a r t s a n d W ho C o n t r o l s ?
5. For a more detailed discussion o f interim governments, see Yossi Shain and Juan J. Linz, eds., Between
States: Interim Governments and Democratic Transitions (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
Theoretical Overview
In t e r n a t io n a l In f l u e n c e
6. Guillermo O’Donnell and Philippe C. Schmitter, Tentative Conclusions about Uncertain Democracies
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1986), 19.
Actors and Contexts 73
Foreign Policies
Conceptually, foreign policies can have an influence on domestic contexts in
very different ways. To begin with, there are in fact three categories of situations
in which the use of force in foreign policy actually determines outcomes that re
late to democracy. First, a nondemocratic country can use force to overthrow a
less militarily powerful democracy and either annex or occupy the country or in
stall a nondemocratic puppet regime (e.g., Germany in Czechoslovakia in 1938).
Second, a nondemocratic regional hegemon (which can be a single country or a
community of countries acting collectively) can in its “outer empire” use military
force to reverse a successful democratizing revolutionary effort to overthrow a
nondemocratic regime (e.g., Hungary in 1956) or to reverse a liberalizing process
(e.g., Czechoslovakia in 1968). Third, a democratic country that is a victor in a war
against a nondemocratic regime can occupy the defeated country and initiate a
democratic transition by installation (e.g., Germany and Japan in 1945). However,
although foreign policies can have determinative force in the democratic transi
tion phase, democratic consolidation in an independent country is ultimately de
termined by domestic forces.
Another influence of foreign policy on democratic transition and consolida
tion concerns what we might call gate opening to democratic efforts. Formal or in
formal empires, largely responding to their own internal and geopolitical needs,
may open a previously closed gate to democratization efforts in subordinate re
gimes. Whether there will be a democratic transition or not and whether this will
lead to democratic consolidation or not is predominantly domestically deter
mined (e.g., most of the British Empire afterWorld War II, the Soviet bloc in East
ern Europe in 1989).
Zeitgeist
The concept of Zeitgeist is taken from the German tradition of intellectual his
tory and refers to the “spirit of the times.” We do not believe in any variant of the
“end of history” thesis— the thesis, namely, that one ideology, such as the demo
cratic ideology, can or will stop human efforts to respond to problems by creat
ing alternative political visions and ideologies.8 But we do maintain that, when a
country is part of an international ideological community where democracy is
only one of many strongly contested ideologies, the chances of transiting to and
consolidating democracy are substantially less than if the spirit of the times is one
where democratic ideologies have no powerful contenders. The effect of a demo
cratically hostile or a democratically supportive Zeitgeist can readily be seen when
we contrast interwar Europe with the Europe of the mid-1970s and the 1980s. In
interwar Europe, in the aftermath of the break-up of the Austro-Hungarian Em
pire, boundary changes emerging out of the Treaty of Versailles, and various po
litical experiments, eleven states with little or no prior experience of an indepen
dent democratic regime made some effort to establish democracies.9 However,
the spirit of the times was one in which the democratic ideal competed with four
8. See, for example, Francis Fukuyama, “ The End o f History,” National Interests (Summer 1989): 3-18.
The return to power in Lithuania, Poland, and Hungary o f reform communists as social democrats is but
one example of how history can evolve in new and unexpected ways. Another example is the resurgence, in
the name o f “democratic majoritarianism,” o f ethnic nationalist dictatorships in parts o f the former Soviet
Union and Yugoslavia.
9. These states were Spain, Italy, Poland, Hungary, Czechoslovakia, Estonia, Latvia, Lithuania, Bulgaria,
Yugoslavia, and Romania. For a discussion o f their demise, see Juan J. Linz, “ La crisis de las democracias,”
in Mercedes Cabrera, Santos Julia, and Pablo Martin Acena, eds., Europa en crisis, 1919-1939 (Madrid: Edi
torial Pablo Iglesias, 1992), 231-80.
Actors and Contexts 75
10. Leszek Kolakowski, Main Currents o f Marxism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978), 3: 4 ^5-
11. For the effects on the domestic politics o f East European countries and the Soviet Union o f having
signed the Helsinki Accords, see Samuel P. Huntington, The Third Wave: Democratization in the Twentieth
Century (Norman: Oklahoma University Press, 1991), esp. 85-100.
12. For Vatican II and how it enhanced the status o f democracy in Roman Catholic theology, see George
Weigel, The Final Revolution: The Resistance Church and the Collapse of Communism (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1992), esp. 67-74.
13. The revalorization o f democracy by the left produced a rich new genre o f writings. For one such ex
ample see Francisco Weffort, “ Why Democracy?” in Alfred Stepan, ed., Democratizing Brazil: Problems of
Transition and Consolidation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), 327-50.
Theoretical Overview
oughly disappointed. In Africa, “one-party” states by the early 1990s had lost al
most all their original credibility as “mobilizing regimes” and were increasingly
disdained as “rent-seeking” formulas exploited by nondemocratic elites.
Diffusion
Zeitgeist in the world of politics refers to historical eras. But the diffusion effect
in an international political community, especially in a community tightly coupled
by culture, coercive systems, and/or communication, can refer to weeks or even
days. Law-like statements about human creations such as democracies are inher
ently different from law-like statements in the physical sciences because no two
moments in history can be exactly alike. Human beings reflect upon previous
events and, where the events seem directly relevant to them, often consciously or
unconsciously attempt to adjust their behavior so as to achieve or avoid a com
parable outcome. Political learning is possible. For example, after the Portuguese
revolution had exploded, a Spanish conservative leader, Manuel Fraga, expressed
some interest in playing a role in leading democratic change because he “did not
want to become the Caetano of Spain.” 14 Likewise Prince Juan Carlos in Spain
was undoubtedly influenced by the Greek case, where his brother-in-law, King
Constantine, lost his throne due to his ambivalence about democracy.
More generally, we posit that the more tightly coupled a group of countries
are, the more a successful transition in any country in the group will tend to
transform the range of perceived political alternatives for the rest of the group.
Indeed, as we shall see when we examine Central and Eastern Europe in 1989, in
ternational diffusion effects can change elite political expectations, crowd be
havior, and relations of power within the regime almost overnight. For practi
tioners and theorists alike, diffusion effects have obviously gained in salience in
the modern world owing to the revolution in communications. Today, the dra
matic collapse of a nondemocratic regime is immediately experienced by virtu
ally the entire population of the neighboring countries through radio and televi
sion. This experience in turn instantly becomes a powerful new component of
domestic politics.15
T h e P o l it ic a l E c o n o m y of L e g it im a c y a n d of C o e r c io n
14. Fraga was referring to the overthrow o f the post-Salazar leader o f Portugal, Marcello Caetano, who
failed to initiate a transition. The diffusion effect here is that Spanish conservatives rapidly began to recal
culate the costs and benefits o f initiating a democratic transition.
15. All countries discussed in this volume experienced some diffusion effects, but none more dramati
cally than the countries o f Central and Eastern Europe.
Actors and Contexts 77
How does the economy affect the prospects of a transition away from a nondem-
ocratic regime? If a transition has begun, how does the economy affect the
chances of democratic consolidation? Are democratic and nondemocratic regimes
equally helped by sustained growth? Are democratic and nondemocratic re
gimes equally hurt by economic decline?
We accept the well-documented correlation that there are few democracies at
very low levels of socioeconomic development and that most polities at a high
level of socioeconomic development are democracies.16 Most of the major mod
ern transition attempts thus take place in countries at medium levels of develop
ment. However, this relationship between development and the probability of de
mocracy does not tell us much about when, howyand if a. transition will take place
and be successfully completed. Indeed, within this critical context of intermedi
ate levels of development we contend that it is often difficult or impossible to
make systematic statements about the effect of economics on democratization
processes.17 However, if one uses an analytical framework that combines politics
and economics and focuses on legitimacy, one can make much more meaningful
statements. Certainly for transition theory, economic trends in themselves are less
important than is the perception of alternatives, system blame, and the legitimacy
beliefs of significant segments of the population or major institutional actors.
Why?
For theoreticians and practitioners who posit a tightly coupled relationship
between the economy and regime stability, robust economic conditions would
appear supportive of any type of regime. We would argue, however, that the
proposition is theoretically and empirically indefensible. We see good theoretical
reasons why sustained economic growth could erode a nondemocratic regime.
We see no theoretical reason why sustained economic growth would erode a dem
ocratic regime. Regime type can make a great difference. From the perspective of
political economy, we absolutely cannot formulate any valid propositions that
take the form, “under conditions of great economic prosperity there will be no in
centives for a transition from a nondemocratic to democratic regime.” This is so
precisely because many nondemocratic regimes, especially those of the statistical
16. The classic initial formulation o f this argument was Seymour Martin Upset, “Some Social Requi
sites o f Democracy: Economic Development and Political Legitimacy,” American Political Science Review
(March 1959): 69-105. Larry Diamond reviewed three decades of literature relevant to the development/de
mocracy debate and concluded that the evidence broadly supports the Lipset theory. See Diamond, Eco
nomic Development and Democracy Reconsidered,” in Gary Marks and Larry Diamond, eds., Reexamin
ing Democracy (Newbury Park: Sage, 1992), 93-139.
17. The specific relationship between economic growth or economic crisis and the initiation o f a tran
sition out o f a nondemocratic regime has been the object o f considerable debate. José Maria Maravall, in
an outstanding and well-researched work, has analyzed this problem in great detail, with particular refer
ence to southern and Eastern Europe. We find that his analysis converges with our brief analysis, which we
had written independently. We are happy to refer the reader to his book for the relevant evidence. See José
Maria Maravall, Los resultados de la democracia: Un estudio del sur y el este de Europa (Madrid: Alianza
Editorial, 1995).
78 Theoretical Overview
mode, authoritarian regimes, are originally defended by the state elite and their
core socioeconomic allies as necessary given the exceptional difficulties (often
economic) the polity faces. Thus, prolonged economic prosperity, especially in an
authoritarian regime, may erode the basis of the regimes justification based on
exceptional circumstances. Prolonged economic success can contribute to the
perception that the exceptional coercive measures of the nondemocratic regime
are no longer necessary and may possibly erode the soundness of the new eco
nomic prosperity.
Prolonged economic growth may also contribute to social changes that raise
the cost of repression and thus indirectly facilitate a transition to democracy. Pro
longed economic expansion normally contributes to the growth of a middle class;
a more important and needed skilled labor force; an expansion of education;
greater contacts with other societies via television, radio, and travel; and a more
diverse range of possible protests. There is even strong evidence to indicate that,
within a territory, increases in regional wealth increase citizens’ expectations that
they should be well treated by the police.18
Empirically, there are a number of cases where sustained prosperity altered re
lations of power in favor of democratic forces. In fact, three cases in our study,
Pinochets Chile, Brazil in the early 1970s, and Franco’s Spain in its last twenty
years (as well as South Korea), had some of the world’s highest rates of economic
growth. Spain’s growth contributed to the belief of some of the core constituents
of the authoritarian regime and among the industrial elite that they could man
age equally well in the future in a more democratic environment. The times had
changed and so did the regime.19 In Brazil, the soft-line military wing announced
its liberalization program in September 1973, after five years of unprecedented
growth and before the oil crisis, soaring interest rates, and its attendant debt cri
sis. In September 1973 the military felt that the economy was in excellent condi
tion and no significant political threat existed. In the absence of the “exceptional
circumstances” that had legitimated their coup in their own eyes, they came to be
lieve that continued authoritarian rule not only was not necessary but might con
tribute to the autonomy of the security forces and the “Argentinization of
Brazil.”20 In Chile many of the key industrialists who had believed that Pinochet
18. For example, seven occupational groups in Franco’s Spain, ranging from manual laborers to those
in liberal professions, were asked if they expected “ equal,” “ better,” or “worse” treatment by the police than
other citizens. The data were broken down according to the level o f economic development o f the respon
dents’ place o f residence. In 19 of 21 o f the possible comparisons, the greater the regional economic devel
opment, the greater the expectation o f equal treatment by the police. See Juan J. Linz, “ Ecological Analysis
and Survey Research,” in Mattei Dogan and Stein Rokkan, eds., Quantitative Ecological Analysis in the So
cial Sciences (Cambridge: M IT Press, 1969)* 91-131. esp. table 1, p. 113.
19. As Adolfo Suárez said before he became prime minister o f Spain, “Our people who at the beginning
of his (Franco’s) government had asked simply for bread, today ask for quality consumption, and in the
same fashion, whereas at the beginning they wanted order, today they ask for freedom— freedom o f polit
ical association.” Speech in the Cortes on June 9,1976.
20. Stepan, Rethinking Military Politics, 32-33.
Actors and Contexts 79
was indispensable in 1980, by 1988 had come to believe that the risk of fair elec
tions to the economic model was less than the risk of supporting Pinochet in un
fair elections.21 In all three cases, the political economy of prosperity contributed
to new perceptions about alternative futures and to lessening resistance to demo
cratic alternatives.
In sharp contrast, when we consider democratizing regimes or consolidated
democracies, there are no theoretical reasons or empirical evidence to support an
argument that economic growth contributes to regime erosion. Of course, a “ rev
olution of rising expectations” may create new demands on democratic govern
ments, but it cannot attack their raison d'être. Indeed, if a regime is based on
the double legitimacy of democratic procedures and socioeconomic efficacy, the
chances of a fundamental regime alternative (given the absence of a “stateness”
problem) being raised by a significant group in society is empirically negligible.
Severe economic problems affect democratic and nondemocratic regimes, es
pecially authoritarian ones, very differently. There are good theoretical reasons
why sharp economic decline (say five years of continuous negative growth) will
adversely affect stability in both democratic and nondemocratic regimes, but it
will affect the latter substantially more. Modern nondemocratic (especially au
thoritarian) regimes are often heavily dependent on their performance claims but
are not bolstered by procedural claims deriving from their democratic status.
Theory leads us to posit therefore that a democratic regime has two valuable
sources of insulation from sustained economic downturn not available to a non
democratic regime: its claim to legitimacy based on its origin and the fact that
elections are always on the horizon and hold the prospect of producing an alter
native socioeconomic program and an alternative government without a regime
change. This means that most new democracies have about eight years of breath
ing space— four years or so for the initial government and four years or so for an
alternative government.
This theory-based assumption gains strong empirical support from data com
piled by Fernando Limongi and Adam Przeworski. In their study of South Amer
ica between 1945 and 1988, they found that the probability that a nondemocratic
regime would survive three consecutive years of negative growth was 33 percent,
whereas the probability that a democratic regime would survive three years of neg
ative growth was 73 percent. More dramatically, their data show that no nondem
ocratic regime survived more than three years of consecutive negative growth,
whereas the probability that a democratic regime would survive four or five years
of consecutive negative growth was 57 percent and 50 percent respectively.22
Let us return to our argument concerning economics and the politics of alter
21. See the interview with one o f the leaders o f a major business interest group in Chile, in Alfred
Stepan, “ The Last Days o f Pinochet?” New York Review o f Books (June 2,1988): 33.
22. Fernando Limongi and Adam Przeworski, “ Democracy and Development in South America,
1945-1988” (University o f Chicago, October 27,1993, unpublished manuscript).
8o Theoretical Overview
23. For a more detailed development o f this argument with supporting data, see Juan J. Linz and Alfred
Stepan, “ Political Crafting o f Democratic Consolidation or Destruction: European and South American
Comparisons,” in Robert A. Pastor, ed., Democracy in the Americas: Stopping the Pendulum (New York:
Holmes and Meyer, 1989), 41-61. We are indebted to Ekkart Zimmerman for his pioneering studies o f in
terwar Europe. See Zimmerman, “ Government Stability in Six European Countries during the World Eco
nomic Crisis o f the 1930s: Some Preliminary Considerations,” European Journal o f Political Research 15, no.
1 (1987): 23-52 and Zimmerman, “ Economic and Political Reactions to the World Economic Crises o f the
1930s: Six European Countries,” paper presented for the Mid-West Political Science Association Conven
tion, Chicago, April 10-12,1986.
Actors and Contexts 81
C o n s t it u t io n -M a k in g E n v ir o n m e n t s
24. In Linz and Stepan, “ Political Crafting o f Democratic Consolidation or Destruction, 44, we note
that, during a period (1978-1981) o f rising unemployment, inflation, recession, and terrorism the Spanish
citizens belief in the efficacy o f democracy declined by 25 percentage points in national polls while the be
lief that democracy was the best political system for a country like Spain increased by 5 percentage points
in the same period. The key implication is that the citizenry did not believe, despite the economic prob
lems, that any alternative political system was preferable.
82 Theoretical Overview
25. Some indispensable sources on constitutions and democracy are Jon Elster and Rune Slagstad, eds.,
Constitutionalism and Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988); Douglas Greenberg,
Stanley N. Katz, Melanie Beth Oliveira, and Steven C. Wheatly, eds., Constitutionalism and Democracy:
Transitions in the Contemporary World (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993); Bruce Ackerman, The
Future of Liberal Revolution (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1992); A. E. Dick Howard, ed., Constitution
Making in Eastern Europe (Washington: Woodrow Wilson Center Press, 1993); and the East European Con
stitutional Review, published quarterly since 1992 by the Center for the Study o f Constitutionalism in East
ern Europe at the University o f Chicago Law School in partnership with the Central European University.
Actors and Contexts 83
26. For an argument in favor o f consensual constitutions produced and ratified by nationwide debates,
see Ackerman, The Future o f Liberal Revolution, 46-68.