Logic and Critical Thinking Module
Logic and Critical Thinking Module
PREPARED BY:
AUGUST 2019
ADDIS ABABA, ETHIOPIA
COURSE OBJECTIVES...........................................................................................................................10
CHAPTER ONE........................................................................................................................................11
Chapter Overview..................................................................................................................................11
3.1 Metaphysics...........................................................................................................................20
3.2 Epistemology.........................................................................................................................22
4.1 Axiology................................................................................................................................27
4.2 Logic......................................................................................................................................30
Chapter Summary..................................................................................................................................33
References.............................................................................................................................................36
CHAPTER TWO.......................................................................................................................................37
Chapter Overview..................................................................................................................................37
Chapter Summary..................................................................................................................................83
CHAPTER THREE...................................................................................................................................87
Chapter Overview..................................................................................................................................87
Chapter Summary................................................................................................................................122
References...........................................................................................................................................125
CHAPTER FOUR...................................................................................................................................126
Chapter Summary................................................................................................................................161
References...........................................................................................................................................162
CHAPTER FIVE.....................................................................................................................................163
Chapter Overview................................................................................................................................163
Informal fallacies.................................................................................................................................168
Chapter Summary................................................................................................................................218
References...........................................................................................................................................219
CHAPTER SIX...................................................................................................................................220
CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS....................................................................................................220
Lesson 4: Evaluating Immediate Inferences: Using Venn Diagrams and Square of Oppositions........236
Chapter Summary................................................................................................................................251
Self-Check Exercises...........................................................................................................................251
References...........................................................................................................................................252
COURSE INTRODUCTION
Dear learners,
The course, Logic and Critical Thinking, is a high-level thought course in the discipline of
philosophy. It is a philosophical inquiry that takes argumentation and reasoning as its basic objects of
investigation and attempts to introduce the fundamental concepts of logic and methods of logical
argumentation and reasoning and critical thinking. It includes evaluation of the methods by which we
form beliefs, weigh evidence, assess hypotheses and arguments, and analyze reasoning. Logic is
concerned with the study of arguments, and it seeks to establish the conditions under which an argument
may be considered as acceptable or good. It includes the development of standard methods and principles
of arguments. Critical thinking is an exercise, a habit, a manner of perception and reasoning that
has principles of logic as its fulcrum, and dynamically involves various reasoning skills that
Therefore, this course is designed to help students to develop not only the ability to construct
reliable and logically defendable arguments of their own and rationally evaluate the arguments of
others, but also the abilities and skills of critical thinking. All education consists of transmitting
two different things to students: (1) the subject matter or discipline content of the course ("what
to think"), and (2) the correct way to understand and evaluate this subject matter ("how to
think"). We may do an excellent job of transmitting the content of our respective academic
disciplines, but we often fail to teach students how to think effectively about this subject matter,
that is, how to properly understand and evaluate it. That means, we often fail to teach how to
think critically. Hence, the primary aim of this course is to teach students essential skills of
analyzing, evaluating, and constructing arguments, and to sharpen their ability to execute the
skills in thinking and writing, and thus better prepare them to succeed in the world. The
understanding of the methods by which we develop our own arguments, form beliefs, weigh
evidence, assess hypotheses and arguments, and analyze reasoning will help you rationally
evaluate the credibility of claims and arguments you encounter in media, in everyday
conversation, and in the classroom. You will also learn to become aware of errors in reasoning
and judgment, which we all occasionally commit. Finally, you will learn to develop your own
arguments with clarity and precision.
COURSE OBJECTIVES
After the successful accomplishment of the course, students will able to:
Understand the basic essence and areas of philosophy, and the necessity of learning it;
Recognize the components and types of arguments;
Develop the skill to construct and evaluate arguments;
Understand the relationship between logic and language;
Recognize the forms of meanings of words and terms;
Comprehend the types, purposes and techniques of definitions;
Understand the concept, principles, and criteria of critical thinking;
1
In this teaching material, the terms “Chapter” and “Module” are equivalent and used interchangeably.
CHAPTER ONE
LOGIC AND PHILOSOPHY
Chapter Overview
Logic is often treated simultaneously as a field of study and as an instrument. As a field of study,
it is a branch of philosophy that deals with the study of arguments and the principles and
methods of right reasoning. As an instrument, it is something, which we can use to formulate our
own rational arguments and critically evaluate the soundness of others’ arguments. Before logic
itself has become a field of study, philosophers have been using it as a basic tool to investigate
issues that won their philosophical attention, such as, reality, knowledge, value, etc. Philosophy
is the study of general and fundamental problems concerning matters such as existence,
knowledge, truth, beauty, law, justice, validity, mind, and language. It is a rational and critical
enterprise that tries to answer fundamental questions through an intensive application of reason-
an application that draws on analysis, comparison, and evaluation. It involves reason, rational
criticism, examination, and analysis. In this chapter, we will learn the fundamental nature,
concepts, features and areas of philosophy. Furthermore, we will discuss why it is so important
to learn philosophy.
Dear learners, after the successful completion of this chapter, you will be able to:
Because of its universal nature, it is difficult to define philosophy in terms of a specific subject
matter. However, we can define it etymologically as ‘love of wisdom’. Thus, as a pursuit of
wisdom, philosophy refers to the development of critical habits, the continuous search for truth,
and the questioning of the apparent. In this lesson, students will be introduced with the
fundamental meaning, nature, and concepts of philosophy.
Lesson Objectives:
Activity # 1: - Dear learners, do you have a prior awareness of philosophy? If so, how do
you understand philosophy?
Dear learners, it is important to note first that giving a clear-cut definition of philosophy is
difficult. It may be easy to define other disciplines, such as, chemistry, physics, geography, etc in
terms of a subject matter, for they have their own specific subject matters to primarily deal with.
However, it is difficult to do the same with philosophy, because philosophy has no a specific
subject matter to primarily deal with. Philosophy deals primarily with issues. What contents
philosophy has are not the specific subject matters, but issues, which are universal in nature.
However, this should not lead us into thinking that philosophy is incomprehensible. It is only to
Philosophy is not as elusive as it is often thought to be. Nor is it remote from our various
problems. It is unanimously agreed that the best way to learn and understand philosophy is to
philosophize; i.e., to be confronted with philosophical questions, to use philosophical language,
to become acquainted with differing philosophical positions and maneuvers, to read the
philosophers themselves, and to grapple with the issues for oneself. Socrates once stated that
“Wonder is the feeling of a philosopher, and philosophy begins in wonder”. It is true that most
of us may not have a clear knowledge about the history, nature, language, and issues of
philosophy. But, we all think and reflect in our own way about issues that matter us most. We all
have touched and moved by the feelings of wonder from which all philosophy derives. Thus, we
all participate, more or less, in philosophical issues, even though thinking alone cannot make us
philosophers.
If, however, you still want to find its clear-cut definition, it is better to refer to the etymology of
the word itself, instead of trying to associate it with a certain specific subject matter.
Etymologically, the word “philosophy” comes from two Greek words: “philo” and “sophia”,
which mean “love” and “wisdom”, respectively. Thus, the literal definition of philosophy is
“love of wisdom”. The ancient Greek thinker Pythagoras was the first to use the word
“philosopher” to call a person who clearly shows a marked curiosity in the things he experiences.
Anyone who raises questions, such as Does God exists? What is reality? What is the ultimate
source of Being? What is knowledge? What does it mean to know? How do we come to know?
What is value?, and the like, is really showing a curiosity that can be described as a vital concern
for becoming wise about the phenomena of the world and the human experiences. Therefore,
seeking wisdom is among the various essences of philosophy that it has got from its
etymological definition. Nevertheless, this is not sufficient by itself to understand philosophy, for
not all wisdoms are philosophy.
Activity # 2: - Dear learners, what do you think is the wisdom that philosophers seek?
To interrogate the obvious means to deal creatively with the phenomenal world, to go beyond the
common understanding, and to speculate about things that other people accept with no doubt.
But, questioning/criticism is not the final end of philosophy, though raising the right question is
often taken not only as the beginning and direction of philosophy but also as its essence. Raising
the right question is an art that includes the ability to foresee what is not readily obvious and to
imagine different possibilities and alternatives of approaching the apparent. When we ultimately
wonder about the existing world, and thus raise different questions about its order, each question
moves us from the phenomenal facts to a profound speculation. The philosophical enterprise, as
Vincent Barry stated, is “an active imaginative process of formulating proper questions and
resolving them by rigorous, persistent analysis”.
Therefore, philosophy is a rational and critical enterprise that tries to formulate and answer
fundamental questions through an intensive application of reason- an application that draws on
analysis, comparison, and evaluation. It involves reason, rational criticism, examination, and
analysis. Accordingly, we can say that Philosophy has a constructive side, for it attempts to
formulate rationally defensible answers to certain fundamental questions concerning the nature
of reality, the nature of value, and the nature of knowledge and truth. At the same time, its
critical side is manifested when it deals with giving a rational critic, analysis, clarification, and
evaluation of answers given to basic metaphysical, epistemological, and axiological questions.
The other thing, which is worthy of noting, is that philosophy is an activity. It is not something
that can be easily mastered or learned in schools. A philosopher is a great philosopher, not
because he mastered philosophy, but because he did it. It is not his theory, but his extraordinary
ability to critically think, to conceptualize, to analyze, to compare, to evaluate, and to
As an academic discipline, philosophy has its own salient features that distinguishes it from other
academic disciplines, be it natural, social and humanistic disciplines. In this lesson, students will
be introduced with the generally fundamental features of philosophy.
Lesson Objectives:
Activity # 1: - Dear learners, list the possible features of philosophy you could think of
based on our previous lesson (Lesson 1) and discuss about them with the
student(s) beside you.
Lesson Objectives:
Understand the fundamental concern and issues that metaphysics and epistemology
primarily deal with.
Identify the major subsets or aspects of metaphysical questions.
Recognize the fundamental philosophical, i.e., epistemological, debates concerning
the sources of human knowledge.
3.1 Metaphysics
Activity # 1: - Dear learners, what do you think is metaphysics? List any question that
you might think is a metaphysical question. Show your question to
student(s) beside you, and discuss about your questions together.
Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the ultimate nature of reality or existence. It
deal with issues of reality, God, freedom, soul/immortality, the mind-body problem, form and
substance relationship, cause and effect relationship, and other related issues. Metaphysicians
seek an irreducible foundation of reality or ‘first principles’ from which absolute knowledge or
Activity # 2: - Dear learners, what do you think is epistemology? List any question
that you might think is an epistemological question. Show your question
to student(s) beside you, and discuss about your questions together.
Epistemology is the other field of philosophy that studies about the nature, scope, meaning, and
possibility of knowledge. It deals with issues of knowledge, opinion, truth, falsity, reason,
experience, and faith. Epistemology is also referred to as “theory of knowledge”.
Etymologically, the word epistemology has been derived from the Greek words episteme,
meaning “knowledge, understanding”, and logos, meaning “study of”. In other words, we can
say that Epistemology is the study of the nature, source, and validity of knowledge. It seeks to
answer of the basic questions as “What is true?” and “How do we know?” Thus, epistemology
covers two areas: the content of thought and thought itself. The study of epistemology deals with
issues related to the dependability of knowledge and the validity of the sources through which
we gain information.
The following are among the questions/issues with which Epistemology deals:
What is knowledge?
What does it mean to know?
What is the source of knowledge? Experience? Reason? Or both?
How can we be sure that what we perceive through our senses is correct?
What makes knowledge different from belief or opinion?
What is truth, and how can we know a statement is true?
Can reason really help us to know phenomenal things without being informed by
sense experiences?
Can our sense experience really help us to know things beyond our perception
without the assistance of our reasoning ability?
What is the relationship and difference between faith and reason?
Epistemology seeks answers to a number of fundamental issues. One is whether reality can even
be known. Skepticism in its narrow sense is the position claiming that people cannot acquire
reliable knowledge and that any search for truth is in vain. That thought was well expressed by
We have said earlier that philosophy deals with the most basic issues faced by human beings.
Axiology is the philosophical study of value, which originally meant the worth of something. It
includes the studies of moral values, aesthetic values, as well as political and social values.
Lesson Objectives:
Understand the fundamental concern and issues that axiology and logic primarily deal
with.
Identify the major subsets or aspects of axiological questions: ethical, aesthetical,
political and social questions.
Recognize the fundamental philosophical debates concerning the nature and sources
of moral, political and social rules and principles.
4.1 Axiology
Activity # 1: - Dear learners, what do you think is Axiology? List any question that
you might think is an axiological question. Show your question to
student(s) beside you, and discuss about your questions together.
Axiology is the study or theory of value. The term Axiology stems from two Greek words-
“Axios”, meaning “value, worth”, and “logos”, meaning “reason/ theory/ symbol / science/study
of”. Hence, Axiology is the philosophical study of value, which originally meant the worth of
something. Axiology asks the philosophical questions of values that deal with notions of what a
person or a society regards as good or preferable, such as:
What is a value?
Where do values come from?
How do we justify our values?
How do we know what is valuable?
What is the relationship between values and knowledge?
What kinds of values exist?
Can it be demonstrated that one value is better than another?
Who benefits from values?
Etc.
I. Ethics
Activity # 2: - Dear learners, how do you define ethics? What ethical rules,
principles, and standards do you know and follow, and why? Discuss
about it with the student(s) beside you.
Ethics, which is also known as Moral Philosophy, is a science that deals with the philosophical
study of moral principles, values, codes, and rules, which may be used as standards for
determining what kind of human conduct/action is said to be good or bad, right or wrong. Ethics
has three main branches: meta-ethics, normative ethics, and applied ethics. Ethics raises various
questions including:
What is good/bad?
What is right/wrong?
Is it the Right Principle or the Good End that makes human action/conduct
moral?
Is an action right because of its good end, or it is good because of its right
principle?
Are moral principles universal, objective, and unconditional, or relative,
subjective and conditional?
What is the ultimate foundation of moral principles? The supernatural God?
Human reason? Mutual social contract? Social custom?
Does God exist? If so, is He Benevolent and Omnipotent?
If God is Benevolent, why He creates evil things? If God does not create evil
things, then, there must be another creator who is responsible to creation of the evil
things? But, if it is so, how can God be an Omnipotent creator?
Why we honor and obey moral rules? For the sake of our own individual benefits?, or for
the sake of others?, or just for the sake of fulfilling our infallible duty?
Ethics, or ethical studies, can be grouped into three broad categories: Normative ethics, Meta-
ethics, and Applied Ethics.
Normative Ethics refers to the ethical studies that attempt to study and determine precisely the
moral rules, principles, standards and goals by which human beings might evaluate and judge the
By: Teklay G. (AkU), Adane T. (MU), and Zelalem M. (HMU) Page 26
moral values of their conducts, actions and decisions. It is the reasoned search for principles of
human conduct, including a critical study of the major theories about which things are good,
which acts are right, and which acts are blameworthy. Consequentialism or Teleological Ethics,
Deontological Ethics, and Virtue Ethics are the major examples of normative ethical studies.
Meta-ethics is the highly technical philosophical discipline that deals with investigation of the
meaning of ethical terms, including a critical study of how ethical statements can be verified. It is
more concerned with the meanings of such ethical terms as good or bad and right or wrong than
with what we think is good or bad and right or wrong. Moral Intuitionism, Moral Emotivism,
Moral Prescriptivism, Moral Nihilism, and Ethical Relativism are the main examples of meta-
ethical studies.
Applied Ethics is a normative ethics that attempts to explain, justify, apply moral rules, principles,
standards, and positions to specific moral problems, such as capital punishment, euthanasia,
abortion, adultery, animal right, and so on. This area of normative ethics is termed applied
because the ethicist applies or uses general ethical princes in an attempt to resolve specific moral
problems.
II. Aesthetics
Activity # 3: - Dear learners, how do you define and understand aesthetics? What
Discuss about it with the student(s) beside you.
Aesthetics is the theory of beauty. It studies about the particular value of our artistic and aesthetic
experiences. It deals with beauty, art, enjoyment, sensory/emotional values, perception, and
matters of taste and sentiment.
The following are typical Aesthetic questions:
What is art?
What is beauty?
What is the relation between art and beauty?
What is the connection between art, beauty, and truth?
Can there be any objective standard by which we may judge the beauty of artistic
works, or beauty is subjective?
What is artistic creativity and how does it differ from scientific creativity?
Why works of art are valuable?
Can artistic works communicate? If so, what do they communicate?
By: Teklay G. (AkU), Adane T. (MU), and Zelalem M. (HMU) Page 27
Does art have any moral value, and obligations or constraints?
Are there standards of quality in Art?
Social/Political Philosophy studies about of the value judgments operating in a civil society, be it
social or political.
The following questions are some of the major Social/Political Philosophy primarily deal with:
What form of government is best?
What economic system is best?
What is justice/injustice?
What makes an action/judgment just/unjust?
What is society?
Does society exist? If it does, how does it come to existence?
How are civil society and government come to exist?
Are we obligated to obey all laws of the State?
What is the purpose of government?
4.2 Logic
Activity # 5: - Dear learners, how do you define and understand logic? Discuss
about it with student(s) beside you.
Logic is the study or theory of principles of right reasoning. It deals with formulating the right
principles of reasoning; and developing scientific methods of evaluating the validity and
soundness of arguments. The following are among the various questions raised by Logic:
What is an argument; What does it mean to argue?
What makes an argument valid or invalid
What is a sound argument?
What relation do premise and conclusion have in argument?
How can we formulate and evaluate an argument?
Dear learners, we have seen in our first lesson that philosophy is a rational and critical enterprise
that tries to formulate and answer fundamental questions through an intensive application of
reason- an application that draws on analysis, comparison, and evaluation-, and deals with the
most basic issues faced by human beings. In this lesson, we will discuss the fundamental benefits
of learning philosophy.
Lesson Objectives:
Activity # 1: - Dear learners, can you list, based on our previous lessons, the
possible benefits of studying philosophy? Who do you think needs
philosophy? Why? Discuss with the student(s) beside you.
Dear learners, if you ask any philosophy student ‘what is the necessity of studying philosophy’,
he/she may give you the following famous philosophical statement: “The unexamined life is not
worth living”. The ancient Greek philosopher, Socrates, once said that “I tell you that to let no
day pass without discussing goodness and all the other subjects about which you hear me talking
and examining both myself and others is really the best thing that a man can do, and that life
without this sort of examination is not worth living.…” Thus, among the various benefits of
learning philosophy is that philosophy provides students with the tools they need to critically
examine their own lives as well as the world in which they live. Let us clarify it more.
Some modern psychologists point out that human beings have both maintenance and actualizing
needs. The former refer to the physical and psychological needs that we must satisfy in order to
maintain ourselves as human beings: food, shelter, security, social interaction, and the like. The
later appear to be associated with self-fulfillment, creativity, self-expression, realization of one’s
potential, and being everything one can be. Although philosophy may not necessarily lead to this
sort of self-actualization, it can assist us to actualize ourselves by promoting the ideal of self-
Chapter Summary
Logic, as a field of study, is a branch of philosophy that deals with the study of arguments and
the principles and methods of right reasoning. Etymologically, the term ‘philosophy’ can be
defined as “love of wisdom”, being wisdom a critical habit and eternal vigilance about all things
and a reverence for truth, whatever its form, and wherever its place. Therefore, philosophy, as a
pursuit of wisdom, is the development of critical habits, the continuous search for truth, and the
questioning of the apparent. It is, however, important to note that ‘questioning the apparent’ does
not mean denying the obviously real. It simply refers to the extraordinary ability and curiosity to
deal creatively with the phenomenal world, to go beyond the common understanding, and to
speculate about things that other people accept with no doubt. Philosophy, as a rational and
critical enterprise that tries to formulate and answer fundamental questions through an intensive
application of reason, is a dual-sided universal discipline: critical and constructive sides. While,
as a critical discipline, it deals with giving a rational critic, analysis, clarification, and evaluation
of answers given to basic metaphysical, epistemological, and axiological questions, it attempts,
as a constructive discipline, to formulate rationally defensible answers to certain fundamental
questions concerning the nature of reality, the nature of value, and the nature of knowledge and
truth.
Philosophy, as an academic discipline, has its own salient features that distinguish it from other
academic disciplines. Its systematic, logical and flexible approach to the ultimate reality of the
universe, human life, knowledge experience, truth and values and its holistic and evolutionary
______________________________________________________________________________
____________________________________________________________________________
_________________________________________________________________________________
_________________________________________________________________________________
3. List and discuss the major features of philosophy.
______________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________
4. Discuss briefly the core branches of philosophy.
______________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________
_________________________________________________________________________________
________________________________________________________________________________
6. Discuss the fundamental epistemological debates concerning the source of human
knowledge.
______________________________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________________________
7. Discuss briefly the major branches Ethics or Moral Philosophy.
References
Emmet, E.R. Learning to Philosophize, London, Penguin Books, 1964.
Hurley, Patrick J. (2014) A Concise Introduction to Logic, 12th Edition, Wadsworth, Cengage
Learning.
Mautner, Thomas (2000) The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy, London, Penguin Books.
Plato ‘Republic: Book I’, in Cahn, M. Steven (1999) Classics of Western Philosophy, 5th ed.
United States of America, Indianapolis/Cambridge, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.
Pojman, P. Louis (1998) Philosophical Traditions: A Text with Readings, United States of
America. Wadsworth Publishing Company: A Division of International Thomson
Publishing, Inc.
Ratner, Joseph, ed. Intelligence in the Modern World: John Dewey’s Philosophy, New York,
The Modern Library, 1939.
CHAPTER TWO
BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC
Chapter Overview
Logic, as field of study, may be defined as the organized body of knowledge, or science that
evaluates arguments. The aim of logic is to develop a system of methods and principles that we
may use as criteria for evaluating the arguments of others and as guides in constructing
arguments of our own. Argument is a systematic combination of two or more statements, which
are classified as a premise or premises and conclusion. A premise refers to the statement, which
Chapter Objectives:
Dear learners, after the successful completion of this chapter, you will be able to:
Lesson Objectives:
Dear learners, the word logic comes from Greek word logos, which means sentence, discourse,
reason, truth and rule. Logic in its broader meaning is the science, which evaluates arguments
and the study of correct reasoning. It could be also defined as the study of methods and
principles of correct reasoning or the art of correct reasoning.
Logic can be defined in different ways. Here below are some definitions of logic:
Activity # 2: - Dear learners, what do you think is the benefit of studying logic?
Discuss with the student(s) beside you.
We use logic in our day-to-day communications. As human beings, we all think, reason and
argue; and we all are subject to the reasoning of other people. Some of us may think well, reason
well and argue well, but some of us may not. The ability to think, reason and argue well might
partially be a matter of natural gift. However, whatever our natural gifts, they can be refined,
improved and sharpened; and the study of logic is one of the best ways to refine one’s natural
ability to think, reason and argue. Likewise, as academicians, our arguments must be logical and
acceptable; and the tool to do so is provided by logic. In general, the following are some of the
major benefits that we can gain from the study of logic:
It helps us to develop the skill needed to construct sound (good) and fallacy-free
arguments of one’s own and to evaluate the arguments of others;
It provides a fundamental defense against the prejudiced and uncivilized attitudes that
threaten the foundation of a civilized and democratic society;
It helps us to distinguish good arguments from bad arguments;
It helps us to understand and identify the common logical errors in reasoning;
It helps us to understand and identify the common confusions that often happen due to
misuse of language;
It enables us to disclose ill-conceived policies in the political sphere, to be careful of
disguises, and to distinguish the rational from irrational and the sane from the insane and
so on.
The aim of logic, hence, is to develop the system of methods and principles that we may use as
criteria for evaluating the arguments of others and as guides in constructing the arguments of our
own in our day-to-day lives. Thus, by studying logic, we are able to increase our confidence
when we criticize the arguments of others and when we advance arguments of our own. In fact,
one of the goals of logic is to produce individuals who are critical, rational and reasonable both
in the sphere of public and private life. However, to be full beneficial of the worth which logic
What is an Argument?
The first technique that can be used to identify premises from a conclusion and vice versa is
looking at an indicator word. Frequently, arguments contain certain indicator words that provide
clues in identifying premises and conclusion.
Here below are some Conclusion Indicators:
Therefore We may conclude Thus So
Wherefore Entails that Consequently It follows that
Accordingly Hence We may infer
Provided that It shows that It implies that
It must be that Whence As a result
In argument that contains any of the conclusion indicator words, the statement that follows the
indicator word can usually be identified as the conclusion. By the process of elimination, the
other statements in the argument can be identified as premises, but only based on their logical
importance to the identified conclusion.
Example:
Women are mammals.
Zenebech is a woman.
Therefore, Zenebech is a mammal.
Based on the above rule, the conclusion of this argument is “Zenebech is a mammal” because it
follows the conclusion indicator word “therefore”, and the other two statements are premises.
If an argument does not contain a conclusion indicator, it may contain a premise indicator.
One premise indicator not included in the above list is ‘‘for this reason.’’ This indicator is
special in that it comes immediately after the premise it indicates and before the conclusion. We
can say that in the middle place between the premise and the conclusion, this indicator can be
both premise and conclusion indicator. The statement that comes before ‘‘for this reason’’ is the
premise of an argument and the statement that comes after “for this reason” is the conclusion.
One should be careful not to confuse ‘‘for this reason’’ with ‘‘for the reason that.’’
Sometimes a single indicator can be used to identify more than one premise. Consider the
following argument:
Tsionawit is a faithful wife, for Ethiopian women are faithful wives and Tsionawit an Ethiopian.
The premise indicator ‘‘for’’ goes with both ‘‘Ethiopian women are faithful wives’’ and
‘‘Tsionawit is an Ethiopian”. These are the premises. By process of elimination, ‘‘Tsionawit is a
faithful wife” is the conclusion.
Sometimes you may an argument that contains no indicator all: neither a conclusion indicator
word nor a premise indicator word. When this occurs, the reader/ listener must ask himself or
herself such questions as:
What single statement is claimed (implicitly) to follow from the others?
What is the arguer trying to prove?
What is the main point in the passage?
The answers to these questions should point to the conclusion.
Example:
Example:
Socialized medicine is not recommended because it would result in a reduction in the overall
quality of medical care available to the average citizen. In addition, it might very well bankrupt
the federal treasury. This is the whole case against socialized medicine in a nutshell.
The conclusion of this argument is ‘‘Socialized medicine is not recommended,’’ and the two
statements following the word ‘‘because’’ are the premises. The last statement makes only a
passing comment about the argument itself and is therefore neither a premise nor a conclusion.
Inference is another concept. In the narrower sense it means the reasoning process expressed by
the argument. And broadly it refers the argument itself. For the purpose of this course, we use the
narrower sense of the term inference or inferential link between the premises and the conclusion
of arguments.
Lesson Objectives:
After the accomplishment of this lesson, you will be able to:
Recognize argumentative passages.
Recognize non-argumentative passages.
Distinguish argumentative passages from non-argumentative passages.
Understand the concepts inferential claim and factual claim.
Since Edison invented the phonograph, he deserves credit for a major technological development.
In the first passage the word ‘‘since’’ is used in a temporal sense. It means ‘‘from the time that.’’
Thus, the first passage is not an argument. In the second passage ‘‘since’’ is used in a logical
sense, and so the passage is an argument.
Second, it is not always easy to detect the occurrences of an inferential relationship between
statements in a passage, and the reader may have to review a passage several times before
making a decision. Therefore, in deciding whether a passage contains an argument one should try
to insert mentally some indicators words among the statements to see whether there is a flow of
ideas among the statements. Even with this mental experiment, however, deciding whether a
passage contains an argument is very difficult. As a result, not everyone will agree about every
passage. Sometimes the only answer possible is a conditional one: “If this passage contains an
argument, then these are the premises and that is the conclusion.”
These statements could serve as the premises of an argument, but because the author makes no
claim that they support or imply anything, there is no argument.
One must be careful, though, with reports about arguments.
Example:
Expository Passages
An expository passage is a kind of discourse that begins with a topic sentence followed by one
or more sentences that develop the topic sentence. If the objective is not to prove the topic
sentence but only to expand it or elaborate it, then there is no argument.
Example:
There is a stylized relation of artist to mass audience in the sports, especially in baseball. Each
player develops a style of his own-the swagger as he steps to the plate, the unique windup a
pitcher has, the clean-swinging and hard-driving hits, the precision quickness and grace of
infield and outfield, the sense of surplus power behind whatever is done.
(Max Lerner, America as a Civilization)
In this passage the topic sentence is stated first, and the remaining sentences merely develop and
flesh out this topic sentence. This passage is not argument, because it lacks an inferential claim.
However, expository passages differ from simple non-inferential passages (such as warnings and
pieces of advice) in that many of them can also be taken as arguments. If the purpose of the
subsequent sentences in the passage is not only to flesh out the topic sentence but also to prove it,
then the passage is an argument.
Example:
Skin and the mucous membrane lining the respiratory and digestive tracts serve as mechanical
barriers to entry by microbes. Oil gland secretions contain chemicals that weaken or kill
bacteria on skin. The respiratory tract is lined by cells that sweep mucus and trapped particles
Illustrations
An illustration is an expression involving one or more examples that is intended to show what
something means or how it is done. Illustrations are often confused with arguments because
many illustrations contain indicator words such as “thus.”
Example:
Chemical elements, as well as compounds, can be represented by molecular formulas. Thus,
oxygen is represented by “O2”, water by “H2O”, and sodium chloride by “NaCl”.
This passage is not an argument, because it makes no claim that anything is being proved. The
word “thus” indicates how something is done - namely, how chemical elements and compounds
can be represented by formulas.
However, as with expository passages, many illustrations can be taken as arguments. Such
arguments are often called arguments from example. Here is an instance of one:
Explanations
One of the most important kinds of non-argument is the explanation. An explanation is an
expression that purports to shed light on some event or phenomenon, which is usually accepted
as a matter of fact. It attempts to clarify, or describe such alike why something is happen that
way or why something is what it is.
Example:
Cows digest grass while humans cannot, because their digestive systems contain enzyme not
found in humans.
Every explanation is composed of two distinct components: the explanandum and explanans.
The explanandum is the statement that describes the event or phenomenon to be explained, and
the explanans is the statement or group of statements that purports to do the explaining. In the
first example, the explanandum is the statement “Cows digest grass while humans cannot” and
the explanans is “their [cows’] digestive systems contain enzyme not found in humans.”
Conditional Statements
A conditional statement is an “if . . . then . . .” statement.
Example: If you study hard, then you will score ‘A’ grade.
Every conditional statement is made up of two component statements. The component statement
immediately following the “if” is called the antecedent (if-clause), and the one following the
“then” is called the consequent (then-clause). However, there is an occasion that the order of
antecedent and consequent is reversed. That is, when occasionally the word ‘‘then’’ is left out,
the order of antecedent and consequent is reversed. For example if we left out “then” from the
above example the antecedent and consequent is reversed: You will score ‘A’ grade if you study
hard. In the above example, the antecedent is “You study hard,” and the consequent is “You will
score ‘A’ grade.” In this example, there is a meaningful relationship between antecedent and
consequent. However, such a relationship need not exist for a statement to count as conditional.
The statement “If Getaneh Kebede is a singer, then Hawassa is in Mekelle” is just as much a
conditional statement as that in the above example.
Conditional Statements:
Antecedent Consequent
If ---------------------------- then ---------------------------------.
In general, non-argumentative passages may contain components that resemble the premises and
conclusions of arguments, but they do not have an inferential claim. However, some passages
like expository passages, illustrations, and explanations can be interpreted as arguments; and the
inferential contents of conditional statements may be re-expressed to form arguments. Therefore,
in deciding whether a passage contains an argument, you should look for three things:
1) indicator words such as “therefore,” “since,” “because,” and so on;
2) an inferential relationship between the statements; and
In our previous lesson, we saw that every argument involves an inferential claim- the claim that
the conclusion is supposed to follow from the premises. Every argument makes a claim that its
premises provide grounds for the truth of its conclusion. The question we now address has to do
with the strength of this claim. Just how strongly is the conclusion claimed to follow from the
premises. The reasoning process (inference) that an argument involves is expressed either with
certainty or with probability. That is what the logician introduced the name deduction and
induction for, respectively. If the conclusion is claimed to follow with strict certainty or
necessity, the argument is said to be deductive; but if it is claimed to follow only probably, the
argument is said to be inductive. Therefore, a conclusion may be supported by its premise in two
very different ways. These two different ways are the two great classes of arguments: Deductive
arguments and Inductive arguments. And the distinction between these two classes of arguments,
because every argument involves an inferential claim, lies in the strength of their inferential
claim. Understanding the distinction of these classes is essential in the study of logic.
In this lesson, we will learn the broad groups of arguments, Deductive arguments and Inductive
arguments, and the techniques of distinguishing one from the other.
Lesson Objectives:
After the successful accomplishment of this lesson, you will be able to:
A deductive argument is an argument incorporating the claim that it is impossible for the
conclusion to be false given that the premises are true. It is an argument in which the premises
are claimed to support the conclusion in such a way that it is impossible for the premises to be
true and the conclusion false. In such arguments, the conclusion is claimed to follow necessarily
(conclusively) from the premises. Thus, deductive arguments are those that involve necessary
reasoning.
Example-1: Example-2:
All philosophers are critical thinkers. All African footballers are blacks.
Socrates is a philosopher. Messi is an African footballer.
Therefore, Socrates is a critical thinker. It follows that, Messi is black.
The above two examples are examples of a deductive argument. In both of them, the conclusion
is claimed to follow from the premises with certainty; or the premises are claimed to support
their corresponding conclusion with a strict necessity. If we, for example, assume that all
philosophers are critical thinkers and that Socrates is a philosopher, then it is impossible that
Socrates not be a critical thinker. Similarly, if we assume that all African footballers are blacks
and that Messi is an African footballer, then it is impossible that Messi not be a black. Thus, we
should interpret these arguments as deductive.
An inductive argument is an argument incorporating the claim that it is improbable for the
conclusion to be false given that the premises are true. . It is an argument in which the premises
are claimed to support the conclusion in such a way that it is improbable for the premises to be
true and the conclusion false. In such arguments, the conclusion is claimed to follow only
probably from the premises. The premises may provide some considerable evidence for the
conclusion but they do not imply (necessarily support) the conclusion. In this case, we might
Example-1: Example-2:
Most African leaders are blacks. Almost all women are mammals.
Mandela was an African leader. Hanan is a woman.
Therefore, probably Mandela was black. Hence, Hanan is a mammal.
Both of the above arguments are inductive. In both of them, the conclusion does not follow from
the premises with strict necessity, but it does follow with some degree of probability. That is, the
conclusion is claimed to follow from the premises only probably; or the premises are claimed to
support their corresponding conclusion with a probability. In other words, if we assume that the
premises are true, then based on that assumption it is probable that the conclusion is true. If we,
for example, assume that most African leaders were blacks and that Mandela was an African
leader, then it is improbable that Mandela not been a black, or it is probable that Mandela was
black. But it is not impossible that Mandela not been a black. Similarly, if we assume that almost
all women are mammals and that Hanan is a woman, then it is improbable that Hanan not be a
mammal, or it is probable that Hanan is a mammal. But it is not impossible that Hanan not be a
mammal. Thus, the above arguments are best interpreted as inductive.
Dear learners, we have said earlier that the distinction between inductive and deductive
arguments lies in the strength of an argument’s inferential claim. In other words, the distinction
lies on how strongly the conclusion is claimed to follow from the premises, or how strongly the
premises are claimed to support the conclusion. However, in most arguments, the strength of this
claim is not explicitly stated, so we must use our interpretative abilities to evaluate it. In the
However, we must acknowledge at the outset that many arguments in ordinary language are
incomplete, and because of this, deciding whether the argument should best be interpreted as
deductive or inductive may be impossible. Let us see the above factors in detail in order to
understand and identify the different styles of argumentation.
The first factor that influences our decision about a certain inferential claim is the occurrence of
special indicator words. There are different sort of indicator words that indicate or mark the type
of a certain argument. Arguments may contain some words that indicate the arguer’s certainty
and confidence, or the arguer’s uncertainty or doubt, about the truth of his/her conclusion. Words
like “certainly,’’ “necessarily,” ‘‘absolutely,’’ and ‘‘definitely’’ indicate that the argument
should be taken as deductive, whereas words like, “probable” ‘‘improbable,’’ ‘‘plausible,’’
‘‘implausible,’’ ‘‘likely,’’ ‘‘unlikely,’’ and ‘‘reasonable to conclude” suggest that an argument is
inductive. The point is that if an argument draws its conclusion, using either of the deductive
indicator words, it is usually best to interpret it as deductive, but if it draws its conclusion, using
either of the inductive indicator words, it is usually best to interpret it as inductive. (Note that the
phrase ‘‘it must be the case that’’ is ambiguous; ‘‘must’’ can indicate either probability or
necessity).
Deductive and Inductive indicator words often suggest the correct interpretation. However, one
should be cautious about these special indicator words, because if they conflict with one of the
other criteria, we should probably ignore them. For arguers often use phrases such as ‘‘it
certainly follows that’’ for rhetorical purposes to add impact to their conclusion and not to
suggest that the argument be taken as deductive. Similarly, some arguers, not knowing the
distinction between inductive and deductive, will claim to ‘‘deduce’’ a conclusion when their
argument is more correctly interpreted as inductive. If one takes these words at face value, then
Arguments based on sign: it is an argument that proceeds from the knowledge of a certain sign
to the knowledge of a thing or situation that the sign symbolizes. For instance, one may infer that
after observing ‘No Parking’ sign posted on the side of a road, the area is not allowed for
parking. But because the sign might be displaced or in error about the area or forgotten,
conclusion follows only probably.
A causal inference: it is an argument which proceed from the knowledge of a cause to the
knowledge of an effect, or conversely, from the knowledge of an effect to knowledge of a cause.
For example, from the knowledge that a bottle of water had been accidentally left in the freezer
overnight, someone might conclude that it had frozen (cause to effect). Conversely, after tasting
a piece of chicken and finding it dry and tough, one might conclude that it had been overcooked
(effect to cause). Because specific instances of cause and effect can never be known with
absolute certainty, one may usually interpret such an argument as inductive.
Furthermore Considerations
It should be noted that the various subspecies of inductive arguments listed here are not intended
to be mutually exclusive. Overlaps can and do occur. For example, many causal inferences that
proceed from cause to effect also qualify as predictions. We should take care not to confuse
arguments in geometry, which are always deductive, with arguments from analogy or inductive
generalizations. For example, an argument concluding that a triangle has a certain attribute (such
Here is an inductive argument that proceeds from the general to the particular:
Lesson Objectives:
After the successful accomplishment of this lesson, you will be able to:
Table 1.1
Activity # 2: - Dear learners, how do you think are strength and cogency? How
do you think are the strength and cogency of an inductive argument evaluated?
The second consequence is that, as validity and invalidity, strength and weakness are only
indirectly related to the truth values of their premises. The central question in determining
strength or weakness is whether the conclusion would probably true if the premises are assumed
true. For an argument to be strong it is not necessary that either the premises or the conclusions
be true, but merely that if the premises assumed true, it is improbable for the conclusion be false.
That is, we do not have to know whether the premise of an argument is actually true in order to
determine its strength (strong or weak). To test an argument for strength, what we need to do is
to assume the premise true and then to see whether the conclusion follows more/less probably
from the premise. Thus, the strength or weakness of an inductive argument results not from the
actual truth or falsity of the premises and conclusion, but from the probabilistic support the
premises give to the conclusion.
We have said earlier that there are four possibilities with respect to the truth or falsity of the
premises and conclusion of a given argument: True premises and True conclusion, True
There is a difference, however, between sound and cogent arguments in regard to the true-
premise requirement. In a sound argument, it is only necessary that the premises be true and
nothing more. Given such premises and good reasoning, a true conclusion is guaranteed. In a
cogent argument, on the other hand, the premises must not only be true, they must also not
ignore some important piece of evidence that outweighs the given evidence and entails a quite
different conclusion. That is, if the premises reflect all the important factors, then the argument is
cogent; if not, then obviously the argument is not cogent. Thus, for cogency, the premises must
not only be true but also not overlook some important factor that outweighs the given evidence
and requires a different conclusion.
Chapter Summary
Logic is a science that evaluates arguments; and takes argumentation and reasoning as its
primary subject of study. The primary aim of logic is to develop a system of methods and
principles that we may use as criteria for evaluating the arguments of others and as guides in
constructing arguments of our own. The study of logic increases students’ confidence to criticize
the arguments of others and advance arguments of their own. An argument is a systematic
combination of one or more than one premises and one and only conclusion. A premise is a
statement, which is claimed to provide a logical support or evidence to a single another
statement, called conclusion. Conclusion is a statement, which is claimed to logically drawn
from the alleged evidence. An argument can be either good or bad argument, depending on the
logical ability of its premise(s) to support its conclusion.
______________________________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________________________
2. Explain how we can distinguish argumentative passages from no-argumentative passages.
_________________________________________________________________________________
_________________________________________________________________________________
3. Explain the meaning and functions of inferential and factual claims.
______________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________
4. Discuss briefly the similarities and differences between deductive and inductive
arguments. Support your discussion with your own examples.
______________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________
5. Explain how we can distinguish deductive arguments from inductive arguments, and vice
versa.
_________________________________________________________________________________
________________________________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________________________
7. Discuss briefly the similarities and differences between strong and weak arguments, and
cogent and uncogent arguments. Support your discussion with your own examples.
______________________________________________________________________________
____________________________________________________________________________
8. Discuss briefly the similarities and differences between sound and cogent arguments.
Support your discussion with your own examples.
______________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________
References
Textbooks
Hurley, Patrick J. (2014) A Concise Introduction to Logic, 12th Edition, Wadsworth, Cengage
Learning.
Hurley, Patrick J. (2012) A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11th Edition, Wadsworth, Cengage
Learning.
Reference Books
Copi, Irving M.and Carl Cohen, (1990) Introduction to Logic, New York: Macmillan Publishing
Company.
Damer, Edward. (2005). Attacking faulty reasoning. A practical guide to fallacy free argument.
Wadsworth Cengage learning, USA.
Fogelin, Robert, J, (1987) Understanding Arguments: An Introduction to Informal Logic, New York:
Harcourt Brace Jvanovich Publisher.
Guttenplan, Samuel: (1991) The Language of Logic. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers
Simico, N.D and G.G James. (1983) Elementary Logic, Belmont, Ca: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
Stephen, C. (200) The Power of Logic. London and Toronto: Mayfield Publishing Company.
Walelign, Emuru, (2009) Freshman Logic, Addis Ababa.
Chapter Overview
In the previous chapter, we have seen the methods of argument construction and the ways by
which we can evaluate arguments. Any good argument must be presented by clear, accurate and
understandable language. Correct reasoning can only be conveyed through language. The
clarification and analysis of terms and statements is the objective of philosophy in general and
logic in particular. In order to interpret, analyze, and evaluate arguments well, one must pay
close attention to language. Many errors in logic stem from a careless or imprecise use of
language, and many misunderstandings about the nature of language. Hence, logic requires
proper use of terms and statements. Therefore, in this chapter we will study about the purposes of
language, meaning and definitions of terms and different techniques of definitions of terms. We
will see an overview of philosophy of language, the formal meaning of words, how to define our
concepts, intention and extension of terms, types, purposes, and techniques of definition, the
standard criteria of lexical definitions, and finally, we will discuss about how to use definition to
evaluate arguments.
Chapter Objectives:
Dear learners, after the successful completion of this chapter, you will be able to:
Lesson Objectives:
There are several approaches to the philosophical nature of meaning. Among others, the
following are the major ones:
1) Idea theories: these theories claim that meanings are purely mental contents provoked by
signs. This approach is mainly associated with the British Empiricist traditions of John
Locke, George Berkeley and David Hume, though some contemporary theorists have
renewed it under the guise of semantic internalism.
Language is a body of standard meanings of words and the form of speech used as a means of
expressing the feeling, emotion, desire, thought etc in a consistent pattern of communication.
Language requires symbol such as words, sounds, gestures, signs that are patterned and related in
a certain way for the purpose of communicating meanings. . We use language in many different
ways. It is the tool of communication and the means of expressing ideas. It is the way of
conveying information and evoking feelings In this lesson, we will learn the distinct functions of
language, which are relevant for the study of logic, along with their corresponding meanings, and
Lesson Objectives:
Recognize the functions of language, which are relevant for the study of logic.
Recognize the cognitive and Emotive meaning of words.
Comprehend the role of emotive terminologies in statements and arguments.
Identify the ways in cognitive meanings can be defective.
Recognize the forms of disputes in logic.
Understand the Intensional and Extensional meaning of terms.
Dear learners, we have discussed, in the preceding chapter, that argument is a group of
statements; and statements are sentences that are declarative. Sentences are made up of words;
and words have their own meanings that are to be conveyed through definitions. Therefore,
words are the most basic units in any language, and thus the most important thing in every
argument.
Ordinary language, as most of us are at least vaguely aware, serves various functions in our day-
to-day lives. The twentieth-century philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein thought the number of
these functions to be virtually unlimited. Thus, among other things, language is used to:
Ask questions Tell jokes
Tell stories Flirt with someone
Tell lies Give directions
Guess at answers Sing songs
Form hypotheses Issue commands
Launch verbal assaults Greet someone and so on.
For our purpose, two linguistic functions are particularly important: (1) to convey information
and (2) to express or evoke feelings. Consider, for example, the following Statements:
“Death penalty is a cruel and inhuman form of punishment in which hapless prisoners are
dragged from their cells and summarily slaughtered only to satiate the bloodlust of a vengeful
public.”
The statement in Example 1 is intended primarily to convey information while the statement in
Example 2 is intended, at least in part, to express or evoke feelings. These statements accomplish
their respective functions through the distinct kinds of terminology in which they are phrased.
Terminology that conveys information is said to have cognitive meaning, and terminology that
expresses or evokes feelings is said to have emotive meaning. Thus, in Example 1 the words
‘‘legal,’’ ‘‘thirty-six,’’ ‘‘most often,’’ ‘‘Georgia,’’ ‘‘record,’’ etc. have primarily a cognitive
meaning, while in Example 2 the words ‘‘cruel,’’ ‘‘inhuman,’’ ‘‘hapless,’’ ‘‘dragged,’’
‘‘slaughtered,’’ ‘‘bloodlust,’’ and ‘‘vengeful’’ have a strong emotive meaning. Of course, these
latter words have cognitive meaning as well. ‘‘Cruel’’ means tending to hurt others, ‘‘inhuman’’
means inappropriate for humans, ‘‘hapless’’ means unfortunate, and so on.
The emotively charged statement about the death penalty illustrates two important Points: First,
statements of this sort usually have both cognitive meaning and emotive meaning. Therefore,
since logic is concerned chiefly with cognitive meaning, it is important that we be able to
distinguish and disengage the cognitive meaning of such statements from the emotive meaning.
Second, part of the cognitive meaning of such statements is a value claim. A value claim is a
claim that something is good, bad, right, wrong, or better, worse, more important or less
important than some other thing. For example, the statement about the death penalty asserts the
value claim that the death penalty is wrong or immoral. Such value claims are often the most
important part of the cognitive meaning of emotive statements. Thus, for the purposes of logic, it
is important that we be able to disengage the value claims of emotively charged statements from
the emotive meaning and treat these claims as separate statements.
These observations suggest the reason that people use emotive terminology as often as they do.
Value claims as such normally require evidence to support them. For example, the claim that the
death penalty is immoral cannot simply stand by itself. It cries out for reasons to support it. But
We have started our previous lesson by stating that argument is a group of statements; and that
statements are sentences that are declarative; and that sentences are made up of words; and
words have their own meanings that are to be conveyed through definitions. That is, the meaning
that words or terms have is explicated by definitions. Definition is a technical and structural
organization of words and/or terms or phrases in explaining the meaning of a given term. Good
definitions are very helpful in eliminating verbal disputes. In this lesson, we will learn the
meaning, nature, and types of definitions.
Lesson Objectives:
Dear learners, definition is a technical and structural organization of words and/or terms or
phrases in explaining the meaning of a given term. For most logicians, definitions are intended
exclusively to explicate the meaning of words. Hence, we may define definition as a group of
words that assigns a meaning to some word or group of words. Accordingly, every definition
Activity # 2: Dear learners, what do you think are practical purposes of definitions?
There are various kinds of definitions that are actually used in our practical life. Based on the
functions that they actually serve, definitions can be classified into five: stipulative, lexical,
précising, theoretical, and persuasive definitions. Let us discuss them in detail
1) Stipulative Definitions
A stipulative definition assigns a meaning to a word for the first time. This may involve either
coining a new word or giving a new meaning to an old word. The purpose of a stipulative
definition is usually to replace a more complex expression with a simpler one.
The need for a stipulative definition is often occasioned by some new phenomenon or
development. For example, the attempt, which has made a few years ago at a certain zoo to
crossbreed tigers and lions, has been succeeded because of the genetic similarity of the two
species- that offspring were produced from a male tiger and a female lion and from a male lion
and a female tiger. When the offspring were born, it became appropriate to give them names. Of
course, the names ‘‘offspring of male tiger and female lion’’ and ‘‘offspring of male lion and
female tiger’’ could have been used, but these names were hardly convenient. Instead, the names
‘‘tigon’’ and ‘‘liger’’ were selected. Any two new words would have sufficed equally well for
naming the offspring- ‘‘topar’’ and ‘‘largine’’, for example, but ‘‘tigon’’ and ‘‘liger’’ were
considered more appropriate, for obvious reasons. Hence, ‘‘Tigon’’ was taken to mean the
offspring of a male tiger and a female lion, and ‘‘liger’’ the offspring of a male lion and a female
tiger. These assignments of meanings were accomplished through stipulative definitions.
2) Lexical Definitions
This definition is used to report the meaning that a word already has in a language. Dictionary
definitions are all instances of lexical definitions. Thus, in contrast with a stipulative definition, a
lexical definition may be true or false depending on whether it does or does not report the way a
word is actually used. Because words are frequently used in more than one way, lexical
definitions have the further purpose of eliminating the ambiguity that would otherwise arise if
one of these meanings were to be confused with another.
As we saw in the first section of this chapter, an expression is ambiguous when it can be
interpreted as having two or more clearly distinct meanings in a given context. Words such as
‘‘light,’’ ‘‘mad,’’ and ‘‘bank’’ can be used ambiguously. Because a lexical definition lists the
3) Précising Definitions
The purpose of a précising definition is to reduce the vagueness of a word. As we saw in the first
section of this chapter, an expression is vague if there are borderline cases in which it is
impossible to tell if the word applies or does not apply. Words such as ‘‘fresh,’’ ‘‘rich,’’ and
‘‘poor’’ are vague. Once the vagueness of such words is reduced by a précising definition, one
can reach a decision as to the applicability of the word to a specific situation. For example, if
legislation were ever introduced to give direct financial assistance to the poor, a précising
definition would have to be supplied specifying exactly who is poor and who is not. The
definition ‘‘‘Poor’ means having an annual income of less than $4,000 and a net worth of less
than $20,000’’ is an example of a précising definition.
Whenever words are taken from ordinary usage and used in a highly systematic context such as
science, mathematics, medicine, or law, they must always be clarified by means of a précising
definition. The terms ‘‘force,’’ ‘‘energy,’’ ‘‘acid,’’ ‘‘element,’’ ‘‘number,’’ ‘‘equality,’’
‘‘contract,’’ and ‘‘agent’’ have all been given précising definitions by specific disciplines.
Sometimes the substance of a court trial may revolve around the precise usage of a term. A trial
in California addressed the question of whether a man who had driven a bicycle while
intoxicated violated the motor vehicle code. The question concerned whether, for these purposes,
a bicycle could be considered a ‘‘vehicle.’’ The court decided in the affirmative, and the decision
amounted to an incremental extension of an already existent précising definition of the word
‘‘vehicle.’’
Another example involves the practice of surgical transplantation of vital organs. Before a heart
4) Theoretical Definitions
A theoretical definition assigns a meaning to a word by suggesting a theory that gives a certain
characterization to the entities that the term denotes. Such a definition provides a way of viewing
or conceiving these entities that suggests deductive consequences, further investigation
(experimental or otherwise), and whatever else would be entailed by the acceptance of a theory
governing these entities. The definition of the term ‘‘heat’’ found in texts dealing with the kinetic
theory of heat provides a good example: ‘‘‘heat’ means the energy associated with the random
motion of the molecules of a substance.’’ This definition does more than merely assign a
meaning to a word; it provides a way of conceiving the physical phenomenon that is heat. In so
doing, it suggests the deductive consequence that as the molecules of a substance speed up the
temperature of the substance increases. In addition, it suggests a number of experiments-
experiments investigating the relationship between molecular velocity and the phenomena of
radiation, gas pressure, molecular elasticity, and molecular configuration. In short, this definition
of ‘‘heat’’ provides the impetus for an entire theory about heat.
However, not all theoretical definitions are associated with science. Many terms in philosophy,
such as “substance”, “form”, “cause”, “change”, “idea”, “good”, “mind”, and “God” have been
given theoretical definitions. In fact most of the major philosophers in history have given these
terms their own peculiar theoretical definitions, and this fact accounts in part for the unique
By: Teklay G. (AkU), Adane T. (MU), and Zelalem M. (HMU) 98
character of their respective philosophies. For example, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz’s definition
of ‘‘substance’’ in terms of what he called ‘‘monads’’ laid the foundation for his metaphysical
theory, and John Stuart Mill’s definition of ‘‘good’’ as the greatest happiness of the greatest
number provided the underpinnings for his utilitarian theory of ethics.
Like stipulative definitions, theoretical definitions are neither true nor false, strictly speaking.
The reason is that theoretical definitions function as proposals to see or interpret some
phenomenon in a certain way. Since proposals have no truth value, neither do theoretical
definitions. They may, however, be more or less interesting or more or less fruitful, depending on
the deductive consequences they entail and on the outcome of the experiments they suggest.
5) Persuasive Definitions
The purpose of a persuasive definition is to engender a favorable or unfavorable attitude toward
what is denoted by the definiendum. This purpose is accomplished by assigning an emotionally
charged or value-laden meaning to a word while making it appears that the word really has (or
ought to have) that meaning in the language in which it is used. Thus, persuasive definitions
amount to a certain synthesis of stipulative, lexical, and, possibly, theoretical definitions backed
by the rhetorical motive to engender a certain attitude. As a result of this synthesis, a persuasive
definition masquerades as an honest assignment of meaning to a term while condemning or
blessing with approval the subject matter of the definiendum. Let us see the following examples:
“Abortion’’ means the ruthless murdering of innocent human beings. ‘‘Abortion’’
means a safe and established surgical procedure whereby a woman is relieved of
an unwanted burden.
Taxation’’ means the procedure by means of which our commonwealth is
preserved and sustained.
‘‘Taxation’’ means the procedure used by bureaucrats to rip off the people who
elected them.
While persuasive definitions may, like lexical definitions, be evaluated as either true or false, the
primary issue is neither truth nor falsity but the effectiveness of such definitions as instruments
of persuasion. Giving their primary objective- i.e., influencing the attitudes of the reader/listener-
persuasive definitions may be used with considerable effectiveness in political speeches and
editorial columns.
In the previous lesson, we presented a survey of some of the kinds of definitions actually in use
and the functions they are intended to serve. These techniques may be classified in terms of the
two kinds of meaning, intensional and extensional. In this lesson, we will investigate some of the
techniques used to produce these definitions.
Lesson Objectives:
An extensional definition is one that assigns a meaning to a term by indicating the members of
the class that the definiendum denotes. There are at least three ways of indicating the members of
a class: pointing to them (demonstrative or ostensive definitions), naming them individually
(enumerative definitions), and naming them in groups (definitions by subclass).
2) Enumerative Definitions
Enumerative Definitions assign a meaning to a term by naming the members of the class the term
denotes. Like demonstrative definitions, they may also be either partial or complete.
Example:
“Actor’’ means a person such as Abebe Balicha, Samsom Taddesse, or Mahder Assefa.
Complete enumerative definitions are usually more satisfying than partial ones because they
identify the definiendum with greater assurance. However, relatively few classes can be
completely enumerated.
3) Definition by Subclass
Definition by Subclass assigns a meaning to a term by naming subclasses of the class denoted by
the term. Such a definition, too, may be either partial or complete, depending on whether the
subclasses named, when taken together, include all the members of the class or only some of
them. See the following examples, the first is partial, the second is complete:
‘‘Tree’’ means an oak, pine, elm, spruce, maple, and the like.
“Fictional work’’ means a poem, a play, a novel, or a short story.
As with definitions by enumeration, complete definitions by subclass are more satisfying than
partial ones; but because relatively few terms denote classes that admit of a conveniently small
number of subclasses, complete definitions by subclass are often difficult, if not impossible, to
provide.
An intensional definition one that assigns a meaning to a word by indicating the qualities or
attributes that the word connotes. There are at least four strategies that may be used to indicate
the attributes/qualities that a word connotes. These strategies result synonymous definitions,
etymological definitions, operational definitions, definitions by genus and difference.
1) Synonymous Definition
Synonymous Definition is one in which the definiens is a single word that connotes the same
attributes as the definiendum- that the definiens is a synonym of the word being defined.
Examples:
“Physician” means doctor.
“Observe “means see.
When a single word can be found that has the same intensional meaning as the word beng
defined, a synonymous definition is a highly concise way of assigning a meaning. However,
many words have subtle shades of meaning that are not connoted by any other single word. For
example, the word “wisdom” is not synonymous with either “knowledge”, “understanding”, or
“sense”.
2) Etymological Definition
Etymological Definition assigns a meaning to a word by disclosing the word’s ancestry in both
its own language and other languages. For example, the English word ‘‘license’’ is derived from
the Latin verb licere, which means to be permitted. Etymological definitions have special
importance for at least two reasons. The first reason is that the etymological definition of a word
often conveys the word’s root meaning or seminal meaning from which all other associated
meanings are derived. Unless one is familiar with this root meaning, one often fails to place other
meanings in their proper light or to grasp the meaning of the word when it is used in its most
3) Operational Definition
Operational Definition assigns a meaning to a word by specifying certain experimental
procedures that determine whether or not the word applies to a certain thing.
Examples:
One substance is ‘‘harder than’’ another if and only if one scratches the other when the two are
rubbed together.
A solution is an ‘‘acid’’ if and only if litmus paper turns red when dipped into it.
Each of these definitions prescribes an operation to be performed. The first prescribes that the
two substances in question be rubbed together, the second that the litmus paper be placed in the
solution and observed for color change. Unless it specifies such an operation, a definition cannot
be an operational definition. For example, the definition ‘‘A solution is an ‘acid’ if and only if it
has a pH of less than 7,’’ while good in other respects, is not an operational definition because it
prescribes no operation.
Operational definitions were invented for the purpose of tying down relatively abstract concepts
to the solid ground of empirical reality. In this they succeed fairly well; yet, from the standpoint
of ordinary language usage, they involve certain deficiencies. One of these deficiencies concerns
the fact that operational definitions usually convey only part of the intensional meaning of a
term. ‘‘Acid’’, for example, means more than blue litmus paper turning red. Moreover,
operational definitions cannot apply to terms outside the framework of science. For example, no
adequate operational definition could be given for such words as ‘‘love,’’ ‘‘respect,’’
‘‘freedom,’’ and ‘‘dignity.’’
In lesson 3, we have discussed five types of definitions. Of these definitions, lexical definition is
the most important and common type of definition that we often use in our day-to-day life. In
this lesson, we will see the common rules of lexical definitions.
Lesson Objectives:
Giving the function of a lexical definition, lexical definitions are what we most frequently
encounter and are what most people mean when they speak of the ‘‘definition’’ of a word.
Accordingly, it is appropriate that we have a set of rules that we may use in constructing our own
lexical definitions and in evaluating the lexical definitions of others. While some of these rules
apply to the other kinds of definitions as well, the unique functions that are served by stipulative,
précising, theoretical, and persuasive definitions prescribe different sets of criteria.
Rule 1: A Lexical Definition Should Conform to the Standards of Proper
Grammar.
Chapter Summary
Language is the most important thing in the study of logic. Giving that logic is the study of
arguments, and language is the fundamental tool of communication, there is not only a strong
relationship between language and logic but also the former has a prominent position within the
discipline of the latter. Argument, as the most special subject matter of logic, is nothing but a
reasoning process that is constructed and conveyed through language. The clarification and
analysis of terms and statements is the objective of philosophy in general and logic in particular.
In order to interpret, analyze, and evaluate arguments well, one must pay close attention to
language. Many errors in logic stem from a careless or imprecise use of language, and many
misunderstandings about the nature of language. Hence, if we are to successfully evaluate the
logical correctness of arguments, it is important to pay a special attention to the language in
which the arguments are cast. More specially, meanings and definitions are very important both,
for clear, effective, and comprehensive communications, and for logical, scientific, and critical
evaluations of arguments. Before we decide whether the requirements of a certain argument are
fulfilled, it is necessary to understand the meanings of the words that make up the statements,
which in its turn, make up the given argument.
References
Textbooks
Hurley, Patrick J. (2014) A Concise Introduction to Logic, 12th Edition, Wadsworth, Cengage
Learning.
Hurley, Patrick J. (2012) A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11th Edition, Wadsworth, Cengage
Learning.
Reference Books
Ackerman, D. (1979) “Proper Names, Prepositional Attitudes and Non-Descriptive
Connotations.” Philosophical Studies 35: 55–69.
Alston, W. (1963) “Meaning and Use.” Philosophical Quarterly 51: 107–24.
Ayer, A. J. (1946) Language, Truth and Logic, 2nd ed.. London: Victor Gollancz.
Copi, Irving M.et al, (1990) Introduction to Logic, New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.
Damer, Edward. (2005). Attacking faulty reasoning. A practical guide to fallacy free
argument. Wadsworth Cengage learning, USA.
Fogelin, Robert, J, (1987) Understanding Arguments: An Introduction to Informal Logic, New York:
Harcourt Brace Jvanovich Publisher.
Guttenplan, Samuel: (1991) The Language of Logic. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers
CHAPTER FOUR
Chapter Objectives:
At the end of this chapter, students will be able to:
Critical thinking can be defined as a wide range of cognitive skills and intellectual dispositions
needed to effectively identify, analyze, and evaluate arguments and truth claims. In this lesson,
we will learn the meaning and general picture of critical thinking.
Lesson Objectives:
Lesson Objectives:
Activity # 2: Dear learners, do you know any standard of critical thinking? How do
you identify good critical thinking from bad critical thinking? What
basic standards do you think critical thinking should meet?
Dear learners, we have seen that the term ‘critical thinking’ generally refers to a wide range of
cognitive skills and intellectual dispositions needed to effectively identify, analyze, and evaluate
arguments and truth claims. It is critical thinking is a disciplined thinking governed by clear
intellectual standards that can be used to identify a critical thinking from the uncritical. Standard
of critical thinking refers a conditions or a level that critical thinking should meet to be
considered as normal and acceptable. Clarity, precision, accuracy, relevance, consistency,
logical correctness, completeness, and fairness are some of the most important intellectual
standards of critical thinking. Let us discuss these standards in detail.
1) Clarity
Clarity refers to clear understanding of concepts and clearly expressing them in a language that is
free of obscurity and vagueness. When we construct argument, we should take into consideration
or pay close attention to clarity. Before we can effectively evaluate a person’s argument or claim,
we need to understand clearly what the person is saying. Unfortunately, that can be difficult
because people often fail to express themselves clearly.
But clarity is a gateway standard. If a statement is unclear, we cannot determine whether it is
accurate or relevant. In fact, we cannot tell anything about it because we do not yet know what it
Sometimes lack of clarity is due to laziness, carelessness, or a lack of skill. At other times, it
results from a misguided effort to appear clever, learned, or profound. As William Strunk Jr. and
E. B. White, in their classic, ‘The Elements of Style’, remark that “Muddiness is not merely a
disturber of prose, it is also a destroyer of life, of hope: death on the highway caused by a badly
worded road sign, heartbreak among lovers caused by a misplaced phrase in a well-intentioned
letter. . . .Only by paying careful attention to language can we avoid such needless
miscommunications and disappointments.
Critical thinkers, however, not only strive for clarity of language but also seek maximum clarity
of thought. To achieve our personal goals in life, we need a clear conception of our goals and
priorities, a realistic grasp of our abilities, and a clear understanding of the problems and
opportunities we face. Such self-understanding can be achieved only if we value and pursue
clarity of thought.
2) Precision
Precision is a matter of being exact, accurate and careful. Most ideas are vague and obscures
though we think we have precise understanding of them. When we try to meticulous these ideas,
we will find that they are imprecise. To get precise understanding, we should pay close attention
to details. Everyone recognizes the importance of precision in specialized fields such as
medicine, mathematics, architecture, and engineering.
Critical thinkers also understand the importance of precise thinking in different contexts. They
understand that to cut through the confusions and uncertainties that surround many everyday
problems and issues, it is often necessary to insist on precise answers to precise questions: What
exactly is the problem we are facing? What exactly are the alternatives? What exactly are the
advantages and disadvantages of each alternative? Only when we habitually seek such precision
are we truly become critical thinkers.
4) Relevance
The question of relevance is a question of connections. When there is a discussion or debate, it
should focus on relevant ideas and information. That is, only those points that bear on the issue
should be raised. A favorite debaters’ trick is to try to distract an audience’s attention by raising
an irrelevant issue. Critical thinkers do not collect any information; they focus and carefully
choose only the information that has logical relation with the ideas at hands. Issues raised should
have logical connection with the question at hand. Two ideas are relevant when they have logical
connection. A critical thinker should be relevant in his ideas and thoughts.
5) Consistency
Consistency is about the quality of always behaving in the same way or of having the same
opinions or standards. It is easy to see why consistency is essential to critical thinking. Logic
tells us that if a person holds inconsistent beliefs, at least one of those beliefs must be false.
Critical thinkers prize truth and so are constantly on the lookout for inconsistencies, both in their
own thinking and in the arguments and assertions of others.
6) Logical Correctness
To think logically is to reason correctly; that is, to draw well-founded conclusions from the
beliefs held. To think critically, we need accurate and well supported beliefs. But, just as
important, we need to be able to reason from those beliefs to conclusions that logically follow
from them. Unfortunately, illogical thinking is all too common in human affairs. When we think,
By: Teklay G. (AkU), Adane T. (MU), and Zelalem M. (HMU) 122
we bring a variety of thoughts together into some order. When the combinations of thoughts are
mutually supporting and make sense in combination, the thinking is logical. When the
combination is not mutually supporting, is contradictory in some sense, or does not make sense
the combination, is not logical.
7) Completeness
In most contexts, we rightly prefer deep and complete thinking to shallow and superficial
thinking. Of course, there are times when it is impossible or inappropriate to discuss an issue in
depth; no one would expect, for example, a thorough and wide-ranging discussion of the ethics
of the right to self- determination in a short newspaper editorial. However, thinking is better
when it is deep rather than shallow, thorough rather than superficial.
8) Fairness
Critical thinking demands that our thinking be fair - that is, open minded, impartial, and free of
distorting biases and preconceptions. That can be very difficult to achieve. Even the most
superficial acquaintance with history and the social sciences tells us that people are often
strongly disposed to resist unfamiliar ideas, to prejudge issues, to stereotype outsiders, and to
identify truth with their own self-interest or the interests of their nation or group.
It is probably unrealistic to suppose that our thinking could ever be completely free of biases and
preconceptions; to some extent, we all perceive reality in ways that are powerfully shaped by our
individual life experiences and cultural backgrounds. But as difficult as it may be to achieve,
basic fair-mindedness is clearly an essential attribute of a critical thinker.
We naturally think from our own perspective, from a point of view, which tends to privilege our
position. Fairness implies the treating of all relevant viewpoints alike without reference to one’s
own feelings or interests. Because we tend to be biased in favor of our own viewpoint, it is
important to keep the standard of fairness at the forefront of our thinking. This is especially
important when the situation may call on us to see things we do not want to see, or give
something up that we want to hold onto.
Lesson Objectives:
Activity # 3: Dear learners, how do you distinguish a good argument from a bad one?
A discussion may involve two or more participants or it may simply be an internal discussion
with oneself. In either case, one who wishes to construct the strongest possible arguments for his
or her views, and to do one’s part in resolving conflicts concerning issues that matter, should
make each of the following principles a part of his or her intellectual style:
Activity # 4: Dear learners, how do you distinguish a critical thinking from the an
uncritical one?
Having discussed the major principles of a good argument, let us now see the principles of a
critical thinking as parts of the codes of intellectual conduct.
So far, in this chapter, we have discussed the meaning and nature of critical thinking; standards
of critical thinking, codes of intellectual conduct: the principles of good arguments and critical
thinking. With this as background, we are now in a position to offer general characteristics of
critical thinking.
Lesson Objectives:
Activity # 1: Dear learners, what do you think of the specific characteristics that best
distinguishes critical individuals from those uncritical ones?
Dear learners, we have defined critical thinking generally as a wide range of cognitive skills and
intellectual dispositions needed to effectively identify, analyze, and evaluate arguments and truth
claims. What then distinguishes a critical thinker from the uncritical one? Let us discuss some
characteristics of Critical and Uncritical Thinkers.
It is said that critical thinking’ is a disciplined thinking that provide a wide range of cognitive
skills and intellectual dispositions needed to effectively identify, analyze, and evaluate
arguments and truth claims; and governed by clear intellectual standards that can be used to
identify a critical thinking from the uncritical. But if critical thinking is so important, why is it
that uncritical thinking is so common? Why is it that so many people, including many highly
educated and intelligent people, find critical thinking so difficult? The reasons are quite complex.
In this lesson, we will discuss some of the problems that impede critical thinking. But we will
limit our discussion to four of them: egocentrism, sociocentrism, unwarranted assumptions and
stereotype and relativistic thinking. These are not exhaustive lists. There are many factors that
impede critical thinking.
Lesson Objectives:
Let us examine in detail five of these impediments that play an especially powerful role in
hindering critical thinking: egocentrism, sociocentrism, unwarranted assumptions, relativistic
thinking, and wishful thinking.
4) Relativistic Thinking
One of the strongest challenges to critical thinking is relativistic thinking. Relativism is the view
that truth is a matter of opinion. There are two popular forms of relativism: subjectivism and
cultural relativism. Subjectivism is the view that truth is a matter of individual opinion.
According to subjectivism, whatever an individual believes is true, is true for that person, and
there is no such thing as “objective” or “absolute” truth, i.e., truth that exists independent of what
anyone believes. For example, suppose Abdella believes that abortion is wrong and Obang
believes that abortion is not always wrong. According to subjectivism, abortion is always wrong
for Abdella and not always wrong for Obang. Both beliefs are true – for them. And truth for one
individual or another is the only kind of truth there is.
The other common form of relativism is cultural relativism. This is the view that truth is a matter
of social or cultural opinion. In other words, cultural relativism is the view that what is true for
person A is what person A’s culture or society believes is true. Drinking wine, for example, is
widely considered to be wrong in Iran but is not generally considered to be wrong in France.
According to cultural relativism, therefore, drinking wine is immoral in Iran but
is morally permissible in France. Thus, for the cultural relativist, just as for the subjectivist, there
is no objective or absolute standard of truth. What is true is whatever most people in a society or
culture believe to be true.
Relatively few people endorse subjectivism or cultural relativism in the pure, unqualified forms
in which we have stated them. Almost everybody would admit, for example, that 1 + 1 = 2 is
true, no matter who might be ignorant or deluded enough to deny it. What relativists usually
claim, therefore, is not that all truth is relative, but that truth is relative in some important
domain(s).
By far the most common form of relativism is moral relativism. Like relativism generally, moral
relativism comes in two major forms: moral subjectivism and cultural moral relativism. Moral
subjectivism is the view that what is morally right and good for an individual, A, is whatever A
5) Wishful Thinking
Wishful thinking refers to a state of believing something not because you had good evidence for
it but simply because you wished it were true. Have you ever been guilty of wishful thinking? If
so, you are not alone. Throughout human history, reason has done battle with wishful thinking
and has usually come out the loser. People fear the unknown and invent comforting myths to
render the universe less hostile and more predictable. They fear death and listen credulously to
stories of healing crystals, quack cures, and communication with the dead. They fantasize about
possessing extraordinary personal powers and accept uncritically accounts of psychic prediction
and levitation,
Being a critical person in general and critical thinking in particular has many benefits. In this
lesson, we will discuss some benefits of critical thinking.
Lesson Objectives:
Activity # 1: Dear
By: Teklay learners,
G. (AkU), Adanewhat benefits
T. (MU), of critical
and Zelalem M. thinking
(HMU) do you think of? 142
Critical Thinking: Skills and Dispositions
Critical thinking teaches you how to raise and identify fundamental questions and problems in
the community. It will teach you to reformulate these problems clearly and precisely. It will
teach you how to gather and assess relevant information, develop reasoned conclusions and
solutions, testing them against relevant criterion and standards. It teaches you how to be open
minded to alternative system of thought, recognize and assess your own assumptions,
implications and practical consequences, how to communicate effectively with others in figuring
out solutions to complex problems.
Critical thinking is what university is all about. University is not only about teaching students
with facts. It’s about teaching students to think- think critically. This chapter will introduce you
the skills and dispositions you need to become an independent, self-directed thinker and learner.
But you’ll only get out of this course what you put into it. Becoming a critical thinker is hard
work. Becoming a master thinker means toning up your mental muscles and acquiring habits of
careful, disciplined thinking. This requires effort, and practice. Critical thinking is an adventure.
Becoming mentally fit is hard work. But in the end you’ll be a smarter, stronger, more confident
thinker. Let us consider, more specifically, what you can expect to gain from a course in critical
thinking.
Critical Thinking in the Classroom
When they first enter university, students are sometimes surprised to discover that university
education seem less interested in how beliefs are acquired than they are in whether those beliefs
can withstand critical scrutiny. The question is not much about what you know, but how you
acquire what you know and whether your ideas stands critical examination.
In university, the focus is on higher-order thinking: the active, intelligent evaluation of ideas and
information. For this reason critical thinking plays a vital role in universities. In a critical
thinking chapter, students learn a variety of skills that can greatly improve their classroom
performance. These skills include:
To succeed in university, you must, of course, be able to understand the material you are
studying. A course in critical thinking cannot make inherently difficult material easy to grasp,
but critical thinking does teach a variety of skills that, with practice, can significantly improve
your ability to understand the arguments and issues discussed in your college textbooks and
classes.
In addition, critical thinking can help you critically evaluate what you are learning in class.
During your university career, your instructors will often ask you to discuss “critically” some
argument or idea introduced in class. Critical thinking teaches a wide range of strategies and
skills that can greatly improve your ability to engage in such critical evaluation.
You will also be asked to develop your own arguments on particular topics or issues. In moral
and civic education class, for example, you might be asked to write a paper addressing the issue
of whether ethnic federalism is good or bad. To write such a paper successfully, you must do
more than simply find and assess relevant arguments and information. You must also be able to
marshal arguments and evidence in a way that convincingly supports your view. The systematic
training provided in a course in critical thinking can greatly improve that skill as well.
Critical thinking is a transferable thinking skill. These skills will be taught in ways that expressly
aim to facilitate their transfer to other subjects and contexts. If you learn how to structure
argument, judge the credibility of sources or make a reasonable decision by the methods of
critical thinking for instance, it will not be difficult to see how to do these things in many other
contexts such as in class rooms and personal life; this is the sense in which the skills we teach in
this text are transferable.
Chapter Summary
Critical also means, “involving or exercising skilled judgment or observation.” In this sense,
critical thinking means thinking clearly and intelligently. More precisely, critical thinking is the
general term given to a wide range of cognitive skills and intellectual dispositions needed to
effectively identify, analyze, and evaluate arguments and truth claims; to discover and overcome
References
Bowell, Tracy. and Kemp, Gary, Critical Thinking. A Concise Guide. 2015. Rutledge, USA.
Damer, Edward, Attacking Faulty Reasoning. 2009. Wadsworth Cengage, USA.
Fisher, Alec. Critical Thinking: An Introduction. 2011. Short Run, UK. 2ed.
Gregory, Bassham, et al, Critical Thinking: A Student’s Introduction. 2013. Mac- Grew Hill.
USA. 5th ed.
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice. 1971. Belknap, USA. 2nd ed.
Moon, J., Critical Thinking: An Exploration of Theory and Practice. 2008. Routledge, USA.
Paul, Richard, et al, The Miniature Guide to Critical Thinking. 2008. Berkeley University, USA.
Sharon, Bailing, et al, Conceptualizing Critical thinking. 2013. Journal of Curriculum Studies.
CHAPTER FIVE
LOGICAL REASONING AND FALLACIES
Chapter Overview
We have seen in chapter two that an argument can be good or bad, depending on the relationship
between the premises and a conclusion. An argument is good as far as it meets all the general
criteria set for a good argument. If, however, it fails to do so, or violates them, it becomes bad,
and hence, fallacious. A fallacy is, therefore, a defect in an argument (or, a mistake frequently
committed in reasoning) that consists in something other than merely false premises. It can be
committed in many ways, but usually it involves either a mistake in reasoning or the creation of
some illusion that makes a bad argument appear good (or both). That is, a fallacy is often
committed because of the problem in the reasoning process or the form of the argument, or
Chapter Objectives:
Fallacy is generally defined as a deficiency or logical problem that occurs in an argument for
various reasons, other than merely false premises. It can be committed in different forms,
Lesson objectives:
Define fallacy.
Differentiate formal and informal fallacies.
Dear learners, the word ‘fallacy’ is a general term that refers to a logical defect or flaw or fault
that a certain argument exhibits in its structural arrangement or reasoning process, or in the
contents of its statements used as premises or a conclusion, for various reasons, other than
merely false premises. In general, it is a violation of standard argumentative rules or criteria. Let
us take a moment now and see the standard criteria or rules of a good argument, before proceed
to the detail discussion of fallacies.
Activity # 2: Dear learners, what are the standard rules of a good argument?
There are four general criteria of a good argument, which specifically evaluate the relevance,
acceptability, sufficiency, and rebuttablity of the premises. A good argument must have premises
that: are relevant to the truth of the conclusion, are acceptable to a logical person, together
constitute sufficient grounds for the truth of the conclusion, and anticipate and provide an
effective rebuttal to all reasonable challenges to the argument or to the position supported by it.
A premise is relevant, if its acceptance provides some reason to believe, counts in favor of, or
makes a difference to the truth or falsity of the conclusion. Otherwise, it is irrelevant. A premise
is acceptable, if it is a reason, that the skeptic is likely to accept, or that a rational person is ought
to accept, or agreed on. However, an argument may not be good, even though its premises may
be relevant and acceptable, unless they are sufficient enough in number, kind and weight.
Finally, a good argument should also provide an effective rebuttal (refutation, or disproof) to the
Informal fallacies
Informal fallacies are those mistakes in reasoning process of an argument that cannot be
recognized by analyzing the structure of an argument, but only through analysis of the content of
Fallacies of relevance are those, (except missing the point) which are committed chiefly due to a
provision premises that are logically irrelevant to the conclusion. Unlike the others, the fallacy of
missing the point is committed due to an irrelevant conclusion. In this lesson, we will discuss
eight fallacies of relevance: Appeal to force, Appeal to pity, Appeal to people, Argument against
the person, Accident, Straw man, Missing the point, and Red Herring.
occur, have premises that are logically irrelevant to the conclusion. Yet the premises are relevant
psychologically, so the conclusion may seem to follow from the premises, even though it does
not follow logically. In a good argument the premises provide genuine evidence in support of the
conclusion. In an argument that commits a fallacy of relevance, on the other hand, the connection
between premises and conclusion is emotional. Such arguments are often called non sequiturs,
which means that the conclusion does not seem to follow from the premises. They are also
sometimes called argumentative leaps, which suggest that since no connection is seen between
the premises and the conclusion, a huge leap (jump) would be required to move from one (the
premises) to the other (the conclusion). To identify a fallacy of relevance, therefore, one must be
able to distinguish genuine evidence from various forms of emotional appeal.
Activity # 2: Dear learners, how do you define the fallacy of appeal to force?
The first type of fallacy of relevance is appeal to force. It occurs when an arguer poses a
conclusion to another person and tells that person either implicitly or explicitly that some harm
will come to him if he does not accept the conclusion. In other words it occurs when a
conclusion defended by a threat to the well- being of those who do not accept the conclusion.
This fallacy always involves a threat by the arguer to the physical or psychological well- being of
the listener. But this threat is logically irrelevant to the subject matter of the conclusion even
though it seems psychologically relevant. Consider the following argument in which the arguer
uses unjustified physical threat on the listeners.
This is a fallacious argument; the arguer is threatening the listener to abandon his charge. The
above argument can be re-written to expose the faulty reasoning most clearly.
Mr. Kebede you have to drop your charge, otherwise you will face accident.
You can see that the conclusion is supported by force. The threat “accident” has no logical
bearing on the conclusion however (you have to drop your charge).
Appeal to force need not use sheer physical force to support a certain conclusion. Consider the
following argument.
Lately there has been a lot of negative criticism of our policy on dental benefits. Let me tell you
something, people. If you want to keep working here, you need to know that our policy is fair
and reasonable. I won’t have anybody working here who doesn’t know this.
Now this is a blatant example, which shows an explicit use of psychological force to impose a
conclusion. The arguer is trying to impose the conclusion that you (workers) should accept the
dental benefit policy as fair and reasonable. The reason given however does not support the
conclusion. It says that ‘any worker who does not accept this conclusion would be fired.’ But a
threat to loss a job cannot constitute a reason to support the proposition that the dental policy is
reasonable and fair. Thus, it is unjustified appeal to force. Such kinds of argument have the
following form:
Premise: You can avoid harm by accepting the conclusion that the policy is fair and reasonable.
Conclusion: Thus, the policy is fair and reasonable.
The appeal to force fallacy usually accomplishes its purpose by psychologically impeding the
reader or listener from acknowledging a missing premise that, if acknowledged, would be seen to
be false or at least questionable. Finally, a note of caution: The fact that an argument mentions a
threat does not necessarily make it a fallacy.
Activity # 3: Dear learners, how do you define the fallacy of appeal to pity?
The Headship position in the department of accounting should be given to Mr. Oumer Abdulla.
Oumer has six hungry children to feed and his wife desperately needs an operation to save her
eyesight.
The conclusion of this argument is “the Headship position in the department of accounting
should be given to Oumer Abdulla”. But the conclusion is not logically relevant to the pathetic
condition of the arguer though they do psychologically. It may be pitiful to see people under
these conditions; but this does not mean that such conditions are logically relevant in every
situation to decide. A certain position should be open to people to fill when they have the
necessary qualification. The relevant logical reason in this situation for Oumer Abdulla to qualify
for the position is if he fulfills the necessary educational experience. But ‘he has six hungry
children to feed and his wife needs operation’ does not lend reason to accept the conclusion. So
this is illegitimate appeal to pity.
There is a tendency to take argument from pity as inherently fallacious. But this is not always the
case. There are arguments from pity, which are reasonable and plausible. There are situations
where compassion or sympathy could be a legitimate response for some situations.
Activity # 4: Dear learners, how do you define the fallacy of appeal to people?
Nearly everyone wants to be loved, esteemed, admired, valued, recognized, and accepted by
others. Feeling of being part of community and belongingness are some of the most important
humans needs. The appeal to the people strikes these desires and needs to get acceptance for
conclusion. Or the appeal to the people (or ad populum fallacy) is an attempt to persuade a
person (or group) by appealing to these desires and needs. Consider the following argument.
I look out at you all, and I tell you, I am proud to be here. Proud to belong to a party that stands
for what is good for the country. Proud to cast my lot with the kind of people who make this
nation great. Proud to stand with men and women who can get our nation back on its feet. Yes,
I. Bandwagon fallacy
Bandwagon fallacy is a kind of fallacy that commonly appeals to the desire of individuals to be
considered as part of the group or community in which they are living. One of the characteristics
of community or group is that they share some values and norms. Not only they share but also
every individual are expected to manifest group conformity to these shared values. Bandwagon
fallacy just uses these emotions and feelings to get acceptance for a certain conclusion. For
instance, consider the following example.
The majority of people in Ethiopia accept the opinion that child circumcision is the right thing to
do. Thus, you also should accept that child circumcision is the right thing to do.
This argument presents appeal to bandwagon and if the person considers that child circumcision
is the right thing to do because the majority of people accepts it, then this argument commits the
fallacy of bandwagon.
Dear learners, do you see any relationship between sociocentrism and bandwagon fallacy?
Activity # 5: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of argument against the person?
Argument against the person is another type of relevance fallacy. This fallacy always involves
two arguers. One of them advances (either directly or implicitly) a certain argument and the other
then responds by directing his or her attention not to the first person’s argument but to the first
person himself. When this occurs, the second person is said to commit an argument against the
person. In any of the kinds of conversational frameworks in which people reason with each
other, despite the opposition and partisanship characteristic of many kinds of dialogue, there
must also be a presumption that in order to achieve collaborative goals, participants must observe
rules of polite conversation.
Arguers must be able to trust each other, to some extent at least, to be informative and relevant,
to take turns politely, and to express their commitments clearly and honestly. Without this kind
of collaboration in contributing to a dialogue, argument of a kind that uses reasoning to fulfill its
goals of dialogue interaction would not be possible.
Haileselassie I of Ethiopia argued in the League of Nations that member states should give hand
to Ethiopia to expel the fascist Italy from the country. But the member states should not listen to
the king. Haileselassie I argue in this way because he wants to resume his power once the Italian
are expelled from Ethiopia.
This argument is fallacious because the arguer does not pay serious attention to the substance of
the argument of the king. He just tried to discredit the idea of the king by association it with the
circumstance with the Italian evacuation. He did not attack directly why member states should
not help the country. The ad hominem circumstantial is easy to recognize because it always takes
this form: ‘‘Of course, Mr. X argues this way; just look at the circumstances that affect him.’’
5) Accident
Activity # 6: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of accident?
The fallacy of accident is committed when a general rule is applied to a specific case it
was not intended to cover. Typically, the general rule is cited (either directly or implicitly) in the
premises and then wrongly applied to the specific case mentioned in the
conclusion. Consider the following example:
Freedom of speech is a constitutionally guaranteed right. Therefore, John Q. Radical should not
be arrested for his speech that incited the riot last week.
In this example, the general rule is that freedom of speech is normally guaranteed, and the
specific case is the speech made by John Q. Radical. Because the speech incited a riot, the rule
does not apply.
The fallacy of accident gets its name from the fact that one or more accidental features of the
specific case make it an exception to the rule. In the example, the accidental feature is that the
movement transgress the right to private property.
Activity # 7: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of straw man?
The straw man fallacy is committed when an arguer distorts an opponent’s argument for the
purpose of more easily attacking it, demolishes the distorted argument, and then concludes that
the opponent’s real argument has been demolished. By so doing, the arguer is said to have set up
a straw man and knocked it down, only to conclude that the real man (opposing argument) has
been knocked down as well.
The following are the main features of straw man fallacy. First there are two individuals or
groups discussing about some controversial issues; the two has opposite views. One of the
arguers presents his views about the issues and the other is a critic. Second the critic however
does not rationally criticize the main or the substantive argument of the opponent. Rather he
criticizes ideas which are the misrepresentation of the main content of the argument. He does so
for easy attacking the argument. Third the critic concludes, by criticizing the misrepresented
ideas that he knock down the main ideas. Since the critic does not attack the main ideas, rather he
criticized the misrepresented argument, one can argues he did not criticize the argument at all.
Consider the following argument.
Mr. Belay believes that ethnic federalism has just destroyed the country and thus it should be
replaced by geographical federalism. But we should not accept his proposal. He just wants to
take the country back to the previous regime. Geographical federalism was the kind of state
structure during Derg and monarchical regime. We do not want to go back to the past. Thus, we
should reject Mr. Belay’s proposal.
This argument involves two persons: Mr. Belay and his critic. Mr. Belay argues for geographical
federalism and his critic opposing the view. This critics show that the critic do not refute or
oppose the idea of geographical federalism. Rather he first misrepresented geographical
federalism as going back to the past and then he criticizes the past regime and by doing so he
believed the real argument knocked down. But he did not criticize the substance of the argument;
he criticizes distorted idea which do not represent his opponent. This is an example of how straw
man fallacy is committed.
When the fallacy of straw man occurs readers should keep in mind two things. First, they have to
try to identify the original argument, which is misrepresented by the critic. Second, they should
look for what gone wrong in the misrepresentation of the argument. Is the critic exaggerated the
Activity # 8: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of missing the point?
All the fallacies we have discussed thus far have been instances of cases where the premises of
an argument are irrelevant to the conclusion. Missing the point, however, illustrates a special
form of irrelevance. It occurs when the premises of an argument support one particular
conclusion, but then a different conclusion, often vaguely related to the correct conclusion, is
drawn. Whenever one suspects that such a fallacy is being committed, he or she should be able to
identify the correct conclusion, the conclusion that the premises logically imply. Ignoratio
elenchi means “ignorance of the proof.” The arguer is ignorant of the logical implications of his
or her own premises and, as a result, draws a conclusion that misses the point entirely. Consider
the following argument.
The world is in the process of globalizing more than ever. The world economy is becoming more
and more interconnected. Multinational companies and supra national institutions are taking
power from local companies and national governments. The livelihood of people is randomly
affected by action and decision made on the other side of the planet and this process benefits
only the rich nations at the expense of the poor. What should be done? The answer is obvious:
poor nations should detach themselves from the process.
Are the premises and the conclusion in this argument related? It is unrelated. The correct
conclusion would be to redirect globalization in a way that is beneficial for both the poor and the
rich, not to detach countries from the process. The above conclusion however is logically not
related with the premises. After all, detachment from globalization process is more costly for
poor countries. It is better to regulate the process of globalization than to detach altogether from
the system if that is possible.
Activity # 9: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of missing the point?
This fallacy is closely associated with missing the point. It is committed when the arguer diverts
the attention of the reader or listener by changing the subject to a different but sometimes subtly
related one. He or she then finishes by either drawing a conclusion about this different issue or
by merely presuming that some conclusion has been established. By so doing, the arguer
purports to have won the argument.
The fallacy gets its name from a procedure used to train hunting dogs to follow a scent. A red
herring (smoked and dried fish species) is dragged across the trail with the aim of leading the
dogs astray. Since red herrings have an especially potent scent (caused in part by the smoking
process used to preserve them), only the best dogs will follow the original scent.
To use the red herring fallacy effectively, the arguer must change the original subject of the
argument without the reader or listener noticing it. One way of doing this is to change the subject
to one that is subtly related to the original subject. Consider the following argument to
understand the point clearly.
The editors of Addis Flower newspaper have accused our company of being one of the city’s
worst water polluters. But Addis flower newspaper is responsible for much more pollution than
we are. After all, they own a Paper Company, and that company discharges tons of chemical
residues into the city’s river every day.
Dear learners, do you think this is a good argument. Let us analyze this argument. There are two
individuals here: a certain editor accusing a certain company about its impact on water quality
and the response of representative of the company. The editor accused the company as a worst
water polluter. But the response from the representative is not about why it is not a worst
polluter; rather it changes the topic into the activity of the paper company in which the editor is
working and accused the company as a worst water polluter. In other words, attention is diverted
from the original topic into a new topic.
Now the question is: is it a right response? The answer is no; because even if the paper company
is the worst water polluters that does not mean that the editor accusation is wrong. The editor’s
accusation is wrong only if evidence is given which proof to the contrary. But no evidence is
given to proof it; rather the activity of another company is discussed which is logically irrelevant
with the original topic. So it is called red herring fallacy because the topic is slightly changed
By: Teklay G. (AkU), Adane T. (MU), and Zelalem M. (HMU) 167
into another but closely related topic. But if the readers do not have experience in following
ideas, they will not notice that there is change of the topic.
A second way of using the red herring effectively is to change the subject to some flashy, eye-
catching topic that is virtually guaranteed to distract the listener’s attention. Topics of this sort
include sex, crime, scandal, immorality, death, and any other topic that might serve as the subject
of gossip. Here is an example of this technique:
Professor Conway complains of inadequate parking on our campus. But did you know that last
year Conway carried on a torrid love affair with a member of the English Department? The two
used to meet every day for clandestine sex in the copier room. Apparently they didn’t realize how
much you can see through that fogged glass window. Even the students got an eyeful. Enough
said about Conway.
The red herring fallacy can be confused with the straw man fallacy because both have the effect
of drawing the reader/listener off the track. This confusion can usually be avoided by
remembering the unique ways in which they accomplish this purpose. In the straw man, the
arguer begins by distorting an opponent’s argument and concludes by knocking down the
distorted argument. In the red herring, on the other hand, the arguer ignores the opponent’s
argument (if there is one) and subtly changes the subject. Thus, to distinguish the two fallacies,
one should attempt to determine whether the arguer has knocked down a distorted argument or
simply changed the subject. Also keep in mind that straw man always involves two arguers, at
least implicitly, whereas a red herring often does not.
Both the red herring and straw man fallacies are susceptible of being confused with missing the
point, because all three involve a similar kind of irrelevancy. To avoid this confusion, one should
note that both red herring and straw man proceed by generating a new set of premises, whereas
missing the point does not. Straw man draws a conclusion from new premises that are obtained
by distorting an earlier argument, and red herring, if it draws any conclusion at all, draws one
from new premises obtained by changing the subject. Missing the point, however, draws a
conclusion from the original premises. Also, in the red herring and straw man, the conclusion, if
there is one, is relevant to the premises from which it is drawn; but in missing the point, the
conclusion is irrelevant to the premises from which it is drawn. Finally, remember that missing
the point serves in part as a kind of catchall fallacy, and a fallacious argument should not be
identified as a case of missing the point if one of the other fallacies clearly fits.
The main function of premises in an argument is to provide reasons so that a reasonable person
would accept the truth of the conclusion. It is a rule of a good argument to contain premises that
together constitute sufficient grounds for the truth of the conclusion. They must provide
sufficient reasons for a rational person to accept the conclusion as true. In some arguments,
premises provide strong reason for the conclusion to be acceptable. Sometimes, however,
premises may not successfully support the conclusion. If premises do not support the conclusion
strongly then the resulting argument will be labeled as Weak Induction.
The fallacy of weak induction violates the principles of sufficiency, which states that whenever a
person presents an argument for or against a position, he/she should attempt to provide
relevant and acceptable reasons of the right kind, that together are sufficient in
number and weight to justify the acceptance of the conclusion. Therefore, the fallacies of weak
induction occur not because the premises are logically irrelevant to the conclusion, as is the case
with the eight fallacies of relevance, but because the connection between premises and
conclusion is not strong enough to support the conclusion.
There are different kinds of fallacies of weak induction and the following are the most important
ones: Appeal to Unqualified Authority, Hasty Generalization, False Cause, Weak Analogy,
Slippery Slope, and Appeal to Ignorance. In each of these fallacies, the premises provide at least
a shred of evidence in support of the conclusion, but the evidence is not nearly good enough to
cause a reasonable person to believe the conclusion. Like the fallacies of relevance, however, the
fallacies of weak induction often involve emotional grounds for believing the conclusion. In this
lesson, we will discuss the above six fallacies of weak induction.
Lesson objectives:
Activity # 3: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of appeal to ignorance?
When the premises of an argument state that nothing has been proved one way or the other about
something, and the conclusion then makes a definite assertion about that thing, the argument
commits an appeal to ignorance. The issue usually involves something that is incapable of being
proved or something that has not yet been proved. Observe the following example:
People have been trying for centuries to provide conclusive evidence for the claims that
Haileselassie I of Ethiopia is the descendant of King David of Israel and no one has ever
succeeded. Therefore, we must conclude that Haileselassie I of Ethiopia is not the descendant of
King David of Israel.
Conversely, the following argument commits the same fallacy:
People have been trying for centuries to prove the claims that Haileselassie I of Ethiopia is not
the descendant of King David of Israel, and no one has ever succeeded. Therefore, we must
conclude that Haileselassie I of Ethiopia is in fact the descendant of King David of Israel. .
The premises of an argument are supposed to provide positive evidence for the conclusion. The
premises of these arguments, however, tell us nothing about the alleged relationship between
Teams of historian have tried for long time to verify the proposition that King Tewodros II of
Ethiopia did not commit suicide during the British attack of Maqdella but they failed to do so.
Therefore, we must conclude that King Tewodros actually committed suicide at Maqdella.
The premises of this argument are true. Given the circumstances, it is likely that the historian in
question would have proved if King Tewodros II did not commit suicide. Since they did not
proof it, it likely that he did commit suicide. Thus, we can say that the above argument is
inductively strong.
As for the two arguments about the alleged relationship between Haileselassie I of Ethiopia and
Kind David of Israel, if the attempts to prove or disprove the historical claims had been done in a
systematic way by qualified experts, it is more likely that the arguments would be good. But as
these arguments stand, the premises state nothing about the qualifications of the investigators,
and so the arguments remain fallacious.
The second exception to the appeal to ignorance relates to courtroom procedure. In Ethiopia, a
person is presumed innocent until proven guilty. If the prosecutor in a criminal trial fails to prove
the guilt of the defendant beyond reasonable doubt, counsel for the defence may justifiably argue
that his or her client is not guilty. Example:
Members of the jury, you have heard the prosecution present its case against the defendant.
Nothing, however, has been proved beyond a reasonable doubt. Therefore, under the law, the
defendant is not guilty.
This argument commits no fallacy because “not guilty” means, in the legal sense, that guilt
beyond a reasonable doubt has not been proved. The defendant may indeed have committed the
crime of which he or she is accused, but if the prosecutor fails to prove guilt beyond a reasonable
doubt, the defendant is considered “not guilty.”
Activity # 4: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of hasty generalization?
Activity # 5: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of false cause?
False cause fallacy is a defective and flawed form of argument from causality. Before discussing
about false cause, we need to discuss about causal inference first. Argument from causality is a
kind of argument which argues either from the knowledge of causes to the knowledge of effects
or from the knowledge of the effect to the knowledge of causes. In such argument two things are
presented as having causal connection.
However, it seems that there is no settled scientific theory of causality. It seems that the causal
relationship is practical and contextual in nature. What it means to say that, one state of affairs A
causes another state of affairs B, is that A is something that can be brought about and when it is
brought about (or stopped), then B is also brought about (or stopped).
Whatever causality means, the most important kind of evidence that event A causes event B in
any particular case, is that there is a statistical correlation between A and B: event A and event B
are correlated. For example, if a significant statistical correlation is found between reduced
incidence of heart attacks and drinking of red wine, the tentative conclusion may be drawn as a
hypothesis is that drinking red wine is the cause of the reduction in heart attacks.
A correlation is a purely statistical relationship, determined by counting up numbers where one
event occurs in a case where another event also occurs. One problem with arguments from
correlation to cause is that there may not be a real correlation between two events, but people
might believe that relation exists. Another problem is that a statistical correlation between two
events can simply be a coincidence. Consider the following example.
A sophisticated statistical study by Dr. Zemenu Ahmed and Pro. Wakjira Negera citing studies
from 141 countries found that the larger the per cent of its gross national product a country
spends on weapons, the higher is its infant death rate. Dr. Zemenu Ahmed and Pro. Wakjira
concluded that there is a plausible link between military spending and the infant death rate.
However, critics questioned whether their finding represents anything more than a coincidence.
Dr. Bilal Ahmed a statistician at the Ethiopian statistics authority said that the same statistical
Activity # 6: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of slippery slope?
Slippery slope fallacy is a defective form of argument from slippery slope. Before discussing
about slippery slope fallacy, some points should be raised about slippery slope argument. One
very common form of argumentation is used when one party in a dialogue says to the other,
“This action would not be good, because it could have bad consequences.” For example, suppose
you are thinking of taking a certain medication and your doctor says, “You have high blood
pressure, and taking this medication raises blood pressure, so in your case there would be a bad
side effect of taking it.” This form of argumentation is called argument from consequences.
It cites allegedly foreseeable consequences of a proposed action as the premise, and the
conclusion is then inferred that this course of action is or is not recommended. This form of
reasoning can be used in a positive or negative way, as an argument to respond to a proposal that
has been put forward when two parties are having a dialogue on what to do. In argument from
positive consequences, a policy or course of action is supported by citing positive consequences
of carrying out this policy or course of action. In argument from negative consequences, a policy
or course of action is argued against by citing negative consequences of carrying it out.
A slippery slope argument is a species of negative reasoning from consequences, used where two
parties are deliberating together and one warns the other not to take a contemplated action,
because it is a first step in a sequence of events that will lead to some horrible outcome. What is
distinctive about the slippery slope argument as a special subtype of argument from
consequences is that there is said to be a connected sequence of actions, such that once the first
Activity # 7: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of weak analogy?
Weak analogy is a defective or flawed argument from analogy. Argument from analogy is a very
commonly used kind of case-based reasoning, where one case is held to be similar to another
case in a particular respect. Since the one case is held to have a certain property, then the other
case, it is concluded, also has the same property (because the one case is similar to the other).
Two things, situations or cases could be similar to each other in certain respects, but dissimilar in
other respects. While one case may be generally similar to another, it does not mean that the two
cases will be similar in every respect. If they were similar in every respect, they would be
identical case. However, two cases can be generally similar, even though there are quite
important differences between them. Consider the following example.
After ingesting one milligram of substance alpha per day for ninety days, white mice developed
genetic abnormalities. Since white mice are similar in many ways to humans, it follows that
substance alpha probably produces genetic abnormalities in humans.
This argument compares two cases, the effects of some substances on human and mice. It argues
that this substance produce genetic abnormalities on mice, then postulates comparable
consequences on humans. It is built onto an argument from analogy; based on a comparison
between the two cases. Of course, the two cases are different in certain respects, but by
comparing them, it puts forward a plausible argument.
The fallacy of weak analogy is committed when the analogy between things, situations and
circumstance is not strong enough to support the conclusion that is drawn. Evaluating an
argument having this form requires a two-step procedure: (1) Identify the attributes a, b, c,. . that
the two entities A and B share in common, and (2) determine how the attribute z, mentioned in
the conclusion, relates to the attributes a, b, c, . . . If some causal or systematic relation exists
between z and a, b, or c, the argument is strong; otherwise it is weak.
The fallacies of presumption include begging the question, complex question, false dichotomy,
and suppressed evidence. These fallacies arise not because the premises are irrelevant to the
conclusion or provide insufficient reason for believing the conclusion but because the premises
presume what they purport to prove. Begging the question presumes that the premises provide
adequate support for the conclusion when in fact they do not, and complex question presumes
Lesson objectives:
The fallacy of begging the question is committed whenever the arguer creates the illusion that
inadequate premises provide adequate support for the conclusion by leaving out a possibly false
(shaky) key premise, by restating a possibly false premise as the conclusion, or by reasoning in a
circle. The Latin name for this fallacy, petition principii, means “request for the source.” The
actual source of support for the conclusion is not apparent, and so the argument is said to beg the
question. After reading or hearing the argument, the observer is inclined to ask, “But how do you
know X?” where X is the needed support.
The first, and most common, way of committing this fallacy is by leaving a possibly false key
premise out of the argument while creating the illusion that nothing more is needed to establish
the conclusion. Examples:
Murder is morally wrong. This being the case, it follows that abortion is morally wrong.
Of course humans and apes evolved from common ancestors. Just look how similar they are.
It’s obvious that the poor in this country should be given handouts from the government. After
all, these people earn less than the average citizen.
Clearly, terminally ill patients have a right to doctor-assisted suicide. After all, many of these
people are unable to commit suicide by themselves.
Activity # 2: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of complex question?
You were asked where you hide the body of the person you killed. You replied “under the bed.”
It follows that you were in fact killed the person.
On the other hand, let us suppose that the respondent answers “no” to the first question and
“nowhere” to the second. We then have the following arguments:
You were asked whether you have stopped cheating on exams. You answered “no.” Therefore,
you continue to cheat.
You were asked where you hide the body of the person you killed. You answered “nowhere.”It
follows that you have destroyed the corpse.
Obviously, each of the questions is really two questions:
Did you cheat on exams in the past? If you did cheat in the past, have you stopped now?
Where did you hide the corpse of the person you killed? If you were killed it, where did you hide
it?
If respondents are not sophisticated enough to identify a complex question when one is put to
them, they may answer quite innocently and be trapped by a conclusion that is supported by no
evidence at all; or, they may be tricked into providing the evidence themselves. The correct
response lies in resolving the complex question into its component questions and answering each
separately.
Leading questions differ from complex questions in that they involve no logical fallacies—that
is, they do not attempt to trick the respondent into admitting something he or she does not want
to admit. To distinguish the two, however, it is sometimes necessary to know whether prior
questions have been asked.
Activity # 3: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of false dichotomy?
Activity # 4: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of suppressed evidence?
Chapter 2 explained that a cogent argument is an inductive argument with good reasoning and
true premises. The requirement of true premises includes the proviso that the premises not ignore
some important piece of evidence that outweighs the presented evidence and entails a very
different conclusion. If an inductive argument does indeed ignore such evidence, then the
argument commits the fallacy of suppressed evidence. Consider the following argument:
Somalia is a good place for investment for the following reasons. First there are cheap raw
materials. Second there is cheap labor. Third there is good market for our product. Forth there
is a port that helps us to export our product. Thus we have to consider investing in Somalia.
If the arguer ignores the fact that there is no peace and stability in Somalia then the argument
commits a suppressed evidence fallacy. This fallacy is classified as a fallacy of presumption
because it works by creating the presumption that the premises are both true and complete when
in fact they are not.
The fallacies of ambiguity includes equivocation and amphiboly. These fallacies arise from the
occurrence of some form of ambiguity in either the premises or the conclusion (or both). An
expression is ambiguous if it is susceptible to different interpretations in a given context. When
the conclusion of an argument depends on a shift in meaning of an ambiguous word or phrase or
on the wrong interpretation of an ambiguous statement, the argument commits a fallacy of
ambiguity.
The fallacies of grammatical analogy include composition and division. Arguments that commit
these fallacies are grammatically analogous to other arguments that are good in every respect.
Because of this similarity in linguistic structure, such fallacious arguments may appear good yet
be bad. In this lesson, we will discuss the four fallacies.
Lesson objectives:
19) Equivocation
The fallacy of equivocation occurs when the conclusion of an argument depends on the fact that
a word or phrase is used, either explicitly or implicitly, in two different senses in the argument.
Such arguments are either invalid or have a false premise, and in either case they are unsound.
Examples:
Some triangles are obtuse. Whatever is obtuse is ignorant. Therefore, some triangles are
ignorant.
Any law can be repealed by the legislative authority. But the law of gravity is a law. Therefore,
the law of gravity can be repealed by the legislative authority.
We have a duty to do what is right. We have a right to speak out in defence of the innocent.
20) Amphiboly
Activity # 3: Dear learners, what do you think is the fallacy of amphiboly?
The fallacy of amphiboly occurs when the arguer misinterprets an ambiguous statement and then
draws a conclusion based on this faulty interpretation. The original statement is usually asserted
by someone other than the arguer, and the ambiguity usually arises from a mistake in grammar or
punctuation - a missing comma, a dangling modifier, an ambiguous antecedent of a pronoun, or
some other careless arrangement of words. Because of this ambiguity, the statement may be
understood in two clearly distinguishable ways. The arguer typically selects the unintended
interpretation and proceeds to draw a conclusion based upon it. Here are some examples:
The tour guide said that standing in Mesqel Square, the new federal police building could easily be seen.
It follows that the Empire State Building is in Greenwich Village.
Habtom told Megeressa that he had made a mistake. It follows that Habtom has at least the courage to
admit his own mistakes.
The premise of the first argument contains a dangling modifier. Is it the observer or the building
that is supposed to be standing in Greenwich Village? The factually correct interpretation is the
former. In the second argument the pronoun “he” has an ambiguous antecedent; it can refer
either to Habtom or Megressa. Perhaps Habtom told Megressa that Megreesa had made a
mistake. Ambiguities of this sort are called syntactical ambiguities.
Two areas where cases of amphiboly cause serious problems involve contracts and
wills. The drafters of these documents often express their intentions in terms of ambiguous
statements, and alternate interpretations of these statements then lead to different conclusions.
Examples:
Mrs. Zenebu stated that in her will that “I leave my house and my clothes to Lemma and
Mengistu.”Therefore, we conclude that Lemma gets the house and Mengistu gets the car.
In the first example, the conclusion obviously favors Lemma. Mengistu is almost certain to argue
that the gift of the clothes and the house should be shared equally by her and Lemma. Mrs.
21) Composition
The fallacy of composition is committed when the conclusion of an argument depends on the
erroneous transference of an attribute from the parts of something onto the whole. In other
words, the fallacy occurs when it is argued that because the parts have a certain attribute, it
follows that the whole has that attribute too and the situation is such that the attribute in question
cannot be legitimately transferred from parts to whole.
Examples:
Each player on this basketball team is an excellent athlete. Therefore, the team as a whole
is excellent.
Each atom in this piece of chalk is invisible. Therefore, the chalk is invisible.
By: Teklay G. (AkU), Adane T. (MU), and Zelalem M. (HMU) 192
Sodium and chlorine, the atomic components of salt, are both deadly poisons. Therefore,
salt is a deadly poison.
In these arguments, the attributes that are transferred from the parts onto the whole are
designated by the words “excellent,” “invisible” and “deadly poison,” respectively. In each case
the transference is illegitimate, and so the argument is fallacious. Not every such transference is
illegitimate, however. Consider the following arguments:
Every atom in this piece of chalk has mass. Therefore, the piece of chalk has mass.
Every component in this picket fence is white. Therefore, the whole fence is white ..
In each case, an attribute (having mass, being white) is transferred from the parts onto the whole,
but these transferences are quite legitimate. Indeed, the fact that the atoms have mass is the very
reason why the chalk has mass. The same reasoning extends to the fence. Thus, the acceptability
of these arguments is attributable, at least in part, to the legitimate transference of an attribute
from parts onto the whole.
Further caution is required by the fact that composition is sometimes confused with hasty
generalization. The only time this confusion is possible is when the “whole” is a class (such as
the class of people in a city or the class of trees in a forest), and the “parts” are the members of
the class. In such a case, composition proceeds from the members of the class to the class itself.
Hasty generalization, on the other hand, proceeds from the specific to the general. Because it is
sometimes easy to mistake a statement about a class for a general statement, composition can be
mistaken for hasty generalization. Such a mistake can be avoided if one is careful to keep in
mind the distinction between these two kinds of statements. This distinction falls back on the
difference between the collective and the distributive predication of an attribute. Consider the
following statements:
Statement One: Fleas are small.
Statement Two: Fleas are numerous.
The first statement is a general statement. The attribute of being small is predicated
distributively; that is, it is assigned (or distributed) to each and every flea in the class. Each and
every flea in the class is said to be small. The second statement, on the other hand, is a statement
about a class as a whole, or what we will call a ‘‘class statement.’’ The attribute of being
numerous is predicated collectively; in other words, it is assigned not to the individual fleas but
to the class of fleas. The meaning of the statement is not that each and every flea is numerous but
22) Division
The fallacy of division is the exact reverse of composition. As composition goes from parts to
whole, division goes from whole to parts. The fallacy is committed when the conclusion of an
argument depends on the erroneous transference of an attribute from a whole (or a class) onto its
parts (or members).
Examples:
Salt is a non-poisonous compound. Therefore, its component elements, sodium and chlorine, are
non-poisonous.
The Royal Society is over 300 years old. General Merid Hussein is a member of the Royal
Society. Therefore, General Merid Hussein is over 300 years old.
Chapter Summary
A fallacy is a mistake in an argument that arises from something other than merely false
premises. Usually fallacies involve defects in reasoning or the creation of an illusion that makes
a bad argument appear good. Fallacies can be either formal or informal. A formal fallacy is one
that can be detected by analyzing the form of an argument; such fallacies affect only deductive
arguments. An informal fallacy is one that can be identified only by analyzing the content of an
argument; such fallacies can affect both deductive and inductive arguments.
The fallacies of relevance occur when the premises of an argument are not relevant to the
conclusion. Cases of such irrelevance occur in premises that threaten the observer, elicit pity
from the observer, create a mob mentality in a group of observers, appeal to the observer’s desire
for security, verbally abuse an opposing arguer, present an opposing arguer as predisposed to
argue as he does, present an opposing arguer as a hypocrite, misapply a general rule, distort an
References
Hurley, Patrick. A Concise Introduction to Logic. 2006. Routledge, USA. 9th ed.
Howord, Snyder, et al, The Power of Logic, MacGrewHill, USA.
Gensler, Harry, Introduction to Logic. Routledge, USA. 2ND ed.
Walton, Douglas. Fundamentals of Critical Argumentation. 2006. Cambridge University, USA.
Chapter Overview:
Dear students, in the fifth chapter of this course, we have seen Logical Reasoning and Fallacies.
However, this chapter emphasizes the standard forms of categorical statements and their
immediate inferences, difference between the modern and traditional squares of opposition what
otherwise are called Boolean and Aristotelian Square of Oppositions, evaluating immediate
inferences: Venn Diagrams and Square of Oppositions and Logical Operations: Conversion,
Obversion, and Contraposition.
Chapter Objectives:
Lesson objectives:
▪ Quantifier = ‘All’, ‘No’ and ‘Some’ indicate the quantity or amount of the subject class.
▪ Subject term = any term (word) or phrase that consists of set of things.
▪ Copula = ‘Are’ and are ‘not’. The Latin copula is a sentential connective that relates the
subject and predicate terms.
▪ Predicate term – A term consisting set of things, which has some kind of relation with
the subject term.
Dear students, please note that the four components of standard form can, otherwise, be summarized as
follow:
(1) Those that assert that the whole subject class is included in the predicate class
(2) Those that assert that part of the subject class is included in the predicate class,
(3) Those that assert that the whole subject class is excluded from the predicate class,
(4) Those that assert that part of the subject class is excluded from the predicate class
The following is, therefore, the correct order of the standard form of a categorical proposition.
Copula: are
Quantifier: Some
Subject term: businesses
Copula: are not
Predicate term: Profitable
Standard form: Some S are not P
Quality and quantity are attributes of categorical propositions. Here, it is useful to rephrase the
meaning of categorical propositions in class terminology:
These are the three fundamental concepts that would help us to deal with the properties of the
four standard forms of categorical statement.
Lesson objectives:
1. What do you think of the need for representing categorical propositions by letter names?
2. Guess what are the four components of categorical proposition and their functions in
logical arguments?
A. Quality:
It refers to those set of things stated in the subject term that are included or excluded from
those set of things stated in the predicate term. If the subject term refers to those classes of things,
which are included (partially/entirely) in the predicate term, the proposition is said to be
affirmative, while if the subject term refers to those classes of things that are excluded
(partially/entirely) the proposition is said to be negative. Study the following table.
Standard form Quality
All S are P Affirmative
No S are P Negative
Some S are P Affirmative
Some S are not P Negative
According to the quality and quantity of categorical propositions, logicians devised letter names
of the four propositions. Letter names of the standard forms of categorical propositions, in this
regard, would help us to:
__________________________________________________________________
E
All S are P
O
C. Distribution: The concept of distribution emphasizes the terms (the subject & predicate
terms) and not the proposition as such. If a term refers unambiguously the set of things
stated in it entirely the term is said to be distributed. It implies that attribute of the class is
distributed to each & every member of the class and we know clearly that the attribute is
shared similarly by every member of the class. If a term does not state the class of things
in this way, the term is said to be undistributed. Study the following table:
How to determine the quality, quantity & distribution? Study the following example.
Lesson Objectives:
At the end of this lesson, you will be able to:
• Understand what venn diagram ,in its broader sense, mean
• How to represent propositions/arguments in in diagram
• Distinguish the difference between modern and traditional square of opposition.
Activity #1:-
What do you think of to represent arguments/categorical propositions in a diagram?
Make a group of five and discuss the feasible difference and similarities, if any, between
modern and traditional squares of opposition.
The two categories (set of things) stated in the subject and predicate terms are
represented by two overlapping circles.
The shading part of the diagram depicts that there no member of the class exists; that
is it is null or empty.
The “*” or simply “X” shows that there is at least one member of the class exists.
Study the following Venn diagrams.
1. Proposition A= All S are P
2. Proposition E = No S are P
Ex. No Marxists are revolutionary
The shaded part shows that the intersection area is
empty. For the proposition “No S are P” no middle
If two propositions are related by the contradictory relation, they necessarily have opposite
truth value. Thus, if a certain ‘A’ proposition is given as true, the corresponding ‘O’ proposition
must be false. Similarly, if certain ‘I’ proposition is given as false, the corresponding ‘E’
proposition must be true. But no other inferences are possible. In particular, given the truth value
of an ‘A or O’ proposition, nothing can be determined about the truth value of the corresponding
E or I propositions. These propositions are said to have logically undetermined truth value.
Like all propositions, they do have a truth value, but logic alone cannot determine what it is.
Similarly, given the truth value of an E or I proposition, nothing can be determined about the
truth value of the corresponding A or O propositions. They, too, are said to have logically
undetermined truth value.
The four relations in the traditional square of opposition may be characterized as follows:
Lesson objectives:
At the end of this lesson, student will be able to:
To diagram “It is false that all A are B,” we enter an X in the left-hand part of the A circle.
Entering an X in an area is the opposite of shading an area:
If the information expressed by the conclusion diagram is contained in the premise diagram, the
argument is valid; if not, it is invalid. Here is the symbolized form of the trade spies inference
that we tested earlier.
Some T are not M.
Therefore, it is false that all T are M.
The next step is to draw two Venn diagrams, one for the premise and the other for the
conclusion. For the premise we enter an X in the left -hand part of the T circle, and for the
conclusion, as we have just seen, we enter an X in the left -hand part of the T circle:
To evaluate the inference, we look to see whether the information expressed by the conclusion
diagram is also expressed by the premise diagram. The conclusion diagram asserts that
something exists in the left -hand part of the T circle. Since this information is also expressed by
Here, the conclusion diagram asserts that the overlap area is empty. Since this information is not
contained in the premise diagram, the inference is invalid. We conclude with a special kind of
inference that: the information of the conclusion diagram is not contained in the premise
diagram, so the inference is invalid. However, if the premise were interpreted as having
existential import, then the C circle in the premise diagram would not be empty. Specifically,
there would be members in the overlap area. This would make the inference valid.
Arguments of this sort are said to commit the existential fallacy. From the Boolean standpoint,
the existential fallacy is a formal fallacy that occurs whenever an argument is invalid merely
because the premise lacks existential import. Such arguments always have a universal premise
and a particular conclusion. The fallacy consists in attempting to derive a conclusion having
existential import from a premise that lacks it.
The existential fallacy is easy to detect. Just look for a pair of diagrams in which the premise
diagram contains shading and the conclusion diagram contains an X. If the X in the conclusion
diagram is in the same part of the left -hand circle that is unshaded in the premise diagram, then
The simplest of the three operations is conversion, and it consists in switching the subject term
with the predicate term. For example, if the statement “No foxes are hedgehogs” is converted,
the resulting statement is “No hedgehogs are foxes.” This new statement is called the converse of
the given statement. To see how the four types of categorical propositions relate to their
converse, compare the following sets of Venn diagrams:
All Christians are Muslims = False – which is the same truth value as the given
proposition.
2. In Proposition (I)
These examples clearly show that we cannot form valid arguments form propositions A
and O
Activity # 2 Dear students, do you remember how a deductive argument is evaluated as valid or
invalid?
We have the confidence in you that, you did not forget the two basic factors for an argument to
be invalid:
Do you know about fallacies? You have to know that fallacies are mistakes committed
in arguments which deludes us into thinking that the mistaken argument as correct one.
They are classified as formal and informal fallacies. Informal fallacies can be detected
by examining the logical problem in the argument, while formal fallacies can be known
simply by their logically incorrect forms that are by the position of terms, quantifiers
and statements. The diagram for the A statement is clearly not identical to the diagram
for its converse, and the diagram for the O statement is not identical to the diagram for
its converse. Also, these pairs of diagrams are not the exact opposite of each other, as is
the case with contradictory statements. This means that an A statement and its converse
are logically unrelated as to truth value, and an O statement and its converse are
logically unrelated as to truth value. In other words, converting an ‘A’ or ‘O’ statement
By: Teklay G. (AkU), Adane T. (MU), and Zelalem M. (HMU) 219
gives a new statement whose truth value is logically undetermined in relation to the
given statement. The converse of an A or O statement does have a truth value, of
course, but logic alone cannot tell us what it is. Because conversion yields necessarily
determined results for E and I statements, it can be used as the basis for immediate
inferences having these types of statements as premises. The following inference forms
are valid:
No A are B.
Therefore, no B are A.
Some A are B.
Therefore, some B are A.
Since the conclusion of each inference form necessarily has the same truth value as the premise,
if the premise is assumed true, it follows necessarily that the conclusion is true. On the other
hand, the next two inference forms are invalid. Each commits the fallacy of illicit conversion:
All A are B.
Therefore, all B are A.
Some A are not B.
Therefore, some B are not A.
Here are two examples of inferences that commit the fallacy of illicit conversion:
All cats are animals. (True)
Therefore, all animals are cats. (False)
Some animals are not dogs. (True)
Therefore, some dogs are not animals. (False)
Accordingly, the immediate inferences of proposition A and O in the case of conversion are
invalid and the formal fallacy committed in the invalid arguments of these propositions is called
illicit conversion. It is a logically incorrect conversion; hence, it is named as illicit conversion.
b. Change the predicate by its term complement. A term which has opposite
meaning against the meaning of a given term is called term complement. A
By Obversion
We now have everything we need to form the obverse of categorical propositions. First, we
change the quality (without changing the quantity), and then we replace the predicate term with
its term complement. For example, if we are given the statement “All horses are animals,” then
the obverse is “No horses are non-animals”; and if we are given the statement “Some trees are
maples,” then the obverse is “Some trees are not non-maples.” To see how the four types of
categorical propositions relate to their obverse, compare the following sets of Venn diagrams:
According to the rule of contraposition, proposition ‘A’ and ‘O’ would give us the same truth
value, while proposition E and I do not. This is just the opposite of what we have observed in the
case of conversion. Please the following contrapositions.
A = All worshipers are believers = True
All non- believers are non- worshipers = True
When it is correctly phrased:-
All atheists are un worshipers
O = Some delicious foods are not good for health = True
Some that are bad for health are bad foods = True
As with conversion and obversion, contraposition may provide the link between the premise and
the conclusion of an immediate inference. The following inference forms are valid:
All A are B.
Therefore, all non-B are non-A.
Some A are not B.
Therefore, some non-B are not non-A.
Chapter Summary
A proposition that relates two classes, or categories, is called a categorical proposition. The
classes in question are denoted respectively by the subject term and the predicate term, and the
proposition asserts that either all or part of the class denoted by the subject term is included in or
excluded from the class denoted by the predicate term. To put the same ideas in different words,
a categorical proposition is a statement that relates two sets, classes, groups or categories which
are presented in their subject or predicate positions that could be connected based on inclusion
(partial/whole) or exclusion (partial/whole) relations. In this chapter, you have, also, learnt the
different components of categorical proposition, the difference between modern and traditional
square of opposition and how to evaluate arguments/inferences using different propositional
representation.
=====================================================================
2. What problems would occur if categorical propositions are not settled in standard form?
_______________________________________________________________________
4. Write a categorical proposition in which its quantifier is “some”, its subject term
“soldier” and predicate term “cowards” and its copula “are not”
__________________________________________________________________
5. If a categorical proposition states that “there is at least one X and that X is in Y”, its
symbolic representation will be
__________________________________________________________________
6. The standard form of “All S are not P” is not a correct standard form. Why?
________________________________________________________________
7. Write a categorical statement in which its subject class is entirely included in the
predicate class.
_________________________________________________________________
I. Draw Venn diagrams for the following propositions.
III. Convert the following propositions and state whether the converse is logically
equivalent or not logically equivalent to the given proposition.
a. All radically egalitarian societies are societies that do not preserve individual liberties.
b. No cult leaders are people who fail to brainwash their followers.
References
Textbooks
Hurley, Patrick J. (2014) A Concise Introduction to Logic, 12th Edition, Wadsworth, Cengage
Learning.
Hurley, Patrick J. (2012) A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11th Edition, Wadsworth, Cengage
Learning.
Reference Books
Copi, Irving M.and Carl Cohen, (1990) Introduction to Logic, New York: Macmillan Publishing
Company.
Damer, Edward. (2005). Attacking faulty reasoning. A practical guide to fallacy free argument.
Wadsworth Cengage learning, USA.
Fogelin, Robert, J, (1987) Understanding Arguments: An Introduction to Informal Logic, New York:
Harcourt Brace Jvanovich Publisher.
Guttenplan, Samuel: (1991) The Language of Logic. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers
Simico, N.D and G.G James. (1983) Elementary Logic, Belmont, Ca: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
Stephen, C. (200) The Power of Logic. London and Toronto: Mayfield Publishing Company.
Walelign, Emuru, (2009) Freshman Logic, Addis Ababa.