Lepauvre & Melloni - The Search For The Neural Correlate of Consciousness. Progress and Challenges (Philosophy and The Mind Sciences, 2021)
Lepauvre & Melloni - The Search For The Neural Correlate of Consciousness. Progress and Challenges (Philosophy and The Mind Sciences, 2021)
Abstract
Twenty years ago, Thomas Metzinger published the book The Neural Correlates of Consciousness
amassing the state of knowledge in the field of consciousness studies at the time from philosophical
and empirical perspectives. On the occasion of the 20th anniversary of this impactful publication,
we review the progress the field has made since then and the important methodological challenges
it faces. A tremendous number of empirical studies have been conducted, which has led to the
identification of many candidate neural correlates of consciousness. Yet, this tremendous amount
of work has not unraveled a consensual account of consciousness as of now. Many questions,
some already raised twenty years ago, remain unanswered, and an enormous proliferation of
theories sharply contrasts with the scarcity of compelling data and methodological challenges. The
contrastive method, the foundational method used to study the neural correlate of consciousness
(NCC), has also been called into question. And while awareness in the community of its
shortcomings is widespread, few concrete attempts have been made to go beyond it and/or to
revise existing theories. We propose several methodological shifts that we believe may help to
advance the quest of the NCC program, while remaining uncommitted to any specific theory:
(1) the currently prevalent “contrastive method” should lose its monopoly in favor of methods
that attempt to explain the phenomenology of experience; (2) experimental data should be shared
in centralized, multi-methods databases, transcending the limitations of individual experiments
by granting granularity and power to generalize findings and “distill” the NCC proper; (3) the
explanatory power of theories should be directly pitted against each other to overcome the
non-productive fractioning of the field into insular camps seeking confirmatory evidence for their
theories. We predict these innovations might enable the field to progress towards the goal of
explaining consciousness.
Keywords
Adversarial collaboration ∙ Big data ∙ Consciousness ∙ Contrastive method ∙ Neural correlate of
consciousness ∙ Phenomenology
a
Department of Neuroscience, Max Planck Institute for Empirical Aesthetics, Frankfurt am Main
b
Department of Neurology, NYU Grossmann School of Medicine
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 2
1 Introduction
Men ought to know that from the brain, and from the brain only, arise
our pleasures, joys, laughter, and jests, as well as our sorrows, pains,
griefs, and tears. Through it, in particular, we think, see, hear, and
distinguish the ugly from the beautiful, the bad from the good, the
pleasant from the unpleasant.
Since the time of Hippocrates, mankind has attempted to understand what con-
sciousness is, what it does, and how physical systems such as the brain, but not
others such as the heart, can instantiate it. David Chalmers famously referred to
the latter aspect as “The Hard Problem” (Chalmers, 1995): why does matter, such as
the brain, give rise to perceptions and emotions that have subjective, phenomeno-
logical qualities?
As underlined by Metzinger (2000), the difficulty in studying consciousness
empirically lies in the inherent subjectivity of the phenomenon. This is indeed
the main reason why consciousness for a long time remained outside the scope
of modern sciences, whose primary goal is to understand objective phenomena.
Notwithstanding revolutionary discoveries made over the past century by study-
ing cerebral lesions and using electrical stimulation to probe brain function, as in
the pioneering work of Weiskrantz, Penfield, Libet, and Eccles among others (Ec-
cles, 1974; Libet et al., 1967; Penfield, 1958; Weiskrantz, 1980), it was Crick and
Koch’s seminal paper (1990) that provided a scientific framework for the study
of the neural correlates of consciousness that set the field in motion. Crick and
Koch proposed putting aside philosophical and metaphysical considerations and
to focus on the “easy problem of consciousness” (Crick & Koch, 1998), i.e., to study
the neural activity that correlates with consciousness while taking subjectivity as
a dependent variable (Dehaene, 2014). The focus of the science of consciousness
would be narrower, yet more tractable, clearly defined, and theoretically neutral,
i.e., in identifying the neural correlates of consciousness (NCCs): the minimal set of
neural events jointly sufficient for a specific conscious experience (given the appro-
priate enabling conditions, Chalmers, 2000). By quantifying which neural activity
best correlates with conscious experience, one could begin to narrow down the
mechanisms involved in consciousness, and to eventually formulate theories to
answer the hard questions of consciousness (Chalmers, 1995).
This bottom-up strategy has dominated the field for the past thirty years, fur-
ther propelled by the development of ever more refined methods for investigating
the human brain non-invasively, e.g., high-field imaging (7T) with laminar and
columnar resolution, and the rapid development of machine-learning algorithms
that have enabled researchers to track the contents of perception. Thirty years af-
ter Crick and Koch’s findings, we now face an entire cartography of brain areas and
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 3
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 4
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 5
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 6
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 7
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 8
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 9
only when subjects were reporting. Comparable results were obtained in forward
and backward masking paradigms, whereby a robust P3b was found in the report
condition, but was absent when subjects did not need to report (Cohen et al., 2020).
Instead, they found that an earlier (200–300ms) negative component over posterior
areas correlated with consciousness independently from report. This component,
named the visual awareness negativity, has been found to correlate with conscious-
ness across a range of studies (Koivisto & Revonsuo, 2010), making it a prime NCC
candidate (but see Melloni, Schwiedrzik, Müller, et al., 2011 for a more nuanced
discussion of the temporal dynamics related to the NCC). Moreover, P3b has also
been shown to differ between frequent and rare stimuli in oddball paradigms, even
when all the stimuli were unconsciously perceived, which calls into question P3b
activation as an exclusive marker of conscious perception (Silverstein et al., 2015).
Such observations are not limited to the visual domain, as Sergent et al. (2021)
recently showed that the P3b correlates with awareness of auditory stimuli during
the active report condition, but not during the no-report task.1
While these studies seem to relegate late, frontal activation to post-perceptual
processes only, other studies employing invasive and more sensitive methods, such
as electro-corticography (ECoG) and single-unit recording, have revealed a more
nuanced picture. For instance, Noy et al. (2015), using ECoG in epilepsy patients,
showed that while the late-onset frontal activation was present under reporting
conditions only, an initial glow spreading through all cortical areas, including the
pre-frontal cortex, was observed regardless of report. Additionally, Kapoor et al.
(2020), using single-unit recordings in macaque monkeys, showed that in the ab-
sence of overt report the content of consciousness can be accurately decoded from
the prefrontal cortex in binocular rivalry. Thus, while some of the previously ob-
served prefrontal activation might index confounding factors such as report, lead-
ing to an exacerbated prefrontal cortex activation, a selective portion might still
correspond to the NCC proper. As such, while no-report paradigms might deal
well with disregarding post-perceptual processes at the level of the experimental
design, by themselves they do not resolve the inherent sensitivity issue faced by
most non-invasive methodologies, e.g., fMRI, PET, M-EEG. Multimodal methodolo-
gies, and in particular a combination of invasive and non-invasive techniques, will
be necessary to arbitrate on the role of prefrontal cortex in consciousness, which
has been challenged by no-report paradigms.
Nevertheless, not all confounds relate to report (Melloni, Schwiedrzik, Muller,
et al., 2011). Prior expectation also influences neural activations in contrastive
paradigms (Aru, Axmacher, et al., 2012; Mayer et al., 2016; Melloni, Schwiedrzik,
Muller, et al., 2011). Therefore, the mechanisms of expectation and prior knowl-
edge are also confounding the search for NCC. In paradigms with passive view-
ing, such as in the experiment by Cohen et al. (2020), encoding in working mem-
ory occurs in the seen but not in the unseen condition, also confounding the em-
1
In that study, the best correlate of conscious access was found in a component overlapping in time
with the P3-like component but with a bilateral positivity over temporal regions.
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 10
pirical findings. Attention level constitutes yet another such confounding factor.
As observed by Pitts and colleagues (2014), in the case of inattentional blindness
paradigms, seen and unseen trials might also differ in the level of attention. Neural
processes related to decision making can also obscure the NCC proper as demon-
strated in a recent study by Mazzi et al. (2020). Here, while both the visual aware-
ness negativity (VAN) and P3b (termed LP, i.e., late positivity in the text) correlated
with awareness, P3b was tightly correlated with decision-making, i.e., with deci-
sion criteria. Siclari and colleagues have also recently addressed confounds present
in state paradigms, i.e., those investigating neural correlates of wakefulness and
sleep in REM vs. NREM states, which are confounded by differences in neuromod-
ulation across states (Siclari et al., 2017). They have extended the methodology to a
no-task, within-state paradigm, in which subjects are serially awakened and asked
to report dreams both during REM and NREM, enabling investigators to contrast
‘consciousness’ to lack thereof (i.e., reported presence vs. absence of dream in both
REM and non-REM sleep) while controlling for both the state and the neuromod-
ulation milieu. Thus, there are a number of confounds, some already known, for
instance: report, prior expectations, working memory, episodic memory, task de-
mands, attention, decision making, and neuromodulatory state. This list is not ex-
haustive. As more studies are carried out and our understanding of the processes
uniquely related to consciousness is improved, this list is likely to be expanded.
Aru, Bachmann, et al. (2012) have previously proposed that, in order to isolate the
NCC proper, it will first be necessary to control for all of these potential (known)
confounds in order to look for the neural activity that systematically relates to
consciousness. In a sense, this pursuit can be framed as a problem of generaliza-
tion: the search for brain responses that systematically covary with consciousness
while manipulating all other nuisance variables, e.g., stimuli, task, experimental
paradigms, and other cognitive processes, etc. (Yarkoni, 2020). Certainly, no sin-
gle study is expected to manipulate all these variables at once. Instead, in addition
to controlling for as many confounding factors as possible within a single study,
it will be necessary to perform multiple studies to cross-validate the results: a re-
search program that will take years and significant collective effort to complete.
This problem has been noted and acknowledged by the scientific community, and
its impact on the theories is just now starting to be grasped (Yaron et al., 2021). For
instance, there is growing empirical evidence that the P3b, a marker once thought
to reflect the broadcasting of information into the global workspace (Sergent et al.,
2005), might instead reflect post-perceptual processes (Forster et al., 2020). These
significant developments have led to theoretical revisions of the theories—e.g.,
Global Neuronal Workspace theory (Sergent et al., 2021)—while at the same time
driving a slow convergence on the tighter link of other earlier, ERP components,
such as the VAN, with consciousness. Despite that encouraging progress, concrete
actions for addressing the challenges faced by the contrastive methods have lagged
behind, and most studies continue using that methodology as originally defined.
Moreover, to this day, there exists no database accumulating electrophysiological
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 11
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 12
easy. Complicating the matter, most studies do not even thoroughly report how
subjects were instructed and what measures were taken to ensure consistent be-
havior across subjects. Anyone who has tried to reproduce a study in a different
laboratory immediately notices how much the “context” of the research matters,
including how the investigator instructed the subjects. But little attention is paid
to making this information accessible in publications. What other approaches can
then be taken in order to move beyond the contrastive method?
Haynes (2009) has argued for the use of multivariate analysis to decode the
content of consciousness, thus providing a much finer identification of NCC than
the simple study of the dichotomy between presence and absence of critical stimuli.
Recent studies using this approach have shown that decodability of stimulus orien-
tation was highest from occipital sources in early time windows (130–320ms). Fur-
thermore, decoding performances increased with clarity of the percept as reported
on a perceptual awareness scale (Andersen et al., 2016). Salti et al. (2015), on the
other hand, showed decoding from frontal regions at later time points—270ms post
stimulus onset—of the spatial location of perceived targets. While decoding might
be an exciting approach for unravelling the neural correlate of consciousness, the
results are not easily interpretable; for example, they might spuriously suggest
widespread patterns that are contradicted when tested further with causal manip-
ulations (Bouton et al., 2018). As such, multivariate decoding analysis should be
considered with caution.
Other approaches relate to focusing not just on what happens following the
entry of a given stimulus into consciousness, but on their maintenance and, more
generally, on a defining feature of consciousness, i.e., the experience of flow and
temporality. With just a few notable exceptions (Gerber et al., 2017; Golan et al.,
2016), most direct empirical work has aimed at understanding the entry of stimuli
into consciousness, thus obviating the questions of how and why a conscious
percept is maintained in consciousness. In this regard, perceptual continuity is
an intriguing concept: we perceive the world as stable despite constant sensory
disruptions caused by eye movements and blinks (Golan et al., 2016). The latter, for
instance, causes a massive disruption in the sensory flow as the eyelid occludes the
pupil for approximately 100–150 ms, yet we do not perceive the world as blanking
out. Such a natural experiment occurs approximately 1000 times an hour (Cruz et
al., 2011), amounting to roughly 3–4% of our waking life spent with our eyes closed,
but without having noticed that the world has disappeared. A promising and more
naturalistic approach to investigating the mechanisms related to consciousness
is to focus on understanding what maintains a stimulus in awareness, i.e., why
we fail to update our phenomenology in light of massive changes in sensory
stimulation. As we have argued elsewhere (Melloni, 2015), understanding the flow
of consciousness—i.e., moving from episodes (the snapshot view that has domi-
nated studies on consciousness) to events (integrations across moments in time)
central to the experience of such “flow”—is another crucial, but hitherto neglected,
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 13
aspect of conscious perception. This resonates with early attempts by Varela (1999)
to address the experience of temporality, called “specious present” by James (1890,
p. 377), and with the proposition that internal brain dynamics, in particular the
synchronization of widely distributed neural assemblies in the gamma band and
phase transitions across states, lies at the core of time consciousness. Support for
this idea comes from studies investigating binocular rivalry (Cosmelli & Thompson,
2007; Doesburg et al., 2009, among others).
Another promising approach to investigating consciousness in populations
with restricted responsiveness, such as infants and patients with cerebral lesions,
is the use of neural frequency tagging, which we initially developed to evaluate
language capacities and access to meaning in neurotypical individuals (Ding et al.,
2016). Recently, we and others have used the frequency tagging approach for both
retrospective (Gui et al., 2020) and prospective (Sokoliuk et al., 2021) classification
on unresponsive patients, and the results have been encouraging.
Despite the clear advantages of the contrastive method, its mostly exclusive use
in the research of consciousness may have constrained the field too much, becom-
ing an obstacle to finding NCCs. It is expected that broadening the experimental
methods will help us to better understand the phenomenon.
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 14
etc. Phenomenal consciousness exists in and of itself, for our own inner spectacle,
while access consciousness is defined by the functions it serves. A shorthand for
the distinction between “being” and “doing.” This fundamental distinction led to
a clear dichotomy in the different theories of consciousness, with some assuming
independence of the two and some assuming them to be one and the same.
For some theories, such as Global Neuronal Workspace, phenomenal qualities
of experience are fully captured by access (see Naccache, 2018). Under this as-
sumption, studying access is equivalent to studying its phenomenology. Other
theories, in contrast, posit that P-consciousness is distinct and independent from
the collection of cognitive processes related to access (Tononi, 2004; Tsuchiya et
al., 2015). The debate on whether phenomenology overflows access is ongoing (Fu
et al., 2021). Notwithstanding the empirical challenge in arbitrating between these
different conceptions, it is important to refocus the debate to the main aim of the
science of consciousness, i.e., what theories of consciousness ultimately aim to ex-
plain is the phenomenological qualities of experiences, the “what it is like to be in
that state” (Revonsuo, 2006).
As a matter of fact, one reason why the debate between access and phenomenal
consciousness will not easily be settled empirically is that we lack clear descrip-
tions of the phenomenological qualities of experience assumed by the different
theories of consciousness. For instance, take the debate on the richness vs. sparse-
ness of consciousness (often discussed in concert with the above-mentioned debate
of A- vs. P-consciousness, see Block, 2011). One side posits that the richness of ex-
perience is an illusion and that what can actually be perceived and remembered is
limited. But what does it mean for something not to be rich? For instance, if a sin-
gle number, say the number 15 in red ink, is foveally presented for enough time to
be perceived, say 100 ms, and at a size that makes it easy to be perceived, what do
the different theories assume is consciously perceived? Just the number, just the
color, just the location, or the font, or the orientation of the letters, or all of those
features? This is not a naïve question, given recent work on attribute amnesia
(Chen & Wyble, 2016; Wang et al., 2021), which demonstrates that subjects fail to
report specific attributes of stimuli, e.g., color, that are otherwise reported as per-
ceived. Can we interpret these results as evidence that phenomenology overflows
access? Not easily, as (some) theories of consciousness have not made explicit
what they assume to be experienced (this is a separate question from whether P-
consciousness is fully subsumed under in A-consciousness). Some could claim that
subjects experience the letter but not its color (Fu et al., 2021). Thus, in the absence
of explicit assumptions from the theories about the phenomenological qualities of
consciousness, the debate between access and phenomenal consciousness will not
easily be settled empirically.
Nevertheless, settling the P- vs. A-consciousness debate, while representing a
significant advance in the field, will not provide understanding of the phenomeno-
logical qualities of experience and their generation by the brain. To that end, clear
and standardized methods for studying phenomenology in cognitive neuroscience
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 15
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 16
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 17
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 18
Studies using no-report paradigms, e.g., indexing perception through eye move-
ments (optokinetic nystagmus) and fMRI in humans, have shown that activity in
PFC may reflect report, whereas other studies in non-human primates—also using
no-report paradigms in a binocular rivalry paradigm, but measuring direct electro-
physiological activity (single unit)—reported decoding of the content of perception
from PFC, which is not explained by report per se. Aggregating data across stud-
ies in a common database would help to make sense of these disparate results.
The best approximation to date is Neurosynth (https://www.neurosynth.org/),
which provides a synthesis of human functional neuroimaging data only (Yarkoni
et al., 2011), built over automated extraction of activation coordinates. While it
addresses a critical need, and as such falls short of being a revolutionary resource,
Neurosynth suffers from a number of shortcomings. First, it currently includes
only neuroimaging data and does not include data from other modalities, such
as M-EEG, ECoG, single units, or lesion/stimulation data. Second, it does not in-
clude unthresholded data, which are critical for reliable meta-analytical results,
especially considering the enormous variability in analytical choices by the inves-
tigators (Botvinik-Nezer et al., 2020). Third, it currently incorporates descriptors
reflecting broad cognitive states, which will need to be refined to incorporate more
nuanced descriptions of the tasks and experimental paradigms.
Distilling the NCC or finding any meaningful correlate of consciousness
presupposes generalization across variables such as a stimulus’s parameters,
tasks, research site, etc. While the scientific aim is clear, i.e., generalization over
non-critical parameters, it is not done in practice, and is also not taken into
account statistically. Yarkoni (2020) has recently provided the clearest discussion
of this problem, calling attention to the need to align verbal descriptions (hypoth-
esis/theories) with statistical expressions in order to avoid current problems in
psychology/neuroscience, such as the replication crisis. As the number of vari-
ables to include in a statistical model is daunting, the most reasonable strategy is
to aggregate across multiple studies. In principle, the prescriptive strategy seems
rather simple: researchers openly share data, run a complex statistical model over
the data, and voilà—the NCC are discovered. However, it is not that simple, even
when leaving aside the conceptual disputes as to how to define consciousness.
Meaningful data aggregation requires far richer and more detailed descriptions of
the experiment and experimental setting than are commonly provided in publica-
tions (or even shared datasets). Recognizing such limitations, some researchers in
the community have made efforts to provide more comprehensive descriptions
of the study materials, e.g., through platforms such as protocols.io and/or lab
protocols, study protocols recently launched at PloS One, as well as through the
development of community standards, such as Neuroimaging Data Model (NIDM)
experiment. The major limitation for data aggregation is the insufficient metadata
descriptor of the study materials, without which no meaningful statistical data
aggregation enabling generalization is possible. Hence, sharing data, while useful,
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 19
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 20
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 21
alternative”) for the reasons previously outlined, or the second criterion of the
unfolding argument (e.g., criterium#2, “the unfolding argument”). In the view of
Doerig et al. (2021), because any input-output function of a recurrent network can
be approximated by an equivalent feedforward network, any theory of conscious-
ness that assumes the necessity of a specific causal structure for consciousness to
emerge is either false or not within the reach of science. This purely functionalist
perspective, which equates consciousness with its input-output function, leaves
little room for rich, phenomenological states, such as dreams. Others have ar-
gued that the treatment of the causal structure as a black box is largely unjustified
(Tsuchiya et al., 2019). Overall, the reductionist strictness of the hard criteria devel-
oped by Doerig et al. (2021) runs the risk of locking down the field to a similar state
as what it was in in its early stages and at a time when it could benefit the most
from a broadening of experimental methodologies (see Tsuchiya et al., 2019, for a
more detailed argumentation against Doerig’s hard criteria for consciousness).
Until agreed-upon criteria emerge, we believe that mechanisms such as
“adversarial collaboration” might offer a viable alternative for arbitrating among
competing theories, as proven by the current existence of several such projects
in the field (such as Melloni et al., 2021). This practice consists in bringing
advocates of two or more opposing theories together to work on a common
experiment or set of experiments (Cowan et al., 2020). By doing so, the different
sides agree beforehand on rules that cannot be broken without direct implications
for their theories. In the framework of consciousness research, for instance,
higher-order and first-order theories could agree on detection rules for a given
experiment (or set of experiments), such that the condition in which a stimulus
is consciously perceived is agreed upon by both sides, side-stepping the problem
of under-determination (Michel, 2019). As each theory has a specific set of
predictions about which patterns of neural activity will lead to consciousness, the
experiment(s) should be designed in such a way that direct comparison of oppos-
ing predictions between the theories is possible. Findings will thus result in the
confirmation or disproof of specific aspects of a theory. While a winner-takes-all
situation, in which one of the theories is fully discredited, is unlikely to occur, such
projects lead to efficient identifications of core vs. auxiliary predictions (Lakatos,
1973). But perhaps more importantly, by explicitly stating these core and auxiliary
predictions and pre-registering them prior to data collection (as recommended
by Cowan et al., 2020), the need to patch-up theories by transforming core into
auxiliary predictions of the data is made evident and is therefore tractable. Such
an effort could not only aid in settling standing quarrels in the field (Michel,
2019), it could also identify the most promising theories, while sidestepping
some of the challenges of the contrastive method and its indeterminacy. This is
without a doubt a challenging process, yet it is a fruitful one and is already imple-
mentable. Currently, there are two consortia, one focused on testing contradictory
predictions of the Global Neuronal Workspace Theory and the Integrated Infor-
mation Theory, and the other pitting first-order, recurrent processing theory (RPT),
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 22
3 Conclusion
We have come a long way in the research of consciousness over the past thirty
years. The initial enthusiasm and the abundance of data obtained through the
contrastive method were followed by the development of a number of theories at-
tempting to explain how consciousness fits into the physical world. As the field
advanced, that initial enthusiasm faded and methodological as well as theoretical
and philosophical disputes clouded the horizon. At the same time, more and more
innovative approaches have emerged, expanding the range of possibilities beyond
the traditional use of the contrastive method. We would like to advocate for these
innovative methods, since the best way through what appears to be an impasse
in the field will be via methodological and theoretical shifts in current practices.
We believe it will be key for future discovery to transcend the basic dichotomy of
seen vs. unseen by bringing phenomenology into the center of the empirical effort.
This will be accomplished, first, by expanding efforts to describe the structure of ex-
perience and using those descriptions to guide empirical research, and second, by
inviting theories to make explicit their assumptions about phenomenological prop-
erties of experience so that they are then accessible to the front-loaded approach.
Furthermore, we believe great advances will be facilitated by the community’s ac-
tive effort to gather empirical data in common databases, to enable cross-studies
analyses, and to increase the spatio-temporal grain. Beyond that, the existence of
common databases will help narrow the search for the NCC by disentangling the
NCC-pr and NCC-co from the NCC proper. While no agreed-upon theory has so
far emerged, adversarial collaboration could offer a powerful tool for testing the
explanatory power of the theories, while also leveraging the theories’ inferential
power to fuel novel discoveries about what the function of consciousness might
be and how experience arises in the soggy matter of the brain.
Acknowledgments
We would like to thank Caspar M. Schwiedrzik and the Cogitate Consortium for discus-
sions, to Diana Koch for the figure and proofreading of earlier versions and to William
Martin for the final proofreading. We would also like to thank the Max Planck Society and
the Templeton World Charity Foundation, Inc. (TWCF0389) for their generous support.
The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the authors and do not necessarily
reflect the views of the Templeton World Charity Foundation, Inc.
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 23
References
Andersen, L. M., Pedersen, M. N., Sandberg, K., & Overgaard, M. (2016). Occipital MEG activity in the early time range
(<300 ms) predicts graded changes in perceptual consciousness. Cereb Cortex, 26(6), 2677–2688. https://doi.org/10.109
3/cercor/bhv108
Aru, J., Axmacher, N., Do Lam, A. T., Fell, J., Elger, C. E., Singer, W., & Melloni, L. (2012). Local category-specific gamma
band responses in the visual cortex do not reflect conscious perception. J Neurosci, 32(43), 14909–14914. https:
//doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.2051-12.2012
Aru, J., Bachmann, T., Singer, W., & Melloni, L. (2012). Distilling the neural correlates of consciousness. Neurosci Biobehav
Rev, 36(2), 737–746. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2011.12.003
Axelrod, V., Bar, M., & Rees, G. (2015). Exploring the unconscious using faces. Trends Cogn Sci, 19(1), 35–45. https:
//doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2014.11.003
Baars, B. J. (1997). In the theatre of consciousness: Global workspace theory, a rigorous scientific theory of consciousness.
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4, 292–309. https://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/imp/jcs/1997/00000004/00000
004/776
Baars, B. J. (2005). Global workspace theory of consciousness: Toward a cognitive neuroscience of human experience. Prog
Brain Res, 150, 45–53. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0079-6123(05)50004-9
Bayne, T. (2004). Closing the gap? Some questions for neurophenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences,
3(4), 349–364. https://doi.org/10.1023/B:PHEN.0000048934.34397.ca
Bjerke, I. E., Ovsthus, M., Papp, E. A., Yates, S. C., Silvestri, L., Fiorilli, J., Pennartz, C. M. A., Pavone, F. S., Puchades, M.
A., Leergaard, T. B., & Bjaalie, J. G. (2018). Data integration through brain atlasing: Human brain project tools and
strategies. Eur Psychiatry, 50, 70–76. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.eurpsy.2018.02.004
Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18, 272. https://doi.org/
10.1017/S0140525X00038474
Block, N. (2005). Two neural correlates of consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci, 9(2), 46–52. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2004.12
.006
Block, N. (2011). Perceptual consciousness overflows cognitive access. Trends Cogn Sci, 15(12), 567–575. https://doi.org/10
.1016/j.tics.2011.11.001
Bockelman, P., Reinerman-Jones, L., & Gallagher, S. (2013). Methodological lessons in neurophenomenology: Review of a
baseline study and recommendations for research approaches. Front Hum Neurosci, 7, 608. https://doi.org/10.3389/fn
hum.2013.00608
Boly, M., Massimini, M., Tsuchiya, N., Postle, B. R., Koch, C., & Tononi, G. (2017). Are the neural correlates of consciousness
in the front or in the back of the cerebral cortex? Clinical and neuroimaging evidence. J Neurosci, 37(40), 9603–9613.
https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3218-16.2017
Botvinik-Nezer, R., Holzmeister, F., Camerer, C. F., Dreber, A., Huber, J., Johannesson, M., Kirchler, M., Iwanir, R., Mumford,
J. A., Adcock, R. A., Avesani, P., Baczkowski, B. M., Bajracharya, A., Bakst, L., Ball, S., Barilari, M., Bault, N., Beaton,
D., Beitner, J., … others. (2020). Variability in the analysis of a single neuroimaging dataset by many teams. Nature,
582(7810), 84–88. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41586-020-2314-9
Bouton, S., Chambon, V., Tyrand, R., Guggisberg, A. G., Seeck, M., Karkar, S., Ville, D. van de, & Giraud, A. L. (2018). Focal
versus distributed temporal cortex activity for speech sound category assignment. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A, 115(6),
E1299–E1308. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1714279115
Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing up to the hard problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200–219.
https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195311105.003.0001
Chalmers, D. J. (2000). What is a neural correlate of consciousness? In T. Metzinger (Ed.), Neural correlates of consciousness:
Empirical and conceptual questions (pp. 17–39). MIT Press.
Chen, H., & Wyble, B. (2016). Attribute amnesia reflects a lack of memory consolidation for attended information. J Exp
Psychol Hum Percept Perform, 42(2), 225–234. https://doi.org/10.1037/xhp0000133
Cohen, M. A., Ortego, K., Kyroudis, A., & Pitts, M. (2020). Distinguishing the neural correlates of perceptual awareness and
postperceptual processing. J Neurosci, 40(25), 4925–4935. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0120-20.2020
Cosmelli, D., & Thompson, E. (2007). Mountains and valleys: Binocular rivalry and the flow of experience. Conscious Cogn,
16(3), 623-41; discussion 642-4. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2007.06.013
Cowan, N., Belletier, C., Doherty, J. M., Jaroslawska, A. J., Rhodes, S., Forsberg, A., Naveh-Benjamin, M., Barrouillet, P.,
Camos, V., & Logie, R. H. (2020). How do scientific views change? Notes from an extended adversarial collaboration.
Perspect Psychol Sci, 15(4), 1011–1025. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691620906415
Crick, F., & Koch, C. (1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of consciousness. Seminars in the Neurosciences, 2, 203.
https://authors.library.caltech.edu/40352/
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 24
Crick, F., & Koch, C. (1998). Consciousness and neuroscience. Cerebral Cortex, 8(2), 97–107. https://doi.org/10.1093/cercor
/8.2.97
Cruz, A. A., Garcia, D. M., Pinto, C. T., & Cechetti, S. P. (2011). Spontaneous eyeblink activity. Ocul Surf, 9(1), 29–41.
https://doi.org/10.1016/s1542-0124(11)70007-6
Dehaene, S. (2014). Consciousness and the brain: Deciphering how the brain codes our thoughts. Penguin.
Dehaene, S., & Changeux, J. P. (2011). Experimental and theoretical approaches to conscious processing. Neuron, 70(2),
200–227. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2011.03.018
Dehaene, S., & Naccache, L. (2001). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and a workspace
framework. Cognition, 79(1-2), 1–37. https://doi.org/10.1016/s0010-0277(00)00123-2
Dehaene, S., Naccache, L., Cohen, L., Bihan, D. L., Mangin, J. F., Poline, J. B., & Riviere, D. (2001). Cerebral mechanisms of
word masking and unconscious repetition priming. Nat Neurosci, 4(7), 752–758. https://doi.org/10.1038/89551
Del Cul, A., Baillet, S., & Dehaene, S. (2007). Brain dynamics underlying the nonlinear threshold for access to consciousness.
PLoS Biol, 5(10), e260. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.0050260
Dennett, D. C., & Kinsbourne, M. (2011). Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15(2), 183–201. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x00068229
Ding, N., Melloni, L., Zhang, H., Tian, X., & Poeppel, D. (2016). Cortical tracking of hierarchical linguistic structures in
connected speech. Nat Neurosci, 19(1), 158–164. https://doi.org/10.1038/nn.4186
Doerig, A., Schurger, A., & Herzog, M. H. (2021). Hard criteria for empirical theories of consciousness. Cogn Neurosci, 12(2),
41–62. https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1772214
Doesburg, S. M., Green, J. J., McDonald, J. J., & Ward, L. M. (2009). Rhythms of consciousness: Binocular rivalry reveals
large-scale oscillatory network dynamics mediating visual perception. PLoS One, 4(7), e6142. https://doi.org/10.1371/
journal.pone.0006142
Eccles, J. C. (1974). Cerebral activity and consciousness. In Studies in the philosophy of biology (pp. 87–107). Springer.
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-01892-5_7
Edelman, G. M., & Tononi, G. (2000). Reentry and the dynamic core: Neural correlates of conscious experience. In Neural
correlates of consciousness - empirical and conceptual questions (pp. 139–151). MIT Press.
Farooqui, A. A., & Manly, T. (2018). When attended and conscious perception deactivates fronto-parietal regions. Cortex,
107, 166–179. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cortex.2017.09.004
ffytche, D. H., Howard, R. J., Brammer, M. J., David, A., Woodruff, P., & Williams, S. (1998). The anatomy of conscious vision:
An fMRI study of visual hallucinations. Nat Neurosci, 1(8), 738–742. https://doi.org/10.1038/3738
Fink, S. B. (2016). A deeper look at the “neural correlate of consciousness.” Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 1044. https://doi.org/
10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01044
Fink, S. B., Kob, L., & Lyre, H. (2021). A structural constraint on the neural correlates of consciousness. Philoshopy and the
Mind Sciences.
Forster, J., Koivisto, M., & Revonsuo, A. (2020). ERP and MEG correlates of visual consciousness: The second decade.
Conscious Cogn, 80, 102917. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2020.102917
Frässle, S., Sommer, J., Jansen, A., Naber, M., & Einhauser, W. (2014). Binocular rivalry: Frontal activity relates to introspec-
tion and action but not to perception. J Neurosci, 34(5), 1738–1747. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.4403-13.2014
Fries, P., Roelfsema, P. R., Engel, A. K., Konig, P., & Singer, W. (1997). Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual
cortex correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A, 94(23), 12699–12704. https://doi.or
g/10.1073/pnas.94.23.12699
Fu, Y., Yan, W., Shen, M., & Chen, H. (2021). Does consciousness overflow cognitive access? Novel insights from the new
phenomenon of attribute amnesia. Sci China Life Sci, 64(6), 847–860. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11427-020-1831-8
Gaillard, R., Dehaene, S., Adam, C., Clemenceau, S., Hasboun, D., Baulac, M., Cohen, L., & Naccache, L. (2009). Converging
intracranial markers of conscious access. PLoS Biol, 7(3), e61. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1000061
Gallagher, S. (2003). Phenomenology and experimental design: Toward a phenomenologically enlightened experimental
science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9-10), 85–99. https://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/imp/jcs/2003/00
000010/f0020009/art00007
Gallagher, S. (2012). What is phenomenology? (pp. 7–18). Palgrave Macmillan UK. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137283801_2
Gerber, E. M., Golan, T., Knight, R. T., & Deouell, L. Y. (2017). Cortical representation of persistent visual stimuli. Neuroim-
age, 161, 67–79. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2017.08.028
Golan, T., Davidesco, I., Meshulam, M., Groppe, D. M., Megevand, P., Yeagle, E. M., Goldfinger, M. S., Harel, M., Melloni,
L., Schroeder, C. E., Deouell, L. Y., Mehta, A. D., & Malach, R. (2016). Human intracranial recordings link suppressed
transients rather than ’filling-in’ to perceptual continuity across blinks. Elife, 5. https://doi.org/10.7554/eLife.17243
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 25
Gosselin, F., & Schyns, P. G. (2003). Superstitious perceptions reveal properties of internal representations. Psychol Sci,
14(5), 505–509. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9280.03452
Graaf, T. A. de, Hsieh, P. J., & Sack, A. T. (2012). The ’correlates’ in neural correlates of consciousness. Neurosci Biobehav
Rev, 36(1), 191–197. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2011.05.012
Gui, P., Jiang, Y., Zang, D., Qi, Z., Tan, J., Tanigawa, H., Jiang, J., Wen, Y., Xu, L., Zhao, J., Mao, Y., Poo, M. M., Ding, N.,
Dehaene, S., Wu, X., & Wang, L. (2020). Assessing the depth of language processing in patients with disorders of
consciousness. Nat Neurosci, 23(6), 761–770. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41593-020-0639-1
Haun, A., & Tononi, G. (2019). Why does space feel the way it does? Towards a principled account of spatial experience.
Entropy, 21(12), 1160. https://doi.org/10.3390/e21121160
Haynes, J. D. (2009). Decoding visual consciousness from human brain signals. Trends Cogn Sci, 13(5), 194–202. https:
//doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2009.02.004
Henson, R. N., Mouchlianitis, E., Matthews, W. J., & Kouider, S. (2008). Electrophysiological correlates of masked face
priming. Neuroimage, 40(2), 884–895. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2007.12.003
Hippocrates. (1959). Hippocrates (W. H. S. Jones, Trans.). Harvard Univ. Press, 1923.
James, W., Burkhardt, F., Bowers, F., & Skrupskelis, I. K. (1890). The principles of psychology (Vol. 1). Macmillan London.
Kapoor, V., Dwarakanath, A., Safavi, S., Werner, J., Besserve, M., Panagiotaropoulos, T. I., & Logothetis, N. K. (2020). De-
coding the contents of consciousness from prefrontal ensembles. bioRxiv. https://doi.org/10.1101/2020.01.28.921841
Kim, C. Y., & Blake, R. (2005). Psychophysical magic: Rendering the visible ’invisible’. Trends Cogn Sci, 9(8), 381–388.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2005.06.012
Kleinschmidt, A., Buchel, C., Zeki, S., & Frackowiak, R. (2002). Human brain activity during spontaneously reversing
perception of ambiguous figures. 5th IEEE EMBS International Summer School on Biomedical Imaging, 2002., 7–pp.
https://doi.org/10.1109/SSBI.2002.1233971
Koch, C., Massimini, M., Boly, M., & Tononi, G. (2016). Neural correlates of consciousness: Progress and problems. Nat Rev
Neurosci, 17(5), 307–321. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn.2016.22
Koch, C., & Tsuchiya, N. (2007). Attention and consciousness: Two distinct brain processes. Trends Cogn Sci, 11(1), 16–22.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2006.10.012
Koivisto, M., & Revonsuo, A. (2007). Electrophysiological correlates of visual consciousness and selective attention. Neu-
roreport, 18(8), 753–756. https://doi.org/10.1097/WNR.0b013e3280c143c8
Koivisto, M., & Revonsuo, A. (2010). Event-related brain potential correlates of visual awareness. Neurosci Biobehav Rev,
34(6), 922–934. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2009.12.002
Lakatos, I. (1973). Science and pseudoscience. Philosophical Papers, 1, 1–7. http://www.podstawyekonomii.pl/metodologia/
files/lakatos1977.pdf
Lamme, V. A. (2006). Towards a true neural stance on consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci, 10(11), 494–501. https://doi.org/10.1
016/j.tics.2006.09.001
Lamme, V. A., & Roelfsema, P. R. (2000). The distinct modes of vision offered by feedforward and recurrent processing.
Trends Neurosci, 23(11), 571–579. https://doi.org/10.1016/s0166-2236(00)01657-x
Lau, H., & Rosenthal, D. (2011). Empirical support for higher-order theories of conscious awareness. Trends Cogn Sci, 15(8),
365–373. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2011.05.009
LeVasseur, J. J. (2003). The problem of bracketing in phenomenology. Qual Health Res, 13(3), 408–420. https://doi.org/10.1
177/1049732302250337
Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64(4), 354–361. https:
//doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0114.1983.tb00207.x
Libet, B., Alberts, W. W., Wright, Jr., E. W., & Feinstein, B. (1967). Responses of human somatosensory cortex to stimuli
below threshold for conscious sensation. Science, 158(3808), 1597–1600. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.158.3808.1597
Logothetis, N. K. (1998). Single units and conscious vision. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci, 353(1377), 1801–1818. https:
//doi.org/10.1098/rstb.1998.0333
Lutz, A. (2002). Toward a neurophenomenology as an account of generative passages: A first empirical case study. Phe-
nomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(2), 133–167. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1020320221083
Lutz, A., Lachaux, J.-P., Martinerie, J., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Guiding the study of brain dynamics by using first-person data:
Synchrony patterns correlate with ongoing conscious states during a simple visual task. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, 99(3), 1586–1591. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.032658199
Mashour, G. A., Roelfsema, P., Changeux, J. P., & Dehaene, S. (2020). Conscious processing and the global neuronal
workspace hypothesis. Neuron, 105(5), 776–798. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2020.01.026
Mayer, A., Schwiedrzik, C. M., Wibral, M., Singer, W., & Melloni, L. (2016). Expecting to see a letter: Alpha oscillations as
carriers of top-down sensory predictions. Cereb Cortex, 26(7), 3146–3160. https://doi.org/10.1093/cercor/bhv146
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 26
Mazzi, C., Mazzeo, G., & Savazzi, S. (2020). Late positivity does not meet the criteria to be considered a proper neural
correlate of perceptual awareness. Front Syst Neurosci, 14, 36. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnsys.2020.00036
Melloni, L. (2015). Consciousness as inference in time. Open MIND, 22, 1–13. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958570566
Melloni, L., Mudrik, L., Pitts, M., & Koch, C. (2021). Making the hard problem of consciousness easier. Science, 372(6545),
911–912. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.abj3259
Melloni, L., Schwiedrzik, C. M., Muller, N., Rodriguez, E., & Singer, W. (2011). Expectations change the signatures and
timing of electrophysiological correlates of perceptual awareness. J Neurosci, 31(4), 1386–1396. https://doi.org/10.152
3/JNEUROSCI.4570-10.2011
Melloni, L., Schwiedrzik, C. M., Müller, N., Rodriguez, E., & Singer, W. (2011). Expectations change the signatures and
timing of electrophysiological correlates of perceptual awareness. Journal of Neuroscience, 31(4), 1386–1396. https:
//doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.4570-10.2011
Metzinger, T. (2000). Neural correlates of consciousness: Empirical and conceptual questions. MIT press.
Michel, M. (2019). Consciousness science underdetermined: A short history of endless debates. Ergo, an Open Access Journal
of Philosophy, 6(20201214). https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.12405314.0006.028
Miller, S. M. (2015). The constitution of phenomenal consciousness: Toward a science and theory (Vol. 92). John Benjamins
Publishing Company.
Naccache, L. (2018). Why and how access consciousness can account for phenomenal consciousness. Philos Trans R Soc
Lond B Biol Sci, 373(1755), 20170357. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2017.0357
Nieder, A., Wagener, L., & Rinnert, P. (2020). A neural correlate of sensory consciousness in a corvid bird. Science, 369(6511),
1626–1629. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.abb1447
Noy, N., Bickel, S., Zion-Golumbic, E., Harel, M., Golan, T., Davidesco, I., Schevon, C. A., McKhann, G. M., Goodman, R.
R., Schroeder, C. E., Mehta, A. D., & Malach, R. (2015). Ignition’s glow: Ultra-fast spread of global cortical activity
accompanying local ”ignitions” in visual cortex during conscious visual perception. Conscious Cogn, 35, 206–224.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2015.03.006
Overgaard, M., Rote, J., Mouridsen, K., & Ramsoy, T. Z. (2006). Is conscious perception gradual or dichotomous? A com-
parison of report methodologies during a visual task. Conscious Cogn, 15(4), 700–708. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.conc
og.2006.04.002
Palmiter, R. D. (2011). Dopamine signaling as a neural correlate of consciousness. Neuroscience, 198, 213–220. https:
//doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroscience.2011.06.089
Penfield, W. (1958). Some mechanisms of consciousness discovered during electrical stimulation of the brain. Proc Natl
Acad Sci U S A, 44(2), 51–66. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.44.2.51
Pins, D., & ffytche, D. (2003). The neural correlates of conscious vision. Cereb Cortex, 13(5), 461–474. https://doi.org/10.109
3/cercor/13.5.461
Pitts, M. A., & Britz, J. (2011). Insights from intermittent binocular rivalry and EEG. Front Hum Neurosci, 5, 107. https:
//doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2011.00107
Pitts, M. A., Lutsyshyna, L. A., & Hillyard, S. A. (2018). The relationship between attention and consciousness: An expanded
taxonomy and implications for ’no-report’ paradigms. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci, 373(1755). https://doi.org/10
.1098/rstb.2017.0348
Pitts, M. A., Martinez, A., & Hillyard, S. A. (2012). Visual processing of contour patterns under conditions of inattentional
blindness. J Cogn Neurosci, 24(2), 287–303. https://doi.org/10.1162/jocn_a_00111
Pitts, M. A., Padwal, J., Fennelly, D., Martinez, A., & Hillyard, S. A. (2014). Gamma band activity and the P3 reflect post-
perceptual processes, not visual awareness. Neuroimage, 101, 337–350. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2014.07
.024
Poldrack, R. A., Kittur, A., Kalar, D., Miller, E., Seppa, C., Gil, Y., Parker, D. S., Sabb, F. W., & Bilder, R. M. (2011). The cognitive
atlas: Toward a knowledge foundation for cognitive neuroscience. Front Neuroinform, 5, 17. https://doi.org/10.3389/
fninf.2011.00017
Poldrack, R. A., & Yarkoni, T. (2016). From brain maps to cognitive ontologies: Informatics and the search for mental
structure. Annu Rev Psychol, 67, 587–612. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-122414-033729
Posner, M. I. (1994). Attention: The mechanisms of consciousness. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A, 91(16), 7398–7403. https:
//doi.org/10.1073/pnas.91.16.7398
Rahnev, D., Desender, K., Lee, A. L. F., Adler, W. T., Aguilar-Lleyda, D., Akdogan, B., Arbuzova, P., Atlas, L. Y., Balci,
F., Bang, J. W., Begue, I., Birney, D. P., Brady, T. F., Calder-Travis, J., Chetverikov, A., Clark, T. K., Davranche, K.,
Denison, R. N., Dildine, T. C., … Zylberberg, A. (2020). The confidence database. Nat Hum Behav, 4(3), 317–325.
https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-019-0813-1
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress and challenges 27
Ramstead, M. J. D., Hesp, C., Sandved-smith, L., Mago, J., Lifshitz, M., Pagnoni, G., Lutz, A., & Friston, K. (2021). From
generative models to generative passages: A computational approach to (neuro)phenomenology. Preprint, 1–29.
https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/k9pbn
Redinbaugh, M. J., Phillips, J. M., Kambi, N. A., Mohanta, S., Andryk, S., Dooley, G. L., Afrasiabi, M., Raz, A., & Saalmann,
Y. B. (2020). Thalamus modulates consciousness via layer-specific control of cortex. Neuron, 106(1), 66–75 e12. https:
//doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2020.01.005
Revonsuo, A. (2000). Prospects for a scientific research program on consciousness. In T. Metzinger (Ed.), Neural correlates
of consciousness (pp. 57–75). The MIT press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/4928.003.0006
Revonsuo, A. (2006). Inner presence: Consciousness as a biological phenomenon. MIT Press.
Salti, M., Monto, S., Charles, L., King, J. R., Parkkonen, L., & Dehaene, S. (2015). Distinct cortical codes and temporal
dynamics for conscious and unconscious percepts. Elife, 4, 1–52. https://doi.org/10.7554/eLife.05652
Schelonka, K., Graulty, C., Canseco-Gonzalez, E., & Pitts, M. A. (2017). ERP signatures of conscious and unconscious word
and letter perception in an inattentional blindness paradigm. Conscious Cogn, 54, 56–71. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.co
ncog.2017.04.009
Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naive introspection. Philosophical Review, 117(2), 245–273. https://doi.org/10.1
215/00318108-2007-037
Sergent, C., Baillet, S., & Dehaene, S. (2005). Timing of the brain events underlying access to consciousness during the
attentional blink. Nat Neurosci, 8(10), 1391–1400. https://doi.org/10.1038/nn1549
Sergent, C., Corazzol, M., Labouret, G., Stockart, F., Wexler, M., King, J. R., Meyniel, F., & Pressnitzer, D. (2021). Bifurcation
in brain dynamics reveals a signature of conscious processing independent of report. Nat Commun, 12(1), 1149. https:
//doi.org/10.1038/s41467-021-21393-z
Shafto, J. P., & Pitts, M. A. (2015). Neural signatures of conscious face perception in an inattentional blindness paradigm. J
Neurosci, 35(31), 10940–10948. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0145-15.2015
Siclari, F., Baird, B., Perogamvros, L., Bernardi, G., LaRocque, J. J., Riedner, B., Boly, M., Postle, B. R., & Tononi, G. (2017).
The neural correlates of dreaming. Nat Neurosci, 20(6), 872–878. https://doi.org/10.1038/nn.4545
Signorelli, C. M., Szczotka, J., & Prentner, R. (2021). Explanatory profiles of models of consciousness-towards a systematic
classification. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/f5vdu
Silverstein, B. H., Snodgrass, M., Shevrin, H., & Kushwaha, R. (2015). P3b, consciousness, and complex unconscious pro-
cessing. Cortex, 73, 216–227. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cortex.2015.09.004
Sokoliuk, R., Degano, G., Banellis, L., Melloni, L., Hayton, T., Sturman, S., Veenith, T., Yakoub, K. M., Belli, A., Noppeney,
U., & Cruse, D. (2021). Covert speech comprehension predicts recovery from acute unresponsive states. Ann Neurol,
89(4), 646–656. https://doi.org/10.1002/ana.25995
Soto, D., & Silvanto, J. (2014). Reappraising the relationship between working memory and conscious awareness. Trends
Cogn Sci, 18(10), 520–525. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2014.06.005
Tononi, G. (2004). An information integration theory of consciousness. BMC Neurosci, 5, 42. https://doi.org/10.1186/1471-
2202-5-42
Tononi, G., Boly, M., Massimini, M., & Koch, C. (2016). Integrated information theory: From consciousness to its physical
substrate. Nat Rev Neurosci, 17(7), 450–461. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn.2016.44
Tsuchiya, N., Andrillon, T., & Haun, A. (2019). A reply to “the unfolding argument”: Beyond functionalism/behaviorism and
towards a truer science of causal structural theories of consciousness. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/a2ms9
Tsuchiya, N., Wilke, M., Frassle, S., & Lamme, V. A. F. (2015). No-report paradigms: Extracting the true neural correlates of
consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci, 19(12), 757–770. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2015.10.002
Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies,
3(4), 330–349. https://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/imp/jcs/1996/00000003/00000004/718
Varela, F. J. (1999). The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, J.
Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.), Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science
(pp. 266–314). Stanford University Press.
Varela, F., Lachaux, J. P., Rodriguez, E., & Martinerie, J. (2001). The brainweb: Phase synchronization and large-scale
integration. Nat Rev Neurosci, 2(4), 229–239. https://doi.org/10.1038/35067550
Wang, R., Fu, Y., Chen, L., Chen, Y., Zhou, J., & Chen, H. (2021). Consciousness can overflow report: Novel evidence from
attribute amnesia of a single stimulus. Conscious Cogn, 87, 103052. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2020.103052
Weiskrantz, L. (1980). Varieties of residual experience. Q J Exp Psychol, 32(3), 365–386. https://doi.org/10.1080/1464074800
8401832
Yarkoni, T. (2020). The generalizability crisis. Behav Brain Sci, 1–37. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X20001685
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369
Alex Lepauvre and Lucia Melloni 28
Yarkoni, T., Poldrack, R. A., Nichols, T. E., Van Essen, D. C., & Wager, T. D. (2011). NeuroSynth: A new platform for
large-scale automated synthesis of human functional neuroimaging data. Frontiers in Neuroinformatics, 5. https:
//doi.org/10.3389/conf.fninf.2011.08.00058
Yaron, I., Melloni, L., Pitts, M., & Mudrik, L. (2021). The consciousness theories studies (ConTraSt) database: Analyzing and
comparing empirical studies of consciousness theories. bioRxiv. https://doi.org/10.1101/2021.06.10.447863
Open Access
This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Interna-
tional License (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted
use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, as long as you give appropriate credit
to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license,
and indicate if changes were made.
Lepauvre A., & Melloni L. (2021). The search for the neural correlate of consciousness: Progress
and challenges. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 2, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2021.87
©The author(s). https://philosophymindscience.org ISSN: 2699-0369