Masterpiece
Masterpiece
Michael Kausch*
1. To the Question
*PD Mag. Dr. phil. habil, Eschenrieder Str. 11, D-82194 Gröbenzell, BRD, Austrian.
Telephone: +49 (0) 89 28803698
† Clark, Kenneth: What is a Masterpiece? London 1979.
78 International Journal of Art and Art History, Vol. 2(2), December 2014
To 1: Classical aesthetics essentially going back to the state of the 18th century
seems to have become relative by aesthetics of the open work of art, which is not
centered in the work, but – being based on the interaction between the work of art
and the recipient – in the observer.
To 3:The limitation to European art and culture seems not any more tenable
in times of a global perspective heading for world art and in the frame of a
postcolonial perspective.
Now which conclusion has to be drawn from these results? Are there no
aesthetic criteria universally applicable to the arts and the cultures? Does each
(individual) work of art and each culture stand just for itself? Do we therefore have to
accept a situation of relativism, subjectivism, even solipsism? Or are there still
possibilities – starting from the classical tradition and in view of the conditions of
modern age – to work out a new aesthetics more open and flexible but universally
valid?
In this analysis arguments for the latter way shall be collected and presented –
which naturally requires an approach to the question without prejudice (!).
The process of modern age has come to a point, where relativism and
subjectivism threaten to erode the base on which just this modern age and its
conception of a free, open society are founded (example: universality of human
rights).‡
It is known that with the nobilitation of the fine arts and the increasing
importance of the creative artistic personality since the Renaissance a shift of the
center of gravity came about: on the one hand to the subject of the artist and his idea,
on the other hand to differentiated theories of art and their teaching at the newly
founded academies.The masterpiece becomes a creation which is produced according
to established rules and criteria by the inspired artist, who is orientated towards idea.
So finally in theBalance des peintrespublished by Roger de Piles marks are given to the
painters in the categories ofcomposition, dessin, coloris andexpression.§
‡ This danger was seen in the famous 2004 Munich discussion between the German philosopher Jürgen
Habermas and Joseph Ratzinger, the later Pope Benedict by both interlocutors from their very
different philosophies and world views.
§See: Vouilloux, Bernard: Article Chef d’Œuvre. In : Morizot, Jacques ; Pouivet, Roger : Dictionnaire
The protagonist of the short story, the painter Frenhofer, goes over his work
so long until the subject has almost completely disappeared under an amorphous layer
of over paintings.Here the elements of the conceptual and of the processappear as
fundamental characteristics of modernism.**
3. Thesis
**
See: Belting, Hans: Das unbekannte Meisterwerk. München 1998.
Rosenblum, Robert: Modern Painting and the Northern Romantic Tradition. London 1975.
Michael Kausch 81
These fundamental natural laws meet different differentiations in diverse artistic and
cultural regions.
First of all a series of criteriashall presented which recur in classical art critic as
well as in art historical analysis and which are considered as being constitutive of a
masterpiece. Many of these can be found in the already cited essay by Kenneth Clarke
and shall be presented from his paper:
- Truth and imitation: „Well, we may agree that devotion to truth is an attribute of
the human mind from which a masterpiece may grow, and most people who are
inclined to use the word masterpiece at all would apply it to Las Meninas of
Velazquez. In the simplest meaning of the word, Las Meninas shows a devotion to
truth that has never been equaled.
But can mere imitation be the basis of a masterpiece? A small detail – what
used to be called a trompe l’oeil – can hardly claim to be a masterpiece. But when the
discovery of truth is extended to a group of persons situated in a large room, and
involved in a delicate human situation, then the painter’s intellectual grasp and his
technical skill can be combined to produce a masterpiece.“†††
- (Human) values: „Thus the Entombment [Titian, Louvre] has that double
relationship with us, which is the prerogative of the masterpiece. It is a superb piece
of design and a profound assertion of human values.
This definition is very close to the Pathosformel by Aby Warburg. Irma Emmrich in Weltbild und
ästhetische Struktur distinguishes two ways resp. degrees of reception and transformation: the
conservative one of modification and the revolutionary one of innovation.
See: Emmrich, Irma: Weltbild und ästhetische Struktur. Dresden 1982.
Michael Kausch 83
Many of these criteria of the tradition of classical aesthetics and theory of art
can be conceived and justified in a better way from the perspective of modern
scientific knowledge. For the field of the formal aspects and structures of the work of
art the psychology of perception and here especially Gestalt psychology has provided
essential insights.
Precursors of this conception can already be found in the theory of art of the
19th century: So for example the German sculptor Adolf v. Hildebrand in his
workDas Problem der Form in der bildenden Kunst (1893) following the contemporary
physiology of perception differentiated between Nahsichtand Fernbild. Due to distance
only the latter would be able to perceive the structure of a work of art clearly; this
ought to be composed of simple, clearly perceivable Gestalt forms.
The actual origin of Gestalt psychology resp. of the term and the conception
of Gestalt lies with the psychologist Christian v. Ehrenfels (1890), who pointed out
that a melody cannot be explained solely by its tones(elements): at a transposition of
the tones the melody stays the same; it is “Gestalt”, the typical structure of the series
of tones, which makes up music.****
**** After: Schuster, Martin; Beisl, Horst: Kunstpsychologie. „Wodurch Kunstwerke wirken“. Köln
1978, p. 24 f..
Ehrenfels, Chr. V.: Über Gestaltqualitäten. In: Vierteljahresschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie.
1890.
†††† Wertheimer, Max: Gestaltpsychologie. In: Saupe (Hrsg.), Einführung in die neuere Psychologie
(1927).
‡‡‡‡ Köhler, Wolfgang: Psychologische Probleme. Berlin 1933.
§§§§ Koffka, Wolfgang: Principles of Gestalt psychology. London 1936.
***** Metzger, Wolfgang: Gesetze des Sehens. Frankfurt 1953.
††††† Arnheim, Rudolf: Art and Visual Perception – a psychology of the creative eye. Berkeley and Los
Angeles, 1954.
84 International Journal of Art and Art History, Vol. 2(2), December 2014
- The law of figure and ground:It means that one always splits up the seen image in
two components, in a figure which is seen in the foreground in a sharp and well-
structured way, and a ground which is assumed to be rather diffusely in the
background. The contour, the form belongs to the outlined figure, the background is
formless. (It is not so that the things around us would offer sharp figures and diffuse
backgrounds by themselves). The best known example is the so-called Rubin vase
(Ill.2), a realization in art is found in Invisible Bust of Voltaire (1940, Salvador Dali
Museum, St. Petersburg, Florida, Ill.3) by Salvador Dali.
Ill. 3: Salvador Dali, Invisible Bust of Voltaire, 1940, Salvador Dali Museum, St.
Petersburg, Florida
The fundamental law of figure and ground is completed by other Gestalt laws:
§§§§§A well-known analytical and therapeutical adaptation is the Rorschach test which works by
projection of visual structures including their emotional or conceptual contents.
See also Leonardo’s advice in hisTrattatodellapittura to developfigures (resp. Gestalten) from
humiditystains on walls.
86 International Journal of Art and Art History, Vol. 2(2), December 2014
The mentioned laws can be resumed in the law of good gestalt. This law means
that forms, especially if they are not perceived precisely, are improved, are made
prägnant.******Improvement of gestalt therefore means: Filling in of gaps, production
of symmetry, approach of the form towards a known object, production of higher
regularity, turning away from an accidental distribution of figurative elements.Now if
these fundamental insights of the Gestalt psychology are related to the traditional
criteria of aesthetics – especially to the formal ones – partially cited in Clarke’s essay,
the following becomes clear:
Simple geometric basic forms such as the triangle (pyramidal composition, f.e.
Madonnas by Raphael, Ill.3) or the circle, but also the rectangle, the ellipse or the
diagonal, are found not by chance and not only in certain styles or cultures. For
evidently they have a psychological, a physiological and in the end an anthropological
base: that means they are based in the constitution of man. The organizing strife for
prägnanz, for the good form is effective as well in the depiction of singular objects as
in the shaping of the global composition.
******If
for example simple figures (circle, triangle, square) showing a gap in the flow of the line are
offered for a very short time, the beholder is closing these gaps, that means he does not notice the
gaps.
Siehe also the special experiments mentioned in Schuster.
In: Schuster, op.cit., p. 31f..
Michael Kausch 87
Among others on this – within a wider frame – the range of variation and the
change of individual and period styles are based. So f.e. Sander (1931) – following on
the thesis of Heinrich Wölfflin – tried to put down the difference between
Renaissance and Baroque to different architectonic ways of construction, which apply
the law of good gestalt.
88 International Journal of Art and Art History, Vol. 2(2), December 2014
††††††See also psychological experiments on the effect of forms resp. the assignment of forms to
artificial names.
Michael Kausch 89
On the contrary Baroque art is characterized by: It wants to seize; attacks with
the power of affect, it overwhelms, produces excitement, ecstasy, transport, is
determined to the impression of the moment, conveys the experience of
development, events, the forms leave the beholder unsatisfied, give the impression of
restlessness, produce tension, the condition of passion.
This effect is based on the following basic forms and construction principles:
Rectangles being near to the square or exceeded in length or width, elliptic curves,
obtuse or acute angles, sequences with not equal distances (windows), the axis of
symmetry is moved out of the center, no frontally parallel plane, solid demarcation
lines broken up.
‡‡‡‡‡‡ This is also or even more true for the relationship between Renaissance and Mannerism.
90 International Journal of Art and Art History, Vol. 2(2), December 2014
On the other hand, within each culture resp. artistic area, there is a range of
sometimes even contradictory varieties which take form in the course of cultural and
artistic development or even in the way of synchronic varieties.
Ill.9: Chacmool from Chichén Itzá, Maya – Toltec, 11.-12.centuries AD, México
City, Museo Nacional de Anthropología
Secondly, the God is represented in one of the basic corporal postures due to
human anatomy, the reclining figure.
Michael Kausch 93
In modern European art, this type of the Reclining Figure has become one of
the major artistic structures in the work of the British sculptor Henry Moore. Moore
got to know the Chacmool figure by a plaster cast which he saw in the Trocadéro
Museum in Paris. It became the work of reference for the creation of his famous
Leeds Reclining Figure (Ill.10)
Ill. 11: Malagan Mortuary Figure, North coast of New Ireland, Late 19th – Early
20thCentury AD, London, British Museum
Figures like this one where made for funeral ceremonies in New Ireland
(Oceania), which were a part of the Malagan system determining the whole life of
man. According the interpretation of Susanne Küchler, the structure was destined to
take in the life force of the deceased. This life force, called noman – a metaphor of
energy and vitality – was linked to the female capability of reproduction.§§§§§§
§§§§§§See:
Gunn, Michael: Ritual Arts of Oceania – New Ireland in the Collections of the Barbier-
Mueller Museum. Genova – Milano 1997.
Michael Kausch 95
In this case, too, Henry Moore, when developing the artistic idea of
Internal/External Form in 1951 (Ill.12), was primarily interested in the formal
structure:
The structure of the Malagan figure fitted perfectly in his artistic thinking of
this period, which strived to open up consequently the compact, solid sculptural mass
by creating voids and “holes”.
As a result of this analysis it may be said, that good Gestalts resp. the principle
of good Gestalts is omnipresent in world art. So it is legitimate to conclude that the
artistic achievement of these may be regarded as fundamental values in works of art
resp. in the process of artistic creation.
4.3. The Image of Man and the Conception of the World – Values - Ethics
Following the discussion of some aspects belonging to the formal side of the
structure of the work of art resp. of the masterpiece now such ones as regards
contents shall be mentioned – being definitely aware that the dichotomy of
form/contents is an artificial perspective which is applied later to the work of art as a
means of analysis.
First of all we refer once again to the essay by Kenneth Clarke: Here criteria
of a masterwork as regards contents were named:
Michael Kausch 97
Ad 1.The demand for the illustration of important themes has been a central
point of classical art theory since antiquity and this not only in the area of the fine
arts, but particularly also in the genre of literature. Here above all in drama – wetherin
Shakespeare, in French classical theatre with Corneille or Racine or in Weimar
classics, that is in Goethe and above all in Schiller. Already in the further course of the
19th century the subject area of important themes was broadened from great issues of
upper class figures to figures of the working classes – wether it is about Thomas
Hardy’s Tess of the d’Urbervilles or Die Weber by Gerhard Hauptmann.
Today nobody will seriously maintain that in the latter works of art less
important themes are treated than in the first ones. For both artistic conceptions
concern the creation of humanly important subjects, which are fundamental for
human social existence. In the sense of the analytical psychology of C.G. Jung these
are archetypal subjects and motives such as oedipal conflicts, the relation of the sexes,
motherhood (see the dominant presence of this archetype in the creation of Henry
Moore and its interpretation by Erich Neumann) etc. or anthropologically speaking,
anthropological constants.
Ad 2.The criterion resp. the claim for truth in art is as old as occidental
aesthetics and philosophy of art. It is known to be rooted in the Platonic doctrine of a
close connection of the good, the true and the beautiful, a conception which –
although in a transformed and lessened form – remained valid until the 19th century.
Even Plato, however, criticized the artistic depiction of reality as being untrue for
creating just copies of copies (of the ideas) and therefore for pedagogical reasons
banished it from his ideal state.
98 International Journal of Art and Art History, Vol. 2(2), December 2014
With Aestheticism, l’Art pour l‘art and in the conception of modernism this
development got to its extreme consequence: The work of art is conceived as being
autonomous with regard to the categories of scientific establishment of truth and to
ethical claims and norms.This conception, however, proves to be an extreme position,
to which numerous artistic movements of modernism stand really in
contrast:Expressionism, realisms such as Neue Sachlichkeit or even Socialist Realism,
social – critical and political directions, environmental – critical and ecological
tendencies are committed to truth in the sense of uncovering and depiction of aspects
of reality. In a time where art with regard to the perspective of science is increasingly
conceived as an original instrument of recognition, the conception of autonomy of
modernism reveals itself as obsolete.
Ad 3.This is also valid for the 3rd area - as regards contents - cited in Clarke,
namely that of (human) values resp. that of ethics:
In the modern age the intention and the extensive realization of a partial or
complete liberation of the work of art from the relationship with morals and the
social laws which regulate “real” life can be observed. And – connected to this –the
abandonment resp. the refusal of a pedagogical conveying of contents coming from
outside of art. The sphere of art and artistry are regarded as a special area, being more
or less independent, which shall serve the unrestrained and unlimited expression of
the ego resp. the free creation of fictional aesthetic worlds.
Nevertheless, with reference to the field of the relation between art and ethics,
too, it has to be emphasized:
1. The work of art (as basically every cultural product) is a vehicle of values
2. It is related with the system of values resp. of ethical principles, norms and rules
‡‡‡‡‡‡‡Connected to this is the function of individual and collective healing (corresponding to the
perspective of psychoanalysis resp. of Analytical Psychology of C.G. Jung) by (re-)integration of the
suppressed into the ego – on the level of the individual or society and culture and thereby the
restoration of the sane integrality.
100 International Journal of Art and Art History, Vol. 2(2), December 2014
As regards contents here the question arises, which values can be valid as
obligatory in the sense of criteria of a good work of art resp. masterwork.
Regarding this it suggests itself to start first of all at the own cultural tradition,
that means at the basic values as they have developed out of the European resp.
western history. Naturally we mean the development, which on the foundation of
Greco-Roman antiquity through Christianity, humanism and the enlightenment has
led to the modern conception of human rights. In the sense of philosophy and
cultural history – especially in an increasingly globalized world – it is not reasonably
possible to fall back from this stage of development.§§§§§§§ In this respect here the
position of a (moderate) universalism shall be hold. A moderate universalism, for,
firstly, in the actual situation the other big cultural traditions of the globe, too, bring in
their experiences relating to this and, secondly, in other cultures there have been
movements of enlightenment, too.********
In this respect there are works of art – and in this category those being
generally accepted as masterworks and having been accepted in the canon are largely
included – which depict these basic human values explicitly or just only implicitly in a
condensed form. On the other hand’s side it is known that also works of art do exist,
which propagate demerits or disparage or deride man in general, a social group resp.
certain ways of life in a contemptuous way.
In the end in this question one has to refer to anthropological basic values
which can be ascertained in an intercultural and transcultural perspective. Examples
may be the respect for human life, the respect for nature/environment, the value of
the transmission of life in the context of parenthood – mother – child, etc.††††††††
§§§§§§§History,of course, shows many examples of this falling back from a higher philosophical, cultural
or technical level, the best known and most famous being the development in late Roman antiquity.
Nevertheless the achieved level remained valid as a point of reference and a source of cultural
technology for all later epochs and, as we know, was taken up in all Renaissances.
See: Panofsky, Erwin: Renaissance and renaissances in western art. New York 1969
********One standard has always to be: the liberty of man to create his life with respect for the liberty of
others.
††††††††About the research on anthropological constants and universals see:
Antweiler, Christoph: Was ist den Menschen gemeinsam? Über Kultur und Kulturen. Darmstadt 2007.