Bioethics in A Liberal Society
Bioethics in A Liberal Society
Liberal Society
MAX CHARLESWORTH
CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
-iii-
-iv-
'Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is
sovereign'.
'No one outside of him can really touch him, can touch his soul, his
immortality; he must live with himself forever. He has a depth within
him
unfathomable, an infinite abyss of existence'.
-v-
Contents
1. INTRODUCTION 1
2. AUTONOMY AND THE LIBERAL IDEAL 10
The idea of autonomy 10
The liberal society 15
Critics of the liberal ideal 20
3. ENDING LIFE 30
The ethics of suicide 30
A moral right to die? 36
Decriminalising suicide 39
Multicultural attitudes to death and dying 41
Choosing for those who cannot choose for
themselves 45
The quality of life 48
The liberal society and the right to die 52
Death and the hospital 55
4. BEGINNING LIFE 63
New ways of birth and family formation 63
Bearing a child for another 69
Questions about surrogacy 73
-vii-
Consequences of surrogacy 81
Feminist views on reproductive technology 88
'Third wave' feminist views 96
Social and legal implications 102
5. DISTRIBUTING HEALTH-CARE RESOURCES 107
The problem of scarce resources 107
Utilitarian approaches 111
A health system in a liberal society 117
Patient and physician 120
Health-care resource allocations: four
examples 123
Reaching community consensus 142
Two forms of community consultation 145
The limits to planning 153
6. CONSENSUS IN A LIBERAL SOCIETY 160
The liberal ideal and bioethical realities 160
Ethical agreement in a multicultural society 162
Conclusion 167
INDEX 169
-viii-
1
Introduction
Issues in health ethics or medical ethics or so-called bioethics are
very often considered in abstraction from the social and political
context in which they arise. But it is obvious that making
decisions about those issues will differ quite radically in a liberal
democratic society as compared with any kind of non-liberal
society, whether it be theocratic or authoritarian (the term is
used in a neutral sense) or paternalistic or 'traditional'. In a
liberal society personal autonomy, the right to choose one's own
way of life for oneself, is the supreme value. Certain conse-
quences follow from the primacy given to personal autonomy in
the liberal society. First, there is in such a society a sharp dis-
junction between the sphere of personal morality and the sphere
of the law. The law is not concerned with matters of personal
morality and the 'enforcement of morals'. Second, the liberal
society is characterised by ethical pluralism, which allows a wide
variety of ethical and religious (and non-religious) positions to
be held by its members. Third, apart from the commitment to
the primacy of personal autonomy, there is no determinate
social consensus about a set of 'core values' or a 'public morality'
which it is the law's business to safeguard and promote.
-1-
-2-
This is, alas, especially the case with some Christians who
seem to think that they have a right to use the law to enforce
Christian morality on divorce, abortion, contraception, assisted
procreation, suicide and so on. I am myself a Christian and I have
always thought that, while upholding their own moral values,
Christians should also be especially concerned to uphold the
value of personal autonomy. There has been a long tradition of
Christian theological thought (more honoured, perhaps, in the
breach than in the observance) which emphasises the primacy
of the individual 'conscience'. St Thomas Aquinas says, for
example, that it is a sin to go against the dictates of one's
conscience. Again, it has always been a tenet of traditional
Christianity that it is a sin to coerce non-Christians into the
Christian Church, and one may legitimately infer that it is simi-
larly against Christian faith to use the law to coerce non-believers
in respect of moral matters.
-3-
-4-
-5-
-6-
-8-
bioethical and medical-ethical questions is possible in a liberal,
ethically pluralistic, multicultural society of autonomous indi-
viduals.
NOTES
1. Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard Univer-
sity Press, 1986, p.441.
-9-
2
Autonomy and the
Liberal Ideal
The idea of autonomy
The idea of autonomy is a blindingly obvious one. It simply
means that if I am to act in an ethical or moral way I must choose
for myself what I am going to do. I may of course take advice
from others and I may be subject to persuasion and pressure
from external sources, but when the chips are down I must
decide and choose for myself. Only then is what I have done
imputable to me so that it is my act, and only then am I respon-
sible for it and praiseworthy or blameworthy for it. 1 As a
contemporary thinker has put it:
-10-
The ruling principle is clear; a man who acts against his conscience is
always in the wrong, even if his conscience is mistaken. If he acts
according to his conscience and his conscience is right, well and
good; if his conscience is mistaken but through no fault of his own,
then his action is not morally bad. 7
In the nineteenth century, Cardinal Newman also drew upon
this tradition of thought. In the English controversy over
whether Catholics' allegiance to the Pope conflicted with their
allegiance to the Queen, Newman affirms the right of personal
conscience. Thus in the Letter to the Duke of Norfolk Newman says
-11-
-12-
-14-
determination, and my responsibility for making myself
through my acts, by practising 'self deception' or 'bad faith'
(mauvaise foi). The attempt to escape the 'burden' of freedom
and self-determination or autonomy is paradoxical, since any
attempt to abdicate from having to choose freely and respon-
sibly for myself presupposes that I am free. I am in effect saying:
'I freely choose no longer to freely choose what I am going to
do', or 'As a conscious self-determining subject I choose to be a
predetermined thing'. Just as for Descartes I cannot doubt that I
am a conscious being since I have to presuppose that I am con-
scious in order to doubt, so also for Sartre the attempt to
abandon one's moral autonomy presupposes that I am free, self-
determining and autonomous. Nevertheless, as Sartre shows in
his brilliant delineations of the pathological strategies of 'bad
faith' and 'self-deception' in all areas of human life, we can cer-
tainly succeed in deceiving ourselves and in forsaking our auton-
omy and evading responsibility for ourselves. In fact, for Sartre
the life of 'authenticity' based upon autonomy is arduous and
only rarely successful. In a sense Sartre deromanticises the idea
of autonomy in that, while emphasising that it is the central
good, he also emphasises that it is a burden which most people
would prefer to avoid and that it is very difficult to escape from
the lures of 'bad faith' and to achieve authenticity. We all say
that we want to be free and autonomous ('Give me liberty or
death'!) but in fact we spend most of our time trying to escape
from freedom and autonomy. 12
-15-
The ideal of the liberal society was given its classic formula-
tion in John Stuart Mill's essay On Liberty. The principle which
enables us to demarcate the sphere of individual liberty from
that of the state and the law, and to set limits to the latter is
this:
The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over
any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent
harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a
sufficient warrant. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do or for-
bear because it will be better for him to do so, because it will make
him happier, because, in the opinions of others to do so would be
wise, or even right. These are good reasons for remonstrating with
him, or reasoning with him, or persuading him, or entreating him,
but not for compelling him, or visiting him with any evil in case he
do otherwise. . . . The only part of the conduct of any one, for which
he is amenable to society, is that which concerns others. In the part
which merely concerns himself, his independence is, of right,
-16-
absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual
is sovereign. 13
-17-
It was noted before that liberalism does not involve any kind
of ethical relativism or scepticism, as though there were no
objective values and it was in some way improper for members
of a liberal society to espouse and propagate their own ethical or
moral positions. In On Liberty Mill expressly rejects any kind of
scepticism about ethical values and contemporary defenders of
the liberal ideal do the same. 15 Liberalism in fact depends upon a
recognition of the unequivocally objective value of personal
autonomy and the other values -- equality, justice and so on --
-18-
-19-
The liberty to decide and choose for oneself is, however, only
part of what Mill means by 'individuality'. He also means the
right to be different. Though this might be superficially inter-
preted as a plea for bohemianism or mere eccentricity, Mill is
getting at something important here, namely that each person
has his or her own moral style of life or 'vocation'. Morality is not
just a matter of conforming to universal rules or following a
maxim which, as Kant puts it, can apply to everyone alike. There
is a saying that the saints are admirable but not imitable. But in a
certain sense this is true of every moral agent. Each person has
an inimitable moral style and vocation, and all his or her acts
bear a distinctive personal impress.
It may be that the ideal of freedom to live as one wishes -- and the
pluralism of values connected with it -- is only the late fruit of our
declining capitalist civilisation: an ideal which remote ages and
primitive societies have not known, and which posterity will regard
with curiosity, even sympathy, but little comprehension. This may
be so, but no sceptical conclusion seems to me to follow. Principles
are no less sacred because their duration cannot be guaranteed. 18
-20-
-21-
-22-
-23-
Freedom and diversity are values too, and individualism and imper-
sonal justice are types of morality as well. To defend them is not to
deny the obvious -- that, whatever 'society' does, it promotes some
set of values. However, the defenders of 'the man on the Clapham
bus' not only are urging upon us a very specific and narrow set of
norms; they are doing it in order to bring conformity into a plural-
istic society, and under the false pretence of defending moral values
against the amoral. 23
The same reply might also be made to the criticism that the
state and the law cannot be neutral with respect to moral values.
Thus a recent critic of the 'liberal political-philosophical project'
argues that there is no neutral vantage point from which legis-
lators, judges and the like can stand and rationally arbitrate the
conflicts between those with different moral stances. 'One can',
he says, 'participate in politics and law . . . only as a partisan of
particular moral/religious convictions about the human'. 24 In
one sense that is true, but it neglects the fact that a commitment
to moral autonomy, and to the ethical pluralism that goes with
it, is not at all like a commitment to a particular and 'partisan'
moral stance. An agreement on the supreme value of autonomy
is precisely an. agreement to disagree about substantive and
partisan moral positions. In that sense it is a meta-partisan
stance.
-24-
-25-
-26-
NOTES
1. On the concept of autonomy see Joseph Raz, The Morality of
Freedom, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1986, especially ch. 14, 'Auton-
omy and Pluralism' and ch. 15, "'Freedom and Autonomy'"; Robert
Young
, Personal Autonomy; Beyond Negative and Positive Liberty, The
Hague, Croom Helm, 1986; G. Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of
Autonomy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1988; J. Christ
man (ed.) The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy, New
York, Oxford University Press, 1989.
-27-
6. ibid. art. 7
15. Mill, On Liberty, op. cit., pp.67-8. See also Ronald Dworkin, Law's
Empire, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1986.
19. See Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory, 2nd
edn, London, Duckworth, 1986; Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the
Limits of Justice, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1982;
Charles Taylor, Hegel and Modern Society, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1979; Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice, Oxford,
Blackwell, 1985. For an excellent counter-critique see Will Kymlicka
, "'Liberalism and communitarianism'". op. cit. See also
C. Kukathas and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and Its
Critics,
-28-
21. For a recent survey of these criticisms see Stephen Macedo, Liberal
Values: Citizenship, Virtue and Community in Liberal
Constitutionalism,
Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1990.
24. Michael J. Perry, Morality, Politics and the Law, New York, Oxford
University Press, 1988, p.183.
-29-
3
Ending Life
The ethics of suicide
In the Foundation of the Metaphysics of Morals Kant asks himself
whether a person may, in certain circumstances, take his life
when he judges that his continued existence is humanly point-
less. Surprisingly, the great apostle of personal autonomy holds
that such a person would be acting immorally. Kant argues that
one contemplating suicide is caught in a 'contradiction' in that
he is, on the one hand, concerned to promote his self-interest by
seeking to escape further suffering or dying in a situation where
he has lost control over himself and become a 'vegetable'; but on
the other hand he wishes, by taking his life, to abolish his 'self'
and all possibility of securing his future self-interest. Since what
is contradictory is irrational, suicide is irrational. Kant also de-
velops another argument to the effect that a person deciding to
commit suicide sees the taking of his life as a means to an end
(the cessation of suffering, the avoidance of an 'undignified'
death). He no longer sees himself as an autonomous moral agent
(or person) deserving of absolute moral respect, or as an 'end-
in-itself', as Kant puts it, that can never legitimately be used
simply as a means. Instead, he treats himself as a thing that can
be used for other purposes. The would-be suicide is then, for
-30-
-31-
-32-
Quite apart from this, Aquinas and other Christian and Jewish
theologians simply do not consider the possibility that I might in
good conscience choose to 'lay down' my life or deliberately
terminate it out of proper self-love, or love for others or for my
country, or even out of love and respect for God.
Traditional ideas about suicide still, of course, retain some
force: in many societies attempted suicide is still seen as a crime
and being an accessory to suicide as equally a criminal offence.
However, there has been a developing recognition, over the last
thirty or forty years, of what has been called a 'right to die'. Like
all such catchy slogans, the 'right to die' slogan can be mislead-
ing, but what it means is that people have the right, as auton-
omous moral agents, to decide in certain circumstances that
their quality of life is so diminished that continued existence is
humanly pointless and may therefore be ended by themselves.
(The term 'euthanasia' is now so hopelessly compromised that it
is better to dispense with it altogether.) Put in another way,
people have the right to determine and control the circum-
stances of their deaths, just as they determine and control the
circumstances of their lives. Dying is, in a sense, the most
important thing a person does and one should as far as possible
be in control of it. I do not exercise my moral autonomy by
allowing my life to be dictated by chance and external forces,
and neither do I exercise my moral autonomy by fatalistically
allowing my death to be dictated by chance and external forces.
It is not 'playing God' to seek freely to control the direction of
my life, and it is not 'playing God' to seek freely to control the
mode of my dying. For a Christian, God is not honoured by a
person (made in the 'image' of God) abdicating her autonomy
and freedom of will and passively submitting herself to 'fate'.
-33-
-34-
-35-
-36-
It does not seem that one would infringe someone's right to life in
killing him with his permission and in fact at his request. Why should
someone not be able to waive his right to life, or rather, as would
be more likely to happen, to cancel some of the duties of non-
-37-
interference that this right entails? (He is more likely to say that he
should be killed by this man at this time, in this manner, than to say
that anyone may kill him at any time and in any way.) . . . An
objection might be made on the ground that only God has the right
to take life but . . . religion apart, there seems to be no case to be
made out for an infringement of rights if a man who wishes to die is
allowed to die or even be killed. 6
the individual, having the prime obligation for his own health care,
has also thereby the right to the necessary means for such basic
health care -- specifically, the right of self-determination in the
acceptance or rejection of treatment. When an individual puts him-
self into a doctor's hands, he engages the doctor's services; he does
not abdicate his right to decide his own fate.
The rights and duties of the doctor are correlative to those of the
patient. The doctor, in fact, has no separate or independent right
where a patient is concerned. In general, he can take action only if
the patient, explicitly or implicitly, directly or indirectly, gives him
permission. 8
-38-
Decriminalising suicide
It follows from what has been said so far that in a liberal society,
based on the principle of the moral autonomy of the individual,
the law should not be concerned with preventing people from
taking their lives in certain circumstances. In other words,
whether suicide may or may not be a sin in some situations, it
should not be a crime. It would have to be shown that suicide
involved direct harm to others and was in some obvious sense an
anti-social act before it could be made a crime. Of course, some
argue on consequentialist grounds that even if suicide is not
morally wrong in itself, its legal toleration would in effect give
state endorsement and support to it and would encourage sui-
cide among mentally disturbed people, the elderly and so on.
Further, it is claimed, legal toleration of suicide would injure
community respect for the 'sanctity of human life' which is cen-
tral to any society and would inevitably lead to 'mercy killing'
and worse. But first, the fact that the state decriminalises suicide
does not imply that it endorses suicide as morally acceptable,
any more than the decriminalisation of prostitution and homo-
sexuality means that the state endorses those sexual practices as
morally acceptable. What the state does, in effect, is to declare
that suicide, like prostitution and homosexuality, falls within the
province of personal morality and is, as such, not the law's
business.
-39-
-40-
-41-
Since our dominant culture is one based upon the liberal value
of individual autonomy, it is hardly surprising that no one now
recognises or accepts that there is a socially imposed and
traditionally sanctioned 'right way to die' which allows no scope
for choice in the way one dies. Indeed, one might say that it is
not only not surprising but also not regrettable, since it marks
progress in moral consciousness when one has a right to control
and choose the way one dies in the same way that one controls
and chooses the way one lives.
-42-
and, as it were, 'owns' us. Since we do not own our our lives
we cannot take them. 19 (In parenthesis, there is a curious ver-
sion of this argument in Plato's Phaedo. 20 Our lives are the
property of the gods and we cannot give away what is not
our property, unless the gods make it clear that we can.) These
views are of course bound up inextricably with Jewish and
Islamic religious beliefs and they are addressed principally to
their own religious believers. It is difficult to see them as
universal ethical prescriptions addressed to Jews and non-
Jews, Muslims and non-Muslims, believers and non-believers
alike. If one is a Jew or a Christian or a Muslim, one's con-
cept of God as a creator, as a providential being with a con-
tinuing interest in his creatures, and as a unitary being, will
play a major part in determining what one may or may not
do with one's life. However, if one is a Hindu, a Buddhist or
an Australian Aborigine, where that concept of God simply
does not apply, one's attitude to taking one's life may be quite
different.
-43-
-44-
Since the problem is at its most acute and most difficult with
regard to decisions about disabled newborn infants, we shall
-45-
-46-
-47-
-48-
-49-
the ruin of his kingdom) that is crucial in determining his 'quality
of life' as a human being. 32
-50-
infants with one or more of the specified conditions should not
receive active treatment since such infants were not likely to
survive without severe handicaps. Lorber's criteria have been
challenged on medical grounds but, whatever their prognostic
efficacy may be, it is clear that for him the infants' quality of life
was measured wholly in medical or biological terms.
-51-
-52-
Some have seen the admission of a right to die as the first step
on a slippery slope that will end inevitably in something like the
Nazi euthanasia program in the 1930s, when some 275 000
people were judged on objective 'scientific' grounds to be
'socially useless' and then killed by medically qualified staff in
hospitals and sanatoriums. Medical staff were not expressly
ordered to kill these inmates but were simply given permission
to do so. These centres were the prototypes of the later exter-
mination camps for the Jews and other 'racially inferior'
peoples. 34 But a 'right to die' which is grounded at all levels on
the moral autonomy of the individual is totally at odds with that
position. We are on a slippery slope only when we move away
from seeing the decision to end one's life as a moral decision
belonging to the individual patient, and as being grounded in the
patient's right to moral autonomy, to seeing it as primarily a
medical or scientific matter, or as a social matter (taking into
account, for example, whether the prolonged life of a handi-
capped newborn infant would be a burden upon its parents or
on society at large). In a liberal society then, any legislation giv-
ing expression to a 'right to die' must relate essentially to the
patient's autonomous right to control the ending of her or his
life. Extraneous considerations, for example whether the con-
tinuation of a patient's life is a burden on parents, family or
society in general, should not be taken into account.
-53-
taking into account the patient's wishes. From this point of view,
the following statement by a group of eminent American phys-
icians places the emphasis in exactly the wrong place: thus, after
acknowledging that 'the patient's role in decision-making is
paramount', the group then goes on to say that 'the patient's
right to accept or refuse treatment notwithstanding, the phys-
ician has a major role in the decision-making process. He or
she has the knowledge, skills and judgment to provide diagnosis
and prognosis, to offer treatment choices and explain their im-
plications, and to assume responsibility for recommending a
decision with respect to treatment'. 35
-54-
-55-
from the fact that the majority of people now die in hospitals
which are centres of sophisticated medical technology. An
American report notes that something like 80 per cent of deaths
in the US take place in hospitals and long-term care insti-
tutions, 40 and these institutions use medical technology which
enables life to be sustained and prolonged far beyond what 'nat-
ure', would allow in an extra-institutional context. This is par-
ticularly true of pre-term handicapped infants and, at the other
end of the spectrum, elderly people (who are claimed to be the
major consumers of medical technology). This is not to suggest,
in a Luddite way, that medical technology is evil and that we
should return to letting pre-technological nature take its course
with the lives of handicapped children and elderly people
(though it has been suggested that there is a natural span of life
beyond which people should not receive treatment by expensive
medical technology).
-56-
Medical curricula and practice were shaped around what was easily
standardised and defined in technological models. To work appro-
priately and to claim expertise in the late nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries was to work with standardised objects defined in
isolation from their social context. The body became a standardised
object, and the medical curriculum organised around standardisable
skills. 44
-57-
-58-
Much the same thing happens with the institution of the hos-
pital vis-à-vis heath care. The physician and other health carers
are supposed to be the ancillaries or servants of the patient.
According to the ancient definition of medicine it is an art that
co-operates with nature (in this case the human body) and en-
ables (not causes) the body to restore itself to health. However,
the hospital institution leads health carers gradually to assume
the role of primary agents or causes of the patient's health.
-59-
NOTES
1. Immanuel Kant, Foundation of the Metaphysics of Morals, 1785,
trans.
Carl J. Friedrich, in The Philosophy of Kant, New York, Modern
Library, 1949.
8. ibid., p.406.
9. For an overview of the report, see Paul J. van der Maas et al.,
"'Euthanasia and other medical decisions concerning the end of
life'", The Lancet, 8338, 1991, 609-74.
10. See Pieter Admiraal, "'Is there a place for euthanasia?'", Bioethics
News, Monash University, 10, 4, 1991, pp.10-22.
-60-
15. ibid.
16. See Philippe Ariès, Western Attitudes Towards Death, Baltimore,
Johns Hopkins Press, 1974, and Robert Herz, "'The collective
representation of death'", in Death and the Right Hand, London,
Cohen and West, 1960. On Australian Aboriginal attitudes to
death see Max Charlesworth, Howard Morphy, Diane Bell,
Kenneth Maddock (eds.), Religion in Aboriginal Australia, St Lucia,
Queensland University Press, 1984, Part 2.
17. Fred Rosner, Modern Medicine and Jewish Ethics, New York,
Yeshiva
University Press, 1986, pp. 142-56
18. A. Carmi, "'Live like a king: die like a king'", in A. Carmi ed.,
Euthan-
asia, Berlin, Springer Verlag, 1984, pp. 11-12.
19. See Fazlur Rahman, Health and Medicine in the Islamic Tradition,
New
York, Crossroads, 1987, p. 126.
21. Hastings Center Report, August 1986, "'Caring for newborns: three
world views'", pp.18-23.
23. K. N. Siva Subramanian, "'In India, Nepal and Sri Lanka, quality of
life weighs heavily'", ibid., p21.
24. Rihito Kimura, "'In Japan parents participate but doctors decide'",
ibid., pp.22-3.
25. See J. Kilner, Who Lives? Who Dies? Ethical Criteria in Patient
Selection,
New Haven, Yale University Press, 1990.
26. See Nancy S. Jecker and Alfred O. Berg, "'Allocating medical re-
sources in rural America: alternative perceptions of justice'", Soc.
Sci. Med., 24, 1992, pp.467-74.
27. See Peter Singer, Helga Kuhse, Cora Singer, "'The treatment of
newborn infants with major handicaps: a survey of obstetricians'
and paediatricians' attitudes regarding the treatment of defective
newborns'", Bioethics, 5, 1991, pp.139-49.
-61-
34. See Robert Proctor, Racial Hygiene: Medicine Under the Nazis,
Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1989.
39. ibid.
41. See, for example, Arthur Kleinman, Patients and Healers in the
Con-
text of Culture, Berkeley, University of California Press, 1980; see
also Catherine Berndt, "'Sickness and health in Western Arnhem
Land: a traditional perspective'", in Janice Reid (ed.) Body, Land
and
Spirit, St Lucia, University of Queensland Press, 1983, pp.121-
38.
43. Elliot G. Mishleret al. (eds.) Social Contexts of Health, Illness and
Patient Care, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981.
-62-
4
Beginning Life
New ways of birth and family
formation
Over the last thirty years there has been a profound shift in
attitudes in societies in the Western European tradition towards
marriage and the family, or rather to traditional means of family
formation. This was set in train by 'the change from pre-
arranged marriages being the norm, to the general convention
that the married should choose one another', 1 and this in turn
was seen as a development in personal autonomy in family rela-
tionships. Of course, the great majority of children are born
from, and most families are created by, heterosexual couples in
formally married unions. Again, marriage and traditional family
formation are still given powerful support by the law and by the
public rhetoric of our society. Further, a number of alternative
ways of family formation (for example, artificial insemination
by donor and in vitro fertifisation) are used only by people
who are infertile. In this sense donor insemination and in vitro
fertilisation (IVF) are not preferred choices but choices of last
resort.
-63-
-64-
-65-
of a homosexual 'marriage', but the fact remains that some
homosexual couples do have children and establish families.
-67-
-68-
-69-
-70-
-71-
-72-
-73-
-74-
which is not the law's business. The issue we are considering here
is, then, whether the practice of surrogacy, and the particular
mode of family formation it makes possible, falls into the area of
personal morality which is not the law's business. Or, put in
another way, in a society where personal liberty is maximised,
and where people have very different views about, and attitudes
towards, sexual morality and also to family formation, why
should surrogacy be prohibited by law? Most people will favour
a stable heterosexual union as the basis for having children and
forming a family, but others may choose to be single parents, or
to use donor insemination (it has been estimated that some
5000-6000 donor inseminations are carried out each year in
Australia), 9 or IVF involving donor gametes (some 12 per cent of
IVF pregnancies in Australia and New Zealand in 1988 used
donor oocytes, donor sperm or donor embryos). Or again,
others may choose to reconstitute a family after divorce and
remarriage. Given these various modes of family formation,
which are accepted in our society, why should we single out
surrogate motherhood for special attention and subject it to
legal prohibition?
Let us then look briefly at the various issues outlined above,
remembering, as I have said, that we are engaged in a rational
analysis and not just an exchange of gut-feelings or a swapping
of anecdotes. First, is surrogate motherhood morally wrong in
itself in that it offends against some kind of moral principle?
Consider the case of a woman who wishes to help another
woman, a sister or a friend who cannot bear a child, by bearing
the child for her. She carefully considers her action and its likely
effect on others and then she freely decides to bear the child for
that other woman. The gametes from which the child is formed
may came from the other woman and her husband and by the
use of in vitro fertilisation an embryo may be formed and then
transferred into her. She is then bearing the 'genetic child' of the
other woman for her. Or she may contribute her own oocyte
while the husband of the other woman contributes the sperm
and the embryo may be formed by IVF and then transferred into
-75-
-76-
-77-
-78-
In this view then women are incapable of making truly free and
informed decisions, and the new forms of assisted procreation
or reproductive technologies, including surrogacy, and the new
ways of birth and family formation they make possible are
-79-
not really means of liberation for women but rather are new
forms of oppression by which women are locked into the role
of potential mother. Surrogate mothers may think that they
are being altruistic in helping other women to have children
but what they are doing in reality is helping to reinforce the
oppressive stereotype of woman as mother.
-80-
Consequences of surrogacy
We turn now to the arguments against surrogacy based upon the
alleged consequences of the practice for both the surrogate
mother and the child born of a surrogacy arrangement. As was
remarked before, in this kind of consequentialist argument it is
not enough to show that surrogacy may possibly lead to some
deleterious consequences for both surrogate mothers and the
children they bear for others; one must show that there is actual
evidence to suggest that it does lead to such consequences
typically or in most cases, and that these consequences are so
serious and of such magnitude as to warrant intervention by the
state to prohibit the practice. One must also show that, if it is
allowed, surrogacy is likely to become a widespread form of
family formation. When one looks at the arguments, however,
little hard evidence is brought forward to show that surrogacy
does in fact have the serious and malign consequences it is sup-
posed to have. A recent report of a committee of the Anglican
Archdiocese of Melbourne in Australia says, for example, that
surrogacy involves such deleterious consequences for the child
in terms of its sense of its own identity (who is my real mother
and whose child am I?) and for the surrogate mother regard-
ing her 'possible manipulation . . . within the context of
emotional family relationships', that it should be severely
discouraged by the community. (It should be mentioned that
the committee thinks that it would be practically futile for the
state to prohibit altruistic or non-commercial surrogacy, or to
subject participants in surrogacy arrangements to criminal pen-
alties.) The committee also expresses the fear that if altruistic
surrogacy is allowed this will be a thin end of the wedge for the
-81-
One might expect that such large and confident claims about
surrogacy would be supported by empirical evidence about its
psychological effects on children or about the manipulation of
women in family contexts. One might also expect some com-
parisons to be made with what happens in 'ordinary' marriage
and family relationships, to see whether children born from sur-
rogacy arrangements are any worse off psychologically than
children born from ordinary families, or from single parent situ-
ations, or from artificial insemination, or from lesbian unions, or
from reconstituted families after divorce and remarriage. But no
such evidence is ever offered. There is, it seems, some evidence
to suggest that children who are adopted are statistically more
likely to have psychological problems than children born within
'ordinary' family situations, but no one has so far advocated that
this is so typical and so large a problem that the practice of
adoption should be banned. (What it does imply is that we
should be more careful about the adoption process with regard
to the problems of adopted children and relinquishing mothers.)
There is, of course, a great deal of evidence to show the del-
eterious effects of divorce and family break-up on children, but
once again no one has advocated that this is an argument for
prohibiting divorce and marriage break-up. To repeat the point
made before, what the consequentialist has to show is that the
practice of surrogacy actually has such undesirable conse-
quences, both for the child and the surrogate mother of the
child, of such seriousness and magnitude that the law should, as
with open access to hard drugs, prohibit it. It might be men-
tioned in this connection that out of 4000 recorded surrogate
births in recent years in the US only one per cent have resulted in
litigation. 13
-82-
custody of children after divorce and marriage break-up; it also
applies to adoption processes and to cases where the child is
removed from its parents' care in cases of neglect or abuse. 14 In
those contexts the maxim has a completely clear meaning,
namely that the child who is already in existence has interests
and rights of its own which must be taken into account. But it has
been given the status of an absolute principle by some and used
to argue that surrogacy is necessarily and always against the best
interests of the child and so should be prohibited. Better that the
child not exist at all rather than be born of a surrogacy arrange-
ment.
-83-
-84-
-85-
-86-
other modes of family formation, but it does not have the right
to prohibit it. The state might, for example, make provision for
counselling women entering surrogacy arrangements to ensure
that they are capable of making free and informed decisions; for
keeping records of the birth circumstances of children born
from such arrangements; and for ensuring that there is an ad-
equate interval between the birth of a child and its being handed
over to the social parents in order to allow the surrogate mother
to make a considered final decision.
-87-
bear a child for another if she so chooses are quite illiberal in that
they effectively deny the moral autonomy of the woman. They
need to be reminded that they are living in a liberal society.
Feminist views on
reproductive technology
Certain feminist views have already been mentioned in the dis-
cussion on surrogacy. One might have expected that the right
which has played a central part in the feminist movement, that
women have final control over their own bodies and their repro-
ductive processes, would have been invoked apropos of surro-
gacy. This right is a direct corollary of the fact that women are
autonomous moral agents and is simply a version of the general
principle of autonomy. If a woman is not able to use her body as
she wishes, so long as no harm is done to others, and if she is not
able to control her reproductive capacities as she freely chooses,
she is no longer in responsible control of a vitally significant part
of her life. (In a sense this is not an exclusively women's right
since it applies equally to men; but it applies of course in a special
way to women.)
-88-
pregnancy were in the last trimester it would seem that the right
of the fetus should take precedence (at the cost of coercing the
mother, against her will, to continue the pregnancy).
-89-
in the early 1970s, when the current wave of feminism began, most
of the women involved in the movement had had their children and
were searching for other means of fulfilment in their lives, or had
not had children and were not yet having to face the issue of
whether they ever would choose to be mothers. Both groups saw it
important to prove that women did not have to be seen only in
terms of their reproductive abilities. For both groups, reproductive
freedom meant freedom from reproduction. 18
Quite apart from these factors, there has been a natural move-
ment of critical revisionism within feminism. All revolutionary
movements, whether they are political, religious or philosophi-
-90-
-91-
-92-
-93-
-94-
-95-
person, but rather because embryos come from the ova 'har-
vested' from women's bodies, so the latter become experimen-
tal 'sites' for reproductive scientists. The use of superovulatory
drugs and invasive surgical techniques also means that women
become experimental 'fodder'. As it has been put by Robyn
Rowland,
-96-
technocratic values, and that there are real dangers of its being
used against women in an exploitative way. At the same time
they argue that the reproductive technologies can be used to
help women achieve liberation if they are able to control those
technologies for their own purposes. If the 'pro choice' principle
governs women's access to the new forms of contraception and
to improved ways of abortion -- both brought about by medical
technology -- why should it not govern women's access to IVF
and other forms of birth technology, provided that there is a real
choice for the women concerned?
-98-
a problematic Marxist analysis, but on the assumption that other
jobs available to women are seriously less alienating. 34
-99-
-100-
-101-
The infertile woman, here and now, forces those of us who care for
her to deal with a distinctively feminist moral dilemma: how to
engage an individual woman's concrete situation in its immediacy
while engaging the condition of women as a social group. Feminists
call for social rather than individual solutions to the problem that
technological and other controversial solutions (such as surrogacy)
for infertility pose for women and for feminist theory and action,
but infertility itself is experienced individually . . . The first social
solution to the problem with no nice feminist answer is for feminists
neither to minimize the painful reality of infertility nor to trivialize
the desire to conceive and bear a child. We do not have to deny the
infertile woman's agency to be vigilant of the consequences for
women of technological developments in reproduction. We do not
have to question the infertile woman's right to choose the solutions
to infertility available to her to affirm any woman's right to repro-
ductive freedom. We do not have to suspect the infertile woman's
desire for a child of her 'own' (genetically, gestationally), or a child
who might have been her own, to celebrate the value of all children
or to protect birth mothers from being forced to relinquish their
children. We do have to make a comfortable place for her at the
center of our passionate debates. 45
-102-
-103-
NOTES
1. Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom, Oxford, Clarendon Press,
1986,
pp.392-3.
11. Lynda Birke, Susan Himmelweit and Gail Vines, Tomorrow's Child.
Reproductive Technologies in the 90s, London, Virago, 1990, p.19.
13. Brent Parker Smith, "'Anna J. v. Mark C.: proof of the imminent
need for surrogate motherhood regulation'", Journal of Family Law,
13, 1991-2, p.495.
14. See Australian Family Law Act 1975, s60 D. See also Stephanie
Charlesworth
, J. Neville Turner and Lynne Foreman, Lawyers, So-
cial workers and Families, Annandale, The Federation Press, 1990,
pp.90-2.
18. Lynda Birke, Susan Himmelweit and Gail Vines, Tomorrow's Child:
Reproductive Technology in the 1990s, op. cit., pp.3-4.
22. Mara Mies, "'Do we need all this? A call against genetic engineering
and reproductive technology'", in Patricia Spallone and Deborah
Steinberg
(eds.), Made to Order. The Myth of Reproductive and Genetic
Progress, New York, Oxford University Press, 1987.
23. Gena Corea, The Mother Machine, New York, Harper and Row,
1982,
p.39.
26. Susan Dodds and Karen Jones, "'Surrogacy and autonomy'", Bio-
ethics, 3, 1989, p.13.
31. Lynda Birke, Susan Himmelweit and Gail Vines, Tomorrow's Child,
op. cit., p.x.
38. Lynda Birke, Susan Himmelweit and Gail Vines, Tommorow's Child,
op. cit., pp.266-7.
39. ibid.
-105-
40. Karen Dawson and Beth Gaze, "'Who is the subject of the re-
search?'", in Peter Singer et al. (eds.), Embryo Experimentation,
Mel-
bourne, Cambridge University Press, 1990.
-106-
5
Distributing Health-care
Resources
The problem of scarce resources
The problem of how health-care resources should be allocated
or apportioned, so that they are distributed in both the most just
and most efficient way, is not a new one. Every health system in
an economically developed society is faced with the need to
decide (either informally or formally) what proportion of the
community's total resources should be spent on health care;
how resources are to be apportioned; which human diseases and
disabilities and which forms of treatment are to be given
priority; which members of the community are to be given
special consideration in respect of their health needs; and which
forms of treatment are the most cost-effective.
What is new is that from the 1950s onwards there have been
certain general changes in outlook about the finitude of re-
sources as a whole and of health-care resources in particular, as
well as more specific changes regarding the clientele of health-
care resources and the cost to the community of those resources.
Thus in the 1950s and 1960s there emerged an awareness in
Western societies that resources for the provision of fossil fuel
energy were finite and exhaustible and that the capacity of
nature or the environment to sustain economic development
-107-
and population was also finite. In other words, we became aware
of the obvious fact that there were 'limits to growth'. The new
consciousness that there were also severe limits to health-care
resources was part of this general revelation of the obvious.
Looking back, it now seems quite incredible that in the national
health systems that emerged in many countries after the Second
World War it was assumed without question that all the basic
health needs of any community could be satisfied, at least in
principle. God, or the 'invisible hand' of economic progress,
would provide.
-108-
The second set of more specific changes that have led to the
present concern about the distribution of health-care resources
stems from the dramatic rise in health costs in most developed
countries, accompanied by large-scale demographic and social
changes which have meant, to take one example, that elderly
people are now major (and relatively very expensive) con-
sumers of health-care resources. Thus in OECD countries as a
whole, health costs increased from 3.8 per cent of GDP in 1960 to
7 per cent of GDP in 1980, and it has been predicted that the
proportion of health costs to GDP will continue to increase. (In
the US the current figure is about 12 per cent of GDP and in
Australia about 7.8 per cent of GDP.)
-109-
The market ideology fails in health care quite simply because the
market fails in health care. That failure is fundamental. Markets
cannot work adequately without informed consumers. Patients in
many consumption decisions in health care are not informed
or at least not sufficiently so. Indeed, often what they consume is
information. 4
-110-
Utilitarian approaches
As we shall see, the debate about the distribution of health-care
resources has been dominated by a consequentialist or utili-
tarian approach and method which determines the value of
medical treatment, health-care policies or strategies exclusively
in terms of measurable consequences or 'outcomes'. Utili-
tarianism is a protean concept but it is taken here to be a species
of consequentialism in that it is concerned with (a) general wel-
fare or happiness, or satisfaction of preferences or wants, as a
consequence of our acts, and (b) with consequences that are
quantifiable and summable in the sense that we can add together
the welfare, happiness or satisfaction of many different peopley
-111-
affected by our acts. Thus, for example, if five people are made
happier by act X as against one person being made happy by act
Y, then act X is five times better than act Y.
-112-
-113-
-114-
However, the fact that ethical values do not obey the rules
of utilitarian cost-benefit 'rationality' does not mean that they
are thereby 'irrational' and that we cannot meaningfully say
whether a medical policy is just or unjust; or whether it is
paternalistic or respects personal autonomy; or whether a hos-
pital system is more or less beneficent or compassionate. One
gets the impression from some of the health-care utilitarians that
only since the recent arrival of cost-effective measurement pro-
cedures have we been able to say whether a health system or
policy is successful or not. Previously, they imply, we blundered
about in total darkness, trusting our intuitions and hunches, but
not really knowing what the real consequences or outcomes
were and thus whether or not what we were doing was worth-
while.
-115-
-116-
-117-
-118-
-119-
-120-
patient, help the patient understand what might serve his or her
welfare. And the patient has to find a way to tell the physician what
he or she is trying to live for. It ought to be a richer language than is
captured in the language of autonomy and rights. 17
-121-
On the other hand, it has been argued that while the two roles
are in principle distinct the physician has willy nilly to com-
bine both in practice. Thus the US medical ethicist Edmund
Pellegrino has written:
-122-
Health-care resource
allocations: four examples
These then are the most general features that a health system in
a liberal society should have. However, it is worthwhile exam-
ining in a little detail how ethical considerations arise in specific
and concrete areas of health-care resource allocation. A major
difficulty here is that the different levels of decision-making are
usually not distinguished from one another. Decisions at the
level of governmental policy-makers and health bureaucrats,
who have to allocate health-care resources in competition with
other areas -- such as defence, education, law -- are made in a
very different way (and have different ethical implications) from
the decisions made by hospital administrators who have to div-
ide up a given health budget between the competing depart-
ments of a hospital. And within a given department or unit, such
as an intensive care unit for newborns, very particular and
immediate decisions have to be made about the allocation of
resources to competing kinds of patients, for example 500 gram
birthweight infants as against 1000 gram birthweight infants.
The ethical issues that arise at this level are very different from
those facing the hospital administrator or the health bureaucrat.
Again, at the individual physician-patient level, ethical ques-
tions present themselves in a more subtle way. As we shall see,
there is a complex array of ethical values, sometimes concordant
sometimes discordant, involved in making decisions in these
areas. These values set severe limits to 'rational' planning of a
utilitarian cost-benefit kind.
-123-
they have a 'right' to have a child, any more than people gen-
erally claim to have a right to good health. What they claim is
that they have a right of access to public health funds for the
treatment of their condition in exactly the same way that other
people have a right of access to funds and treatment for in health
or disease.
It is clear from what has been said that we cannot decide how
health-care resources should be allocated to the alleviation of
infertility by the various forms of reproductive technology un-
less we first settle the question of how we value infertility, that is
determine how serious a human disability it is. That, as we have
seen, is a complex business since we are dealing not just with a
bodily dysfunction but with a dysfunction with a social aspect:
how infertility is perceived within a particular socio-cultural
context.
-125-
infertile patients presenting for IVF treatment it is to be expected
that success rates will be low; (c) it is claimed that it is not far
short of mother nature's own success rate in that a high per-
centage of naturally formed embryos in utero do not implant or
are spontaneously aborted; and (d) there are good prospects of
improved success rates resulting from further research. 20
Some have claimed that the costs of IVF treatment are dis-
proportionately high. It is true that they appear so when com-
pared with the costs of ordinary natural childbirth. But if they
are compared with the costs of keeping a low-weight premature
infant (born through natural childbirth) alive by intensive care,
and of coping with the continuing effects of its premature birth,
often through the rest of its life, then $40 000 per IVF child is very
cheap. No one argues that intensive care for newborns should be
restricted solely on the grounds that it is so costly and it is dif-
ficult to see why alleviation of infertility by IVF and GIFT, so that a
child is able to be born, should be restricted solely for reasons of
cost. (Though some have argued that intensive care 'saves' a life,
whereas IVY 'merely' creates one, and that whereas we have an
obligation in the first case we do not in the latter.)
-126-
-127-
-128-
-129-
-130-
Renal transplantation
Renal transplantation is an area where the just and efficient
allocation of scarce resources has always been a central con-
sideration since (a) the availability of donor kidneys is severely
restricted relative to the demands of patients suffering from
renal failure, and (b) the medical criteria for the use of renal
transplants in respect of individual patients are extremely com-
plex. 29
The process of allocating donor kidneys to particular patients
involves a number of different levels of decision-making. There
is, first, the personal doctor-patient level, where a doctor and
patient decide whether a renal transplant is medically feasible
and personally acceptable. Second, there is the institutional
level, where physicians in their role as program directors have to
decide about the amount of medical resources to be committed
to a renal program as against other programs in the institution.
Third, there is the state and national level, where the allocation
of health-care resources to renal programs has to compete with
wider health priorities and even with non-health priorities. Inevi-
tably political considerations play a large part at this level.
Fourth, there is the international level, where issues related to
the relative needs of developed countries and underdeveloped
countries, and of the obligation of the former to allocate some
medical and health-care resources to the latter, have to be taken
into account.
-131-
A recent study makes the point that since 'medical need tran-
scends national boundaries' any account of health care as a
universal human right 'should recognise that the greater needs
of the poorest countries ought to be met first, before even think-
ing about improving our own quite tolerable condition'. 32
Unfortunately, in the present climate of economic rationalism,
this seems no more than a pious hope. Nevertheless, it is a
primary ethical consideration in any allocation of health-care
resources.
The decisions made at these different levels may not always
harmonise with each other. For example, a decision that a phys-
ician may make about allocating a kidney to an individual who is
his or her patient may conflict with a decision that the same
physician may have to make as director of a renal transplant
program in an institution. 'In Australia', it has been said, 'the
physician-patient relationship is all important and is the main
gate-way by which persons are assessed as suitable to be placed
on an allocation list'. 33 If this is so then it places severe restric-
tions on any attempt to allocate resources in a systematic way at
the institutional and national levels. However, as noted before, it
has been claimed that physicians can no longer evade the larger
social consequences of their decisions and that in rec-
ommending a renal transplant in a particular case they must also
explicitly take into account both institutional and national re-
sources. (Implicitly, of course, they already do so because in
practice their individual advice and decisions are constrained by
the level of health-care resources available at the institutional
and national levels.)
-132-
The larger question has also been raised: should major bodily
organs, because they are so scarce, be considered as individual
'property' or rather as 'assets of the community'? At the first
joint meeting of the European Society for Organ Transplanta-
tion and the European Renal Association ( Munich, 1990) on the
theme, Ethics, Justice and Commerce in Organ Replacement, the fol-
lowing resolution was proposed: 'Cadaveric organs procured
within a community should be considered assets of the com-
munity, and the community rather than just the medical pro-
fession should determine their allocation through announced
criteria'. 34 It is not clear exactly how in practice 'the community'
might feasibly determine the allocation of major organs, includ-
ing kidneys, but it is evident that there is a concern that organs
should be allocated according to the principles of justice or fair-
ness. This involves specifying publicly the criteria in accordance
with which the allocation of bodily organs is to be effected.
-133-
The same author goes on to argue that 'in programs which are
supported by public funds such as exist in Australia, any form
of selection on social worth is unacceptable. It is discrimi-
natory, and open to being used capriciously, arbitrarily and
unjustly. 35
However, it might be argued that while this is clear in prin-
ciple, kidneys and other major organs are in such extremely
short supply that in practice some non-medical criteria will in-
evitably be used to select patients. Some indeed have argued that
in a situation of drastic scarcity it is responsible and even just to
use such 'social worth' criteria (for example, by not allocating a
liver transplant to a chronic alcoholic).
-134-
-135-
HIV/AIDS Treatment
Ethical questions relating specifically to health-care resource
allocation issues in the HIV/AIDS area are raised by the large costs
of treatments, educational and preventative programs, research
and so on. (As already remarked, it has been estimated that the
total ongoing treatment costs for an HIV/AIDS sufferer are close
to $934 000: $55 000 in direct health costs, including AZT, and
$879 000 in indirect costs.) This is compounded by the escalat-
ing numbers of HIV/AIDS sufferers.
-136-
-137-
-138-
-139-
-140-
-141-
A further constraint on 'rational' resource allocation comes
from the fact that certain health situations have what may be
called a powerful 'symbolic' or 'metaphorical' character. 49 Thus
intensive care for newborn infants symbolises people's concern
for the value of human life and for the protection of the defence-
less, so that any attempt to allocate resources in a rational
cost-benefit way in this area is seen almost as an attack on the
'sanctity of human life' itself. It is wrong to call these issues
'emotive', but they do set a limit to any kind of rational assess-
ment of health-care priorities, all the more so since politicians
and policy makers (and the media) are usually very sensitive to
them. Again, they can change in a quite volatile way from time
to time; thus, for example, abortion is no longer a symbolic issue
for the majority of people in Australia (though it is in the US),
whatever they may think about its morality; on the other hand,
human embryo experimentation and genetic manipulation in
humans certainly is. Again, while most people now accept arti-
ficial insemination, they are more hesitant about IVF and surro-
gacy. IVF still, to some extent, symbolises the medical scientist
'playing God', and surrogacy symbolises an attempt to bring
motherhood and reproduction out of the purely 'private' sphere
into the 'public' or social sphere. Finally, HIV/AIDS has of course a
complex and potent set of symbolic connotations: 'the plague',
homophobic fears, disease as divine punishment.
Reaching community
consensus
Granted that the allocation of health-care resources depends
upon ethical assumptions or judgments, how do we as a com-
-142-
munity reach agreement on those assumptions? For example,
how do we attain some kind of consensus on how serious a dis-
ability infertility is and the proportion of resources that should
be apportioned to IVF and other forms of reproductive tech-
nologies? As we have seen, some people see infertility as a grave
disability which prevents them from having children and form-
ing a family. Given the importance accorded to the family in our
society, they ask why the alleviation of infertility should not be
accorded much the same importance. Other people, however,
see the importance given to having children as the result of
socio-cultural factors (pro-natalist attitudes which in turn reflect
views about women's identity as women being bound up with
fertility and reproduction) and women's 'false consciousness'.
For these the allocation of health resources to reproductive
technology has a very low priority.
-143-
For example, some might argue that justice requires that each
candidate receive an equal chance of getting a scarce, social, life-
saving resource such as a kidney even if not all have an equal chance
of benefiting. They may insist that those who have waited longest or
those who are sickest get priority, recognising that these patients
may not be the ones who would predictably benefit the most. 51
-144-
-145-
-146-
At the same time there has been some critical reaction to the
Oregon scheme, questioning its bias in favour of the health
needs of white, middle-class, college-educated members of the
community who are able to use 'community consultation' for
their own purposes. Again, it has been emphasised that public
consultation on health-care resource matters needs to be a con-
tinuing process if it is to be effective and that this is an expensive
business. Further, it has been pointed out that the health values
on which there was consensus among Oregonians are extremely
general. Thus, in answer to the question, 'Do Oregonians share a
living tradition of values about health care that can help define
some package of health services as constituting a common
good?', the values given priority were prevention, quality of life,
cost-effectiveness, ability to function and equity. 58
-147-
to obtain one QALY through a heart transplant and $1200 for one
QALY by hip replacement.
-148-
-149-
-150-
-151-
-152-
-153-
-154-
8. ibid., p.179.
15. Stephen Leeder and Jason Grossman, "'Is there more to health
than
money?'", unpublished paper, 1992.
-155-
25. ibid.
26. ibid.
27. Though see Murtonet al. "'Care of very low birthweight infants with
limited neonatal intensive care resources'", op. cit.
28. For further discussion of the ethical and legal issues involved in
the treatment of disabled newborns, see the contributions by
Mr Justice Michael Kirby and Julie Hamblin in Proceedings of
the National Consensus Conference on Neonatal Intensive Care,
Sydney,
Department of Health, New South Wales, 1989. See also the con-
tributions by Julie Hamblin and Max Charlesworth in Proceedings of
the Birth Defects Conference, International Clearinghouse for Birth
Defects Monitoring Systems and Australian Teratology Society,
Sydney, 1991, and the paper by Loane Skene The Baby M Inquest:
Treating Children with Severe Spina Bifida, Melbourne, Law Reform
Commission of Victoria, 1991. See also Helga Kuhse, "'Quality of
life and the death of Baby M", Bioethics, 6, 1992, pp.233-50. The
special problems arising from the donation of organs from new-
borns, when there are difficulties (as in anencephaly) in determin-
ing whether they are 'brain dead', are discussed in a symposium
sponsored by the Law Reform Commission of Victoria, the Royal
Children's Hospital, Melbourne, and the Australian Association
of Paediatrics Centre in March, 1991. See Anencephalics, Infants'
and Brain Death: Treatment Options and the Issue of Organ
Donation,
Melbourne, Proceedings of Consensus Development Conference,
1992.
-156-
30. See, for example, the work of the Centre de Bioéthique at the
University of Louvain-la-neuve in Belgium.
32. M. and H. Hayry, "'Health care as a right'", op. cit., p. 14; see also
Hans Kung, Global Responsibility, London, SCM Press, 1991.
35. Layton, p. 7. See also Michael Kirby on the Sage dialysis case in
the
UK, Bioethical Decisions and Opportunity Costs, George Judah
Cohen
Memorial Lecture, University of Sydney, 1985.
40. See M. Gunderson et al., AIDS: Testing and Privacy, Salt Lake City,
University of Utah Press, 1989.
47. Ronald Bayer, "'AIDS and liberalism'", Bioethics, 6, 1992, pp. 23-7.
See
also the same author's Private Acts, Social Consequences: AIDS
and the
Politics of Public Health, op. cit.
-157-
48. J. Hyde, "'Why Professor Hollows is Wrong About AIDS'", The Age,
27 March, 1992.
49. See Susan Sontag, Illness as a Metaphor, New York, 1978. Sontag
discusses the ways in which cancer and tuberculosis have reflected
cultural views of these diseases and those affected by them.
-158-
61. See Hiram Caton, "The Quality Adjusted Life Year: a social tech-
nology'", Bioethics Research Notes, 3, 1991, p.32.
62. On the practical difficulties of measurement and interview tech-
niques in the QALY and other similar approaches see J. Richardson,
"'Economic assessment of health care: theory and practice'", The
Australian Economic Review, 1st quarter, 1991, table 2 and table
3.
68. Amartya Sen, "'Equality of what?'" in Liberty, Equality and the Law,
Selected Tanner Lectures on Moral Philosophy, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1987.
69. See, for example, Max Charlesworth, "'What kinds of life are not
worth living?'", Teratology Conference, Sydney, 1991.
70. The Open Society and Its Enemies, 1945, Princeton University
Press,
1966, 5th revised edn.
-159-
6
Consensus in a
Liberal Society
The liberal ideal and bioethical
realities
At the end of The Republic Plato confesses that the state he has
constructed is an ideal, a thought-experiment, and that it would
be difficult, even impossible given human self-interest, to realise
in practice. Nevertheless as a utopian political regime it has a
purpose, Plato suggests, in that it enables us to measure actual
political structures and processes against it. Plato's aim, of
course, was to show that both tyranny at one extreme and
popular or mob democracy at the other could never be just
regimes, and that we need the paternalism of an elite group of
'philosopher rulers' to bring about a just society.
-160-
bureaucratic; the state and the law often invade the realm of
personal morality and act as moral policemen; the toleration of
ethical pluralism is minimised in the name of social unity and
cohesion.
-161-
Ethical agreement in a
multicultural society
One of the issues briefly discussed in a previous chapter was the
idea of a public morality or a community consensus which would
be the basis for our judgments in medical ethics in general and
bioethics in particular. Many people have claimed that unless we
have such a basis of 'core values' bioethical discussion will be
futile. This is, no doubt, the hope that many people have of the
'expert' bioethics committees that have proliferated in many
countries, as though select groups of quasi-Platonic sages will
be able to agree upon and formulate a common bioethical
code. Unfortunately, without detracting from the value of such
committees, this is a vain hope -- they too reflect the ethical
pluralism that exists in the community at large. They can, of
course, have a valuable educative role in promoting public dis-
cussion on bioethical questions, but they cannot realistically be
expected to formulate a corpus of ethical principles that would
constitute a public or common morality and which would guide
the discussion of controversial bioethical issues. 1
-162-
-163-
-164-
-165-
-166-
Conclusion
From one point of view, the liberal society can appear too ab-
stract and 'thin' an ideal to evoke deep and passionate commit-
ment of the kind that partisan or confessional or sectional
positions inspire. It is difficult to get excited, so to speak, about
Dworkin's characterisation of the liberal society as one 'whose
constitutive morality provides that human beings must be
treated as equals by their government'. 3 This is, at first blush, not
the kind of ideal that one might be prepared to die for.
The liberal ideal can appear like this because autonomy and
its associated values are often seen in negative or weak liber-
tarian terms, as though they simply meant that one could do as
one chooses, and as though they were wedded to some kind of
atomic and self-interested individualism. But when we see auton-
omy and its attendant values in a more positive light -- one
thinks here of Kant, Newman and Mill -- the liberal society
appears as a richer and more compelling ideal. For Kant the
autonomous moral agent or human person is deserving of
-167-
NOTES
1. For an interesting philosophical discussion on the possibility of a
'common morality' in a pluralistic society see the recent book by
the
noted US bioethicist H. Tristram Engelhardt, Bioethics and Secular
Humanism: The Search for a Common Morality, London, SCM
Press,
1991.
-168-
Index
abortion, 41, 80, 88 -9
Aquinas, Saint Thomas, 2, 11,
on suicide, 32 -3
Aristotle, 11, 49 - 50
Augustine, Saint, 2
Australian Aborigines, 116, 135 -6, 140,
166
authoritarianism, 2, 16, 165, 168
autonomy
and altruism, 6, 22
and feminist views, 8
and health-care resource allocation, 8,
111, 150
and HIV/AIDS, 138 -42
and individualism, 6, 21, 34
and newborn infants, 45 -8
and quality of life, 7, 48 - 52
and utilitarianism, 7
Christians and, 2, 3
concept of, 10 - 15, 37
criticisms of, 21 -6
in a liberal society 1, 2, ch. 2
Kant on, 12 - 13
Mill on, 15 -20, 21
Sartre on, 14 - 15
Bayer, Ronald, 139
Berlin, Isaiah, 5, 20, 168
bioethics committees, 162
birth
new modes of, 63 -9
see also surrogacy
Birke, Lynda, 97, 100
Callahan, Daniel, 120 -1
cadaveric organs, 133
categorical imperatives, see Kant
Catholic Church
and assisted reproduction, 87
and natural law, 3, 69 - 70
see also Instruction on Respect for Human
Life
conscience
Aquinas on, 2, 11,
Christian views of, 2, 3
Newman on, 11 - 12
common good, 23
community consensus, 142 -5, 152 -3,
in a liberal society, ch. 6
community consultation, 145 -33
community values, 25, 26, 27
the Oregon approach, 145 -7
the QALY approach, 147 -51
consequentialism, 3
consequentialist arguments against
surrogacy, 71 -2, 81 -5
see also utilitarianism
Corea, Gena, 93
Court of Appeal, UK
on medical treatment of disabled
newborn infants, 46 -8
-169-
-170-
and utilitarianism, 7
common good in, 24
concept of, 1, 5
consensus in, 7, 18, 23
minority groups in, 24, 42, 45, 55
neutrality of, 24, 25
role of law in, 1, 7
libertarianism, 2
Lorber, John, 50 -1
Mahler, Hafdan, 117
majoritarianism, 116 -17
McCormick, Richard A., 4, 33 -4, 38
Mies, Mara, 92
Mill, John Stuart, 5, 6, 15 -21, 25, 113,
116, 168
on individuality, 19, 20
on the liberal society, 15 - 20, 165
Mishler, Elliot G., 57
morality
and the law, 1, 7, 17, 27, 68 -9, 164
public, 1, 27
multiculturalism, 18, 162 -7
Muslim views in bioethics, 163 -4
National Bioethics Consultative
Committee, 67, 85
natural law 3, 32, 69 - 70
newborn infants, 36, 112
choosing for, 45 -8
costs of treatment, 128 -30
medical treatment of, 46, 47, 127 -31
quality of life of, 47, 130
with spina bifida, 50 -1
Newman, John Henry, 11 - 12, 168
Nietzsche, F., 3
'nightwatchman state'. 5
O'Brien, Mary, 93
outcomes, 111 -12, 114 -15, 148
Overall, Christine, 93 -4
paternalism, 2, 16, 17, 38, 58 -9, 111 -12,
121 -2
patient rights, 120
Pellegrino, Edmund, 122 -3
physician-patient relationships, 59 - 60,
120 -3, 141
'piecemeal social engineering', 8, 153 -4
planning, 153 -4
Plato, 160
pluralism, 1
ethical, 1, 2, 18, 161
in feminism, 91
Popper, Karl, 153 -4
positive discrimination, 136
privacy, 137 -9
private-public distinction, 99 - 100
procreation, assisted, 2, 8
see also in vitro fertilisation
procreative liberty', 7, 65, 102 -3
Purdy, Laura M., 84, 98 -9
quality of life, 7, 35, 48 - 52
of newborn infants, 46 -7
Quinlan, Karen Ann, 38
Rawls, John, 5, 113
Raz, Joseph, 5
refusal of medical treatment, 34 -5
Remmelink Commission, Netherlands,
39 - 40
renal transplantation, 131 -6
reproductive technology
access to, 123 -7
Richards, Janet Radcliffe, 101
Richardson, J., 149
'right to die', 2, 33, 36 -8, 52 -5
Rowland, Robyn, 96, 100
Roach Anleu, Sharyn L., 99 - 100
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 152, 161
Rushdie, Salman, 164
Sandelowski, Margarete, 101 -2
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 14 - 15
Seattle Artificial Kidney Center, 134
Sen, Amartya, 151
Shklar, Judith, 23 -4
'social worth' criteria, 134 -5
South Australian Reproductive
Technology Council, 135
suicide, 30 -41
Aquinas on, 32 -3
assisted, 33 -4, 40
autonomy and, 33 -4
decriminalisation of, 39 -41, 45
Kant on, 30 -1
McCormick on, 33 -4
surrogacy, 8, 65 -7, 69 - 88
and personal liberty, 74 -5, 86 -8
and slavery, 78 -9, 82
arguments of moral principle against,
76 - 80
Australian Catholic bishops on, 70
-171-
-172-