100% found this document useful (1 vote)
221 views34 pages

Tastes and Indifference Curves: Chapter Highlights

This chapter introduces the concepts of tastes and indifference curves. It makes the following key points: 1) Tastes are conceptually distinct from budgets and reflect preferences rather than constraints. 2) Models of tastes assume some consistency across individuals, such as completeness and transitivity of preferences. 3) Indifference curves can map tastes by showing bundles that provide equal utility or satisfaction. 4) The slope of an indifference curve indicates how much of one good someone is willing to trade for another.

Uploaded by

rubiska
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
100% found this document useful (1 vote)
221 views34 pages

Tastes and Indifference Curves: Chapter Highlights

This chapter introduces the concepts of tastes and indifference curves. It makes the following key points: 1) Tastes are conceptually distinct from budgets and reflect preferences rather than constraints. 2) Models of tastes assume some consistency across individuals, such as completeness and transitivity of preferences. 3) Indifference curves can map tastes by showing bundles that provide equal utility or satisfaction. 4) The slope of an indifference curve indicates how much of one good someone is willing to trade for another.

Uploaded by

rubiska
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 34

C H A P T E R

4
Tastes and Indifference Curves

This chapter begins a 2-chapter treatment of tastes — or what we also call “pref-
erences”. In the first of these chapters, we simply investigate the basic logic be-
hind modeling tastes and the most fundamental assumptions we make. In the next
chapter, we then turn to what specific types of tastes look like. Call me a geek — but
I think it’s pretty cool that we have found ways of systematically modeling some-
thing as abstract as people’s tastes!

Chapter Highlights
The main points of the chapter are:

1. Tastes have nothing to do with budgets — they are conceptually distinct.


Budgets are all about what is feasible — and they arise objectively from “what
we bring to the table” and the prices we face. Tastes are all about what we
desire and have nothing to do with incomes, endowments or prices.

2. While our model of tastes respects the fact that there is a great diversity of
tastes across people, we assume that some aspects of tastes are constant
across individuals. The most basic of these are completeness and transitiv-
ity, but the assumptions of monotonicity, convexity and continuity are also
intuitively appealing in most circumstances. When we say tastes are “ratio-
nal” we only mean that individuals with those tastes are capable of making
decisions.

3. Maps of indifference curves are a way of describing tastes, with the usual
shapes and orderings arising from our assumptions of monotonicity and con-
vexity. For those covering part B, indifference curves are simply levels of util-
ity functions — and these levels can no more cross than the elevations of
mountains on geography maps can cross.

4. We typically assume that utility cannot be measured objectively — which is


why the labels on indifference curves do not matter beyond indicating the
ordering of what is better and what is worse.
Tastes and Indifference Curves 2

5. The slope of an indifference curve — or the marginal rate of substitution —


at a particular bundle tells us how an individual feels about different goods
at the margin — i.e. how much the individual is willing to trade one good for
another given that she currently has this particular bundle.

4A Solutions to Within-Chapter-Exercises for


Part A

Exercise 4A.1

Do we know from the monotonicity assumption how E relates to D, A and B?


Do we know how A relates to D?
Answer: E must be preferred to D because it contains more of everything (i.e.
more pants and more shirts). Monotonicity does not tell us anything about the re-
lationship between A and E — A has more shirts but fewer pants and E has more
pants but fewer shirts. For analogous reasons, monotonicity does not tell us any-
thing about how E and B are ranked. A has more shirts and the same number of
pants as D — so we know that A is at least as good as D (and probably better).

Exercise 4A.2

What other goods are such that we would prefer to have fewer of them rather
than many? How can we re-conceptualize choices over such goods so that it be-
comes reasonable to assume “more is better”?
Answer: Examples might include pollution, bugs in our houses, weeds in our
yard and disease in our bodies. In each case, however, we can re-conceptualize the
“bad” by redefining it into a “good” that we want more of. We want less pollution
but more clean air and water; fewer bugs in our houses or more “bug-free” square
feet of housing; fewer weeds in our yard but more square feet of weed-less grass;
less disease and more health.

Exercise 4A.3

Combining the convexity and monotonicity assumptions, can you now con-
clude something about the relationship between the pairs E and A and E and B if
you do not know how A and B are related? What if you know that I am indifferent
between A and B?
Answer: We can only apply the convexity assumption if we know some pair of
bundles we are indifferent between — because convexity says that, when faced with
bundles we are indifferent between, we prefer averages of such bundles (or at the
very least like averages just as much). So, without knowing more, I can’t use mono-
tonicity and convexity to say anything about how A and E (or B and E ) are related to
3 4A. Solutions to Within-Chapter-Exercises for Part A

one another. If we know that I am indifferent between A and B, on the other hand,
then I know that C is at least as good as A and B because C is the average between
A and B. Since E has more of everything than C , we also know from monotonicity
that E is better than C . So E is better than C which is at least as good as A and B. By
transitivity, that implies that E is better than A and B.

Exercise 4A.4

Knowing that I am indifferent between A and B, can you now conclude some-
thing about how B and D are ranked by me? In order to reach this conclusion, do
you have to invoke the convexity assumption?
Answer: By just invoking the monotonicity assumption, I know that A is at least
as good as D since it has more of one good and the same of the other. If A is indiffer-
ent to B, I then also know (by transitivity) that B is at least as good as D. Invoking
convexity won’t actually allow me to say anything beyond that since indifference
between A, B and D is consistent with convexity. (It is not consistent with a strict
notion of convexity — where by “strict” we mean that averages are strictly better
than (indifferent) extremes. In that case, A and B are definitely preferred to D if we
are indifferent between A and B.)

Exercise 4A.5

Illustrate the area in Graph 4.2b in which F must lie — keeping in mind the
monotonicity assumption.
Answer: By monotonicity, F must have less than C and must therefore lie to
the southwest of C . Thus, it must have no more than 5 shirts and no more than 6
pants. But it also cannot have fewer than 4 pants because then it would contain
fewer pants and shirts than A and would therefore be worse than A. And it cannot
have fewer than 2 shirts because it would then have less of everything than B and
could no longer be indifferent to B. F must therefore lie in the area illustrated in
Exercise Graph 4A.5.

Exercise 4A.6

Suppose our tastes satisfy weak convexity in the sense that averages are just as
good (rather than strictly better than) extremes. Where does F lie in relation to C in
that case?
Answer: In that case F is the same bundle as C — because C is the average of
the more extreme bundles A and B.

Exercise 4A.7

Suppose extremes are better than averages. What would an indifference curve
look like? Would it still imply diminishing marginal rates of substitution?
Tastes and Indifference Curves 4

Exercise Graph 4A.5 : Graph for Within-Chapter-Exercise 4A.5

Answer: The indifference curve would bend away from instead of toward the
origin, as illustrated in Exercise Graph 4A.7. The shaded area to the northeast of the
indifference curve would contain all the better bundles (because of monotonicity).
But the line connecting A and B — which contains averages between A and B —
does not lie in this “better” region. Therefore, averages are worse than extremes.
The slope of this indifference curve is then shallow at A and becomes steeper as we
move along the indifference curve to B. Thus, the marginal rate of substitution is
no longer diminishing along the indifference curve — and the indifference curve
exhibits increasing marginal rates of substitution.

Exercise Graph 4A.7 : Non-concex tastes

Exercise 4A.8

Suppose averages are just as good as extremes? Would it still imply diminishing
marginal rates of substitution?
Answer: If averages are just as good as extremes, then indifference curves are
straight lines. As a result, the slope would be the same along an indifference curve —
5 4A. Solutions to Within-Chapter-Exercises for Part A

implying constant rather than diminishing marginal rates of substitution. This is


the borderline case between strictly convex tastes that have diminishing marginal
rates of substitution and strictly non-convex tastes that have strictly increasing
marginal rates of substitution.

Exercise 4A.9

Show how you can prove the last sentence in the previous paragraph by appeal-
ing to the transitivity of tastes.
Answer: Pick any bundle that lies on the bold portion of the indifference curve
to the southwest of E and call it B. As noted in the text, we know from monotonicity
that E is better than B. Because A and B lie on the same indifference curve, you
are indifferent between them. Thus, E is better than B which is indifferent to A.
Transitivity then implies that E is better than A.

Exercise 4A.10

Suppose less is better than more and averages are better than extremes. Draw
three indifference curves (with numerical labels) that would be consistent with this.
Answer: Exercise Graph 4A.10 illustrates three such curves. Since less is better,
the consumer becomes better off in the direction of the arrows at the top right of
the graph. Thus, if I take A and B that lie on the same indifference curve, the line
connecting them (which contains averages of the two) lies fully in the region that
is more preferred. Thus, averages are indeed better than extremes. Since the con-
sumer becomes better off as she moves southwest, the numbers accompanying the
indifference curves must be increasing as we approach the origin.

Exercise Graph 4A.10 : Convex tastes over “bads”


Tastes and Indifference Curves 6

4B Solutions to Within-Chapter-Exercises in
Part B

Exercise 4B.1

True or False: If only one of the statements in (4.6) is true for a given set of
bundles, then that statement’s “%” can be replaced by “≻”.
Answer: True. If both statements are true, then the consumer is indifferent be-
tween the A and the B bundles (because that is the only way that the A bundle can
be at least as good as B and the B bundle can be at least as good as A at the same
time). If only one of the statements is true, then the consumer is not indifferent
between the bundles. That must mean that one of the bundles is strictly preferred
to the other, which means we can indeed replace “%” with “≻”.

Exercise 4B.2

Does transitivity also imply that (4.8) implies (4.9) when “%” is replaced by “≻”?
Answer: Yes. If A is strictly preferred to B and B is strictly preferred to C , transi-
tivity implies that A must be strictly preferred to C .

Exercise 4B.3

True or False: Assuming tastes are transitive, the third line in expression (4.11)
is logically implied by the first and second lines.
Answer: True. Suppose we call the averaged bundle C . Then the first two lines
say that the consumer being indifferent between A and B implies that she thinks C
is at least as good as A. Thus, C % A ∼ B implies by transitivity that C % B, which is
what the third line says.

Exercise 4B.4

If you were searching for the steepest possible straight route up the last 2,000
feet of Mount “Nechyba” (in Graph 4.9), from what direction would you approach
the mountain?
Answer: It looks like you would approach it from the northwest (heading up the
mountain toward the southeast) — because that is where the levels in the graph are
closest to one another (which is where the mountain must be steepest).

Exercise 4B.5

In Political Science models, politicians are sometimes assumed to choose be-


tween bundles of spending on various issues — say military and domestic spend-
ing. Since they have to impose taxes to fund this spending, more is not necessarily
7 4B. Solutions to Within-Chapter-Exercises in Part B

better than less, and thus most politicians have some ideal bundle of domestic and
military spending. How would such tastes be similar to the geographic mountain
analogy?
Answer: Such tastes would be similar in that the “utility mountain” would have
a peak just like geographic mountains do. This is not usually the case for our “utility
mountains” because usually we make the assumption that more is better — which
means we can always climb higher up a mountain without peak. (More on this in
end-of-chapter exercise 4.11.)

Exercise 4B.6

How does the expression for the marginal rate of substitution change if tastes
could instead be summarized by the utility function u(x1 , x2 ) = x11/4 x23/4
Answer: We would calculate this as

(1/4)(x1−3/4 x23/4 ) x2
MRS = − =− . ( 4B.6)
(3/4)(x11/4 x2−1/4 ) 3x1

Exercise 4B.7

Can you verify that squaring the utility function in exercise 4B.6 also does not
change the underlying indifference curves?
Answer: Squaring the utility function from the previous exercise results in v(x1 , x2 ) =
¢2
(u(x1 , x2 ))2 = x11/4 x23/4 = x11/2 x23/2 . This will give rise to the same indifference
¡

curves so long as the MRS everywhere remains unchanged. The MRS is

(1/2)(x1−1/2 x23/2 ) x2
MRS = − =− , ( 4B.7)
(3/2)(x11/2 x21/2 ) 3x1

exactly as it was before. Thus, the shape of the indifference curves is unaffected.

Exercise 4B.8

Illustrate that the same conclusion we reached with respect to u and v repre-
senting the same indifference curves also holds when we take the square root of
u — i.e. when we consider the function w(x1 , x2 ) = (x11/2 x21/2 )1/2 = x11/4 x21/4 .
Answer: The MRS is then

(1/4)(x1−3/4 x21/4 ) x2
MRS = − =− , ( 4B.8)
(1/4)(x11/4 x2−3/4 ) x1

exactly as it was when we calculated the MRS for u(x1 , x2 ) = x11/2 x21/2 in the text.
Tastes and Indifference Curves 8

Exercise 4B.9

Consider the utility function u(x1 , x2 ) = x11/2 x21/2 . Take natural logs of this func-
tion and calculate the MRS of the new function. Is the natural log transformation
one that can be applied to utility functions such that the new utility function rep-
resents the same underlying tastes?
Answer: Taking logs, we get: ln u(x1 , x2 ) = ln x11/2 x21/2 = (1/2) ln x1 + (1/2) ln x2 .
¡ ¢

Note that the derivative of this with respect to x1 is 1/(2x1 ) and the derivative with
respect to x2 is 1/(2x2 ). The MRS is then

1/(2x1 ) x2
MRS = − =− , ( 4B.9)
1/(2x2 ) x1

exactly as it was before the log transformation. Thus, taking logs does not change
the shape of indifference curves. Logs also do not change the ordering of the labels
on indifference curves. Thus, when we take the log of a utility function, the new
utility function represents the same tastes.

Exercise 4B.10

Consider the utility function u(x1 , x2 , x3 ) = x11/2 x21/2 x31/2 . Take natural logs of
this function and calculate the marginal rates of substitution of each pair of goods.
Is the natural log transformation one that can be applied to utility functions of three
goods such that the new utility function represents the same underlying tastes?
Answer: Taking logs, we get a new function v(x1 , x2 , x3 ) = (1/2) ln x1 +(1/2) ln x2 +
(1/2) ln x3 . Taking any pair of good xi and x j (where i , and j can take values of 1, 2,
and 3 but i 6= j ), we get

1/(2xi ) xj
MRS = − =− . ( 4B.10.i)
1/(2x j ) xi

If we instead work with the original utility function u(x1 , x2 , x3 ) = x11/2 x21/2 x31/2 ,
we can similarly calculate the MRS between xi and x j while denoting the third
good as xk :

(1/2)xi−1/2 x 1/2
j
xk1/2 xj
MRS = − =− . ( 4B.10.ii)
(1/2)xi1/2 x −1/2
j
xk1/2 xi

We therefore again get the same expressions for the MRS between any two
goods after we take logs of the utility function as we do before. Logs are general
transformations that can always be applied to a utility function (regardless of how
many goods the function is over) to get a new utility function that represents the
same underlying tastes.
9 4B. Solutions to Within-Chapter-Exercises in Part B

Exercise 4B.11

What would be the expression of the slope of the slice of the utility function
u(x1 , x2 ) = x11/2 x21/2 when x1 is fixed at 9? What is the slope of that slice when x2 = 4?
Answer: When x1 = 9, the expression reduces to (1/2)(9)1/2 x2−1/2 = (3/2)x2−1/2 .
This is the expression of the slope of the slice holding x1 = 9. When x2 = 4, that
slope is (3/2)(4)−1/2 = 3/4.

Exercise 4B.12

Calculate ∂u/∂x1 for u(x1 , x2 ) = x11/2 x21/2 . What does this reduce to when x2 is
fixed at 4? Where in Graph 4.12 does the slice along which this partial derivative
represents the slope lie?
Answer: ∂u/∂x1 = (1/2)x1−1/2 x21/2 reduces to x1−1/2 when x2 = 4. The relevant
slice is depicted in Exercise Graph 4B.12.

Exercise Graph 4B.12 : Slice holding x2 constant at 4

Exercise 4B.13

Calculate ∂u/∂x1 for the function u(x1 , x2 ) = 10ln x1 + 5ln x2 .


Answer: ∂u/∂x1 = 10/x1 .

Exercise 4B.14

Calculate ∂u/∂x1 for the function u(x1 , x2 ) = (2x1 +3x2 )3 . (Remember to use the
Chain Rule.)
Answer: ∂u/∂x1 = 3(2x1 + 3x2 )2 (2) = 6(2x1 + 3x2 )2 .

Exercise 4B.15

Verify that equation (4.28) is correct.


Answer: The partial derivatives are
Tastes and Indifference Curves 10

∂u 1 x 1/2
= x1−1/2 x21/2 = 21/2 ( 4B.15.i)
∂x1 2 2x1
and

∂u 1 x 1/2
= x11/2 x2−1/2 = 11/2 . ( 4B.15.ii)
∂x2 2 2x2
When substituted into the equation, it verifies what is in the text.

Exercise 4B.16

Calculate the total differential du of u(x1 , x2 ) = 10ln x1 + 5ln x2 .


Answer: This is

10 5
du = d x1 + d x2 . ( 4B.16)
x1 x2
11 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

4C Solutions to Odd Numbered


End-of-Chapter Exercises

Exercise 4.1

I hate grits so much that the very idea of owning grits makes me sick. I do, on the
other hand, enjoy a good breakfast of Coco Puffs Cereal.
A: In each of the following, put boxes of grits on the horizontal axis and boxes of
cereal on the vertical. Then graph three indifference curves and number them.
(a) Assume that my tastes satisfy the convexity and continuity assumptions
and otherwise satisfy the description above.
Answer: Panel (a) of Exercise Graph 4.1 graphs an example of such tastes.
In the top right corner, arrows indicate the directions in which I become
better off. As you will see in this exercise, convexity always implies that
indifference curves bend toward the origin that is created by arrows such
as these that indicate the directions in which a consumer becomes bet-
ter off. In the graph, A and B appear on the same indifference curve —
and the line connecting them lies “above” the curve in the sense that it
contains only bundles to the northwest that are more preferred.

Exercise Graph 4.1 : Grits and Cereal

(b) How would your answer change if my tastes were “non-convex” — i.e. if
averages were worse than extremes.
Answer: Panel (b) graphs an example of such tastes. I still become better
off moving toward the northwest where there are fewer grits and more
cereal. But now the indifference curves bend in the other direction. A and
B again lie on the same indifference curve, but the line connecting them
now lies “below” the indifference curve in the sense that all bundles on
that line segment lie to the southeast where I become worse off.
(c) How would your answer to (a) change if I hated both Coco Puffs and grits
but we again assumed my tastes satisfy the convexity assumption.
Answer: An example of such tastes is graphed in panel (c) of Exercise
Graph 4.1. Now the arrows at the top right of the graph point down and
Tastes and Indifference Curves 12

left, with better points lying to the southwest as we move toward the ori-
gin of the graph. Convexity again implies that indifference curves bend
toward the origin that is created by the arrows that indicate which direc-
tion makes us better off. Bundles A and B again lie on the same indif-
ference curve, and the line connecting them lies “above” the indifference
curve in the sense that it lies to the southwest where I become better off.
(d) What if I hated both goods and my tastes were non-convex?
Answer: An example of such tastes is graphed in panel (d) of the graph. As
in panel (c), the consumer becomes better off moving toward the south-
west. But because tastes are non-convex, the indifference curves now
bend in the other direction (and away from the origin that is created by
the arrows in the top right corner of the graph). A and B are once again on
the same indifference curve, but the line connecting them now lies “be-
low” the indifference curve in the sense that it lies to the northeast where
the consumer becomes worse off.
B: Now suppose you like both grits and Coco Puffs, that your tastes satisfy our
five basic assumptions and that they can be represented by the utility function
u(x1 , x2 ) = x1 x2 .
(a) Consider two bundles, A=(1,20) and B=(10,2). Which one do you prefer?
Answer: You would be indifferent between the two because, when you
plug these into the utility function, you get the same utility value; i.e.
u(1, 20) = 1(20) = 20 and u(10, 2) = 10(2) = 20.
(b) Use bundles A and B to illustrate that these tastes are in fact convex.
Answer: Suppose I construct a new bundle C that is the average of A and
B — i.e. take half of A and mix it with half of B. This would give 5.5 boxes
of grits and 11 boxes of cereal; i.e. C =(5.5,11). Plugging this into the utility
function, we get u(5.5, 11) = 5.5(11) = 60.5. Thus, utility of the average is
higher than utility of the extremes.
(c) What is the MRS at bundle A? What is it at bundle B?
Answer: The MRS for this utility functions is

∂u/∂x1 x2
MRS = − =− . (4.1.i)
∂u/∂x2 x1

Plugging in the values for x1 and x2 at A and B, we then get MRS A = −20
and MRS B = −2/10 = −1/5.
(d) What is the simplest possible transformation of this function that would
represent tastes consistent with those described in A(d)?
Answer: The simplest possible transformation would be to multiply the
function by a negative 1. This would leave the shape of the indifference
curves unchanged because the MRS would be the same. (The negative
would cancel in the calculation of MRS.) But the ordering of the num-
bers accompanying the indifference curves would change because each
number would now be multiplied by minus 1. This means that, rather
13 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

than numbers going up as we move toward the northeast of the graph,


numbers will go up as we go to the southwest of the graph. The indiffer-
ence map would therefore look like the one we graphed in panel (d) of
Exercise Graph 4.1.
(e) Now consider tastes that are instead defined by the function u(x1 , x2 ) =
x12 + x22 . What is the MRS of this function?
Answer: The MRS is

∂u/∂x1 2x1 x1
MRS = − =− =− . (4.1.ii)
∂u/∂x2 2x2 x2

(f) Do these tastes have diminishing marginal rates of substitution? Are they
convex?
Answer: Notice that the MRS is the inverse of what we calculated for
the Cobb-Douglas utility function x1 x2 . Consider, for instance, the bun-
dles (1,5) and (5,1) which both lie on the same indifference curve (that
gets utility 26). At (1,5), MRS = −1/5 while at (5,1), MRS = −5/1 = −5.
Thus, the MRS is shallow toward the left of the indifference curve and
gets steeper toward the right — we have increasing marginal rates of sub-
stitution rather than diminishing marginal rates of substitution. Put dif-
ferently, these indifference curves bend away from rather than toward the
origin. Since more is better, this implies that tastes are not convex.
(g) How could you most easily turn this utility function into one that repre-
sents tastes like those described in A(c)?
Answer: In A(c), the two goods are “bads” and tastes are convex. The
tastes represented by the utility function u(x1 , x2 ) = x12 + x22 in the previ-
ous part give rise to indifference curve with the shape needed for those in
A(c) — but the direction of the labeling is one that assigns higher labels
to bundles that contain more rather than fewer goods. By simply multi-
plying the function by −1, however, we reverse the labels and thus have
indifference curves with the right shapes and labels increasing in the right
direction. Thus, v(x1 , x2 ) = −x12 − x22 would represent tastes such as those
in A(c).

Exercise 4.3

Consider my tastes for consumption and leisure.

A: Begin by assuming that my tastes over consumption and leisure satisfy our 5
basic assumptions.
(a) On a graph with leisure hours per week on the horizontal axis and con-
sumption dollars per week on the vertical, give an example of three indif-
ference curves (with associated utility numbers) from an indifference map
that satisfies our assumptions.
Answer: Panel (a) of Exercise Graph 4.3 graphs an example of three indif-
ference curves that satisfy these assumptions.
Tastes and Indifference Curves 14

Exercise Graph 4.3 : Tastes over Consumption and Labor/Leisure

(b) Now redefine the good on the horizontal axis as “labor hours” rather than
“leisure hours”. How would the same tastes look in this graph?
Answer: Panel (b) illustrates these indifference curves with the good on
the horizontal axis redefined. I now become better off going to the north-
west in the graph since I prefer less labor.
(c) How would both of your graphs change if tastes over leisure and consump-
tion were non-convex — i.e. if averages were worse than extremes.
Answer: Panels (c) and (d) illustrate examples of indifference curves with
leisure (panel (c)) and labor (panel (d)) when tastes are non-convex. The
line connecting any two points on any of these indifference curves con-
tains only bundles that lie in the “worse” region — implying that averages
are worse than extremes.

B: Suppose your tastes over consumption and leisure could be described by the
utility function u(ℓ, c) = ℓ1/2 c 1/2 .
(a) Do these tastes satisfy our 5 basic assumptions?
Answer: Yes. The utility function is one that has been used a number
of times in the chapter. It is clearly a continuous function that assigns
higher value to bundles that have more consumption and leisure (i.e. it
represents monotonic tastes). The MRS for this utility function is given
by MRS = −ℓ/c. When ℓ is low and c is high (i.e. to the left in our graph),
the MRS is therefore large in absolute value, and when ℓ is low and c is
high (i.e. to the right in our graph), the MRS is small in absolute value.
Thus, we have indifference curves that have the property of diminishing
marginal rates of substitution — which is the case only when convexity is
satisfied. Thus, continuity, monotonicity and convexity are all satisfied.
(And the function clearly assigns utility values to all bundles — thus rep-
resenting complete tastes — and any mathematical function automati-
cally satisfies transitivity.)
(b) Can you find a utility function that would describe the same tastes when
the second good is defined as labor hours instead of leisure hours? (Hint:
15 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

Suppose your weekly endowment of leisure time is 60 hours. How do labor


hours relate to leisure hours?)
Answer: Let l represent labor hours and assume that I have a total of 60
hours per week in possible leisure time. Then, since ℓ = 60 − l (because
the leisure hours we actually consume are just those during which we do
not work), we can write the utility function in terms of l instead of ℓ by
replacing ℓ with (60 − l). Our new function is then v(c, l) = c 1/2 (60 − l)1/2 .
(c) What is the marginal rate of substitution for the function you just derived?
How does that relate to the sign of the slopes of indifference curves you
graphed in part A(b)?
Answer: The marginal rate of substitution is

∂u/∂l (−1/2)c 1/2 (60 − l)−1/2 c


MRS = − =− = . (4.3.i)
∂u/∂c (1/2)c −1/2 (60 − l)1/2 60 − l
Note the minus sign that appears in the denominator (because of the
Chain Rule), which cancels the minus sign in front of the fraction to give
a positive MRS. This is exactly what we graphed in panel (b) of Exercise
Graph 4.3 where the slope of indifference curves is positive. (The expres-
sion above also implies that slopes start shallow and become steeper as
they do in our graph — see the answer to the next part for an explanation
to this.)
(d) Do the tastes represented by the utility function in part (b) satisfy our 5
basic assumptions?
Answer: They do not because l enters negatively — which implies more
l reduces utility. Thus, monotonicity is violated because of the way we
have redefined the goods. The other assumptions, however, still hold.
We still have a continuous function that assigns values to all bundles (i.e.
we have continuity, completeness and transitivity). Also, when l and c
are both low (to the left of the graph), the denominator of our MRS is
large while the numerator is small — leading to a small positive number.
When l and c are both high (to the right of the graph), on the other hand,
the denominator becomes small while the numerator is large — leading
to a large positive number. Thus, the slope of indifference curves starts
small (i.e. shallow) and becomes large (i.e. steep) — precisely as depicted
in panel (b) of Exercise Graph 4.3 that mapped out indifference curves
under the assumption of convexity.
Exercise 4.5

In this exercise, we explore the concept of marginal rates of substitution (and, in


part B, its relation to utility functions) further.
A: Suppose I own 3 bananas and 6 apples, and you own 5 bananas and 10 ap-
ples.
(a) With bananas on the horizontal axis and apples on the vertical, the slope
of my indifference curve at my current bundle is −2, and the slope of your
Tastes and Indifference Curves 16

indifference curve through your current bundle is −1. Assume that our
tastes satisfy our usual five assumptions. Can you suggest a trade to me
that would make both of us better off? (Feel free to assume we can trade
fractions of apples and bananas).
Answer: The slope of my indifference curve at my bundle tells us that I
am willing to trade as many as 2 apples to get one more banana. The
slope of your indifference curve at your bundle tells us that you are willing
to trade apples and bananas one for one. If you offer me 1 banana in
exchange for 1.5 apples, you would be better off because you would have
been willing to accept as little as 1 apple for 1 banana. I would also be
better off because I would be willing to give you as many as 2 apples for
1 banana — only having to give you 1.5 apples is better than that. (If you
are uncomfortable with fractions of apples being traded, you could also
propose giving me 2 bananas for 3 apples.)
This is only one possible example of a trade that would make us both
better off. You could propose to give me 1 banana for x apples, where x
can lie between 1 and 2. Since I am willing to give up as many as 2 apples
for one banana, any such trade would make me better off, and since you
are willing to trade them one for one, the same would be true for you.
(b) After we engage in the trade you suggested, will our MRS’s have gone up or
down (in absolute value)?
Answer: Any trade that makes both of us better off moves me in the di-
rection of more bananas and fewer apples — which, given diminishing
marginal rates of substitution, should decrease the absolute value of my
MRS; i.e. as I get more bananas and fewer apples, I will be willing to
trade fewer apples to get one more banana than I was willing to originally.
You, on the other hand, are giving up bananas and getting apples, which
moves you in the opposite direction toward fewer bananas and more ap-
ples. Thus, you will become less willing to trade 1 banana for 1 apple and
will in future trades demand more bananas in exchange for 1 apple. Thus,
in absolute value, your MRS will get larger.
(c) If the values for our MRS’s at our current consumption bundles were re-
versed, how would your answers to (a) and (b) change?
Answer: The trades would simply go in the other direction; i.e. I would
be willing to trade 1 banana for x apples so long as x is at least 1, and you
would be willing to accept such a trade so long as x is no more than 2.
Thus, x again lies between 1 and 2 if both of us are to be better off from
the trade, only now I am giving you bananas in exchange for apples rather
than the other way around.
(d) What would have to be true about our MRS’s at our current bundles in
order for you not to be able to come up with a mutually beneficial trade?
Answer: In order for us not to be able to trade in a mutually beneficial
way, your MRS at your current bundle would have to be identical to my
MRS at my current bundle.
17 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

(e) True or False: If we have different tastes, then we will always be able to
trade with both of us benefitting.
Answer: This statement is generally false. What matters is not that we
have different tastes (i.e. different maps of indifference curves). What
matters instead is that, at our current consumption bundle, we value goods
differently — that at our current bundle, our MRS’s are different. It is
quite possible for us to have different tastes (i.e. different maps of indif-
ference curves) but to also be at bundles where our MRS is the same. In
that case, we would have the same tastes at the margin even though we
have different tastes overall (i.e. different indifference maps.)
(f) True or False: If we have the same tastes, then we will never be able to trade
with both of us benefitting.
Answer: False. People with the same tastes but different bundles of goods
may well have different marginal rates of substitution at their current
bundles — and this opens the possibility of trading with benefits for both
sides.

B: Consider the following five utility functions and assume that α and β are
positive real numbers:

β
1. u A (x1 , x2 ) = x1α x2
2. u B (x1 , x2 ) = αx1 + βx2
3. uC (x1 , x2 ) = αx1 + β ln x2 (4.5)
µ ¶
α
4. u D (x1 , x2 ) = ln x1 + ln x2
β
5. u E (x1 , x2 ) = −αln x1 − β ln x2

(a) Calculate the formula for MRS for each of these utility functions.
Answer: These would be

β
αx1α−1 x2 αx2
1. MRS A = − β−1
=−
βx1α x2 βx1
α
2. MRS B = −
β
α αx2
3. MRS C = − =− (4.5.i)
β/x2 β
α/(βx 1 ) αx2
4. MRS D = − =−
1/x2 βx1
−α/x 1 αx 2
5. MRS E = − =−
−β/x2 βx1
Tastes and Indifference Curves 18

(b) Which utility functions represent tastes that have linear indifference curves?
Answer: Linear indifference curves are indifference curves that have the
same slope everywhere — i.e. indifference curves with constant rather
than diminishing MRS. Thus, the MRS cannot depend on x1 or x2 for
the indifference curve to be linear — which is the case only for u B (x1 , x2 ).
(c) Which of these utility functions represent the same underlying tastes?
Answer: Two conditions have to be met for utility functions to represent
the same tastes: (1) the indifference curves they give rise to must have the
same shapes, and (2) the numbering on the indifference curves needs to
have the same order (though not the same magnitude.) To check that in-
difference curves from two utility functions have the same shape, we have
to check that the MRS for those utility functions are the same. This is true
for u A , u D and u E . To check that the ordering of the numbers associated
with indifference curves goes in the same direction, we need to go back
to the utility functions. In u A , for instance, more of x1 and/or x2 means
higher utility values. The same is true for u D . Thus u A and u D repre-
sent the same underlying tastes because they give rise to the same shapes
for all the indifference curves and both have increasing numbers associ-
ated with indifference curves as we move northeast in the graph of the
indifference curves. But u E is different: While it gives rise to indifference
curves with the same shapes as u A and u D , the utility values associated
with the indifference curves become increasingly negative — i.e. they de-
cline — as we increase x1 and/or x2 . Thus, higher numerical labels for
indifference curves happen to the southwest rather than the northeast —
indicating that less is better than more. So the only two utility functions
in this problem that represent the same tastes are u A and u D .
(d) Which of these utility functions represent tastes that do not satisfy the mono-
tonicity assumption?
Answer: As just discussed in the answer to B(c), u E represents tastes for
which less is better than more — because the labeling on the indifference
curves gets increasingly negative as we move to the northeast (more of
everything) and increasingly less negative as we move toward the origin.
In all other cases, more x1 and/or more x2 creates greater utility as mea-
sured by the utility functions.
(e) Which of these utility functions represent tastes that do not satisfy the con-
vexity assumption?
Answer: As we move to the right on an indifference curve, x1 increases
and x2 decreases. We can then look at the formulae for MRS that we de-
rived for each utility function to see what happens to the MRS as x1 in-
creases while x2 decreases. In MRS A , for instance, this would result in a
decrease in the numerator and an increase in the denominator — i.e. we
are dividing a smaller number by a larger number as x1 increases and x2
decreases. Thus, in absolute value, the MRS declines as we move to the
right in our graph — which implies we have diminishing MRS and the
usual shape for the indifference curves. Since they share the same MRS,
19 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

the same holds for u D and u E . For uC , it is similarly true that an increase
in x1 accompanied by a decrease in x2 (i.e. a movement along the indif-
ference curve toward the right in the graph) causes the MRS to fall — only
this time x1 plays no role and the drop is entirely due to the reduction in
the numerator. For u B , the MRS is constant — implying no change in the
MRS as we move along an indifference curve to the right in the graph.
We can then conclude the following: u B satisfies the convexity assump-
tion but barely so — averages are the same as extremes (but not bet-
ter). Furthermore, u A , uC and u D all represent monotonic tastes with di-
minishing marginal rates of substitution along indifference curves. Thus,
averages between extremes that lie on the same indifference curve will
be preferred to the extremes because the averages lie to the northeast
of some bundles on the indifference curves on which the extremes lie,
and, since more is better, this implies the averages are better than the
extremes. So u A , uC and u D all satisfy the convexity assumption. That
leaves only u E which we concluded before does not satisfy the mono-
tonicity assumption but its indifference curves look exactly like they do
for u A and u D . If you pick any two bundles on an indifference curve, it
will therefore again be true that the average of those bundles lies to the
northeast of some of the bundles on that indifference curve — but now
a movement to the northeast makes the individual worse off, not better
off. Thus, averages are worse than extremes for the tastes represented by
u E — which implies that u E represents tastes that are neither convex nor
monotonic.
(f) Which of these utility functions represent tastes that are not rational (i.e.
that do not satisfy the completeness and transitivity assumptions)?
Answer: Each of these is a function that satisfies the mathematical prop-
erties of functions. In each case, you can plug in any bundle (x1 , x2 ) and
the function will assign a utility value. Thus, any two bundles can be com-
pared — and completeness is satisfied. Furthermore, it is mathematically
not possible for a function to assign a value to bundle A that is higher
than the value it assigns to a different bundle B which in turn is higher
than the value assigned to a third bundle C — without it also being true
that the value assigned to C is lower than the value assigned to A. Thus,
transitivity is satisfied.
(g) Which of these utility functions represent tastes that are not continuous?
Answer: All the functions are continuous without sudden jumps — and
therefore represent tastes that are similarly continuous.
(h) Consider the following statement: “Benefits from trade emerge because we
have different tastes. If individuals had the same tastes, they would not be
able to benefit from trading with one another.” Is this statement ever true,
and if so, are there any tastes represented by the utility functions in this
problem for which the statement is true?
Answer: What we found in our answers in part A is that, in order for in-
dividuals to be able to benefit from trading, it must be the case that their
Tastes and Indifference Curves 20

indifference curves through their current consumption bundle have dif-


ferent slopes. It does not matter whether their indifference maps are
identical. So long as they are at different current bundles that have dif-
ferent MRS’s, mutually beneficial trades are possible. You and I, for in-
stance, might have identical tastes over apples and bananas, but I might
have mostly bananas and you might have mostly apples. Then you would
probably be willing to trade lots of apples for more bananas, and I’d be
willing to let go of bananas pretty easily to get more apples. The only
way we cannot benefit from trading with one another is if our MRS’s
through our current bundle are the same. This might be true for some
bundles when we have identical tastes (such as when we currently own
the same bundle), but it is not generally true just because we have the
same tastes. The only utility function from this problem for which the
statement generally holds is therefore u B , the utility function that repre-
sents tastes with the same MRS at all bundles. If you and I shared those
tastes, then we would have the same MRS regardless of which bundles we
currently owned — and this makes it impossible for us to become better
off through trade.
The statement in this problem could be re-phrased in a way that would
make it universally true for all tastes: “Benefits from trade emerge be-
cause we have different tastes at the margin” — that is, when we have the
same willingness to trade goods off for one another around the bundle
we currently consume, then we have the same MRS and can’t trade.

Exercise 4.7

Everyday Application: Did 9/11 Change Tastes?: In another textbook, the argu-
ment is made that consumer tastes over “airline miles traveled” and “other goods”
changed as a result of the tragic events of September 11, 2001.

A: Below we will see how you might think of that argument as true or false de-
pending on how you model tastes.
(a) To see the reasoning behind the argument that tastes changed, draw a graph
with “airline miles traveled” on the horizontal axis and “other goods” (de-
nominated in dollars) on the vertical. Draw one indifference curve from
the map of indifference curves that represent a typical consumer’s tastes
(and that satisfy our usual assumptions.)
Answer: This is illustrated in panel (a) of Exercise Graph 4.7 with the in-
difference curve labeled “pre-9/11”.
(b) Pick a bundle on the indifference curve on your graph and denote it A.
Given the perception of increased risk, what do you think happened to the
typical consumer’s MRS at this point after September 11, 2001?
Answer: The MRS tells us how much in “dollars of other goods” a con-
sumer is willing to give up to travel one more mile by air. After 9/11, it
would stand to reason that the typical consumer would give up fewer dol-
lars for additional air travel than before. Thus, the slope of the indiffer-
21 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

Exercise Graph 4.7 : Tastes before and after 9/11

ence curve at A should become shallower — which implies that the MRS
is falling in absolute value.
(c) For a consumer who perceives a greater risk of air travel after September 11,
2001, what is likely to be the relationship of the indifference curves from the
old indifference map to the indifference curves from the new indifference
map at every bundle?
Answer: The reasoning from (b) holds not just at A but at all bundles.
Thus, we would expect the new indifference map to have indifference
curves with shallower slopes at every bundle.
(d) Within the context of the model we have developed so far, does this imply
that the typical consumer’s tastes for air-travel have changed?
Answer: Rationality (as we have defined it) rules out the possibility for
indifference curves to cross. Thus, within the context of this model, it
certainly seems that tastes must have changed.
(e) Now suppose that we thought more comprehensively about the tastes of
our consumer. In particular, suppose we add a third good that consumers
care about — “air safety”. Imagine a 3-dimensional graph, with “air miles
traveled” on the horizontal axis and “other goods” on the vertical (as before)
— and with “air safety” on the third axis coming out at you. Suppose “air
safety” can be expressed as a value between 0 and 100, with 0 meaning
certain death when one steps on an airplane and 100 meaning no risk at
all. Suppose that before 9/11, consumers thought that air safety stood at 90.
On the slice of your 3-dimensional graph that holds air safety constant at
90, illustrate the pre-9/11 indifference curve that passes through (x1A , x2A ),
the level of air miles traveled (x1A ) and other goods consumed (x2A ) before
9/11.
Answer: This is illustrated in panel (b) of Exercise Graph 4.7 as the indif-
ference curve labeled “air safety = 90”.
Tastes and Indifference Curves 22

(f) Suppose the events of 9/11 cause air safety to fall to 80. Illustrate your post-
9/11 indifference curve through (x1A , x2A ) on the slice that holds air safety
constant at 80 but draw that slice on top of the one you just drew in (e).
Answer: This is also done in panel (b) of the graph.
(g) Explain that, while you could argue that our tastes changed in our original
model, in a bigger sense you could also argue that our tastes did not change
after 9/11, only our circumstances did.
Answer: When we explicitly include air safety as something we value as
consumers, we get indifference surfaces that lie in 3 dimensions. But
since we don’t get to choose the level of air safety, we effectively oper-
ate on a 2-dimensional slice of that 3-dimensional indifference surface —
the slice that corresponds to the current level of air safety. That slice looks
just like any ordinary indifference curve in a 2-good model even though
it comes from a 3-good model. When 9/11 changes the perceptions of air
safety, outside circumstances are shifting us to a different portion of our
3-dimensional indifference surface — with that slice once again giving
rise to indifference curves that look like the ones we ordinarily graph in a
2-good model. But when viewed from this perspective, the fact that the
indifference curve that corresponds to more air safety crosses the indif-
ference curve that corresponds to less air safety merely arises because we
are graphing two different slices of a 3-dimensional surface in the same 2-
dimensional space. While both curves then contain the bundle (x1A , x2A ),
they occur at different levels of x3 . The pre-9/11 indifference curve really
goes through bundle (x1A , x2A , 90) while the post-9/11 indifference curve
really goes through bundle (x1A , x2A , 80) — and the two therefore do not
cross. Thus, when viewed from this larger perspective, tastes have not
changed, only circumstances have.

B: Suppose an average traveler’s tastes can be described by the utility function


u(x1 , x2 , x3 ) = x1 x3 + x2 , where x1 is miles traveled by air, x2 is “other consump-
tion” and x3 is an index of air safety that ranges from 0 to 100.
(a) Calculate the MRS of other goods for airline miles — i.e. the MRS that
represents the slope of the indifference curves when x1 is on the horizontal
and x2 is on the vertical axis.
Answer: The MRS is

∂u/∂x1 x3
MRS = − = − = −x3 . (4.7.i)
∂u/∂x2 1

(b) What happens to the MRS when air safety (x3 ) falls from 90 to 80?
Answer: It changes from −90 to −80.
(c) Is this consistent with your conclusions from part A? In the context of this
model, have tastes changed?
Answer: The change in the MRS as air safety falls is a decrease in absolute
value — i.e. the slope of the indifference curve over x1 and x2 becomes
23 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

shallower just as we concluded in part A. But we are representing tastes


with exactly the same utility function as before — so tastes cannot have
changed.
(d) Suppose that u(x1 , x2 , x3 ) = x1 x2 x3 instead. Does the MRS of other con-
sumption for air miles traveled still change as air safety changes? Is this
likely to be a good model of tastes for analyzing what happened to con-
sumer demand after 9/11?
Answer: The MRS now is

∂u/∂x1 x2 x3 x2
MRS = − =− =− . (4.7.ii)
∂u/∂x2 x1 x3 x1
Thus, the MRS for tastes represented by this utility function is unaffected
by x3 — the level of air safety. This would imply that the two indiffer-
ence curves in panel (b) of Exercise Graph 4.7 would lie on top of one
another. If we think consumers felt differently about air travel after 9/11
than before, then this utility function would not be a good one to choose
for analyzing changes in consumer behavior.
(e) What if u(x1 , x2 , x3 ) = x2 x3 + x1 ?
Answer: In this case, the MRS is

∂u/∂x1 1
MRS = − =− . (4.7.iii)
∂u/∂x2 x3
This would imply that as x3 — air safety — falls, the MRS increases in ab-
solute value; i.e. it would mean that a decrease in air safety would make
us willing to spend more on additional air travel than what we were will-
ing to spend before. It would thus result in a steeper rather than a shal-
lower slope for indifference curves post-9/11. It seems unlikely that a typ-
ical consumer would respond in this way to changes in air safety.

Exercise 4.9

Business Application: Tastes for Cars and Product Characteristics: People buy
all sorts of different cars depending on their income levels as well as their tastes. In-
dustrial organization economists who study product characteristic choices (and ad-
vise firms like car manufacturers) often model consumer tastes as tastes over product
characteristics (rather than as tastes over different types of products). We explore this
concept below.

A: Suppose people cared about two different aspects of cars: the size of the inte-
rior passenger cabin and the quality of handling of the car on the road.
(a) Putting x1 = “cubic feet of interior space" on the horizontal axis and x2 =“speed
at which the car can handle a curved mountain road” on the vertical, where
would you generally locate the following types of cars assuming that they
will fall on one line in your graph: a Chevrolet Minivan, a Porsche 944,
and a Toyota Camry.
Tastes and Indifference Curves 24

Answer: Panel (a) of Exercise Graph 4.9 illustrates where the product
characteristics of these cars would place them in a graph with interior
space on the horizontal axis and speed on the vertical. Porsche’s do not
have much space in the interior but they handle well at high speeds. Mini-
vans have tons of interior space but don’t handle that well at high speeds.
And Toyota Camrys are somewhere in between — with more space than
Prosche’s but not as much as minivans, and with better handling at high
speeds than minivans but not as good as Porsches.

Exercise Graph 4.9 : Porsche, Toyota and Chevy

(b) Suppose we considered three different individuals whose tastes satisfy our
5 basic assumptions, and suppose each person owns one of the three types
of cars. Suppose further that each indifference curve from one person’s in-
difference map crosses any indifference curve from another person’s indif-
ference map at most once. (When two indifference maps satisfy this con-
dition, we often say that they satisfy the single crossing property.) Now
suppose you know person A’s MRS at the Toyota Camry is larger (in ab-
solute value) than person B’s, and person B’s MRS at the Toyota Camry is
larger (in absolute value) than person C’s. Who owns which car?
Answer: The indifference curves (through the Toyota Camry) for the 3 in-
dividuals are depicted in panel (b) of Exercise Graph 4.9. In order for one
of these cars to be the most preferred for one and only one of the indi-
viduals, it must be that the Porsche lies above one person’s indifference
curve through the Camry and the minivan lies above another person’s in-
difference curve through the Camry. If indifference curves from different
indifference maps cross only once, it logically has to follow that the steep-
est indifference curve through the Camry lies below the minivan and the
shallowest indifference curve through the Camry falls below the Porsche.
Since person A’s MRS is largest in absolute value, person A’s indifference
curve through the Camry has the steepest slope. By the same reasoning,
person C has the shallowest slope going through the Camry. Thus, per-
son A owns the minivan, person B owns the Camry and person C owns
the Porsche.
25 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

(c) Suppose we had not assumed the “single crossing property” in part (a).
Would you have been able to answer the question “Who owns which car”
assuming everything else remained the same?
Answer: No, you would not have been able to answer the question. The
ambiguity that arises when indifference curves from different indiffer-
ence maps can cross more than once is depicted in panel (c) of Exercise
Graph 4.9. Here, person B’s (bold) indifference curve is shallower at the
Camry than person A’s just as described in the problem. However, person
A’s indifference curve takes a sharp turn at some point to the right of the
Camry while person B’s continues at roughly the same slope. Thus, B’s in-
difference curve ends up below the minivan (making the minivan better
for B than the Camry) while person A’s indifference curve ends up above
the minivan (making the Camry better for him than the minivan). Thus,
once we allow multiple crossing of indifference curves from different in-
difference maps, it becomes ambiguous who is driving which car.
(d) Suppose you are currently person B and you just found out that your uncle
has passed away and bequeathed to you his 3 children, aged 4, 6 and 8 (and
nothing else). This results in a change in how you value space and maneu-
verability. Is your new MRS at the Toyota Camry now larger or smaller (in
absolute value)?
Answer: You would now be wiling to sacrifice more speed and maneuver-
ability for an increase in interior cabin space — which means the slope of
your indifference curve at the Camry should get steeper. Thus, the MRS
will increase in absolute value.
(e) What are some other features of cars that might matter to consumers but
that you could not fit easily into a 2-dimensional graphical model?
Answer: You could think of many other car features: the quality of the
upholstery, the shape of the seats, the color of the exterior and interior,
whether there is a sun-roof, the quality of the speakers on the stereo sys-
tem, the degree to which each passenger can control air temperature, the
size of the engine, etc.
B: Let x1 denote cubic feet of interior space and let x2 denote maneuverability as
defined in part A. Suppose that the tastes of persons A, B and C can be represented
β
by the utility functions u A (x1 , x2 ) = x1α x2 , u B (x1 , x2 ) = x1 x2 and uC (x1 , x2 ) =
γ
x1 x2 respectively.
(a) Calculate the MRS for each person.
Answer: The MRS for person A is

∂u A /∂x1 αx1α−1 x2 x2
MRS A = − =− = −α . (4.9.i)
∂u A /∂x 2 x1α x1

Similarly, MRS B = −βx2 /x1 and MRS C = −γx2 /x1 .


(b) Assuming α, β and γ take on different values, is the “single crossing prop-
erty” defined in part A(b) satisfied?
Tastes and Indifference Curves 26

Answer: Pick any product characteristic bundle (x 1 , x 2 ). Consider indi-


vidual A and individual B and how their MRS’s are related to one another
at that bundle by dividing one MRS by the other; i.e.

MRS A −αx 2 /x 1 α
= = . (4.9.ii)
MRS B −βx 2 /x 1 β
Now, it does not matter what bundle (x 1 , x 2 ) I use, the above equation
tells me that the MRS A is always equal to α/β times the MRS B . Thus,
any indifference curve from A’s indifference map can cross any indiffer-
ence curve from B’s indifference map only once. If that were not the case,
(as in panel (c) of the graph), the relationship between the slopes of the
indifference curves would have to be different at the second crossing —
but we have just concluded that this relationship is the same everywhere.
The same of course holds for any other pair of individuals from our group
of persons A, B and C.
(c) Given the description of the three persons in part A(b), what is the relation-
ship between α, β and γ?
Answer: Since A’s indifference curve at any product characteristic bundle
is steeper than B’s and B’s is steeper than C’s, it must be that α > β > γ.
(d) How could you turn your graphical model into a mathematical model that
includes factors you raised in part A(e)?
Answer: All that’s required is that the utility function includes more prod-
uct characteristics. So, if we identify n different product characteristics
that matter to consumers, we would model their tastes as represented by
a utility function u(x1 , x2 , ..., xn ) where xi is the i th product characteristic.
Exercise 4.11

Policy Application: Ideology and Preferences of Politicians: Political scientists of-


ten assume that politicians have tastes that can be thought of in the following way:
Suppose that the two issues a politician cares about are domestic spending and mil-
itary spending. Put military spending on the horizontal axis and domestic spending
on the vertical axis. Then each politician has some “ideal point” — some combina-
tion of military and domestic spending that makes him/her happiest.
A: Suppose that a politician cares only about how far the actual policy bundle is
from his ideal point, not the direction in which it deviates from his ideal point.
(a) On a graph, pick any arbitrary “ideal point” and illustrate what 3 indiffer-
ence “curves” would look like for such a politician. Put numerical labels on
these to indicate which represent more preferred policy bundles.
Answer: The first panel in Exercise Graph 4.11(1) illustrates an example
of such indifference curves. The ideal point is at the center of concentric
circles, with circles farther way from the ideal point representing policy
bundles with less and less utility. Since distance from the ideal point is
all that matters, the indifference “curves” should be circles with the ideal
point at their center.
27 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

Exercise Graph 4.11(1) : Ideology and Political Tastes

(b) On a separate graph, illustrate how tastes would be different for a politi-
cal conservative (who likes a lot of military spending but is not as keen on
domestic spending), a liberal (who likes domestic spending but is not as
interested in military spending) and a libertarian (who does not like gov-
ernment spending in any direction to get very large).
Answer: This is illustrated in the second panel of Exercise Graph 4.11(1).
The politician’s ideology determines the location of his ideal point, with
ideal points lining up as described in the problem. Indifference “curves”
will then again be concentric circles with each ideal point at the center of
the circular indifference curves.
(c) This way of graphing political preferences is a short-cut because it incor-
porates directly into tastes the fact that there are taxes that have to pay for
government spending. Most politicians would love to spend increasingly
more on everything, but they don’t because of the increasing political cost
of having to raise taxes to fund spending. Thus, there are really 3 goods we
could be modeling: military spending, domestic spending and taxes, where
a politician’s tastes are monotone in the first two goods but not in the last.
First, think of this as three goods over which tastes satisfy all our usual as-
sumptions — including monotonicity and convexity — where we define
the goods as spending on military, spending on domestic goods and the
“relative absence of taxes”. What would indifference “curves” for a politi-
cian look like in a 3-dimensional graph? Since it is difficult to draw this,
can you describe it in words and show what a 2-dimensional slice looks
like if it holds one of the goods fixed?
Answer: The indifference “curves” in this 3-dimensional graph would be
bowl-shaped, with the tip of the bowl facing the origin. Along any slice
that holds one of the goods fixed, the shape would be the usual shape of
an indifference curve in 2 dimensions as, for example, that depicted in
Tastes and Indifference Curves 28

panel (b) of Exercise Graph 4.11(2).

Exercise Graph 4.11(2) : Ideology and Political Tastes: Part 2

(d) Now suppose you model the same tastes, but this time you let the third
good be defined as “level of taxation” rather than “relative absence of taxes”.
Now monotonicity no longer holds in one dimension. Can you now graph
what a slice of this 3-dimensional indifference surface would look like if it
holds domestic spending fixed and has taxes on the horizontal and mili-
tary spending on the vertical axis? What would a slice look like that holds
taxes fixed and has domestic spending on the horizontal and military spend-
ing on the vertical axis?
Answer: The indifference surface would still be bowl shaped but would
now point toward the far end of the tax axis. The slice with military spend-
ing on the vertical and taxes on the horizontal is graphed in panel (a) of
Exercise Graph 4.11(2) where the politician becomes better off with less
taxes and more military spending. The slice with military spending on
the vertical and domestic spending on the horizontal axis is illustrated in
panel (b) — and looks like an ordinary indifference curve since taxes are
fixed along the slice.
(e) Pick a point on the slice that holds taxes fixed. How does the MRS at that
point differ for a conservative from that of a liberal?
Answer: The slope at that point would be shallower for a conservative
than for a liberal because a conservative is willing to give up less military
spending to get one more dollar of domestic spending. So, in absolute
value, the conservative’s MRS is smaller than the liberal’s.
(f) Pick a point on the slice that holds domestic spending fixed. How would
the MRS at that point differ for a libertarian compared to a conservative?
Answer: Libertarians would need to get a lot more military spending to
justify one more unit of taxation while conservatives would need less.
29 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

Thus, libertarians would have a steeper slope — i.e. a higher MRS (in
absolute value).

B: Consider the following equation u(x1 , x2 ) = P − (x1 − a)2 + (x2 − b)2 .


¡ ¢

(a) Can you verify that this equation represents tastes such as those described
in this problem (and graphed in part A(a))?
Answer: Along any indifference curve, the utility level is constant. Con-
sider one such indifference curve with utility constant at u. This can then
be written as
P − u = (x1 − a)2 + (x2 − b)2 . (4.11.i)

which is the equation of a circle with center (a, b) and radius (P − u)1/2 .
At the ideal point (x1 , x2 ) = (a, b), utility is at its peak P . As x1 deviates in
either direction (with x2 = b), utility declines by (x1 − a)2 . For instance,
if x1 deviates in either direction by 1, utility declines to (P − 1), and if x1
deviates by 2 in either direction, utility declines to (P −4). The same is true
for deviations of x2 in either direction (holding x1 = a). And the same
holds for any deviation from (a, b) in directions that involve changes in
both x1 and x2 . Thus, utility declines from its peak in relation to a policy
bundle’s distance from the ideal point (a, b).
(b) What would change in this equation as you model conservative, liberal
and libertarian politicians?
Answer: Conservatives would have a > b and liberals b > a. Libertari-
ans would have low values of a relative to those of conservatives and low
levels of b relative to liberals.
(c) Do these tastes satisfy the convexity property?
Answer: Yes, they do. To see this, take any two points on an indifference
circle. The line connecting those two points lies in the region of policy
bundles that are better than those on the indifference circle. Thus, aver-
ages of policy bundles that the politician is indifferent between are better
than extremes.
(d) Can you think of a way to write a utility function that represents the tastes
you were asked to envision in A(c) and A(d)? Let t represent the tax rate
with an upper bound of 1.
Answer: To turn the tax from a “bad” to a “good”, we can define it as the
“relative absence of a tax” by writing it as (1 − t ). We can then treat (1 −
t ) just like any other good, writing the utility function, for instance, as
β
u(x1 , x2 , t ) = x1α x2 (1 − t )γ where α, β and γ are just numbers on the real
line.

Exercise 4.13

In this exercise, we will explore some logical relationships between families of


tastes that satisfy different assumptions.
Tastes and Indifference Curves 30

A: Suppose we define a strong and a weak version of convexity as follows: Tastes


are said to be strongly convex if, whenever a person with those tastes is indiffer-
ent between A and B, she strictly prefers the average of A and B (to A and B).
Tastes are said to be weakly convex if, whenever a person with those tastes is in-
different between A and B, the average of A and B is at least as good as A and B
for that person.
(a) Let the set of all tastes that satisfy strong convexity be denoted as SC and the
set of all tastes that satisfy weak convexity as W C . Which set is contained
in the other? (We would, for instance, say that “W C is contained in SC ”
if any taste that satisfies weak convexity also automatically satisfies strong
convexity.)
Answer: Suppose your tastes satisfy the strong convexity condition. Then
you always strictly prefer averages to extremes (where the extremes are
such that you are indifferent between them). That automatically means
that the average between such extremes is at least as good as the extremes
— which means that your tastes automatically satisfy weak convexity.
Thus, the set SC must be fully contained within the set W C .
(b) Consider the set of tastes that are contained in one and only one of the two
sets defined above. What must be true about some indifference curves on
any indifference map from this newly defined set of tastes?
Answer: We already concluded above that all strongly convex tastes are
also weakly convex. So tastes that are strongly convex cannot be in the
newly defined set because they appear in both SC and W C — and we
are defining our new set to contain tastes that are only in one of these
sets. The newly defined set therefore contains only tastes that satisfy
weak convexity but not strong convexity. The only difference between
weak and strong convexity is that the former permits averages to be just
as good as extremes while the latter insists that averages are strictly better
than extremes. When an average is just as good as two extremes from the
same indifference curve, it must be that the line connecting the extremes
is all part of the same indifference curve. Thus, some indifference curves
in a weakly convex indifference map that lies outside SC must have “flat
spots” that are line segments.
(c) Suppose you are told the following about 3 people: Person 1 strictly prefers
bundle A to bundle B whenever A contains more of each and every good
than bundle B. If only some goods are represented in greater quantity in
A than in B while the remaining goods are represented in equal quantity,
then A is at least as good as B for this person. Such tastes are often said to
be weakly monotonic. Person 2 likes bundle A strictly better than B when-
ever at least some goods are represented in greater quantity in A than in
B while others may be represented in equal quantity. Such tastes are said
to be strongly monotonic. Finally, person 3’s tastes are such that, for every
bundle A, there always exists a bundle B very close to A that is strictly bet-
ter than A. Such tastes are said to satisfy local nonsatiation. Call the set of
tastes that satisfy strict monotonicity SM, the set of tastes that satisfy weak
31 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

monotonicity W M, and the set of tastes that satisfy local non-satiation L.


What is the relationship between these sets? Put differently, is any set con-
tained in any other set?
Answer: If your tastes satisfy strong monotonicity, it means that A is strictly
preferred to B even if A and B are identical in every way except that A has
more of one good than B. This means that your tastes would automat-
ically satisfy weak monotonicity — because weak monotonicity only re-
quires that A is at least as good under that condition and thus permits in-
difference between A and B unless all goods are more highly represented
in A than in B. All strongly monotone tastes are weakly monotone, which
means SM is fully contained in W M. Local non-satiation only requires
that, for every bundle A, there exists some bundle B close to A such that
B is preferred to A. If your tastes satisfy strong monotonicity, then we
know such a bundle always exists: Begin at some A and then add a tiny
bit of every good to A to form B. As long as we add a tiny bit to all goods,
strong monotonicity says B is strictly better than A. The same works for
weakly monotonic tastes. Thus, both SM and W M are fully contained
in L. But there are also tastes in L such that these tastes are not in W M.
Consider tastes where at some bundle A there are no bundles with more
goods close to A that are preferred to A but there is a bundle with slightly
fewer goods that is preferred to B. Then such tastes would satisfy local
non-satiation but not weak (or strong) convexity.
(d) What is true about tastes that fall in one and only one of these three sets?
Answer: Since we have just concluded that SM is contained in W M which
is contained in L, such tastes must satisfy local non-satiation but not
weak monotonicity. Consider tastes over labor and consumption. We
would generally like to expend less labor and have more consumption.
Such tastes are not strongly or weakly monotonic because A is strictly less
preferred to B if A contains the same amount of consumption but more
labor. But they do satisfy local non-satiation because for every A, we can
make the person better off through less labor or more consumption (or
both).
(e) What is true of tastes that are in one and only one of the two sets SM and
W M?
Answer: Since SM is contained in W M, such tastes must be weakly mono-
tonic. (If they were strongly monotonic, they would be contained in both
sets). Consider bundles A and B that are identical in every way except that
A has more of one of the goods than B. For tastes to be weakly monotonic
but not strongly monotonic, it must be that there exists such an A and B
and that a person with such tastes is indifferent between A and B. (If
such a person strictly preferred all such A bundles to all such B bundles,
her tastes would be strongly monotonic.) Thus, tastes that fall in W M
but not SM must have some indifference curves with either horizontal or
vertical “flat spots”.
Tastes and Indifference Curves 32

B: Below we will consider the logical implications of convexity for utility func-
tions. For the following definitions, 0 ≤ α ≤ 1. A function f : R2+ → R1 is defined
to be quasiconcave if and only ¡ ifA the following is true: Whenever f (x1A , x2A ) ≤
B B A A B A B
¢
f (x1 , x2 ), then f (x1 , x2 ) ≤ f αx1 + (1 − α)x1 , αx2 + (1 − α)x2 . The same type
of¡function is defined to be concave ¢if and only if αf (x1A , x2A )+(1−α) f (x1B , x2B ) ≤
f αx1A + (1 − α)x1B , αx2A + (1 − α)x2B .
(a) True or False: All concave functions are quasiconcave but not all quasicon-
cave functions are concave.
Answer: True. Suppose we start with a concave function f . Then

αf (x1A , x2A ) + (1 − α) f (x1B , x2B ) ≤ f αx1A + (1 − α)x1B , αx2A + (1 − α)x2B .


¡ ¢

(4.13.i)
Now suppose that f (x1A , x2A ) ≤ f (x1B , x2B ). Then it must be true that

f (x1A , x2A ) ≤ αf (x1A , x2A ) + (1 − α) f (x1B , x2B ). (4.13.ii)

But that implies that whenever f (x1A , x2A ) ≤ f (x1B , x2B ), then

f (x1A , x2A ) ≤ f αx1A + (1 − α)x1B , αx2A + (1 − α)x2B


¡ ¢
(4.13.iii)

— which is the definition of a quasi-concave function. Thus, concavity of


a function implies quasi-concavity.
But the reverse does not have
¡ toAhold. Suppose that when α =¢0.5, f (x1A , x2A ) =
10, f (x1 , x2 ) = 100 and f αx1 + (1 − α)x1 , αx2A + (1 − α)x2B = 20. The
B B B

condition for quasi-concavity is satisfied — so suppose f is in fact quasi-


concave throughout. Notice, however, that αf (x1A , x2A )+(1−α) f (x1B , x2B ) =
0.5(10) + (0.5)100 = 55. Thus,

20 = f αx1A + (1 − α)x1B , αx2A + (1 − α)x2B < αf (x1A , x2A )+(1−α) f (x1B , x2B ) = 55,
¡ ¢

(4.13.iv)
which directly violates concavity.
An example of a function that is quasi-concave but not concave is u(x1 , x2 ) =
x12 x22 .
(b) Demonstrate that, if u is a quasiconcave utility function, the tastes repre-
sented by u are convex.
Answer: Tastes are convex if averages of bundles over which we are in-
different are better than those bundles. Suppose tastes are represented
by u and u is quasiconcave. Pick A = (x1A , x2A ) and B = (x1B , x2B ) such that
u(x1A , x2A ) = u(x1B , x2B ). Let bundle C be some weighted average between
A and B; i.e.

C = (x1C , x2C ) = αx1A + (1 − α)x1B , αx2A + (1 − α)x2B .


¡ ¢
(4.13.v)

Then quasiconcavity of u implies that


33 4C. Solutions to Odd Numbered End-of-Chapter Exercises

u(x1A , x2A ) ≤ u(x1C , x2C ), (4.13.vi)


which tells us that the average bundle C is at least as good as the extreme
bundles A and B ( since u(x1A , x2A ) = u(x1B , x2B )) that the individual is indif-
ferent between. Thus, quasiconcavity of the utility function implies con-
vexity of underlying tastes represented by that utility function.
(c) Do your conclusions above imply that, if u is a concave utility function, the
tastes represented by u are convex?
Answer: Since we concluded in (a) that all concave functions are quasi-
concave, and since we concluded in (b) that all quasiconcave utility func-
tions represent tastes that satisfy convexity, it must be that all concave
utility functions also represent tastes that are convex.
(d) Demonstrate that, if tastes over two goods are convex, any utility functions
that represents those tastes must be quasiconcave.
Answer: Suppose we consider bundle A = (x1A , x2A ) and B = u(x1B , x2B ) over
which an individual with convex tastes is indifferent. Any utility func-
tion that represents these tastes must therefore be such that u(x1A , x2A ) =
u(x1B , x2B ) which makes the statement

u(x1A , x2A ) ≤ u(x1B , x2B ) (4.13.vii)


also true (since the inequality is weak). Now define a weighted average C
of bundles A and B; i.e.

C = (x1C , x2C ) = αx1A + (1 − α)x1B , αx2A + (1 − α)x2B .


¡ ¢
(4.13.viii)
Convexity of tastes implies that C is at least as good as A. Thus, any utility
function that represents these tastes must be such that

u(x1A , x2A ) ≤ u(x1C , x2C ). (4.13.ix)


We have therefore concluded that the utility function representing convex
tastes must be such that, whenever u(x1A , x2A ) ≤ u(x1B , x2B ), then

u(x1A , x2A ) ≤ αx1A + (1 − α)x1B , αx2A + (1 − α)x2B ,


¡ ¢
(4.13.x)
which is the definition of a quasiconcave function. Thus, convexity of
tastes implies quasiconcavity of any utility function that represents those
tastes.(We actually showed that this statement holds when u A = u B — but
the same reasoning holds when u A < u B .)
(e) Do your conclusions above imply that, if tastes over two goods are convex,
any utility function that represents those tastes must be concave?
Answer: No. We have concluded that convexity of tastes implies quasi-
concavity of utility functions and we have shown in (a) that there are qua-
siconcave utility functions that are not concave. So the fact that convex-
ity is represented by quasiconcave utility functions does not imply that
Tastes and Indifference Curves 34

convexity requires concave utility functions. In fact it does not — it only


requires quasiconcavity.
(f) Do the previous conclusions imply that utility functions which are not qua-
siconcave represent tastes that are not convex?
Answer: Yes. In (d) we showed that convexity necessarily means that util-
ity functions will be quasiconcave. Thus, when utility functions are not
quasiconcave, they cannot represent convex tastes. They must therefore
represent non-convex tastes.

Conclusion: Potentially Helpful Reminders


1. Convexity in tastes is easy to recognize when “more is better” — but might be
a bit confusing otherwise. Here is a simple trick to check whether the tastes
you have drawn are convex: Use two arrows that have the same starting point
and indicate which horizontal and vertical direction is “better” for the con-
sumer. (When tastes are monotonic, these point to the right and up.) Con-
vexity then implies that the indifference curves bend toward the corner of the
arrows you have drawn. (Graph 4.3 in the answer to within-chapter exercise
4A.10 has an example of this. Another example is in Graph 4.6 in the answer
to end-of-chapter exercise 4.11.)

2. It should be reasonably clear that tastes — how we subjectively feel about


stuff — should not typically depend on prices (which only affect what we can
objectively afford). Put differently, our circumstances are different from our
tastes. But sometimes that gets a little hazy when circumstances other than
the usual budget parameters matter. An example of this is given in end-of-
chapter exercise 4.7 where we think of “air safety” as one of the circumstances
a consumer cannot himself change.

3. Exercise 4.5 is a good exercise to prepare for some of the ideas that are coming
up in Chapter 6 as well as later on in Chapter 16.

4. But the last two end-of-chapter exercises are relatively abstract and probably
beyond the level of most (but not all) courses that use this text.

You might also like