Application of Systems Thinking To Health Policy Public Health Ethics Public Health and Private Illness (Michele Battle-Fisher (Auth.) )
Application of Systems Thinking To Health Policy Public Health Ethics Public Health and Private Illness (Michele Battle-Fisher (Auth.) )
Series Editor
Macey Leigh Henderson
Georgetown University Kennedy Institute of Ethics, Washington,
District of Columbia, USA
SpringerBriefs in Public Health present concise summaries of cutting-edge research
and practical applications from across the entire field of public health, with contri-
butions from medicine, bioethics, health economics, public policy, biostatistics, and
sociology.
The focus of the series is to highlight current topics in public health of interest to a
global audience, including health care policy; social determinants of health; health
issues in developing countries; new research methods; chronic and infectious dis-
ease epidemics; and innovative health interventions.
Featuring compact volumes of 50 to 125 pages, the series covers a range of content
from professional to academic. Possible volumes in the series may consist of timely
reports of state-of-the art analytical techniques, reports from the field, snapshots of
hot and/or emerging topics, elaborated theses, literature reviews, and in-depth case
studies. Both solicited and unsolicited manuscripts are considered for publication
in this series.
Briefs are published as part of Springer’s eBook collection, with millions of us-
ers worldwide. In addition, Briefs are available for individual print and electronic
purchase.
Briefs are characterized by fast, global electronic dissemination, standard publish-
ing contracts, easy-to-use manuscript preparation and formatting guidelines, and
expedited production schedules. We aim for publication 8-12 weeks after accep-
tance.
More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/10138
Michele Battle-Fisher
Application of Systems
Thinking to Health Policy
& Public Health Ethics
Public Health and Private Illness
1 3
Michele Battle-Fisher
Wright State University
Kettering
Ohio
USA
v
Acknowledgements
vii
Contents
ix
x Contents
Index������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������ 97
Part I
Systems Within Health Policy and Ethics
Chapter 1
Framing and Revisiting Ethical Policy
with a Systems Perspective
We take then our point of departure from the objective fact that human acts have conse-
quences upon others, that some of these consequences are perceived, and that their percep-
tion leads to subsequent effort to control action so as to secure some consequences and
avoid others. Following this clew, we are led to remark that the consequences are of two
kinds, those which affect the persons directly engaged in a transaction, and those which
affect others beyond those immediately concerned. In this distinction, we find the germ of
the distinction between the private and the public. (Dewey 1987)
well intentions, the activation of the policy is often uneven in this effect. Health
disparities exist while well-intentioned policy was created for the very reason of
eradicating them. A revised approach would require to not ignore the innate struc-
ture within the fabric of the policy. Building upon the World Health Organization’s
definition, health policy must better dissect its systemic elements as follows:
• Interdependent social realities
• Epidemiological goals and measures
• Policy initiatives (past, present, and future)
• Governance impacts on the healthcare system
• Health related actions of agents affected by the policy
• Ethics and morals, both individually and collectively
• Political climates
Note that this reconstruction of the health policy realizes the arc of policy as a
confluence of public interests and private welfare. Reactive policymaking responds
to an outcry that merits immediate action and governance (Torjman 2005). Policies
may be made to target the short term or the long term concerns. In media, policy is
often announced as an act being passed in response to a politically acute problem in
hopes of reversing and/or reducing any emerging effects based on the chronicity of
the health concern. The exigency of a particular situation demanding does not ex-
cise the fact that care must be taken in its development and implementation. How-
ever, network research by Crane (1991) has shown that a problem from sparse to
more populated problems may more quickly spread than anticipated. Health policy
has to worry about medical as well as systemic spread.
… if the incidence [of the problem] reaches a critical point, the process of spread [within a
network] will explode. (Crane 1991)
The magnitude of the coverage of the health policy in part is defined with epide-
miological evidence over time or proof of an emergent need happening now. Of-
ten in the aftermath of activating the existing policy, new developments that make
evident the need for tweak or overhaul appear during the act of its use. Assessment
while doing so (such as outcome evaluation) is often necessarily, a good business.
System-based assessment for future policy allows for simulation of ready data to
anticipate “what ifs” versus real-time trials where it is baptism by fire with no safety
harness. If a policy is afforded the liberty to be worked out over time without duress,
policy stakeholders may relish in the ability to break down and reassess the policies
before implementing them into action. But public health always has fires to put out.
Meadows and Robinson (1985) spoke of the public’s mystery of the “logic” be-
hind how the social policy was created. What may be clear to the public is the
overarching paternalistic goal of the policy. This logic of how it came in existence
may not matter to the public if the policy is working. If the policy is found to be less
than successful with continued ill effects on the community, the public may ask for
answers from policymakers.
Systems Thinking Over Linearity 5
Phillip Tetlock (2005) sought to explain why political experts fail so badly at dis-
cerning complexity, let only forecasting the civic future. In order to more fully
understand this phenomenon, he compared two styles of thinking. Tetlock (2005)
called up Isaiah Berlin’s prototypes of the fox and the hedgehog to explore patterns
of political prediction in terms of discrimination of information to the calibration
of that information (see Berlin 1953). The traditionalist “hedgehogs” are myopic,
often resorting to the use a simple model which suits his ontology. The “foxes” are
quite sly yet scattered in approaching judgment calls. Foxes rely on many mental
models without discerning them any further. In the end, if you place your policy
bets on the fox do so at your own risk though the odds are far more dismal with
a hedgehog. Better yet, formal modeling with experience as called upon by von
Bertalanffy (1962) outwits the fox and leaves the hedgehog’s myopic judgments in
the dust.
Tetlock is speaking primarily of getting to what is called structural knowledge
(see Brehmer 1990). Changing judgments about a system with such structural
knowledge can lead an organization to the operations of a model and is a require-
ment but it cannot discern how the system might react (Hamid 2009). How might
this all affect policymaking? Where should stakeholders with the quill of governance
intervene? In systems, there are leverage points. According to Meadows (1999), a
leverage point is power. These leverage points “are places with a complex system
where a small shift … can produce big changes in everything” (Meadows 1999). It
is great if policy can uncover a leverage to change the course as intended but it is a
disaster if used selection of this leverage turns out to be incorrect (Meadows 1999).
For those who view the world as a constant interplay of its elements, this is sys-
tems thinking. Systems thinking is a methodological call for a critical reappraisal
of policies under a new critical eye. It is an approach to understand how a whole
of interrelated parts change dynamically over time. How would one know if he or
she is a systems thinker? In the end, systems thinking resolves interrelationships in
time and space. Booth-Sweeney and Meadows (1995) offered a laundry list of the
characteristics of a systems thinker. A systems thinker would naturally:
1. See the “whole” picture
2. Change perspectives to see new leverage points to intervene
3. Look for interdependencies in elements
4. Pay attention to the long-term and not be swayed by short-term results
5. “Go wide” to see complex causes
6. Focus on structure not blame
7. Hold the tension of paradox and controversy without rushing to resolution
8. Make systems visible through maps and simulations
9. See oneself as a part of, not outside of, the system
The point is not to display a neon sign to the world that one is a “systems thinker”
or exercising “systems thinking.” No disclaimer must be affixed to the start of ev-
ery policy document with the marque to the effect that no interdependences of the
6 1 Framing and Revisiting Ethical Policy with a Systems Perspective
What Is a System?
The definition of a system is foundational to systems thinking. Not unlike other at-
tempts to define the physical and social worlds, there are many definitions given for
“system.” The father of modern General Systems, Ludwig von Bertalanffy defined
a system as “an entity that maintains its existence through the mutual interaction of
its parts to achieve” (von Bertanlaffy 1968). For starters, a system is comprised of
interconnecting parts that affect the integrity of the whole when the components
change over time. Systems denote interaction and flow of elements. The obvious
“what ifs” are often are taken at face value, and are used to inform decision-making.
The elusiveness system takes some work to discover but can be done through vari-
ous systems approaches and methodologies. Until the recent advent of sophisticated
computer based visualization and analysis programs (such as Vensim PLE, STEL-
LA, iTHINK (used specifically for applications to policy), UCInet, Pajet, Linku-
rious, Gephi and NodeXL), social systems were described metaphorically. There
were no computer based tools to mathematically formalize the theoretical hunches,
or a way to reasonably concatenate and simulate this big data’s complexity until
most recently.
Policy “Bread Crumbs” 7
What is surprising about a social system? Ross Ashby (1956) wrote some years
ago that “the harder you push, the harder the system pushes back.” The hard tobacco
control pushes, other drives, anticipated or blindsiding, recalibrates the tobacco sys-
tem after the passage of US Public Law 111-31. Systems are built upon interaction,
or as in the cases presented in this book, specifically predicated on social interac-
tion. External environmental factors can affect how a system operates. In addition,
feedbacks may also be apparent in a system. With feedback, there is a continuous
flux in social influences from the external environment that require recalibration of
the system. Systems thinking requires “seeing” beyond the common go-to elements
of how policy has always been approached. Systems thinking can harness an under-
standing of social elements that often unpredictable and uncontrollable. What poli-
cymakers can control is their approach to those changing, interconnected elements.
Systems thinking leads to another conclusion–however, waiting, shining, obvious as soon
as we stop being blinded by the illusion of control. It says that there is plenty to do, of a
different sort of “doing.” The future can’t be predicted, but it can be envisioned and brought
lovingly into being. Systems can’t be controlled, but they can be designed and redesigned.
We can’t surge forward with certainty into a world of no surprises, but we can expect sur-
prises and learn from them and even profit from them. We can’t impose our will upon a
system. We can listen to what the system tells us, and discover how its properties and our
values can work together to bring forth something much better than could ever be produced
by our [political] will alone. (Meadows n.d.)
Policymakers have been sorely aware that the many moving parts related to a public
policy were present. Harvesting and understanding those parts into a comprehensive
way, emerging as a whole has been more difficult. The interplay of the components
will change when people are added in the equation. The policy defines explicitly the
state of the current system with intention toward change in the future. It is important
to connect the concept of state of the system to policy success. It takes time to real-
ize what is happening in a system in terms of social impact. New policies and its
components are not separate from the histories left by ones before.
According to Forrester (2007), there is a life span for any component of a system.
This system variable is bonded to its history (“past path”) until it dies in the system.
8 1 Framing and Revisiting Ethical Policy with a Systems Perspective
Forrester (2007) noted that in the short term, there is less chance for error as the
system. But the longer the policy is active, the game changes across the landscape.
The policy is often not the last attacking a particular problem. There should ideally
be a return to the policy unless outside forces torpedo it, there is a built-in shut-off
mechanism, or perhaps the situation targeted by the policy no longer exists (see
Bardach 1976).
[Systems thinking and tools] give people the ability to “see” a neighborʼs backyard even if
that backyard is thousands of miles away. They also confer the ability to “experience” the
morning after—even if the morning after is tens of thousands of years hence. (Richmond
1993)
Systems theory stands for attempting scientific interpretation and theory where previously
there was none. (von Bertalanffy 1968)
Rigorously defining constructs, attempting to measure them, and using the most appropri-
ate methods to estimate their magnitudes are important antidotes to casual empiricism,
muddled formulations, and the erroneous conclusions we often draw from our mental mod-
els. (Sterman 2002)
…all decisions are made on the basis of models. Most models are in our heads. Mental
models are not true and accurate images of our surroundings, but are only sets of assump-
tions and observations gained from experience. Mental models have great strengths, but
also serious weaknesses … computer simulation models can compensate for weaknesses in
mental models. (Forrester 1994)
The book, The Fifth Discipline, written by Peter Senge (1990) introduced the idea
of the mental model as generalization. At the core of Senge’s (1990) book are the
five principles of learning. These principles comprise of:
1. Personal mastery
2. Mental models
3. Building shared visions
4. Team learning
5. Systems thinking
Systems thinking is the overarching tie through these principles. Included as one of
these principles, the mental model specifically is the premature and often under ana-
lyzed mental representation. Mental models are blind spots that obscure the need to
dig deeper. The mental model is not the problem; failing to return to more nuanced
analysis, accounting for the mental model, is. Heuristics or cognitive shortcuts that
serve as social rules, which often fail and offer a false sense of security (Gigerenzer
and Gaissmaier 2011). But policy must account for the past to move forward. Heu-
ristics unwittingly act as undesirable, often detrimental noise. When told that some-
thing appears too good and simple to be true, that heuristic often is faulty logic. It
is simple to take in and may in the end fool in its simplicity. Preference, according
to Gigerenzer and Gaissmaier (2011), reigns supreme over measurable inferences.
People do not go through the day modelling against cognitive shortcuts to decide
between lattes with soy over a Frappuccino. A decision may be made quickly as
work starts in 5 min, or the cappuccino machine is out of order.
When the stakes are high such is the case of the systemic effects of a health
policy, formal modeling is indispensable. Vast amount of research supports the
behavioral decision model (BDM) (see Hogarth 1987; Thaler 1991). In such a case
of BDM, human cognitive abilities have been experimentally shown as limited. The
call here is for policymakers to avail themselves the policy road maps and the social
footprints left as a consequence of that governance decision. The public has short
memories about the latest health scare or exploding epidemic unless a personal nar-
rative continues to strike them. The ramifications of an unsuccessful policy linger
glaringly for policymakers and this is not a time for cognitive frugality.
10 1 Framing and Revisiting Ethical Policy with a Systems Perspective
Fig. 1.1 The linear model of policy reform. (Reprinted from world development, 18 (8), Thomas,
J. & Grindle, M., After the decision: implementing policy reforms in developing countries, 1163-
81, 1990, with permission from Elsevier)
Jake Chapman (2004) offered the warning that reigning policy making approach
is rational. Not much has changed since the Chapman’s monograph was produced.
But if there can ever be a way that behavior can be annulled and controlled by a
policy, and then rationality would suit the purpose of policymaking. However, the
policymaking approach cannot rest on reductionism. Below I introduce two oppos-
ing illustrations of policy. Figure 1.1 offers Thomas and Grindle’s (1990) graphical
representation of a linear approach to policy making. Next, Fig. 1.2 presents the Dy-
namic Adaptive Policy Pathways as one example of a complexity-based approach to
policymaking (Haasnoot et al. 2013). How are the two approaches to policymaking
different, or perhaps similar?
The calculus of policy making is more often than not left to experts to hammer
out the dialectics. People are not classically rational; neither should our approach
to policy be limited by a misplaced bias toward linearity across the board. Human
rationality is gilded photo shopping. The appearance is pristine and hypnotically
enticing but is improbable to achieve. To this end, Chapman (2004) offered four
factors that are woefully underestimated with rationality. They are, according to
Chapman (2004):
1. Feedbacks, which loop forward and backward in effect
2. Complexity
3. Interconnectedness (though I add that the parts are more than connected, the
parts additionally interact and self-organize)
4. Globalization
One would be hard pressed to not find elements of many, if not all, of these factors
at play within public policy. But Fig. 1.2 more closely fits these requirements. The
very reason for policy is impact. Therefore, the wording of a policy is calculated
as to hopefully reduce the risk of misinterpretation. The implementation trajectory
The Mental Model and Its Shortcuts 11
Fig. 1.2 The dynamic adaptive policy pathways model. The dynamic adaptive policy pathways
was created to help explain the implications of the uncertainty of external factors in global sustain-
ability policymaking. The model brings together two elements inherent to policymaking- adaptive
policymaking and adaption pathways. This figure represents this systemic approach to tracking
and understanding uncertainties and monitor outcomes in light of this uncertainty. (Reprinted from
global environmental change, 23, Haasnoot, M., Kwakkel, J., Walker, W. & Ter Maat, J., dynamic
adaptive policy pathways: a method for crafting robust decisions for a deeply uncertain world,
pp 485–498, 2013, with permission from Elsevier)
taken as a result of the policy after the ink dries is not. One could say that policy has
less to do directly with the outcomes based on personal actions. Policy is respon-
sible for fostering an environment based on legally sound, agreed upon rules that
serve to support decision-making. Warner (2002) pointed out that a law, or even a
policy, cannot organize a public (system). The people then act within the constraints
of those prescripts, for better or for worse. But if the population (public) turns out
to be adversely harmed by their personal actions (private), policy is often revisited
to mitigate these newly significant social developments. Was there a policy in place
that should have protected to public? If so, was the scope of that policy sufficient to
cover the magnitude of the event? If there was no applicable policy in place, how
was the health concern handled in the absence of such guidance? If there were poli-
cies that could be employed, did they work and to what extent were they successful?
12 1 Framing and Revisiting Ethical Policy with a Systems Perspective
When health policies are enacted, policymakers and the society at large speak of the
side effects of that policy on real people. The power of harnessing support using this
model is to underline the delicacy of linked relationships. Schelling (2006) warned
to look away from the light of coveting constant balance or equilibrium. Balance
is just an event, not the savior of a policy. Change is coming no matter the drive to
maintain that balance. The society reacts under its mandates. Thus, it is more appro-
priate to view equilibrium as a goal oriented horizon point, but a result nonetheless
will change again (Schelling 2006). However, unless the chain of events central to
the policy disappears and becomes inconsequential, life still churns along and the
residuals of policies ride on.
Most policies fall far short of maximizing benefits. The primary reason, (Zeckhauser)
would argue, is not that policymakers are ignorant or ill informed about these matters,
though assuredly some of them are. Rather, policymaker’s concerns, quite appropriately, go
beyond choosing the policy alternative that offers the greatest level of efficiency benefits
…. The political process recoils from the “let the chips fall where they may” nature of
traditional efficiency maximization. (Zeckhauser 1981)
The Veteran Affairs (VA) health system represents the largest integrated sys-
tem in the nation. While current military are served by the Department of
Defense for medical care, upon separation of duty the veteran is under the care
of the VHA. The VA has is made up of 1700 facilities which are charged with
the care of over 6.3 million veterans each year. A healthy military is a strong
military. A healthy military helps to ensure the best quality of life of the ser-
vice members, their families as well as their communities. The proud employ-
ees of the VA have answered the noble call to serve our military. As health is a
partnership across agencies and patients, the VA must place a priority on real
systemic successes and lapses beyond the organizational outcomes expected
to succeed. The workings of VA support and hinder continuity of care. In addi-
tion, the service member and the veteran enter a web of clinics and support
services with that can be dizzying to navigate and disjointed in organization.
It is imperative that the Veterans Health Administration (VHA) honestly mea-
sure the true complexity of serving its patients. A lean and nimble VA system
is one that does not fear the complexity before it, but rather honestly evaluates
the network of layers tying medical services and patients. Understanding and
aligning the formal and informal structure of VA requires a new plan of attack,
one that starts with discovering the power in looking at medical services and
patients as a changing web of relationships involved in patient care.
In this graph, there is a disconnection of the veteran patient (the circle) and the
VA hospital (the sphere) which interferes with the medical plan required by
the domiciliary. Also, there is no connection between the clinic (square) and
counseling (diamond) segments in caring for the patient’s PTSD although the
patient (circle) is still connected to both. (Fig. 1.3)
Fig. 1.3 Hypothetical VA patient care scenario. This is a network graph of possible coordinating
agents of the VHA system as nodes (veteran, VA hospital, medical clinic, counseling services,
domiciliary). It should be noted that a veteranʼs care may not require all of the agents in the graph.
For the sake of illustration, the veteran in this scenario is central to the discerning breakdowns in
patient care. (Network graph created by author using NodeXL- used with permission Smith et al.
(2010). NodeXL: a free and open network overview, discovery and exploration add-in for Excel
2007/2010, http://nodexl.codeplex.com/ from the Social Media Research Foundation, http://www.
smrfoundation.org)
Veterans’ Health and the VA Healthcare System 15
Proposed Solution
As noted by Dr. John Daigh in the above comments before the committee, the
“airline” checklist approach that “all health care is local” a part of the prob-
lem (Veterans Health Administration 2014). I argue the health care is local
and whole system based. It is part of the reality that no matter the changes
made to standardize the formal VA organization structure, work happens
sometimes without regard of the formal structure. Reliance on technology to
tie elements of the VA system, while of merit, is only a small part of the solu-
tion. The informal networks must be acknowledged as “local” in the sense
that people are act as individual agents within a system. An academic study
16 1 Framing and Revisiting Ethical Policy with a Systems Perspective
in 2007 found that the odds of mortality were higher when there was a delay
in getting an appointment beyond thirty days (Prentice and Pizer 2007). This
is not only an issue of backlogs which certainly must be improved greatly.
Another facet of this issue is the connection between a patient and the vari-
ous services required from the VHA. I propose two policy initiatives. First,
stronger measures must be taken to decrease disruptions in continuity of care
for VA patients. The formal organization must be reassessed from a systems
perspective. This formal organization assessment must be compared to the
rules and policies used by employees of the VHA. Finally and perhaps more
importantly, the informal organization structures (how things are really done)
must be studied accounting for the fact that systems and members of those
systems attend to change over time.
It is time to see the VA patient as an integral part of the network and work
to foster an environment where patients remain engaged with the appropriate
services over the long term. It is acknowledged that the VHA has begun part-
nerships with accomplished academic institutions to pursue improving qual-
ity with the “System Redesign Framework.” These partnerships at the local
level develop operational decision support systems based on simulation mod-
elling. This is evidence that VHA is dipping its toes into systems thinking.
This is a welcome and much needed development that must then be taken up
practically and translated into policy changes. Any policies henceforth must
approach the VA “system” as a changing system using the tools and methods
ties to uncovering mechanical as well as social complexity. Veterans’ lives
hang in the balance.
This, then, is the aim of the systems approach: looking into those organismic features of life,
behavior, society; taking them seriously and not bypassing or denying them; finding conceptual
tools to handle them; developing models to represent them in conceptual constructs; making these
models work in the scientific ways of logical deduction, of construction of material analogues,
computer simulation and so forth; and so to come to better understanding, explanation, prediction,
control of what makes an organism, a psyche, or a society function. (von Bertalanffy 1967)
The take home from the memo should be that the complexity should be tackled in
policy. Saying the VA mess is complex does not go far enough. The complexity is
there. As will be discussed later in this book, the act of attacking one element of a
system is the least productive way to deal with issues that percolate within a system.
There can be a myriad of factors, both manifest and latent, that work within any
system. On top of that, there are two general classes of systems:
1. Open systems
2. Closed systems
Open systems are not cut-off from the environment around them, conventionally
understood as one “having import and export (of materials, energy or information)”
(Checkland 1981). In other words, there are inputs that undergo change to give
output. These are systems that are affected by other systems or the environment at
Policy Feedbacks 17
Policy Feedbacks
There are negativeand positive feedbacks which are the lifeblood of a system. Mar-
tinez-Garcia and Hernandez-Lemus (2013) clarified the role of such feedbacks in
terms of public policy. Accordingly, negative feedbacks “stabilize” and correct a
policy, while positive feedbacks serve as a “self-amplification of trends and diffu-
sion of new ideas…into the policy” (Martinez-Garcia and Hernandez-Lemus 2013;
see Meadows 1999). The negative feedback returns policy from going away from
the intended policy goal. Furthermore, Martinez-Garcia and Hernandez-Lemus
(2013) defined the necessitated recalibration of policies based on social “changes”
in terms of positive (reinforcing feedback) and negative (balancing feedback) loops.
For instance, what positive and negative feedbacks may be hampering VHA policy
success?
With systems thinking, feedback loops are just as they sound. A system main-
tains its overall stability by feeding depleting (as negative) or amplifying an ele-
ment back into a system (as positive) whereby self-correcting and adjusting itself.
According to Meadows (1999), the optimal benchmark for success that tips the
policy goal and feedbacks are invisible. In fact, according to Meadows (2008), the
goal is deceiving obvious. Dynamic change in a system arrives due to the inter-
action of positive (reinforcing) and negative (balancing) feedbacks (see Sterman
2000). As the name implied, positive reinforcing feedbacks “amplify whatever is
happening in the system” as well as lead to uncontrolled growth (Sterman 2000).
The negative balancing feedbacks are there to reign in the growth of the reinforcing
loops (see Sterman 2000). For example, a policy is seeking to improve the stock of
immunization. The policy seeks to influence rates of vaccination among preschool
children within underserved populations over the next year. An inflow could be the
units of the stock (net rate of the kids that got the shots) that did ultimately get fully
vaccinated. The 20 % increase is the goal being targeted for the stock (Meadows
1999). The goal may be research based, political motivated or pulled out of the air
because that is the way it has always been done. The new policy is to accumulate
more kids with shots into the policy “bathtub” and not lose many down the drain
to non-immunization (see Booth-Sweeney and Sterman 2000). However, it is well
accepted that there will be children that for a myriad of systemic reasons will not get
fully vaccinated by school age over that time period. Those unvaccinated children
deplete as an outflow the targeted policy stock of optimizing immunization. De-
spite the fact that healthcare systems are open to the environmental forces, Sterman
(2006) advanced a portending of the error caused by the outside as well. The system
by its nature is embedded in something bigger. The social environment should not
18 1 Framing and Revisiting Ethical Policy with a Systems Perspective
Policymakers can begin by approaching systems with the respect due to its power
to uncover social mechanisms. The well regarded and “successful” Australian Plain
Packaging policy illustrated internal and external systemic changes underlie even
the best made and well-intended policies.
Australia has one of the best organized, best financed, most politically savvy and well-
connected anti-smoking movements in the world. They are aggressive and have been able
to use the levers of power very effectively to propose and pass draconian legislation…. The
implications of Australian anti-smoking activity are significant outside Australia because
Australia serves as a seedbed for anti-smoking programs around the world. (Philip Morris
1992)
Australia has since implemented and had challenged progressively with preventive
policies to reduce the tobacco use and mortality in that county. An ambitious harm-
reducing policy, the 2012 Plain Packaging Act required that all domestic cigarettes
in Australia be packed in drab packaging with prominent graphic fear appeals on the
box (see Commonwealth of Australia 2012). The main effect of this policy would
be to discourage the consumption of tobacco products and lessen the burden of to-
bacco related illness in Australia. A destabilizing effect occurred—the sale and free
offers of cigarette box stickers that conceal the health warnings such as those made
commercially available after the passage of Australia’s Plain Packaging Act (see
Commonwealth of Australia 2012; “Canberra probes free cigarette covers” 2013)?
Does such plain packaging discourage smoking when the industry of cigarette skins
banks its business on the fact that the cigarettes will be consumed without the gore
in the customer’s faces? The risk/benefit of the consumer is tied to reaction of the
tobacco industry and early entry of complementary products such as the skins. Mar-
ket share is based on attractiveness and utility of the good to probable consumers.
The measured reaction by the tobacco company is very much short to medium term,
a knee jerk reaction to strike hard and fast to end this.
Policy Feedbacks 19
Complementary products such as the skins for tobacco packs must strike quickly
in order to gain a monopoly. According to Sterman (2000), the entry of the skins
before other competitors may allow the utility of the good to increase as customers
become more accustomed to availability of the good (either legally or on the black
market) and the usefulness of the product. So how on earth can policy offset the net-
work effects of market share? The graphics on the cigarette box serve double duty
in supporting smoking cessation while in turn reinforcing the need for harm reduc-
tion through promotion messaging as “why to quit” framing. “Why to quit” framing
messaging that used smokers’ stories or graphic fear appeals but did not work for
smokers in with no intention to quit in the next year (Davis et al. 2011). Smokers in
stages of attempting to give up tobacco were found to be more swayed by the ads.
While the messages studies by Davis et al. (2011) were not technically “plain pack-
aging,” the influence of personal and collective perception is highlighted as one
component of the system that will only become more apparent over time. A study of
tobacco policy experts conducted by Pechey et al. (2013) employed expert elicita-
tion methods to combat uncertainty around what could happen after the Australian
legislation’s launch. Expert elicitation is used to help fill in the blanks when some
level of quantitative accuracy is desired. According to the experts, the “plain pack-
aging policy” should result in smoking decreasing in adults, more so in children two
years are the policy was implemented. How would this be accomplished with the
policy? The harm reduction warning is still there underneath a patriotic Australian
flag skin purchased by the smoker.
The Australian Department of Health and Ageing later ruled that the skins were
not in breach of the 2012 Plain Packaging Act as the sticker product was not sold
or supplied at the time of sale of the tobacco product. Higgins et al. (2013) brought
to bear the legal question on the tip of the tongue of policymakers in examining the
implications of the Australian Plain Packaging Law- was there enough evidence to
merit the law? A cross-sectional study conducted by Wakefield et al. (2013) shortly
after the launch of the policy, plain package smokers were found to be more likely
to contemplate quitting. But contemplation does not a make a policy successful or
even legal? Does the lack of replicated, longitudinal evidence harm the standing of
this evidence in terms of continuing to justify the policy’s broad reach? (see Higgins
et al. 2013). A disadvantage to the quick policy fix is that the tub may leak. Social
leverages that are linked to the policy will no doubt change. There could be fewer
smokers. There could be an uptick among a select cohort of smokers though this
is highly unexpected. Market share of the skins could gain traction without legal
restriction. Tobacco companies could justify racking up the legal fees and weaken
any legal attack. The harm reduction could become the prevailing social rule over
time among smokers and former smokers. But what if it does not take hold to a tip-
ping point that the war on tobacco is being won by public health? What effect will
the artifacts of e-cigarettes and skins have on realizing future public health goals?
Embrace and attack wisely the unintended effects that creep up in the aftermath of
a policy. Willingly accept the artifacts have taken residence, affecting the policy’s
effects, and act as swiftly dutifully and wisely as possible.
20 1 Framing and Revisiting Ethical Policy with a Systems Perspective
Individuals need, and some may qualify, deserve, medical care. There is not an
infinite piggy bank to fund remediation of every issue. Often there are immediate
calls for policy to act now. There are constituents with personal values and beliefs
that shaped their impassioned positions that overflow the desks of legislators’ in-
boxes. There are special interests that can affect social mores and values. There is
media spin. Policy is about striking a balance that serves the most people in the most
fiscally prudent manner. Policy changes human lives. Discovering that policy sweet
spot (while owning the ramifications) is the hard part. Hopefully the sweet spot will
not be obscured by a patriotic skin or business as usual leaks in the VA pipes.
References
Hamid TKA (2009) Thinking in circles about obesity: applying systems thinking to weight man-
agement. Springer, New York
Ashby WR (1956) An introduction to cybernetics. Chapman and Hall Ltd, London
Bardach E (1976) Policy termination as a political process. Policy Sci 7(2):123–131
Berlin I (1953) The hedgehog and the fox. Simon & Schuster, New York
Booth Sweeney L, Meadows D (1995) The systems thinking playbook. Chelsea Green Publishing,
White River Junction
Booth Sweeney L, Sterman J (2000) Bathtub Dynamics: Initial Results of a Systems Thinking
Inventory. Syst Dynam Rev 16:249– 294
Brehmer B (1990) Strategies in real-time, dynamic decision making. In: Hogarth R (ed) Insights in
decision making: a tribute to Hillel J. Einhorn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Canberra probes free cigarette covers (2013) The Sydney Morning Herald. http://www.smh.com.
au/national/canberra-probes-free-cigarette-covers-20130103-2c6lo.html. Accessed 17 Feb 2014
Chapman J (2004) System failure. Demos (London). http://www.demos.co.uk/files/systemfail-
ure2.pdf. Accessed 12 Jan 2014
Checkland P (1981) Systems thinking, systems practice. Wiley, Chichester
Commonwealth of Australia. Tobacco plain packaging act. No. 148. http://www.comlaw.gov.au/
Details/C2011A00148. Accessed 17 Feb 2012
Corporate Affairs Plan: Philip Morris (Australia) Limited. (1992) University of California San
Francisco Legacy Tobacco Document Library. http://legacy.library.ucsf.edu/tid/fgw48e00. Ac-
cessed 27 Feb 2014
Crane J (1991) The epidemic theory of ghettos and neighborhood effects on dropping out and teen-
age childbearing. Am J Sociol 96:1226–1259
Davis K, Nonnemaker J, Farrelly M, Niederdeppe J (2011) Exploring differences in smokersʼ
perceptions of the effectiveness of cessation media messages. Tobac Contr 20:26–33
Dewey J (1987) The public and its problems. Holt and Winston Publishing, New York
Drew R, Aggleton P, Chalmers H, Wood K (2011) Using social network analysis to evaluate a
complex policy network. Evaluation 17(4):383–394
Forrester J (1994) Learning through system dynamics as preparation for the 21st century. Paper
presented at: systems thinking and dynamic modeling conference for K–12 education, Concord,
Mass
Forrester J (2007) System dynamics- the next fifty years. Syst Dynam Rev 23(2/3):359–370
Gigerenzer G, Gaissmaier W (2011) Heuristic decision making. Annu Rev Psychol 62:451–482
Ghaffar A, Tran NT, Reddy KS, Kasonde J, Bajwa T, Ammar W, Ren M, Rottingen JA, Mills A
(2013) Changing mindsets in health policy and systems research. Lancet 381:436–437
References 21
Haasnoot M, Kwakkel J, Walker W, Ter Maat J (2013) Dynamic adaptive policy pathways: a
method for crafting robust decisions for a deeply uncertain world. Global Environ Change
23(2):485–498
Higgins A, Mitchell A, Munro J (2013) Australiaʼs plain packaging of tobacco products: science
and health measures in international economic law. In: Mercurio B, Ni K-J (eds) Science and
technology in international economic law: balancing competing interest. Routledge, New York
Hogarth R (1987) Judgment and choice, 2nd edn. Wiley, Chichester
Kalish Y, Robins G (2006). Psychological predispositions and network structure: the relationship
between individual predispositions, structural holes and network closure. Soc Netw 28:56–84
Keane C (2014) Modeling behavior in complex public health systems: simulation and games for
action and evaluation. Springer Publishing, New York
Keijser B, Kwakkel J, Pruyt E (2012) How to explore and manage the future? Formal model analy-
sis for complex issues under deep uncertainty. Proceedings of the 30th international conference
of the system dynamics society. St. Gallen, Switzerland
Luke D (2005) Getting the big picture in community science: methods that capture context. Am J
Community Psychol 35(3/4):185–199
Martinez-Garcia M, Hernandez-Lemus E (2013) Health systems as complex systems. Am J Oper
Res 3:113–126
Meadows D (n.d.) Dancing with systems. Donella Meadows Institute Archives. http://www.donel-
lameadows.org/archives/dancing-with-systems/. Accessed 8 June 2014
Meadows D (1999) Leverage points: places to intervene in a system. The Sustainability Institute,
Hartland
Meadows D (2008) Thinking in systems: a primer. Chelsea Green Publishing Company, River
Junction
Meadows D, Robinson J (1985) The electronic oracle: computer models and social decisions.
Wiley, Chichester
Pechey R, Spiegelhalter D, Marteau T (2013) Impact of plain packaging of tobacco products on
smoking in adults and children: an elicitation of international expertsʼ estimates. BMC Publ
Health 13:18
Pouvreau D (2014) On the history of Ludwig von Bertalanffyʼs “general systemology”, and on its
relationship to cybernetics—part II: contexts and developments of the systemological herme-
neutics instigated by von Bertalanffy. Int J Gen Syst 43(2):172–245. doi:10.1080/03081079.2
014.883743
Prentice J, Pizer S (2007) Delayed access to health care and mortality. Health Serv Res 42(2):644–
662
Richmond B (1993) Systems thinking: critical thinking skills for the 1990s and beyond. Syst Dy-
nam Rev 9(2):113–133
Richmond B (1997) The “thinking” in systems thinking: how can we make it easier to master. Syst
Think 8(2):1–5
Schelling T (2006) Micromotives and macrobehaviors. W.W. Norton, New York
Senge P (1990) The fifth discipline. Currency Doubleday, New York
Stacey RD (1999) Strategic management and organisational dynamics: the challenge of complex-
ity, 3rd edn. Financial Times, London
Sterman J (2000) Business dynamics- systems thinking and modeling for a complex world. Mc-
Graw Hill, Boston
Sterman J (2002) All models are wrong: reflections on becoming a systems scientist. Syst Dynam
Rev 18:501–531
Sterman J (2006) Learning from evidence in a complex network. Am J Publ Health 96(3):505–514
Tetlock P (2005) Expert political judgment: how good is it? How can we know? Princeton Uni-
versity Press, Princeton
Thaler R (1991) Quasi-rational economics. Russell Sage Foundation, New York
Thomas J, Grindle M (1990) After the decision: implementing policy reforms in developing coun-
tries. World Dev 18(8):1163–1181
22 1 Framing and Revisiting Ethical Policy with a Systems Perspective
If we try to eat differently from our friends it will not only be inconvenient, but we risk
being regarded as cranks and hypochondriacs… It is difficult to step out of line with…
peers. (Rose 1985)
At the heart of public health is the improvement of individual private lives in order
to improve population-based outcomes of the most urgent need to society. Public
health and private illness are political as well as biological. The dichotomy of public
and private (terms I use here reservedly for the lack of better ones) is embodied.
It is social. I believe that an overly stringent demarcation of the public and private
is premature and fundamentally flawed. The boundaries of the public and private,
I will argue, are perforated and overlap. A “public” in health is often defined as
anything that is “population based.” Kenneth Burke, a renowned linguist, once said
there is always a “not” to a word. “Not public” is often understood as the somatic,
social, and emotional experiences central to a person. These definitions of public
and private are not on the surface incorrect. These definitions unfortunately do not
go far and deep enough. This concept is expanded in this book as a narrative arc,
deconstructing private illness embedded in publics as a dance.
We can’t control systems or figure them out. But we can dance with them! Meadows (2004)
The discussion of public versus private health is framed with a dance lesson of
the “evolutionary” bachata, a partnered dance that originated in the Dominican
Republic.
How to learn the basic bachata with a partner facing the other, without getting
fancy (accent in fourth count)
Basically, it is “Step-together-step touch” with beats at:
Step 1—step 2—step 3 HIP (accent)
Step 5—step 6—Step 7 HIP (accent)
An earlier version of this chapter was presented at The Complex Systems Advanced Academic
Workshop (CSAAW) at the Second Michigan Complexity Mini-Conference, University of
Michigan- Center for the Study of Complex Systems (CSCS), on May 13, 2013.
© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015 23
M. Battle-Fisher, Application of Systems Thinking to Health Policy & Public
Health Ethics, SpringerBriefs in Public Health, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-12203-8_2
24 2 The Public, Private, and “Stepping on Toes” in Healthcare
As with any energetic bachata, two partners in close physical proximity enter
an agreement to “lead and follow” in order to perform the dance. Like taking a cue
from your lead partner to start movements, we also take cues from people around
us. Agents in a social system do not adhere to “global lock-and-trigger” conditions
in regulating their actions (Martinez-Garcia and Hernandez-Lemus 2013). To add,
complex systems acknowledge the existence of many causes and effects which is
radically different in approach to a “single cause causes a single effect” (Martinez-
Garcia and Hernandez-Lemus 2013).
While there is some comfort in expectation of predictability of the agents’ actions
in physical systems, there is no such relief with social agents. People can do what
they want and often do. Policies are there to guide, support, and regulate actions that
are acted out in everyday life. Human agents are endowed with the ability act upon
intention if the social order allows such freedom. In order to have intention, there
must be cognition. For the sake of this book, a social agent may be thought of as:
A natural or artificial entity with sufficient behavioral plasticity to persist in its medium by
responding to recurrent perturbation within that medium so as to maintain its organization.
(Goldspink 2000)
Partner dancing requires “real-time coordination between a human leader and fol-
lower,” and resembles other decentralized systems with “supervisory control and
coordination of agent teams” (Gentry and Feron 2004). Each partner is an agent
who must take physical and verbal cues to move together. More often than not, there
are glitches mingled among the passion to work together. The yearly homecoming
of mandatory influenza vaccinations is a good example of the difficulties in recon-
ciling and satisfying both private and public interests. One person gets the vaccina-
tion, perhaps under his own volition or social pressure (e.g., my boss tells me to
comply for the safety of patients). One person may be left out of the loop in learning
of the directive to get that mandatory flu shot (organizational lapse). Another may
decide to forego the advice to immunize and take the chance of illness and being
singled out as a result. In the end, the dancers in this public health situation become
a small public where each must abide by the rules of gestures of bachata (getting the
shot). Bachata is different from the waltz. There are rules in place to guide the an-
ticipated actions of abiding by the requirements to obtain the flu vaccination. When
that gesture is something like getting that flu shot before reporting to work, some
may decide to become wallflowers and ignore the requirement altogether.
In essence, there is a give-and-take among all dancers (social agents) toward
a collective end result. This is not unlike the give-and-take of navigating health
as a person that is a part of a public. How could this be? While living as a social
creature may lack the lyrical musicality of a bachata song, effective public health
action requires that the private sphere be under the watch of the public for the sake
of the society as a whole. However unlike the Bachata dance and song that has a
definite outro, the political intensity and prescriptive requirements surrounding a
policy typically hit a loop section. The song never ends.
One partner cannot do waltz steps while the other performs Dominican bachata.
In other words, an entity such as a government or even a bachata partner should not
demand to have a say in his status. But this would not make sense for dancing bach-
ata, which is by design a partner dance. Likewise, when we evoke the idea of public
The Will of the Public 25
health, the idea of intervention into the private sphere is central to improving the
health of the larger public. Some of our private has to give for the sake of the public.
People tend to gravitate homophilously both politically and culturally (see
Aristotle 1991; see Kilduff and Tsai 2003). Michael Warner (2002) wrote a piece
in Public Culture which later became a book of the same name, Publics and
Counterpublics. The public is “everyone within a field of study” (Warner 2002).
The public is the study population. Warner (2002) presented the argument that be-
ing a member of a public requires that each citizen participate at some level. Not
being fully activated in deliberation may not be feasible. Some may not be activated
to participate at all. Sometimes a citizen does not act as the hand is forced. Ethical
issues are off of the radar and lack saliency, until the acute issue strikes them in the
face or knocks them off of their feet (Nordgren and Morris McDonnell 2011).
Gigerenzer (2010) said that social pressure to comply with the peer network
is based on intuition. The legal scholar Cass Sunstein (2005) asserted that moral
heuristics are also susceptible to error. As morals and ethics are inherent to policy-
making, the ill effects of such heuristics can bleed into ill-advised policy decisions
(Sunstein 2005). A heuristic by nature is an artifact based on socially accepted fact
(Sunstein 2005). A heuristic is not unlike pulling off that decisional Band-Aid as
quickly and painlessly as possible so you can hop back on your bike. Likewise,
making strategic and ethical choices does not cleanly translate to an assurance of so-
cially or medically appropriate actions by the public under the stricture of the policy
(see Adler 2005). Choice is a test of feedback based in part on ethical fallibility in
following socially agreed upon ethical rules.
Aristotle (1991) tendered a guide on how to live with other flawed people in a
reflective, public space. In his work, On Rhetoric, Aristotle (1991) said what is un-
avoidable is to be a part of a larger public which is composed of people with moral
blemishes. In Book 1, Aristotle gives character a new name, ethos. This ethos is
born of a sense of justice. But Aristotle made it clear that ethos cannot be mandated
by law. Hannah Arendt (1958), in The Human Condition, said that people lapse
into a social world. Because humans are so intertwined, the public realm is infinite
so should be our concern for others. Our identity becomes one of the collective
(Arendt 1958).
Van Kleef et al. (2010) were interested in this very question in mortals by saying
that emotions should be treated as bits of information that must be understood. In
their empirical findings, during a situation that requires competition, people draw
off of trying to analytical weigh the emotions of the opponent (Van Kleef et al.
2010). In those situations where we are “in this together,” emotions rules by getting
into someone’s head (Van Kleef et al. 2010). For health policy, there may be longer
peace between the social and related ethical upheavals but policy revisits at some
future point to restore order (see Martinez-Garcia and Hernandez-Lemus 2013).
The very basis of public health rests on overlapping influences and relationships
26 2 The Public, Private, and “Stepping on Toes” in Healthcare
Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign. (Mill 1999)
The will of society, with our funny little orb of health hovering and bobbing within
it, aligns religiously with the will of the majority. Mill (1999) wrote On Liberty
in 1895 as a treatise on the overlay of personal responsibility and an authoritative
state. He advocated a balance of Pareto efficiency as good for the majority, which
is fundamental to public health) and personal autonomy (with the translation you
cannot make me do it for my own good). For the sake of this argument, Mill also
defends the existence of protection against prevailing feelings and opinions (Mill
1999). People, according to Mill (1999), base decisions on “personal preference.”
If health invokes the power to infringe on the personal liberty of an individual,
Mill (1999) said that the public only have that right when the burden of proof sug-
gests that “preventing harm to others” is the only justification. Mill also defends
the existence of protection against prevailing feelings and opinions (Mill 1999).
The explanations that we view as valid or potentially valid are at the mercy of the
“denial of usefulness” (Mill 1999).
The need for an intellectual irritant is often necessary to spur innovative discus-
sion. Mill (1999) wrote that “men are not more zealous for truth than they often are
for error.” Human nature requires adjustments to our reasoning out of realized and
accepted necessity. Individuals do not expend unnecessary energy when they are
comfortable with the status quo. Mill (1999) explains our propensity toward remedy
as being tied to two factors: the direction of the sentiment (as in complexity versus
convention) and the degree of interest in that sentiment. Otherwise, we are indiffer-
ent or opposed to seeking out alternatives.
What is made quite evident is the warring of the ideals of maintaining personal
liberty with the maximization of social utility. What is the acceptable tipping point
before we topple too far to the side of autonomy while undermining social welfare?
Dworkin (1972) in response to Mill wrote that paternalism “will always involve
limitations on the liberty of some individuals in their own interest but it may also
extend to interferences with the liberty of parties whose interests are not in ques-
tion.” Mill sets an unreasonably high threshold for achieving paternalism. This cer-
tainly is not unusual with such sweeping pronouncements.
In light of the impossible achievability of Mill’s requirements, Dworkin (1972)
said that what is at work in reality is impure paternalism. As impure paternal-
ism is followed, a disenfranchised class’ needs are met by way of subjugating the
References 27
References
Adler M (2005) Cognitivism, controversy and moral heuristics (open peer commentary to
Sunstein). Behav Brain Sci 28:524–542
Arendt H. (1958) The human condition. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Aristotle (1991). On rhetoric. A theory of civic discourse. Translated by Kennedy G. Oxford
University Press, New York
DuBois, WEB (1965) The souls of black folk. In: Franklin JH (ed) Three negro classics. Avon,
New York
Dworkin G (1972) Paternalism. Monist 56(1):64–84
Gentry S, Feron E (2004). Musicality experiments in lead and follow dance. In: Systems, man and
cybernetics, 2004 IEEE international conference 1:984–988
Gigerenzer G (2010) Moral satisficing: rethinking moral behavior as bounded rationality. Top
Cogn Sci 2:528–54
Goldspink C (2000) Modelling social systems as complex: towards a social simulation meta-
model. J Artif Soc Simul 3(2). http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/3/2/1.html. Accessed 1 Feb 2014
Gregson J, Foerster S, Orr R, Jones L, Benedict J, Clark B et al (2001) System, environmen-
tal, and policy changes: using the social-ecological model as a framework for evaluating
nutrition education and social marketing programs with low-income audiences. J Nutr Educ
33(Suppl 1):S4–15. doi:10.1016/S1499-4046(06)60065-1
Griswold KS, Lesko SE, Westfall JM, Folsom Group (2013) Communities of solution: partnerships
for population health. J Am Board Fam Med 26(3):232–238. doi:10.3122/jabfm.2013.03.130
Kilduff M, Tsai W (2003) Social networks and organizations. Sage, Los Angeles
Martinez-Garcia M, Hernandez-Lemus E (2013) Health systems as complex systems. Am J Oper
Res 3:113–26
Meadows D (2004) Dancing with systems. Donella Meadows Institute Archives. http://www.
donellameadows.org/archives/dancing-with-systems/. Accessed on 8 June 2014
Mill JS (1999) On liberty. Longman, Roberts and Green, London
Nordgren L, Morris McDonnell M-H (2011) The scope-severity paradox: why doing more harm is
judged to be less harmful. Soc Psychol Personal Sci 2(1):97–102
Rose G (1985) Sick individuals and sick populations. Int J Epidemiol 14:32–38
Sunstein C (2005) Moral heuristics. Behav Brain Sci 28:531–573
Van Kleef G, De Dreu D, Manstead A (2010). An interpersonal approach to emotion in social deci-
sion making: the emotions as social information. Adv Exp Soc Psychol 42:45–96
Warner M (2002) Publics and counterpublics. Public Cult 14(1):49–90
Chapter 3
The Menagerie of Social Agents: People
and Their Connections
Tom would eventually renege on this assurance from scene VII. Tom leaves Lau-
ra…and Amanda. Then there are two, Amanda and Laura, left in that dank rundown
apartment with a broken glass unicorn. Each member of the family, as members
of this cloistered network, brings his or her own ethics, actions, and perceptions
that when taken together adversely affect the family dynamic. Closed systems in
that sense are stifling. Looking at social engagement with the strictness of network
formation alone is also stifling as well.
Egocentric is great in terms of drilling down to the structural narrative of one person
and those connections. With the complete network, the intimacy is lost by broaden-
ing the conceptual lens by analyzing the network as a whole. Newman (2003) notes
the futility of graphically representing overly large populations because the graph
will never sufficiently represent every node that could be in it. This is often a rare
opportunity, for this works not unlike a census.
Strogatz (2001) acknowledges that the structure and function of a system cannot
be divorced. According to Newman (2003), there are three central tenets to ap-
proaching social networks:
1. Uncover the measurement and nature of networks statistically
2. Create models to understand these inherent relationships
3. “Prediction” of an outcome variable, based on the discrete mathematical rules of
social network analysis (Newman 2003)
The key assumptions of social network theory are:
1. The aggregate influence of the group is more important.
2. The analysis is at the level of the network.
3. Patterns of relationship exist across the whole network.
4. Social networks are linked relationships (Kadushin 2012).
Borgatti and Halgin (2011) made a necessary peculiarity of network theory and/or
the “antecedents of network properties” (see Borgatti and Halgin 2011). This trans-
formation of composition can be viewed as a reorganization or emergence of a com-
plex network, in the sense that this form of complexity is inherently on a dynamic
continuum with continuous reorganization of the nodes (Halley and Winkler 2008).
Networks have much more than a common interest in keeping nodes (people) to-
gether. Before employing social networks to an issue, whether the systems thinking
paradigm, more specifically, social network applies must be questioned. Based on
Borgatti et al.’s (2009) four categories of network arguments (2009) if any of these
queries apply in the development of a policy, the social network perspective should
be investigated further (Table 3.1).
For guidance, Borgatti et al. (2009) offered four categories for network argu-
ments:
1. Transmission
2. Adaptation
3. Binding
4. Exclusion
Being connected takes work but working to stay connected may be harder when the
person is on the social fringes. Social capital, or philo, as defined by Krackhardt
(1992) requires three attributes: time, affection, and interaction. The strength of a tie
is measured by a “combination of the amount of time, the emotional intensity, the
intimacy, and the reciprocal services that characterize the tie” (Granovetter 1973).
With the “navigability of strong ties” proposed by White and Houseman (2002),
the nature of strengthened engagement fortifies within a network trust among its
Social Network Theory and Analysis 33
Table 3.1 Application of the categories of network arguments to health policy development
Category of network argument Policy questions to pose
Transmission Do social elements targeted by the policy involve flow of
information among people?
Are there certain people in a network with the advantage of
accessing social resources? Are some people disadvantaged
in accessing social resources?
Must the policy account for social structural changes that
create different circumstances?
Adaptation Is the basis of the health concern the issue of people mak-
ing the same choices due to similar network positions?
Is a person’s position in a system possibly tied in part to
similar life chances and circumstances?
Binding Do people act as one, sharing actions and outcomes?
Is the influence to act collectively possibly linked to struc-
tural issues?
Exclusion Does the policy seek to influence overcoming breakdowns
and exclusionary situations that hamper a person’s access
to social relations and health based resources?
Do social structures change under certain social and/or
poilitical circumstances? (category of transmission)
Is the policy involved in the altering of choices when the
actors are exposed to similar social constraints?
members (White and Houseman 2002). Carpenter et al. (2003) found in a simulation
model of health political networks that increased burden of involvement in the af-
fairs of the networks increased reliance on strong ties. In addition, strong ties must
be cultivated to maintain such networks, with five times the maintenance effort over
weak ties (Carpenter et al. 2003). Borgatti and Halgin (2011) present the distinction
of a state tie from event tie. State ties have “open-ended persistence” and get at the
idea of social connection. On the other hand, event ties can be bean counted. Tom
and Jim, the paramour thus christened by Tom, had a flow relationship in which
Jim had as the role-based state-tie relationships of coworkers and minor friends.
Borgatti and Halgin (2011) define this flow as in terms of exchange. How in the
world do the fictitious Wingfields offer lessons in systemic engagement? The ties in
a network are rather enduring. According to Borgatti and Halgin (2011), such a per-
sistent tie is known as a state-tie. As with the nature of the ties that will be described
in this book, a state-tie “flows” in a manner that can following some rules of en-
gagement. According to Borgatti and Halgin (2011), the three tie characteristics are:
1. Tie strength,
2. Intensity, and
3. Time duration.
People who do better are somehow better connected and leverage those connec-
tions as optimally as possible. Holding a better position in the structure of these
exchanges can be an asset in its own right. This asset is social capital (Burt 2005).
34 3 The Menagerie of Social Agents: People and Their Connections
and survival (Mizuno et al. 2003). For homeless teens, they could build survival
networks. In such a network, the refuted model of the risky person is not resurrect-
ed. The once predominate risky person model placed culpability for risky behaviors
on character traits and failings of the homeless individuals that were brought with
them into the homeless context (Aidala et al. 2005). Risk is instead found to be tied
to the context of risk based on homelessness of which the teens navigate together
(Aidala et al 2005). Network analysis can examine more widely the macroeffects of
housing on a complete network, one that gives an overview of the whole structure
rather than concentrating on the structural experience of one node in the network.
This actuality of a survival network is based on the existence of a risky shared space
of homelessness egocentrically.
Survival networks most likely would not have occurred with their current con-
tent or in its present configurations without the factor of homelessness that brought
the nodes together. Friends made on the street may not have shared homerooms or
civic activities before with the newly homeless teen. Lack of secure housing dimin-
ishes social capital often taken for granted by those who are stably housed. The lack
of a roof over the teen’s head does not open a sea of opportunity but rather lowers
a glass box over the survival networks that become further removed from society.
Sometimes those in health policy may wish to merely bean count the uniplex and
multiplex roles in question (Barnes 1972). But those designations may not fully
serve the dynamic requirements of developing health policy. An understanding of
the underlying structural relationships and the social environments in which people
are embedded should be a part of the policymaking process. For others, the roles
become muddled with roles that support health and others that result from non-
medical reasons. Barnes (1972) defined multiplexity in terms of a “multiplexity of
interests” that bond the two nodes together. The tie that is formed in such instances,
called a multiplex tie, tends to be very strong and enduring. According to Kilduff
and Tsai (2003), this is easier said than done for a person who serves many pivotal
roles to say goodbye to those relational responsibilities. Notions of roles and al-
legiance to the patient versus own taking care of one’s own life breeds complexity
at every turn.
The context of the social network matters. The focus theory approach, as pre-
sented by Feld (1981), frames social context in terms of “a group’s activities are
organized by a particular focus…and two individuals that share the same focus are
most likely to share joint activities.” To bring social context into focus for home-
lessness, the context becomes a pairing of identity (as in homophily) and social
engagement based on that shared focus. Sharing a recognized characteristic de-
notes homophily (Kadushin 2012). But the overwhelming evidence of the gravity
of homelessness on health outcomes would call for a broadening to the connection
of elements of bond formation. When the teens come together within a network, an
acknowledgement of association is presumed. Homophily does not scratch the sur-
face on issues of social context. Homophily is not concerned with the “opportunity
to meet” or ties emerging from shared context (Feld 1981).
The risk, as supported by recent network analysis of homeless teens’ HIV risk
then is based on position within a network and not solely risk based on personal
36 3 The Menagerie of Social Agents: People and Their Connections
failings (Rice et al 2012). A place where a person lands in a network may not be
same as the role that person pays in a network. In addition to highlighting the im-
plications of position in a network, the teen also must comply and conform. The
Solomon Asch conformity experiments from the 1950s investigated the propen-
sity “minority of one [to conform] versus [the influence of] a unanimous majority”
(Asch 1956). There has been general agreement since Asch (1956) that a single in-
dividual is apt to conform even when the decision runs contrary to established fact.
The will of the majority (public) may possibly lead to the denial of private judgment
held to the contrary (Asch 1956). This denial for the sake of fitting into the survival
network is conformity. Information is only so if it is novel to the network (Rapo-
port 1953). Rapoport (1953) found in experimental studies that an inner circle of
“knowers” may slow innovation. That inner circle may be stalwart in their beliefs
(risky behavior). So in the end, there is a naturalization path for outsiders to come
in the core. In terms of randomness of distribution, new teens from the periphery
and old, stalwart core teens intermingle. But once the outsiders are there, they may
take on the difficult task of being an innovator or disappearing into the scenery and
conform. The quandary here is that the policy wants to work against the propensity
to conform to norms putting the homeless teens at risk for HIV if transitioning into
the core.
Taking into account the unique risky context of homelessness, survival networks
can be viewed in the following ways:
1. Networks with a socially restricting glass box that restricts the possibilities of
fully realized social integration
2. Propinquity that may affect the state-tie composition of nodes that are accessible
and acted upon by a particular teen (whether under own agency or under pressure
to conform)
3. Bond forming that may intensify due interdependence linked to the social con-
text (such as homelessness)
4. Bond forming based on common foci that may entrench relationships and
increased risk of social conformity
In social networks, there may be a significant difference in the core or the periphery
partitions of a social network. According to Borgatti and Everett (1999), there are
three intuitive notions of the core to the periphery dichotomy:
1. A group that is built of nodes that are incident to different number of ties (highly
integrated or largely distant and isolated)
2. Two groupings of nodes that form one larger group, one as core and one as
periphery, where the “the character of ties within the periphery as well as within
the core [are specified]”
3. “Cloud of points in Euclidean space” where the big ball of spaghetti in the center
of the network are the core
Nodes in the periphery by definition are sparsely interconnected among themselves
while the core forms a clique (Borgatti and Everett 1999; Persitz 2010). The core is
right at the “center to the action” (Borgatti and Everett 1999).
Risk and Network Analysis: The Case of HIV + Risk and Homelessness 37
As a result of Rice et al.’s (2012) study of HIV risk behavior, homeless adoles-
cents were located within the core, were more likely to be female and were more
likely to have been homeless for at least 2 years. The longer the teen, particularly for
the young woman, is outside of the family unit, the more teens form strong, compact
ties with a new definition of family. Surprisingly, being on the periphery of the tight
core of homeless teens may be protective against HIV risk taking. Teens on the pe-
riphery also reported being homeless for shorter periods and are more likely to have
maintained prosocial connections to home (Rice et al 2012). The solitary existence
of the ill-defined netherworld between the former “home” and the tight clique of
homeless teens may become unbearable for the peripheral teen to maintain. The
homeless teen who is outside of the support of other teens and cannot go to a stable
housing environment may in the end succumb to the human need for safety and so-
cial connection on the streets. A focus is a “social, psychological, legal, or physical
entity around which joint activities are organized” (Feld 1981). According to Feld
(1981), a focus serves as a social glue, keeping nodes engaged with each other as
long as commonalities are fostered. Once the identity of being homeless becomes
the relationship-based focus, the shared identity as well as engaging in purposeful
interaction can lead to more time spent together (Feld 1981).
Highly connected, dense cores in networks are conducive due to their central
location, galvanizing and passing information within that group due to the short
path to get from one node to another (Borgatti 2005; Persitz 2010). However, a
dense group may be more difficult to infiltrate, diminishing informational flow
and hampering positive bond formations. Preliminary evidence has shown that it
is not enough to be connected to a person that engages in risky behaviors. Being
a member of the core group where social learning may be more likely increased
the risk of the hazard of homeless teens engaging in risky HIV behaviors (Rice
et al 2012). This result is in stark contrast to previous research that has found
that deep social integration is often positive among teens (see Allen et al. 2005;
Valente et al. 2003).
When evaluating health economics, Shiell et al. (2008) noted along with uncov-
ering change in the overall social systems, the movement of the elements of the
systems must be understood as well. They are least invested so how invested would
that expert be in using its scare resource of political clout to bring harmony to the
support? According to “structural holes,” the node is brokering a relationship with
someone that person does not already have a relationship, across a social gap or
hole. Burt (2004) trumpeted the idea of “vision advantage,” where the two discon-
nected networks that are spanned across a hole can help to bring in new ideas to the
other. Long et al. (2013) contend that such vision advantage can lead to overdeple-
tion of resources and a resulting loss of acuity that was desired in the first place.
However, node and tie failures are not ideal. If a node is removed from the net-
work, it is called a vertex cut. In an analysis of peer-reviewed systems literature
conducted by Long et al. (2013), this brokerage as a bridge between groups that
were not previously connected is central to understanding whether “good ideas”
as resources are being diffused. According to Long et al. (2013), the take-home
38 3 The Menagerie of Social Agents: People and Their Connections
messages are worth a long gander to frame approaching that next framing of home-
less policy. Long et al.’s (2013) findings were:
1. The more comprising the network, the more efficiently information gets around
among its membership.
2. Boundaries spanning a “hole” between the core and the periphery by and bring-
ing in new people that has not been a part of the in-crowd (core) may not be
the most reliable method of getting good ideas and positive support for positive
sexual choices.
3. Teens, as brokers with their increased yoke of responsibility may just burn out
and leave, creating a cut vertex.
Granovetter (1973) defines a bridge as a person in a position of linking people who
would not have otherwise been connected. Granovetter (1973) found that, in gen-
eral, it was the existence of weak ties in networks that had the more positive influ-
ence on behavior change as there was no competition for scarce resources. It is not
assumed that every tie in a network would be designated as weak. Strong ties link
friends who make more of an investment into maintaining the relationship which
may also result in a more lasting relationship (see Krackhardt 1992).
If the public policy being developed pertains directly to HIV prevention, perhaps
targeting the core network to diminish risk perhaps could be a first step. Next, nor-
malizing the teen to a stable housing environment may reduce the risk of becoming
more deeply embedded in social networks that support high-risk behavior. But in
the work of being connected to other people, the low-risk teens may help each other
or could transfer into the high-risk group over time. But policymakers must remain
attentive to the systemic changes can flow from targeting any component of the
network. People come and go into each other’s lives. Policy must be mindful that
the longer the teen is outside of a traditional household, the more human connec-
tions will be made with the people that they have the most contact with. Could the
teens in periphery have formed cliques that supported less risk taking or conversely
supported more risk taking? The teens are tied together by something stronger: love,
support, concordance in values, and shared protective as well as risky behaviors
(see Feld and Carter 1998, Kadushin 2012). In other words, people live by forming
bonds wherever they land. When teens land without a consistent source of shelter,
teens huddle for physical and emotional warmth. Once a teen chooses to expend en-
ergy to deepen relationships, this act takes time and resources from already deleted
stock of navigating instability. It is easier to choose a new focus that is tied in some
way to the foci they already share (Feld 1981).
If the policy lumps the core and periphery together, network membership chang-
es over time which could influence the ability of the policy to have the desired ef-
fect. Teens that tie together two completely separate networks are called bridges. By
theory, the separate networks would not have connected if not for this new bridge. A
teen could theoretically build enough prestige and power to convince two divergent
groups of homeless teens to join forces (Granovetter 1973). A necessary element to
move from the act of convincing into action is conformity. McCulloh (2013) noted
Risk and Network Analysis: The Case of HIV + Risk and Homelessness 39
that there was a noticeable lack of research that sought to uncover the influence of
social network position on conformity. According to McCulloh’s (2013) replication
of Asch-type conformity tests on two groups of military personnel, actors in the
core were less likely to conform and were also more apt to deviate from the social
norms without fear of loss of status. The military subjects who were least connected
and in the periphery were more likely to conform (McCulloh 2013).
Being on the outside (periphery) of the homeless core appears to protect against
HIV risk-taking (Rice et al 2012). The peripherals may be at risk in other ways that
may lead to a greater risk of HIV risk taking once the teen is in the core. But there
is also a possibility that the teen will become enveloped and become high risk him-
self. But the possibility illuminated by social network analysis is significant enough
to take notice of elements of social embeddedness and social compliance among
homeless teens. However, it may be too much to ask of that teen to work to overhaul
the collectively held value of higher-risk sexual practices (Long et al 2013). That is
where social agencies and interventions must play a sizable role.
In light of the conformity research, the following possible systemic factors may
be considered when exploring the structural context of homeless teens’ survival
networks:
• Every homeless teen is not the same and each with present different social or-
ders.
• Being deeply connected in the homeless culture (core) may be attributable to
increased risk for unsafe sexual behaviors.
• Flip the switch on foci among teens that reinforce risky sexual behaviors to foci
that are more supportive of positive health choices.
• Targeting low-risk teens on the periphery should account for the higher likeli-
hood to conform to the core values for acceptance.
• While there may be opportunities to use low-risk teens as “bridges” to the high-
risk teens, this should only be done with extreme care and oversight. The bridge
is more susceptible to falling into the activities of the core and may suffer from
burn-out for the heightened sense that change is on that teen’s shoulders.
• Watch the movement of teens from the core to periphery (and back again). This
movement brings a whole new set of structural realities both for the teen as well
as the core and peripheral networks.
• Assess the social purgatory effect on peripheral teens. Target prosocial connec-
tions of the periphery which may support a return to a stable living environment.
• Teens in the core, due to their influential status, may be more willing and able to
deviate from the prevailing social norms without losing clout with the others.
Social networks are powerful and are often underutilized in uncovering the underly-
ing structure of health policies. The policy work must be held to high standards due
to its position in at the forefront of combating ecological gaps and failures. Some-
times the lesson radiates from the personal and societal failing of one HIV-positive
homeless teen.
40 3 The Menagerie of Social Agents: People and Their Connections
References
Aidala A, Cross JE, Stall R, Harre D, Sumartojo E (2005) Housing status and HIV risk behaviors:
implications for prevention and policy. AIDS Behav 9(3):251–265
Allen JP, Porter MR, McFarland FC, Marsh P, McElhaney KB (2005) The two faces of adolescentsʼ
success with peers: adolescent popularity, social adaptation, and deviant behavior. Child Dev
76(3):747–760
Asch S (1956) Studies of independence and conformity. A minority of one against a unanimous
majority. Psychol Monogr 70(9):1–70
Barnes JA (1972) Social networks. Addison-Wesley Modul Anthropol 26:1–29.
Borgatti S (2005) Facilitating knowledge flows. http://www.socialnetworkanalysis.com/knowl-
edge_sharing.htm. Accessed 8 June 2014
Borgatti S, Everett M (1999) Models of core/periphery structures. Soc Netw 21:375–395
Borgatti S, Halgin D (2011) On network theory. Organ Sci 22(5):1168–1181
Borgatti S, Mehra A, Brass D, Labianca G (2009) Network analysis in the social sciences. Science
323(5916):892–895
Burt R (2004) Structural holes and good ideas. Am J Sociol 110:349–399
Burt R (2005) Brokerage and closure: an introduction to social capital. Clarenden lectures in man-
agement studies. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Carpenter D, Esterling K, Lazer D (2003) The strength of strong ties—a model of contact making
in policy networks with evidence from U.S. health politics. Ration Soc 15(4):411–440
Cooper A-J (1988) A voice from the South. Oxford University Press, New York
Denning P, DiNenno E (2010) Communities in crisis: is there a generalized HIV epidemic in im-
poverished urban areas of the United States? Centers for disease control. Presented at: XVIII
international AIDS conference, Vienna
Feld S (1981) The focused organization of social ties. Am J Sociol 86(5):1015–1035
Feld S, Carter W (1998) Foci of activities as changing contexts for friendship. In: Adams R, Allan
G (eds) Placing friendship in context. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Fingerman K, Birditt K (2003) Do age differences in close and problematic family ties reflect the
pool of available relatives? J Gerontol B Psychol Sci Soc Sci 58(2):80–87
Granovetter M (1973) The strength of weak ties. Am J Psychol 78(9):1360–1380
Green H, Tucker J, Golinelli D, Wenzel S (2013) Social networks, time homeless, and social sup-
port: a study of men on Skid Row. Netw Sci 1(3):305–320
Halley J, Winkler D (2008) Classification of emergence and its relationship to self-organization.
Complexity 13:10–15
Hanneman R, Riddle M (2005). Introduction to Social Network Methods. http://faculty.ucr.
edu/~hanneman/nettext/. Accessed 20 June 2014
Hawe P, Webster C, Shiell A (2004) A glossary of terms for navigating the field of social network
analysis. J Epidemiol Community Health 58:971–975
Kadushin C (2012) Understanding social networks. Oxford, New York
Kidder D, Kidder DP, Wolitski RJ, Campsmith ML, Nakamura GV (2007) Health status, health
care use, medication use, and medication adherence among homeless and housed people living
with HIV/AIDS. Am J Public Health 97(12):2238–2245
Kilduff M, Tsai W (2003) Social network and organizations. Sage, Los Angeles
Krackhardt D (1992) The strength of strong ties: the importance of philos in organizations. In:
Nohria N, Eccles R (eds) Networks and organization. Harvard Business School Press, Boston
Laumann EO, Marsden PV, Prensky D (1983) The boundary specification problem in network
analysis. In: Burt S, Minor MJ (eds) Applied network analysis: a methodological introduction.
Sage, Los Angeles
Long J, Cunningham F, Braithwaite J (2013). Bridges, brokers and boundary spanners in collab-
orative networks: a systematic review. BMC Health Serv Res 13:158
McCulloh I (2013) Social conformity in. Netw Conn 33(1):35–42
Meadows D (2008) Thinking in systems: a primer. Chelsea Green, River Junction
References 41
Milloy M, Brandon M, Montaner J, Wood E (2012) Housing status and the health of people living
with HIV/AIDS. Curr HIV/AIDS Rep 9(4):364–374
Mizuno Y, Purcell D, Borkowski T, Knight K, the SUDIS Team (2003) The life priorities of HIV-
seropositive injection drug users: findings from a community-based sample. AIDS Behav
7:395–403
Newman N (2003) The structure and function of complex networks. SIAM Rev 45:167–256
Paranyuskin D (2010) The inclusive exclusivity of the “Dynamique d’Enfer”. http://deemeetree.
com/current/inclusive-exclusivity/. Accessed 19 Dec 2013
Persitz D (2010) Power and Core-Periphery Networks. SSRN. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.
cfm?abstract_id=1579634. Accessed on April 9:2014
Rapport A (1953) A marginalized network highlights both the mathematical finiteness as well as
socio-political constriction on life chances. Bull Math Biophys 15:523–533
Rice E, Barman-Adhikari A, Milburn N, Monro W (2012) Position-specific HIV risk in a large
network of homeless youths. Am J Publ Health 102(1):141–147
Shiell A, Hawe P, Gold L (2008) Complex interventions or complex systems? Implications for
health economic evaluation. BMJ 336:1281. doi:http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/bmj.39569.510521.
AD
Strogatz S (2001) Exploring complex networks. Nature. http://www.nature.com/nature/journal/
v410/n6825/pdf/410268a0.pdf. Accessed 15 March 2014
Trotter R (1999) Friends, relatives and relevant others: conducting ethnographic network studies.
in. In: Schensul J, LeCompte M, Trotter R, Cromley E, Singer M (eds) Mapping social net-
works, spatial data and hidden populations. AltaMira, Lanham
Umberson D, Croscoe R, Reczek C (2010) Social relationships and health behaviors over the life
course. Annu Rev Sociol 36:139–157
Valente TW, Hoffman BR, Ritt-Olson A, Lichtman K, Johnson CA (2003) Effects of a social-
network method for group assignment strategies on peer-led tobacco prevention programs in
schools. Am J Public Health 93(11):1837
Wasserman S, Faust K (1994) Social Network Analysis: Methods and Applications. Cambridge
University Press, New York
White D, Houseman M (2002) The navigability of strong ties: small worlds, tie strength, and net-
work topology. Complexity 8(1):72–81
Chapter 4
Communication and Politics in Healthcare
Goel et al. (2010) described attitude homophily, that is analogous to being in at-
titude agreement. There is often a misconception afoot within clusters of allies
among that all are in agreement on an issue based solely on allegiance (Goel et al.
2010). A false consensus occurs when an overestimated leap is made regarding the
nature of a person’s private political stance made in the absence of information to
the contrary (Krueger and Clement 1994). For instance, misguided assumptions
of allegiance can occur where inference is made that all moderates of a particular
political party would affirm the same spirit of positions to the same degree and in
every case. Holding a dissenting position (or attitude) may not materialize into a
dissenting vote that counters the party’s positions (see Goel et al. 2010).
Policymakers take cues from social and political energies that are often under-
stood as the successes and failures realized from the vantage afforded as the agent
of governance. But this may offer an incomplete or even incorrect explanation of
how policy works once the policy regulation is released into the public. Colander
and Kupers (2014) in their formative work call for the use of complexity theory
to elevate market economics to public economics. The liberal top-down blanket of
governmental control and the conservative explanation of free markets are devoid of
any appropriate responses to the fact that government is but one of “endogeneously
evolved control mechanism” (Colander and Kupers 2014). Any sophistication that
recognizes that top/down mechanisms and markets are s ymbiotic is lost within the
puffin fight (Colander and Kupers 2014). Strict adherence of political h omophily
at all costs breeds an environment where attribution errors and snuffing of novel
The Flow of Ideas within Networks: Focus on Interprofessional Communication 45
information into the system can harm the public policy. The chasm between political
networks is more than ideological. The fissure between puffins due to homophily
ignores complexity in public policy to its grave detriment.
Granovetter (1978) presented the idea the threshold model of collective behavior.
In accordance to this threshold model, binary decisions such as pro tobacco control
and con tobacco control is based on a threshold of others’ participation in the delib-
eration. Accounting for the element of direct communication, Valente (1996) also
added to the network lexicon network thresholds, which are measured in terms of
exposure to direct communication ties but not as a threshold measured for the whole
social system. This threshold shows the point where a node is more convinced to
adopt an idea. This would be important to know if a person may be ethically mal-
leable meaning that ethical stances are influenced by others and are not resistant to
change (Battle-Fisher 2010). Valente (1996) found that opinion leaders have lower
network thresholds; they need the least convincing to innovate. However, these
opinion leaders must find a way to influence a more resistant node in the network.
These people would be those later adopters that are hard to reach and crack. But of-
ten in health, we do not have enough buy-in of the public. If that public is bounded
by smaller, more approachable networks, we have a chance. If that influential net-
work bridges to other networks to diffuse an ethic, then we have lift-off. Now how
that ethic is being diffused is another story.
We have a natural tendency to romanticize breakthrough innovations, imagining momen-
tous ideas transcending their surroundings … But ideas are works of bricolage … We take
the ideas we’ve inherited or that we’ve stumbled across, and we jigger them together into
some new shape. (Johnson 2010)
The importance lies in the layering of the overarching political landscape to the
connectivity within these networks. Individuals will be most influenced by their
in-group when saying yea or nay to an idea (Mackie 1986). Inherent to the ability
to influence must be an inclusion of the factor how the information (idea) actually
flows within a network. Simply, word of mouth communication involves the flow
of information between an information sharer and a receiver. To this requirement
of word of mouth, Frenzen and Nakamoto (1993) noted two elements of the theory
of information flow: the decision and the structure. Frenzen and Nakamoto (1993)
noted that both tie strength and opportunity cost demonstrated as pro-idea versus
con-idea would affect information sharing. Fundamentally, during word of mouth,
words could be heard but if the determination of worth lay squarely with the receiver.
In illustration, of all the possible ties in the Department of Health and Human
Services (DHHS) agencies involved in tobacco control, Leischow et al. (2010)
found that only 16f % were used. Size of the network is a cumulative count of the
number of nodes in the network graph. But the most central bears the burden of
over-reliance on a few agencies to conduct enough communication of behalf of the
leadership network at large to not compromise DHHS’ work in tobacco control.
This is also true for the structural integrity of networks. These connections need to
be physically as well as emotionally accessible. In the figure, a tie is shown if two
agencies communicated at least once quarterly. High centrality, which is a high-
level power and reliance in the hand of a node, is a heightened factor in network
failure. This translates to power concentrated in the hands of very connected nodes
and places the health of the network on the backs of those nodes.
The systemic tale from the DHHS research is in the protection of the integrity
of the network. For the sake of governance, all the agencies by principle were to be
involved in varying degrees in regulating tobacco. In terms of network connectivity,
according to Miller and Page (2007), the “deep” quality of the complexity would
mean that the parts of a sum of the networks will have structural repercussions on
the health of the entire system (the sum). However, actor and tie failures are the
main culprits to its overall stability. A breakdown in a major throughfare for infor-
mation or the loss of a pivotal agency’s involvement could spell trouble. If the agen-
cies that are overly relied upon, fail to continue to act as a catalyst maintaining the
system, the systemic effects could be immense. This is particularly true if fail-safes
have not been put in place by policy to fill these gaps or create equivalent detours to
assure the network works (Figs. 4.1 and 4.2).
Using The United States’ The Family Smoking and Prevention Act (Public Law
111–31) as an example, systems inherent to anti-tobacco policy and how unexpect-
ed factors emerge once such a divisive policy is enacted. Passed during President
Political Expediency: Influencing Ideas 47
Fig. 4.1 Network of communication contacts among Department of Health and Human Services
tobacco control leadership (network tie indicates contact at least once a quarter). ACF Admin-
istration for Children and Families, AHRQ Agency for Healthcare Research and Quality, CDC
Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, CMS Centers for Medicare and Medicaid Services,
FDA Food and Drug Administration, HRSA Health Resources and Services Administration, IHS
Indian Health Service, NIH National Institutes of Health, OGC Office of the General Counsel, OS
Office of the Secretary, SAMHSA Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services Administration.
(Reprinted from Leischow et al. 2010, with permission from Taylor & Francis Ltd)
Fig. 4.2 Reported barriers to collaboration with other agencies in the DHSS network. (Reprinted
from Leischow et al. 2010, with permission from Taylor & Francis Ltd)
48 4 Communication and Politics in Healthcare
Barack Obama’s first administration, The Family Smoking and Prevention Act
(Public Law 111–31) as an addition to new Chapter IX to the Food, Drug, and
Cosmetic Act became the most sweeping regulatory support in combating a leading
cause of preventable death in the USA that have been scientifically linked to tobacco
use. The Family Smoking and Prevention Act did not take away access to tobacco to
consumers of age. Tobacco is sold legally, under the continued regulatory oversight
from the Federal Food and Drug Administration. Newly ‘strengthened’ regulatory
powers supplied by this act works to ensure the “safest” possible tobacco products
sold to US consumers using the most ethical forms of marketing to the public. Safe
is certainly used loosely here. The sale of tobacco as ethical is another question. But
tobacco is legal to use for those of age to use the product. What is allowed from
a regulatory standpoint by this Act is targeting sales, marketing and distribution
channels. Upon maximization, the virtuous goal is to optimize the desired benefit
of tobacco control policy, thereby saving lives and improving quality of life from
morbidity and mortality related to tobacco use.
“This legislation will not ban all tobacco products, and it will allow adults to make their
own choices … We know that even with the passage of this legislation, our work to protect
our children and improve the public’s health is not complete.”
—President Barack Obama during the signing of the Family Smoking Prevention and
Tobacco Control Act (2009)
Deliberate or orderly steps are not an accurate portrayal of how the policy process actually
works. Policy making is, instead, a complexly interactive process without beginning or end
(Lindblom and Woodhouse 1993).
President Obama’s statement illustrates the depth and limitations of the powers of
policy and portends systemic mess that could possibly ensure even under the most
noble of intention. From his statement, we can take away that the following issues
are central to the prescript of the law.
1. Increasing regulation of a legal product, in this case, tobacco.
2. Blocking tobacco advertisements from children within a specified distance of
schools and parks.
3. Making flavored tobacco distribution illegal. Menthol is excluded from this ban.
4. All harmful chemicals must be fully disclosed to the smoker along with graphic
fear appeals on the labeling.
5. Public Safety overrides autonomous actions of the consumer. Some elements of
the society, such as children, require higher ethical safeguards which require the
power of policy behind it.
Is an advertisement on the way home from the park that falls outside the banned
quadrant acceptable? By the letter of the policy, it is allowed. Is it ethical at the point
of exposure to the ad or to the mere possibility of exposure to the marketing?
Cigarette smokers have been found to have very high levels of brand loyalty (see
Dawes 2012). The smoker knows the brand, down to the flavor, even recalling the
specifications of the box that they want. At times, perhaps another perceived equiv-
alent cigarette will do just this once and buy a comparable brand if the requested one
References 49
is not available (Dawes 2012). For others, not having their brand is a game breaker.
Dawes (2012) in his analysis of US cigarette consumer panel data uncovered the
strong power of perception in cigarette branding.
1. A smoker that purchases high end cigarettes most likely will not lower the expec-
tation of the quality perception by buying a generic brand.
2. If there is a female aesthetic on the box, men will not bite at all even when the
call of nicotine gnaws. They will look for a cowboy or something testosterone
driven in marketing appearance.
3. Price point does matter.
If you want overwhelming consumer loyalty, market to a smoker. (Dawes 2012)
References
Battle-Fisher M (2010) Organ donation ethics: are donors autonomous within collective networks?
Online J Health Ethics 6(2). http://aquila.usm.edu/ojhe/vol6/iss2/6. Accessed 14 April 2014
Burt R (2004) Structural holes and good ideas. Am J Sociol 110:349–399
Colander D, Kupers R (2014) Complexity and the art of public policy-solving society’s problems
from the bottom-up. Princeton: Princeton University Press
Dawes J (2012). Cigarette brand loyalty and purchase patterns- an examination using U.S. con-
sumer panel data. Available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=21226951. Accessed on 14 April 2014
Feigenbaum M J (1983) Universal behavior in nonlinear systems. Physica 7:16–39
Feld S, Carter W (1998) Foci of activities as changing contexts for friendship. In: Adams R, Allan
G (eds) Placing friendship in context. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Frenzen J, Nakamoto K (1993). Structure, cooperation and the flow of market information. J Con-
sum Res 20:160–175
Goel S, Mason W, Watts D (2010) Real and perceived attitude agreement in social networks. J Pers
Soc Psychol 99(4):611–621
Granovetter M (1973). The strength of weak ties. Am J Psychol 78(9):1360–1380
Granovetter M (1978) Threshold models of collective behavior. Am J Sociol 83(6):1420–1443
Hemelrijk C (2013) Simulating complexity of animal social behaviour. In: Edmonds B, Meyer R
(eds) Simulating social complexity—a handbook. Springer, New York
Johnson S (2010) Where good ideas come from. Riverhead-Penguin, New York
Kadushin C (2012) Understanding social networks. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Krueger J, Clement RW (1994) The truly false consensus effect: an ineradicable and egocentric
bias in social perception. J Pers Soc Psychol 67(4):596–610
Lack D (1966) Population studies of birds. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Lazarsfeld P, Merton RK (1954) Friendship as a social process: a substantive and methodologi-
cal analysis. In: Berger M, Abel T, Page C (eds) Freedom and control in modern society. Van
Nostrand, New York
Leischow S, Luke D, Mueller N, Harris J, Ponder P et al (2010) Mapping U.S. government tobacco
control leadership: networked for success? Nicotine Tob Res 12(9):888–894
Lindblom C, Woodhouse E (1993) The Policy-Making Process. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs,
NJ
Mackie D (1986) Social identification effects in group polarization. J Pers Soc Psychol 50:720–728
Marsden PV (1988) Homogeneity in confiding relations. Soc Netw 10:57–76
Meadows D (2008) Thinking in systems: a primer. Chelsea Green, White River Junction
Miller J, Page S (2007) Complex adaptive systems: an introduction to computational models of
social life (Princeton Studies in Complexity). Princeton University Press, Princeton
50 4 Communication and Politics in Healthcare
Schön DA, Rein M (1994) Frame reflection. Basic Books, New York
Smith K, Christakis N (2008). Social networks and health. Annu Rev Sociol 34:405–429
Smith J, Halgin D, Kidwell V, Labianca G, Brass D, Borgatti SP (2014) Power in politically
charged networks. Soc Netw 36:162–176
Valente TW (1996) Social network thresholds in the diffusion of innovations. Soc Netw 18:69–89
Wasserman S, Faust K (1994) Social network analysis: methods and applications. Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, Cambridge
Chapter 5
Health Systems and Policymaking
as the “Price Is Right”
Game theory uses math and probabilities to predict future results. By definition,
game theory deals with the rules of strategy that are in some fashion dependent
on external influences in a competitive environment. An example of how people
grapple with social complexity could be the popular US game show, The Price is
Right. The error in the guess is not revealed in the Cliff Hanger game until after
the cardboard yodeler has moved up the mountain illustrating the deviation of the
guess from the correct answer. Factors present in the decisions made when playing
a game include:
1. The initial mechanism used by the contestant to come to the guess
2. Any dynamic alterations made to subsequent guesses
3. The distance away from the actual price (which is shown in the steps taken by the
figure)
4. The distance left from the goal
Berk et al. (1996) wrote a paper, testing whether rational decision theory exists in an
environment of substantial economic incentive. An important caveat is that the con-
testant in the game show must believe that there is a chance of beating the system.
As elemental to the games of chances, the contestant had incomplete knowledge to
make a successful rational choice (Berk et al. 1996). Imagine the dismay when the
contestant is surprised how far away they are from the correct guess. The contestant
would continue to bid.
Hodl-oh-ooh-dee
Hodl-ay-ee-dee-
Hodl–––––-ay–ee-dee-yi—ho.
The show is based on the fascination of the possibility of success, not its realization
of success. Policy is graded by securing success. But what is unique to The Price
is Right is that the contestant often calls upon the help of the screaming audience
for help in making future guesses in real time, particularly if he or she failed on a
previous attempt. In the end, there is a system to work through which may in this
case be futile.
Miller and Page (2007) explored the standing ovation problem that dealt with how
peer effect can modify behavior. In the Price is Right example, the standing ovation
model is concerned with the public displays of social compliance to a group. In this
case, the compliances can be demonstrated by standing up in applause or matching
verbal expression to match those displayed around them. According to this model,
agents are in pressure to make sure that our actions match others around them. But
there are choices:
• Some people in the audience are early birds and they stand and clap first.
• Others may choose to not stand or clap at all regardless of the social pressure
around them.
• Others may look around either through personal judgment of the performance or
through mimicking the behavior of others around them. In the end, each joins in
the ovation.
The standing ovation problem is about the power of peer effect.
The standing ovation problem presented by Miller and Page (2007) supported
the idea of peer effect strongly encouraging the act of applauding in public in accor-
dance to the actions of the group. Individuals have been found to more likely copy
an action if there is more pressure to comply with the peer effect. In general, the
lower personal threshold to trigger an action (applauding) increased the probability
of applauding (Miller and Page 2004, 2007). Intimacy to people in the crowd also
mattered. If there is a recognized dyad (such as two people with a relationship in the
same public space and time), there is a higher recognized level of peer influence. A
person is more likely to match actions with his or her companion in the dyad (Miller
and Page 2007). The people in the front and well as celebrities matter to collective
behavior (Miller and Page 2007). All the while, if the threshold tip is easier to reach
in a group, more may be encouraged and socially protected to stand (Miller and
Page 2007). Individuals in the audience are able to enjoy a social protection in a
social display if the same action reflects that of the group.
Collective Action
Miller and Page’s (2007) rule-based assertions on peer influence differ slightly from
that of Mark Granovetter’s theory of collective action (see Granovetter 1978). In
appraising quality in collective action, Granovetter (1978) warned that motives in
collective action are not mirrors into the soul of agreed upon norms. When all of the
Collective Action 53
Rules imply people are devoid of cognition or autonomous ethical struggles. Here
lies the conundrum. But there are no ironclad rules in what agents assert as their
decisions. Political decisions are not made within civic squares. Rationality is ex-
tremely restricted to achieve. But rule-based models offer choices devoid of the
messiness of cognition. A trigger is a trigger. There are no purposeful agents to
contend with. The rules have been created to mimic reality as much as possible. It is
important to discern if the policy targets actions that have no wider consequence to
others or if the driver depends on the actions of other to comply. But in order to un-
derstand if people act based on sorting (homophily) or peer effect (collective behav-
ior), the question must be answered if there is only movement/action (homophily)
or there is a change afoot supporting that action (peer effect). Is the policy seeking
to gain surface insight of policy outcomes or understand the underlying cascading
mechanisms of change propagated by that policy? Rules offer a foundation but are
not the end of the story.
For instance, discussions of living organ donation often occur during times of emi-
nent duress of the eminent need for an organ. Networks may cross based on purpose
or be marked by isolation. As social beings, negotiation of social agreement often
requires personal engagement with people we trust and share strong attachments. If
an ethic develops at a larger level, how might success of a positive donation ethic
is accomplished if consensus may be made as a collective of individuals that they
know? Likewise, how much does one person hold in influencing the ethical beliefs
of others around them if the overall moral position contradicts the larger system
network level?
Organdonor.gov, in its “Get Started” tips for declaring donation, intentions the
point to familiarize your family with your decision. This assumes that one’s eth-
ic aligns with the “decision” rendered to others or that there will be a “collective
change of heart.” As Fox (2010) notes that a less-charged setting would be appro-
priate for discussing postmortem donation, what of the charged reality that there is
a collective ethic that may be working against donation? People in a network by
nature are emotionally invested. It would be best to approach this health discussion
as it is emotive and difficult to navigate in all circumstances.
54 5 Health Systems and Policymaking as the “Price Is Right”
This talk enters the process at delayed juncture. They may very well have been
socially influenced by the very advocates that were asked to support during the
big disclosure. Again, explore the nature of the networks and collective influence.
Donors are “potential” even if their bioethical position is contrary (Fox 2010). “It
ain’t over till it’s over” (unless the patient’s body fails or everyone in the network
rejects donation). It is the tricky part. It may not be fully apparent just how much
manipulation and change in a system is required to reach a goal (see Meadows
1999). It would be premature to guess just how many prodonation individuals it
would take to make the network tip positively to result in a living organ donation.
Taken from another perspective, what is the tipping point that outflows, resulting in
losing support? Case in point, human agency and the ability to change one’s mind
give an ethical malleability that makes changing ethical positions possible and gives
clinicians a glimmer of hope for a successful conversion to organ donation.
Typically, the expert knowledge of the people who actually operate the system is required
to structure and parameterize a useful model (Ford and Sterman 1997).
We are unaware of the majority of the feedback effects of our actions. Instead, we see most
of our experience as a kind of weather: something that happens to us but over which we
have no control (Sterman 2002).
Perhaps, the real power of stories lies in their reflection of ideas and values … Much of the
policy process involves debates about values [ethics] masquerading as debates about facts
and data. (McDonough 2001)
Aaron Riley, a longtime social advocate, offered his thoughts on the roles of commu-
nity stakeholders in affecting policy. Currently, Mr. Riley is the CEO and Founder
References 55
of New Leaf Columbus in Columbus, Ohio. The mission of New Leaf Columbus
(http://newleafcolumbus.ning.com/) is to strengthen LGBTQ (Lesbian, Gay, Bi-
sexual, transgender, and Questioning) communities of color through dialogue and
advocacy. With advocates, often peering from the outside into the political process,
there is a tension between being heard and affecting observable social change. Ac-
cording to Mr. Riley, “far too many policies lacked both the art [reflexivity] and
science” that in turn fundamentally flaw policymaking. He added that advocates
and policy makers often find themselves facing a reality of reliance on business as
usual that breeds competing priorities and competing factions with little gained for
any party. Advocates are aware of the limitation of resources, which in his opinion,
“in itself is a powerful generator (to push) policy.”
It is a quagmire for sure; however, in my opinion, it is much worse to do nothing. So do
extraordinary circumstances call for extraordinary problem solving? Perhaps, it sometimes
just calls on us to learn from what we have tried that did not work in order to turn us in a
new or different direction. After all, as imperfect beings in an imperfect world that can only
create imperfect policy, the best we can hope for is the evolution of our imperfection. Aaron
Riley, interviewed by the author (2014).
Reflexivity is often flatly ignored when examining social systems. Greg Fisher
(2012) offered what he called the Law of Ostrichs (Fisher 2012). Contrary to the
popular belief, ostriches do not place their heads in the sand at all. In defense of a
predator’s advance, ostriches in fact run in an attempt to coax the enemy to follow
them, so that they (ostriches) can protect their eggs. In terms of its applicability to
policymaking, comfort is often taken over the “awkward truth” of what is really
happening in a social system (Fisher 2012). The Law of Ostrich’s applies “when a
comforting yet inaccurate narrative is believed ahead of an awkward truth.” (Fisher
2012). Meadows (2008) wrote that stakeholders hold fast to their own bounded
rationality of the policy issue. What results is a clash of the rationalities based on
the decisions toward acknowledging reflexivity in the policymaking process. The
system becomes policy resistance, typified by the “intensification of anyone’ effort
leads to the intensification of everyone else’s” (Meadows 2008). The best approach
to abolishing policy resistance is to get rid of the bad policies (Meadows 2008).
Some may argue that politics makes this requirement of outside engagement less
than realistic.
References
Ackoff RL (1974) Redesigning the future: a systems approach to societal problems. Wiley-Inter-
science, New York
Berk J, Hughson E, Vandezande K (1996) The price is right, but are the bids? An investigation of
Rational Decision Theory. Am Econ Rev 86(4):954–970
Bourdieu P (1993) Structures, habitus, practices. In: Lemert C (ed) Social theory: the multicultural
and classic readings. Westview, Boulder
Chapman J (2004) System Failure. Demos. http://www.demos.co.uk/files/systemfailure2.pdf. Ac-
cessed on 15 Jan 2014
56 5 Health Systems and Policymaking as the “Price Is Right”
Chia R (1998) From complexity science to complex thinking: organization as simple location.
Organization 5(3):341–369
Fisher G (2012) Reflexivity and Narrative. http://www.synthesisips.net/blog/reflexivity-and-nar-
ratives/. Accessed 8 June 2014
Ford D, Sterman JD (1997) Expert knowledge elicitation to improve mental and formal models.
Syst Dyn Rev 14:309–340
Fox M (2010) Organ donation should be a part of health discussions. American Medical News.
http://www.ama-assn.org/amednews/2010/05/31/prca0531.htm. Accessed 14 April 2014.
Granovetter M (1978) Threshold models of collective behavior. Am J Sociol 83(6):1420–1443
McDonough J (2001) Using and misusing ancedote in policy making. Health Aff (Millwood)
20(1):207–212
Meadows D (1999) Leverage points: places to intervene in a system. The Sustainability Institute,
Hartland
Meadows D (2008) Thinking in systems: a primer. Chelsea Green, White River Junction
Miller J, Page S (2004) The standing ovation problem. Complexity 9(5):8–16
Miller J, Page S (2007) Complex adaptive systems: an introduction to computational models of
social life (Princeton Studies in Complexity). Princeton University Press, Princeton
Schumacher E (1977) A guide for the perplexed. Harper & Row, New York
Sterman J (2002) All models are wrong: reflections on becoming a systems scientist. Syst Dynam
Rev 18:501–531
Wheeler JA (1989) Information, physics, quantum: the search for links. Proceedings III Interna-
tional Symposium on Foundations of Quantum Mechanics-Tokyo, pp 354–368
Chapter 6
Ethical and Systematic Approaches
to Health Policy
As long as a person exists in the presence of other carbon life forms, ethics will be
batted around. Ethical malleability acknowledges that a person may “change” his
ethical stance to suit his present belief system (Battle-Fisher 2010). The private ele-
ment of self-reliance perculates under the same ecological conditions as the public
concern for others (see Colander and Kupers 2014). Brass et al. (1998) introduced
the idea of using social network analysis to understand ethical negotiation.
The [effective] government does not impose norms [ethics] or even force individuals to
self-regulate. Instead it attempts to encourage the development of an econstructure that
encourages self-reliance and concern for others. (Colander and Kupers 2014)
not the action but a precondition to action. But the public ultimately must pay for its
actions so the public indirectly pay for personally held ethical positions.
As rationality serves a purpose in framing situations, people are owners of active
frontal lobes. Granovetter (1985) introduced the fundamental idea of the conse-
quence of embeddedness on social relationships. The private self is folded into a
public one. A person does not act autonomously when under the influence and pry-
ing eyes of one’s network (public). “Concrete personal relations and structures (or
networks) of such relations” guide members of a system (Granovetter 1985). While
struggling to maintain the sanctity of personal agency, people are influenced by oth-
ers in a position of social influence. An ethic may never necessarily be displayed as
a discernible action or even need to be articulated. Must an ethic be communicated
to count? Is it something else when discussed by morphing into a value or norm?
Only if (punitive) consequences can sometimes override such factors in determining mor-
ally appropriate actions do the cases illustrate moral mistakes. (Adler 2005)
Morally conscientious government actors must ultimately settle on a moral theory (or a
probability distribution across theories) and choose. (Adler 2005)
As the public engages with its environment , “good” or “moral” changes are tied to
the overall state of a public health issue. Law provides government institutions the
authority to act in enforcement, thus enabling healthy personal choices. Law cannot
dictate, though it may influence the nature of personally acted-upon ethics. There is
no direct recourse of the legal authority to the nature of a held ethic insofar that the
actions connected to an ethic do not cause an obvious violation of legal standard.
Until there is a legal violation, I argue that people have the right to change ethics
and often act upon that right. When these decisions happen, the state of the moral
system is thus affected.
Politics and ethical decisions comingle insomuch as the explicit rules come un-
der constant scrutiny by a public who themselves stay “malleable” based on their
own exogeneous factors that pull at them as well (Battle-Fisher 2010). The political
process explicitly works in an environment of competing interests. The interests
do not solely compete based on ideological group-based differences at the macro
level. This is the tenuous environment in which policy functions, one that buoys
rules existing under the constraints of political infeasibility and the ever-present
possibility of public fatigue toward regulatory oversight. For policymakers, the
scuffle becomes one based on leveraging expertise and influence to make marks on
policy. After the scuffle subsides, the policy puffins are proud puffins with a com-
mon goal but displaying allegiance with sameness. Policymakers navigate a primal
system of conquering to advantage or at the least, staying relevant in the debate.
There are drawbridges for moral hazards by influential actors which control the
flow of information (Frenzen and Nakamoto 1993). But this flow is not done in a
Interplay of Politics and Ethics 59
Yeats metaphorically described the center and periphery as dynamic (Deane 1995).
Most importantly, if society is a whole, its unity and coherence—even its very iden-
tity—is dependent on the integrity of the center. For if the center is removed, the
peripheral parts will no longer join together to form a whole by means of structural
cohesion. Moreover, the continued unity of the whole depends on the strength of the
center, that is, its ability to hold the periphery in place (Deane 1995). How might
one take Deane (1995) out of the world of “ordinary language” of metaphor of
the center as influencers in tobacco control and into the universe of mathematical
complexity? While everyone may not have the resources to act upon their inclina-
60 6 Ethical and Systematic Approaches to Health Policy
tion, there is will always be some level of disharmony. In other words, people do
not follow set rules very well. Sometimes the rules are not made by public required
to follow them.
References
Adler M (2005) Cognitivism, controversy and moral heuristics. Behav Brain Sci 28:542–543
Battle-Fisher M (2010) Organ donation ethics: are donors autonomous within collective networks?
Online J Health Ethics 6(2). http://aquila.usm.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1085&context=
ojhe. Accessed 14 April 2014
Bikchandani S, Hirshleifer D, Welsh I (1992) A theory of fads, fashion, custom, and cultural
change as informational cascades. J Polit Econ 100:992–1026
Brass D, Butterfield K, Skaggs B (1998) Relationships and unethical behavior: a social network
perspective. Acad Manag Rev 23(2):14–31
Colander D, Kupers R (2014) Complexity and the art of public policy-solving society’s problems
from the bottom-up. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Deane P (1995) Metaphors of center and periphery in Yeats’ the second coming. J Pragmat
24:627–642
Frenzen J, Nakamoto K (1993) Structure, cooperation and the flow of market information. J Con-
sum Res 20:360–375
Granovetter M (1985) Economic action and social structure: the problem of embeddedness. Am J
Sociol 91:481–510
Kilduff M, Tsai W (2003) Social network and organizations. Sage Publications, Los Angeles
Chapter 7
Health Disparities in Public Health
Berlinger (2009) spoke eloquently of the dogged issue of the perpetuation in flawed
reasoned (in)action within complex systems. If complex systems defy description,
the personal social network of the potential donors must be a part of the discussion
of supporting living organ donation (Berlinger 2010). Thank goodness that no man
or woman is an island. Other people (and their valuable organs) are needed in con-
sort with organ donation. The norms of living organ donation may be understood by
mapping a network of close confidants (known as nodes or actors) that are linked by
a particular circumstance. The central character or ego (ironically named so) is not
alone with his or her thoughts. The ego is connected to others in a network whether
large or small in size. The self-centeredness of an “ego’s” ethical decision becomes
complicated by its embeddedness in a network of concerned others. To embed so-
cially leads to an overlap of roles of private lives.
Health disparity of organ donation is often explained with statistics. This is only
a part of the narrative: enumeration as foreign to the ego as the connectedness to the
entire population of end-stage renal disease (ESRD) patients that only emotionally
reach as far as those they know and care about. Each family is aware of the finite-
ness of opportunity cost for their loved one; a kidney transplanted to another with-
out a donor in replacement lengthens the odds of a miracle. Most living donations
come from biological-related donors. This will be the network. There is a layering
of judgment of morality. An event that may begin in earnest as an autonomous act is
no longer so. One must account for the heteronomy, or difference in values that may
be originated and perpetuated by the network.
Earlier versions of this chapter appeared as Battle-Fisher M (2010) Organ donation ethics: are
donors autonomous within collective networks? Online J Health Ethics 6(2). http://aquila.usm.
edu/ojhe/vol6/iss2/6 as well as Battle-Fisher, M. (2011) Severity of scope versus altruism: working
against organ donation’s realization of goals—an essay. Online J Health Ethics 7(2). http://aquila.
usm.edu/ojhe/vol7/iss2/4. Permission has been secured from the publisher.
© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015 61
M. Battle-Fisher, Application of Systems Thinking to Health Policy & Public
Health Ethics, SpringerBriefs in Public Health, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-12203-8_7
62 7 Health Disparities in Public Health
A question to ask might be the moral entropy brought out when the values of
members of a social network differ. More likely than not, everyone will never agree.
In addition, ethical values are transitory and have gradients of buy-in. What can
policy do to furtherance buy-in? “Potential” has its distinct silos in organ donation.
As a potential donor, Battle-Fisher (2010) originally classified possible donors into
three categories:
1. A “potential” with viable organs to agree and then act as donor
2. A “potential” with viable organs to choose not to act now (which the hope that
this could change over time) but not against the idea, or
3. A “potential” with viable organs that is unobtainable with negative ethics toward
donation
Upon revision, four updated variants of donor potentiality now account for the con-
servation and accumulation of feedbacks in social systems.
1. A “potential” that publically agrees with donation in all cases (pro-donation) and
supports all donation options including becoming a possible donor himself.
2. A “potential” that publically agrees with donation in all cases (pro-donation) and
but this kidney should come from someone else.
3. A “potential” that publically agrees with donation in select cases but not in the
case of the patient in question (e.g. “I know mama won’t take care of it so why
bother”, “Grandpa has lived a long productive life, why put him through this?”)
4. A “potential” that has not committed to either pro or con publicly (perhaps in fear
of reaction from others in the network)
An article in Social Psychological and Personality Science written by Nordgren and
Morris McDonnell (2011) posed a research question that should be central to public
health ethics. This was published in a psychology journal which may not be on the
radar of many bioethicists. Nordgren and Morris McDonnell (2011) posit that ratio-
nality is thrown out of the window when the burden of people afflicted by a crime
becomes incomprehensible.
The basic premises of “scope-severity paradox” according to Nordgren and Mor-
ris McDonnell (2011) are:
1. People only connect emotionally with crime victims within our personal social
network (i.e. family, clan, neighborhood, civic group) that we know and care
about.
2. Increasing the number of victims decreases the perception of severity of the
problem. “Your problem, not mine” could be reworded as “call me only if a
loved one is directly affected.”
At a more elemental level, the lack of prowess in recognizing the gravity of an event
would be explained by a presence of scope insensitivity. Desmentes et al (2007)
note the importance of personal gain versus loss in unraveling this scope insensitiv-
ity. But public health must find a way of emphasizing a collective gain/loss framing
that is linked to personal actions. What would be the social cost for donating (gain
for society and personal gain for patient)? Moreover, is the public not paying in the
Organ Donation in a Complex System 63
end by the lack of living donations as both loss for society and personal losses for
patients)? A central tenet of the Health Belief Model is perceived benefits where
a health behavior must be framed as having a chance of affecting change in order
to support the utility of that decision (Janz and Becker 1984). This would be an
individualized framing of gain and loss. Does this cover all of bases of explaining
the public’s health? While perceived benefits are individualistic, what is lost is the
exploration of the grand scope of the health concern on decision making.
Policy must reframe the public narrative to combat scope. According to the scope-
severity paradox, the public does not easily care about those that people and nar-
ratives do not know, especially when they originate from masses of far-flung
individuals. How much emotional energy can each realistically give, especially if
specific energy needs to be directed to an unimaginable host of others? A lesson
could be learned here in terms of framing scope-severity paradox around public
health ethics. This is a prime example of the gain-framed experience that perhaps is
radiating from a personal loss. Organ donation is a situation with the best intentions
(altruistic compassion), but does not automatically resolve with a saved life in the
end. Is the son gaining a mother by donation (gain-frame) or losing a mother by
not donating (loss-frame)? Or is it both? As an “anticipated health behavior,” living
organ donation cannot be practiced and reinforced through active trial and error of
the behavior (Battle-Fisher 2010). What can change would be the donor’s belief as a
potential donor, which is wedded to the possibility of ever-changing personal ethics
(Battle-Fisher 2010).
The question, whether there can be sufficient saturation of altruistic compassion
achieved in order to trigger innovation in a network, should be raised. After review-
ing the legacy on donation prevalence after the policy was enacted, what happened
to this health indicator under the policy in light of the system’s history? Did the
organ donation policy counteract the outflow of parameters draining any gains in
organ donation? Or did the policy create inflow values that were protective of organ
donation?
There is much to be said about defying the overall collective ethic of one’s so-
cial network when the act for donation actually occurs and becomes embodied in
convalesce and a physical scar reminding of the removal of “Uncle John’s kidney”
(Jones 2009). Unlike most illness discourses, there would not be physical changes
to the body that the network would have to grapple warranting medical intervention.
Most chronic illness is a deal breaker in living donation. So what is left is a nego-
tiation of a possible medical event that can place an otherwise healthy individual
in possible harm’s way (though risks are miniscule). The potential donor is asked
to play a role as a giver of organs and live to tell the story that end with a happy
ending for another (Battle-Fisher 2010). Take Jones’ (2009) well grounded point
of the continued attachment of the transplanted organ to the donor. The network is
64 7 Health Disparities in Public Health
consistently reminded of the divergent decision and may be called to help the do-
nor when they disagreed with the initial decision. There goes the extemporaneous
harmony.
The risk and rewards become that of the collective. Life no longer exists as an
individual attribute but one that is negotiated with the needs and desires of the net-
work in mind. The increased risk of chronic kidney disease and ESRD is outstretch-
ing the decreasing supply of viable kidneys available after each donation (assuming
replacement that does not keep pace). But as time passes the physical body can only
take so much wear and there will be a watershed “moment” when a loved one, such
as Ann’s cousin, needs an organ. The prevalence rates cruelly illuminate this pos-
sibility. People discuss certain issues with the Thursday night bowling league and
a radically different set of bioethical discussions in Sunday school. But the public
hold a quiver of stocked beliefs that are selectively shared. The nature of ethical de-
liberation is animated and changing. The most complex system is the one in which
the public has the most to lose. Then it is up to human agency, clinical knowledge,
and a network of gatekeepers as to an organ’s fate. But as time passes, the state of
the system moves on and policy must be created to account for the new fate as the
public’s ethical stances has evolved.
References
Battle-Fisher M (2010) Organ donation ethics: are donors autonomous within collective networks?
Online J Health Ethics 6(2). http://aquila.usm.edu/ojhe/vol6/iss2/6. Accessed 14 April 2014
Berlinger N (2009) Friends in high places: doing bioethics at 36,000 feet. Bioethics Forum. http://
www.thehastingscenter.org/Bioethicsforum/Post.aspx?id = 3500&blogid = 140. Accessed 14
April 2014
Berlinger N (2010) Spin doctors and torture doctors: inconvenient truths about com-
plex systems. Bioethics Forum. http://www.thehastingscenter.org/Bioethicsforum/Post.
aspx?id = 4704&blogid = 140#ix zz0sNaUFyK8. Accessed 14 April 2014
Desmentes R, Bechara A, Dube L (2007) Subjective valuation and asymmetrical motivation
systems: implications of scope insensitivity for decision making. J Behav Decis Making
21:211–224
Janz N, Becker M (1984) The health belief model: a decade later. Health Educ Q 11(1):1–47
Jones N (2009) The importance of embodiment in transplant ethics. In: Ravitsky V, Fiester A,
Caplan A (eds) The Penn center for bioethics guide to bioethics. Springer, New York
Nordgren L, Morris McDonnell M-H (2011) The scope-severity paradox-why doing more harm is
judged to be less harmful. Social Psychol Personal Sci 2(1):97–102
Part II
Applications of Modeling to Health Policy
Chapter 8
Mental and Simulated Models in Health
Policy Making
Essentially all models are wrong, but some are useful. (Box and Draper 1987)
Microworlds take our great ideas and mental hunches and input them into a “con-
structed reality” (Papert 1980). The formal system thinkers and their technologies
share the policy glory as an understudy but they have to be in the race. In my
opinion, system thinking does not take precedence over the art of policymaking. A
system is inherent to the filigree of policy. It is a supporting role in assuring integ-
rity in policymaking but system thinking should never be demoted to an understudy.
Sometimes, we will not like the answer when the modeling, such as the offerings
gained system dynamics modeling, upends our pacifying policy realities.
System Dynamics
Fig. 8.1 Examples of a causal loop diagram of the cycle of population change (a) and basic
stock and flow with one inflow and one outflow tied to population change (b). (Reprinted from
BMC Health Services Research, 7, Elf, M., Putilova, M., von Koch, L., & Öhrn, K. Using system
dynamics for collaborative design: a case study. 123. Using system dynamics for collaborative
design: a case study. Open access. BioMed Central original publisher)
together by the arrows serving as causal links. Notice that the positive signs
between population and births. The population procreates, therefore increasing
the births (+) which subsequently adds (+) to the population. As for the effect of
death, the population is the source of deaths, thus labeled as positive polarity (+).
However, in an act of balancing the system, deaths take away from the stock thus
labeled as negative polarity (−). It should be noted that additional elements can
be added to the diagram. The causality, or better yet, how this system fits together
with the additional restraints, may be far less apparent without using systems and
modeling.
The fluctuations in global populations have merited public health intervention. An-
other way to view this system is the use of the stock and flow diagram (as illus-
trated in b). The stock in the second figure is shown as the rectangle with valves
(the coupled small rectangles on the pipes) that control the flow into and out of the
stock, population. This gives a snapshot of a simple system that is the bedrock of
understanding all social systems (see Gonzalez and Wong 2012).
Unfortunately, there is increasing and robust evidence of a fundamental lack in the human
understanding of accumulation and rates of change: a difficulty called the stock–flow (SF)
failure. (Gonzalez and Wong 2012)
Stocks and flows are said to be the simplest dynamical system. Stocks must always
be defined in terms of flows. A flow is akin to a rate of change over time (either
inflow or outflow) of that stock. An inflow adds and an outflow depletes. Flows do
not generate immediate changes in the stock to which they are connected. Thus is
the requirement of time in order to understand the system. There can be any number
of inflows and outflows and they do not have to be equal in number or rate of ac-
Stock and Flow of Public Health Interventions 69
ing!” I said to myself. “They haven’t the SLIGHTEST IDEA how this complex structure
will behave,” myself said back to me. “It’s almost certainly an example of cranking the
system in the wrong direction—it’s aimed at growth, growth at any price!! And the con-
trol measures these nice, liberal folks are talking about to combat it—small parameter
adjustments, weak negative feedback loops—are PUNY!!! (Meadows 1997)
Meadows (1999) listed on the flip chart of this meeting the following leverages,
from least effective (denoted as #12) to most effective (denoted as #1) places to
target in affecting the nature of a system. These leverages are:
12. Elements of a sociopolitical system (better known as the parts)—It is the basis
of debunking reductionism in affecting systems. Sometimes, the best systemic
choice is not the call of the vocal public who by nature are not privy to the com-
plexity inherent to making that choice.
11. “ Buffers” in relationship to its stocks—Large stocks that often are too cumber-
some or expensive to change.
10. Actual structure of the stocks and flows or nodes of a network which may be un-
changeable or too expensive to attempt to change—After the structure is there,
the power lies in acknowledging the missteps and mistakes in design.
9. Attacking delays in the system “relative to the rate of system changes”—“Things
take as long as they take.”
8. B alancing Feedback Loops—This negative, balancing loop, and its strength
are there to keep focus toward a policy goal. They are necessary. We all use
balancing feedbacks as a mode of controlling our environment. As a conse-
quence, when a balancing loop leads a system astray, there must be “a goal, a
detecting … device … and a response mechanism.” This is the policy equiva-
lent of putting out fires but there is always dry brush out there.
7. Reinforcing Feedback Loops—Unlike balancing loops, a positive, reinforcing
loop gains momentum in growth and erosion of a system. Any “unchecked” re-
inforcing loops leads to the implosion of a system. When you slow a reinforcing
loop, the system sprouts balancing loops.
6. Leveraging Information Flows—This requires finding out who is in the loop
and who is out. Who in the network is in the know? Who in a social network has
the influence to persuade and diffuse information?
5. “The Rules of the Systems”—This addition should make ethicists happy. This
would be the rules of the collective and the individual—paternalism, autonomy,
norms, values, ethics, laws, edicts, constitutions. Meadows added the distinc-
tion that in opposition to physical rules, social rules are “progressively weaker”
with a slippery slope.
4. Engaging changes to the self-organization of the system—This is a largest pre-
dictor of resilience of a system. Giving a system the freedom to change requires
a faith in experimentation that may be feared.
3. Understanding the overarching goal of the system—Analogous to a mission
statement, “what is the point” of all of this?
2. P aradigm Shifts—While there is no monetary or physical cost to changing a
mind-set, this may be the most bruising to a policymaker’s ego. Business as
usual may need to become history for the sake of effecting systemic change.
The Role of Simulation in Policy Making 71
Justin Lyon, the founder and CEO of SIMUDYNE offered insight on the power
of gamification as a health policy tool. As a mission of SIMUDYNE, simulations
are at the core of supporting well-informed decisions of their clients. The mantra
of SIMUDYNE in its use of policy simulation is to test scenarios before investing
on time, energy, tangible resources, and cognitive power. Lyon entertained ques-
tions about the place of simulations in policy and the future of gamification as a
mode of visualization for policy matters. According to Lyon, a problem in transla-
tion of mathematical models (which is the means to a policy end) is resolved in
the approachability in using artificial life visualization. Lyon said that this kind of
visualization “frees people to hold (policy) dialogue and debate without having to
concentrate on backdoor mathematics.” The nuts and bolts science of simulation is
inaccessible to most, however, gamification in the form of avatars instantly makes
the math accessible without being off putting. If the math is approachable, it is more
likely to engage as a part of the policymaking process.
What power does simulation hold for health policy? According to Lyon, simu-
lations serve to “reduce risk and reduce cost.” But the financial, social, and spiri-
tual costs attached to health care are mountainous. That vastness of systemic effect
should by nature call for an investigation with new, dynamic eyes. Case in point, in
terms of health promotion and intervention, Lyon offered that cautionary tale must
be aware that health cannot shift out cost by concentrating on one specific change
in one sector of health without realizing that financial and social cost shifting to
another part of the system. What does that cascade of change look like? Graphs are
static. Simulation can change and morph to suit new situational parameters. Choose
simulation when rigorously conducted as well as pertinent to the policy matter be-
ing debate. The simulation, if used appropriately, could help to break the stalemates
that can impede policy development (see Repenning and Sterman 1999; Sterman
2006; Sterman 2000).
72 8 Mental and Simulated Models in Health Policy Making
Regardless of the policy model used in a policy system, when a new policy is written or
committed in the system, the administrator must consider [policy ratification as] how the
new policy interacts with those already existing in the system. (Agrawal et al. 2005)
Minyard and her colleagues at Georgia State University demonstrate that system
thinking is not an esoteric, inaccessible concept but rather a set of skills that any-
one—especially policymakers—can benefit from learning about and practically
applying. In 2008, the Georgia Health Policy Center (GHPC) began an intensive
educational program for state policymakers and legislative staff wanting a deeper
understanding of health policy issues. The Legislative Health Policy Certificate
Program (Certificate Program) is a continuing education program for state legisla-
tors and staff designed to build systems thinking competencies using health policy
content. Two sessions address “core” health policy topics, such as health financing,
insurance coverage, and access, while two sessions are devoted to issue-specific
topics determined by the participants, ranging from childhood obesity to trauma
care (Minyard et al. 2014). However, they believed that policymakers could also
benefit from building their skills to approach policy issues as “system thinkers.”
That is, to look at the big picture, integrate diverse perspectives, consider changing
dynamics, and explore high-leverage interventions in order to begin to change the
way they frame issues, ask questions, and consider solutions to challenging health
issues (Minyard et al. 2014).
After searching the literature for how research influences policy and how poli-
cymakers take in and respond to information, GHPC found that most education for
legislators focuses on specific topics or supports specific policy decisions and that
this approach was inadequate to generate the type of policy we—and policymak-
ers—desired. System dynamics (and system thinking) provides a useful lens for
approaching challenging policy issues. System thinking utilizes multiple disciplines
and critical thinking skills such as dynamic thinking (looking at an issue over time),
system-as-cause thinking, and forest thinking (looking at the big picture and how
things fit together). This was just the type of learning capacity GHPC thought poli-
cymakers would benefit from and decided to build their curriculum around this ap-
proach (Minyard et al. 2014).
Simply asking questions, such as these, can dramatically raise the level of con-
versation.
• What does an issue look like if expressed as a trend over time? What might
be causing that trend? Is there a systemic structure in place causing (or
influencing) that trend?
• What policy might address this underlying trend?
Reflective and Systematic Approaches 73
When people brainstorm, we battle with mental, qualitative models pieced together
as divergent points (inputs). We have all been there. Mentally, we approximate all
the time. It is a natural part of the policy process. To the miasmic stench of perma-
nent markers littering a flip chart, the decision makers and perhaps a silent minority
74 8 Mental and Simulated Models in Health Policy Making
are left to make sense of that complex data to get at the process that has no obvious
end in sight. There needs to be “reflective conversation” with the situation of the
simulated results (Schon 1992). But the model alone will not be a predictive crystal
ball. Much chatter has been circulated about the overreach of models into the world
of prediction in policy.
The model does not forecast. The model may not be able to capture all of the
connections to other policies that it is related to. It is a simulation. It is a model
that is based on decision rules. It is a system with a priori boundaries. Systems
offer math to support or refute initial reactions to early conditions viewed under
a policy (see Forrester 2007). This is indispensable and this fact should not be
taken lightly.
Each policy must be approached and respected as a necessity to prudent, sys-
temic action to debate, not as a letdown of the expected policy desired beforehand.
The satiation comes in what policymakers do with the systemic knowledge that is
gained and ideally apply with prudent judgment and systemic consideration.
References
Agrawal D, Giles J, Lee KW, Lobo J (2005) Policy ratification. Policies for distributed systems
and networks, 2005. Sixth IEEE international workshop on policies for distributed systems and
networks, 223–232. doi:10.1109/POLICY.2005.25
Booth Sweeney L, Sterman JD (2000) Bathtub dynamics: initial results of a systems thinking
inventory. Syst Dyn Rev 16:249–294
Box GEP, Draper NR (1987) Empirical model building and response surfaces. Wiley, New York
Forrester J (2007) System dynamics—the next fifty years. Syst Dyn Rev 23(2/3):359–370
Gonzalez C, Wong H (2012) Understanding stocks and flows through analogy. Syst Dyn Rev
28(1):3–27
Hamid TKA (2009) Thinking in circles about obesity. Springer, New York
Homer J, Milstein B (2004) Optimal Decision making in a dynamic model of community health.
Proceedings of the 37th Hawaii international conference on system science. http://citeseerx.
ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi:10.1.1.135.3301&rep=rep1&type=pdf. Accessed 15 April
2014
Homer J, Hirsch G, Milstein B (2007) Chronic illness in a complex health economy: the perils and
promises of downstream and upstream reforms. Syst Dyn Rev 23(2/3):313–343
Meadows D (1997) Places to intervene in a system. Whole earth review. http://www.wholeearth.
com/issue/2091/article/27/places.to.intervene.in.a.system. Accessed 8 June 2014
Meadows D (1999) Leverage points: places to intervene in a system. The Sustainability Institute,
Hartland
Meadows D (2008) Thinking in systems: a primer. Chelsea Green, River Junction
Minyard KJ, Ferencik R, Phillips MA, Soderquist S (2014) Using systems thinking in state health
policymaking. Health Systems. doi:10.1057/hs.2013.17
Papert S (1980) Mindstorms. Basic Books, New York
Repenning N, Sterman J (1999) Getting quality the old fashioned way: self-confirming attributions
in the dynamics of process improvement. In: Scott R, Cole R (eds) The quality movement and
organizational theory. Sage, Newbury Park
Schon D (1992) The theory of inquiry: Dewey’s legacy to education. Curric Inquiry 22(2):119–139
Sterman J (2000) Business dynamics—systems thinking and modeling for a complex world. Mc-
Graw-Hill, New York
Sterman J (2006) Learning from evidence in a complex world. Am J Public Health 96(3):505–514
Part III
A Brief Exploration of the Complexity of
Health Disparities (As Humanistically as
Possible)
Chapter 9
Social Disparity, Policy, and Sharing in Public
Health
Only the BLACK WOMAN can say, when and where I enter, in the quiet, undisputed dig-
nity of my womanhood, without violence and without suing or special patronage, then and
there the whole Negro race enters with me. (Cooper 1988)
Our reactions are far from linear. We are human. Black women may converse in the salon,
free to vent among the miasmic heat of irons, stench of acetone nails and lye-laced chemi-
cally treated hair. The conversation mixes purpose with the unbridled freedom to discuss
her life, love and sorrows. This self may not be demonstrated in the clinician’s office but
the same sorrow song of her life is necessary to care for her health. Looking at the health
disparities plaguing the U.S., the self-projection by the Black female patient must be uncon-
strained and she must “speak” to respectful clinicians in return. (Battle-Fisher 2013a)
For a black woman, she is her social effeminacy. Playing race and gender requires
making a conscious determination of the internalized and socially projected selves.
Research has shown stark disparities in health outcomes for black women in the
USA across all ages and socioeconomic backgrounds. Phelan, Link, and Tehranifar
(2010) cite the persistent health disparities have proved resilient to most health
promotion efforts. Recalling Link and Phelan’s theory of fundamental causes, this
chapter is a call to dig beyond the surface to uncover mechanisms perpetuating
disaparties (see Phelan et al. 2010). Determining “when and where I enter” in light
of resource disparity may be exasperated by intervening mechanisms set to improve
outcomes in health interventions (see Phelan et al. 2010). An issue of embodiment
is a precursor to policy development that must not be ignored. Epidemiologically,
each woman has a footprint of exposure over the lifespan that bolsters or hinders
realizations of health. Sex matters in etiology of disease. Gender is linked to life
chances.
Dissatisfied with the gender-based prejudice, Cooper spoke of making a choice be-
tween two rooms at a hotel. One was labeled “for ladies” and the other “for colored
people”. She mused “under which head it come” (Cooper 1988). Society often plac-
es race above all other social constructions. Society had dictated to which she must
oblige “colored”. Living a departmentalized self for the sake of social stratification
serves no one. But the reality remains that it is this stratification from which we
tend to self-define or get “self” defined through proxy. Although most would now
agree that race is socially created, the dark hue of one’s skin does not come with
a disclaimer that the hue should not matter. Cooper highlights that society often
demarcates based on social dichotomies (Cooper 1988). In doing so, a woman must
contend with whether she is black or not, or healthy or ill.
The history of the American Negro is the history of this strife- this longing to obtain self-
conscious (person) hood, to merge (the) double self into a better and truer self. (DuBois
1965)
Multiple, layered selves are engineered yet are socially and physically coped with
at varying degrees of success.
With identity thus re-conceptualized [with intersectionality], it may be easier to understand
the need for, and to summon the courage to challenge, groups that are after all, in one sense,
‘home’ to us, in the name of the parts of us that are not made at home. (Crenshaw 1994)
Would a black woman then be embodied as “female” not black if she has successful
beat the grim statistics of black morbidity and her progeny? When can she be black
again? Is she then something else? Anna Julia Cooper wrote in 1892 that there are
two kinds of peace [balance]in the world: one produced by suppression and the oth-
er brought by “proper adjustment to living, acting forces.” (Cooper 1988). “Other-
isms” are determined inside (endogenous) or outside (exogenous) the social system.
Housing and Equal Opportunity Impacts 79
Just as a system variable leaves behind a history, so does the veiled history of
people of color (see Sterman 2000; DuBois 1965). If the peace allowed by optimal
health remains confined to the uncertainty of such a hermeneutic, not exploring “the
Other” of the black female or any other marginalized groups, for that matter, may be
the worse folly of all, in policy. Even if race, gender, or take your pick is found to
be exogenous, it does not mean that this striving to reconcile dichotomies is incon-
sequential. As written by Harvey (2001), complexity itself can be “socially deter-
mined, productions of historically situated social structures”. Social complexity in
networks based on “other-isms” requires the critical examination of the overlapping
multiplexity of roles that are affected by social constraints (Crenshaw 1994; Ver-
brugge 1979). Roles, while important in understanding the nature of social relation-
ships, are not the same as social projections of worth both internally and externally
ascribed to those roles.
Community is ingrained for some. For others, they live only in a zip code. (Battle-Fisher
2013b)
Our modern world may shrink due to common interest while the physical and emotional
resources necessary to house us become more and more constrained. Such constraints can
place undue burden on the state of health among urban dwellers. (Battle-Fisher 2013b)
The selection of these components was important not only to assure the integrity of
the model but also demonstrate the macro/micro levels in decision making. Macro
level meant segregation. Micro level in the model translated to the level of accepted
tolerance for social diversity.
Schelling (2006) found a threshold point that people can tolerate until that point
becomes undesired. In order for Schelling’s model to be completed, balanced math-
ematically, the model exhibits too much randomness to even be achieved. Schelling
created “happiness (mathematical) rules” for expressing threshold-based preferenc-
es toward segregation (Schelling 2006). If an agent’s tolerance for diversity was low
in accordance to the mathematical rules. the agent would flee in the model. Racial
tolerance was defined mathematically as being ‘happy’ but staying put (Schelling
2006). But his model was still based on rules. Practically, these outcomes translate
to everyone in that neighborhood being happy with their personal welfare with the
residential mix based in part on the mobilization efforts. Living as one is sometimes
saccharine.
When an individual under peer influence duplicates the exact action of another
(such as leaving a neighborhood), this is called an exodus tip that occurs due to a
departure from a system. If one person moves into the system and another leaves
that system, this is known as a genesis tip. No neighborhood can sustain a balance of
equal representations based on a social attribute such as race. The index of dissimi-
larity shows the extent of that imbalance. Card, Mas, and Rothstein (2008) found,
using US Census Track data from 1970 to 2000, that the threshold or tipping point
for white flight was higher for communities that exhibited a higher race-based toler-
ance. The tipping points ranged from “5–20 % minority share” (Card et al. 2008).
Where does this white flight tipping point leave urban revitalization projects?
Gentrification policies move individuals with financial means into often in-
come-depressed neighborhoods in order to lift up and bring back the neighborhood.
An approach that does not account for the complete actions of agents regrettably
underestimates the dialectic of connection, choice, and social function. Does the
Schelling model still apply in the same way today? How is this tipping affecting the
framing of urban housing policy? Policies can help to move bodies into shared so-
cial spaces. But those bodies with means are ambulatory. Lack of opportunity clips
wings hampering a flight of another kind. Aspiration is often trampled by poverty.
A child that lived in the now-demolished Cabrini Green formerly splicing Chi-
cago’s Near North Side sky view spent years co-existing, and surviving with people
that loved or loathed each other. How does that child with a Cabrini identity then
leverage finding and maintaining beneficial ties outside of that Cabrini space in a
gentrified neighborhood? Distance apart may not make the heart grow fonder. As
previously discussed, homophily is a social characteristic describing the tendency
to share one or more attributes. In terms of social and racial disparities, someone
may gravitate to someone for knowing his pain.
Marginalized groups are often inundated with social hazards buoyed by dimin-
ished chances of physical migration (leaving). Therefore the structure of the social
network may become more salient. A person is less likely to flee undesirable social
circumstances without the social and financial resources to do it. Also a person for
Policy Affecting and Targeting Underserved and Vulnerable Populations 81
the sake of keeping support nearby may choose to forego leaving. Individuals with
the fewest ties to reach a person or who shared a social attribute were found to be
effective in supporting homophily (Kossinets and Watts 2009).
Sterman (2000) warned us to not become complacent by the faulty belief systems
that worship the quest for “side effects” and their presumed effects on policy.
According to Sterman (2000), a realized effect is “just an effect”, not a “side effect”.
The dynamic “effects” are either:
1. Main or intended effects—the good ones that the policy intended in the first
place
2. Signs of an “understanding of a system that is narrow or flawed” leading to unde-
sired ones (mistakenly called side effects). (Sterman 2000)
Some policies could possibly be adequate if enacted true to spirit resulting in de-
sired main effects. Unsuccessful effects and feedback undermine the original inten-
tion of the policy. It is agreed that policies must be well crafted and actionable but
sometimes effects crop up that come out of left field. The landfall of the effects of
a policy does not always match up with the anticipated outcomes upon which the
policy was based. Sterman (2000) contended that with complexity comes a long-
time horizon from cause to effect.
Failure to recognize the feedbacks in which we are embedded, the way in which we shape
the situation in which we find ourselves, leads to policy resistance as we persistently react
to the symptoms of difficulty, intervening at low leverage points and triggering delayed
and distant, but powerful feedbacks. The problem intensifies, and we react by pulling those
same policy levers with renewed vigor, at the least wasting our talents and energy, and all
too often, triggering an unrecognized vicious cycle that carries us farther and farther from
our goals. (Sterman 2002)
The US Department of Housing and Urban Development (HUD) reframed urban re-
vitalization as a 10-year Section 8 voucher Moving to Opportunity (MTO) program
in New York, Los Angeles, Chicago, Boston, and Baltimore that transplanted lower
SES families into more affluent neighborhoods (see Feins et al.1996). Interested
in the main effects that such migration may have on the adolescents of volunteer
families relocated under the vouchers, Kessler et al. (2014) conducted a randomized
study with three groups:
1. Experimental group 1 with voucher, counseling, and adjustment assistance
2. Experimental group 2 with voucher and no additional support services
3. Control group with no voucher
Network research has found strong evidence that lower-rated health has been tied to
homogeneity and bond formation. Young people tend to seek the support of peers.
Assessment and Evaluation of Health Policy 83
The intended main effect of the policy was to expose lower-income families to
increased social capital and opportunity. Young men were found to be adversely
affected by depression, posttraumatic stress syndrome, and conduct disorder in both
experimental groups when compared to the control (Kessler et al. 2014). But here
is a lesson for the policy. Girls were found to be far more resilient and the moves
were statistically protective. Development of a policy may have differing effects on
the collective family unit as well as the welfare of the individuals themselves. The
authors stated that “it is difficult to draw policy implications…policy will have to
grapple with this complexity based on the realization that no policy decision will
have benign effects on both boys and girls” (Kessler et al. 2014).
“Things take time” in policy to assess success (see Meadows 1999). What systems
policy offers is not the advisement of the current policy decision, “but rather on how
to change policies that will guide future decisions” (Forrester 2007). Ethically and
politically, how much time is comfortable for policymakers to let things play out?
The power in using systems to examine policy lies in its ability to offer insight on
84 9 Social Disparity, Policy, and Sharing in Public Health
how a policy decision made now might cause systemic ripples based on the chang-
ing social conditions (Forrester 2007).
The structure is already present as the voucher program was already in place and
had already started its effects on the families as well as the affected neighborhoods.
Intact families move lives together but members’ lives in effect can take different
trajectories. The house is a home perhaps only for some. The fabric of the neighbor-
hoods tipped. Systems thinking teaches that every system at the local level may not
mirror the expectations of effects at the global level. An element at work in a system
cannot and must not be divorced from the larger effect that element presents on the
integrity of the system. What we have to consult is the current state of the research.
As the social tides change, we have changes flowing in and among overlapping ele-
ments and systems.
First, policymakers must honestly assess whether the policy indeed leads to the
effect that is wanted in the first place for the populations targeted as a popula-
tion as well as local collectives (see Sterman 2000). Models from Kossinets and
Watts (2009) additionally found that “forward looking” individuals have a greater
penchant to get closer to people that they want in their network. But what forward
thinking could marginalized populations call upon when social capital is bankrupt?
I contend that the some strictures on civil society constrict people unapologetically.
Bourdieu places the ability to have power gained over one’s personal situation (so-
cial capital) squarely into networked relationships (Bourdieu and Wacquant 1992).
The “habitus”, as coined by Bourdieu, is a person’s subjectivity of experience which
takes place in the “field”.
Networks support social capital or share the lament. Portes and Sensenbrenner
(1993) argued that social capital must be redefined, as “expectations for action
within a collectivity”. The parameter often targeted by urban policy is to move
people to a new land of opportunity—a new abode, a new school, a new job with
promises of a better life. It is painted as removing the underprivileged to a public
space askew in its allowance of economic and social opportunity. What of the bod-
ies that are being moved? While systems have antiquity that lingers, policies have a
legacy that leaves its own residue of feedbacks behind.
References
Ajrouch K, Antonucci T, Janevic M (2001) Social networks among blacks and whites: the interac-
tion between race and age. J Gerontol B Psychol Sci Soc Sci 56(2):S112–S118
Battle-Fisher M (2013a) The heavy load of agency on health: Anna Julia Cooper, race and gender.
Orgcomplexity blog. http://wp.me/p32x8n-q. Accessed 19 June 2014
Battle-Fisher M (2013b) Urban greenspace and collective health ownership. Mindful Nat 6(3):33–
35. http://www.humansandnature.org/urban-greenspace-and-collective-health-ownership-arti-
cle-159.php?issue=21. Accessed 14 April 2014
Bott E (1957) Family and social networks. Tavistock, London
Bourdieu P, Wacquant LJD (1992) An invitation to reflexive sociology. University of Chicago,
Chicago
Cacioppo J, Hawkley L (2003) Social isolation and health, with an emphasis on underlying mecha-
nisms. Perspect Biol Med 46(3 Suppl):S39–S52
References 85
Card D, Mas A and Rothstein J (2008) Tipping and the dynamics of segregation. J Econ
123(1):177–218
Cooper A-J (1988) A voice from the south. Oxford University Press, New York
Cornwell E, Waite J (2009) Social disconnectiveness, perceived isolation and health among older
adults. J Health Soc Behav 50(1):31–48
Crenshaw KW (1994) Mapping the margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence
Against Women of Color. The public nature of private violence. (eds) Martha Albertson Fine-
man and Rixanne Mykitiuk. Routledge, New York:93–118
DuBois, WEB (1965) The souls of black folk. In: Franklin JH (ed) Three Negro classics. Avon,
New York
Feins JD, Holin MJ, Phipps A (1996) Moving to opportunity for fair housing program operations
manual. Abt Associates, Cambridge
Fischer C (1982). To dwell among friends: personal networks in town and city. University of
Chicago Press, Chicago
Forrester J (2007) System dynamics—the next fifty years. Syst Dyn Rev 23(2/3):359–370
Giddens A (1979) Central problems in social theory: action, structure, and contradiction in social
analysis. University of California Press, Los Angeles
Harvey D (2001) Chaos and complexity: their bearing on social policy research social issues.
http://www.whb.co.uk/socialissues/harvey.htm. Accessed 15 April 2014
Jackson L, Langille L, Lyons R, Hughes J, Martin D, Winstaley V (2009) Does moving from a
high-poverty to lower-poverty neighborhood improve mental health? A realist review of ‘mov-
ing to opportunity’. Health Place 15(4):961–970
Kessler R, Duncan G, Gennetian L, Kling J, Sampson N, Sanbonmatsu L, Zaslavsky AM, Ludwig
J (2014). Associations of housing mobility interventions for children in high-poverty neighbor-
hoods with subsequent mental disorders during adolescence. JAMA 311(9):937–47
Kossinets G, Watts D (2009) Origins of homophily in an evolving social network. Am J Sociol
115(2):405–450
Leventhal T, Brooks-Gunn J (2003). Moving to opportunity: an experimental study of neighbor-
hood effects on mental health. Am J Publ Health 93(9):1576–1582
Leventhal T, Dupéré V (2011) Moving to opportunity: does long-term exposure to “low-poverty”
neighborhoods make a difference for adolescents? Soc Sci Med 73(5):737–743
Lin N (2000) Inequality of social capital. Contemp Sociol 29:785–795
Louch H (2000) Personal network integration: transitivity and homophily in strong-tie relations.
Soc Netw 22:45–64
Marsden P (1987) Core discussion networks of Americans. Am Socio Rev 52(1):122–131
Meadows D (1999) Leverage points: places to intervene in a system. The Sustainability Institute,
Hartland
Phelan J, Link B, Tehranifar P (2010) Social conditions as fundamental causes of health inequali-
ties- theory, evidence and policy implications. J Health Soc Behavior 51:s28–40
Portes A, Sensenbrenner J (1993) Embeddedness and Immigration: notes on the social determi-
nants of economic action. Am J Sociol 98(6):1320–1350
Resincow K, Page S (2008) Embracing chaos and complexity: a quantum change for public health.
Am J Publ Health 98:1382–1389
Schelling TC (2006.) Micromotives and macrobehavior. Norton, New York
Sterman J (2000) Business dynamics—systems thinking and modeling for a complex world. Mc-
Graw Hill, Boston
Sterman J (2002) All models are wrong: reflections on becoming a systems scientist. Syst Dyn
Rev 18:501–531
Verbrugge L (1979) Marital status and health. J Marriage Fam 41:267–85
Chapter 10
The Concentric Model of Health-Bound
Networks
Introduction
The roles become muddled with roles that support health and others that result from
nonmedical reasons. It may be a foredawn conclusion that the person’s quality of
life (QOL) stays just that—inherent to a personal experience with disease. More-
over, QOL is often analogous to length of life and prognosis. What if the patient
believes that life is fine as it has been dealt, imperfect clinically but personally ac-
ceptable (or tolerated)? What happens when the self-care decisions of a patient run
counter to the evidence-based prescriptivism of medical care? There is a blurring of
the penumbras of the public and private spheres in our understanding of QOL. The
complexity of social relationships and support requires policy for social integration
has been shown to be linked to both physical and mental health. As the patient is
embedded into a support network, I additionally posit that there is a “shared” collec-
tive QOL on the microlevel by which caring others are affected by the life state of
the patient. It is an interesting question to explore the final victor in QOL: the psy-
chometrically measured QOL which is constructed by the “others” in the medical
establishment or a patient’s subjective understandings of a sick existence. In light of
generational issues of longevity with decreased physical and mental functionalities
of patients, what must not be ignored is the network of support.
A verbal model is better than no model at all, or a model which, because it can be formu-
lated mathematically, is forcibly imposed upon and falsifies reality […] It may be prefer-
able first to have some nonmathematical model with its shortcomings but expressing some
previously unnoticed aspects, hoping for future development of a suitable algorithm, than
to start with premature mathematical models following known algorithms and, therefore,
possibly restricting the field of vision (von Bertalanffy1968).
Earlier versions of this chapter were presented at 2011 Aging and Society: An Interdisciplinary
Conference, University of California, Berkeley, CA, and the 2012 Aging and Society: An
Interdisciplinary Conference, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada.
© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015 87
M. Battle-Fisher, Application of Systems Thinking to Health Policy & Public
Health Ethics, SpringerBriefs in Public Health, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-12203-8_10
88 10 The Concentric Model of Health-Bound Networks
Social relationships, or the relative lack thereof, constitute a major risk factor for health—
rivaling the effect of well-established health-risk factors such as cigarette smoking, blood
pressure, blood lipids, obesity, and physical activity. (House et al. 1988)
Pervasive poor QOL marks society’s as a measure of the state of the public’s overall
health. There are social and economic implications to acting as a paternalistic ward
of the nation’s health. The concepts of personal autonomy and collective autonomy
at first blush appear to be incongruent at best. Healthy patients demand a “better”
QOL as an inalienable right of getting treated. Do the concerned others also have
some “say” in what QOL should and must be for the patient? The fact that the so-
ciety has become so vocalized at midterm elections bodes the concern of where the
line between personal autonomy and collective self-governance come together. Is
there a duty (as an appendage of “autonomy”) that asks for duty not to merely act in
one’s own interest but also that of the collective?
While autonomy is often presented as a hallmark of medical ethics, autonomy is
best framed with degrees of variation. It cannot be ignored that there can be social
influence from others on patients. Socially constructed autonomy differs from the
vanilla version as there is an assumed outside influence on the QOL of a patient.
The effect of collective autonomy is shown as the rights are afforded within a self-
governing network. Take the case of a family that has been stricken with end-stage
renal disease (ESRD). There may be apathy to the perceived benefit of proper self-
care and the quest for the elusive QOL that the clinicians expound as the Holy Grail.
Other family members have languished on dialysis and complied at varying degrees
toward “better QOL” and still died. A young person ran away but returned. This
emotive back story could have grave consequences on compliance within the per-
son’s network. So what is the use of complying with physician’s directives or social
services when the network expresses discontent with the patient’s health choices?
Joanne Lynn (2014) of the Center for Elder Care and Advances Illness of the Al-
tarum Institute wrote that in observance of US caregiver policy there is a misplaced
“overinvestment in health care and an underinvestment in support services” in a
Journal of the American Medical Association editorial. While policies have placed
insufficient priority in abating the stress on caregivers, patients continue to age and
caregivers continue to be overburdened. The caregivers often are regulated to piece
together support mechanisms, often to the detriment of the caregivers’ own social
integration (Lynn 2014).
Disability compels engaged nodes in a support network. The demographic shift
could result in an older, more infirm population that will have a more profound
demand of caregivers. According to projections of The US Department of Health
and Human Services, by 2050, the number of individuals over the age of 65 will
double from projections in 2010 (Department of Health and Human Services n.d.).
The policy must act to temper the burden of costs for medical care in light of the
Concentric Model for Health-Bound Networks 89
skyrocketing number of aging boomers around the bend. While those on dialysis
aged 65 and over have fallen in absolute numbers, QOL and life expectancy falls
severely as an ESRD patient initiating dialysis at 65 or older (Tamura et al. 2012;
United States Renal Data System 2013)
An exemplary model for the integration of federal oversight and nonprofit organi-
zation was created when US Congress passed the National Organ Transplant Act
(NOTA) in 1984. The act established the Organ Procurement and Transplantation
Network (OPTN) to maintain a national registry of organ allocation and lead the
on-the-ground charge in attacking health disparities in ESRD. Unfortunately, not
enough kidneys are available so patients turn to long-term caregiving. The reality
is that the kidneys are not keeping pace. The patients get older. Policy must also
account for the life on dialysis. People have to keep continue on with damaged
nephrons. “Donate life” but ESRD patients press on, abiding by the rules and con-
strictions of health disparities dampening QOL. Reality becomes “donate” caregiv-
ing support so the ESRD patient can “live” waiting for a kidney. From a clinical
standpoint, a kidney or even dialysis may not improve life expectancy and QOL,
which are among the main reasons for the clinical interventions.
We need primary care providers to facilitate health care decisions for the dyad—to think
about each decision as it affects a 78-year-old man with Alzheimer’s and how it affects his
74-year-old female caregiver. We need to think beyond patient-centered care to dyadic-
centered care or even caregiver-centered care.
(Rosenthal 2014)
Fig. 10.1 The Concentric Model of Health-bound Networks (CMHN). CMHN visualizes changes
in social support network composition. The ego (denoted by a triangle in the kidney network) is
the patient in question. There are overlapping networks in the model’s four spheres: the ‘kidney’
network (which may more generally be labelled the health network), the general well-being net-
work, the social network, and the polis
The Health Network The health network is the core and most inner sphere of the
model (Fig. 10.1). It should be noted that the exemplar in Fig. 10.1 is labeled “kid-
ney network” allowing nominalization based on the illness narrative under inves-
tigation. This label would be open to change based on the illness being explored;
for instance, the inner sphere may read “breast cancer network” as research has
shown that QOL has been best measured as disease specific. The network revolves
around the “ego” patient who is connected to other nodes. Specifically, members
of this “kidney” sphere would include the ESRD patient (the ego), and socially
invested alters (defined as caregivers or concerned, active others). Everyone in a
network is interdependent in the mathematical and social sense. Remember that
networks by definition embrace and account for interdependence both theoretically
and mathematically.
As a strong tie or linked relationship, the nature of engagement could be more
engaged and fortified within a network so there can be encouragement and trust
among the members of the network (White and Houseman 2002). Carpenter, Es-
terling and Lazer (2003) found in a simulation model of health political networks
that increased burden of involvement in the affairs of the networks depended most
on strong ties. Strong ties can be socially depleting, requiring with five times the
Concentric Model for Health-Bound Networks 91
maintenance effort over weak ties (Carpenter et al. 2003). The engagement in culti-
vating such strong ties, which are often kinship based, is time and resource intensive
(Granovetter 1973). What if there are instances where a strong tie could be more
optimal for social support? Within this sphere where there is an expectation of high
support, a person with a more casual interest (weaker tie) might prove harmful to
the health of the kidney network. Is it just best to leave them be and let them sashay
away or lumber away with a gait rattled by conscience? The answer in terms of
chronic disease outcome management may not so simple.
The General Well-Being Network and the Social Network As illustrated in
Fig. 10.1, the second most inner sphere, general well-being network, refers to a
larger network including health network and active caregivers in life situations who
may not exclusively be health related. The third most inner sphere is the “social
network”, a yet larger network which may also include probable and inactive care-
givers. This would be the location of individuals with a more casual social role. But
what will keep him or her there over the long haul?
The “Polis” Network Within the CMHN©, I refer to the polis in Fig. 10.1 as the
“public” sphere or the general population affected by population health. The term
“polis” is borrowed from the city–state of Aristotelian politic as it illustrated the
expansive and intertwined nature of community formation (see Aristotle 1959). The
polis is infinite in size but for illustration, the sphere is given an outside boundary
in the model (see Fig. 10.1). Newman (2003) noted the futility of trying to capture
representation of all possible members. What we will catch is what is named and
available for inclusion in the analysis. The individuals exclusively found only in
the outer ring of the polis may come to understand QOL as a politically driven or
policy-based concern as opposed to an intimate discourse connected to the patient
in question.
These spheres and their networks are possibly more meaningful over time. Be-
cause there will be losses due in the future, the effect of such loss can be captured
mathematically. Real-world networks may be more resistant to the random loss of
nodes from a network (Newman 2003). However, the tolerance of loss is allowable
only to a point. For instance, Albert (2000), using World Wide Web simulations,
supported the inherent resistance to random loss of alters. However, when actors
were randomly lost at a rate as low as 7 % within a single network, it proved detri-
mental to the health of the network (Albert et al. 2000).
How can the movement across networks be conceptualized? Two distinct pro-
cesses could mark this movement across spheres and embedded networks:
1. Direct migration
2. Intermediary migration
Direct and intermediary migration within CMHN©, as illustrated in Fig. 10.2, visu-
alized the movement as gain/loss of nodes across the spheres that occur over time:
1. Either through a direct ultimate path within a finality in destination (direct) or
2. Via a series of intermediate steps across spheres to a new support role (indirect)
92 10 The Concentric Model of Health-Bound Networks
Fig. 10.2 Direct and intermediary migration patterns in CMHN. For illustration, the ego is ‘Shir-
ley’ denoted by the triangle in the kidney network. The arrows (explained in the legend to the right)
visualize possible patterns of gain and loss of support (nodes) over time
The patient’s illness initially defines why these health-bound networks exist. The
patient or ego is unique as she or he serves as a core, as the pretext for its very
existence. Nodes migrate in and out of closeness and nodes’ roles with the patient
around with the social support evolve. This form of complexity is a dynamic and
continuous reorganization of the actors (Halley and Winkler 2008). People come.
People go. Ideally, a person that comes, stays, helps, and influences positively is a
node worth fussing over to stay invested.
Understanding the migration patterns will require policymakers to have a spe-
cific study period in mind (time x to time y). Direct migration means that a person
moves from one sphere (and its network) to another with no intermediate steps to
reach the final destination. A change of role from intimate engagement to no contact
at all could be illustrated by a change in medical provider. There is no other support
role to be served other than the clinical role. Is that clinician replaced in the network
with one that will engage or engage more than the lost node? The nephrologist will
not be taking the patient to the store. So the clinician skips to the polis (e.g., the
patient is no longer a patient in the nephrology practice). This is a situation where
replacement of nodes becomes important to support with policy. Social networks
are organic in the sense that each thrives and is constrained by the social environ-
ment. Policy is tied beyond a nudge to the public. Networks affect choices and
toggle with ethics. Members of a network self-organize (Halley and Winkler 2008).
Choices and their resultant (un)ethical actions bolster or torpedo adherence and
benefits to the collective.
Concentric Model for Health-Bound Networks 93
could help later. The structural folds are power brokers to combat “out of sight, out
of mind.” Now whether that information is truthful or even helpful is a question for
another day. Whether that power is used for good or personal gain is another issue.
If this becomes the case in this model, a strong tie may only remain effort intensive
when called upon and the intercohesion may have a better chance of successfully
supporting a network. The prior existence of a more intimate tie may, under the
context of Jack’s (2005) work, reactivate and become an active tie again. The point
would be to work on maintaining ties with support persons in order for the tie to be
reactivated in the future if the node becomes distal. Maintaining support networks
does not just happen spontaneously and its inertia may work for or against health
outcomes.
There is a fundamental misconception to mistake for a “problem” what actually is only
a mathematical “exercise.” One would do well to remember the old Kantian maxim that
experience without theory is blind, but theory without experience is a mere intellectual play.
(von Bertalanffy1962)
Allegorically, for a moment, imagine a tie as an elastic band. Elastic bands bounce
back into the shape even after it is stretched. A physical band possesses resilient
properties, just like a network tie. When the two ends of the band are held taut, the
force exerted between the two ends is tension. The band without an outside source
pulling it will not exhibit tension. As such, in order for a node to be meaningful
in most cases, there is a tie to another node. The exception to this condition is the
isolate, one that is within the network boundary but unconnected to another node.
Without delving into molecular, heat properties which play a huge role in the elas-
tic’s integrity, the elastic band that is overstretched always breaks off in the middle.
The middle between the two nodes (rubber tie) is actually the cross section with
the highest amount of tension. The length of the social elastic tie can be short or
elongated. Recall that there are three characteristics to a tie: tie strength, intensity,
and time duration (Borgatti and Halgin 2011). When the “elastic” tie begins to wear
due in part to the characteristics just mentioned or also exogenous factors outside of
a system, the resources or the will to stay connected may weaken the middle cross
section of the tie between the two nodes. It is not the tension on the band pulling the
ends apart that is the culprit toward physical breakage. The band breaks due to the
amount of stress at its thinnest part. What is the point where fractures in the tie in
social support can be avoided? How can policy help to circumvent social elastic tie
failure, which breaks and then no longer exist?
As mentioned previously, the robustness of real networks is more real due to
the exhibition of strong social organizational properties (Gao et al. 2012). If the
network is larger, then that threshold may be more difficult to reach. It may be
unrealistic to expect policy alone to increase substantially support networks large
enough to tolerate such losses. However, if policy can serve to lessen the chance
of losing people in the first place, that may be more plausible for policymakers to
References 95
tackle. For instance, does a community have policies in place to increase support for
caregivers to lessen the probability of burnout and fatigue? Is the policy leveraging
what actually fights the burnout? In turn, adding the complexity of interdependent
networks, loss of actors in any network can lead to a cascade of failures that rever-
berates across all networks (Gao et al. 2012). However, actor and tie failures are the
main culprits to its overall stability. In other words, the realities of caregiving and
living with the stress of ESRD may lead to losses of support ties and movements of
support across spheres to a lesser intensive role.
There are exogenous parameters in a dynamic system insidiously at work, har-
kening Meadows’ (1999, 2008) point of the often phantom nature of systemic feed-
backs. I propose that social factors and stressors that affect social ties to supply
valuable information for policymakers. While all of the following could possibly
be framed as feedbacks, I ask that we take a moment to pay specific attention to the
minutiae of a tie. What societal forces can create brittle ties that are so desperately
needed for the sake of the patient? Mische (2011) wrote that to assure the relational
durability within a network, the ties are those comprised of “shared history and
values.” Some time ago, the work of Rapoport (1953) said that we may only add
to our friendships as we have access to. But often the biases become inexplicably
tied to our life chances, those latent tentacles that push and pull on us often without
us knowing. It does really become about who we know and who is giving up the
goods, both as a structural and political phenomenon. From ordinary language to
mathematical modeling, this is an interesting question for policy to acknowledge
what hazards befalling chronically ill patients and their networks might be willing
to shoulder.
References
Albert R, Jeong H, Barabasi A-L (2000) Attack and error tolerance of complex networks. Nature
406:378–382
Allen T (1977) Managing the flow of technology. MIT Press, Cambridge
Aristotle (1991) On rhetoric. A theory of civic discourse. Translated by Kennedy G. Oxford
University Press, New York
Barnes JA (1974) Social networks. An Addison-Wesley module in anthropology. Addison-Wesley,
Reading, pp 1–29
Battle-Fisher M (2013) Urban greenspce and collective health ownership. Mindful Nature
6(3):33–35. http://www.humansandnature.org/urban-greenspace-and-collective-health-owner-
ship-article-159.php?issue=21. Accessed 14 April 2014
Borgatti S, Halgin D (2011) On network theory. Organ Sci 22(5):1168–1181
Burt R (1992) Structural holes: the social structure of competition. Harvard University Press,
Boston
Burt R (2004) Structural holes and good ideas. Am J Sociol 110:349–399
Carpenter D, Esterling K, Lazer D (2003) The strength of strong ties—a model of contact making
in policy networks with evidence from U.S. health politics. Ration Soc 15(4):411–440
Cooper A-J (1988) A voice from the south. Oxford University Press, New York
Cornwell B, Schumm L, Laumann E, Graber J (2009) Social networks in the NSHAP Study:
rationale, measurement and preliminary findings. J Gerontol B Psychol Sci Soc 64B(Suppl 1):
i47–55
96 10 The Concentric Model of Health-Bound Networks
Cornwell E, Waite L (2009). Social disconnectedness, perceived isolation and health among older
adults. J Health Soc Behav 50(1):31–48
Department of Health and Human Services, Administration on Aging (n.d.) Projected future
growth of the older population, population 85 and over by sex: 1900–2050. http://www.aoa.
gov/Aging_Statistics/future_growth/future_growth.aspx. Accessed 12 June 2014
Everett M, Borgatti S (1998) Analyzing clique overlap. Connections 21(1):49–61
Feld S (1981) The focused organization of social ties. Am J Sociol 86(5):105–1035
Feld S, Carter W (1998) Foci of activities as changing contexts for friendship. In: Adams R, Allan
G (eds) Placing friendship in context. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Gao J, Buldyrev S, Stanley H, Havlin S (2012) Networks formed from interdependent networks.
Nat Phys. doi:10.1038/NPHYS2180
Granovetter M (1973) The strength of weak ties. Am J Psychol 78(9):1360–1380
Gregson J, Foerster S, Orr R, Jones L, Benedict J, Clark B, … Zotz K (2001) System, environ-
mental, and policy changes: using the social-ecological model as a framework for evaluating
nutrition education and social marketing programs with low-income audiences. J Nutr Educ
33(Suppl 1):4–15. doi:10.1016/S1499-4046(06)60065-1
Halley J, Winkler D (2008) Classification of emergence and its relationship to self-organization.
Complexity 13:10–15
Hansen M (1999) The search-transfer problem: the role of weak ties in sharing knowledge across
organizational subunits. Admin Sci Q 36:82–111
House JS, Landis KR, Umberson D (1988) Social relationships and health. Science 241:540–545
Jack S (2005) The role, use and activation of strong and weak network ties: a qualitative study. J
Manag Stud 42(6):1233–1256
Kossinets G, Watts D (2009) Origins of homophily in an evolving social network. Am J Sociol
115(2):405–450
Long J, Cunningham F, Braithwaite J (2013) Bridges, brokers and boundary spanners in collabora-
tive networks: a systematic review. BMC Health Serv Res 13:158
Louch H (2000) Personal network integration: transitivity and homophily in strong-tie relations.
Soc Netw 22:45–64
Lynn J (2014) Strategies to ease the burden of family caregivers. JAMA 311(10):1021–1022
Meadows D (1999) Leverage points: places to intervene in a system. The Sustainability Institute,
Hartland
Meadows D (2008) Thinking in systems: a primer. Chelsea Green, River Junction
Mische A (2011) Relational sociology, culture and agency. In: Scott J, Carrington P (eds) The
SAGE handbook of social network analysis. Sage, London
Newman N (2003) The structure and function of complex networks. SIAM Review 45:167–256.
Palla G, Derenyi I, Frakas I, Vicsek T (2005) Uncovering the overlapping community structure of
complex networks in nature and society. Nature. doi:10.1038/nature03607
Rapoport A (1953) A marginalized network highlights both the mathematical finiteness as well as
socio-political constriction on life chances. Bull Math Biophys 15:523–533
Rosenthal M (2014) Caregiver-centered care. JAMA 311(10):1015–1016
Sterman J (2002) All models are wrong: reflections on becoming a systems scientist. Syst Dyn
Rev 18:501–531
Tamura MK, Tan J, O’Hare A (2012) Optimizing renal replacement therapy in older adults—a
framework for making individualized decisions. Kidney Int 82(2):261–269
United States Renal Data System (2013) USRDS 2013 annual data report: atlas of chronic kidney
disease and end-stage renal disease in the United States. National Institutes of Health, National
Institute of Diabetes and Digestive and Kidney Diseases, Bethesda
Vedres B, Stark D (2010) Structural folds: generative disruption in overlapping groups. Am J
Sociol 1115(4):1150–1190
von Bertalanffy L (1962) General system theory—a critical review. Gen Syst 7:1–20
von Bertalanffy L (1968) General system theory—foundations, development, applications. Bra-
ziller, New York
White D, Houseman M (2002) Navigability of strong ties: small worlds, tie strength and network
topology. Complexity 8(1):72–81
Index
A Health Network, 90
agents, 24 social network, 91
rational, 53 spheres, 89
Tipping Model, 79 Concentric Model of Health-Bound Networks,
alters, 88, 90 94
random loss, 91 Consequences of human action, 3
autonomy, 88
and self-realization, 57 D
as a rule of the system, 70 decision support systems
degrees of variation, 88 Veterans Health Administration, 16
effect of the public, 58 DuBois, WEB, 26
tipping point for social welfare, 26 Dworkin, R., 26
Dynamic Adaptive Policy Pathways, 10
B
Bertalanffy, L., 6, 16, 87, 94 E
binary decision-making, 53 emergence with shared purpose, 93
Borgatti and Halgin, 29, 30 emotions in decision making, 25
Burt, 30 ethical mallebility
actualization, 57
C ethics, 25
Caregiving and ESRD, 95 and action, 57
categories of potential organ donors, 62 as innovation, 57
including conversation and feedback ethos, 25
mechanisms, 62
centrality and opinion leaders in ethical F
deliberation, 57 faulty sensemaking and policy failure, 82
CMHN See Concentric Model of Health- feedback
Bound Networks, 89 and innovation in ethical networks, 57
collective behavior as leverage point, 70
proximity and celebrity, 52 negative, 17
Collective kidney, 64 positive, 17
complexity versus \weather\ experience, 54
structure and agency, 79 flows
uninsurance policy, 73 principle of accumulation, 69
Veterans Health Administration, 16 rates of change, 69
Concentric Model of Health-Bound Networks Ford and Sterman, 54
direct and intermediary migration, 93 Forrester, J., 74
General Well-being Network, 91
© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015 97
M. Battle-Fisher, Application of Systems Thinking to Health Policy & Public
Health Ethics, SpringerBriefs in Public Health, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-12203-8
98 Index
G Marginalized networks
General System Theory See Bertalanffy, L., 6 in urban policy, 80
Georgia Health Policy Center, 72 Meadows, D., 17, 55, 77
goal of the system mental model, 73, 87
as leverage point, 70 methodological consilience, 8
Granovetter, M., 52 Microworlds, 67
Mill, JS, 27
H morality in an open system, 58
Habermas See public sphere, private sphere, Moving to Opportunity (MTO) housing policy
24 Mental health among black youth, 82
health disparities in End Stage Renal Disease, research studies, 83
89 Moving to Opportunity (MTO) housing policy,
health disparity, 61, 77 84
heteronomy of values, 61
heuristics, 25 N
homophily, 45, 80, 93 National Organ Transplant Act, 89
cultural and political, 25 network formation
status, 79 and social engagement, 29
versus peer effect, 53 nodes, 30
migration in social support, 91
I
impure paternalism See Dworkin, R., 26 O
informal versus formal structure opinion leaders in ethical deliberation, 57
Veterans Health Administration, 15 overlapping influences
information flow, 70 and public health, 25
Concentric Model of Health-Bound
Networks, 93 P
inter-cohesion paradigm shifts
structural fold, 93 as leverage point, 70
isolation in social networks, 81 Pareto efficiency, 26
peer effect, 44
K peer network, 25
Kidney network See Health network, 90 personal liberty and social utility, 27
kinship, 90 policy, 3
family, 29 and main effects, 82
combating loss of social support, 94
L creation, 3
leverage points effect on private and public, 4
12 places to intervene from Meadows, 71 failure to maximize benefits, 12
delays in the system, 70 global policy versus targeted policy, 82
feedbacks, 70 ratification and existing policies, 72
information flow, 70 role in social support, 95
nodes, 70 side effects, 12
paradigm shifts, 70 use of systems for early conditions of the
self-organization, 70 policy, 74
stocks and flows, 70 policymaking
linear approach to policy making, 10 available information and decision making,
7
M reflective conversation and simulation, 74
main effect, 18 systemic questions to pose in
mandatory influenza vaccinations, 24 policymaking, 72
marginalized networks policy memo, 12
social constriction under policy, 84 policy resistance, 55
polis, 91
Index 99
T Tipping Model, 80
the Other, 79 Tobacco policy
threshold tolerance Australian, 19
rule based, 79
tie U
elastic, 94 urban housing policy, 81
maintenance effort, 90
Tipping Model V
components, 79 valves
exodus tip, 80 variation and implications for policy, 69
genesis tip, 80 Veterans Health Administration
threshold, 80 scheduling policies, 15
VHA See Veterans Health Administration, 12