001 Camus On The Absurd
001 Camus On The Absurd
“There is only one truly serious philosophical problem, and that is suicide. Judging whether life is or
is not worth living amounts to answering the fundamental question of philosophy.” – Albert Camus
It might seem flippant to remark that the essential question in philosophy is “Should I kill myself?”
But the question of suicide rests on what Camus considered the essential human problem: the sense
in which our lives are entirely absurd. This essay will outline the origin and consequences of Camus’s
notion of the absurd from his 1942 The Myth of Sisyphus.[1]
There are many things we might naturally call absurd: a rude joke, an outrageous statement, or the
price of a pair of designer jeans.
This though is not what Camus means by “absurd.” For Camus, the absurd originates from a
combination of two things: the way we want the world to be and the way the world actually is.
About how we want the world to be, it just seems to be a part of human nature that we have a
sense of justice and fairness, and so we want the world to be just and fair: we want evil punished
and virtue rewarded. We also want to understand why bad things happen to good people, why good
things happen to bad people, why we’re here, where we’re going, and what it all means.
Concerning how things actually are, however, evil goes unpunished, good deeds often are not
rewarded, good things happen to bad people, bad things happen to good people, and we don’t
understand any of it. We just do not, and according to Camus, we cannot understand what we want
to understand.
Camus’s doctrine of the absurd then has both metaphysical and epistemological aspects. As a
metaphysical thesis, the absurd is a confrontation between the human mind and an indifferent
universe: what exists is a “mind that desires and the world that disappoints” (50). As an
epistemological thesis, the absurd highlights our desire to understand and the fundamental limits of
our knowledge.
Having diagnosed the essential human problem, Camus shifts his interest to prognosis, determining
whether and how to live in the face of the absurd.
The Myth of Sisyphus is primarily a critique of existentialism, specifically the attempts by thinkers
such as Kierkegaard, Jaspers, and Heidegger to overcome the absurd by appealing to God or the
transcendent. These thinkers, Camus claims, contradict themselves by presupposing that life is
absurd in some way, but proposing a solution to the absurd (so that life isn’t really absurd after all).
For example, Kierkegaard sees life as profoundly absurd, due to its central lack of meaning. He
thereby proposes that we take “a leap of faith,” essentially arguing that belief in God will ultimately
provide one’s life with meaning. Camus opposes this form of escapism, claiming that existentialists
“deify what crushes them and find reason to hope in what impoverishes them” (24).
Camus rejects appeals to the transcendent; for him, the absurd – the “divorce” between us and the
world – represents the inescapable human condition. As we’ll see, in place of the false hope of
religiosity, Camus advises a vivid awareness of the absurd and a form of revolt.
In Greek mythology, Sisyphus was condemned by the gods to the pointless task of rolling a large rock
up a mountain, only to watch the rock roll back down, and to repeat the task for eternity.
As a life filled entirely of mundane and trivial labor, Sisyphus’s existence is meant to illustrate the
futility (and absurdity) we confront in our own lives. Camus observes that a person’s life can
become, essentially, a mundane routine: “Rising, streetcar, four hours in the office or the factory,
meal, streetcar, four hours of work, meal, sleep, and Monday Tuesday Wednesday Thursday Friday
Saturday and Sunday according to the same rhythm…” (12-13).
Yet, for Camus, Sisyphus is not to be pitied. Sisyphus represents the “absurd hero” because he
chooses to live in the face of absurdity. This “choosing to live” is a matter of consciousness, for
through his attitude and outlook, Sisyphus can free himself from his punishment and triumph over
his situation without being able to change it. Sisyphus is aware of the full extent of his punishment:
he is fully conscious of the fate imposed on him by the gods and the utter futility of his existence. His
passion, freedom, and revolt, however, make him stronger than the punishment intended to crush
him.
Though it may seem odd, Camus indicates that Sisyphus is happy. By making his rock “his thing”
(123), Sisyphus finds joy in being. Perhaps the climb up becomes more comfortable over time:
maybe the muscles that once strained under the weight of the rock now effortlessly control it;
conceivably, the rock moves so gracefully upwards that the act of moving it becomes a work of art.
Through his freedom, Sisyphus revolts against the gods and refuses the futility of their punishment
by consciously living with passion. The rock, the mountain, the sky, and the dirt belong to him and
are his world. Sisyphus has no hope to change his situation but, nevertheless, he uses all that’s given
to and available for him.
4. Conclusion
Camus’s answer to the question of suicide is no. Camus insists that we must persist in the face of
absurdity and not give ourselves over to false hope; he ultimately suggests that life will be lived all
the better if it has no meaning.
It is up to us to live our lives with passion, freedom, and revolt – three consequences of the absurd –
or else we give in to false hope or even choose not to live at all. By embracing our passions and
absurd freedom, we can thus throw ourselves into the world with a desire to use all that’s given.
Though we can never reconcile the metaphysical and epistemological tensions that give rise to the
absurd, we can remember that the “point,” after all, is “to live” (65).