R. L. Gordon (Ed.) - Myth, Religion and Society Structuralist Essays-Cambridge University Press (1982)
R. L. Gordon (Ed.) - Myth, Religion and Society Structuralist Essays-Cambridge University Press (1982)
Edited by
R.L. GORDON
Srn1°or Lrctu~r in Ille
School of Modem Lanp.p, and Europen History,
llnir~rsity of Eat An,tia
With an introduction by
R.G.A. BUXTOK
Lrctur,r in Classie, in thr
Vniunsity of Bristol
Fintpublilhrd 19111
The following are the sources of the essays in this collection. The Editor
and Publishers wish to thank the publishers mentioned for their per·
mission to publish these essays. The translations have been made by the
Editor or adapted by him from those listed.
1
L'Union avcc MCtis ct la royautC du cid', in M. Detienne andj.-P.
Vcmant, Les nues de l'intellitence: la mitis des grecs (Flammaricn,
Paris, 1974), pp. 104-24 [= Me/ang<s ... H. Ch. Puech (Paris,
1974), pp. 101-16]. Published in English as Cunning intelligence in
Gree• culture and society (Harvester Press, Hassocks, Sussex;
Humanities Press Inc, New York, 1978), pp. 107-30, translated by
Janet Lloyd.
2 'La Corneille de mer', in Les ru.ses de l'intelligence, pp. 201-41
[= 'Le Navin d'Athena', RHR 178 (1970), 133-77 considerably
altered). Cunning intelligence, pp. 215-58.
3 'Le Mythc promcthCcn chcz HCsiodc', in J .-P. Vcmant, Mythe et
sociiti en Gr~ce ancienne (Maspcro, Paris, 1974), pp. 177-94
{= II mito greco: atti del convegno intemazionale (Urbino 1973),
edd. B. Gentili and G. Paioni (Rome 1977), pp. 99-106]. Published
in English as Myth and society in ancient Greece (Harvester Press,
Swsexj Humanities Press Inc, New York, 1980), pp. 168-85, trans-
lated by Janet Lloyd.
4 'Sacrifice ct alimentation humainc a propos du PromethC:e
d'Hisiode', Annali deUa Scuola Normale di Pisa 7 (1977), 905-40,
reprinted as pp. 37-71 of •A la table des hommes' in Detienne and
Vcmant ct al. La cuisine du sacrifice en pays grec (Gallimard, Paris,
1979), pp. 37-132.
'Valcurs rcligicuscs ct mythiques de la terrc ct du sacrifice dans
l'Odyss«', Annales ESC 25 (1970), 1278-97 [= Problimes de la
TffY'e en Grice ancienne, ed. M.1. Finley (Mouton, The Hague,
J 973), pp. 269-92]. (With alterations and corrections here.)
6 'Orphce au miel', QUCC 13 (1971), 7-23 [= Fafre de l'hi,tofre,
edd.J. Le Goff and P. Nora (Gallimard, Paris, 1973), 3, pp. 56-75].
7 'La Notion mythiquc de la valeur en Gl'Cce', in Louis Gemet,
Antleropologie de la Grice antique (essays collected by J .-P.
Vrmant) (Maspcro, Paris, 1968), pp. 93-137 (reprinted without
vii
Sources Cftd acbowledfnw-•
significant alteration from Jountal dr psychologi, -t I ( 1948),
415-621.
8 'IA- Chasseur noir et l'origint: de l'cphCbie athinicnne', Annales ESC
23 (1968), 947-64, which appeared in the same year id 'The Black
Hunter and the origin or the Athenian Ephebeia', PCPhS 194 (n.s.
14) (1968), -19-64 (translated by Janet Lloyd). (With ex.tensive
alterations and corrections here.)
9 'Le Cru, l'cnrant grcc et le cuit', in Faire de l'histoirr, pp. 137-68.
(With lltcrations and additions hett.)
10· 'Esclawge ct gynCC::ocratic dans la tradition, le mythc ct l'utopie', in
8«hwchn sur les structures sociales dtlJls l'Antiquiti cltUsiqwe,
introduced by C. Nicolet (Colloqucs nationaux du CN RS, ed. CNRS,
Puis, 1970), pp. 63-80. (With additions and corrections here.)
11· 'Ma.met ct l'Atlantidc', REG 78 (1964), 420-44. (With addidpns
·: 1 -.ftortections here.)
tt· '96uc Bites ct Dicux', in Nou1Jelle rrvue de psycM...tyu 6 (191i2),
, ,~ ··"lfl-t6 (special iuuc 'De5tins du cmnibalisllle') (reprint.-, widl
·· ~ alkrations as 'Rongc-r la tCte de ses parents', in M. Octffflne,
~ mis a mart (GaH.imard, Paris, 1977), pp. 155-60.J Pub-
lf.taecl 'in English as Dionysos slain Uohns Hopkins, lmtimorc,
"1,979), pp. 35-67, translated by Mireille '9.uellner and Leonard
lolucUncr.
Introduction, by R.G.A. Buxton
It may be useful to say something about how the selected aniclcs have
been grouped together. Section I consists or two pieces on the Greeks'
perception of their gods. Vemant discusses how the sovereign power of
Zeus was thought to operate; Detienne looks, as we mentioned earlier,
at the relative provinces of Athena and Poseidon. In both studies the
central theme is the extent to which divinities display or lack mttis.
The concept is one for which we have no satisfactory equivalent, so the
two papers cover a similar area to Vcmant's analysis of Hermes/Hestia,
viz. a demonstration of the way in which Greeks divided up their
experience differently from ounclvcs.
From boundaries between divinities we tum in Section II to bound-
aries which externally delimit and internally structure the condition of
humanity. In "The myth of Prometheus in Hesiod' Vcmant, after
examining the 'narrative logic' of the two accounts, summarizes what is
implied in them regarding the position of mortals: ' ... the story locates
humankind between beasts and gods, its status characterized by sacri-
fice, the use of fire for cooking and for manufacture, woman seen as
wife but also as animal belly, com as staple food and labour in the
fields' (p. 50). Sacrifice, agriculture, marriage: these arc the markers of
human life, distinguishing men from gods and from beasts. (Compare
the last paragraph of'Sacrificial and alimentary codes in Hesiod', p. 79.)
Sacrifice and agriculture also appear as central themes in Vidal-Naquct's
fine essay on the Ody11ey. This might just as well have been placed in
Section IV, since it is much preoccupied with questions of deviation
from social normality. Vidal-Naquet shows how accepted Greek con-
ventions relating to land-cultivation and sacrifice arc contrasted with a
rich variety of alternative modes of behaviour found in lands with
which the wandering Odysseus comes into contact. The last paper in
thr section, and perhaps the most methodologically radical (and con-
tentious) one in the book, brings us to the third Hcsiodic constituent of
the human condition: marriage. In seeking to make sense of the
Aristarus episode in Virgil's fourth Georgie, and in particular that
aspect of it which concerns Aristaeus's loss of his bees, Detienne goes
right outside, or behind, Virgil's text. He starts from two facts: (1)
Aristacus is guilty of a sexual transgression - pursuit of Orpheus's wife;
(2) Aristaeus loses his bees. The link is rcconscructed by Detienne on
the basis of associations which bees have elsewhere in ancient thought
with sexual purity. The analysis broadens to incorporate more and
R.G.A. Bus:ton
··-
mon: myths about bees and honey, especially those which in somr way
touch on the relations which 1hould properly obtain between mC'n and
wumcn in m•niagc. Some scholan will remain unconvin«d thaL the
key to Georgie 4 has been discovered here, feeling perhaps that what
Virgil himscl£ chruc to convey disappun from time to time u~dcr the
weight of mythological context, But thne CUI be DO dmym11 \bat
Detienne once again provides many insights into the way in which myths
make statements about social reality through the dcploymenl of m
C19.pirical logic.
The third scction brinp together three cuays which show how myths
n:Occt features of social orpnization, Gcmct, as WII have Kffl, uses a
tJOUP of myths to illustrate thC" ccinccption of value held by Gr~lu at•
particular stage in the development of their society. Vidal-Naquct 's two
1tudie1 relate to the period of social adolcsctm:c. known in thC" case of
Athenian males as eplaebeia, through which young poople pasacd before
reaching adulthood: 'The Black Hunter' ancmpta, by recoostructini;c a
little-known myth, to recreate the ideology of &he ~IJN; while
'Recipes for Greek adolescence' - a slight depmtun: from the t"rcnch
title, which translates literally as 'The Raw, die. Gnelr. child, and the
Cooked' - involves initiation rituals outside Atbeu• wd u in it, girls
u well u boys. To any who remain sceptical a'"-i interpretations in
terms of empirical logic I recommend Vidal-N.q•\ ACCOunl of the
astonishing nnd in a necropolis at Erctria (p, 171) ......,. drie Raw and
the Cooked differentiate childhood (rum aduldlotld..in a manner cle·.i.r
enough to quicken the pulse of even the mos, alpbnic.c,:f eb\lcturalists.
Sometimes Grttk myths reflect social reality, m.,t sometimes they
distort or in~rt it. In the final three papen "'" n,,·1·1 a number of
mythical na1Tativc1 which tell of invenions of the norm. In "Slaverv and
the rule of women' Vidal-Naquet asR"mhlcs several 'world-upside-down'
tr.ulitions in which it is imagined that power is in 1he hands of women
and/or slaves; from the way in which slavery is projected idcologi."-a.lly,
important conclusions are drawn about the differences between the
Athenian and Spartan models of slanry. 'Athens and Atlantis' is about
a rather special sort of myth, name-ly the one invented by Plato in his
dialogue Tim11t"w. Vidal-Naquet's densely-argued analysis of the twin
mythical cities, proto·Athcns and Atlantis, demonstrates that rh(')'
represent alterna1ivc imaginative models which contrast with c-ach other
and with the real Athcns;t'n po.u,u.i he disposes of a number of naively
realist hiHorical-geographical interpretations of the Adan tis 1tory, 1
procedure which might well be extended to diM:ouragc c1•mp1rably
literalist rcadinn of the more orthodoll. mvths.
Introduction
gods) u,ually practised \\ithin the polis, he shows the compll"mcntary
and contrasting v..-ays in which four sects circumvent this normality.
The analysis is neat and formally satisfying - whether too neat is some-
thing for the sceptical empiricist to decide for himself - and the style is
refreshingly direct.
lt should be clear from what l have said that no one uniform approach
will he found exhibited in what follows; rather, a variety of strategics, a
number of which arc common to many or most of the pieces. Needless
to say, there is nothing sacrosanct about the order - the articles may be
taken by date of composition, or grouped according to author. In the
latter case what emerges is the individuality of the four scholars repre-
sented. If structuralism is 'some glistening Method', the quality of the
reflected light is entrancing in its variety.
Notes
1 Vidal-Naqu.et and ~tienne are still there; Vern.ant i, now at the CollC'ge de
France.
2 Vern.ant and Vidal-Naqu.et, 1972.
5 Detienne and Vern.ant, 1978.
4 Detienne and Vern.ant, 1979.
5 Detienne, 1977.
6 One may cite Torture: Conca of Democracy, Harmondsworth, 1965;Joumi1l
de ha commwne ihl.dionte (with Alain Schnapp), Paris, 1969; 'La mCmoire
d' Au.1chwitz', in Esprit for September 1980, 8-52.
\'emant, 1962; 1971.
At this point l am adapting 1ome remark, from my note in the Bull~rin of th~
Council of U,ii11nsity Cloui~ol D~po,tmrnts, 1977, 12-1'.
9 Vern.ant, 1971: I, 124-70.
10 Vemant, 1971: 11, 5-64.
11 Detienne and Vemant, 1978.
12 i,·0 r another aspect or the Athen1/Poseidon di1tinction see Vidal·Naquet at p.
206 below.
13 er. a chaptn in \'emant, 1974, entitlrd 'Reuons or myth'.
14 Uoyd, 1966: 1979.
IS t"or an appraisal or his work see Humphreys, 1978: 76-106.
I: Myth and divinity
1. The union with Metis and the sovereignty
of heaven
Jean-Pierre Vemant (1974)
WU
Ji:an-Picrrc Vcmant
hibitions, boundaries which may not be crossed, l~~_J!_~-~!ions ~hich_
must be ~~~.!':.9 if e\·cr~one....is ta .be kept ~ways._within liis· proper
•I.ink and sphcrc. By contra.st, Mctis makes her prc1cncc felt when t_hc
di\'li,c ·worlO iS~sl'lll nuid, or when?t"s balance of forces is momcntanly
out of kilter - in disputes over !ucccssion,:stn,i.gd~ (~i:_~~~crciK1;'tY,
wars and rebellions, the rise of a new power. At these moments, thmgs
get dramatic and disconcerting in heaven; if they arc to triumph, the
_powers that be in the world _bcy~nd must_ display no~ ~4:r:~f?~g~
\*f'd strcngt~_, but i~~~jg~~t p~anrung, ~unmng an~ rc~urc~.J
- In marrying Mct1s, Zws - who has Just overthrown Cronus an~ upset
the old on:lcr - is not simply recognizing the services she rendcted him;
he is also providing himself with the wherewithal to estab.Iish an entirel~
fne~ order. In marrying Themis, he renden pe~nt imd. sacrosanct
the rules he has just decreed and his redistribution of b.oDAIJit ~~ privi-
leges. His double muriage both sets the seal upon the faD~n! ~~ ptd
his own accession, and precludes the possibility of N ~ change.
11
Jean-Piatt Vemant
Oppian's version (Halieutilu, 3.9-28). Although this has ol,\•ious simi·
larities to the Hittite myth of IDuyankas, it is also related to Apollo-
dorus's and so to the Hesiodic tradition whieh, in the myths of sover-
eignty, closely usociates the motif of cunning with those of food and
swallowina;. Oppian's whole account is dominated by He-rme-s
poiltilornilis ('or variea;ated mitis'), who fint dcvistd the tactics used
by skilled lishermen (Oou>..«t .Si 'll'@W'OOIIOWV ~""-'., •• • 'll'pWTIO'fO(
qA~aao) and revealed the arts of hunting and plaiting the death of fish.
Hermes encrusted the 'art of the deep-sea' (that is, fishing) to his son
Pm, who is also reputed to h&VC' been the saviour of Zeus and the killer
of Typhon: he tricked the horrid monster by tempting him with the
offer of a fish-feast. Typhon was thus persuaded to leave his roomy
cave safe in the depths of the ,ca and come ashore, where Zeus's
thunderbolt in a trice set all hit heads ablaze.
This Typhon destroyed by greed clearly owes a good deal to the
earlier of the two venion1 or the llluyank.• myth known to us (ViU1,
1960: 28-52; Walcot, 1966: H-15). The dragon llluyankas fought
and defeated the Weather-god, who occupies in the Hittite pantheon a
place that corresponds to that of Zeus in the Greek one. With the aid
of an accomplice, a mere monal called Hupuiyas, the goddns Inara
then organizes a great celebratory banquet and invitcs Illuyankas. The
dragon leaves his lair and comes to the feast, where he procecds to stuff
himseU with so nn1ch food and drink. that he cannot get back into his
hole. Hupuiyas hobbles him and the Weather-god hu simply to kill
him. The ttsemblancc between the two stories is beyond dispute. All
the same, if Oppian hu given Typhon characteristics taken from thc
Hittite llluyankas, it is because they can be integrated almost unchanged
into the Greek story of Zeus's adwrsary. Oppian's Typhon low-1 fish
and lives on them; but he him1elr i1 not so much a dragon, like
llluyank.u, as a fish. To overcome him, you have to go lishing; and that
involves all the rnitis of Herma, all the snares of thal cunning aod,
master of nets and traps, inventor of all thosc dn-iccs called even in
Homer doloi. Zeus's supremacy among the gods is thus achin·ed by the
same kind of cunning which is at a premium in ht1ntin1 i1Rd fishing, Mid
which enables men to gct the bcner of animals u su.btlc as thc fox ut
the octopus (cf. Detienne and Vemmt, 1978: 27-5-l). MdftOft'r,
Oppian's Typhon i1 killed thank, to his greed. Like the bait which
enables (uhermen to catch fish - which hides death behind the prctt)'
arras of life - the fish-feut offcred T·rphon i1 a lutc, an apali {decep·
tion), like Cronus'• paaion honey, which Zeus empluys as a11 'ambuth-'
for his father to stumblc into;aad like th(.· fruit offercd Typhon by ihc
Moirai in Apollodorus, which he eicpc-cts to 1Pvc him adc(ed flKC)Ur but
which dooms him in fact to mortaliu.·.
Thr union with Mrtis and the sovereignty of hraven
The motif of a 'food of deception' turns up in another passage in
Apollodorus, which also has to do with Zeus's struggles against his
enemies, this time the Giants (Bibliotht:ca 1.6.1). So long as the battle
between the Giants and the King of the gods remains in the balance,
their status seems ambiguous: arc they mortal and crushable, or
immortal and invincible? From an oracle, the gods know that they will
never win on their own; to succeed, Zeus needs the hdp of someone
less great than himself. To kill the Giants he needs a mere mortal:
Herak.les, not yet a god, fits the bill. Warned of the danger to her off.
spring, GC takes counter-measures. She sets off to look for a pharmakon
(philtre, charm, drug) which wiU protect the Giants from death even at
the hands of a mortal. Zeus checks the appearance of dawn, sun and
moon, anticipates GC (<t,86:oai;} and himself cuts and gathers the anti·
death herb, just as he surprises (<t,86:ocxi;) Metis in Apollodorus's other
story and swallows her down before she can give birth to an invincible
son (1.3.6).
Both the language and the structure of the story emphasize the close
connection in Apollodorus between the various episodes of the conquest
of sovereign power. Thus Metis tricks Cronus by getting him to swallow
a pharmalton which instead of increasing his inner powers tenfold
makes him vomit up those who arc to defeat him; Zeus tricks Mctis,
swallows her and retains her inside him for ever; Zeus tricks GC by
plucking from under the Giants' noses the plant of immortality which
would, had they been able to cat it, have made them invincible; the
Moira.i deceive Typhon by causing him to swallow what they allege to
be an immortalizing drug, which is in fact a food which condemns him
to defeat and death.
Apollodorus's text, in its description of Zeus's struggle for royal
supremacy, thus lays decided emphasis on the motif of swallowing
some kind of food, which is sometimes deceptive and sometimes genu-
ine. Do we have simply here to do with a distortion of Hesiod's think-
ing about the birth of the gods, or a true glimpse of one of its main
structural clements?
The theme of swallowing appears in Hesiod at two decisive moments,
which arc clearly opposed to one another: Cronus swallows his children,
but Rhea's mitis causes him to down a stone instead of Zeus, and he is
soon compelled to vomit up all the children he has devoured; by con·
trast, Zeus gulps Metis down and keeps her forever in the pit of his
belly (Tluogony 459-97, 888-900). Some other episodes in the
Theogony allow us to interpret the significance of this double sequence
in the myth. After Zeus has freed the Hundred-Arms and restore~ them
to the light, he decides to summon their aid in a struggle which has
raged indecisively for ten years, neither the Titans nor the Olympians
13
Jean-Pierre Vcmant
being able to swin~ it in their favour (629-41). Before they enter the
rray, the status or Cottus, Gyges and Briarcus seems to have been c~m-
parable with thal of the gjanu in Apollodorus - .not .monal. yet .With·
out that unquenchable vitality and youth which IS the particular
attribute of the Immortals. It is only when the gods allow them to par·
take of their nectar and ambrosia - the food 0£ immonality reserved
exclusively to them - that the Hundred-Arms acquire their full
strength and become the spearhead 0£ victory: 'then a bold spirit swelled
in all their brcasu• (641). This nourishment feeds a divine energy in the
Hundred-Arms which must have bttn etiolated by their earlier confine·
ment: it is the nact coun1erpart of that pharmahn through which
Typhon in Apollodorus expeces to find the acc~·ss of strength he needs
to supplant Zeus, but which in £act reduces him to the common state
of mortals.
In the Tlaeo1ony, the effects of this immortality-food contrut with
those of the waters of the Styx: Hesiod describes how, when a dispute
takes place between two gods and one has to be.- shown to be in the
wrong, Iris goes off to a subterranean ann of Ocean to fetch some of
this primeval water (775-806). She brinp it back in a golden ewer. The
gods involved in the dispute pour on to the earth a libation 0£ this
water in support of their swom claims, and it is natural to suppose that
they also drank some (since that was usual in human contcxu). The one
who had falsely swom at once fell to the ground and swooned, sense·
less and spiritless, for an entire 'great year'; as though wnppcd in magic
dumber, the sleeper is denied the divine nourishment while the stupor
lasts: 'ntvtr docs he dn.w near to partake of ambrosia or nectar' (796-
7).u
It will now be easier to understand the signal imponancc in the
11ittogony of the division of shares of nourishment established between
men and gods by Prometheus when ht performed the first sacrifice.
The story's structure is as follows (Tlae·a,.any 535-57; Wo,U ond Days
42-50; cf. pp. 57-65 below). In the beginning, gods and men lived
to~ther and ate together at the same feasts. Prometheus was given the
wk or dividins the food appropriately to each group. He planned to
use this opponunity to trick Zeus and cheat him for the profit of man·
kind. This was the origin of the duel of cunnin1 ad deception bctwt"en
the Titan with miris and the sovereign 1od lcnown as ,..o ,nilioeis; on
either side, the weapons were dolos and ap,,ti (deception). A grut ox
was killed in the presence of gods and men. Prometheus divided the
cue.ass into two ponions, each deceptive: one cooccaled under UM
most appetizing surface the bare bones stripped of meat. tht other hid
the choicest meat under the sir.in and the stomach. which c1111not ~
eaten. With due deference to rank. Zeus was irivrn (int choice. 'fhe lord
The union with MetU and the sovereignty of heaven
oC Olympus, who 'had seen the trick and was not deceived' (Theogony
661), pretended to fall in with Prometheus's ploy; but in so doing, he
turned Prometheus's snare for himself into a trap for men. The portion
that was inedible, the white bones ever since burned by mortals on
w:rificial altiilfS in honour of the gods, is in fact the only genuinely
wholesome portion; men reserve the meat for themselves and cook it to
revive their failing strength. But what they keep is an 'ephemeral food',
like the fruit treacherously offered to Typhon by the Moirai. Those
who must live on it, and ta.kc pleasure in the eating, experience a hunger
~er-renewed; their strength fades, they tire and die. By the same token,
those who live only off the smoke from the bones, from the savour and
the aromatics, enjoy the banquets of immortality and sit down at the
tables where nectar and ambrosia arc served.
Each category of animate creature has thus its proper food, the food
it deserves: mortal men get the cooked meat of a dead animal; Typhon
and the Giants have the 'ephemeral fruit' instead of the pharmalt.on of
immortality; Cronus gets the 'food of deception' which confines him in
the prison-house of sleep; the Olympians and Zeus's allies whom he has
freed from their bonds, nectar and ambrosia. But Zeus, and he alone,
gets the divine sustenance which his cunning gave him to swallow and
digest, the goddess Metis - the drug that grants intelligence an~ clev~~-
ness beyond compare, the true pharmahon of unshakabl_e sovereignty.
15
2. The 'Sea-Crow'
Marcel Detienne (1970, 1974)
.
the line of Alcinous and who grant1 lhe Ph.acac.ians thC' privilegf of Cl'OM·
ing the seas. Poseidon's so\·ereig:nty over I.hi, land 11Ums undeniable •
The 'SH·Cror»'
There is just one other god who could rival him, at lcut if we were to
accept one Interpretation of four disputed lines in praise of Poseidon's
... bjects:
A1 111\lCh u Phaiakian men uc expert bq,ond .U. othen
for drivinc a f•t lhip on the open sea, IO their women
an 1killcd in weninc and dowered with wildom batowed by Athene,
to be es.put ln beautiful worlr., to have pod character.
(7.108-11, tr. Lattimott}
Don Athena's patronage extend to the weaving women only, as the last
scntcncc seems to imply in iu employment of a formula used elsewhere
for Penelope, who is likewise, by the grace of Athena, as nimble of wit
as she isat the loom (>"tp, .,.ap ""°' &wK.,. 'A8,j"'I I lna- ,· bloTaaBa,
>'fpuca).).ta Kai w,t- ta8).6'( - m fpowaua' />J.Q 8uµo, II ol fffPI
6wK ... A8,j"'I, I lna- ,· t ..loTaaBru >'fpuca>.>-.ta Kai "P'- ta8Aa<
Kep6<dl 8' ... : 2. 116-18)? Or doc:s it extend also to the Phacacian
sailors, as might be implied by the affinities I have noted earlier be-
tween Athena and helmsmen?n But, attractive though it is, there are
two reasons for rejecting such an interpretation.
First, Athena intervenes only at the very edge of Phaeacia: befon:
Odysseus sets foot there, Athena makes a single appearance to block
winds sent by Poseidon against his victim's ship - she stirs a brisk
North wind for Odysseus to reach the shore (5.283-7). 11 Once he has
done so, she behaves with immense discretion, refusing to show herself
to him, unwilling to act openly, hanging back. 'out of respect for her
uncle' (6.329-Sl). She no sooner guides her protCgC to the house of
Alcinous than she disappears on her way back to Athens and the house
of Ercchtheus (7 .78-87). And a topographical point betrays exactly
the relation between her and Poseidon in Phaeacia: while his temple
dominates agora and city, the one place dedicated to Athena is a modest
grove (6.521) - and it is outside the town, on the edge of Alcinous's
kingdom.
The second reason confirms that Athena scouts the Phacacians, but
it also gives the key to the relationship between them and the great god
of the sea. They are seafarers and carriers, and they possess extra-
ordinary ships - quite as extraordinary as Dionysus's: they travel with·
out a hitch, faster than wings or thought - not even a falcon, the fastt'st
thing that flies (13.86-7), can keep pace. But Poseidon has ad1kd to
this gift of speed over the water the privilege of 'crossing tlw grc:.Lt
abyss of the sea' (AalT'µa llrf' l1<we-pdwow: 7.35). These ships cross the
chasm of the sea evC"n when shrouded in mist and cloud 'without fear of
damage or shipwreck': they themselves "undentand men's thoughts and
purposes' (8.559; cf. 560-5). When ordinary men go to sea, they must
constantly adjust the ship's course with the steering-oar, but on
35
\1arcel Detienne
Phaeacian ships there is •no helmsman, no tiller' (8.55 7-8). Sine"
Poseidon has granted t h ~ m of the chasm of the lta, $11i~y
do not have to cheat tht' winds or watch for bad Wt"ather. Fur them UI
fact Lhc sea is not a 'chasm' that cannot be crossed: it has become
familiar terrain stripped of mystery. And of course that is why Athen~
and her mitis have no place in the land of Phaeacia. Thi' art of navi-
gation is there useless, rendert"d superfluous by the vt"ry ships' privilege
of knowing all the paths of the sea. . . . .
If 'the men of Phaeacia surpass all other men m rowing swtft ships on
the sea' (7.108-9)," they do so thanks only to Poseidon who gives
tht'ir ships navel-knowlt"d~ of the chasm of the Kil. But equally he
may take away that knowledge all of a sudden in a fit of rage, meta-
morphosing hawk-swift ship into a dumb stone or somt' inen. su·r~tcd
rock.'° In other words, so far from undermining my earlier analysu of
the proper modes of Athena and Poseidon, the case of Phaeacia offen
precious confirmation. ~n when Post"idon's power rules supreme,
when it is as it were given free play, it operates on either side of navi-
gation, outside the field of Athena's proper sphere.
(2) Hae, then, Poseidon's character is revealed by the total exchuion of
Athena. In the other two cases, the two gods arc in more direct com·
petition, and in contuts which do involve navigation and the stetring
of ships. The fint is set at the very tip of Attica, at Cape Sounion. Herc,
£acing the sea and dominating the site, stands a temple of Poseidon,
31.15 m long and 13.48m'ol.;de(KintenandK.raiker, 1967: 163-7). 11
Sounion was famous even at the period of the composition of the
Odyssey, for it was hen that Menelaus's fteet on its way b.w:k from
Troy lost its helmsman Phrontis, slain by Apollo's arrowi as his ship
was speeding along, u he sa.t with his hand on the steering-oar (3.278-
81). He had to be buried, so Mendaus beached his ships and gave him a
full funeral, probably on thi, he.adland sacred to Poseidon.
Some years ago Charles Picard, following up the exca.,·ations carried
out by Greek archaeologists, found strong evidence for identifying ;,;a
small building just outside the temrnos of Poseidon as a '1ir0011 (shrine
of a 'hero'] of Phrontis (1940: 5-28). Sounion may therefon provide
evidence for a particularly close a..uociation bttwetn Poseidon and a
helmsman who,e very name Phrontis ('Knowing one') indicatts that he
possessed n.avigating skill worthy of a protigiE of Athena:
(He) lllrpua,rd all lhr b~d of mo1Uh
Plthrt1ttrin1 ora ehip wh-,cr(~;';';~t::. ~!:~·
The nst of this episode in the Odyssey teUs u1 more about his skill.
.. ..
Once he loses Phronti,, Menelaus is caught unawaru in a trap set by
Zeus: rounding Cape Malea, the fltet i1 surprised by a 1torm wbich the
The 'Sea-Crow'
King of the Gods has deviS<d (t.poamo) for them (3.286-92)."
Sevcnil ships arc destroyed; the rest are blown as far off course as Egypt,
where Menelaus finds himself stuck: a god holds him prisoner and
'binds his path' (f6110• KEXEllllou: 4.380). It seems evident that by
losing Phrontis at Sounion, Menelaus has lost the mite's without which
ships cannot ride out bad weather (cf. Scveryns, 1966: 119).
But must we therefore conclude that this skill in navigation has been
somehow confiscated by Poseidon, who otherwise gives the impression
of having no connection with any form of mitis? If we look more
closely at the evidence from Sounion, I think we will find that we
should not. For it is clear that the site at Sounion was not reserved
exclusively to Poseidon. We find in Pausanias (I.I.I cf. Euripides,
Cyclops 293-4) that when sailors arrived within sight of Attica the first
thing they saw was a little temple perched right on the top of the head
land (f,ri ,c.opu4Jij 1"1~ &c,ow;). This was the temple of Athena Sounia.s,
the foundations of which have been found about 500 m away from the
temple of Poseidon, on a level eminence. In their excavation of this
sanctuary, the Greek archaeologists came across more precise evidence
for Athena Sounias: a small painted clay plaque, a votive o£fering,
which shows a ship steered by a bearded man who is sitting with his
hand on the steering-oar (as described in Pausanias 10.25.2: a scene
painted by Polygnotus in the /eschi of the Cnidians at Delphi). Even if
we do not go so far as to identify this with Picard as 'a memento of the
death of Phrontis', it is nevertheless clear that the helmsman heroized at
Cape Sounion was connected with Athena as well as Poseidon.
The relation between Phrontis and the two divinities of the sea may
be defined by analogy with the role of another legendary helmsman
who w.u also one of Menelaus's men. A post-Homeric literary tradition
has it that Phrontis's place was ta.ken by a helmsman named Canopus or
Canopus. It was he who took Menelaus's fleet from Rhodes to Egypt
wheTe he was accidentally killed and turned either into a star visible
only to sailon crossing from Rhodes to Egypt, or into the brightest star
in the constellation Argo (which represents tht' ship's stecring-oar). 64
The story of Canopus illustrates perfectly and concisely the relationship
between navigation and astronomy: the legendary helmsman is trans-
formed into one of the brilliant beacons which help the good navi~ator
to find his way across the sea. And according to the Chronicle set up rn
the temple of Athena Lindia at Lindos on Rhodes, the same Canopus
dedicated the stccring·oan of his ship not just to the patron deity of
Llndos, who is also the protector of pilots but jointly to Athena and
Poseidon:
Marcel Df:ticnne
'Canopus the helmsman 0£ Menelaus ( dedicated) his ncering·oa.n on
which wu inscribed "Can~....._ md P<*idon'"."' ·,
At Lindos II at Souniori thf1 clo1c U1ociation of Athena and Poseidon
with the helmsman can mean only one thing: while the navigator'• skills
derive principally Crom Athena, no helmsman can effectively exercise
them without also acknowledging: that aspect of Poseidon's sovereignty
which is represented in the banal image: of the Lord of the sea curving
on his back ships mm have made. It is not cnou11h for Phrontis and
Canopus to be Athena's protigis: they are necessarily also clients of
Poseidon. He may do without Athena, but she cannot dispense with her
powerful partner - precisely inasmuch as the nfflgator's skill cannot be
deployed without the collaboration of the clement which is at bean
beneath Poseidon's sway.
(3) At Sounion as at Lindos, Athena and Poseidon are to be understood
as twin powers, at once clearly distinct from one another but also
collaborative; indeed their collaboration is both c£fcctivc and ncccuary.
In our third case, however, the- two are found in more or less direct
collision, apin in the context or navigation. Nonnus's Dionynlllu,
describes a chariot race in which the competiton are Athena's charioteer
and Poseidon's coachman (Detienne and Vcmant, 1978: 204);just so a
real opposition seems to be set up between the successive helmsmen of
the Arra, between Tiphys, who is chosen and sent by Athena, and
Ank..aios son of Poseidon, who is entl'Ultcd with the helm on the sudden
death of Tiphys." It is true that strictly speaking Ankaios docs not
cornpete with Tiphys. Bu, he is presented u his rival in the art of steer·
ing:, as is evident from two passages in the A'1'onniil11 of Apollonius
which praise his knowledge as a naviptor and his slr.il1 in handling &he
steering-oars:
(Erpllo1 and Ankaio1) . , . ~ 6 'lpfc.,
ll,,iPMIWWIKIJ6'~n,xffdwM'o(l.lll-9 Friinkel)
'both boasted their prowess in seafaring and war';
... nparp6,., 1!6.t•i•croro
iltM'w (2.867-1 Frankel)
'for he was especially skilled in guiding (ships)'.
We might expect that a comparison between them miaht cau1e us to
modify in at least some rcspecu the division of powtr we have sketched
here. Let us sec. ·
We may note fint thal the gods' rclatian.10.cfl.:protips is wry dif·
fercnt. A&hena encourages Tiphys to join the ......... md bcc:ome
the helmsman. She 11ands at his side and acb with llilD whell they come
to the Symplepdes. By conu-a.st, Poseidon never inte,t.elles in faYOUr gf
the man whom it ia kmptinc to call 'his" hebum111: Q.~not Potr:idon
but Hera who prompts Anlwm to lay claim to _111• ,-1cr1 vacuit by
,a
Th, 'Sta·Cf'OUI.
phys's doath. And at points of high drama it is Argos, Juon, the
ioscuri or even Triton (a lake-god) and Apollo aiglitis ('the dazzler')
ho come to his usistance and get him out of trouble. Ankaios never
thcr receives or requests help from his divine father. Once this dis·
nction is made, the contrast between the two helmsmen becomes
ansparc:nt. Where• Athena•, pilot shows himself to be truly in control
r the ship, even to the point of outshining Jaaon on occasion in front
[ all his companions, Ankaios seems a dim, insignificant figure, usually
uite inadequate to cope with eventualities he has been unable to
n.ticipatc.
From the very beginning of Apollonius's .Argonautika, Tiphys is
resented as a. masterly helmsman, quick to anticipate (1rpo6CltljJ.'Q't)
hanges in the \,·eather and shifts in the wind, able to calculate his
oune {«Kiuipaab) by the position of the sun and stan (A,r. 1.106-
1; d. Valerius Flaccus, .Argonautica 1.481-3; 2.55-71). It is he who
~vcs the signal for departure and who supervises the manhandling or
he ship into the water (A,r. 1.381-91). All through the fint part of
he expedition he is up with the morning star, watching for favourable
•inds and urging the Argonauts to set sail (1.519-22, 1273-5). It is
tis mitis and his prudence (•pa61,1ocn)1'17) that decides the route
:1.559-62). At the entrance to the Bosphorus only his skill in
manoeuvring enables him to find a way through the gigantic waves
which threaten to overwhelm the boat (2.169-76). But the supreme
demonstration of his mastery is the shooting of the Symplegades. the
Clashing Rocks. They follow the advice of the seer Phineus; Euphemus
releases a rock-dove to test out the pusagc as Tiphys gives the order to
row (2.555-67); the bird has barely cleared the rocks when he orden
the Argonauts to haul on the oars and shoot between the two cli£fs just
as they begin to move apart again (2.575-4). When they arc half-way
through, he is quick enough to make a last-minute swerve to avoid a
giant wave which threatens to swamp them (2.580-7); and then it is
Athena's tum (see p. 19 abo,:e)." When they finally emerge into the
Black Sea, Tiphys is filled with a great joy in striking contrast to the
other Argonauts' ten-or. He encourages Jason and comforts the crew,
declaring to their general surprise that henceforth the mission's success
is assured: all Phincus's predictions have come to pass and now that
they arc through the Clashing Rocks the way is open before them
(2.610-37)." Shortly afterwards, he suddenly dies (2.854-7).
Ank.aios then comes forward (2.864-98). In him we have a 1aclically
different type of helmsman. No doubt he has some knowledge of navi·
ption and can use the steering-oars. But he never anticipates anything,
De"Yer makes a decision or truly control, the ship. At the very fint
difficulty they meet, when they have to leave the Black Sea to enter the
39
Marcel Detienne
River Phuis which leads to Cokhis, it is Argos who takes Ank.aio,'s
plac, to sup,m1< w ...-·'(2.1260-1; cf. 1211-9). Oa ibe_
retum journey, it is apin Arso• who tells the AfFnauts what_ eoune »
follow (4.256-93). From then on, the voyage or the Arp 11 punctu·
ated by a ,cries or miraculous interventions. To show them the way to
the River lstro1 (Danube), Hera traces out a great shining line in the 1lr.y
(4.294-302). After the murder or Apsyrtus (Medea's brother), the
prophetic bearn built into the ship's prow reveals that the Dioscuri mun
pray the gods to open up the 'paths of Ausonia' which lead to the
island of Circe (4.580-92) .., On another occasion, when the wind
looks like blowing the expedition off into mid-Ocean, Hera once again
intervenes, this time more dirccdy and cncfFtically: she shouts at them
and alerts them to their mistake (4.640-4). In all this, Anlr.aios might
just u well not be there: he plays no part at all. Nor is he any more in
evidence when they shoot the Wandcrin1 Rocks (the PI.Gn.lta1). It is
Thetis and the Nereidl who seize the ship and 11,1idc it through, taking
advantage of a moment of calm brought about by the collaboration o(
Hephaestus and Aeolus, the Master of fire and the Kini of the winch
(4.922-65). And the rest of the voyqc- simply confirms his impotmcc.
With the Peloponnese already in sight, yet another 1torm forces them
into the Libyan Sea and beaches them deep in the Gui( of Syrtis, on a
de.en coast (4.1245-9). This is too much: Ankaim tearfully tells the
othen that he is abandoning his post and that he refuses to be helm•·
man any loftFr (4.1261-76).°'° Henceforth we hear nothin1 more of
him. The final part of the voyalC is marked by two further divine
interventions: Triton (the son of Poseidon) rises from the depth• of the
lake which is called after him and 11,1ides the ship by the keel to the
point wheR the lake flows into the sea (4.1551-1619); and fmally
Apollo oiflitis causes a bright liP\t to shine out in the blaclr. 1tormy
night, so saving the Argonautl from the perils of the impenetrable- dark·
""" (<"1Gt1A<I<:) (4.1694-1718).
Throughout the epic, Poseidon's helmsman ii 1huply contrasted with
Athena's. Unlike Tiphys, Ankaio1 never shows that he poncSIC'I even a
pin of mitil. N the expedition continues his incompetence becomes
more and more evident until he is forced to resign. But of all lhe epi·
sodcs in the 1tory u Apolloniu, tcU. it there is one which spells our the
limitations of this Poscidonian pilot better than any - that is when the
Dioscuri uc given charge of the Argonauts' lhip." When the .4.,ro
reaches the Stoichades, the DiolC'llri, who have beca dcsipar.ed. by the
prophetic beam, arc confirmed in their new rQlc by U\11 who cntrulll
them with rcsponlibility in the future for savin1 mip1 in danpr
(4.588-9, 649-55). Their mode of intervention is markedly diffcreac
from Athena's. The '1aYioun of shipl' appear in the di.y, shinina at the
40
Tiit 'Sta-Crow'
top of ships' masts: they are pho,phoroi, 'bringers of light', and they
still the wind and calm the waves (Homnic Hymn to tit.~ Dioscun·
2.11-17:cf. Cook, 1914-40: 1.760-74). There was a ritual for caosing
them to appear: sailon saaificcd white lambs to them on the ship's
stnn when danger threatened (Homme Hy,nro 2.9-11). This ritual is
the exact convene of the one the Athenians performed to appease
storm-winds: when a 1torm threatened they would sacrifice a blaclr.
lamb to them on the sea-shore (Aristophanes, Frop 847-8). The
object here was to appease the dark clouds ("'9Wt), to avert the fury of
the winds by the offering of a black victim, a colour reserved to the
powcn of the underworld. The fint ritual is a request to the Dioscuri to
make a light shine in the storm, whose dazzling brilliance is symbolized
by the colour o! :h, sacrificial victims. And Plutarch well describes the
singularity of the way in which the Dioscuri operate: 1thcy do not sail
{with men) U\d share their danger, but appear in the sky as saviours'
(D• def•ctv orocvlo"'m SO, 426c).
This digression on the Dioscuri continn1 that there is no rivalry be-
tween Tiphys and Ankaios that might reflect a rivalry between Athena
and Poseidon in connection with navigation. The one helmsman who
can claim to have any connection with Poseidon is obliged to entrust
the safety of his ship to the good offices of the Dioscuri. In other
words, the salient difference between Tiphys and Ankaios is precisely
the point at which the difference between the action of the Dioscuri
and the intervention of Athena is most evident. Ankaios is as neglected
by Poseidon as the Phaeacians arc blessed by him. He is a dreadful
helmsman: he can only appeal for help to the Dioscuri.'2
It cannot then be denied that Poseidon's power, which is limitless on
the sea, applies neither to the helmsman nor to the art of navigation,
but operates both 'above' and 'below' this technical level. It operates
'below' when the god at will unleashes or calms the forces of the sea;
and 'above' when he grants the Phacacian ships such perfect knowledge
of the paths and the chasm of the sea as to render superfluous the
whole art of navigation.
Marine Athena, a 'sea crow' like lno Uucothea, affords the seafarer
help as total as it is magical, yet which cannot be characterized by the
opposition between black and white typical of the Dioscuri. '' She may
stand by the helmsman to open up a path for him over the sea; she may
release a bird to find the way through the chasm of the deep; but
always she manifests herscir in the marine world in the cxe~Li~c of a
skill in navigation which can hold a counc over the sea, outW1ttmg the
winds and the beating waves. But this same sharp practical intelligence
is manifested also u technical skill, in the art of cutting the timbers
straight with the line, and then in the equal art of fixing them together
41
Marcel Detienne
to build the very meillll whereby navigation becomes po11ible. In the
area or activity which ,.....,..... widi Paeeicloa. Leucothea md the
Diotcuri, Atheiaa ii characterized against all other divinities of the ,eai
by a dual capacity, both to make and to guide ships. And he~ lies her
CWltinction, her special mode of action, in the world or navigation.
II: The human condition
3. The myth of Prometheus in Hesiod
Jean-Pierre Vemant (1974)
Hesiod devotes two long passages to the story of the theft of fire by
Prometheus. one in the Theogony (535-616), the other in Wor•s and
Days (45-10!»). These two versions arc not merely complcmcnu. They
arc formally interrelated by virtue of an allusion in each to an incident
explicitly nanatcd in the other: WD 48 refers to the fint section of the
story in the Theogony, Prometheus's trick in apportioning the sacrifice
at Mckone; while Th. 512-14, by way of introduction to the myth of
Prometheus, mentions the acceptance by Epimcthcw of Zeus's fatal
gift to man in the shape of Pandora, which is the final section of the
story in the WorAo:s and Days. The two versions thus constitute a single
entity, and must be analysed as such.
I begin by presenting a formal analysis of the narrative, taking agents,
actions and plot one by one, first in the Theogony and then in the
Worls a.nd Days. I shall then attempt, by comparing the two texts, to
bring out the oven.11 logic of the narrative conceived as one.
1.1.1 Tlaeogony
In the presence of gods and men
43
Jean-Pien-e Vemant
1.1.2. Woris and Doys
on one band Pronae~- ~r-..,
Epimetheus
I on the other Zeus (asmted. by
Hephaestus, the Graces, Peitho,
Aphrodite, Athena and Hermes)
representing: men gods
Prometheus's mitis, a compound of anticipation, guile and deceit, is
matched by Epimetheus's wanl of mitis, for Epimetheus never und~r-
stands anything until it is too late, and is always the fall-guy. T~e. ~n-
~ s are opposed but complementary, uniting subtle calculation
with grou fatuity; and precisely that combination ch~kli.zn the
human condidon. - ·
1.2.1.
Preparatory (premeditated) dispositions (f"lBf"/J.U. and its compounds; cf.
for Prometheus, n. 557-9, 541; for Zeus and his ass.istanu, Th. 577-
8, 585, 601; WD 61, 74, 80) which arc designed to deceive, .,,.tan, the
opposition. On each side, this deception (OfHti) or trick. (dolos) involves
the wne rccounc to 'hiding' or 'concealing from sight' (Wap,~;n.
-':ruptein), and, in the cue of Prometheus, 'stealing' without being ICCft
(ll,p,.in).
1.2.2.
A pme of reciprocal giving of deceptive presents, trick gifu, which
may be either accepted or rejected. The rules of thlll pmc follow
the followin1 formal pattern, which also sums up the logic of tM
Th~ myth of Prometht!us in Hesiod
I
taking the gift ~ accepting
not-taking the gi£t = rejecting
not-tak.mg what 1s not-given
not-giving
taking what lS not-given= stealing
1.3. Plot
1.3.1. Th,ogony
Thu general grammar represents the organization of the narrative. The
individual episodes can be expressed in the following terms, with each
one introduced by a time-marker which gives it a particular relation to
the other episodes in the sequence:
Episodt I (535-61)
Time-marker: 535-6: Kai ")'QP OT' ... .,.or· hEmx ('Now when ... ,
after this ... ')
In the presence of gods and men, and that there might be distinction
between them (cf. h:pUJOvro), Promethcw 'secretly disposes' (539:
1tcrrflJt?KE KaAUtJ.,a(; 541: E~ETiaac; Kcrr,8flKE KaXUW~) the two por-
tions of the ox he has 'laid before' (537: wpoli81JKE) gods and men, and
sacrificed and then cut up. Prometheus offen Zeus the appealing but in
fact uneatable part of the ox; Zeus accepts this apparently preferable
ponion and finds he has been tricked - though all along the trick itself
was part of the mitU, the cunning trap, laid on purpose by Zeus to en·
compass man's downfall. Zeus is angry.
This transaction establishes which share of the blood sacrifice is to be
reserved in future to men (i.e. the meat and the entrails covered in their
fat = the edible parts) and which to the gods (the stripped white bones,
burned upon the alter after being scattered with incense).
Episodt 2 (562-9)
Time·marker: 562: E,c TOVTOV 6rj l,rftW ('From that time on ... ')
Zeus cannot forget Prometheus's trick, and 'refuses lo give' men the
heavenly fire (the thunderbolt) which they used previously (ob,c €6ihov)
Unseen by Zeus, Prometheus steals fire (ffa,rQ:1170EP . • ,c).fijJw; .
n,pO( QV")'11P). Men arc denied heavenly fire, but Prometheus's fire
bums among them and enables them to cook food.
Zeus is angry at thus being tricked.
Episode 3 (~70-84)
Time·marker: 570: ai.rru«X ('Whereupon ... ')
In recompense for the fire which he had denied and which Prometheus
45
Jean-Pierl'C' Vernant
stole, Zeus orders the manufacture for men of something which had not
47
Jean-Piern Vemant
And thus the ills go UDICCll lhat men wCMdcl ,woid. if they could but
,.. diem; and the ill - • !by cu, both ,cc one! heor - ...i
seduces them in the specious image of the good.
Conclusion
It is then impossible to 'escape the mind of Zeus' (and men must pay
heed).
1.4.2. Pandora and her role • a 'gift' - a deceptive, baneful Jift which
might have been either accepted or rejected - are emphuized hcarily
(cf. the explanation of the name Pandora, and lina 57, 82, 85, 16). But
the theme of the gift is prnm.t already in the 71t•oto••1 version - and
n.·
in fact dctennincs its entire lope (note cspcci.U.y ('lake". 'chooR'),
549; ov,c Hi&v ('he irluocl to gi...,1, 565; and the 'cducol' dolivc1
/ia,8pwtrOU1u, ('lo, muwnd? in 570 and 589).
1.4.4. The episode of the theft of fire is identical in the two versions.
The two versions of the creation of the first woman and/or Pandora
corrtspond exactly, though tht: account in the Works and Days is more
detailed: in each case, the feminine creature made by the gods for
humankind is presented as a parthenos ( an unmarried but nubile girl)
adorned for her wedding ceremony.
49
Jean-Pierre Vemant
deception, and in fact withholdl what it pre~ 10 baEow - it looks
like dwe girt or a 1ood, a..n·iiMlihu an umern evil. In effect, • .- ....
things have been hidden (not-given) by the gods, men_ carn~ot havt
access to them except by way or the ills (pono1; womrn~ 1n ~•c? they
arc wrapped. And conversely, the gods' girts to men arc ills disgu11Cd u
goods. .
The opposition giving venus not-giving which seemed to domanate
the structure of the narrative thus resolves into two dirrercnt forms or
a single action 'hiding':
(1) •not-giving'-= 'hiding' a good so that it cannot be gained except by
way of the ills in which it is wrapped
(2) 'pving' ,. 'hiding' an evil under the seductive appearance or good.
'Ole narrative-logic reflects the ambiguity of the human condition, in
which, thanks to the gods' action in 'hiding', goods and ills whether
'given' or 'not-given' are always linked indissolubly. At the same time,
the story locatH humankind between beasts and gods, its status charac·
tcrizcd by sacriricc, the use or fire for cooking and for manufacture,
woman seen u wife but also as animal belly, com u staple food and
labour in the fields.
1.5. The discussion so far has dealt with the orpnization or the tex.t u
a nanativc, with its syntu and logic. We must now extend it, at a dif-
ferent level, by examining its semantic content, taking into account all
the details of the architecture of each cpitodc u well as the complez
network or relations between their constituent clements.
This will enable us to set u.p a third lcvcl, the structural contnt, or
more accurately the structure of the mental world (clusificatory
catq;orics, the pattemin1 Uld encoding of reality, the delimitation of
semantic fields) within which the mythical narratives were produced,
and which pmnits the modem interpreter to make them once again
fully intelligible in all their density of signification.
2.1. Pandor~ (at the story's end) corresponds to the pub of the sacri·
ficcd ox (at the outKt).
!O
Tia~ myth of Prorndla~w in H~siod
2.1.1. She is an inviting gift offered by Zeus to men just as Prometheus
had offered Zeus the inviting portion of the carcass.
2.1.3. She is agastir (Th. 599), a ravening belly that devours the bios, the
staple food that men get by agricultural labour (see WD 374, 704 for
this female voracity). The eatable portion of the ox which Prometheus
set apart for men is likewise placed inside the animal's gastir (here
'stomach'). Gastir means a container, a vessel in which food is cooked
(Ody.uey 18.44-5; Herodotus 4.61); but it also has another semantic
value: Prometheus's deception in hiding all the eatable parts inside the
animal's gastir condemns the human race henceforth to be unable to
live without eating, without filling this 'paunch' which concealed its
appointed diet of sacrificial meat. As slaves for evermore of this hateful,
wretched, baneful gastir - the source of all evils and worries, says
Ody11ey 15.344; 17.286, 474; 18.55 - men themselves are in danger of
becoming 'just like bellies' (Th. 26: 'YfflJ'f'Epot olaP; cf. Epimenides, FVS
1, p. 32 frg. Bl). Pandora embodies physically that 'bitch-belly' charac·
teristic of the human condition, sundered now by Prometheus's trick
from the gods. 'What is there', asks Odysseus, 'bitchier (,hntnon) than
the hateful gastir?' (Od. 7.216). And within Pandora Hermes hides a
lumeos noos, the 'soul of a bitch'.
But the voracity of the female belly is not merely directed towards
food: it is also for sex. In high summer - the Dogdays - women's
hunger for sex erupts in La,civious self-abandon (WD 586-7; cf. Alcacus,
51
Jean-Pierre Vemant
frg. 347.4 Lobcl-Pq:e). ~ · s bneo1 noOI involve, ffttacAlonfU,
'liotpaau',nolastha . . . . . .'
2.2.1. She is !int a dalos. Promethean fire acu as a mare in just the
same way u the portions of the ox and Pandora. It is hidden from view
inlide a fennel-stalk, the interior of which UI not damp but dry and
6brous and bums in secret. Put inside the hollow fennel (lP ,c,ofAlt,
l'Ctp6JJIU: Th. 567; WD 53), the stolen fire is concealed within• green
pbnt curled in the huld. But unlike heavenly fire, Promethean fire is a
hunpy fire: it dies whm not fed. It is also an engendered fire: to light
it you need a fire·'tced', lilr.c the one Promethcw hid in the fennel. jwt
u the (.-mer hides the com-seed in the belly of the earth, and the bu,-
band his seed in the belly of his wife.
2.J. Pandora corresponds to bios, the staple which U\11 'hides' alons
with hlS heavenly fire; just u Promethcu1 hid meat in the g,utir of the
ox, and the seed of stolen rll'C in the fennel-ttalk. The belly ol the
woman, which man must till in order 10 implant hil seed if he wutl
children, is like the belly of the earth whicb. man nnalt till if he wanLI
com - because Zcu1 has hiddal bio, wilhin it. Plato ohlcrvc1 that
52
Th, myth of Prom,th,w in H,liod
woman imitates the earth in pn,gnancy and childbinh (Memxmus
2!8a). Moreover, 'Pandora', All-gi.fts', is one of the names of Earth,
1
because, we are told, she freely grants us all that is needful for life. That
is why she is called zndoros, fruitful; and why another of her names is
Anisidora, 'she who Knds gifts up from below' (Scholiast on Aris-
tophanes, Birds 972, p. 229 Dindorf [4.3]; Hesychius and Etymo-
loficon .lf.,..um s.v. '.A."'1at6wpa [1,5096, Latte;p.108.31 Gaisford]).
This l'Olc of Pandora-Ancsidora as the giver of good things hidden in
the earth is emphasized in painting and sculpture: her fruitfulness is no
longer due to the spontaneous bountifulncu of the 'obliging fruitful
earth' (t•l&.ip~ lipovpa odwo,.ani: WD 117-18) as in the golden age,
but a fruitfulness which demands now agricultural labour, toil {Panos),
ploughed fields (fffG), At Phlius, near Corinth, the title Ancsidora was
given to Demeter, in association with Ge, Earth (Pausanias 1.31.2).
Marriage, which entered human life with Pandora, is of coune a sort of
ploughing in which the woman is the furrow (a,oura) and the man the
ploughman (arotff). At this level, the female belly adds to its appetitive
and sexual meanings (what the belly docs in consumption and consum-
mation) an association, linked fundamentally to marriage, with the pro-
creation of children and the production of grain - what the female
belly first hides and then brings forth; and which cannot be produced
except by way of this belly, which first 'hides' it.
It will be clear, despite the limitation of this analysis to the major
aspecu of the myth, that the grammar of the narrative (the logic of the
actions) and the semantic content arc closely linked. The narrative logic
operates by a process of inverted equation: for the gods in their dealings
with men, both "giving' and 'not-giving' = 'hlding'. The grammar of the
narrative also has a semantic function: for men good things arc hidden
in ills; and ills arc either concealed within goods, or else invisible. The
entire system of semantic relations is articulated about the same theme,
which is illustrated and developed at several levels and in numerous
directions by the network of correspondences. Their interaction gives
substance to the underlying idea that, beneath all its forms and in all its
divenc aspects, human life is set thanks to divine 'concealment' in a
world of good and evil mixed, of ambiguity, of doubleness.
56
4. Sacrificial and alimentary codes in
Hesiod's myth of Prometheus
Jnn-Pltm: Vtmanl (1977)
The significance of Greek sacrifice is defined for us in one particular
myth: 1£ we push the analysis far enough, the myth suggests an undcr-
standmg both of the structure of ideas upon which the sacrificial ritual
is based, and of the enormous range of evocations it carried. In one
episode o~ the The.ogony, parts of which arc picked up in Works and
Days, Hcs10d dcscnbcs how Prometheus set himself up as Zeus's rival,
and how he tried by trickery, lies and deception to attain his own ends
by thwarting those of the King of the Gods. The first outcome of this
battle of wits between Titan and Olympian was the ritual distribution
of those parts of the sacrificed domestic animal - here a large ox
supplied, killed and dismembered by Prometheus - which were assigned
on the one hand to men, and on the other to the gods: to the fint, the
meat and the entrails thick with fat - everything one can cat; to the
second, the bare bones burned on the fire with a little fat and aromatic
spices at the sacrificial altars. 1 The a.etiological value of this sequence in
the myth is explicitly stressed by the text: 'And thus it is that the race
of men upon earth bum white bones to the immortal gods upon fragrant
altars' (lines 555-6), and has been rccognlZed by most commentaton.
But only the narrowest implications have been elicited. Almost
always it is undentood as an explanation of a particular, indeed minor,
aspect of the ritual, ~ a response to a kind of paradox supposedly
presented to the religious consciousness of the Greeks by a detail in
the blood sacrifice (which was also a meal) that later became incompre-
hensible. Sacrifice was supposedly an offering bestowed upon the gods
to pay them honour and to gain their favour; how then to explain that
it was not the best morsels that were set aside for them, but the parts of
the animal that were inedible - the junk, as it were? But to confine the
significance of the first part of the text to this one point is simply to
condemn oneself to supposing that it is more or less gratuitous, and to
misunderstand the links between it and the following sections which
give the myth its meaning as a whole. If the fiBU:re of Prometheus, _his
ri\"alry with Zeus, his fmal come-uppancc, the cnllrc talc told by Hesiod
in the long passage of the Theogony whi_ch deals _with the children ?f
lapctus (507-616), only deals with sacnficc entirely by the way, m
passing, then we ha,·c to admit that Hesiod's choi« of Prometheus is
57
jean-Pierre Vemant
pretty arbitrary. Prometheus would have been made respon.sible for_a
ycrifidal ritual whose ~liptlfK"Ulct' Hesiod h2d no Ink~ UI
ttYealing by placing it within a complex theologicaJ ~yst~; h e ~
only have wanted to find an ad hoc explanation by inventing a fairy·
story, as one makes up a fib to justify oneself after the event.
On this view what relation could there pouibly be between the first
act in the Prome,theus saga and those which follow it in Hesiod's ~nion;
between the cutting up of the ox and the ritual allocation of its parts
on the one hand, and on the other, the theft of fire ( Act the Second)
and the creation of the first woman (which concludes the dltmal
dnma)? He1iod must have bundled together into the same tu.t quite
disparate elements; quite artificially have attached to the tnditional
theme of the theft of fire an utiological myth desiped to account for
what seemed to him peculiar about sacrificial ritual, and off the top of
his head a tanadiddle about the origin of women that betrays his own
private antifeminist 'philosophy'. It would then be quite a.s vain to hunt
in the myth for a coherence which does not exist as to expect to derive
from it some und~tanding of the nature and function of sacrifice.
But this will no longer do. Fint, because it stems from a view of
mythical habits of thought which belongs to the past. But more precisely
- more concretely too - because the text contradict, it at every tum.
Hans Schwilhl (1966: 73-85) has shown that even at the formal level
the Prometheus episode follows in its mode of composition ttrict rules
which give the whole an undeniable unity, give it a strictly logical and
unified character. This coherence is equally marked at the nanative
level: Hetiod underscore, in the logical relationship between the epi·
sades the perfect continuity of the account, and mak.es quite evident
the necessary dependence: of each episode upon the one that precedes
it, It is because Zeus never forgets for an instant the deception or which
Prometheus has been guilty in granting men the meat from the sacrificed
animal (Th. 562), that he determints henceforth to deny men hi.a
(heavenly) fire. And it is because he catches sight of the fire sc:cretly
stolen by the Titan (Th. 569) merrily blazing on earth, that in return
for this new gift-by-deception that men enjoy he offen lhmi for his
part the third and final gift·by·deception: the fint woman, 'fire't
counter-gift' (Th. 570). The action proceeds accordin& to an impeccable
logic from start to finish, to conttitute a drama whote succcu.ive suces
ta.kc their strictly necc:saary places in I.he narra1ive tequmce. Flflally, I
have shown in the previous study (above, p. 50-3) that on the: sematitic
level there is a dense structure of 1ymbolic relations between the thane,
employed in each section of the story of Prometru'us: lD the unfoJdin1
of the narrative, each event is linked with others; and by the end, they
constitute: u a whole a coherent coraposition whose every constituent
58
SacnJicial and aliment•,y codes in Hesiod
put is related in a quite strict manner to every other. At the diachronic
lev~I?'. the accou~t, the episode of the theft of fire has a mediating
r61e: 1t is through lt, and by means of it, that the link is made between
the first se~ti~n (the ~eception, dolos, of Prometheus in the assignment
ol th< sacnficial portions) and th, last (th• de«ption, dolos, ol Zeus in
assigning to men the first woman). Again, it is through it that the
revcna.1 of the activity and of the relative position of the acton takes
place: in the fint episode, the initiative, the deception, is Prometheus's
- ~eus appe~ _to be tricked, 3 men receive from the Titan the gifts in
which they reJotce; after the theft of fire,just the reverse: the initiative,
the deception, become Zeus's - it is now he who 'gives' to men, but the
happiness men experience at receiving the divine gift is nothing else
than the trap in which they lll"C' about to be ta.ken, and indeed, in a
wider sense, the symbol of mortal man's misery.
From this perspective, the final episode is simply the inevitable con-
sequence of those which came before. Here, as in a mirror, are reflected,
arranged and ordered all the earlier events; through it, they illuminate
each other to ta.kc on their true significance which can only be revealed
at the very end. The 'trap' that is woman has then to make its entrance
before the true nature of Prometheus's 'trap' for Zeus can be finally
understood - when the Titan 'fiddles' the portions of the sacrificial
animal so as to bestow upon men the benefit of all the meat: the good
part, upon which men congratulate themselves (as they congratulate
themselves on the 'beautiful evil' that Zeus bestows upon them in the
penon of the Woman), turns out in reality to be the bad. The petard
set by Prometheus to hoist Zeus devastates mortal men as it blows up in
his facei and fire itself, which Prometheus stole, for all its benefits, is a
gift no less ambiguous than the first female human-being - all decked
in perilous allure.,
These sequences arc too intimately related within the narrative tex-
ture, and their symbolic values too overlapped, for it to be possible to
isolate them and treat them separately. We must take the myth for
what it is, not an assemblage of disparate episodes but a single story;
and understand that in this coherent whole the relationship linking
blood sacrifice Prometheus's fire and the creation of woman can be the
result neither ~f serendipity nor of an author's whimsy: they arc neccs·
sary, necessary in the sense that they are of the. very essence of t~e
myth and fulfil the function Hesiod assigns them m the context of h11
Tllrogony. All lhrough the struggle betwee~ Tit~'s supple _cunn~g ~d
the unbending intel.nce of Zeus what 1s ulumately at issue 1s this:
the rules which define man's estate, the mode of life appropriate for
men now. The ritual of sacrifice is presented as the initial consequence
and as the most immediate expression of the gulf opened between gods
59
Jea.h.·ficrr.c Vernant -t ;r
and men on the day tl\at fr()mcthcu-s cntt'tcd upon his.rebellious Cbunc,
Tfic m) th links sacr1 ice to primc\.,l even\) "'·hich have made men whilt
they arc-,.dp~mc~ 10 duth,' dweifi..ng upOrl the cartb,J ,trou~lcd bf .•lls
w.ir,hout nUnJbct, • C41ting b.ulc\ tpm ~Ne field ~h'Cy work. d_":dhng
'With fcma1'C' sp"lucs.1 aJJ ,n alt,- tri~c -of ,crtaturn utterly cv.J. ~ff
1
fr'om tb_osc, ~o whdat: iq tbc!b~ping-fhcy_t,rcre- yet so f.}osc, Liv1'1g .U
they did iJ} ,<:Q,mn\cnsa.Utx with tJ'frm, ,11tun at the ,am~ µ.bks- Mlcl
sh~i>g 1'1C' same.., ft:iit.s• L th $ SJcss•d lmnfort:Us, ~ ~ho d"'·tll ,i~
hu,J!·n, nourishc e ambrofo, ..up, to ;)\'bor&_ I.here now waft.s .the Jmok•
o(bl,l.mt-orfcriogs . t The sat fi~~~pisode i1 neither se_s:y ndary nor an
aftcrtH.b_u ·~11 lt ijcs at the _CC&Qt?t .?' ft\(-q,tth. {t1~ nothmjftO d"p Wilh
'cxplain!llg' an oqsLdctail n). lhc ni,µa.1, that ban.es '1cre bumr:,b) p9mt-
ing oµt the dirferfncc h«"twccb t ost:- prut1Qns thcn·l=d in ncrificc for
the goQs 1-!ld th~(' for men. i~.thig~li8,htl the ~1f_ W:hid1 ~ver after
~paritcs 1hem + lbc fac i'h t t~Cy belong~ h Q, d,IDncr-tritJcs.,Jun
as the carlic.r ~lo! iic s w d,P'l'.tisc in my.th b) meaSu (>f't ~c inta,gc of
:i. cpmmynit 1of ba.nquctca fca..1UnR tpg"U{_cr. to sq>arauon now IS
mark.ec!..b.y tl1c c~nlTjl.St b"t\V"fCO'\\\'O( alimcntll)·"Tnodes. The opposi1ion
!x:.t:wem i.hcic ro.nns is' writW\ Q ~ ncii\- hC~rt' _ tfic rituaJiand }C.l
the...ritual is a means or ·c r~ttng a link-, mmuni~non. hctwc(n the
S'undc'tcd tri~s - it tritt, )o. (a.,;l.fj_t"-c;an, t> build:.a, bridge £rpm c:,vth
tOt1i.ea\TcQ.
'Q\c su.~ect of~lct 's ro~I\Cnt in. tht m.yth tljlt'n;and it rcsonatc_J LJl
0
.
rests fir.ml}' .on thf d rdtoary' stmantic o{ ~c langu.~ of sacnfjco. ,
,,
Tp, ndcrstand th~d fofm of Grcck--p cr1ficc WhiCV_·nfq:l~~d lfi~ c~~ing qf
meat, one has th<.n tr takli f\esidd's ~fcoll.(ll cnui;t~~ J~mwsl}: \\.c nru,t
study he tc,xt ~-lo~y, without as um g,Y,1t an ·thing 1, non-J1gn1~c~nt.
And we myst c.ompar~ the t o \~ io1 ~ in i,hl_ Tlrcqg9f"Y and m the
Works apd DaJs, ta~ng not Of <\gtcemcnts and d1,c11cne1~_._ .
firs fall, ·,,rha.t. iS' t.h~ context g( the Prometheus epiaodc m each
poem? Ap~ ~O'i da,:s th~ cq_l\J.~x fid.p;.10 elucidate the status of th.c
ritua;l? For the Tlu;o(<J"Y.- t,here 1s nP, d1£fic.uliy. The work as a whok '.s
de\·ou:;d to tQ.C orjgjnl, the bi'i""th, ut hatJks and .~lie \'kton· or Zeus, hu
fombl s~i{µrc 1 f overcignt)' b : alnj of which he successfully euah·
lis~cs, over ag ·nst the former r~g_,m'- the (qund~t16_}u or a permanently
¥\able au~onty w'hich. c . l)t.v, t f,c. ov~rc:pro or ~h.J.cn. Zai 's
atcc~~on t Q lhc in om ot e~-..~ doe~ no mcc_c l :i.1gniry, as the tcx(
str.cssfs t thrc~ ..scpu~tC poiou. f~~ ~dcri"ng of all things for t~c gods,
a tl,rii.t _di\-is1on ~l~eCI) thc.m ~ l · 'fiO~oiJT$. powe and pTl\,Jcgc~;u
"'ilOng w1t'1 the s6 u:rc1go wfi"o IO)indccf It, this c 1m1c order I to exist
ll)~p((,for.th unchang~d a.J\i) cJriWgibJl
t, a poem in w'hich C\'~r;) thing \ ~ plac:t at the_ ie)·el of t e god\,
:u,ton~ the r>~s.f 1h~ce is nq p)~ for. .\n ac.c oynt.. of the.p rij,'lns qf_ .me,o
in iho ~r9pe,: scn\C· We learn how thC odt came into ing, not J1Jffl. 0
'tht Tlteogtmy (l~s 11,ot a S¥hcthCr Gala, the Ea.r:th. l)o~ them'.,
wh_c,her \J(c.'( wcrt crcatc4 b); Zd"us: jU)d t.l\c immofj.aJs, or whether the)
were born 9£ .th hi ted"'titan/ a ~s. 31 tic; Orphic fr.tdJtjon h\l,d II ,
1
The counterpart in the Works ond Days of the eris which, in the
Theogony, though it uses divine machinery, is essentially concerneci
with, and directed towards, men, is that which takes place in Bnt:(,t1.1
directly between Hesiod and his brother Pencs.
There is a stricter parallelism between the relation of the two text~ to
their context than might appear. In the Theogony, Prometheus's tricker)
oHr the parts of the SiACrificial animal is introduced by ga-, 'for', whkh
links the cpisOlk from which stems man's misfortune directly to the
preceding linc, which concerns the ms of Prometheus against Zeus. In
67
Jcan-Picne Vcmant
the Woris and Days, the _sc<;ond wrsjon o t" thC Promcthe ~n1 stor) afso
begins with afaY-, wttich this time n:fcrs. to thcadm~n 1tto~ which llc~od
tin Just ~ n is broth n~mi,ng the ens ..,.hich scu tlu:m . _ nst
one another. Their ldiros, their family pl,d t j rJind, ha:s been d.iv1<1t~
M1wecn them. This division was not adnt'-cd b _): force. by Qrutc
violence , as when one takes pou«.ion of cncn'l.) .bo.o \y in w;u. r,,;onc-
thclcn . it did RO( tak.C place by -ig6:Cit).l-J\ft)ClW gi the {W(,S ~rothcrt,
by a fric-ndly arr.u:iJt,mqi1 ..-~ iu.hould. In ot,dC' ,o DbJ.aii:r_ rn~rc th~
?is shatc~ ft r~s )lad stirrc4 up rancorou! qu~ _nc1lt( 4 "f.W.. dn1n: rt~
33). He hid takp:i t._hc m"at..tcno. arbiltauon br tb~roJers< of lhc1p1tt, in
principle tM cc"f)rgcptath·es o1 Olympian Zc\U.'s a)l~ ito~·ju~ti~. But
the rulers were- f\l.bprtu:.d: and gave judgement ~!Jtui JUshce. They
haudr:<i.a.own a qpQ k.c vcrdlct , a ptejirdj~e(j 6pin.icm : Tak.in.g the si4,e
that lllC:k'c..d justice, they apponioned the lcUJQ) .1a.e.qu~j~: , granting the
Pl e much of what bclonaed to the o ther. M shu ttfe displayed that
µme spirit or partiality wit h which Zcllt; ~J pjcalL-; rcprb¥he.d
Pro~lhc\ls in 1he n~101ty. There t6trtls t o to 'b t::_i .i;~~ an.a.loS)-·
et\Y.ecn the 1wo situations, divine and hl.l ~ n r wl:).*ti int.r.odUc,: in c.ach
poem the myth or Prometheus, with its b,.rih irnW,cation~ for IJl~rta1
men. Moreover, Hesiod don not sjfnply· c;mind his r othfr of t~
grievous wrangle he had provoked, o r th.e fia4c;iuknl divt.rif.!"I he h.id.
cleverly obtained at Hetiod's hptQ.st: Pc: enlarg thc.JJ 1(icant( o
the private. quUTel to univeru.1 justice and 9rdt.r; he. ma\CS il the.p 1s
for what one might wcU caU a veritable .ti ol or nu .-:-irl.ymuch .u
the firstborn daughter of Night intp'resSq":ill h_"rpan existcnc.e,withJttr'
seal. And thl, theology, right at the ~ginni.na .9( U'od:) anf/ Days ,
co ntains an cx.plicit allusion to the ;T,hp,,gQn Qr/. C subject cJf int,
which is he.re taken up and specified.
To the cods there might appear to b ~ Ot\lY one ~ind o! eris -:, the
Immortals ~ew only that viole nt ~ [ ( cfutihg which ;lt'u,1
t11umphdij 1.1vti'h' rJv~~d w}iiCrh his vietOr)'$il.Used t~ bctqme .extinct
in the divine ~rtd.11- Sul al ~tte level of IT1.lJlklnd, ~hU)gr iU'C q\fl.JC
dirferent. There is thtre. not pne ffls but two! ,a.nd this bi v..rcr t1on <:i£
the daughter of Nrghf cbp:l:spPn to 'lw: 1,QYercJg'} po'1,C;r O\CI" J'TICn's
lives, to h_er continl©lU pr se.nc~ in and for tl)C gd6d as well u in and
fQt rhe worse. In hCJ" 4ouble.., bifur""cft~d ,..a.,-ablguous form t'nS has ,ww
two-a.spt..ets jpJt a th<=rt arc two kituh of wick7 d division b,ctwecn men:
war·aga.iJ»t an t.n.emy (r9.m without, on e. b~trltfitld .. and fa1.:tion
IUlln a silJ.Slc ¢mm\lnity, in the Pl.;lf\lk' plil.Ce orasscrri\>ly (WD 29 .u,d
3Ql, 1'.ht. firsr reliu on forte of arms, the se.t:on4 employs the tani{UC!
md lri lfy dcvio~socu (lt:D 321 - 2, with an Op\)-0 tion . tween xcpq,
fJlv "Qd q,tO t'twoq~). But whcd\cr they use viole.1'1cc or dcceu, both
have the s~~ ob·c~t, to grab t)ooty 1 fo n,Ue pnesclf~ch a\ tm .cxpcnMl
}
Sacrificial and alimentary codes in Hesiod
of another by takins from him what belonp to him. lll-sotten pins do
not last. Zcu1 him1elf make, halte to pay the guilty the Brim ·reward of
their crimea (WD 325-6, 333--4), just u he crushed the brute violence
of the Titans, and u he punished the crooked trickery of Prometheus.
This wicked ms, extinct unong gods, punished unong monals, men do
not love. And, Hesiod goes on, if they do honour it, it is against their
will, under con,traint of the decisions of the Immortals (WD 15).
But before she gave birth to this rancorous ms, which the will of the
gods has given men against their will to be their companion, Night bore
another, similar, but of different disposition, whose praise the wise man
should sing. It is she who stin, by emulation, every man who secs
prosperity abounding in the fields and in the house of a neighbour whose
application to hard agricultural toil is greater than his. This eris of
competition, of energetic rivalry in work, Zeus, sat on high in the
lambent aether, has established below u the foundation for all well·
gotten pin. He has set her in the roots of the earth (gaii: WD 18-19,
with the opposition aUMp, Mllw1,1 - "Y<l6,( Ell ptr,,a,), where men li\o·e
and from which they draw their sustenance. The Son of Cronus desired
that by means of this eris they should find the path to wealth in accord·
ancc with the order instituted by himself. There is then no way in
which men can escape eris, to whom their whole lives arc subject: they
may only choose the good rather than the evil one. It is not by bandy·
ing words in the agora, listening to disputes and avoiding work in the
fields (ap' n,ou: 28), that Perses can hope to set himself on the path to
succeu. To earn the means of life (bios), the fruit of Demeter
(Dimitnos akti: 31-2), which Gaia bestows on men in plenty when
she is worked, a man has to get down to it, water his furrows with the
sweat of his brow, compete with someone else in toil. How could it be
otherwise? Zeus exacts a harsh penalty for profits which are the fruit
of violence or trickery by means of wicked en's; and the goods that he
has granted to men, the wealth that gives them life (bios) and which is
hidden in the earth, he docs not wish that they should be able to gain
without labour (A:ai urgon eonta: 44), without appealing to good eris.
That might have been the case once, in the Age of Gold, when the earth
hcnclf, without having to be turned or seeded, caused the life-giving
can to sprout in such profusion that plunder, nor theft in the dark, nor
competition in work - no sort of eris - had any place here on earth
any more than in heaven. Man could live and cat without lifting a
rmgcr.2 1 But the gods hid the means of life from ~en; the?' sunk it
deep in the soil on the day that Zeus found himself tncked by
Prometheus Crookedthought. And since that day human life has been
what we KC: the victim of a twofold strugle, endlessly pulled between
each. now merciles1ly punithed by the gods if one follow, the wone to
69
Sacrificial and alimtntary cotus in Hesiod
and men because it implies for each a 1harply different kind of nourish-
ment. How then can it be that in the WorAs and Days Hcti.od makes no
specifac reference to this act of division which founded the ritual and
Mt only instituted the Fall but continues to symbolize, in its double
character of rcligioa1 ritual and form of consumption of food, the
11nbiguity of a humanity linked with the gods in cult but separated
from them by the miafonune and misery stemming from the portion of
sacrificial meat which men alone may consume?
In point of fact the alimentary aspect of the myth of Prometheus is
no less in evidence in the Worb and Days than in the Thtogony. The
theme of a kind of food reserved for men and intimately linked to their
specific kind of existence is central in each account. It is simply that
the theme is displaced. And that displacement, which is intelligible if
we take account of the difference in penpcctive between the two texts,
illuminates some essential aspects of the myth, in relation to sacrifice.
In the Works and Days it is the products of the cultivation of the earth,
Demeter's com, ccreal..c;onsumption, which have a status analogous to
that of the ox which is sacrific"d, the ponions of meat and meat-eating
in the Tlaeogony. The interest of the author of the Erga (that is,
.A.gricultt,ral WorlcH) is in maJ) as cultivator. Man is understood and
fint defined as 'cater of bread'. The interest of the author of the
Tluotony is in man undentood from the penpectivc of the gods: man
is defined as one who consumes that portion of the sacrificial victim
offered to the gods which is ritually reserved to him. But in each cue
human consumption of food is marked by Prometheus's eris. Ever since
Zeus hid away the food that keeps him alive (bios), man can only cat
bread if he has paid the price in labour, if he has won it by the sweat of
his brow. Cereal food can be had only by dint of rivalry in labour, and
it recalb the Titan's spirit of rivalry no less than docs the sacrificial
animal. Be1idcs, it is not that the grain was simply iuelf hidden during
the struggle with Zeus: that alteration of status, by which food was
made to disappear beneath the earth whereas previously anyone could
make use of it freely, constitutes Zeus's response to Prometheus's trick
in concealing beneath the ox's hide the edible portions of the victim, so
as to give them to men (WD 47-8). The cultivation of cereals is thus
the countcrpm of sacrificial ritual, its inverse. For henceforth, thank!I
to Prometheus's trick, men have the ox's meat to eatj and, thanks to
Zeus's will, they will no longer have within easy reach, at their crn,1
convenience, the com they must have to live.
Again, just like the sacrificial victim, cereals are eaten at the end_ of a
negotiation conducted with the gods. The caring_ of _com ~tab!1sh_es
between men and gods a form of ritual commumcauon while, m its
very essence, it undcncorcs the tcparation, the distance, the disparity
71
Jean-Piare Vemant
between their statuses. For Hesiod to cultivate the earth for com is a
uue cult which t h e ~ thcpowal that~ (V..-.c, 1971:
2.19-20'; Detienne, 196!: 54-51). For him, work is a tort of M,
o£fice, careful to perform every wk at ~e appropriate m~ent and
respectful of traditional forms. If the fumer'1 ham ii stocked ~th tom,
iC he hu bread enough and to spare, it is the reMlh of a labon~s and
suictly regulated life whose punctiliousness hu been rewarded ntully
by his becoming dear to the Ble11ed Ones, by his becomina: a kinsman, a
pAilos, of Demeter (WD 500-1, 309: l«U' tPlGf6,ae'MN. .-o).U ~').npot
6t8cndT'Ocon•; 826-8). But to become a friend, a k.intman of the gods
and to escape limos, huncer, presupposes that he recognizes and has
accepted by his life of labour the harsh fiat of the fielcb (WD 388:
•dlw• ,6pol;) ordained by Zeus, that marks with the passing of the
Aac of Gold the loss of that time when men grew not old, and d~lt in
ignorance of hardship and toil, feasting with the gods. To eat com
implies that if he is to avoid hunger man, poor child of eris, can only
devote himself heart and soul to grinding work, to ponos, that stcond
child of nis (TII. 226-7: Eris gives birth to Panos and Lim0$). To
tseapc tht tvil born of ffll, he must pus by its brother.
Ont final point of similarity. I havt argutd that, in the logic of the
myth, all tht edible parts of tht sacrificial victim come to men, HC&UK
these pieces of dead meat, which satisfy man's endleuly demandi.n1
hunger and rc1tore his strength that without nourishment would con·
1ume away, constitutt the proper food of fully monal creatures, whose
life-force is not, like that or thC' gods, Free frorn any taint of thC' negative
but uncertain, unstable, unsettled, pttjudFd to death. Now the very
expttnion bios (life), used by Hesiod to refer to tM ear of com which
is man's specific food, stretsCs a relationship betw«n CC'l'C'al-catintt: and
thC' life-force typical of man which is so close that we mif!:ht 1ptak. of
consubstantia.lity: tht fabric of man's lifC' is woven of thC' sunC' material
u thC' food which sustains it. It is 'because they do not C'at bread' thas
the gods arc not monal; innocent orbartty, ftd on ambrosia, they have
no blood.,. The icAOr in them has no inegularities of flow, no falls in
pressure, no ups and downs, which are for men the stipnata, • it Wffl',
of their cphemerality, adumbrations of thC' death which C'&tin& can only
stave off. In the Iliad there is a formula dcscribing human-belftll (21.
464-5),
Mm nowWi oe. the rtpc •hnt ol t u ~
1ben Uli 1Piridca 1p they ,.. .c and 6. (tr. fitqaald.)
To pick up the txpression or the Odyssey, barlty and wheat, the food
of mtn, ma.kt up the mwfos ndrcin, the manow of men, W YffY aub-
stancc of thcirlirefortt(Od. 2.290 and 20.180: lil.._,TG, .,>..Oii' ""'4pW•)..
Sa.cnficial and alimmta.ry cocks in Hniod
By mcan1 or these relationships and correspondences, which are 10
dearly marked, the myth o( Prometheus connects sacrifice closely with
the cultivation of com. It presents them u phenomena or two dif-
ferent types which arc yet interrelated and have the same value. This
relationship is ma.de clear by the explicit indications in the text which I
have noted; but perhaps even more strikingly in what the text docs not
say, in its silence. The disconcertingly abrupt allusion in the Works and
Days to Zeus 'hiding bio.s away' would be absurd, inept, incomprehen-
sible i£ the text did not presuppose, written as it were tacitly into the
myth-frame, a positional symmetry, a complete complementarity,
between bio.s-by-com and the sacrificial victim. The ritual of sacrifice
plays the same rble in relation to meat-eating as the cultivation of com
in relation to the eating of plants. In that case, the existence of an
episode linking Prometheus's trickery at the sacrifice to the necessity of
working the land in order to obtain the bios on which men subsist has
no need of any justification other than its mere presence in the text.
Moreover, the ox killed and dismembered by Prometheus, at the fint
sacrifice, is the domestic animal which is closest to man, most nearly
inkgrated into his sphere, above all when yoked to the plough to cut
the furrows. As such, it occupies the opposite pole to the wild animals
which men hunt like enemies and do not sacrifice. The ox is sacrificed
in principle with its own consent, as an animal which. by virtue of its
closenen to man, is able if not to represent him directly at least to offer
itself as a son of delegate. The otherness of wild animals in relation to
the world of men is revealed puticularly in what they cat: they cat one
another, without rules or restrictions. and without keeping back any
part of the prey they consume for the gods. Their world knows no
other laws than appetite. Indifferent to justice and to ritual. the act of
eating on the part of animals cannot reflect, either in its modes or in its
technique, a divine order on high: it expresses merely the relations of
naked violence in that internecine war upon which wild animals arc
engaged in order to cat (WD 276-80).
What the ox is to wild animals, com in tum is to wild plants. Of all
the fruits of the earth, it is the most humanized. Wild plants grow by
themselves, wherever conditions arc favourable. Wheat can only be
harvested at the end of a year of careful attention, rather as one
educates children to tum them into men.JS In the harvest the interplay
of human effort and divine blessing produces an equilibrium of regular
exchanges. Non-carnivorous animals feed off the plants whi.ch nat~ue
produces without cultivation, off the wild grass and vegetation which
grows outside the fields and orchards worked by the hand of mci:i,
beyond the ,phcrc of the domestic (Detienne, .1~~7: l~-1~). Bread is
peculiar to man; the mark and guarantor of c1vd1zed hfe, It separates
73
Jean-Pierre Vcmant
mankind from the animab, and from the 1ods. Men live on cultivated
domestic plants and ~ n t i c anhhla. Thele two com.pie·
mcntary aspects or human diet, locatin~ u they do ~c hurnut·~,
midway between animals and gods, which arc two kmdt of bcmp
simultaneously distanced from yet near to men, c~lish !he l~ner in
this median status which defines their proper cond1uon (Vidal-Naquet,
PPp::;: 0
1b;: i:)~ow easier to understand the full implications or the
link ntablished in the myth between the theft 0£ rue and the division
of the sacrificial victim on the one hand, and the hiding of grain in the
earth on the other. According to the Th~ogony, it is bcca\llC he is
constantly mindful of the trick played on him by PromcthC"m in allo·
eating the portions in such a way as to bestow on men all the edible
paru, that Zeus decides no longer to provide them (011A: edid,o11, 563)
with his celestial fire, the lightning, that they had previously enjoyed,
and which had been freely available from ash-trees so long u they dwelt
and feasted together with the gods.
Why this response? What docs it signify? Obviously Zeus wiahcs fint
of all to prevent men rrom making use of the gift which men have
received after the first round. By depriving them of fire, he prevents
them rrom cooking the meat, which thq could not cat raw. So the pri·
mary value of Prometheus's rue is alimentary. The Titan's ruse in
hiding fire, concealing it within a fcnncl ..talk to carry it off to men, is
intended to providc them with the means of sacrificial cookins. But to
cook meat before eating it UI by that very act to point up the contrast
with animals, who cat raw flesh, The culinuy fire of Hesiod's
Prometheus thus has a quite general significance: it rt:pretcnts culturc in
opposition to primitiveness. In that sen.c it adumbrates lhe theme or
'eivilizin1' fire, 'master or all artl ', dcvcloped in Aeschylus's Pro~thftu
Bound (110-11 and 254). But thc adumbration is idio1yncratic. wath
all the additional complexities and ambiguities dC'muided in the myth
by the median status of humanity.
Prometheus's fire ii not that or the gods, ii not the fire of heaven,
the lightning omnipotcnt in the hands or Zeus, immortal• its muter.
It can perish: it is cngiaulcrcd, l'ows hunsrv, rattcn, like .U mortal
creatures. To produce fire one must have a seed, prt:sctffd in the uhct
or curled insidC' a fennel-stalk as was Promctheu1'1.1t For it to stay
alive, it must be fed; it dies ir not rucllcd.,, Fire's unquenchable peed,
which cause, it to con1umc all that falls into its path, mU.a it like a
wild beast, u several formular in Homer already augcst (sce p. 76
below, and Gru, 1965: 108-16, 183-93). Or would, if, DAN in-the
hands of man whose mastery it ensures, it weft not at tbe SUM tir.e
dome1ticated. This cultural aspect, which is equal and oppolitc tQ the
74
Sacnficial antl alimmtllf')' code, in H11iod
unleuhing of a violent, animal nature, is dearly apparent in Prometheu1's
fire, associated as it is with clever artifice, subtle invention. No mere
conaequence of a cunning which eluded Zeus's sharp eyes and made it
po11ible for men to have what god denied, it involves a technique for
ttansporting fire, kcepin1 it alight and starting it afresh, an aspect of the
knowledge indiopensablc for human life.
But the tecl&nai at the disposal of men are quite as ambiguous as the
Titan who made them available. Fire is a dolos, a tricky ruse, a uap,
directed from.the outset against Zeus. It allows itself to be taken, but
may on occasion tum against men, not merely because the 'might of
unwearying fire' is possessed of a power within, which passes human
control, but, more precisely still, because this might is somehow
mysterious, has something of the supernatural in it: its name is
Hephaestus, after the god. And this quality adds a new dimension to
what I have just said about the animal world and the acquisition of
human civilization. 11 Fire exists in three different modes, animal,
human and divine, and it can therefore act, at the very centre of sacri-
fice, as a mediator. When it is lighted on the altu, it docs not merely
pass between euth and heaven in its ascent to the gods with the burden
of sweetsmclling smoke. It completes Prometheus's act of division
because it separates, by the act of cooking, what is simply roasted or
boiled, and which belongs to man, from what is entirely consumed
away and, together with the animal's life itself, restored to the world
beyond. In eating what has not been tumcd into ashes, but simply
cooked - that is, softened and made tender to allow it more easily to
be digested by weak human bodies - men retain only, as it were, the
sacrificial left-oven, the gristle from a divine feut in which what really
matters can only be had by being consumed entirely, caused to dis-
appear utterly from this world below, devoured in the roar of the flames.
The Wor4s and Days introduces the episode of the theft of fire in an
allusi"e, abrupt and apparently illogical manner. Hesiod explains to
Pcncs that 'the gods have hidden from men the means to life (bios). lf
they had not you could live without lifting a finger, without work. But
Zeus hid your bios away when he found himself tricked by Prometheus.
Ever since, he has ensured harsh cares for men; he hid the fire from
them.' One might be puzzled about the rOle of fire here if we did not
already know, from the Theogony, that Zeus's refusal of the gift of fire
was grounded in Prometheus's trick over the portions of the sacrifice.
But the Kqucnce still seems quite incoherent. The fact that Zeus was
mgry at being duped by the Titan is used to justify the necessity of
agricultural work.. Furious at allowing himself to be caught out, he
hides the means to life by sinking com into the earth. In the context,
'hiding fire' seems quite gratuitous, without any intelligible relation to
what come, before. Unless there were, in archaic Greece, so intim<llc
and evident a relation between hiding bios and hiding fire that the one
has to go with the other.
Ut w note first that in the beginning the same situation held for
both fire and grain. In the Age of Gold, before the sundering of gods
from men, that is before what happened at MCkOne, barley and fire
were both d.ittctly and oixnly available to men. The latter used them as
77
jt"an-Pierre Vt"mant
'natural' goods bestowed ~ them, with no aced to .hWlt for _tht"m,
the olljec:IO neither of,Wf•lll;. que,t, For th• gods. ~ ~ a n d
fire means, in a material sense, that com has fint lo be buned, h ~ ..
in the ground in the form of seed to u to gnminate and then npt"n
above ground. n And that fire bu to be buried, hidden in the ashes or
in a fennel-stalk, in the form of seed. to shoot up and then dance.on the
hearth. Morally and metaphysically, it means that these two k1ncb of
good hitherto na.tunlly at the free dil)>Olition of men must henceforth
be gotten, striven after, paid for; will be accessible _on!y through t~e
integument of evils in which they are shut; through gnndin1 effort, toil,
unccasin1 attention and reflection. Such evils, the necessary counter·
part of blessings formerly dispensed with an open hand, tum barley and
fire into the victories of human civilization rather than I.he natural
products they once were.
Ap.in, com and more generally all cultivated plants were opposed by
the Grcelr.1 to wild plants as the cooked against the nw (Detienne,
1977: 11-14). There arc two upccts of this cookin1. Species of plants
which lend themselves to being cultivated arc those in which the process
of internal 'coolr.in1' goes funher than is the case with the wild species,
where the raw humoun predominate. In addition, the intervention of
man, in opening and turning the soil to that the sun may penetrate,
allows a still further improved and elaborate cooklng of domesticated
plants. And to thil double cooking, the one natural, the other achieved
by cultivation, we may add a third, which brinp thC" process to com-
pletion: by transmutin1 flour into bread md pancake, oven-cookery
makes com fully digestible. It cuts the last link with nature and the
raw, a link which made flour a hybrid, a muddle:, neither raw nor
cooked, nc:ither wild nor civilized. Once out of the oven, bread hu
bc:come somethin1 quite different: it is now sitos, human food,ju,t u,
once roast or boiled, a lump or raw, bloody meat i, trammuted into a
civilized dish.M
Now in the: Age of Gold earth spontaneously be1towcd on men
products which possc:.c:d naturally all the chuactcristics and qualitic1
of cultivated planu. The1e producll grew already couked, u though the
soil, albeit unworked., had been cultivated and tumcd by the ploup.
They were moreover eatable at once; they did not have to be: tram-
muted and humanized by the action of rltC' in coollin1. The AF or
Gold has nothing to do with the opposition between uv•ry and
civilization: it cancels their difference by prc1enting civilized food as
the spontmeous product of nature, which man once upon a time found
without UIY bother, already cultivated, haive1ted, cooked and 11tady r01
eatin1. ln thil respect, the com-harwsts of the Age of Gold an like the
meat-harvests of the blcslCd Echiopians, which, a«ording to HerodoNI,
78
Sacrijicud and •limentory codes in Hesiod
they found cloac by the Table of the Sun: each morning, scattered over
the plain which had produced them unaided overnight, the cuts of meat
lay waiting, all carved, served-out and ready-boiled, for their patrons to
com< and din<. They just gr•w there cooked (Herod. 3.18).
The close of the Age of Gold means three things simultaneously: the
necessity of sacrificial fire to cook meat, the necessity of agricultural
labour to cook com, the necessity of cooking-fire to render com fit to
cat. The anger of Zeus, to make men pay for the meat they obtained
from Prometheus, hides both fire and com from them in the selfsame
gesture. 1£ that is all that had taken place at MClc.OnC, men would not
have been able, from that moment, to eat the fruit, now raw, of
domesticated plants, any more than they would have been able, in the
version of the TMopny, to cat uncooked the flesh of domesticated
animals.
Prometheus's trickery did not simply establish, for all time, the rules
for the division of the sacrificial victim. It brought in its train, no less
inevitably, the constraint of labour, of ponos. Henceforth men, that
they may cat as men cat, ue doomed to the cultivation of com as they
arc doomed to cook in the sacrifice.
S. Land and sacrifice in the Odyssey: a study
of religious and mythical meanings
Pierre Vidal·N•quct (1970, 1976)
To/.·P.0-ort
This is an cuay about land. Perhaps paradoxically, l begin with 1omc
details taken not from Homer, but from Hesiod. Contrary to common
opinion, both the 11&cogon)' and the WorAs ...d Doy, can be uKd to
elucidate, not merely works composed after them, but also those which
mtcdatc them or which au more or lets contemporary with them - as
is perhaps the case with the Odyssey.
I believe that the •myth of the races' and the myth 0£ Pandora in the
Wor.U and Days, and the myth of Prometheus in that poem and in the
Thcogony, justify a definition of the human condition which could be
lcrmcd both anthropological and nonnative, both exclusive and inclwW'c.
The exclusion is twofold. Hcsiodic man is the man of the age of iron;
which means in the first place that he is not the man of the age of gold
- the mythical time when mm 'lived like gods', knowing neither old
ll£C nor true death: 'They had all good things, and the grain-giving earth
unforced bore them fruit abundantly and without stint. They pastured
their lands (fp'Y' b4,rowo) in cue and peace, with roany good thinp'
(WD ll2-19). 1 The distinction betw«n the ICC of gold and our own
which I wish to study here - there are othen - is that of work verms
non-work (agricultural work, or course).' As compared with the age of
iron, the age of gold - the age of Cronus - is an absolute model; it is a
condition which the other other ages can never hope to attain. The lot
of tjie race of the• of.1old during their lives is eJ\ioycd by the r~ of
heroes, or at least by some of them, after death: Zeus placn them
'apart from men' (&lx' WpW.wP), and apart from the gods, 'under thr
rul~ of Cr~~~'.. '!!.!h.c.cndi o[ the e~ta· . .'Arid t~ey d~D untouched
by IOrrow in the islands of the Blessed along the shore of the deep
swirling Ocean, _happy heroes for whom the_grain·giving earth bean
honey-sweet fruit Rourishin1 thrice a. ye•.'' The age of gold in 'time'
is succeeded here by an age of gold in 'space', in the islands of the
Blessed, which arc characterized also by the richncu of the earth.
Elsewhere, in the myth of Pandora,• Hesiod 1ummariza in advance
u it were the leuon of the myth of the races: 'Before this the tribes ol
men lived on earth remote and free from ills and hard toil (xa)..rlNNO
80
Land ond ,.,rifiu in tlu Odyssey
........,) and b..vy sickness•• which bring the Kira upon men: for in
mite.,. men grow old quickly' (WD 90-5).'
To have been excluded from the 8F of gold means that man is not a
p.• But he it not an animal either; and the second exclusion bars him
&om llllilo,,/aafit,, cannibolim,: 'For the Son of Cronus has ordained
thil law for men, that fuhes and beasts and winged birds should devour
one another, for Right (diki) is not in them' (WD 276-8). The practice
of dilti ii what enables man to escape from the animal state: man is the
creature which docs not cat its fellows.
The inclusions arc clo1ely related - simultaneously inverse and com-
plementary - to the exclusions. The Worh and Days itself is about the
workin1 of anble land and all that is implied by it - the planting of
trees and the rearing of animals, especially for ploughing. Dilci is a
means of regaining - perhaps not the age of gold, for men are obliged
to labour - but at least prosperity and fruitfulness in humans, land and
flocks: 'The earth gives them (i.e. those who practise di4i) a life of
plenty, and on the mountains the oak bean acorns on high, and in the
midst, bees. Their fleecy sheep ue laden with wool; their women bear
children resembling their fathen. They flourish continually with good
thinp; and do not travel on ships, for the grain-giving earth bean them
fruit' (WD 252-7).'
This human work UI linked in tum to the possession (thanks to
Prometheus) of fire for cooking, that fire which had previously been
concealed by Zeus (WD 47-50; sec Vernant, pp. 74-9 above). In
revenge for the theft of fire, Hephaestus made at Zeus's command
Pandora, who is both earth and woman (WD 59-105).' The hints of
the Worb and Days arc filled out by the Tla~ogony. The qu111Ttl be-
tween gods and men at Mcie.one has two episodes which arc carefully
paralleled.' There UI fint the primordial saaificc of an ox and iu un-
equal division, the gods receiving the smoke and men the flesh: which
rcsultl in the confiscation of fire by Zeus and its theft by Prometheus.
Secondly, men are given the ambiguous girt of woman, to make up for
the gods' acceptance of the state of affain brought about by Prometheus.
Arable land, cooking, sacrifice, sexual and family life within the oi•os
- even, at one extreme, political life - form a complex, no clement of
which can be separated from the othen. These arc the terms which
define man's estate, in between the age of gold and allilophagia.
cannibalism. 10
The limits we find marked out here by Hesiod, with their character-
istic features (which arc also features of the crisis of his period) arc
repeatedly employed d1roughout the subsequent history of Greek
thouatn. From the end of the IUlth century BC in particular, these pat·
terns were taken up in the violent political disputes which divided thc-
81
Pierre Vidal-Naquet
Greek world and led tbeQrUU. lO adopt eoa"1111iaJ 'potitive' or 'nega-
tive' views of primitive·miinTlhe age o( gold josdes apimt t h e ~ of
the misery of primeval man. One might be tempted-: and some schollff
have not resisted the temptation - to trace these disputes back ta chc
time of Hesiod, and poruay Hesiod as himself an opponent or pro·
gress. 11 It is not perceptibly more plausible to make hiJn both a sup·
porter of 'chronological primitivism' (because he starts with an a~ of
gold) and an opponent of 'cultural primitivism' (in that he con~u
civilization with cannibalism), as docs one useful anthology (Lovqoy
and Boas, 1935: 35). For these two positions arc in fact one.
It is not my intention to discuss this post·Hesiodic literature here. 11
I note simply, for reasons which will shortly become dear, that Hesiod's
age of gold, the age of Cronus, the 'vegetarian' age befoff' cooking and
before sacrifice, which is described for us in so many tcxts, 11 is also the
period of cannibalism and human sacrifice, in at least part of the
tndition. Some of the texts which ma.kc this association between
opposites may seem very late. 14 But we should not forget that as early
as the fourth century BC the Cynics developed a theory of a 'natural'
way of life which both condemned the eating of dead flesh and cooked
food, and championed raw food, cannibalism and even incest, the
opposite paT ~xcelln1ce of culturc.u And it would be wrong to sec this
as merely a view held by theorists: Euripides's Bacchat: o,cillate, be·
tween the atmosphere of paradise described by the messenger early on
in his speech, and the orgy of nesh-cating which culminates in the quas.i-
incestuous murder of Pentheus by his mother (Bacclta~ 677-768,
1043-147). Hesiod's Cronus is also a god who cats his own children
(Th. 459-67) ... From this perspective, it is Plato who is 1theoriz.ing',
when in the Politic"-! he chooses to define the age of Cronus as the time
when cannibalism was unknown - a choice which happens to be the
same as that made by Hesiod in his venionorthemythoftheraccs. 1 '
If we begin from the other end, we find agriculture intimately linked
with cooking, u for example in the Hippocratic treatise On .·hacl&111t
Medicine, 3 (ed. FestugiCre), where it is shown that the cultivation of
cereals. which replaced the eating of raw foods, is founded upon a form
of food which has to ~ cooked. An association ~tween agriculture,
family life and the origin of civilization similar to that implied by
Hesiod also occun in the Athenian myths about Cccrop,, who, guided
by Bouzy~s ('Ox-team Ma.n'), 11 invented agriculture, and invented abo
the monogamous patriarchal family (Pembroke, 1967: 26-7, 29-!2;
and see pp. 215-28 below). The purpose of this csuy ii &o see wbcther
such associations exist already in Homer.
82
Land and sacrifice in the Odyssey
'lwa.!lie ~-gi~ng e_an!i. in a.aree!ing_ to his native land': xo,ipc.>• t)
.,ala,"""" 5t tei&..>po• /Jpoupa,, (Odyss.,. 13.354).". Now this is not
merely the act .of a. man returning to his native land:. it Coiitains a
fundamental point which deserves close analysis. -
In talking about the Odyssey, we have to make further distinctions:
not between the comp01itions of different bards detected by 'analytic'
critics in the light of criteria that differ with every scholar and produce
re1ult1 at once predictably divergent and fatally untestable; but be-
tween units which have a significance in the poem as we have it. To put
it crudely. we cannot discuss Cyclops or Calypso in the same manner as
we discuu Nestor or Telemachus. In effect, as has often been rccog-
nizcd,10 the Odyssey c9ntrut1 a. world we may term 'real', essentially
the world of Ithaca, but "1so Sparta and Pylos to whichJ'el~i:n.•~hus
goes. with a ..mythical world which is roughly coterminous with that of
the stories in Alcinous's palace (Segal, 1962: 17). Similarly,
Shakespeare's Tempest contrasts Naples and Milan on one hand with
Pr01pcro 1 s magic island on the other (Maricnstras 1 1965: 899-917).
Odysseus enten this mythical world after his stay with the Cicones, a
perfectly real Thracian people, known still to Herodotus (7.58, 108,
110), in whose territory he eats, fights and plundcn just as he might
have done at Troy; and after a ten-day storm 11 which he encounters
while rounding Cape Malea, the last 'real' place on his travels before he
gets back to lthaca. 12
Proof that this contrast is indeed relevant is supplied by the text
it.self. Telemachus's route never crosses that of Odysseus. There arc two
points of contact only between the two worlds. One is plainly magical:
Menelaus tcUs Odysseus's son how he was informed by the magician
Proteus, in Egypt, the land of wondcn, that Odysseus was detained on
Calypso'• island (4.555-8; 17.138-44).as The other is the land of the
Phacacians, those professional seamen who have been shown to occupy
a strategic place at the junction of the two worlds (Segal, 1962).14 l
need hud.ly press the point. Odysseus's travels have nothing to do with
•geography'; and there is more geographical truth in the 'untrue' stories
he tells Eumacus and Penelope (14.191-359; 19.164-202)15 than in
all the stories in Alcinous's palace.H Crete, Egypt and Epirus arc real
enough.
For Odysseus to leave this fantasy world means to leave a world that
is not the world of me.rh_ a world whi<:h. is by turns super-human and
sub-human, a world in which he is offered divinity by Calypso but also
threatened by Circe with reduction to the condition of an animal. And
he must leave it to return to the world of normality. The Ody_ssey as a
whole is in one sense the story of Odysseus's return to ~ormality, ~f h~s
deliberate acceptance of ~ human condition. n
83
Pierre Vidal-Naquet
There is therefore no paradox. in saying th.t, from the Lotus-E.ltcn
to Calypso by way ol't'tlf land of the Cyclopes and the Undaw~ld,
Odysseus meets with no creature which is strictly human. There LI of.
course sometimes room for doubt: the Laestrygoncs, for example, have
an agora, the mark of political life; but physically they arc not as rMn
arc but giants (IO.I 14, 120). Circe causes us to wonder wh~ther we are
dealing with a woman or a goddcu: but fmaJJy, just as With C;a..lypso,
the humanity is merely in the outward form, in the voice. She is in
truth 6EIVl7 8e0( ca'.161/eaaa, the 'tenible goddess with a human voice'
(10.136; 11.8; 12.150, 449; cf. 10.228). Twice Odysseus asks himscU
what 'eaten of bread' he has landed among - that is, what men. But in
each case the point is that he is not among 'bread-eaten' but among the
Lotus-Eaten and the Laestrygones (9.89; 10.101). 21
There follows from this a signal implication, that the 'stories' rigor-
ously exclude anything to do with working the land, or with arable land
itself insofar as it is worked.n The Thrace of the Ciconcs is the last cul-
tivated land Odysseus encountcn: there he cats mutton and drinks
wine; and there he obtains the wine he later offen the Cyclops (9.45ff.,
161-5, 197-211).H Euripides's Odysseus, when he lands in an un·
known land, asks Silcnus, 'Whcrr· are the walls and the city towers?'
The answn comes: 'Stranger, this is no city. No man dwells here'
(Cyclops 115-16).11 Here it is fortifications which arc the 1ymbol of
the presence of civilized humanity, or indeed of humanity at all. But
Homer's Odyneus looks for cultivated fields, for the sign of human
labour.n When the Achuans reach Circe's island, they search in vain
for the n-ga broeOn, the 'works of men', that is, for crops. But all they
sec iJ scrub and forest, wh"rc stag-hunts can be organized (10.1-4:7,
150, 157-63, 197, 251). ln the land of the L:acsuya:oncs, the sight of
smoke might be taken u evidence of domutic hearths and the presence
of human·bcinp (10.99). 0 But there is 'no trace either of the work of
oxen or of the work of men': tlllJa 11,t11 oUn tJoW11 alk" b:v6pW114'ainTo
tna (10.98). The Sirens live in a meadow, u do the gods et.cwhcrc
(12.159; cf. Homeric Hymn eo Herma 72; Euripides, H,pflolytu.s
73-4). Although Calypso's island ii woo,;kcl and nocn possesses a vine,
this is never said to be cultivated (5.6S-74-).
There is one specifically human ~ preaent. D'I tM world o( the
'stories': the olive, the uc_e of whosc~J:tulhhil~,the
fixed point of his home (23.iSl..;zot},. ~ ~~~----AliYrj!, ~ ~
number of ocea.,iom the m e ~ - ~ ( ~ · - ~ from ~ r . ii:t
several different forms. It provides the stab- widl wli:lffl. ht boR1
through the Cyclops's eye·; anti the -~.ol'.:.tb,-@e~widi \midi. he
build, h~ boat (9.319---20; 5.254---6; d. S.pl, 1962,-f5,-G2,"6!):And
although it is true that when hr i, with Aeotu,. Cir« or Calyp,o.,
M
land and sacrifictt in thtt Odyury
Odyueus has plenty to rat, and that the poet playfully draws attention
to the vast difference between the gods' meals and those of men
(5.196-9), we att never told where it comes from or who produced it.
A accond exclusion is entailed by this exclusion of cultivated land:
that of the sacrificial meal, which we saw from Hesiod to be so inti-
mately related to the first. One could almost, in a sense, extend to the
entire world of the stories the remark Hennes jokingly makes to Calypso
when he arrives on her island: 1Who would choose to cross this waste of
salt-water? There is not in these parts a single city of mortal men to
offer rich hecatombs to the gods' (5.100-2). But only in a sense. For
the sacrifice which Odysseus offen to the dead in accordance with
Circe's instructions and with lambs she has provided is perfonned in a
trench, and is intended to provide blood for the feeding of the dead
(10.516-40, 571-2; 11.26-47) - it is the opposite of a sacrificial
meal, whose purpose is to feed the living. And the same is true of the
victims which Odysseus promises the dead and Teiresias that he will
offer on his n:tum: a barren cow and a black ram (10.521-Si 11.
29-SS).
In the land of the Cyclopes, Odysseus's companions offer sacrifice
(9.2!11: lBLlaell'E'I'), as Polyphemus himself does not. But it is not a
blood-sacrifice, for they arc living on cheese (9.232i sec below, p. 88).
And the sacrifice they offer on the island just across from that of the
Cyclopes - which is abnormal becauK the victims are the sheep belong·
ing to Polyphemus, animals not reared by man - is rejected by Zeus
(9.551-5): even when a human community docs sacrifice in non-
human tcnitory the sacrifice is improper.
I
88
Land and socrifice in lh• Odyss,y
Odyaeu, is d<bl>orately choosing the human against all that is not-
bwaan (Segal, 1962: 20).
89
PitrTC Vidal-Naqutt
is cdtbrating tht maniagc of hil..fC!'a (4..S-H). .By coalnlf., on Ithaca
we fmd a ,oc;iety in crisis:· lie tlin:c gtntrations of the royal family_
represented by an old man (whose exclusion from the throne brcomcs
slightly mysterious when we compatt him with Nestor), a woman, and
an adolesctnt youth who is portraytd as slightly backward (J.296- 7;
cf. Finley, 1977: 76). 51 A society upsidedown, a society in a crisis sym·
boliztd by the revolt of the A:ouroi ( the young aristocrats I , waiting for
the re-establishment of order.
Sacrifice here turns out to be both the sign of the crisis and the
means of its resolution. Who makes sacrifice on Ithaca? If our sole
criterion is the use of the verbs hiereuiJ and spntdo and related words,
the answer is everyone - both the suiton and Odysseus and his fol·
lowcn.u But if we examine the texts in which sacrifice is specifically
addressed to the gods, we find that the su.iton do not sacrifice. Mon:
precisely, one of them does suggest a libation to the gods: but this is
Amphinomus, the one suitor whom Odysseus attempts to exclude from
the coming massacre." Antinous sugnu a sacrifice to Apollo accord-
ing to the Nies, with the thighs bumt; but he is unable to fulfil his
promise (21.265-8). 11 By contrast, on Odysseus's side, sacrifice either
retrospective or immediate, is perpetual; E.umacus's piety is streued.
'l'he swineherd did not forget the immortals; he Jlad a good heart'
(14.420-1)." The comparison certainly suggests that we have lo allow
that lai1tUu6 sometimes has a meaning which is not spccifaca.Uy
religious. 11 More importantly, sacrifice is a double criterion in the
Odyury: of humanity, between humans and non-humans; and of social
and moral values, bctwccn human-beings.
But there is in the human world of Ithaca at least one place directly
connected with tht world of the myths - the complex consisting of the
harbour of Phorcys, named after Cyclops's own grandfather (l.7J-2;
13.96-7; cf. Stgal, 1962: 48), and the cave ~ to the Nymphs, the
divinitic1 of nature and or water. This cave hu two entrances, one for
gods, the other for mortals (1.5.109-12); ad appropriately enough,
just near it is a sacred olive-tree, under which Athena speaks to
Odyacus (13.122, 572). And it is here that the Phaeacians I.cave
Odysseus and his treasures.
Charles Segal ( 1962: 17) bu oblcned tllat the Phacacia.ns arc 'be-
tween the two worlds': they are placed It tbe intenet:tion or the world
of the talcs and tht 'real' world; and their...._ function in thr poem is
to transport Odysseus from the one to the other.11 When Odyllftll
comes ashore in Phacacia, naked, after complctina, or almo,t complc-t-
ing, hil rctum journey home 'wit~. 11t the hrlr :-.f aods or mortal men'
(5.52),•• he takes shelter under an uliv~tffr Mut this olive-tree i1 qui«
remarkable: h is double, b ,Js, •).Ole, b 6' Uairic, both wild and
Land and sacnfice in the Odyssey
pf'ted; olnstcr and olive (5.477).'° The very land of Scheria is double,
con,.panble at once both with Ithaca, Pylos and Sparta and with the
1mdt of the stories. Phaeacia contains all the characteristic elements of
a Guek settlement in the age of colonization, physically framed as it is
by the 'shadowy peaks" which can be seen from afar (5.279-80). lt has
anble land distributed by a founder (<6aooru lipov-: 6.10)." Iu
field, arc beyond doubt the 'works of men': l:,rypOV<: ... 1((ri fP"'t'
Mp.:,.-w,, 'field& and human tillage' (6.259) - exactly what Odysseus
has looked for in vain in all his travels. It has a fortified citadel, distinct
from the fields: poli, lcai gaia (6.177, 191; also 6.3: 6~µ6.r, ,r6).u, TE).
The country has in abundance wine, oil and corn; Alcinous has a
flourishing vineyard of his own (6.77-8, 79, 215, 259, 293; cl. 7.122-
6). In sum, the Phatacians arc men just like other men: they 'know the
cities and rich fi,,i,1s of all men' (8.560-1). When Odysseus lands in
Phacacia, he is [clu.ming to humanity. As he draws near to Nausicaa,
he is likened to a lion which descends from the hills and kills livestock
or deer; but when he leaves Phacacia to return to Ithaca, he is likrned
to a tired ploughman returning home (6.130-3; 13.31-5).
But at the same time, Phaeacia is sharply contrasted with Ithaca.
There are no seasons in the magic garden of Alcinous (7.113-32). 61
The West wind blows there ptrpctually; the vine bears blossom, un·
ripe and ripened grapes all simultaneously. In effect, it is no ordinary
orchard, but a goldcn·age land in the heart of Phacacia. By contrast,
LaCrtcs's garden is quite normal: 'each vine had its own time to be
harvested, and the clustcn of grapts were of every colour, as the sea.sons
of Zeus caused them to change' (24.342-4; cf. Segal, 1962: 47).U On
the one hand, the age of Cronus; on the other, the age of Zeus."' The
contrast can be developed. The dogs guarding Alcinous's house, the
creations of Hephaestus in gold and silver, arc immortal, and naturally
possess eternal youth; but everyone remembers the story of the dog
Argo, whose life is exactly commensurate with the period of Odysseus's
absence (7.91-4; 17.290-327)."
And what of sacrifice here? They arc performed in Phacacia much a.s
they art' at Pylos or on Ithaca. 'We shall offer choice victims to the
gods', declares Alcinous (7.191; cf. 7.180-1). Before Odysseus's
departure an ox is sacrificed in the proper manner (13.24-7;cf. 50-IJ.
libations to Zeus). And when the Phacacians arc threatened w1tl,
destruction by Poseidon and Zeus combined, their fate turns on the
result of the sacrifice which Alcinous decides to offer them: 'a.nd the)
prepared the bulls' (f'l°oll,&GaCJQvro liE 'f'Ql}pou<:: 13.184~. This is t~c last
act by the Phacanans in the Odyssey, and we never discover their fate
- the onh,· case of a fate left in the balance. And yet, even here, the
Phacacian; arc not as other men. Alcinous c-an say: 'When we sacrifice
91
Picl'TC' Vidal-Naquct
our magnificent hccatombs to the SOOs, they come ~d ~t by u, and ~at
with us' (7.201-3)." That sort or sharing has nothmg m common wal.h
normal sacrifice which, in contrast, separates men from the~- The
Phacaciuu are 0£ course men: AlcinOUJ aD4l ~ zemmd each
other of their mortality (7~~-Ug....f!j,·aiNitll'c.........,. ~S
.,,..._._ ia,.tlle poem c1early show, them racing the precarioumcst of
the human condition. But they are also onllhithtoi, 'relatives 0£ ,he
IO(b' - not mcttly a polite epithet, for Homer usn it twice only, and
both times of them (5.S5; 19.279). They were once neishbours 0£ the
Cyclopes and suffered from their attacks until Nausith001 set them
'aput from men who eat bread' (l'JCO( m,6pW11 M.f,tqcmiwll': 6.4-8).
And in one smse they arc indeed the complete reverse of the Cyclopes
(Segal, 1962: 55): all their human virtues, the practice or ho,pitality."
piety, the arts of feastin1 and gift-giving, are the inverse of Cyclopean
barbarism. Moreover, the present disjuncture and previous proximity of
the Phacacians and the Cyclopes is a sign of a more subtle relation: 'We
arc intimate, {of the pxb)', says Alcinous, 'like the Cyclopes and the
savqc: tribes of the Giaau' (~( ••P KUd,Wl'II!( ff ICGi biyplCI fvAcr
rrycn,rwiv: 7.205-6) - those: same Giants whom the Laestrygonct are
said to resemble (10.120). Proximity and kinsbip: 1Un:ly an invitation
to search in Phaeacia for both the pattern of lhe world or fmtuy and
its rncne.
After landing in AJc:inous's country, Odysseus meets a gid washina
clothes, who invites him to come and meet her father and mother
(7.290-!07). He had met another 1irl, elsewhere. drawing water from
a spring, who pvc him a similar invitation; but she WII the daughter of
the king or the Lacstrygones. Both in the cannibal and in the hospitable
kinpm Odyucu1 meetl the queen before he me.eu the kin1 (10.105-
15; 7.U9-!i4; d. 7.5S-5). And is Nausic:ai a girl or a god.de•? A
dichi, of coune; but we must realize that she is a girl who loob like a
goddess; while Circe and Calypio were goddascs who looked like girk
(6.16,,66-7, 102-9; 7.291; 8.457). AlcinoU1, md very dil<lttlly
Nausic:ai herself, entertain. a marriqc to OdyltC!'WI, p....Uel to thcte
goddesses' more cncraet,ically prosecuted plans. The IC<luctive Sireft1
sing like bards of the Tro.P,ft war (12.184-91), just tili.e Dcmodocua •t
lhc court of Alcinous, who brinp tears to Od)'UCU1"1 eyes (8.499-531).
The fll'tt represent the perilous, Omiodoc:u1 the poaitive, apect of
poetry (Detienne, 1967).
lt will no doubt be objected tha, there is • limil to the number ol
utterly difreren, 1ituationa a man like Ody1Hu1 can cncoun\cr. That ;11
uue; but there is one coincidem.."C whic:b it pnbap1 nwrc than- u,ually
curious. Before mcctiog wilh his ~ntual carriers, the Phacac-.,
Odyucus cnc:olUlten another, who brougbt him lo tbc n e i g h ~
Land and sacnfice in tlte Odyssey
of ltha.ca - Aeolus, master of the winds (10.2l}i who spends his time,
lik.t the Phaeacians, in feasting. In the course of both 'returns' Odysseus
falls asleep; disastrous, after his sojourn with Aeolus, fortunate after
Scheria (10.23-SS; 13.78-92; cf. Segal, 1967: 32~9). Now it will be
recall~ that Aeolus's family practise inctst;and, if we are to accept the
lines which introduce the genealogy of Akinous and Aretc, the same is
true of the Phaeacian royal couple:
'Ap'lfll &' &q.,.' tar!V hWWJ,ILVI, b: Sf ro«f}W11
rWv cd,rWv o\',re-p rftt.OII 'AAAivotN jJaolAijo:
Arete ll the name she is called, and she come. of the same
parcnu u in fact produced the 11.i.og Alkino\lS
(7.54-5, tr. Lattimore, ali,tttly altered)
The rest of the text as we have it ( 56-66) corrects the inevitable im-
pres1ion by claiming that Aretc is not Alcinous's sister but his niecc;
but in this case tht..: l' is some justification for invoking the hypothesis
of ll\terpolation.19
All the same, the 'mythical' aspect of Scheria is counterbalanced by
what I have termed the 'real' world. I have alrudy shown this for land
and sacrifi~. but the point can be extended to its entire social organiz-
ation. The social institutions of Pylos, Sparta, and of Ithaca particularly,
arc to be found on Scheria,6 ' and the details of palace organization arc
identical between Ithaca md Akinous's court: is it an 'accident' that
there are fifty servants in Alcinous's house, and the same number in
Odysseus's (22.421-2; 7.103), and the same with everything clse? 70
But these identities do not produce identical societies. For ex.ample,
although there is at least one ·angry young man' on Scheria, Euryalus,
who insults Odysseus, he is compelled to apologize (8.131--415, esp.
396-415). One could hardly find a swineherd, a cowman, or a goa.t-
herd in Ph acacia; and there would be no chance of finding on Ithaca
those professional sailors, who steer infallibly without the aid of pilots
(7.318-28; 8.555-63, 566; 16.277-31; compuc 16.322-7): Ithaca i,
an island whose men once went in ships, but it is in no sense a country
of sailon, for all that Odysseus has acquired the necessary skill. Once
back in harbour, he puts to purely static use the equipment of his ship
- as when the ship's cable is used to hang the faithless servant-girls (22.
465-73).
And yet Phacacia is an ideal and an impossible society: Homer, at thr
height of the Dark-Age crisis of monarchy, pictures a king who <.an
restore peace, who rules over twelve obedient vassals (8.390-1), over
docile rons, over a wife whose rOlc, despite claims to the contrary, is
limited to intercessionj71 and over old men whose sole function is to
give advice (7.155--66 {Echeneus's sp~cch)), and_wh~ are nei_ther dis-
carded like Laertes nor embittered bke Aegypt1us. In this sense,
93
Pierre Vidal·Naquct
Alcinou,'s palace constitutes a perrcct ol4os; and yet ~l is impossiblc,
as I have sucsstd. The Phacacians arc ipi.orant oC phy11cal 1tn1glc (8.
246), and 0 £ political strugle too: the stormy ~,a ('politic:11
The ma.in clement which ancient mythology preserved from the myth
of Orpheus and Aristaeus was the death of Eurydice and the tragic
pusion which drove Orpheus to go down to the underworld. This tra·
dition emphasized the exemplary fate of the loven precisely because it
was incapable of accounting for the relation set up by the myth between
the bttkeeper Aristacus and the couple Eurydice-Orpheus. Two series
of questions arise immediately from the story in the Georgics. In the
fint place, why did Aristaeus chose to pursue Eurydice rather than
another nymph? And why docs his action result in the disappearance of
bees which, apparently, have no special connection with Orpheus's
young wife? Secondly, Orpheus is only brought into the myth because
of Eurydice; is not his connection with the bee-keeper purely fortuitous
and therefore gratuitous? In a famous study, the German philologist
Eduard Norden set out to demonstrate the arbitrary character of the
myth told in the Georgics. He argued that Virgil had latched on to the
insubstantial figure of Aristaeus and simply invented his adventure with
Eurydice and his rivalry with Orpheus (Norden, 1966: 468-532). The
fact that the author of the Georgics was apparently the only authority
for a connection between two separate myths, at least as far as their
immediate significance was concerned, seemed to support his claim.
The only objections were from those who attributed Virgil's inspirdtlun
to a Greek venion of Ule Hellenistic period,2 a mere question of
'sources' which did nothing to challenge the myth's status as the product
of individual imagination. The reason for the persistent failure of
ancient myth analysis to understand the meaning of the triangular
relationship Aristaeu.-Eurydice--Orpheus to which the Georgics bear
witness UI not simply that the method has an implici1 tendency to select
97
Marcel Detienne
from the myths values which legitimate a particular idc~ogy of the
eternal man. At a deeper lcvc:I, its own definition of the h~IV}' work
makes it incapable of "cognizing the double context of this story, the
mythical context and the ethnographic cme. Only tbc Ont of these can
account for the unexpcc:ted.,.._.:evf~ -·o.,.._.111~
dOrY of - ilMntOr Of honey, and the K"Cond ~ eucn~ial i_f any Ill'~
ing is to be given on the level of myth to AristacW s mufortWIC in
losing his bea.J Virgil's story begins with the disappearance or
Aristaeu1'1 bees. Three reasons an given for the disappearance of the
bees, all equally explicit. Finl, there is a statement which derives from
the experience of the pcuant bee-keepers to whom book 4 of the
Georgic1 is addrcucd: the bees died of hunFr and disease (4.25lff.,
98
Th, myth of 'Honeyed Orpheus'
arist-, out of their hatred of effeminacy and voluptuousness and their
particular hostility towards debauchees and seducers, in other words,
£or those who miausc ointments and aromatics.' Plutarch even, in one
of his treatise,, stresses the infallible discernment with which bees
singk out for their attacks only those usen of perfume who arc guilty
of illicit sn.ual nlationships.' He also emphasizes, in a chapter of the
Conivgalia praecep-ta (44, 144<!.), that bee-keeping requires exemplary
marital fiddity of its practitioncn: the bee-keeper must approach his
bees as a good husband dot"s his lawful wife, that is, in a state of purity,
without being polluted by sexual relations with other women. If he
docs not, he will have to face the hostility of his charges as the husband
has to face the anger of his partner. This ethnographic context explains
why Aristaeus lost his bees. While Virgil has no more than a discre('t
rdercncc to the flight of Eurydice and her nymphs bdore the Thcssalian
bee-keeper, other less squeamish writers say plainly that Aristaeus
d«ircd Eurydice, that he wanted to seduce her and attempted to
assault her (stuprare, uitiare).' It was because the inventor or honey
had the smell of seduction on him that he was deprived of his bees.
Orpheus's bitterness and the Nymphs' anger are therefore reactions to
a sexual offence. This, by accidentally causing the death of Eurydice -
who was bitten by a serpent in her flight - drove to despair a lover
passionately devoted to his new wife, and deeply disappointed
Aristacus's protecting powers, the bees, who had chosen him for his
exemplary conduct and his good upbringing - for which latter they had
also been largely responsible.
The ethnographic context, which reveals a dose relation between the
conduct of the bees and the sexual behaviour of the bee-keeper, now
sends us back to the wider mythical context to which the meeting be·
tween Aristaeus and Eurydice belongs. There arc two immediate prob·
lems here. What can be the significance of the misconduct of a figure
whose reputation as a virtuous husband is solidly established by the rest
of the mythical tradition? And why does he pick on Orpheus's wife
when no other myth puts them in direct connection or makes any
reference to their possible affinity? A full answer would require a
detailed analvsis of the early sections of the myth of Aristaeus, for
which thet-.: ~ no room here, but two things can be said. Fint, all the
education given to the 'master of honey' was a preparation for a sokm11
marriage with the eldest daughter of the king of Thebes, and tht' bndc
groom scaled the allianct with his fathcr·in·law with the honey he
brought as one of a number of useful presents. Secondly, one of the
main results of Aristaeus's activity - in the episode which takes place
on·<Aos - is the establishment of harmony in conjugal relations; the
sweet honey seems to produce a marritd life untroubled by either
99
Marcel Detienne
ildultcry or seduction. But what about the madness which ~ame. oYcr
Aristilcus when he came in contact with Eurydice? To a plain thui the
sociological status of this young woman hu to be uamined and defined
in refation to the mytholo* of honey, ~ 7 . ,~• u a nymph,
Eurydice ii one of the ,,_......., .l,hich tome tndltion1 ~-Jb:c
DWmtiolft6f'hof\rY. Two myths, which dovetail closely, make an associ-
ation between two groups in Ikmeter's entourage, the Nymphs and the
Bee-Women, the M~liss.i. According to the fint of these storie,, it was a
nymphcallcdMeliuawho discovered the fJJ1t honeycombs in the forest,
ate some and mixed it with water and drank it, uid then taught her
companions to make the drink and cal the food. This was part of the
nymphs' a.chinement in bringing man out of his wild state; under~
guidance of Melissa, Bee, they not only turned men away from caung
each other to eating only this product of the forest trtts, but also
introduced into the world of men the feeling of modesty, o.idi>s, which
they established by mean1 of another invention, intended to reinforce
the fint, the discovery of wovC'n gannenu. Sin« then, explains the
myth fmally, no marriage takes place without th" fint honoun being
reserved to thC' nymphs, the companions of Demeter, in mC'mory of
their part in C'stablishing a way 0£ lifC' ruled by piety and approved by
the gods. The purpose of thC' second story is to explain thC' association
of Demeter with thC' nymphs connC'cted with honey· and bees. ThC'tt is
nothing unusual in thC' presence' of DemdC'r in a myth cmtred on a
'cultivated' form of life conaisting of dietary prescriptions and a sexual
code, but it i1 given even greater justification by a ritual feature men·
tioned explicitly in thC' second myth. After the kidnapping of Pase·
phone, thC' sorrowing Demeter entru1ted to the Nymphs the basket
(K&>..a6cK) which had held Pent-phone's ~aving and went to Paras,
where she was wdcomed by King Mclisseus, the king of the bees. When
she was leaving the goddess wanted to thank her host, and 10 die pve
Meli1tC'us's sixty daughtcn the cloth Persephone had been wnvina for
her wedding, and at the IUDC' time told them of her sufferinp and
revealed to them the secret ceremonK's she wished to institute. Ever
after, the women who celebrate the Thctmophoria - the fcut of
DcmelC'r reserved for lawful wives - were known as MelUstli; their
ritual namC' was Bees (cf. Detienne, 197 7: 79--80; Detienne and Vemaet,
1979, 211-12).
The emphasis now is no Jongtr on dietary rules, which slip into the
background, but on two diffC'rcnt female statusc1. ThC' daupllC'n of
Melisscus move between thC' two ftnt ttceiving the cloth woven by
PC'nephone, which stands for the stale of the ""''"/'W, the young girl
thinking of marriage, and thC'n giYing their nunc to the 111u,icd women,
lawful wives, who meet to cclcbnte the mysteries of Demeter Thesmo-
100
Th• myth of 'Hon,y•d Orph,,u'
phoros. Nymph woman, Thesmophorian woman: this duality of the
dausht•n of MelisKus it only fully expo-=d when placed in the 1etting
of a series of imatJes in which the bee is the animal symbol of cenain
female vinua. The description given above of various unique features
in the behaviour of bees relied on the evidence of Plutarch in a long
comparison between the bee and the lawful wife. When Plutarch
included in the Coniuplu prucepta the advice that the husband should
have the same regard for his wife u a bee·keepcr for his bees, he was in
agreement with a tradition as old as Hesiod, in which the bee stands for
the good wife in the same way that the fox symbolius cunning. In the
minds of the Greeks, the melissa is the emblem of female domestic
virtue; faithful to her husband and the mother of legitimate children,
she watches owr the private area of the house, taking care of the
couple's poucaions, always reticent and modest (sOphrOn and
aiditnOn), so adding to the functions of a wife those of a housekeeper
nevH greedy or fond of drink or inclined to doze, who firmly rejects
the romantic chatter that women in general enjoy.
It ii this model of the bee-woman which determines the distribution of
attributes between the two female statuses possessed by the daughten of
Mclisseus, who an: at one stage nymphs and at another thesmophoroi.
Since only the women who celebrate the Thesmophoria are given the
explicit title of Melissai, Bees, it is with their rOle that ~ will stut.
The structure of the Thcsmophoria is most clearly shown by contrast
with the ritual of the Adonia. A comparison of the two rituals (sec fig.
1) reveals a series of fundamental oppositions: between Demeter and
Adonis, between cereals and aromatics, and between marriage and
seduction (Detienne, 1977: 60-98). Analysis of the mythology of
aromatics has produced two results which are relevant here, the con-
trut between \he legitimate wife and the courtesan and the distance
between the former, with her faintly unpleasant smell, and the pungent
perfumir of thir latter. Whereas the festivals of Adonis display the licence
of which womirn are capable when abandoned to themselves, the
Thesmophoria always took place in a serious, almost severe atmosphere.
The wonhippcn of Adonis were often courtcnns; lhe followen of
Demeter Thcsmophoros were always the legitimate wives of the citizens,
and the fcslival was stricdy reserved for them; ceremonies were clond
to sla\'e women, the wives of metics and forcignen, and of coursL·
courtesans and concubines. The opposition between the thumophorul
and the devotee of Adonis was most shuply marked in the sc:xual
behaviour prescribed for th~ puticipanU in the two rites. In the
A.donia men and women behaved u loven, on the model of the
rclati.onlhip ot" Aphrodite and Adonis, but in the Theunophoria not
only WCff' men carefully ex.duded but even the manicd women were
101
Marcel Detienne
ADONIA nD,SMOPHOaJA
ContiJ1ueJK:r
Suul•tlihfd,r Seduction
Auod•tird,r.ni. lnceme and mynh Abnham'1 balm
Smirll, Abule of perfumn Slipt amell or futiae-
Hatred of the Bee-women
Ficurc 2
109
m: Myth and social order
7. 'Value' in Greek myth
Louia~m•t (1948)
Bu.t there is yet another level at which we can examine the mental
115
L:)uil Gernet
activity through which "value' comes into bang, that is, bttoma
'objective': the level or myth.' . .
We can sec that precious ob,JCcts occur 111 leftnds - CYCD that they
pla}', so to speak, a central l'Olc - became in them t~cy are ~waJI
endowed with a peculiar power. What I want to ,tress ~ that th11 '"Y
or thinking is particularly evident at the very stage at which I ~ s~udy-
ing the notion or 'value', that is, in the pre-monetary stqe whida 11 the
immcdiacc prccunor of a period in which it wu conceived abl~Y·
Perhaps we can learn somethin1 from that; at the very lcut. there ts a
problem to es.amine mOJC closdy. . .
There is no 'method' by which to conduct such an cxannna.ooo. We
must read the storica, nothing more. But the storica prnuppoac or
imply particular human attitudes: we should take them into consider-
ation if llllC wish to read aright. ~ stories, moreover, are intcrcon·
nected: there arc similarities which we would do well not to overlook.•
prion· because we U'C terrified of making arbitrary conncctiona. 1 need
really be granted only one thing: that mythology is a kind of lanpagc.
We know the function of ',ipifomts' in a language (de Sauuutt, 1966:
122-7); taking my cue from linguinics, I would say that we hPe to
take into account two kinds of conntttions. First, th<>11: bet~n the
constituent clements or 'moments' of a linclc talc (which ~ may tab
sometimn as the more significant in that their rationale is not immcdi·
atcly obvious and even seems on occasion not to have been und.entood
by those who told them); and second, the msociatiom by means of
which one episode, theme or imqt: evoffl a similar llf'OUP· Such con·
ncctions and associations arc: of somit help. But we must oot bC" in too
much of a hurry,
This discuuion of the mythic density to ~ found in one and the same
story would be incomplete if I failed to point out one element that
might seem utterly adventitious.
Before it is awarded to one of the sages, the tripod is usually the
focus or a disputt- which turns into a war between cities. The episode is
not essential; the story could have dispensed with it. Y ct it fits neatly
with the tale, as is revealed by one very interesting detail (Diogenes
Laertius 1.32): as Helen threw the tripod into the sea, she foretold that
it would be much fought over (,rep~-r()('). That makes it sound as
though it were endowed with a mysterious power: it exercises, exactly,
a baneful influence. I incline to think that the pcnisten«: of this theme
which has no bearing on the story derives from the fact that it is a
constituent of the very idea of the precious object.
There is one other matter that I shall limply call to the reader's
attention in the same way: the venions in which the cup figures do not
include this feature. There must then have been a special connection be·
tween the ,ymbolism associated with the tripod and an essential element
of the mythi.cal conception of 'value'. Indeed, the theme of the 'dispute
over the tripod' is illuminated itself by a famous legend which pits
Heracles against Apollo. The tripod is the one at Delphi: and so we can
relate the possession of an agalm.4 to the establishment or the repos·
session of some religious authority. And it is only to be expected that it
might at the same time have a 'political' significance: a tripod given by
the Argonauts to the Libyans or the Hylleans [ or the people of
Euesperis/Berenice) assured these nations of their right to undisputed
possession of their land (Herodotus 4.179; Apolloniu1 of Rhodes, Argo·
nauti•a 5.522-36; Diodorus Siculus 4.56.6).
For us of course the symbolic implications of a single motif may well
seem to diverge in different directions. But in myth they are bound
tightly one to the other.
Eriphyle's necklace
Rather similar connections in relation to the precious object seem to
have existed in the minds of those who created legends inspired by it;
and they are revealed by other stories connected with conflict. .
According to the tradition describing the oldest games, the thmgs
119
LouisGemet
which were offered as prize1 wett truly impressive and in their own way
,,cry valuable; and among them we occasionally find arms and armour·
Not or coune to~ used: these objects belong to a class well known to
anthropologists - 'ornamental armour'. Our most interesting ex~ple is
the 'shield or AfKos', which gave its name to one of the contests m the
great festival of Hera: as a synonym, Pindar uses the expreuion 'the
bronze in Argos', thus stressing that aspect of the value or the metal
object which is socially of greatest importance (Pllldar, Olympian 7.85
Snell). But there are resonances here too. This shield was connected
with the one which King Dan~s carried in the days of his youth and
later consecrated in the temple of Hera (Robert, 1920-6: l.273). And
the prizes annually awarded seem to be a sort of coiMge derived from
this shield (Reinach, 1910: 221). In the lesirndary tradition, moreover,
the shield is a bit like a talli:man - it figurct in relation to the installation
and transmission of royal power in one case: on Dan~s·s death, his
son-in-law takes it down and gives it to hit own son (who is the proper
rc:prescntative or his maternal grandfather). On the other hand, the
shield also possesses the power - manifested miraculously in time of
wu - or protecting the city to which the temple bclonp. One glimpse
of the shield or Danaus is enough to make itt enemies tum and flee
(Scrvius, in Vngil. Aennd. 3.286 (3, p. 115.20 Harvard edition)). We
come across the same motir of magical armour .. and in exactly the
same form, 01. the story of Aristomcncs't ahi.eld, which had also been
consecrated, and which pined the day for the Thebans at Lcuctra
(3 71 BC) when it was placed on a trophy set up in full view of the
enemy (Pautanias t.!2.5-6).
The most typical example of the malefic power of the precious object is
provided by the necklace which figures in the Theban cycle.H
Sewn Argive heroes have undenaken to make war upon Thebc1 to
restore to Polyneices, son of Oedipus, his proper rights after ~e hu
been driven out by his brother Eteocles. One or the SC"Yen, Amph1araus,
takes part only with extreme reluctan~e. To ob.tain his co-ope~ation'. his
wife Eriphyle has to be employed as mtermediary, for a cons1derat1on:
a peplos and a golden necklace. A series of disutcn ensues. A~phiar~us
loses his life on the expedition. His son Alcmacon avmgics him by kill·
ing his mother. Polluted by his mother's blood, he too cor.ncs to a
terrible end. He gives the peplos and the necklace to two wwves, one
121
LouisGemct
after the othrr; and they arc fatal. Their evil power peni1ted ~en into
historical times: after the Phocian sack of the temple at D~lph1, where
they had been consecrated, the wife of one of the Phodan generals
wanted to wear these treasures. They bumcd her to death, . .
We would do well to note in the initial story one or two links With
social reality. The peplos and the nccltlace had a long history: they ~d
been given to Harmonia., forebear of the kinp of Thebes, on the occU1on
of her marriage to Cadmus; and they were hand~d do~ through the
royal family until they reached Polyneiccs (who, mte~un~y m.ough,
according to one source, received them when the 1nhentance ;"•
divided up, in exchange for allowing Eteodes first tum U king:
Hellanicus, FGrH 4 F 98 (= Scholiast on Euripides, Ph.onsisstu 71) ). So
they belong in principle to the category of marriage-gifts~ iuclf pan ~f
the category of customary presta.tiom ad u such 1ubJect to soaal
Nies. We should also note that such thinp arc found in pain elsewhere
too: in Euripides's Mede., the daughter of the king of Corinth is given a
crown and a pcplos by Medea - an association which rccun in the fint
century AD in the case of an imperial offering {by Nero) at Delphi:
IDld crown and purple fHplos (Pausaniu 2.1 7 .6); Amphitrite gives
Theseus a crown and a tunic, more or lcu as a prc1cnt for his bridc·to·
be Ariadne; Alcmcne is given a necklace and a CLIP by Zeus, who has
taken the fonn of her husband.11
Some traditional prcslations, in puticu.lar those given on the occasion
of a marriage, certainly became heirlooms. And one could say that it
looks very much as though, in our story at leut, their alienation from
the family brought about by Polyneicc1'1 action initiated the unible
career of the oplmato. But it is worth thinking about tbe manner in
which their power is, at that decisive moment, let loose. Why did
Amphiaraus have to Co on the expedition? The legendary tradition on
this point is at once opaque and complex.. Now we find the idea of
'persuasion', now of 'obligation'. But all the sources agree that when
Amphiaraus goes he is aware of what hu happened and yet still hu to
go. Why must he go? One c1r.planation involu:a the idea that his wife bu
been granted beforehand the right to decide. The philolopts rightly
observe that tbia rtnden the motif of the inducement - the gift -
ruperOuous (cf. llobcrt, 1915: 1,208). The duty is without e•planat:ion,
the pcrsuuion incffectualj and aayway, they arc mutually coaLn-
dictory. When the legend was created in the epic poem Co which our
sources refrr, it seems that an attempt w• made, by dint of dwasy
prosthesis, to explain thia ccnual clement away bccaulC i.1 WM 110
lonser fully understood. But i.n tnath it is it.sdf the ezplan•tioD• And
,ometimes vtt can just glimp,c that it is all the nplanation nccdcd: fut
aample, when vtt look, in the figurative rcpreacmations, at the scene
'Value' in Gred m)'th
of Amphiaraus's departure, where Eriphyle nands before her angry
husband, dearly wearina; the fatal neck.lace;1 1 or when we arc told that
Amphiaraus, precisely so as not to have to 80· forbade hi.I wife to
accept Polyneices's gifts (Apollodoru1, Bibliotheca 3.61); or when
Homer tells us that the hero's death was brought about by 'gifts to a
womm' ('YulOUt.Ja, Eiw'KCI' 5Wpwa,) - an expression even the ancients
found difficult, but which in its other occurrence in a dirferent con·
text refers to a legendary motif(Odyu•y 15.24 7; 11.521). In each case
we can sec the underlying notion of the 'coercive force of the girt':
Amphiaraus has to go off to his death once the gift has entered his own
house.
That idea cannot in principle be sepuated from the notion that there
inheres in the object given a mysterious power (Mauss, 1970: 8-12,
6S-9); and we should note that the two do become separated in the
usual run of legends about a,almato.. That more or less obscures both the
origin and the point of the motif in the myth - yet the motif endures,
and the object of value cannot be represented socially without it.
But it docs of course have other aspects: and they appeu stereo·
typed in legendary tradition.
Polycratcs's rina
Wealth is the focus of religious awe. Can it be got rid of? Sometimes it
must - witness the scene in the Agamemnon: where we also saw that
even to vow to destroy it involves facing terrible danger.
Polycratcs wu tyrant of Samo, during the second half of the sixth
century; for all that, the legend associated with him incorporates a
number of instructive themes. ln the form it takes in Herodotus (3.40-
3), it has of course been adapted in the interests of a morali2ing piety
of the le.ind often to be found in that author: the unmarred prosperity
of Polycrates stin the gods' envy; he is advi1ed to divest himself of
some portion of his wealth - precisely, •the object which is most
precious to him'. And so he throws into the sea, during what cilll'I only
be described as a ritual, n the famous ring which is the thing he values
most. But strange to tell, the ring tums up again. Polycratcs is unable to
renounce that which he had accepted he must renounce. And he must
be destroyed: only utter ruin can expiate obdurate prosperity.
Though it has come to dominate the unfolding of the story. the
metaphysical idea of nemesis has not, in general, done too much
violence to the uaditional clements that we can glimpse even through
the folk-talc motifs. Scholars have trird to define these clements by
dint of parallels which arc not exactly irTClcvant, but too general to
123
LouisGcmet
explain anything in a proper manner; .for instance •. the invocatio? o.f the
ceremony in which the Doac of Vmacc was mamed to the Adri~, to
symbolize the Venetian claim to rule the seL It is more approp~atc to
ttt:at the myth u a myth, to break down iu comtitu~~ts, Uld pick u.p
the usociadons it suggests in the Greek legendary tracbllon.
The finl point is that the throwing of a ring into .the sea~ occun
in the legend of Theseus. The contcxt, to be sure, lS rather different:
but that simply makes the praumption of the act's ritual character the
more natural. While the ship canying the victims destined for the
Minotaur to Crete is on ib way, Minos md Theseus quarrel - it docs
not here matter why, because quite independently of the reason (which
is anyway later forgotten), it is clearly in itself a strugle for pttStigl:
between the two kinp. MinDI is grmted by his father Zeus a favourable
sign which confirms his divine de.cent; Thcseua has to obtain a similar
sign &om his father Poseidon - and get it he docs, after divine into the
water. Such an ordeal of diving into the sea is well known elsewhere
and might have done perfectly by itself. But it is motivated in the story
by a quite extraordinary challcnac: by Minoa which was not indisperuabk
- indeed IO dispensable that it does not even figure in our primary
source - and which for that reason ad.Yffliscs itself the moft' loudly:
Minos throws his ring into the sea and bids Theseus rmd it.u
So one ru1t clement to note is the l'Olc of thc,ring in a situation
involving a competition in royalty: the test is unilateral in Polycratcs's
case, bilateral here; but there is a test in each: it is the power or a tyrant
that is in the balance a, it is the authenticity of royalty that is in ques·
tion, the same act and the same object arc the substancr of a ritual.
But it is an.other story about a marvellous ring which enables us to
approach nearer to the impo~ or the symbol in the 1yrant'1 talc: the
story of GY1~•'s ring in the form which Plato is the fint to pc us
(Republic 3, !159d-!160c}.11 A shepherd in the service of one of the
k.inp of Lydia, Gyp FU into an underground cave by way uf an
opening which auddenly appears; and there he discl>'len inside a bru.n
hone a naked corpse wearing a ring on its fin1Jer, He takes thc ring uwl
makes his way out. He ditcoven tha1 if be turns the collct towaids him,
be becomes invisible. He takes advantage: of this to murder the king and
take the throne.
The ring here is the means of obtaining royal 1taws by rcmse, .. in a
story which even in Plato prc:1ervcs its most traditional clements (111:urdier
of 0M'1 predecessor and 19arriall" to the queen). But panted that we
arc in the kingdom of Lydia, which is often belic¥cd to hiwc iuued lhc
fint money,• Uld where d,e incident iuclf is ,mer.-lly n:prded II
having taken place in die quasi·historicaJ period of tbc ICYfllth century,
the really tip.ificant clcmenl is what pve1 the narntive its pcctdial
124
'Va:Ju,.' in Grulc myth
flavour. The csaential put of Gyge:s's ring is the collct. The collet it
what holds the seal in place (cf. now Cassin, 1960: 742-50); and Poly-
cratcs•1 rin1, and even Minos•s sometimes, is called a 'seal'. The rin1
fitted with an engraved stone is an important object in Greece from
Mycenaean times, the sort of thina; a prince takes with him to his tomb
(Bruclr., 1926: 8). We Ir.now that the seal wu employed from very early
times in Near·Eastcm civilizations. Both facts allow us to infer that the
seal was used relatively culy in Greece; it is at any rate cenain that the
seal is directly related to the earliest coinl - it is the antecedent of the
struck. coin (MacDonald, 1905: 43-52). It signifies, or rather marks,
ownership, and as such is endowed with a special a.ura that was orig·
inally magical. 27
It was in an underground cave - what the Greeks though of as a
'trC'asure·house' - that Gygcs found his ring, his magic carpet to wealth
and power; and, masked by a rationalizing context that ultimately
makes it look a little childish, Polycratcs's ring seems to be a charged
'sign' of wealth held and used by a tyrant. For what is special about this
precious object in the Samian talc is that it can be used as a bet in an
enormous wager in which all the power of its owner is at stake:
Polycratcs throws it into the sea - •so that it can never more return
among men', as Herodotus has his adviser say. But will the gift be
accepted? - it is not, Polycrates fails to secure the favour or legitimacy
that he wanted. It was not inappropriate for the legend to have inter-
prrtcd this failure as a manifestation of nemesis: cucntially, it is the
outcome of an ordeal. The test is closely related to divination (so,
Saintyvcs, 1912: 68-76). 21 For in divination (where the use of the ring
pcnistcd) it is a bad sign when an object thrown into the water docs
not sink to the bottom but is 'sent back' (cf. Pausanias 3.2'.i.8 on the
method used by an oracle at a shrine in Laconia).
126
'Yalu,.• in G,,.,.1,, myth
the Oam•• (Pausanias 10.1.6; cf. Nil11on, 1906: 222-S). Rituals which
involve throwing things into the sea can be understood in the same
way: here we find the chariot and team u the focu1 of the 'sacrifice'
(Festus, s.v. Octob., •quus (p. 190, 28-30 Lindsay: Rhod<s]
Pausaniu 8.7.2 (Argos]; S.rvius, in v..,.1. Georg. 1.12: (3, p. lH
10-12 Thilo: lllyrians)) - that is, lhc special sisn of sup<rabundant
wealth: the chuiot itself, whose mythical 'charge' I scarcely need to
recalli and the hones (sometimes still in harness), which only figure in
sacrifice in the classical period on a small number of special occasions
as everyone knows. but which ue reserved in the le~ndary tradition
for the most sumptuous sacrificial occuions which have no doubt lost
nothing in the tclling.12
Whether we take flamboyant sacrifices of an exaggerated kind or the
ring, cup, or tripod cut into the seai whether the sacrifice be a holocaust
or focus upon a single symbolic object, it signals, in a whole gamut of
rituals and legends, the destruction of wealth. But I have a feeling that
at the level of myth the word 'destruction' is only a gesture towards the
truth. lt means, among other things, that the act is not necessarily
dirl'ctl'd: one might even argue that it docs not in principle involve the
idea of a god to whom it is offered; in the legendary tradition at any
ntc it excludes that notion almost rx laypothl'1i: there can be no qucs·
tion of it in the extreme cue of Polycrate1 (cf. Stengel, 1920: Jl!S),
any more than in the story of Helen's tripod. But if the act is not
directed, it has a purpose. And it is here that the mythical view is most
plainly to be apprehended.
Polycratcs's ring was not supposed to return to the human world; but
such a thought opposes the human world to some other. One might
even say that it presupposes it. .
It is a constant theme of religious thinking that to destroy somcthmg
can never mean that it simply ceases to exist. Of course we have to
consider that point in relation to its concrete consequences. And for
my present purposes, a rather odd story told us by Herodotus cou~d be
at least suggestive. Note that it too come, from a lcFnd conccmmti a
tyrant: the legend of Periandcr or Corin~. (Herodotus !> ••9211.l·-~)-
Periandcr consults an oracle of the dead (1t u perhaps nut 1mmatcnal
that he should have consulted it about a lost hoard which cannot be
found); his dead wife, Melissa, appears but refuses to tell him where i~ is
hidden because she is cold and naked: fur the clothes that were buned
with her arc useless because they had not been consumed in the funeral
flam.cs. Hearing this, Pcriandcr calls all the townswomen, decked in
their finest apparel, to a shrine, whither they proceed 'u though they
127
LmusGemet
were off to a festival'; on« there, he has them stripped ~y his ~els.
All the clothes arc burned, and Melissa's ghost gives him the mfor-
ma;i:; :::;:~~~e focus is clcu from the story iue1£. We know th~t the
institution of grave-goods wu not done away with by the practice of
cremation; indeed, for the dead to remain in possession of the goods he
takes with him because they uc 'part of him', they must be- burned
with him:H the very fact that they are destroyed by the names mcanc
that they are guaranteed to the dead man. But in Herodotus's story
this idea is slightly altered: its purpose is in some degree novel, le11
well defined in intention, especially with reprd to the substan« of
the offering. No doubt Melissa is the beneficiary; but the sacrifice -
monstrous, u befits a tyrant, and quite out of proportion to iu
immediate purpose - is, actually, directed towards the world of the
dead which was the only consideration in the M:ginning and of which
the ghost of Pcriander's wife is only one member. Morcovc,; the a.ct
itself - and this is basic to the story - has lhc character of a gigantic
holocaust whose particular object is these typical symbols of opulence,
and for which the finest clothes of all the townswomen arc not excess-
ive. Tyrants by definition amass goods in the l~st quantities; and
they excel at making their subjects' property their own. But thesc
goods, and above all t.hne valuables, can be used 'to some purpoK if
their conspicuous destruction ~rvcs another world. Periandcr has his
models: a tyrant in legend must follow the rules laid down by myth.
Those rules can be pieced to~ther, by pursuing the different stories:
we have several ways of gcttinK at them. Somewhat differently, the
theme of things not consumed but which disappear from view ~vols
its original significance in the legend about the early history of Cyrcne.
h docs not concern an ogalma, a focus of 'value', but an object which
is simply poucssed of magicaJ power and nothing else. But it too is
related to a typical agolma in terms of iu {unctions, l th.ink.
In the course of their voyage the Argonauu readied North Africa;
they were received hospitably by the marine di~inity Triton, to whom
in exchange they gave a tripod (Herodotus 4.179.2) or in another ver-
sion a gold crater. But we arc also told that Triton himKlr pve one of
the Argonauts, Euphl:mos {Euphamos in Pindar), a clod of earth,
bOlos (Pindar, Pythion 4.20-3 Snell). At fint sight thetc two facu
seem quite unrelated nen though they arc both given us by old vcr·
sions: if we find that in the later t.radition the gifts arc reciprocal and
related to each other (Apollonius of Rhodes, A,pnau#.b 4.1!<67-6!),
that is aurely not accidental; gift and countcr-gift have a rcciprodl
relation. The tripod, whose thematic undertones arc sugcsted by tlU'
golden crater which is its equivalent, is here a. guarantee of srcuri.ty for
128
'Valul'' in Grulc myth
the land wher< the recipient dwcU. (sec p. 119 above). The bolos (pa·
haps the lc~nd made it precisely parallel) guarantees to its ttcipien1 the
right to the land from which it was taken: we find it in thlt familiar
&ignificance in ,cvcral stories in Greece containing some trace of a ritual
of troditio pn ti•km (Nilsson, 1951-60c: 330-5). In the story about
E.uphi-mos, the bOlos contain, a magical power (mana) to help iu
owner. And to make this magical power cffcctivc, the bOlos has to be
thrown into the sea (Apollonius of Rhodes, Argon. 4.1755-7). Pindar
is more predsc (Pytltian 4.40-8): the proper time for their taking
possession of the land was delayed by the imprudence of Euphamos's
companions, who dropped the clod of earth into the sea in the wrong
place; they should have dropped it off Cape Tacnarum, in one of the
entrances to the underworld. M
When you throw a magic object into the sea, you know what you art-
up to. It is a pcnistent theme: but its recurrence in legends about
a,alm.ota docs not mean that a Greek had to have a specific awareness
of the imaginatiw 'field' which they once occupied. It is enough for an
imaginative scheme to endurt. And their value in myth is revealed again
in another set of motifs, which arc, as it were, the mirror-image of the
preceding one.
......
analogy is the more striking in that the objects involved att oot tM
For all tha.t it Mloogs to what is generally called history, the 'Kc:·
ond MeMCnian ww' is myth-stuff: Ariltomcnet, the nuiopal hero, is
known by virtue of a tradition o[ popular cpit::1. We havr seen that hiis
shield was supposed to be able to destroy I.he enemie-1 ol t.lenenia
snenl centuries after his death (p. 120). Thil shield.._ 11 history.
U-0
'Valtu 'in G~~• myth
A.rl,tomcnea lost lt in a battle - rather mysterioully (it wu taken by
!be Dioocuri). The DelpN< oracle MlviKd him to go down into the
underground ahrinc of Trophoniua in order to get it back. And
Aristomencs did indeed get his shield backi and with it he performed
mitbrier feats o( anns than ever (Pautanias 4.16.7). Trophonius wu a
hero who ran an oracle. How was hit intervention supposed lo havr·
worked?
The same question might spring to mind in an epi.Jode in the
Bcllcrophon legend - this time, in connection with an agolma. Pindar
telk us tha.t the hero tried in nin to break in Pegasus, until Pallas
Athena gave him a golden bit; and immediately afterwards, we find
mention of a dream - or rather a dream which i1 reality - in which the
goddess gave him the bit (Olymptiin 13.65-86 Snell). And whcTc it all
happened the~ was a shrine of Athena Kholinitis ('of the bit') as whose
foundation-legend this story ,cNcs (Pausanias 2.4.l) ;while Bcllerophon 's
ex.pcricnce is treated as a story of divination by dream. But it was not
just a sign or an insight th.at the goddess gave: it was the bit itself. And
that helps us to undcntand what might have seemed odd about the
story of Aristomenes: Ariatomenes 'got his shield back from Tro·
phoniw's cave'; the gift of a god is given directly. The thing comes
from a world beyond which is as well the land of dreams as it is the
su.btCTTancan cave of an oracular hero.
For Bellcrophon, it i1 a matter of an object that is magical in that it
acu in a marvellous way. But honc·hamea.,e~cially bridle and bit, is
one of the most important items of warrior wealth; age-old trailition
demanded that it be buried with its owner; fine ex.a.mples were found at
Olympia in the Roman period during construction work (Pausaniu
5.20.8); Cimon of Athens, that perfect 'knight', solemnly and sym·
bolically made an offering of one on the Acropolas on the eve of the
battle of Salamis in 480 BC (Plutarch, Life of Cimon 5.2).
Like other mythical objects which are rel:.,.ted to them in the Greek
imagination. pucious objects, traditional symbols of opult'nce, arc-
ineluctably related - indeed, in a way espcda.lly related - to chat other
world pre-supposed by the ttligiou1 mind: now they go down to it, and
now they journey back.
The two kgcnds l ha~ ta.ken - and matched - arc evidence for a
relation betwectn the 1ymbol 0£ opulence and tht themes of confir-
mation or investiture o[ a kin@:, They alao enable us to glimpse, in the
mythical imagination, how this symbol works. It is associated, in the
story of the sons or Pclops, with the magical power of a form of kin@:·
ship characterized by its authority over the Sun. ln the story of Jason,
it is associated with the agrarian prosperity guaranteed by the exercise
of a sole ri@:ht to perform certain religious functions. And through these
stories, it is associated with a mythical and ritual back.Kfound involving
the idea of an effective concentration of agrarian wealth and pastoral
wealth in the penon of the king, and under his control: the enduring
rituals of the Boultoleion. at Athens, of the Cattle Byre bcsi~ which
was celebrated each year the marriage of Dionysus and the Queen
(Aristotle, Corutitution of the Athnaions 3.5], the special power
attributed to the sacred flocks, the special value - and the multifarious
implications - that one finda in the imagt: of the sacred or royal field
(which is actually where AietCs performed his exploit); all of this is evi-
dence for a way of thinking which I will here simply state, because the
really important question ii this: if the way in which the golden lamb
or the golden fleece arc represented is closely linked with the theme 0£
agrarian wealth, which is iuclf also connected with royal responsibility,
is not this form of representation simply the spontaneous and meaning·
less elaboration of a religious object which had a fundamental place in
the scenarios?
The composite character of the image iuclf is quite instructive. Why
a iolden fleece, and even more, why a golden animal? We do not need
to discuss the imprecisions and the contra.dictions of the legend: the
important point ii the fusion of two elements connotin1 wealth, wealth
in flocks and herds, and wealth in precious mctals -- the very sa.mc
clements which make up the mythical thcme studied long ~o b.,·
Uscner, and whose relationship and fusion, in the legend of Atreus and
that of Phrixos, he noticed (1899: 182-5). The theme i1 sufficiently
amenable to particular intentions to free it from the narrowing and the
coherence which it would have required i£ it were to stand by itsdl .1
plays in the midst of a set of cultural forms and pu':Po1e1 ~roi_n whi 1 Ii 11
cannot be extricated. Following the path of mythical dunk.mg, it will
travel in this direction or in that. Atttus locked the golden lamb in a
chest u be would have done with some meta.I object; in the case of the
im.; of the golden fleece, it ii once apin the id~a of preciow i_nc~l
which seems to dominate. Convencly, it is the ammaJ aapect wh1ch 1s
135
Luu:, Gernet
highlighted when the talisman of kingship is concrivcd particul~y M
coming from the royal flocks. But in truth the two elements, m tbc
golden Ocea, cannot be separated. It is odd to find, in a late dctcenclNI•
of ancient myth - a modem folk-talc from Epirus (~k: 1914--40:
1.412-14) - how, moft' or lea unconsciously, the assoaaaons of~d
and its proper power have insinuated themsdons into a ~ontczt With
whose framing they might have seemed to him: had nothmg to do. A
king's daughter hu been shut up in an underground palace: she mu1t be
found befott anyone can marry her; a young man hu himself 11:wn into
a sheepskin, sold to thit kins • a sheep, and succeed, in gettin1 to the
prl. The skin he coven tlimtclf with is a goldm fleece: the echo, or the
ft'miniscence, might seem forced. But the king's daughtC"r LI shut up just
like Danae and Zeus 101 to her in the guise of a shower of sald; sin«
the folk-talc speaks of a fleece, no doubt it wu a golden flc«c; and a
golden tleca naturally gMs underground, becau,c th.at is where some-
thing valuable belongs. Even within a contnl in which imapllatift
products are simply for plea.urc, the traditional •oc.iations continue
to play their part.
The term 'composite imap' is really only a label. lt is not a matter of
different imqes comin1 toacthcr; rather, of sevcr.J meaninp of a sinpit
collective representation which is, in the true ~cnte, u "plucic' as
necessary. I cannot here malyse all these mcaninp; but l ouP,t to
sketch them at least in outline, bcc:aulC' then: is no better W&')' of unda·
standing the constituentl of the notion of the.,.,...., which lia deep
behind the idea of the pldcn fleece.
1 start with something extremely old: one of the cults most ,-Ip.ably
archaic: is that of Zeus Aknios on Mount Pelion - close by the land of
Phrixos;4s his ministnnb each year wound their way in proccaion up
the mountain, wrap~ in the sir.ins of fre1hly-ucrificed runs; the ritual
wu performed at the time of the (heliacal) rising of Sirius, a crud.al
date which wu the focus of meteorological mqic in eua other than
this. Ritually, the bide of the sacrificial animal has special powen o[ all
kinds (Plcy, 1911); but the miraculous ftccce hu a special ttlation to a
dau of objects in myth wbo.c meaning is fairly apparent. lnsofu • the
animal-hide can be used u defensive armour, h i1 map:al annom Wen
it is the famous ufis: when uxd by Zeus, it tprads panic lilr.e a NpCr·
natural force. But Zeus may use it differnlly: when he. thakes it 1ikr an
Arcadim 'rain·maker' (cf. Vil)il, Anuid 8.351-4), it inOwencea the *Y
and the atmosphere. II. also, even when wielded by Athena. hu I.he
power to make thinp fertile. The«,U isa pl-tkin: the SOU. A.mahhea.
which suckled Zeus, i1 usually a bcneraccnt creature, one of her horn.
became the horn ef abundance (the conauc. . .), m4 P"M• •
IS&
'Value' in Gr,elc myth
mythical name for a number of other symbols of agrarian prosperityi
but it is sometimes a Lerrifying beut, and had to be 'hiddcn •: iu hide
provided Zeus with a weapon when he undertook the farnoua war
~ • t the Titans after whose conclusion he founded a new monarchical
ord<r ([Eratosthenes), Cowterismi 13, pp. 98-100 Roben). But the
Chimera, the monster defeated by Bcllerophon, ii also, as its nune
reveals, the Goat: it seems tha.t, in its homeland Lycia, the Chimera was
a shield-d,vice (Radcnnachcr, 1938: 97;cf. Maiten, 1925: 125-9). The
lamb at Argos may have been one (Fraztt, 1898: 3.187): a stone ram
stood ·on a tomb in the plain of Argos which was known as the 'tomb of
Thycstes' (Pausanias 2.18.1).
These observa.tions, few as they iltt, suggest at least a context of
imagery: the notion of 'royal' potency which I have shown to have
been associated with the representation of the fleece in myth may seem
multifarious and almost endlessly ramified. It has nonetheless, far back
in time, a sort of unity which the symbol's very plasticity sometimes
enables us to glimpse. The link between sold and the Sun - which
indeed specially 5allctifita royal power - ii particularly close in the
legend of Ai~tCs, lung of a mythical East: it appears somewhat differ-
ently, more opaque but more suggestive, in the story of Atreus. Further·
more, the fleece is not always 'golden'; sometimes it is purple: in
Etruscan divination, the appearance of an animal of this colour {or of
gold] in a flock or herd is the presagr of a new dispensation which will
be an age of prosperity and fertility (Macrobius, SotMmolio ,. 7.2).
Amid all the variations produced by the working of the imagination,
this fact, which takes us back to a tradition of 'Aegean' beliefs, fits
pcrlcctly, even in its ex.pression, with the idea revealed directly in the
legendary history of Mycenae.
But there i, an interesting shift. Pindar, one or our sources with tht'
most highly developed sense of myth, mentions 'the shimmering flrt"ce
with tassels of gold' (l';tltion 4.231; imitated by Apolloniut or Rhodes,
Argonauh'lca 4.1142 Frinkel). "Tassels or gold' is a detail Homer note,
in a description of Athena's aegis (Iliad 2.447-9). And Ho~er tt'lls.us
how many there were, and how much they wert' worth. It IS a dr1c~1p·
tion of a ritual vestment, this; borne by the goddess herself, the obJe, l
is the locus or all manner of qualities, including beauty illld 'valur' I i,1·
manner in which the fleece is presented in myth is evolving inu, .ui
image of an agolma even while it preserves, as it were, Its malcnJ.l
subi.tance.
This imaginative shift which is neverthclen qualified by a relative
penistence of the mythical symbol is a q~ite genrral phmome~on: we
can see its analogue in relation to real oLJt:cts or wht:n real actJons are
157
l.(.ui"GC'met
performed. Kings in kgends or in epic c ~ a seep~ (Ixubntr, 193,:
85) which is both sign and in1trumtot of the11 authonty: at Homer putt
it, there resides in it something of the power of Zeus, the fount of_royal
power. There is actually a necessary connection bttwttn the btmng of
the sceptre and the power of uttering themistes, pr~nounc_ements _and
judgcmenu, like those of the oracles: the sccpttr 1s ceru,m~y dcnved
from thc prophet's staff, itself cut from a tree s«:t a.pvt by lU natural
capacity for divination. But thc king's sceptre came to be made by a
craftsman: the sceptre given by Zeus to the house of Pclops was
fashioned by Hephaestus, the divine smith. And it of course ended up
made of gold. Yet in that object made of metal - costly m_etal :--- there
endurcs a magical quality akin to that once stored in a quite different
material. Conversely, thc practice of ma.king offerings sometimes rcvea4
a continuity of function in which one can observe the same uansition:
for example, the anathima comes to replace the offering which is
dc,troycd. The anathima is a reproduction of the offering in pn-ciow
metal: a typical example is the sheaves made of gold consecrated by a
number of cities at Delphi (Plutarch, De PythiM oraculis 16, 401f-
402a; [Suabo 6.1.15: 264C]; Rouse, 1902: 66 n. 3); one, Metapontum,
was to keep thc symbol on its coins. And of course it is sacrificial ani-
mals that we find rC'prescntcd, cspccially in gold: and it is quite pttdict-
able that the legendary tradition should happen to pre~rvC' a parallel
substitution in thc case of thc golden lamb of thc house of Pelops
(Antiklcidcs, FGrH 140 F 8 ["' Scholiast on Ari,tophanes, Cloud, 144,
p. 88.39-45 Di.ibncr) ).
All this is evidence for what, failing a more satisfactory term -
bccause in reality thC're is continuity too - I will call 'd.itplaccment'
(transfert): the samc thematic field. sometimes tht samc ttatC"S of feel·
ing and thC' sam.C' attitudes, arC' C'Vokcd or intimated by an object which
is dC'C'mcd identical but which ncvcrthcless is characterized by funda·
mentally ncw aspccts. And it is of course here that we can sec the
transition to the full notion of value taking place: we find evidence of
this in the case of one of the ob~cts employed in religious 'tra<k ', aod
which we also find as the object of human exchange u an .,aim., with
the kind of evocations we saw in tht motif of the golden fleece; and i,
is not what we might have" e1pC'ctC'd. In temple-inventories we some·
times find mC'otion of a 'golden vine' (Homollc, 1882: 146 (from thc
Artcmision at Delos)). ThC' displacf"mcnt hC"re is o( the same order ..
that in thc cue o( the golden com~an. for ex.111Dple. The ordinary
vine-stock is to be found in a number of rituals and myths, linked itself
to a dcn5C" group centred upon the motif of thc fruit-trtt planted or
cruted by a god or a hcro; and I.ht:: entire group is related to myths
about kingship, and indced to the mc-morics of tttniltios which peni.ft
U8
'Valut' in Grtd myth
in enduring rituals. This thematic compln. extends into the golden
analogu.e. It is a golden vine-stock which ensures the recognition of two
heroes [Thoas and Eune01}. sons of Jason and grandsons of Thoas;
and Thoas received it from Dionysus god of the vine. It has. at a deci1ive
moment. to be '1hown', to be 'set forth'; it opcrat« as a hereditary
talisman.44 Yet we also fmd the same object as an ago.Ima proper. One
of the clearest illwtrations of the coercive force of the gift is offered by
m episode at the end of the Trojan War: in order to obtain military
assistance from his nephew, his sister's son, Priam sends his 1istcr a vine
with golden leaves and silver grapes made by Hephaestus; it had been
th< payment for the rape of Ganymede (Robert, 1920-6, 3.2.1, 1222-
3). It is a fine ex.ampk of the theme of 'gifts to a woman' (Odyssey
11.521); and the story unfolds in the same manner as that of Eriphyle's
necklace (p. 121 above).
The object created by labour that represt"ts a thing endowed with
magical properties, and which we have seen to have acted as a. talisman,
is here the same as the object in which economic value inheres.
We have to do with a sort of projection of the ideal notion in the
other world on to the plane 0£ human life: treasure is real enough
socially - an institution indeed; but it is also real enough in myth. It is
both a social reality and a mythic reality. And the notion of 'treasure'
involves also the place in which it is kept.
Hermann Usener quitr rightly pointed out the link between the
legend of the golden fleece and the motif of the storehouse. And of
course, since its double significance as talisman and as 'value' is quite
apparent, the object is kept by AiCtt:s in his palace, by Atreus locked in
a chest. By definition the symbol of opulence is something more or less
concealed: its magical properties cannot be divorced from a degree of
necessary secrecy. Certainly it must on some occuions be 'let out',
unlike pailaduJ, which arc ultra-secret; but thal d()('s not mean that they
arc not related to objects which i;ruarantee protection just as palladia do
and which arc, convcncly, represented in legend from time to time in a
way which recalls an object kept in a treasury. The bronze hydn"a which
contained a lock. of Medusa's hair, the guarantee of a royal city's sa£cty,
suggests a whole rangr of associations, in which the notion of opulence
alternates or combines with that of magical power (ApoUodorus,
Bibliotheca 2.7.3 [cf. Pausanias 8.47.51).
Precious thin~ arc often underground: a hoard at Delphi, which .\~,1.~
discovered by miraculous means, had been buried. But it is th1ni,:s
endowed with a. power which is now 'political', now rcliRious. that arc
buried in the earth: the knife used in the sacrifice which scaled a pact
(Euripides, Suppliant Women 1205-9); the arrow of Apollo, .hidden in
the land of the Hyperborearn and made of gold, but .ilso a s1pt of the
139
l..,(,uisGemet
ki,;:itimacy of the prophet Abaris ((Eratosthe11n], Cahlrte~~j 29, P·
154 Robut; cf. Delcourt, 1938: 89 n. 1);41 the Atgonau.ts tnp~;thC'
goat Amal the a; the thunderbolt or Zeus granted ~im on ~· acces:11on al
the symbol and as the guarantor of hil authonty (Hcuod, Tlteogon}'
146
8. The Black Hunter and the origin of the
Athenian ephebeia 1
Pierre Vidal-Naquct (1968, 1979)
To Al.I. Firtlry
We l&aH IIHft "o,A ...,•
It'• .e '1nrd1-subd,r u tl&C' fo• for ,wry,
Liu ..,.,,ilH ., Me •olf for IUMt IN' nt;
0... Niau!' i, to c"'- wh•t flW, , .•
SlldHfN.-e, Cymbelint J.J.J9- 42
148
The Bladt. Huntnand the on.gin ofth~ Arhe,iian ephebeUI
oath which mak~ them full hoplitcs. they mention the boundary-stones
which 1epuate Athens• territory from her neighboun'. But with the,e
stones ltt u1ociated wheat, barley, vines, olive,, fig·trce1 - in a word,
the world of cultivation (Daux, 1965: 78-90; cf. J. and L. Robert,
1966, 362-3 no. 16~).
A 1hon discussion of a non-Athenian poetic text may make it easier
to understand this. The finest evocation of the duality of the Greek
cphcbc is no doubt the Jason of Pindar's fourth Pythian ode. Pclias, the
old king of lolcus, was appointed to 'die by the hands of the noble sons
of Aeolus or their unrelenting schemes':
l! lrJ<,&,w• AloMS<i,, 9...i,- x<i·
p~aou, ti tk,u~ la:t,IQ,µffot(' (72-! Snell)'
He had been warned to beware 'at all costs the man with one sandal'
who should pass from •a lofty retreat' to 'the sunny plain' - 'stranger
be he or townsman' (ffUIIX ai.'T'W11 b:ank: 75-7). And indeed Jason
comes from afar off where he had been brought up, in wild nature, by
Chiron the centaur and his daughten. He is a foreigner, and received as
such, but also a citizen, speaking of himself as such to his fellow·
citizens: J<f6K>i ,ro>.in:a, ~pQaaari ll°' aa+Ewt ( 117). He is a qualified
cphebe twenty years old, ambiguous, with two javelins, and dressed
both in the clothing of Magnesia but also in the leopard-skin of the wild
man:
lo6a< 6
a. ff Mcrp,,1rr'-JII·-·pa,.."''"·
ht)(Wpca( t,p,,0 -
Cowa:8CIITJ'TO'Ol 1UIOL(,
a,,f( 61 ,rap6(>Alq c,r.-,ero fpiaoo,m,, ~ - (79-8 l)
... and a twofold ,uiR wu on him.
A tunic of Map.nian fuhion fined doK hit mq,uficent limbs,
and acroe, it a panther'• hide hdd off the lhiv'erin1 rairu.
(tr. LattiP1orc)
The hair which the Athenian ephcbc cut as a mark of entry into man·
hood still hangs down his back (82-3).
This prolonged adolescence takes us away from the world of social
reality and into the realm of myth. Let us_ re~~ to _Athens, ~here the
ephebe's ambiguity - at the level now of its uutJtut1onal rul1ty ~ can
be seen as double. As Jules Labarbc saw (1953: _58-9~), there w:e~c
really two ephcbic structures: the official epliebel4, wh.1ch was a ~lVlC
military service, and a more archaic one throu_gh_ wh1cl~ ~ne_ gai~ed
admission to the phratry. Hence the cxpreuion ep1 d,etrs hebesa1, which
means (1) to be an ephcbe in the civic sense, that is, lo have rca~hed the
age of eightcen;a.nd(2),as the literal sense suggesU, to have att.1.med the
hibi to have been an ephcbe for two ycan (cf. Labarbc, 1957: 67-n;
Pe&Ck.idis, 1962: 51-65). Labarbe showed that the firn rphebeia was
marked ritually by the sacrifice of the A:ourt>ion (the youn~ man's long
149
Pierre Vidal-Naquet
hair) at the ai;:e of sixteen. I may add that in one case at lust admission
to the phratry was not ratified until one year.had dapsed from the dat~
of the offering of the hair (Sylloge 3 921, Jines 27-~ (s: Sokolowski.
1969: no. 19, with bibliography - the so-called 'Ruling of the Demo·
tionidae')). . .
The sacrifice of the hair took place at the time of the Koureotu, the
third day of Apatouria, the great festival celebrated by the phrat~es
of the Ionian world, which took place in the month Pyaneps1on
(September-October). This month was marked by a series of festi,,als
which have been shown, by Jeanma..ire in particular (1939), to havt'
been festivals celebrating the re-tum of the young men from the cam·
paigns of the summer. And it was through studying the aetiological
myth connected with the Apatouria that I was led to formulate the
ideas presented here.
The myth is known from a large number of texu dating from the
fifth century BC right down to the Byzantines Michel Psellos and
Johannes Tzetzes, who are of course simply resuming older sources.
The texts do not for the most part come from the principal ar :ient
works of literature or history; though alluded to by Strabo and
Pausanias, it is recounted only by Konon (an extremely obscure Hellen-
istic mythographer), Polyaenus and Frontinus; otherwise it is a matter
of scholiast1' remarks and entries in ancient lexica.,' In view 0£ the 1tate:
of the sources, it is hardly possible to define an 'ancient' and more
recent versions of the story, and l will therefore try to indicate the
most important variants.
The scene is the frontier between Athens and Boeotia: an eschatia,
mountainous areas that arc the 'end' of a city's territory, and whosc-
inhabitants arc always at loggerheads with their neighbours over the
border. Such places existed on the borden of al.I Gttdt states (Robat,
1960: 304-5, esp. 304 n. 4). They were the tenain of hunters and
shepherds, frontier zones constantly in dispute. And they ~re necess·
ary to Greek cities if only for training the young 10}dien for war (the
ritual nature of which training has been demon,trated by Bttlich, 1961;
cf. Gar)an, 1975: 29-31).
A conflict broke out between the Athellians •d the Boeotian•. In
some venions, over On\~ and Panactoo, in others OftT the frontier
dcmc Mela..inai. The fourth.century hiltorian Ephorus (quoted by
Hupokntion) says that the dispute WU lw.pn th ~ c1'onu:
'over an area called Melania'. I will obscrtt linll~y thM at Panacton
th~ was an annual sacrifice to mark the Apatounl (Syl1op3 485 ).
The Boeotian king was Xanthos (or Xanthiot, oc x.n~as), which
meam 'the fair one'. The Athenian king was Thymoitct, the lut of the
descendants of Theseus. It wu agreed to sc-ttlr the d'i,pv«: by means of
ISO
Th• Bt.d H•nt,r and th, orifin of th, Athmian ,ph,b,ia
a duel, a monomachia. But Thymoitcs stood down, according to a
scholia.tt on Aristophanes's Frop and another on Aeliu1 Ari1tcidc1'1
,-.tlinuiicw. because he was too old. Another warrior came forward
and was, according to some vcnions, promised the succession in return.
His name wu Melanthoa (or Melanthioa), 'the black one'. So the Black
One was to fight the Fair One.
Ai they were fighting, Melanthos suddenly cried out, 'Xanthos, you
do not play according to the rules ( ou"'9iJKCrL) - there is someone at
your side!' - and as Xanthos looked round in surprise, Mclanthos took
his chance and killed him. The sources dirtcr over details of what
happened. Polyacnus and Frontinus say it wu a ruse pure and simple;
Halliday compares it to Tom Sawyer's trick when he cries out 'Look
behind you Aunty' and thus escapes the beating she was about to
administer (1926: 179). The Luica S,p,riano makes Melanthos pray
to Zeus .ApathaOr (Zrus 'of wiles1. Most mention Dionysus's inter·
vention - Dionysus Melonaigis, 1of the black goatskin'; and Plutarch
(Quaesiion,-s conviviales 6. 7 .2, 692e) says that Dionysus Ml'lana1gis and
Nu,ierinos ('of the night') was wonhippcd at Eleuthcrac (that is, not
far from Panacton). 19 Afterwards, the victor Melanthos became king of
Athens.
In every source, the Apatouria is explained by paronomastic ety-
mology. The festival is supposed to commemorate this apaii ('wile',
'deception'), whether the inspiration of the deception is ascribed to
Dionysus, to Zeus or to Mclanthos himself .11 The sources offer this
explanation even though the scholiast on Aristophanes's Ac:laanuGns
146, as well as the grammarian quoted by the Suda s.v. )\wcrrOU_Pca:,
knew an explanation which is more or lea conect: A.poiouna ""
Homopoioria ( 'Ol'ft'cn-dplO). Nowadays we would ~~ that th~ a of
~•m-OVpca: is a copulative: the festival of the Apatouna IS thc_fest1val of
those who have the •same father' - in other words, the festival of the
phratries.
Over the years, there have naturally been many attempts to explain
this myth. Finl of coune historically - many such_, from Jo1hannes
TOpffcr's AUisclae Genealogie (1889: 225-4_1) t~ Fd1x Jac~by s great
commentary on the Atthidographen, the historians of ~tuca. We an
usured that Mclanthos wu a historical pcnonagc, ~ Ncle1d, the father
of Codrw who, thanks to anotherapali (disguising himself as a pcasan~),
managed tu gel himself killed and thus ensured the _safety of A1!'ens m
accordance with the oracles' prophecy. Melantho1 &S also dcscnbed as
the 'ancestor' of the phratry of the Mcdontidac. ~ttemp~ havr cv~n
been made to pinpoint the 1tury's date - Wilamo'_"lt;i put 1l not carhcr
than 508 BC, because the frontier was o~ly estabhshe~ then ( 1955-7:
5.1, 22 n. 2). And Jacoby, while not deny mg the mythical nature of the
151
Picr'!"C Vidal·Naquct
story, cnvilagrd the pouibility or a real frontier akinnish (FGrH Sb
Suppkmcnt 2: 50 (on 323a P 2SJ). .
But it was Hermann Uscncr who fint attempted to prorick an overall
explanation of the myth. 11 He pointed out that this Wiii. a due.I bctwttn
the Blaci and the Fair, as a few ancient mthon realized: P~lyarnus
quotes or invt:nts, an oracle- given bdore the- encounter, which run1:
n;., ~r,-, TElifa( b JAEA11t "'°"°., faxE M f ~ 'Having wrou~lt the
death of the fair one the black one seized McJainai.' (Mela"not mnn•
"the black country'. J Usena 11.w the duel in 1ymbolic term,, as a ritual
combat between winter and summer, an intcrptttarion wrlcomcd by,
among othen, Lewis FamcU (1909: :dvii; 1896-1909: 5.U0-1), A.B.
Cook (1914-40, 1.619) ond Herocrt RDK (1961, Ul-S)." But it
fails to explain what nttds to be explained: the link between the duel
and the festival itself. The umc applies to Nilnon whe:n, in a Yariant of
the theory, he su•s•cd that this agon ('contest') linked with tM wor-
ship of Dionysus w• one of thc earliest forms of tragedy ( 195 l-60a:
1.61-110.111-16).
Many years later. in COM:roi~t Cou,.;u,, Henri JeanmaiR offm:d an
entirely different view (19.59: 382-!). He saw the duel Mtween.
Xanthos and Melanthos as a ritual joust. pcrhap, followed by a pro·
cnlion, throupl which a claimant to ~ throne dcclattd himself
master of the tclTitory, The name of Melanthos i1 replaced in Pautani.u
9.~.16 by that of Andropompos ('the Leader of die procession'). and
according to Plutarch (C:ZU-,tio,a~s ,,.«u U, 294b-c) it Wiii in a
similar way - a duel inYOlving a trick almo1t identical with oun - that
Ph.mtlu1, king of the Acnianians, e1tablilhed his claim to the valley of
the Inachus. It also recalls the funous - lclffldary - bank between
PittakOI and Phrynon at the time of the war over Sigeum bctwffn
Athms ond Mytilene (Will, 1955, 581-5).
But to my knowledge only Angelo Brclich hu really artcmptcd to
eKplain the poniblc ttlation,hip between this myth and the
Apatouria, the festival of the phratric1 during which the ephebcs wtte
received into the phntry after consecrating tMir hair (1961: 56-9). 14
In particular, he stresses the frequency with which duels between young
men take place in frontier·districll and ol»rrvet that Diouytut {whom
he identifies with Dionysu1 Mcl.nfli,U) is dacribcd sometimet u '-ibdJI
('with his beard stuting to grow'). But he Caile to puth his illtc,prewion
much further tha.n this.
For my part, I wa ltNcl by tbrtt pointt which 1C4plir~ c•planatiorn.
First, that lh.c 1tory takes place in the frontier rqion,just u i1 i, 10 t,bc
frontier dw tbe Athenian cphebc1 lllff sent. md that in-their oadl they
swear to protect the boundary-1tunc:1 or their country. The secoad
point is the 1tory11 1tre11 on the 4fMli, the- trick. Why 1hould · *
152
Tht Blac• Hcmttrand the ongin oftht Athenian ,ph,btia
~ have been offered a model of behaviour quite contrary to that
wbic,b. thty swear in their oath to observe? We have single-handed com-
11ot· (*ot,i>muhia) and trickery, contrasted with fair hoplite-fightins on
even tenns. (Let it be noted in passing that the very name Melu1tho1
~ .probably evocative for a reader of Homer: just as Dolan is the
oriininl wolf in the Iliad (Gemet, 1968b: 154-71) so in the Odyss<'J
Melmthios or Mclanthcus is a treacherous goatherd (17.212, 22.1.59,
161, 182 etc.) and his sister Melantha is a truchcrous servant (18.
;21-2). Their father is called Dolios, 'the cwming onc'.) 15 Thirdly, I
was struck by the stress on black in the story (mtla.s (adj.), stem
mt'4n·). We find the name Mclanthos, the location, which in some texts
is c::allcd Mclainai, and Dionysus of the Black Goatskin (Mtlantugis).
And this is not the only occurrence of an association bt:twccn the
Athenian cphcbes and the colour black: at least on certain solemn
occasions, they wore a black chlamys (a short cloak) which was rt-
placcd, thanks to the generosity of Herodes Atticus, by a white one in
the second century AD."
In his discussion of the inscription which provides us with this last
item of information (/G 111 3606), Pierre Roussel showed that tht
black chlamys was suppo~d to commemorate Theseus's forgetfulness:
that cphebc of ephebcs forgot to change the black sails on his ship for
white ones on his return from Crete (after killing the Minotaur). But
aetiology is not explanation; and George Thomson understood this
black. garment as a sign of ritual exclusion (1941: 107). And there is
certainly something very peculiar about this predominance of black -
we have only to refer, for txamplc, to Gerhard Radkc's conscientious
catalogue (1936; cf. Morcux, 1967: 237-72) to undcrst~d just ~ow
startling, indeed shocking, a ritual victory for .black might be 1~ a
festival celebrating the entry of young men into the commumty.
1t may help to formulate these problems ~ore p~eci~tly_ if l n~w
digress in order to discuss the Spartan lcrypt~w.,. an mst1tu_t1on which
has often been compared to the Athenian epla~b~. and which, though
it involved a much smaller number of young men, was indeed paralltl to
it in somt respects. It is well known that we have a very small number
of sources for the ltrypteia. 1 " But the scholiast on Plat~'.s Laws_ 1, 633b
says explicitly that it was a preparation for the m1.htary .. hfe. And
KOchly argued as early as 1835 {following Karl Otfncd .Muller)_ that.
this tn..ining was to be compared to that of the Ath~1an prnpolo1
([Muller, 1844, 2.302); Koehly, 1881-2, l.587-8); a point made •ve.n
more clearly by Ernst Wachsmuth, ~ho lucidly observed that tht~
military apprenticeship took the speaal form of a helot-hunt (1846.
1.252; 2.304)." ) l 'd d h
A brilliantarticlebyHenriJcanmai~(l91S: 121-50 euc1 ate t e
U3
Pierre Vidal·Naquet
fundamental characteristics of the ltrypteia by muns of comparuon
with certain African societies: compulsory isolation or ccn.ain ~~I
men around the time of puberty; living in the bmb; ncn ~c ~ p
of helots - all of these can be panllelcd. in black Afnca, m the
initiation-cettmonies and secret societies of Wolf·mcn and Panthcr·men..
But if that is so, what of the military l'Ole of the Ji,yp1N? Jcanrnairc's
reply wu unequivocal: 'the whole of Spartan military history cries out
apimt. the idea of t.urning the Spartiatc hoplitc into a tnckcr in the
bush domberi"I aver R>Cks and walls' (p. 142). And he added wryly
that 0if the lrryptft/11, with its camping-out by nipt in the mountains,
had really been a training for military life at the time of the battle of
Thcrmopylae (480 BC), Epbialtes's path (by which the Pcnian1 sur-
prised the Spartans) would have been discovered and parclcd..
To my mind Jeanmaitt wu both profoundly right and profoundly
wrong. What he failed to understand was that the lnyptN WU by no
mean, completely unrelated to the life of the hoptitc: for ,ryprN and
the hoplite life were symmetrical opposites. If we make a list from what
the sources &eU us, we get the following remit:
(1) The boplite is armed to the teeth; the youth in the ltrypta. is
gumt1os, which means either that he carried. no arms at all (Scholiaill
on Plato's Laws l, 65!b) or that he had only a dlllJl'CT (Plutucb.,
L;f• of Ly<"'f'U 28.2).
(2) The member of the pltMan:c is opposed to the'youth on hill own or
living in a smaU group.
(!) The fighter in the plain ii opposed to the youth who runs wild ia
die mountain,.
(4) Plato's youth in the ltryptria did his tninin1 in the middle of
winter; the hoplitc, according to Thucydidn, fought in sununn (cf.
WOKQ{p1 in Modern Greek).
(5) The tna1tworthy hoptitc: chttnd on by Tyrtacus (7th cent. BC) is
opposed to the cunnin1 killer of helot1.
(6) The man who fightl in the liKf'it of day is oppoaed to the youth who
fiahts by nipL
(7) The Scholiast on Plato's UJws u.ys that the youth in the Jt,yptftd
ate whatever he could lind, living from hand to mouth, probably
without ever findinc time to have anything cooked; whe'"5 lh•
hoplite is above aU a member of a common narss, the: ~s,itioN.
(8) The mcmben of the ltryptcil, stayed UI the uu1 which became. in a
scn1e, the frontim, of enemy territories - for the Ephon anually
declared war on the Mlots in a ritual comparable to tbe Romu
dedara.tion o[ war by the Fctial,s. 1• (By C011trut, the: full boplite1
were obliacd to remain, in peacct.ime, clo_. to their .ysriti., that is,
close 10 Spu,a itself.)
IH
Tli• Bu,d Hunt" ond th, ""IP" of th, A th..,;.,, -,,A,bm
In oum, with the hoplite order (ta,ns) reign,;" in the h,-yptn11 there
is nothing but cunning, deception, disordH, in"ationality. To bonow
Uvi-Straua•, terms, one might 11.y that the hoplite is on the aide of
Culture, of what ia •cooked', while the l&ryptN is on the side of Nature.
of the •raw', bearing in mind of coune that this 1Natun: 1, the 1idc of
non-aaltun:, is itsetr to some degree aocially orpnized. 21 And we might
apply this point more widely: for example, in Ctttc we find ap'4i of
young men, which Pierre Chantrainc interprets u the 'herds of an.imab
that are driven along' (19&6: 32-3), opposed to the h,toir,i,,i, the
'brotherhoods' of mature men. And I could ao on, but I have said
enough to indicate how, by a proadure which Uvi.Sttauss would term
a logical inversion, the lcryptti. dramatizes the moment when the
young elite Spartiate leaves ~hind him forever hia childhood.
In his Poi,.,;ty ""d A...tol)I (1966) Geoffrey Lloyd hu brilliantly
shown how the principle of polarity played a fundamental role in the
reasoning of Greek. thinkers in the Archaic period - indeed I believe
that his conclusions could euily be extended to include the Classical
period itself: how can we undentmd Thucyclidcs. for example, without
using the notion of polarity?111 And my intention here, a, must already
be evident, is to detect evidence of polarities cx,prcued not in book-
thinking but in social institutions; and I propose to do that without
entering upon the question of whether 'thought' and 'institutions' are
the effective consequcnce1 of one single entity, the Levi-Straussian
•human mind'.
I think we may generalize and extend what I have already said in dis·
cussing the Spartan ltrypteili: for we must recognize that in Athens, and
in many other parts of the Greek world - above all in Sparta and Crete,
where very archaic institutions were preserved until well into the
Hdlcnistic period - the transition between childhood and adulthood
(the period of maniace and fighting) is dnmatized both in ritual and in
myth by what we might call the "law of symmetrical inversion'. Indeed,
since the publication of Arnold van Gennep's Tire Rites of Passage in
1909 (van Gcnnep, I 960), many rituals of sutus-transition have been
analysed in these term,. 11 I may ttmind the reader, for eumplC', that in
Argos young women sported a (falsr) beard when they got married
(Plutarch, De mulinum r,;,.iutibus 4, 2451); and that in Spar~a, when a
prl was to be married sM' •was handed over to a numph,utna who cu I
off all her hair, dressed her in a man's clothes and shoes, and mad" her
lie down all alone on a mattress in the dark• (Plutarch, Life of Lycurgus
15.5). The two casc:1 arc quiu parallel, as is o~viou1 when we rcmc~bcr
that, according to Ht:rodotus (1.82. 7) adulh in Arp had to be entirely
bald, while in Sparta, they had to let their hair tVOW long. We have hett
dlen a kind of double invenion.
1&5
Pierre Vidal-Nilquet
But we must return to Athens, and look again at the- festiuh con·
nected with the young men's 'return' that att so marked f~a~
the month Pyanepsion (Septemixr-OctoMr). In thc,e es?v .
t ;< t'
ephebes played an important part; and they are all the more s1~ficant
for IM inasmuch as they also marked the end of _the pcnod o{
'apprenticeship' - for this was probably the .point at which the eph~ba
took their famous hoplite-oath in the Aglaunon and when they recCJVcd
their arms from the city. .
Very shortly after the Apatourio occurred the- ~ctuv:_! lr.n~~ as the
Oscltopltortll (held on the snoenth day of P7ane~1on). ~11 IS a pilZ'·
ticularly interesting festival bc<:ilusc 1t1 acaolog:tcal myth rs co?cemcd
precisely with Theseus's return from Crtte after killing the Mwota~r.
and the conflicting emotions be fr els - glad be-cause he. ha, been vie·
torious, filled with grief at his father', death (Plutarch, L1f# of 11,.esr:w
22.4). And it was preci1ely thit death which the ephebes' black cltlamys
was belirvcd to commemorate.
The traditional sources for the Oschophoria diverge m.ark.e-dJy from
one another. I do not propose to an.alY11e them exhau,ti~ly,,. but will
simply emphasize some points which have- sometimes been negfcctfli.
First of all an eucntial rOle in the- Oscbophoria is played by an outlyinJ
gr:nos (a group of relatively wealthy familie1 clai~ng descent from a
single ancestor), that of the Salaminians who had moved to Attia. It
was this gnaos in particular which provided the youths (ua:Niar) who
cvried the vine-branches complete with bunches of grapes (Osch.or) -
who were in conscquena: called Osclaopltoroi.. 11 Set":ondly, the fint
rvcnt or the festival was a procession (/,•rapornpi) from Athens to the
shrine of Athena Skiras at Phaleron. Now the word ,•iron mn.n, 'lime'
and so 'badlandl'; and Felix Jacoby hu shown that the names S~uras,
SJ,iros and s•iron weft' generally given to outlying dittri<:ts which
either were, or had been at some- time in the past, frontier-areu. 1 ' Tbw
'Skira' is another name for the offshore ill.and of Salami,; Skiron i& ~
village on the old boundary between Athens and Eleusis, and so on. The
procession to the shrine of Athena Sk.iras was made up of boy, (p,cudd)
led by two boys dispisr:d III girls carrying the Oschoi~ these boys .aft
referred to u paides amplailltaleis. n Plutarch nplai.ns the tr11n,vesti1m
by saying that among the ttven maidens whom Thcaeus took with him
to Crete there were two boy, disguised as girls. 19 l cannot here venture
to tackle the very co1111pln problems pn,ented by the fe,tivals cart·
nected with Athena Skins: the source-s are so confused that it i• hard to
tell which or the various festivah they refer to. I will limply point out
that Athe~ Skiras K"em, to have bc-=n linked tigniftcantJy with Ult
(:Ustom of dreuina-up: it is during her festival that Prnagnra and lit'f
friends decide in Aristophanes's Tit~ AunnbJy of Wo,,,wn to dress op
156
Tltt! Blaclf. JJunttT and the origi" of the Athnaion ephrbeia
u men and wear false beards (and it 10 happens that one of the chuac·
kn hu a husband who is a Salaminian {18-25, ,s)).'° Plutarch, lift
of Solon 8, gives two vcnions of how the Athenians seized Salami.I
( otbcrwi.w known as Skiras) from the Megarians; and in one of them
the bcardleu young men disguitt themselves u women. And he says
that a restival was established on the promontory Skiradion after the
seizure (though he link.a its details to the second story, which, though
involving a deception, contains no transvestism) (9.4).
Besides the procession and the boys 1 transvestism, the Oschophoria
ft-atured a race (atOn, lt.amilla) between ephebcs carrying Osehoi. Most
of our information about this is derived from Proclus's Chrestomathia. 51
The cowsc ran from the temple of Dionysus to Phaleron. The com·
pctitors were either two representatives from each of the ten tribes,
rach pair running separately; or else twenty youths, two from each
tribe, all running apinst each other. The victor drank the 'fivefold
cup', a mixture of oil, wine, honey, cheese and flour. After the
ceremonies at Phaleron, and in particular the rituals of seclusion and
the deipnop/toTUJ ("food<arrying'), there were libations, followed by a
Mvcl (•O'"os) which brought the participants back to Athens. It is evi·
dent from Plutarch (Life of 11aeuus 22.3) that this revel was accom·
panied by a herald, and that the return journey too was explained by
reference to Theseus's retum from Crete (he wu supposed to have
stopped at Phaleron in order to sacrificr). In the story, Theseus's herald
precedes him with the news of success, and diJcoven the death of
Ae~us, which he rcpons to Theseui;, who is still outside Athens.
Theseu1's party then entered Athem loudly lamenting, but still the
bearers of happy news. And for this reason, says Plutarch, it is not the
herald himself who is crowned at the O.Chophoria, but his staff
(lf.iruAteion); and cries of joy, 'Eleleu', alternated with keening, 'iou,
K>u', in commemoration of Aegcus's death.n
The structure of the Oschophoria is thus marked by a series of
oppositions. The most blatant is that between male and femal", which
is clear in the procession itself (boys dttucd as girls venu1 the youths),
but also in the contrast between the procession (boys ctn-ned as girl!)
and the race (dromos) between the ephebes (th" race of course is
nothing if not virile: in Crete, the dromeus is a matur" m_an (Willetts,
1955: J 1-14), and in Lato, in particular, the word for leaving the age/a
to become a man is 'running out' (~6pa1,1ei11: IC 1.16 [Latol, 5.21);
according to Aristophanes of Byzantium an apodromos was a you11~
boy not yet allowed to take part in the public races). 11 Th" ra~e
during the Oschophoria is indeed exactly_ par~tl to the stapltulo~rom1a
during the Spartan festival or the Camna, which v.:ai also a fesuval of
the phratrie1: it was a race in which five unma.rned youn1 men ran
U7
Pierre Vidal-Naquct
apinst each other (Harrilon,1927: 234cf. .!121). Thirdly,joy is o~po,ed
to grid, as is shown by Plularch's Life of Thesnu 22.~ - which h•
been considered, wrongly I think, to be: a later in&erprc:tabon. .
It is well kn.own that in archaic Greek socic:tie1, as well u UI other
societies, dressing up u a woman, u in the procession at W Oscho-
phoria, was a means of dramatizing the fact tha_t a young i:nan had
reached the age of virility and marriage. The dauac example m Gn:c.k
mythology is the story of Achilles on Skyros Qeanma.irc, 19:59.: 354-5;
Dckourt, 1961: 1-16; cf. Bettelheim, 1962: 109-21). But ll can be:
demonstrated that it is not the lind of diqu.ilc which is important..
nther the cofttruf which it undcncores. The opposition bctwttn li&h,1
and dark for example ii no less 1ignificant: youn1 men not yet adult arc
known sometimes to haft bHn called slr.otiai ('of the dark': Scholiast
on Euripides, Akeslis 919); the r&eftiai {'youths') of the Otchophoria
arc called eslciatn1pllirnmoi, 'brought up in the dark' {Plutareh, Life of
Tiies~ 2!.2; Proclus, Ch~sloJMthia 89 (p. 56 Scvcryns) ).,.. Both
Malla and Dreros in Crete seem to have held cc:remonics of adminicm to
the adult age-classes, which involved ritual nudity before the conffflinc
of hoplite arms. The youn1 men att called uOStoi, which Hesychi1U
dcfma u 'those who are without arms'. At Dreros they were called
· pwuuu.Osioi and egd11ommoi, 'those who have no 9,othcs' - thie latter
term occun also at Malla.u There was likewilc at Phacstus a festival
called the EJcdysS. ('Clothie1 ofr): the actiolOff here ii a ttory about a.
girl who twned into a boy - whleh forms a link bietwcen the two sets
boy : fir/ and "4h4 : Cffllftl (Antoninus 1..ibcnlis, Met•morphoses 17
[Leukippo,); cf. Pepathomopoulm, 1968: 109-10; Willctu, 1962:
175-8).
It is perhaps worth noting finally that the 1exual imrenion of any
young man about to become an adult is quite cliearly related to theK
facts: it is cnoup to mention Ephorus's well-known story about the
rape (,..,.,,,,i) of a YOUIII Cretan boy, who ii taken by his lover into
thie country (of couniel) for two months, for a life of relu.ation and
i\u•tiftf. h is on his n.:tum to thr town that hie reciti"l:s the.,_, whicll
mu.c him• hoplitc (FGrll 70 F 149 [from Suabo 10.4.21: 41,CI).
I come now to thie thiemc of the hunt, which appcan in thie title or this
papier, and which I still have to explain and, if pauibk, juatify. ,Pian
Chantrunc hu noted (1956: 40-65) that huntias is linll<4 1 . -
mientally with lAC qro, in Greece, the land which Jit:1 beyond thie cul-
tivated area, that ii, with the escluttiai, the borderlands of a,cd, c-i~
Plato calla hi1 ephebc, the p,enon who dcfuds the f~tier area~ 18\
_ . , . . , {Loin 6, 760.-76la). Mo.. .....,.Uy, buntiag - ,a
IIOl1PU for heroes, whc,m dlie q>hebes emu.laud. thal I\ Orth
Ill
Th, Blach Hunur ottd the origin of the A.then,-•n ~ht'b•UJ
remarked that 'heroes ue hunten and hunten heroes' (1914: 559).H
In a 1cntt, hunting is firmly on the 1idc or the wild, the 'raw', or
night~' and the skills employed ia the Spartan ltryptN ~tt those or
hunting. But only in a sense: 'WC have to make certain distinctions.
My starting-point is a well-known test on education, from the end or
Plato's section on education in the Laws (1, 822d-824a). Using the
method demonstrated in the Sophist, Plato introduces here a whole
series of distinctions. Each time he spuks of a left side, the side of evil,
and a right side, that of good. Fishing depends upon the use of neu: it
therdort falls squarely on the left. One ought then to restrict oneself to
the hunt and the capture of quadrupeds (91)pEVO'k rE K.Oi Q"fpa: 824.11.).
Here too, though, he makes a distinction: one is not allowed to hunt by
night with nets and traps. All that seems to be permissible is that type
of hunting which conforms to the ethos of the horseman and the hop·
lite: coursing the animal, or killing it with a lance - both of them kinds
of hunting which involve the use of one's bare hands (though bird·
catching is tolerated en41FoU, 'beyond the area of cultivation'). 'But as
for the man who hunts by night, the nu•ureutis, with only nets and
t.ra.ps, let no man allow him to hunt anywhere' (824b).
When faced with a text of this kind, we must of counc allow for
Plato's dichotomizing method, and for bu moralizin1 tone. Perhaps we
should allow for a similar tone when Pindar describes Achille, k.illin1
deer without dogs, and without guile or nets, but simply by running
futer thmi. they (Nemean 3 ..51-2) - even though it reminds us of the
Cretan dromeus. But there arc several texts which draw a contrast be·
tween two types of hunting: adult hunting, where the spear is used
rather than the net, and which takes place by dayli1ht, sometimes in a
group, and which is in kecpin1 with the hoplite ethos; opposed to it is
hunting by ni1ht, a 'black hunt' baJed on the use of the net. The heroic
prototype of the group·hunt is of counc the hunt of the farnou, black
Calydonian bov. Now it has been observed that 'thC' use of OC'ts is not a
feature of pictorial representations of the Ca.lydoni.tn boar hunt' - any
more than it is of the literary accounts (Chantrainc, 1956: 65, quoting
La Costc-MuscliCre, 1936: 130-52 (though lmmerv.·a.hr, 1885: 52-4
points out that U,is feature dues occur on Roman representations of
the hunt on sarcophagi; and see now Koch, 1975. E<l.J). And for this
reason: the Calydonian boar hunt is a hunt involving the adult heroes •Jf
Greece. Likewise, Hcgesandros reports a Macedonian custom whC'r("ll\
no man could dine reclining until he had killed a boa.r "A-ithout the .11d
of net or snare (Athcnacus, Deipnosophist•e 1.31, I Ba). Poor C,m.~uki
had to wait until he was thirt)·.fivc before he could enjoy this priv1lcgl"
- distinguished hunter though he wu. We may put the point slightly
differently: unless he had accomplifhed somc signal exploit a young
)59
Pierre Vidal-l',aquet
man i.:ould not be a full participant in the communal meah which ~
a feature of so many archaic or marginal societies.
Two Spartan customs neady illustrate how integral hunting was to
the hoplite ~thos. According to Plutarch (L•fe of Lycurps 12 . .f.), ~y-
onc who took part in the communal meals had to present ~c ~ e W1th
the choiast parts of his sacrifice, or if he had been hunnng, WJth pan
of the bag. One was allowed to dine at home if the sacrifice or hunt had
finished late, but the othen had to come along too (TOO( 6 • tiXMJU~ t'&et
l'QPEiM:r,.). And Xenophon informs us that hunting dogs and hones were
common property; while any food left in the meu after dinner had to
be kept in a special place for any huntcn who ~tt delayed (Constitu-
tion oftlae LscedlJemonion.s 6.5-4).
By contra.st with these heroic and communal exploitl, huntins b~·
on~lf and with neu seems ohcn to be rypicaJ of the adolesa:nt. This
is indicated by many texts, though it is true that many an: late. Accord-
ing to Oppian, Cyncgetica 2.25, it was Hlppolytus, the prototype of the
youth who is unmanied and who rcfuSC5 to marry, who invented thr
hunting-net. In the story of young Philios, the 6nt task impo,W on
him was to kill a lion lil'ftl ac.&9'-pov, 'without an iron weapon'. And be
slew it not with a net, but with a typical trick (apati) - hC" made i.t
drunk (Antoninus Libcralis, Metamorphoses 12) . . - And Bttlich hu
emphuized the interest of an odd passage in XC"nophon's Cynqeticus
(2.!), where he defines the hunt ;u chanctnistic of thC" transition from
childhood to adolescence and adds: 'the hunter who URI a net must
love his art, moat be: of the Greek tongue and be about t~nty yean
old'. It is in such terms perhaps that onr might explain why on -the
Chigi Vase in the VWa Giulia in. Rome there ii a line of mm creeping
through the undergrowth, over against the line of hononen and the line
of hoplites (the Chigi Vue is of course Late~rinthian). And it is by
re£erence to the same oppositions that we can undentand why Nestor
has two dirfercnt initiations into the art of war in the //itul, first a, a
young man, lightly-armed, taking part in a catt1e-raid at night, and then
as a heavy-armed adult (/li•d 11.6 70- 762, with the dttisiW" ditcuuion
of Bra\lO, 1979).
But I want to aflUC tlQt the essential evidence for the J'Olc of the hunl
in the \lariow stages of a young Greek male's life it providtd by a facu,ft'
whom it is high time that I dealt with: the IJadi: Huatff, Melanlon.
Let me tell you ,1 li1tlc llory
1 beard when Iw• a boy
How
nim once IWU a you.lh l~oi.J ca&led.Md.nMln, who
Wu 10 appuled u the prOlpCCt of women he fte.w
To the mm.maiiu rather th• mSTY.u
And he hunted hana
160
Th~ Bladt Hunttr 11nd th, onfin of th, Athmian eph~briJ
And he ~t hit mun
With hil do1 there,
Ancl ftffet' cunt b&clr. for IIDYOftCI
(Al'Utophanca, L1N,,_ta 781-H, U'. Dicklnton)
162
9. Recipes for Greek adolescence
Pierre Vidal·Naquet (1974, 1979)
ficurc ,. fronti,piccc from.J. Ldil.au '• ltlunHJ drJ sa•H•Otf" I a,., ; n ·q 11•i"1 cu '",,.,.,~,
dri ~"'Wn tonps. ( R,dn,wn b y R. K. Brill o n)
...... ffl(,t"llf'J
1(,5
PieJTe Vidal-Naquet
essence of our Religion'. 1 do not know whethrr Lafi~u i~aginc-d that
Time, with his wings and scythe, was a figure from antJ.qu1ty: ~ ~ow
of course today thal it is not (Pmofsky, 1962: 69-93). Father Time,
descended from ancient Saturn and the mediaeval fip1tt of ~th, own
his iconography to the Renaissantt: he is contemporary With the mm
who witncucd the 'Great Expansion'; Lafitau"s dnughUmUI stresses
his vitality rather than his destructive aspect (the ~the is _not at work).
The Jesuit saw no contradiction between the ~bon o! ~1mr and ~om-
1
parison, between, as we miP,t say now, the diachroruc and the 1yn·
chronic'.
Comparison between the customs of the Indians and the Greeks is
legitimate because Indians and Grerk.s are each desccndrd from Adam
and Eve. The scene is given unity by the figures and symbols of Judaro·
Christian myth. Moreover, Lafitau makes his own attempt to historicize
the myth by making his Indians thr distant cousins both of the Grerka
and of their barbarian neighboun (hr~ again he differs from his ptt-
deccssor de Acosta who thousht indeed that the Amrrican Indians
came from the Old Continent - hr had gucacd the e:itistencc of the
Behring Strait - but stressed that these ancestors can hardly have been
anything but 'mas hombres ulvaFS y cazadorn, que no gentr ttpU.blica
y pulida' ( 'savages and hunters rather than a refined and civiliJ:ed
polity')' - 'savages and hunten': the very n:duncbncy of the phrase i•
characteristU:). But Lafitau could hardly ignore (and did not) the fact
that rven before hil own century, and in particular aftrr the Great
Expansion, the possibility of mother Adam, or of several othrr Adams,
had been raised (PoJiakov, 1974: 137-44), sometimes to justify the
enslavement of the Indians, but sometimes to assert that they were free
of original sin. The death 0£ God, so close to Lafitau's work, while it
cut away the top of his pictul't', in a way left things as they stood. ls
that why~ now have the right tu comp.rr, that i1, as it wrre, to annu.l
fathrr Time?
Ninekenth-century rvolutionary theory, in its own way structuralist,
injected a dose of secularism into Lafitau's schrma. At Stuttprt, in
1861, Johann Jakob Bach.ofrn pubJishrd his Da M•ttnncltt (Mitri·
arclay ). Right from the start the Swiss ,cholar relied upon a now famous
passage or Herodotus (1.173): in Lycia the mrn took the name a.ot of
thrir fathrr but of their mothrr -- which is whai the Iroquois, among
others, also did. Now Lafitau knew chis tcxl: indcfll, be had colkcled
all the tn.u he could find on what we must altrr him call 'matriarchy'
and "malrilinearity'. 'Gynaecocracy. the Rul,: of Women', M ob,erved,
'was practicaUy univenal' (1.7J). His lint reaction an con:fpm'UII
Lycians, Iroquois and Hurons wu to suppose that the ARM:rican Indians
wrrc descended Prom thr Lycian1 (1.64). He wu a little doubtful on
166
R«ipn [M' GruA odolt1cmc,
ICCO\lftt ofthe claimed univenality of matriarchy in the ancient world,
but baoin1 no ch1nae of th<ory at hand, finally conc:lud<d that 'th•
larger put 0£ the inhabitants o( America stemmed originally from thOIC
borbarians who dwelt on the mainland or Gr..e< and th< islands'
(l.82-S), befott the arrival of the Gtt<u. Bacholm did not n«d such
a hypothesis. For him, all manltind hu pused throush a •taae or
"matriarchy', a stage of comforting con1.aet with nature which repro-
duces the mother's breast and which precedes the cultural break
brousht about by patriarchy. Even earlier than Bacholen and
appattntly without knowing Lalitau, LH. Morgan had likened the
Lycians to the Iroquois.• When the time came for a 1ynthc1is in 18 77
(Ancinat Socidy), God, incrssantly on Lafitau's pen, makes an appear·
ance only on the very last page, where Morgan pays homage to th~s<"
•savages', these 'barbarians' whose patient toil was •a part of the plan ot
the Supreme lntclligence to develop a barbarian out of a savage, and .1
civilized mm out of this barbarian'. A hesitant enough appearance; but
all the same ncccssuy. for the parallelism of social evolutions is
explained at least putly by the presence in all men, if not of a gleam of
original Revelation, then at kut or the 'primary germs of thous}\t'
which the transition between one stqe of IOcial evolution and another
allow> to develop.' Scculariud by Enaeb (Oril"• of lh• Family was
published in 1884), Morpn'11ehema makes comparison both legitimate
and straightforward. To compatt two societies, it is ncceuary and
sufficient to determine their co-ordinates on the anph of social evol-
ution. The Iroquois are at the lower margin of the state of barbarism
whole upper marx:in is represented by Homeric Greece. Fine, but what
about all the innumerable institutions which Lafitau knew perfectly
lffll could exist in quite dirferent societies? Must we for example for-
bear to comp~ the warrior societies of the mediaeval West and
Homeric society on the grounds that the one, in Marx's and En~ls'
temainology, belongs to a social formation founded on slavery, and the
other to the 'feudal' period? Even if wr do make the sacrifice, the prob·
lem refUKS to go away. We have to make a choice: either we say, with
the Soviet version of Marxism in panicular, that all human societies
have pused or will pass through thr same stages ·- which is just not
tn1e;' or we restrict the occuncncr of 'feudalism' simply to the medi
anral West and Japan, which involvcs an n.tnordinary comtriction ,,1
the comparative field, one which would disallow a whole serin ,if
studies whosc very cx.istcncc prove• that you cannot make 1oml·1hi11K
true simply by believing it.
Though I tw,c cited Lewis MOl'pft, it wu not - unfortunately - his
work the work of a man who had received a double cducation, lroquois
and American, and who, in spite of or because or that, iftlUtcd upon
167
P1c"Te Vidal·Naquct
the unity of the human family, that dominated such in~t a s ~ ~
pologists had in the Greek world. Six ycan bcfott Ancwnt .son~ty_,_m
1871 there appeared the lint edition of Edward B. Tylor s Pnm,trw
Cult~rt:, and it wa., through Tylor and his foUowen, above all And~
Lang (1844-1912) and J.G. Frazer (1854-1941), that Gn:ek stud1n
were decisively influenced by the work of anthropologisu,' after the
collapse of Max Muller's 'comparative mythology'. 10 Of count th~
wett many points on which Morgan and Tyl~r ~ ~cd, but thnr
views we« at heart d.iffcralt. Right at the bepnrung of his book T~l.or,
while allowing for the existence of good savages, sets up an o~posttr_on
between Savagery and Civilization - that is of course Wntcm 1~penal·
ist civilization. But comparison is justifiable bccautt of nimllllls (an
older notion significantly adapted by Tylor) from the savage world at
the hurt of the civilized: 'If~ choose out in this way things which
have altered little in a long counc of centuries, we may draw a pictu.ff
wheK" then shall be scarce a hand's breadth diffen:nce between an
English ploughman and a negro of Central Africa. ' 11 Then: is a funda-
mental unity between the lower classes of the West and the inferior
ruces of the world: in Tylor's day English royalty could not yet bt:
compared with African chiefs. Mo~ovcr Tylor made a point which it
the origin of many theories of totemism: 'The Kntc of an absolute
psychical distinction between man ;md beast, so pl'C'\'alent in the civil·
ized world, is hardly to be found among the lowu raccs.' 12
What was the place of lM Gn:ek world sttn through the evolutionary
spectacles of the nineteenth cmtury? It is crisply defined by Andrew
Lang, a key figure of the age, at once a journalist, a historian on the
grand and the small ,calc, and a fo~most anthropologi,t. lt went with-
out saying that, from the agr of Homer, the Grtek world belonged
utterly to Civilization. After all, from then on there wett royal hou,.es.
But it was equally obvious that the Gn:eks wcrt conscious of having
bttn savages. Their rituals and their myths att full of odd thinp, from
human sacrifi~ to cannibalism. Htre the notion of survival combin~
with evolution plays a crucial rOle: the Greeb lu,d bet'ft u.vqes.. they
WttC so no more; thei:r myths are survivals from 1hci.r pat,u and
mythology tell.s wlat their ancestors did. Comparison was compatible
with hicrarchization.
The synthetic system, of the Romantic period and the Arc of
Positivism are now men: rotted hulks or etiolated to the point of un-
r«ogniubility. Let us take a look at a alightJy later period; a1 a lime
when the kings of anthropology were Frazer on one side and Malinowskl
on the other, what freah basis for eompan.tiw sh.1dy could a his,oriui
have found? Frazer wa, a fact-gleaner. Starting from the Graeco-lfoman
world, which he knew admirably well, he W-dl Mt indefatigable footnoter
168
•
R1cipes for G,u• adol11Cfflct
p...._. •d Ovid without ever cxplairung what it was that per·
~ him to compare the Prie1t·k.in1 of Ncmi slain by his 1ucccuor1
••
·JL
Cliril& dymc on the Cross or the God-King of Pharaonic Egypt.
*8laowtki dedicated him1dr to an unprecedented dfon of reflection
iapon the functioning of a sinsle Mclaneaian society, ovcr-hutily
..;.d with the Sava,e lokt cotu"I (Leoch, l966b: 360-7). For the
hielorian, the choice might properly appear ruinous. And yet, of the
two, from the time of Salomon Rcinach to our own, it was un-
doubtedly Fta%er who waa, in France and elsewhere, the more influ-
mtial. With hardly an exception (but 1tt Finley, 1977), the central
concept which we owe to Malinowrki (and refined by his succeHon,
above all R.adclifre-Brown), 'social function', has hardly been put to use
by historians of the Ancient World. To be sure it wa.s not a clear or a
crisp notion, and it hu properly been strcucd that the word 'function'
has two senses for Malinowski, an organicist tense - an institution is an
element which has a function, a r61e, in a social aggregate; and a logistic
or symbolic sense - mythology has a symbolic function in the structur·
ing of social relations (Panoff, 1972: 109). But there was here an open
door which almost no one stepped through. One may be allowed to
regret this at a time when anthropology has, once again, rocketed in the
most divergent directions, of which 'structuralism' is just one - though
the one which, even allowing for fashion, attracts many historians most
strongly.
How arc we placed now? The latest racarch, so far from ma.king the
historian's choice easier, limply ma.kn it fflOff painful, because every
historian today knowa that what he studies ii propc:rly speaking neither
the unique nor the univenal - even if the univenalism of the 'human
mind' has replaced Frazer's empirical univenalwn. We all know as his-
torians that the truth of the history of a Breton village is not to be
found in the simple history of a Breton villagt>; but also that the divertt
metahi.stories which crowd us, from a more or leSI refurbished Marx.ism
to psychoanalysis, from the philosophy of the price-curve to that of
univcnal logic, will never relieve us of the obligation to get back to our
village.
Structural anthropology is one of these metahistorie1, one of the
Siren-voitts - surely one of the most exciting and uimulating, inas
much as, privileging on the Saussurian model of language the s, n
chronic over the diachronic, it offen the most complete challengr rH1
thrown to a diacipline which bdieved that there was no pecpinK o,·rr
the walls of time, unln1 it was for some rhdorical or pc:dagogic purpose
to paint what the diss.crtation·scribblcn call •. "picture' .. Yct _th~s
challenge docs not abolish those offered by carher gcnentlons: 1t as
simply added to them. for it i1 not enough to .u&erl. f'Vm to prove, as
169
Pi.-ne Vidal-Naquct
'structuralism' atlcmpts, not unsuccessfully, to d~, ~,1t the 'hum_.an
mind' is a universal logical agent, to rcstorc to the h1sto~an the sccunty
he has lost, and which, one must hopt'. ht will ~ever rcdtseovtr_- For the
'human mind' is not in itself tht obJtCt of hutory, and &n)Way ~
tthnologists who postulate, t'.'tn prove its uni~e~~ty do_ not c~m
that it is, if it bt that the aim of their undertaking ts the ~ntegra~on
of culture in nature and finally of life within the wholt of its phy11Co-
chemical conditions' (Uvi·Stnuss, 1966a: 247). The 'logic of the
living', which is also that of things in themsdves, 1~ is not answer~blc to
historical reason which is constitutivt, not conslltuted, and which un-
endingly makes' and rcmaktt its operational fields, its 'scenarios'
Among all the many human institutions which Lafitau sought to relate
to one another there is one which C'thnography was to take up in
remarkable fuhion - initiation. To adopt a recent dC"ftnition, initiation
is 'a body of ritC"s and oral tc-achings whose purpose" is to produce a
radical modification of the religious and social status of the penon to
be initiated. In philosophical terms, initiation is equivalent to an onto-
logical mutation of the csistcntial condition. The novice emcrgC"s from
his ordeal a totally different being: he has become another' (Eliade,
1969: 112). Even before Lafitau the initiations which att, even today,
best known and best studied, had been perfectly rehearsed and idcnti·
ficd: the means by which the young ·savage' C'nten upon the adult
community. So Robc:n Beverley, author of The History •nd Ptesent
Staee of Virginia, retailing the rituals unde'IOne by the young Indians:
The Solemnity of Huakan.wina ll commonly pnctil'd once every fourteen or ,a;.
teen yean, or oftener, u their YO\lnl men happen to pow up. It is an Institution
or DiKiplinc which all youn1 men m1111 pau, bcfOft' they can be admitted to be or
the number of the Great men, or Cock.arouiw1 of the Nation; whereu by Capt.a.in
Smith•, I.elation, they were only ,ct apart to aapply die Priesthood. The whole
ceremony is performed after the followin1 manftft.
The choice,t uid briu.nt youncmen of the Town, and 111ch on1y u have acquired
tome Treuure by their Travd, and Huntina:, 1n chOleft out by the Rulers lo be
Hu,lr.anawed; and whot"vcr refuses to undcf'IO dus Prot"e•, clan not remain amona:
thera. SnenaJ of thote odd preparatory f opperiet aft premis'd in the bcplnin1,
which h.ve before been rdated; but the prindplll pu, of the b\Wlleu is to carry
them into the Wood.a, and there keep them under confinement, and dc1titut~ of 1111
90Cicty for KYenl month,; 1ivin1 them no other su1tenanl'e, but the Jnfu11on, or
Decoction of ,ome Poiaonou1 lntos.katin& Roou; by virtue of wtuch Phy1iclr., and
by the scverity of the di,,cipline, which they unckr10, they become 1tarlr., 1tarin1
Mad; ln which ravin1 condition they arc Ir.cpl eipltcen or twenty day, ...
(On their return to the villa,c) thcy mu1t preU:nd tu havc for1ot the ¥~ry Ult of
their Tonpt1 sou not to be able tu ,peak, nor undnuand anythin1 that l l 1pokcn,
till they lean:: it apin. Now whether thi1 be re.al or counterfeit. I don't Ir.now; but
certain it ii. that they will not for some tim, take notic, or illlY bod), nor llrl~
thins, with which they WCK before acquainted, bein1 •till ~nder 1he pard of then
Kccpen who contuntly wail upon them nery where, Lill they havt lcam1 all
thinp ~rfccdy over apin. Thu, lhey unliw their former lives, and commence Mm,
by forJettin1thatthey baveeverbeen Boyl. ()70!!,; 5.8 §52 [pp. 5941})
But Lafitau improved this initial interpretation in two w,1,ys. lk
allowed into the category of initiations not merely admission into the
community but acceptance into 1mallcr groups (secret socit"tics),
rcJip<>us and ,hamanist initiations and 10 on. And in the 1pirit of the
171
Pierre Vidal-Naquet
nieral rogrammc of hil enquiry. he compared the l~dian initia~ons
:th th!H' known in clusical civilization - the Myltenes of _Elna~, •
well as Spartan and Ctttan education sys!cms - and~ ~~di~al. for
he treated the ritual of admWion to knighthood u an m1aat1on - yet
another stroke of daring (1.201-56; 2.1-70, 28.5-8).
It was not indeed until 1909, with the publication or Arnold van
Gcnnep's Rit,s de possage, that this framework was further enlaraed
and that the fmt steps were taken towards tht elaboration of a formal
structure of analysis, the French folklorist dcmons_tntin1 that the
enormous body of rituals such as these could be clus1r1ed under thrtt
headinp: rituab of separation, rituals of cxdusion, rituals of (re)·
incorporation. .
This classification obviou.ay presupposes in addition, indeed m fi~t
place, an articulation of time 1nd space peculiu to ritffl d~ ptus.p {i.e.
rituals of status-transition. Ed.). Time first. Its rhythm 11 not that of
the continuum, invented by the mathematicians: "The idea of Time·,,
is one of those categories which we find necessary because we ue 1ocial
animals rather than because o{ anything empirical in our objective
experience of the world. •1• Time in rituals of status-transition is abo a
human creation: the year ii punctuated by the rituals and the ritual
itself causes the initiate to paSI from the ordinary to the extra-ordinary
and back again to the ordinary, now consciously accepted For the
ritual to operate also at the level o{ conccptions.,.of space, it must itself
be broken up: 'hulDUI' space in which social life is lived, against
'marginal' space, which may be a symbolic 1acred area, 'the bush'
whether literal or figurative, forest or mountain 11 - it hardly mattcn,
provided it be perceived a.s other: 'heaven' and 'hell' in children's hop-
scotch is a good, i( extreme, example. So time and space arc 'binllt'Y'
{that is, each organized into two mutually exclusive - and inverted -
c:atc1orie1. Ed. J, though the ritual rhythm, u defined by van Cennep,
is threefold. Edmund Leach defines three kinds of r61n men find them~
selves playing in this kind of ritual action: formality, muqueradc,
l'Ole reversal (1966a: q5). In the context of initiation of young men
into the warrior life, for example, the three terms will be reprncnLcd
by warrior uniform, by dissuisc, of which countleq type1 ~ found at
the point of marginality, and by the invenion which temporarily tuffll
the man into a woman, which causes him. too to behave in aactly the
oppo1itc manner from how he ii to brhavc in 'normal' life.
It would be po11iblc to exemplify thil rhythm amon1 the Au.strali•
aborigines no kss than in Africa ur amont the Amerindian.a; but u Joni
• we remain on lhia very general Incl, we an: not actually within tM
ttalm of the historical, or the -.UbJunary', to llSC a term hulYeyne h•
borrowed from Aristotelian.ism. Let u, see what b«omet of'&hc1e con-
I 72
R,cipt1 for ~tic •dol•snnct
ccpu - 111d they an: ind<ed concepts - in a particular hi,torical society:
Iha& of ll'Chlic and clusic:al Gn:ecc.
Recent ncavation at the site or the Greek city of Eretria., on the
island of Euboca, by Swis, arcboeolopsu, bas n:vealed amons other
tbi:np • small necropolis sunoundin1 the tomb o{ a prince or kin1,
dalOblc to the late eighth and early l<Vfflth century - pn:ciscly the
~od or the emel)fflce of the uchaic city .11 The tombs excavated
fonn two groups: to the west we find only incineration; to the eut,
inhumation. It it not a cue of change of (uh.ion. since the two groups
arc contemporvy; nor ii it a matter of competing funerary cu1tom1 1
such as one finds elsewhere - for example, at the Keramcikos at Athens
in the ninth century. We have rather a quite deliberate and significant
oppoaition at the symbolic level: the inhumations are of children, the
incinerations of adults. Both sex.cs arc represented in the two groups.
Their opposition is ai.pialled in the group of incinerations by the
presence of UTD.I in the one case, and of jewellery in the other. Claude
Berard, the excavator, makes the point: "inhumation was the practice
at Eretria until just before adolescence, Cftmation being re1ervcd for
marriageable girb and married women, and for youths and men able to
use the lance and to take their place in battle' (C. Birard, 1970: 50;at
Marathon, the a.duh male Athenians wen: cremated. but not the
Plataeans and the slaves, who fought, but not on the same buis: Kurtz
and Boardman, 1971: 246; cf. the conclusions of Loraux, 1978: 810).
Trying to determine the • al which the appropriate funerary practice
chmged, Bml'd suggests that at Eretria, uid very probably in many
other places.'• it wu about the age of si:11.teen. The mere account of the
archaeological r.nds (is an account ever innocent though?) directs us to
the search for a ritual of status·tran&i.tion which dramatized for the
Greek adolescent the transition between Nature and Culture, or, if you
wish, between the Raw and the Cooked, in the moil concrete senK.
This ritual is relatively well knownj at Athens in the archaic and clas1ical
periods, as Claude Berard notcs, it is idcntificd with admi1sion into the
phratry. Thc distinctive occurrence on the third day of the Ionian
festival of the Apatouria (the fe1tival of 'those who have the same
father' - that is, of clanificatory 'brothen') was an initiation «rt>mony,
the lou,..dli.r: the name derives from the shearing (h.ouro) of the flocks
and of men, and it probably connotCI also the young warrior (h.ouros).
At A.thens, the 1acrifice of the h.ourt'ion (probably the offering of tll(·
hair itself. Ed.J which marM'd the admission of the cphebc1 into tilt'
phratry, took place at the age of six.teen.io
One point however 1Crvcs to remind us that we ought not to neglect
the 'diachronic' aapcct. The oppoaition between cremation and in·
hwnation employed at Eretria and ellcwheft to denote the opposition
175
Pierre Vidal-Naquet
between childhood an~ adulthood ob~iou~)' cannot pred;::ilti:;tc~~i:
duction of cremation into Gre«e, which did not haps>4=n
collapse of the Mycenaean world. . . . .
Nevertheless the discovery, due u we hW to L.t.fit31;1, of lnlb~Uon
rituals in Greece parallel to those of 'primitive' 1odeues, has 1bmu-
lated, ess>4=cially in the twentieth century, a very large amou~t of. wor~
recently synthesized by the Iu.lian historian An~lo Breli«:h in hd
Poldes e Parthenoi (1969).u Jean-Pierre Vcmant, usmg the ev1d~nce of
the mythical tndition css>4=cially, has analysed a number of ~£fcren1
religious fettivals, summarizing his results as folloW'I: 'If. ntuals of
status-transition mean for boys entry into the statUJ of warnOT, for the
girls associated with them in the same rituals, and frrquently them-
selves subjected to a period of seclusion, the initiation ordeals mean a
preparation for sexual union in maniaF. Here again the association,
which is also an opposition, between war and marri• is evident.
Marriage is to the girl what war is to the boy: for each, they mark. the
fulfilment of their ff'spective natures, by quitting a state in which each
has still some of the characteristics of the other' (197.,t: 37-4-0 d.
Calame, 1977: 1.239-40; Schmitt, 1977: 1059-73). This &I the
explanation, for example, of the fact that the Athenian ephebes wear
the 'black chUJmys' (a kind of short cloak. Ed.], not always perhaps,
but at least at the solemn occasion of the proce•ion to Ele:usi1 to be
initiated into the my.teries.11 before the:y put on, aftu •~aring the
oath, the hoplitc panoply (Vidal-Naquet, 1972: 161-2); and it also
explains why the festivals and myths frequently dramatized the young
man', entry into adulthood by having him put on female diJgu.isc:. and a
girl's into womanhood by meU\sof a male: charadc.u And here o( course
we remember Leach's three terms, formality, masquerade, role ft"Venal.
The male rituals of the ephebe'UJ in puticular allow us to define a
twofold structure: on one side the hoplite, who fights by day, in ranks,
face-forward, supporting his fellows, on the lrvel plain; and on the
other the ephebe (or the Spartan ltruptos), who fighu by !light, un.ded,
resorting to triclu of thC: kind deplored by hoplite and citnen values,
skulking on the frontien,. - all-in-all K"ting in a manner quite thr
rnene of how he must behave wbe:n he is intepted into the polis,
Surely ~ have here culture on one side, nature on the other; on one
side: sav•ry - or femininity, on the other civili%ation. Pt.a.to, in com-
mon with many other Greek think.en, defined childhood as the savage
time of human life (Timaeus +4a-b; Uu,r 2, 653d-e; 666a-c). The
Grttks made the principle of polarity one of the comentooct of th~
mode of ttpKat:nting the world (Lloyd, 1966). No tu, thu ,11 wen:
they capable of representing the oppositions which articultkd the-it
world in the fonn of a u.ble with. two columns. Th!M t h e ~ ·
174
1ecor-ding to Arittodc, 'recognized tm principlcl, which they list in
two parallel columns:
limited unlimited
equal unequal
unity plurality
right left
male female
still moved
straight line curve
light darl<
good bad
&qua.re oblong'
(M•14physics 1.5, 986a 22~ 6)
That list one could easily extend by looking at diffennt aspects of
Greek culture:: master-slave, Grt"ck-Barbarian, citizen-foreigner -
C"Yen Apollo-Dionysus perhaps. Heff again ancient thought in large
measure anticipated modern structural analysis: th.ink for example of
how Ariatode asks himself how far the sets adult-child, man-woman,
master-slave, employer-craftsman coincide, and the senses in which
they do not (Politics 1.12, 12l9a57ff.). And do we need to be reminded
of the propensity of sophists, tragedians and philosophers to contrast,
oppose, compare pltusis (Nature) and nomos (Law, Custom)?
These and other pairs may be considcnd to constitute the frame·
woii Of the discOune of thC Greeks. But the s~ctunJ.Mlthropologist
and'1.TlCiilif0iiiri.··cannC)t b~th .Jcai with them in the same manner. For
example, if we tak.e the opposition between cphcbcs and hoplites,
fledgling warrion and adult warriors, the comparatist will observe,
from the work of Georges DumCZil, that the oppo1ition bdween the
noked (i.e. not heavily-armed) warrior, thcephcbe, fighting unaided, and
the warrior integrated into some group and fully armed, is much earlier
than the set ephcbc-hoplitc, since hoplite warfare makes its appe...rance
in Greece only ear1y in the seventh cenLury; and that the opposition can
be traced elsewhere in the lndo-Europcan world. The opposition is the
same, but the words used to describe it arc not. Thus, in the Indian
epic. the 'heavy' warrior is an archer, while in Greece the bow bdongs
to the Savage (DumC:iil, 1968: 63-~; J. Le Goff and Vidal-N.it.quct,
1978: 275-5). 15 It will be objected that the Inda-Europeans, or al
least their conceptions, arc nevertheless historical, yet Dumizil, 111
studying a ritual of warrior-initiation at home, makes use not onl~ nl
Indo-lraniiUl and Irish evidence, but also of evidenoe from Canadian
Red-Indians: 'It is British Columbia, the East coast of Canada, which,
by virtv.e of• coincidence we cannot expltJin, best helps us to see the
meaning of the Indo-lnnian lc~nds about a thre1··hcadcd moMtct'
175
rie""c Vidal-Naquet
(1942: 128, my stress). The upJanation, if indeed it is ~bl.e, ii h~re
fatally a-historical: no historian. can postulate a collocabon md~~
Red Indians, Inda-Iranians and Romans, all ~ee. S~ch a colr!u~?o~;
in fact the human ra« itself - or better ,till, the human · .
Greek historian on the other hand is concerned with a da~able reali~,
the hoplite, and with another datable reality. an in1titut1~n fint.n"I·
dencc-d epigraphically in 361/0 BC and ~~ w.orking IS explained
some 35 years later by Ariltotle, that is the msutubon called at Athens
the tf)hcbeul, and its panllels in the rest of the Greek world.
One characteristic of the history of Ancient Grttce, from the very
beginnings of our knowledge of it, is an extraordinlV)' unevenneS9 of
development - an unevennese so marked that for an Athenian of the
fifth century some indisputably Greek pcoplts were thought of as
'sa~s·, almost as the Brazilian Indians wett by their ai~tttnth-cen~ury
conquerors (sec Thucydides 3.94 for example). Following Thucydides,
modcm historiaru: see the oppolition between Sparta and Athent, be-
tween the type of con1ervatism and of rejection of history on the one
hand, and the city which by contrast chose, in the fifth cmtury, to
identify itself with historical chan&e on the other, as one of the major
features of the classical period. In view of that, what of male and
female initiations? Put it another way: what differences arc there be-
tween thc two in terms of the sets child-adult and girl-boy (Alter·
natively, malc-fcmale)?
The cphebcia as descri.lxd by Aristotle is a form of civic military
servicc.u For the philosopher, the two-year period of service ii in no
sense a period of isolation preparatory to inu:gration into the ci"ic
community: he say, n:prcssly that the admission of a young man into
the deme-lists pr1tced,es the military service: recognition of citizenship
prcudes the pcriod of probation and is not its comequcncc. One point
only suggests something other than the mere performan« of military
obligations: 'During thete two yean of prri1on-duty, they wur a
chlom1s, and they are ftec from all fmancial. impositions; they cannot
be involvcd in a lawsuit, either as plaintiff or as defendant, 10 that they
will have no excuse for absenting themselves. The only nccptions are
cues concerned with an inheritance or with an hcirc1,1; or when a man
has to take up a priesthood hereditary in hls family' (Co,vh't1,lio11 of
thc .AtJsimimu 42.5). The chlamys is undentood not • the dreu or
ritual scclu,ion but like the miliury uniform of our own day. Aristotle
Ill.so undcntands the debarment from litiption in purely 1cC1Jla.r t ~ ;
and it ii obviously u:tremcly significant that. he can take this approadt
quite naturally. The question of origiru. ii ,1 q\Ute diffettt*probkm.
Loni ago it was ob1t:tvcd that 'the scdu1ion of the )'Olllll, in tht
pcrM>d immediately prior to UMir definite inclulion within the sodrtY,
176
Reci'pe1 for Grwt• Mal,icn&e~
ii so well attelted in .n kinds of different societies and, in Greece, in
Sparta, lhat one is inclined to discern a trace ol it here' (Rouael, 1921:
459). To be IUR, but what exactly do ,.. mean by 'trace'? II the
fuNt:tion of an institution in a society to be confu.sed with ill orifin? b
lhe B.A. delllff to be explained by its mediuval oritpno? 01 coun• not.
any more th.an Ari1tophani.c comic,dy is to be explained by a seuonal
ritual ol fertility u the Cambrid!I" School would have it (lorexamplr,
Cornford, 1914: 55-69). Of coune then, an, inertias and n,peals in
society, but it does not live in the pa.st. The put is influential only
inasmuch u it is pre1mt in the structures of thought, manners, inter·
prctati.ona. To return to the •ltebN, it is obvious that in Aristotle's
time the ordinary undentanding of the ephcbcs' stay in the frontier
forts wu not u an ~elution of the young men prior to their entry, or
re~ntry, into the poli.rj but u pnison-servicc. And when Thucydides
mentions in passins that the pnipoloi ('thOJC who go round'), that is,
the ephebcs, went on a ftipt alt.ad: near Nisaea in 425 together with
the new Plataean citizens (4.67), there can be no doubt that the ephebes
are not (yet) citizem like other citizen, and that they are usociated
with irregulu activities jn wu; all the- same, we must show that such an
interpretation was current at the time. In any cue it is obvious that it
no lonFf wu so in Aristodc's time.
If we look at the historical chanacs we an obtain some idea of what
happened. The earliest q,lt,beila wu 1ct in the context of the phratry,
an archaic institution, certainly reactivated in the fifth century, but
whose J'Ole wu diminished markedly after the Cleisthcnic refonns
(508 BC) by the dcmes. One b«ame an ephebe in the civic or military
tense of the word at eighteen, but one became an ephcbe in the phratry
at sixteen. It war within the phratry that there took place the rituals of
status-transition which mark entry into ,dulthood, the most importuit
being the offering of the child's long hair (Vidal-Naquct, 1968: 179-
80). But in myths, comedy, in a philosopher suc-h as Pl;,,to, and even, as
I bavc tried to show, an entire tragedy ofSophocln, thcffa.uocldes, 27
there i, prcservcd something elle - the "trace' of an initiatory ritual in
which the young man, as a guileful 'black" hunter, was sent out to the
frontier atta until he should perform the 'exploit' symbolically imposed
upon the young men in archaic 1ocietie~. ~tu~ of this t ~ wen rt:a1
enough in Crete where nen in the hcllcn11bc penod the official vocahu·
1ary of a city like Drcros mall.ct a distinction between city, country J.nd
the frontier forts, and where the educational i111titution1 set thr 'flocks'
(agelai) of adolescents over against the 1od.uitie1 (he~N~) ~f t~c
adults (oat.arc apimt culture) (pp. 155-8 above). Thrsc insutuuons in
Alhena have been for the moll part detached from eac:h other, in• civic
world which had been profuundly effected by rationalism - one might
177
ric:-re Vidal-Naquet
almost say secularized. And so Brelkh, hardly one to ~void com~son
with 'archaic' societies, in his discussion of the Athenian t!phel,no con·
duded that 'the original initiatory elements ~ can discern in it came _to
be voided of their original functional integrity' (1969: 227). The pnn·
dple of 'elders fint' endured of course. In the Athenian asscmbl',', the
old men had first right to speak. In the coul'H' of what was perhaps the
most crucial debate ever held in the d.lt.lesi• (Assembly), whether or
not to deploy almost all its forces in the expedition to Sicily (415 BC),
Nicias appeals to the old men as a group to resist the crazy idc-m of
Alcibiades and the young men with him, attempting thus to swing the
traditional mechanism of •-classes into action; Alcibiades asks the
Athenians not to be afraid of his youth: the city is made up of young
and old. Togt!thn they can win (Thucydides 6.13, 17, 18). Alcibiades
carried the day, though the Athenians were to regret it; at lcut his
speech suggests that the city l5 an inclusive totality which to a siMDifi-
cant degree cancels the opposition betwem age-classes.
'Old' Nicias thought of a city in which the young held power mo«: or
less as an inversion, a topsy-turvy world. The comic poet Aristophanes,
imagining a utopian situation in which everything is turned upsi<k
down - in Lysistrata or Ecclrsiazusoe (Womtfl in .Asumb/y) - makes
the women or Athens responsible for the decisions of govnnment. In
Lysistrata (411 BC) the wives of the Athenians have seized the democ·
racy. They decide to go on a sex-strike if peace'is not made. In their
ju,tification, the chorus of women, using the lanfl\.lage of usembly-
meetinp, declare:
It'• opni lo anyon, to pn.i1,
The dty md I to the end of rny daya,
Sh.U love her for 1ivin1 joy 10 a ,cnde child.
I wu only ,even whtll I
Carried the Sacttd
Vatel1; and It len I
l«e the Ternpk Mill;11
Then UI yellow I acted the Lildc Bur al lrauron,
And, srowin1 Ulltr.
An4 lovelier, took Caft
Of the Holy lull.et - it wu heawenl
(658-47, tr. Dick.in-)
That looks at fint sight like a list of female initiations in which there
were sevtral stages, rather like the system for boys at Sparta. H But no
such thing existed, and we mwt undentand this speech a idcologial:
Athenian women ~tt not properly speaking citizens, and young girll
were not citizens to be, whom the city had to take through the •lal"•
of an educative initiation. The Athenian polu wu founded upon tbr
exclusion of women, just as, in other respect,, it wu founded upon the
exclusion of foreipen (metic•) and daves. The sole ciYic flAlction g{
178
R~ci.p~, for Gr~d adolrsunu
women w11 to give bin.h to citizens; the condition imposed upon them
by Perida's law of 451 wu to be thc daughter of a citizen and of a
citizen'• daughter. The chorus in LyW,..,..ta is arguing as tf the women
of Athen1 were in fact the citizens. The stages referred to arc thotc of a
fictitious cycle. Most of them have nothing whatever, or virtually
nothing, to do with rituals of sutus·transition: there were only two
oniplt.oroi (?"bearcn of the ~crct symbols'), chosen from among girls
of noble birth. They were responsible for weaving the peplos ('robe') of
Athena Poliasi and they played a key l"Olc in the highly sccret ritual of
the Ancphoria (or An-etoplao"4). 30 As for the 'grinden of grain', they
prepared the flour and bread for the sacrifices in the cult of Athena; the
most important duty of the Ufl~horoi wu to carry baskets in the
solemn Panathcna.ic proccssion. ln short, these arc duties undertaken by
young girls Lil the service of the community; even if some of them
reveal characteristics of initiation rituals - special dress, seclusion of
the arriphoroi, for instance - there is here no question of a regular
institution affecting an entire agc·dass,ll rather of the city at each
festival renewing its contact with divinity. The women of Athens arc
not altering their status.
The case of the little 'Bean' in the sanctuary of Anemis at Brauron is
very diffncnt and much more complex. The very name of the animal
which the girls represent is that of the divinity. Artemis, goddess of
wild nature. The evidence of the scholiuu for the cult and that of
other sanctuaries of Artemis in Attica (see Brclich, 1969: 247-9), and
archaeological evidence going back to the fint half of the fifth century
(Kahil, 1965: 20-33; 1976: 126-30), permit no doubt about the
general character of the ritual: it invol\'ed a seclusion preceding - by a
considerable period of time - and preparing for marriage. The girls - so
the scholiast Harpokration for example tells us - had to 'become bears
before marri~. (in honour of) Artemis of Mounychia or of Artemis of
Brauron'. The explanation offered by the a.etiological Jc1cndi for this
obligation in\'ol\'c an original killing of a !Jcar by some boys, the ~tri·
bution for which was at first a human sacrifice, and J,1,ter thUI ritual of
substitution performed by the girl·bcan.n Varia..nu or no, the myth is
not d.ifficult to explain: in exchange for the \'Cry advanc(' of 1.:ulturc
' implied by the killing of wild animals, an ad\'illlt:t" for which m<'n are
~sponsiblc, the girls arc obliged bdorc marriage - indeed bdort
~ puberty - to undergo a period of ritual 'wildness'. Study of the pottnr
evidence from Brauron reveals that the rituals in honour of the go<ldns
involved (sequentially?) nakedness and the wearing of a special form of
•. clothing (the •crocu1' lJ a u.ffron·yellow robe) - p~r~~ps .a means ~f
dramatizing the tran1ition between savqery and ctv1hnt.1on. But. 1t
: ~ rcmain 1 true that it was pouible for only a small nurnb~r of Atheruan
179
Piene Vidal-Naquet
girls to become 'bears': the very size of the sancnaaries enforces .tiw
conclusion. The Aristophanes lCholion which gives w our most detailed
account (on Lysi.rtrat• 645; cf. Brelich, 1969: 265--4), 1ay1 both that
the 'bean' were girll who had bttn 'chOICII', and that the goddes1 ~
determined - at the original institution or the ritual - that no Athauan
girl might many before she had become a bear in her service. We m_1.111
then allow that, CVffl if the little bean represent the female commun~ty,
in the sense in which the Boule (the Council or 500) represents the city,
they constitute an elite of the: 'chOSt"n' and that initiation was c~rmcd
to them. Mo~er such a patlem ii well known to anthropologllts -
the pattern of the 'secret IOCicty', a small group which fulr~ a function
for the public weal, the precondition of that being a spcctal degree of
initiation.
Let us return to Vemu1t's parallel which we wed as a model:
'Marriage ii to the p-1 what war is to the boy', a formulation which
quite cvidcndy can be applied to innumenble societies. We cut now see
just what happened in Athens. As regards boys, the •laebftlJ a a rib.lal
of entry into adolescence ii 1eparatcd from the epladeia u compulsory
military service for all: at this lcvel, thett are no longer uiy groups
privileFCf by birth, wealth or membenbip of some priady family. At
most, considerations of family~rder - atablishing one's inheritance,
saving an oillos [family} from the thftat of 'eschoat' by manyinc an
epilclirol - could relieve one of the obliption!1 Depending upon his
wealth qualirKation, a young Athenian would later serve as a rower in
the fleet, u a cavalryman or as a hoplite, but in each cue he would
haft scnrcd u an cphcbc and hatt sworn UI oath based upon the
ideology of the hoplite: 'I will not abandon the man who 1tancll next to
me in the batde-lines.' Initiatory rituals proper are to an extent separ-
ated from the proceu of entry into the civic community. It is obvious
that nothing or the kind existed for girls: certainly marriage involved
well-known rituals of statu•lransition (being carried over the threshold
by the husbU1d), and it bestowed the right to take part in 1pe:cif"lcally
Female cettm0nics for WOftl.en citizens, ihc Thcsmophoria (DC'ticnne,
1977: 78-81; Detienne and Vemant, 1979: 185-214), which wu the
only forum which brought women toselhcr 111 citizens of Athens For
the one kind of political activity (if one CUI call it that) allowed than;
but age<lasl initiation properly so called, if it ever bad been a collective
experience, developed in a direction oppotite to that of male initiation,,
it involved only a minuscule group of initiatn who could n:prcsent the
city only by metonymy.
The imacc of Sparta u-an1ntlttcd to us by the •cient texts, panic»·
Jarly thole deriving from Athene, ii that of a society which rer~d NI·
torical change and auapended iuclf in the chanfclcunea of she 'Consd.·
110
Recip.1 for Grult. afUJle1ttntr
tu1ion of Lycurgua' (Tiaffstedt, 1965; Rawaon, 1969). Such modom
acholara II haw not capitulated to the 'Spartan ming,,' have directed
themoel,,a to 'nonnalizing' Sparta'• oddneu - Arnold Toynbee would
have it • one of his 'ciWizationa'. To normalize is the resort both of
Henri Jeanmaine in Coo,roi et Courif., (1989), when: he diacema
'beneath the muk of Lycursus' a aociety exacdy comparable with
African aocieties, and of M.l. Finley, in ahoWDII that the thn:e funda-
mental aspects of clu1ical Sparta, the agrarian infrutructure, with the
hienrchy of llomoioi ('the Equals'), pnioilioi (the free non-Spartiate
inhabitants of th• towns of Lakonia and probably Mesaenia. Ed.], and
hclota;. the governmental and the military structure; the 1y1tem formed
by the rituala of status-transition, education (the Gf'Ogi), •-classes,
coUectivc eating etc., were not developed and instituted at a stroke; and
that the 'sixth-antury ft'Yolution' which gave to classical Sparta its
chuacteriltic stamp was • complex procea of innovation, transform·
ation, and revival of features and institutions apparently transmitted
&om remote prehistory.•
What wu true of the Athenian hoplite at tlae lerMI of myth is true of
Spartiatc: 11.,,.,,tos in f'TGdice: the lt.n,pto1 appean in every respect u an
antihoplite. The 11.n,ptoi were young men who left the city to roam, in
ICa"et md in isolation, 'naked' (that is, not heavily-armed), throupi
mountain rand countryside, feedins themselves u they might, ususinat-
ing helot:J under cover of night - the helots apinst whom the Ephon,
to ensure that no pollution attached to such killinp, each year declared
war. According to the scholiast on Plato's I.AWi 9, 6S9b, the period of
,eclusion lasted m entitt year, though Plato him.self exprealy rcmarb
that it occurred in winter. We have only to invert this text to find the
Nici which governed the manner of life and the moral uid aocial
behaviour of the hoplitc, whoac virtue• otherwitc compose the very
fabric of Spartan life: collective living and eating, fiahting in the open,
by day, on the Oat, in summer - a mode of fi1hting founded upon the
face-to·faa: encounter of two tcts of phalanxes. And yet, ju1t u only a
tiny number of Atheniui girls played the part of 'bears', only a tiny
number of Spartiates followed thit mode of life which JeanmaiJT com-
pared to the 'Jycanthropy' known particularly in Africa Ueanmairc,
1959: 540-69). Plutarch notes that it wu 'the mosl utute' ( ~
,->.urra """" tx«" bociim>\': Lif• of Lycu,ps 28.2) youns Sparuate,
who were chosen for this ritual of 1tatus·transition; uid it ii probahlr
that, once they had become adulu and full wurion, it wu the ltrupto1
who composed the elite fonnation of thl"ft hundred 'cavalrymen'
(Nf'l'N: they actually fou1ht on foot), conccmed above all with police
dutiea ije....,..;n:, 1959: 5•2-5). In other wordt it is impoaaible to
...,,Mii
cletach the • from the pnctical part which it played in Spanlate
181
Pierre VidaJ-Naquet
society, a rOle which mutt ha~ been developed fort.he m~t part .from
the eighth century, the date of the conqu~t of ~cssaua; th~t 11, to
maintain in every way possible a rq,rut1ve regime facxd_ w,th the
endemic tt:beltions or the subject population of Meucma and of
Lakonia itself. The Jr.ru.plos, like the ephebc or Athenian myth, 11 a
guildul hunter - but he hunts helots (Wachsmuth, 1846: l.f~2i
2.30f). The temporary 'wildness' of the hrupt~tll. is an utterly soc1a..l-
ized, even political, wildneu: it functions directly to maintain the
political and social order.
At first glance, the education of the young Spartiate, the •10gi,
which was the precondition for the entry of a Sparti.ate into ruU citizen-
ship, has every appearance of being a system of initiatory rituals of
'primitive' type which ttmained, in the classical period and even there-
after, fully effective. Ind«d Spana is the only G~ck city whc-re ~
know at any rate the names of the different age-classc, which articulated
childhood, youth and adolescence (Brclich, 1969: 116-17). According
to a Roman historian, 'Lycurgus laid down that the children should be
brought up not in the area of the city but in the fields so that they
might past their early years not in luxury but in toil and suffcrin3; and
he directed that they should return to the city only when they had
!)(:come fully~own men' Uustin 3.3.6). "Bush' venus city, childhood
versus adulthood: the oppositions look transpattat. But if we look
more closely, things arc not so clear. One surprising point fint of~.
which seems to have escaped notice: it Kerns difficult, not to say
impossible, to fix precisely the point at which a young Spartiate
became a full a.dult.' 5 We know of coune tha.t around twenty or
twenty-one the Span.iate eirin (i.e. ephebe) became a spluzirnu ('ball-
player') (Pausaniu 3.14.6). But this moment docs not seem to have
been made particularly drama.tic: nothing at Sparta recalls the oath of
the Athenian cphebes when they became hoplitcs, though ,uch an oath
is found in other societies in srvcral respects closer to Sparta than to
At.hem, for example in Crete. A text of Xenophon has sometimes been
used to prove the existence of such a statu11-tran.sition at thi, point
(Brdicb, 1969: 125). But it say, nothing of the kind - mdttd quite
the rcvcne: 'In respect of those who have p~d through the period of
adolescence and arc now eligible even for the highest public ofliccs. the
other Gn:ek states no longer insist that they should keep fit, yet lay
upon them neverthclcu the obligation to go on campaign; Lycurgus on
the other hand laid down that for men of this a,c hunting was the
perfect thing, so long as it did not interfere with any public obligation.
so that they too would be able to su,tain the physjcal h:vd&hip of
cunpaigning no lcu than thosie in the flo~r of ,their yo.. th' (Xenophon,
Constitution of the Ulcedaemo,U,u 4. 7). It tS hard to trll whctheor
182
RrciPts for Grrtlt odolrsc•nct
adulthood at Sparta wu an cxtmaion of childhood; or whether child-
hood Wiii rather an anticipatory preparation for the life or an adult and
a so~r. At any rate, by contrast with what happened elsewhere, for
example in Ctttc, marriage is in no sense the point at which adol('tc('nce
comes to an end: for several yun after his muri~c. the husband con-
tinued to live in barracks, and saw his 'M.fr only in secttt (Xenophon,
COtLSt. laud. 1.5; Plutuch, Lafe of Lycurgus 15). Morco~r. whereas
in other Greek cities it w;u the offcri111 of the child's long hair that
marked the end of adolcscmcc, in Sputa it was customary for the adult
maks to wear their hair long (Herodotus 1.82; Plutarch, Lifr of
Lysander l ). The offering of the hair is a ritual of status-transition,
because it involves a 'before' and an 'after'; to keep one's hair is quite
different, because that can hardly be betokened by a ceremony. And
search though one may through the successive ordeals undergone by a
young Spartiatc, the most notorious of which is the cheese-stealing
beneath the lash at the altar of Artemis Orthia.." for thc ghosts of
initiations and even of fictive deaths, not one of these ordeals is in the
least decisive (Brelich, 1969: 156).
By contrail, a patient reading of the well-known tex.tJ which describe
the 410gi, Xenophon's C'11Utitution of the Loced«monians and
Plutarch"s Life of Lycur-ps, reveals one striking fact. Childhood at
Sparta has two iimultancom connotations: 'Nvagcry' and hoplite-
culture: the child is at one and the same time a small animal and a prc-
hoplite; and that is the mark of thc extent to which properly military
institutions 'consumed' Spartiatc education. The vocabulary - so far as
we have any direct knowledge of it - i1 characteristic. For the groups
of young men, two words were used in antiquity: oge/4, fJoek; and the
word ii.a, which really means the group of young 1oldiers ..n Xenophon's
description is particularly telling: th,: children arc simultaneously intro-
duced, like the lcruptoi, to guile, to 1tealing, lo activity by night; but
they also mix with the adults at thC' nasitia, the common muls (Co,ut.
Laced. 2.5-8; cf. Pluwch, lycurps 12). One ritual deserves ~pc:cia.l
cmphuis: from time to time two batallions (mofrai "" "'orai, .1 term
used in the Spartan army) of Spartan 'cphebcs' met at Plat.misw
{'Plane-tree Wood': actually an open space surrounded by plane trees.
Ed.) in Spa.rta. The fight was simultaneously hoplite and 'wild', since
the combatants were allowed to resort to a number of ~xpedient,,
including biting, which were ordinarily forbidden; and _it was pn
ceded Uy the sacrifice to Enyalios, the god of Bloody Fight, ol lwo
dogs, that is of the most domesticated of animals - in fact, to be more
precise, of two puppic:11 (cf. Plutarch, Q114t'stionn romanae 111, 290d).
]t wu preceded too by 41 fight between two wild-hoars, wild U1imal1 if
ever there were, but in this cue ithalUs, which mc,rns 't.ame'. The vie·
18l
Pierre Vidal·Naquet
tory of the boar belongin1 to Ont' or other camp usu.an; en,u.~ the
victory of its group of young mcn. 11 It al.I looks u 1f the ~Id and
'culture' were not memin whose hostility had to be dramauz«d, but
two opposed principles which it wu appropriate • far as ~blc to
bring tognher.H It w• the lrn,ptoi alone who had the pnvilqr of
dramatizing their hostility.
As early as Lafitau it had bttn noted that the •tatu, of womm at
Sparta wu quite di£ferent from elsewhere in Grectt; and he ewn uSN.
the word •gynaecocncy• ('rule of women') in thi1 conflect.ion (l.75).
One might aay in gcncnl that in the mo,t archaic of archaizing Greek
cities the opposition bctwccn the sexes was ,ttt~d lcu hn.vily th:'° in
a dcmocntic city such u Athens. In the laucr female pown 11 an
issue only in comedy and in utopian thinking; at Sparta or Loffllll and
cllcwhcre it fonn1 part of the historical-lcFndary tradition, auoc:iatcd
moreOYCr with po-werbcingsciud by the daYCS (pp. 189-200 below). In
the particular cue of Sparta, and of what little we know of its •fcmalr
Jnitiations* we know that the Spartiate woman underwent on hu
marriage rituals of invcnion comparable to thOK known dsewhctt in
the Greek world: the girl 'wu put into the care of a woma called a
mnnph.nhia, who shaved her hair, clrcucd her in the clothes and the
shoes of a man, and settled brr down on a mattreu stuffed with leaves.
all alone and without light' (Plutarch, Virtun of Worian. 245(; L1e11rp,
15). But aenerally spcakin1 what we know of a girl's childhood. and
adoleterncc gives less the impression of bein1 a preparation, punctuated
by rituals, for marriafe, th• an imitation of imtitudons for males ....
not that the Sputiatc woman prepares henelf for war. like tht!' fem UC'
citizcN of Plato's R..,blic and Law,; but the only specifically £emalc
duty whid'I mnainl ii the obligation to produce fine childRn. The
Spartiate family ii ..:araly an institution of the city, which on
the contrary took peat pains to rrstrict funily lffc to the baft
minimum.
At any rate, the irnprulion given by the few ancient texts is not so
much of a parallelum between the education of aids and that of boyi
(compare Brelich, 1969: 157), as or a direct reproduclion: thc,e wc,c
.,._ of girb u wdl u of boys (Pindar, l'I. 112 SneU); nakcdn. . ,...
obtiptory for girls in certain ttrcmonies u it wu for boy, (Plutarch.
Lyn.,p, 14--15); both teKes had to perform physical exnc:ilc1 .-nd
compete (Xenophon, Co,vt. I.M~. l.4) - it would be cay to (IO on.
Certainly the reproduction was not complell': little prh md ecea•"
were not orpnized into a,e·clusc1; in maoy twb the girl•' rol£ w•
different from that of boy,; boy, alone u ~ orm• to rest
endurance tuch u that at the altar of Aneinit Orthia; and the.,.,.,..
wa1 1b'ictly conrmed to mala, jUR II were all the properly political
114
R«;p,, for Gr.,• •dol,1cmtt
imtitution, of andmt Sparta. The Spartiat< prl wu in a real ICIIK a
boymanqui.
It will probably now be clear where the compariaon bctwcm Athen,
ud Spmu has led ua - a comparison which I am not the fint, nor the
lut, to m.akt. In each case the lexical item, of the lanauap of initiation
are doubtless the same; and it is euy enough to find in them the
oppo,.d pairs which modem 111thropology hu tau9"t ua to discover.
But their articulation into phrasa is radically diffeftnt - 10 much 10
that one would almost WU'lt to say that the opposition between Athens
Uld Spana at the level of practice ii nearly as strict as it is in
Thucydides's speeches. Yet this opposition is quite evidently the consc·
qumcc of a historical development which accentuated instead of
reducing the differences. No doubt Greek society is a 'historical'
societyj and we k.now some have contruted • "cold" and "'hot"
societies; the former seeking. by the institutions they give themaelves,
to annul the possible effects of historical facton on their equilibrium
and continuity in a quasi-automatic fashion, the latter resoluttly
internalizing the historical procc• and making it the moving power of
their dew,lopment' (Uvi-Strauaa, 1966-, 234). But Sparta is the arch<·
type exactly of a society which refuses to internalize history and which
is, for all that, compared with the other Greek. states, the comcquen«
of a complex historical evolution. The quad.on now is whether, having
borrowed from the anthropolopts ideu they themselves took over,
with chanp, from structunl lin11.1istics, we in tum should not require
of them the same holism which they have quite properly demanded of
us: that they should give the l&IIH~ weight to the diachronic dimension
u to synchronic analysil. 41 Unlea we make that demand, what signifi-
cance could the 1y1kms of sign, po1sc11 within which we encapsulate
the societies we study - ignorin1 their Kicntific import, of coune,
which ii 1upra-historical, not to say supra-ethnolosical - but the
dcpos.it or the spoor that each of them leaves be-hind in the form or
ttxts, anworks or ruins? Edpr Morin has a nice commenl on tht
stranse world of tourist-guides: 'It ii a kind of gi1antic Luna.Park. The
land is ,tripped of its socioloSY {and of iu history) for the ta.kc of its
ethnology, its archaeology, ill folklore and its oddities."'' We can
admire the work of ethnolopts past and present - they have cnor·
mously increased the historian's 'proper' field. But without history c:m
ethnology be anything but a kind of day-trip - fmt-clus?
iV: Disorder and deviance
10. Slavery and the Rule of Women in
tradition, myth and utopia
Piem: Vidal-Naquet (1970, 1979)
To Shno,. Pr'"broh
Wuc then traditions in Greece about the rule of slaves or the rule of
women? lf so, is there any connection between them? On the fint
point, if ~ set aside such famous but obscure episodes of Helleniltic
history u the 'City of the Sun' founded by Aristonicus (Eumenes lll)
of Perpmum (Rohen, 1962: 264-7l;Dumont, 1966: 189-96;Finlcy,
1975a: 183-4), or the anecdote about Chio, reported by Nymphodorus
of Syra.CUK (ap. Athcnacus.D.ipnosophistoe 6, 265c-266c),4 evidence
in myth for the city of the &laves (Doulopoli.s or dou/On polis) is thin.
To a Greek, the very expression wu of counc contradictory. A
character in the Anchises of Anax.andridc1 (a writer of Middle Comedies,
mid-foun.h century BC) pull the point 1uccincll.y: 'Slaves have no city,
old man' --- oo< lion liouXw•, .:,.Y<IB', ol,&r,.o,i in!X« (frg. 4 (GAF 2,
p. 137} = Athenacus, Vftfmosoplustae 6, 265b). There arc references in
historians, comedians (quoted, unfortunately, only by Jcxicogn.phcn)
ad puotmiographcn to a 'city of slavcs',S a place where all one had to
do to become free wu to bring a atone (Hccatat:us of Milctus, FGrH 1
F 345, Crom Stephanus of Byz:antium). This city is b&ff'ly dutingui.shcd
in the tradition from the City of Crooks (Po"hopolU: Pliny, HN 4.41;
Plutarch, De curiositot,: 10, 520b),• or from the onr- in which there as
only one frrc m;m, the priest (l-lccatacus, FGrll I t' 345 ).
The one interesting feature of these tcxu is the locatioa ucribed to
this 'city of slaves'. Sometimes it is placed in biU'barian tcnitory (Egypt,
Libya, Syria, Caria, Arabia); sometimes in Crete.' And what intereslcd
Soaicratcs and Dosiadas, who both wrote Histon'es of Crde (J'GrH 461
F 4 and 458 F 2, 3, from Athcnan&s, DeipnoJophistae 6, 263f-264.1>.
was precisely the different terms used for 'slaves' - or rather the stat1n:·~
'between slave and free' - on the illand, the place pat cxccllenn· m
antiquity where technical terms of this kind were developed (cf. Vida.I·
Naquct, 1965: 128 n. 46). Not one ~xt locales~ 'city of slaws' in any
part of Greece where davcry in the stnct ,ense cxmcd - thal b, chattel·
slavery b,-d on slavc·t.rading.•
)89
Pierre Vidal-Naquet
That implies that when the Greeks wanted to ~~ •. 'city of
slaves' they could chooae: only bctwcm complete marginaliza~on (!Mr·
barian countries) and locatin1 it in a counuy ~ a 'sl-:c was n.ot
quite a slave. There is a tense ila which Naupactus (founded: m the- ~~
fifth century by helots who had Ocd from Mcucnia), and othn abC'I
established by the Menenians, and Mnsmc it.elf (rcfoundcd afttr
Epaminondas's upcd.ition, !69 BC), might be added to Cretan
Doulopolis. Yet even when they had become helots, the Meumians
continued: to be thought of• Greeb and Dorians, jwt like the Spartans
themK"lves. Pausanias claimed not only that they had not lost their
Dorian dialttt evffl after three ttnb.lries of exile for many or them; but
that, in the Empire, it was the purest Doric in the Peloponnese (4.27.
11 ). The right of these relllly peculiar 'slaves' to a political ex is ten« or
revival, a right which they rq,catedly assC"rttd, could be legitimated by
means such as these.
And what of women? llncarch in this area has been srcat1,· stimu·
lated by the work of Simon Pembroke: on Greek uaditions about 'matri·
archy'.' In the lut century Bachoren, followed by Enaels and many
othen, saw matriarchy u a universal stage in tM history of man. It,
'survivals' - such as the institutions of Lyda dacribcd by Herodotus
(1.173) - wctt seen as evidence for an earlier period. Pembroke has
shown that the ancient sources do not stand up to qitical euminarion,
and that the Lycian imcripciom, for nample, show no trace whatrva
of a matriarchal system. But he has alto explained the l<>pcaJ. srructure
of the concept of matriardly itself: whelhcr we are taJ.k.in1 aboul the
Amazom or the Lycians, it ii tbc Greek polis, that male club, which ii
being defined by its hislOrians and its 'ethnographen' in terms of its
opposite (cf. now Roscllini. and S.td, 1978: 949-100~). There ii a
splendid example of this technique or invenion, or rewnal, in
Hcrodotu1's statement thal the institutions of Egypt att euctly tbc
oppo1itc of thox of the Grttks (2.35). The imagi~ polj_ty_af__$hc
~~ _tl:!._e inVf:!!!i, set in a precise locadOft, 0( the Grttk city.
Lcmno,, the ilbnd noloriom for its 'atrocitic:t'.. is also characterized as
):,&.led.~·• The chorus in Aeschylus'• Libstion-bHrtn, ft'fcr·
riq to Cytemnutra, 11 picb up cxprcnion1 from the fant play, tht
.4pffl,annon: the mU1-womU1 (A,.,..nnnon l 0-11 ; 550 d. 259-60)
ond the 'female that kills the mole' ("iAo< &po...,._.....,., A,- 12!1) -
human monsters who have failed to pas, the barrier separating....,,..
from civilization:
'i"he mule fOIU, the dnpencr
IGVCCQ1111itsNliltalway
- •mriip Md lhc dark e•br.llC"~
of lmne beu&a. of ....W .....
(599-601, tr. La1tnon)
190
St.vny and th• Ru/• of ll'o"'""
l'lo!e """ ,...red hen: 11 'the female force' is tluiluAratis, an adjective
whicll ca metll both 'which conquen women' and 'where the female
hM ....-,; ·and tho lint cxamp~ Ihm &ivon is that or the Lemnian
...,..., (691--4), whose 'powor' took the form or tho murder or their
hu........ -
.Now·the tradition doa know of female power exercised honourably.
But tho fflCVlllt texts speak not of Athens (see p. 198 below) but or
Spana, which 'WU o( c:ounc the mak city par excellence - but also the
city Amtotlc beli~ to be threatened politically by a takeover by
women, u we have lff1'I (p. 188 abOYe). Plutarch records a famous
witdcilm by Gorgo, wife of Leonid• and. according to Herodotus
(5.!l), the woman who prncn~d Clcomene1 from doing as Aristagoras
of M.iktus wished (i.e. to support the Ionian revolt against the Pcnians
in 499/98): to a woman who observed, 'You Spartan women att tht·
only women who give men ordcn', she was supposed to have ~plied,
'Yes, because we uc the only women who give men birth' (Life of
l.yt'IIJ'PS 14.8; er. Apophth,putta L«,dMmonilln,m (Gorso( 6,
240c; Apophth<Jlffl4'4 l.awiumonio,um (Lycursu•I 15, 227c). And it
wu Sparta. not Athena, which provided Plato's model when he pve
women their place in his R.,.blic.
In \'Kw o[ all this. it ii perhaps worth enquiring whether theft wu an
111cicnt tradition in_ any way linlc.i1J.& .tb'-..a.aciat..ol.powa.~~n
~d by slavrs. I argue ihi1 such a tradition did indeed ex.isl, and in at
·1eaitf'0Ufforms.
The fmt is connected with a well-known hi11orical evcnl, the defeat
of Argos by the Spartans at the battle of Scpeia, which hu been dated
variously between 520 and 490 BC. 12 Our earliest source ii Hcrodotu1
(6. 77, 83), who prefaces his account with a Delphic oracle in venc pre-
dicting a drama in which ·~~-[~1!!~~-~!l..prcv~ over the ~~and win
glory among the Argivca•: · - ·- - -
l<)X-~B,j~"'""'llpw... -
tfe>.aoQ &oi •u6ot iv :\p"J'l'IOtOII-' 6i,oqrol.
Argos is defeated, and loses all i(s men. The aHain of state are run by
the llaves (tx,qpc.;,611 olfrw WO'T"f ol &w~o, abTW11 tuxo,, fflVf'O TO:
•P1h",,aM 6\oXOlo"l"t't} until the young Argi.vc citizen111 rnch manhood.
The 'davcs • thereupon flee to Tiryns, whence they arc ultimately driven
out by the Argivcs. In this account the two clements, rule of womc 11
and rule of slaves, arc pttscnt but are krpt separate: the fin1 occ.ur, iu
the oracle while the Kcond appcan in the historical a,;count. f11i~
scheme disappears in the later venions, which no doubt involves an
alteration 0 ( the original material; but thi1 hardly mal ten, aincc rny
taak ia not to reconsUUct the •fact,' but to und~ntand Ile IGpC of
the myth&. What is important di that nrcn in H~rodutus Areos is an
191
Pierre Vidal-Naquet
u_pside-do~_world: the frmale has o\·ercomc the male and the slncs
arc in power. u . .
Plutarch (De mulierum 11frtutibw 4, 245f) gave! hu o~ giou to
Herodotus in quoting him as saying that when the cty Iott JU ~en ~
'slaves' married the Argive women; and introduces, from the h1sto~
Socrates 0 £ Argos, a new character, Tdesilla. a poet~. She ?rgamzcs
the women of Argos to defend the city, dressing them in mens do~
_ which later P"e them the right of putting up a comm~mont:M=
monument to Enyalios, the god of warriors (245c-e). Most un.portant
of all, be says that thit episode wu the origin of a festival still 0celcbn.tcd
in Argos, the hyl!Pll.li~!_:!'~~-h- c'?m_m.c;ff!o_~te, t!'e "'!'~fn . 1 . _ ~
and in the course of which men and women wear each other s drns
<2~.:;!.,,, ~
venion di!fmnt again (2.20.8-9). Acco,ding to him,
Tclesilla called upon all those who could take pan in the defence of the
city - women, the old men, the young boys, the slave, (oiAl:et.u): in
other words, all those normally excluded froro fighting for the polis.
(He also quotes Herodotus's oracle, however: 2.20.10. Ed.)
But who exactly were theM!: slaves? Aristotk's own mention of this
'sen.rile interregnum' (Polih.cs 5.3.7, 1303a6-8) says nothing of womm
at all: he obJervcs simply that the Argives 'had ~n forc.cd tc;, admit
into the city a cenain number of pm'o;Aai': "1AJO"JKQ09,Ja(DI
fflPQ6'Ea:o6w TW11 repfDU(w11 TW<'. It has been shown that Aristotle
generally uses the word perioiltoi to mean rural dependant! or bond,-
mcn rather like the belou of Laconia (\\'ilk-tts, 1959: 496). And in fact
there can be no doubt but that our sources' Argivc 'slaves' arc to ht
identified with the occupants of the servile status-category known ill
Argos as the p,nnitllh: those who were 'naked' by contrast with thosc-
who wore the hoplitc pmoply. Equally important, when Ari1totle
wanu to give a comparable example from Athens, he speaks not of the
recruitment of slaves but of hoplitc, from outside ua~
r~gisteT - that i.s,
the thiles, the citizen, of the lowest category i.n term• of property.
A tndition known from much latrr texts offen a panlld SCJ ptteisc
with the Argivc episode as to be 1uspicious. This time we att at Cums,
in Magna Graccia, where in 505/4 BC Arirtodcmu, made bim,clf tyrant,
put to death or exiled the aristocrats and be,towed thcit propert',', tbc:0
wives and their daughtcn, upon the slavN who bad 11tWdcrtd thcit
mutrn. 1• That left, according to our principal sour«, Dionysiu> of
Halicamassus, only the fate of the roalc childttn to be dictermiDed. Al
first, Aristo<kmus thought of putting them. all to death; but afW
appcala from their mo~n. and the lattcn'iitlcw lovcn, dccidc-d to .nd
them off 10 the fields to lead scrvlk lives of agricultu~ or ~101al
labour. The world is turned upside-down: the you.na aristocrau tab cht
192
Slavery and the Rule of Women
pl&« or the 'slavtt' whom they now se~. So far, we can interpret the
rtory in common-sense terms: hut what follows i1 rather odd. TheK
yoang alaves in the fields an brouwh.t up u girls: long curly tre11e1, kept
in a net: embroidettd dresses; Living in the ,hadc or parasols, with cnd-
lca baths and perfume (Dionysiu, of Halicamassu1, Ant. Rom. 7.9.4
Jacoby). It is hard not to suppose a ritual comparable to the Argive
hybristillo or the Oschophorio in Athens (see pp. U6-8 above). There
comes a time when the 'sons' - who seem, as in Argos, to be all of an
. - - riK in revolt and with the help of the exiles suppress the tyrant
(Ant. Rom. 7 .9.6). It is Plutuch who supplies the dimension of the
episode ~Levant to the theme of the rule of women (De mulierum
uirtvtibvs 26, 262c-d): Xenocrite, the daughter of an c:,;ile, becam"
Aristodemus '1 mistress; and it was she who persuaded the young men to
tupprcss the tyrant (c. 491/90), together with an unnamed woman al
Cumac who JTmarked to them that Aristodcmus was the sole man
(oni,) in the city (262b).
Herc again servile power and female power arc linked, the women
assuring the continuity or legitimacy. But it is lcs, easy to say what pre·
ciscly the 'slaves' were, though the 'hclot·typc', given that these men
scrmingly lived in the fields and made an effort to act politically or
collectively, is mott likely than the 'Athenian' type.
My third ex.ample comrt from the well-known tradition about the
origins of Epizcphyrian Locris in Sou them Italy, a colony founded by
mainland Locrians, whether Opuntian or Ozolian is undcar. 11 The
foundation of the city was the subject of an acrimonious debate,
reported by Polybius, bctwccn Aristotle (or more probably the author
or the Peripatetic Constitutiot1 of Locris) and the Sicilian historian
Timacu, of Tauromenium; Poly bi us reports the debate as part of his
own polemic against Timaeu1. 1• Aristotle said that Locril had been
founded by riffraff, runaway slave, and 1lavc-d<"alrrs; m reply, Timaeus
argued that in the very early period 'it was nut the nationaJ custom of
the Gtteks to use slaves bought with moncy'. 11 Nu doubt repeating
Aristotle, Polybiu1 then tells the story of how, when the Locrians WCI"<'
the allies of Sparta in the Mcs,enian War (pttsumably the fint war),
they wctt prevented - perhaps by an oath, as in the lc~nd of the
foundation of Tarentum (sec p. 195 below), but certainly cffrcti'vely -
from having intercourse with their wives. The wives then tumt"d 1"
substitute husbands, the slave,; and it was these women and 1lavc~ who
later became the fint colonists of Italian Locris. Consequently
hereditary nobility in the colony was derived originally not from the
men but from the women: .-a,,,rQ' rd: 6ca 1rpO"(dvw1,1 fVOOEa rap' ailroi~
tinrO f"WI' ,yuM111CWv OOK b~ .,.e,;,., lri16pWt1 tonv (Polyhius 12.5.6). We
also know that some of the female founders of Locris belonged to the
19,
Picl'T" Vidal-Naquet
hundred noble families who had the 'pri"Vilegc' of K"nding two girls each
year to serve Athena of llion. 1• • • •
Irenically-minded rcaden will doubdns obserYC tha~ It 11 not unpoN-
ible to reconcile Aristode and Timaeus, at lcut m tmnl of the
coherence of the tradition. Certainly a famou1 inscription, tht branu
plaque £rom Galaxidi (Ozolian (Western) Locrisl, seems to prow the
existence of hclotagc in Locrian territory at an early date (early fifth
century BC)." The inscription gives the regulations for ~ colony
established by the E•tem Locriam at Naupactus, and prescnbca • tM
penalty for a magistrate who refuses_ justice to a plain.tiff ~c ~ru:
cation of his property, cbe land 1uc:lf together With tts sla~
(rooi.tidtai): ,CCU x,,,,aro. ~E"ioflOI. TO ,d11« 11mlr Fouc.lMCIP
(lincs 45-5). Notwithstanding that Hesychius identifies the oiltulis
(which occun only here) with the chattel-slave (OUC:11)~: WIIIJTO('
aou>..~). there can be little doubt but that the Locrian woilt.ill.lM, wbme
position is linked closely with the citizen's land-allotment, is more like
that of the Cretan woi4nu (FOUtak): he is in effect a helot. So there is
no reason not to accept that in the tradition followed b)· Aristode and
Polybius the Locrian 'slaves' who married their mistresses ~ in a
category similar to that of tbe Argive pmnitoi.
The women '1 rOle is no less important, thou(lh Polybius doC"s not say,
as has been claimed, that at Epizephyrian Locris' nobility desccnclcd
through the fC"male line: he lll)'S simply th•t originally in the Locrian
'nobility' there wa a FOUp of women; lhcy were citizens, and many of
them or good familie1; and their husbands were lll•vet." And he
explains by reference to thit same tradition the fact that a procatioa,
which he says was taken o\'er from the Siculi, waled by a girl •d not
by a boy (12.5.10-11).
This connection between female citinns and "slaves• recun in a
legendary tradition whose "Variants are far more complex, that of the
Foundation ofTarent\UD..21 Although all the sources agstt i.n clc.scribinl
the foundcn or Tarentum as a minority felt to be ,1adesirable in their
country of origin, Sputa, and who were c:allC"d the Partllmilll. thcR
were at lcut thrft versions. The oldest is rcpraented by Antiochw of
Syracuse, a contemporary of Thucydides (FCrH 555 F 13, from SUMG
6.3.2 (278-279C) cl. Vidol-Noquet, 1975b: 2!1-42). Hc.1ayt tl,ot
during the firat Mc11Cnian War the Sputiates dilfranc:b.Qcd lftQIC: qi
their number who had not taken pan in the tlghan,: they were~
sla"Vel (~,cp"l'poa.r 6au01) and then:after termed "helop', u werr dtcil
dc1Cendanu, the ,.,,.nilli. The ls.UC"r plotted '°IHM', but 'MN cl"_.
covered by lho ephon ( the onnual ,,,...,,..., or SponaJ , tl,cy """'
n.pelled from die ci1y and amt to h.J.y. Ith.is vcniaD caa,... ·~
mylhs: one about the foundation or Tuentu.m., the odwr .bout the
·'• a 194
Slavery and the Rule of Women
origin or Spartan 'slavery': the original helots are supposN to have been
tresantt:s, those Spartiates who had failed in war and so been dis-
franchi.z.ed (Herodotus 7.231; Plutarch, Lift: of Agesilaus 30; Life of
Lycurgus 21.2; cf. now Loraux, 1977: 105-20).
Strabo rejects this version in favour of one followed by the fourth-
ccntury historian Ephorus and consequently by many others, whether
directly or indirectly (FGrH 70 F 216, from Strabo 6.3.3 [279-
SOCJ ) .21 The Spartans were at war with Messenia and had sworn not to
return home until they were victorious. But the war dragged on, and
the next generation could not be born. It was decided that the young
men, who had not taken the oath, should return home to Sparta and
all of them should have intercourse with all the young women
(partheno1) so far as possible: avr,l.veafJai mi~ wap(Jf1101,f; itwaoa,.~
cho:Pl'a(.21 It was the offspring or these promiscuous unions, who knew
their mothers but not their fathers, who received the name Partheniai.
In other words, the Partheniai were the result not of normal marriage
but of a sort of original saamble (Rosellini and Said, 1978: 955-66,
995-1003).
The third and simplest version is analogous to that of the foundation
of Epizephyrian Locri: while the Spartiates were away fighting, their
wives slept with their slaves, and the Partheniai were the resulting
bastards. 14
There are some further texts which arc not quite parallel to any of
these versions. A rather elliptical passage of Aristotle (Politics 5.7 .2,
1306b27-31) seems to suggest that the Partheniai suffered from some
kind of political discrimination without there being any question about
their birth. 35 To make things even more complicated, a fragment of
Diodorus Siculus published in 1827 (8.21) gives a composite account of
a rebellion which occurred in Sparta after the First Messenian War. 2•
The most important group of rebels were the epeunaletai, who arc
defined by Hesychius as atl'JKOijtipr(u, 'bed-fellows'; they were respon·
sible for the plot, and later got in touch with Delphi in order to found a
colony. The other group was the Partheniai, who came to terms with
Sparta as soon as the conspiracy was discovered. It is tempting, but
unprovable, to suppose that the second arc the sons of the first. 11 They
arc often confused, all the more easily in view of Hcsychius's equivalent
for the very similar word epeu.nahtai: Portheniai. But Thcopompus docs
explain the identity of the epeu.nahtai (though he calls them
epeunaletoi): they were helots who during the Mcsscnian War - he docs
not say which one - took the place of the dead Spartiatcs, not in their
marital beds but 'on their beds in camp': bird:~ onJ3dt6o:~ (FGrH 115 F
!, from Athcnacus, Deipnosophistae 6, 272a; cf. Pembroke, 1970:
•
1245-7). It is important to understand that in the myths relating to
195
Pier:'f' Vidal-Naquet
Sparta a 'slave' could substitute for a citizen in his basic du.ty, thal: of
fighting. . . ..
Although these venion.1 are all 10 different, thae u on~ cOnJC.Ut. it
is the women who ensure the continuation of the population. In shorl,
the P,,,.tlaniai are the sons of young wonu•n befOff they att tM IOftl of
men. The versions disagree only about the identity of their fathers. And
yet as a. whole they are quite coherent. In the tint case ~Antioch~•)
they are cowards, in the second (Ephonas) young men, an the third
(Hcraclcides) '1laves'; and perhaps for Aristotle political infcrion. In the
fint cue they arc made cliltinctivc by a moral judgement; in the second
by their place in the rystcm of age-classes; in the third by a social judl'·
mcnt; and in the founh by their place in the political hierarchy. The
variants have a common theme: the fathcn of the Parthna;ai both arc
and arc not of the city - they arc nu,rginal. Exactly the same WU true
of the Argivc 'slaves' and of the husbands of the women who founded
Locris; the nonnal hierarchy is invcn.cd.
Other texts on the foundation of Tarentum make thi1 invcnion
quite explicit, though it is unfortunate that they arc often contaminated
by traditions about the foundation of Rhcgium (Vallct, 1958: 68-76;
Ducat, 1974: 93-114; Valenza. Mcie, 1977: 512-17). An oracle i1 said
to have advised the foundcn of Tarentum to settle' where they uw a
she-goat mounting a buck.,11 or where they saw rain falling out of a
clear 1ky (Pausanias 10.10.&V" Both arc ways of sugatin9 an inwrtcd
world. The parallel texts about Rhcgium quite explicitly dirrct the
founder, Antimcdcs of Chalcis, to • place where he saw 'the male
mounted by the [cmalc'i 'fOv tipp~ta lnrO nj( "1h~ bwudpl'..,..
(Diodorus Siculu.s 8.2:5.2; Heraclcides Ponticu1, hri Poluftim 25 •
FHG 2, 220) - which takes us right back to the oracle Herodotus says
was given to th~ Argivc.1 (p. 191 above).
All the same, thUI topsy-turvy world which gives extraordinary
prominence to women and to 'slaves' is an imaginable one. Whneas at
Athens the exceptional UIC' o[ slaves in war wu logically followt'd by
their emancipation," in Sparta there was nothing unusual about hd.ou
u such fighting - as in the case of Thcopompu111 -,mmelttoi (d.
Herodotus 9.29; Thucydides 4.80 etc.). Likcwilc, the Gortyn law Code
provides for the possibility or a marriqr between a male tbave and a
fttc woman: 'If the s1aft (dOlos) sacs to the [rec woman ad muria
her, their children will M free; but if the fttc womm goes to tht alawc
and marries him, their children will be slaves•: (al 11:' b IP.~) 1t•i.,.,
IA<U6'pco, !AB°"'"""''· l!Aalfl•p'i~ li>nirft,a.al.U •' llltAruB,pcr
hrl nw M).o•, &P.' fµ I i•ni ri<..,(/C4,a.!'7Z,col. 6,56; 7, t-5)."
Moreover, although in the classical period Spartiatc marrillN'Ulc• did
not permit such liaisons, they a1 leut pvc both husbmd and wife tha
196
Slavery and the Rule of Womt'11
right to take a sub,titute partner (Xenophon, Constitution of the
Lacedaemonians 1.7-8). And there was at Rome, in a religious context,
an association between slaves and women: at the Saturnalia masten
(domiratl served their slaves (servi), while at the Matronalia, wives were
honoured by their husbands and prepared a feast for their male slaves:l2
yet another detail that makes archaic Rome look more like Sparta than
Athens.
All the same, Lysistrata at onc point calls for a Scythian archcr, an<l
slaves appear on a number of occasions (18, 184, 241) ..
But of course my best cvidence here comes from 1he Assnnbl! of
Women (Ecclesiazusae). The play is based upon a double transvestism,
199
Pierre Vid&l·Naquct
fint that usociatcd with the fcnival of Athena Skiru (the Sli,...,._.)
when women dressed up in beards (18, 25, 38, cf. p. 156 above), bat
also the comedy's own: the Athmian women dill',UIC dNnnlclva u
men in order to votc themselves into power in the A.ucrobly. The com-
munist system they start is prnentcd as thc fulfilment of democncy
and involves the sharing of all wealth risible and iavuible, iaduclint:
slaves. h is rorbiddcn that some should have much and othcn nothiag
at all. But of course the bnd itself will be worked by sines - while
cbeir muten ttlu. and wait for their dinncn (593, 602, 631, 651-S,
c(. PIKltu 510). Now all this is rcuonably familiar; perhaps le11 so arc
the sexual implications of this femino-communist democracy. For the
women propose to equaliH 1exual opportunity (944-5) - for the
young citizens naturally: of male slaves, not a word. By conttast, the
fana1c slaves are expressly cxduded from citizen-amours: they have to
IDMe arnnacmcnts with male slave, (725-7).
Ariltode's point ttmains tnlC then: theff is some difracnce betwcca
women and alavcs. An Aristopbanic utopia can put women on top, jutt
u Plato later can set them almost on the aunc level as men. But chattel·
Uva are limply not part of the city at all. And I would say that myth,
legendary tradition and utopiu as wcU, respected this ,tau of affairs
. even though it was of recent datc. 11 A myth accounts for_lhc n:ducti9!!.
of the statu~ of women_ at ,Mlle.w_ a,. 911e brick in the wall betw_cai
sav111ef-i"iAa..c!isor4~ ..Q.P. dll..ilof t\¥~.1 anc1 civiC-mder ~
s~·t the distinction bctWCfll free mcn and ·,i;;;-~p1y-~~ not a "prob-
lem' of this kind. In uchaic societies on the other band ( of which
Sparta is the bc11 known), the: situation. is quite different. Slavery w.
undcnilood thtte u having an origin in biltory (J have disc:uucd one of
the traditions in thi1 connection, but lhere ~ many othen), Uld on a
number of occaaiom the status of women and the status o( llava are
sccn 1.1 linked. Each occupies a variable polition on the continuum
between the free Uld the non-free.
I began by oboerving that Athens md Spana con be ,..., • loti<aJ
oppositca; I hope that this at.udy serves to reinforce the paia&•
..
200
,,
,f!~.
Many 1cholan have compared the island of Atlantis with the Phaeaciam'
Schcria. 14 And the paral1clilm cannot be doubted. After all, the tint:·
dom or AlcinOU1, with itl idealized patriarchal monarchy and ill palace
filled with marvels. is the rust utopian city in Grttk literature (Finlry,
1977: 100-2, 156). At lcut, that might have been the imprasion of a
fourth-century Greek. Again, it is importmt that we have a utopia
connected with the sea. Schcria, like Atlantia, is a city of tail.on:
ncy, conflclent in the ipCed of their nalllUIII ilhlpa, a - O"ff'I'
the peat opm watcr, liacir thil d the ti.rt of the Em-dlllbU.tt
to them... (Od),017 7.54-5. tr. Lattim.Oft)
The kinp or Atlantis weTe dctccndcd from the union of Poseidon •d a
mortal woman, Klcito, while Alcinou1 and ~ \ft'rc the dcsccnduu
of the union of Poseidon and the nymph Pen"boia (Critia, l Udct Od.
7.56r.). The one temple on Schcria is comccratcd to the god or the sea.
as is the one temple dcteribed by Plato (Od. 6.266;Critias l 16d-ll 7a).
Homer speaks of two sprinp, as don Plato (CM. 7.129; Crilia l 17a).
And 10 on.
The local colour then ii epjc t and Plato actually notc1 at the- very
beginning of the Tiffl8111 that Solon. had he to wished, could h&YC
equalled. Homer and Hesiod (Tim. 2lc). The names of tome o( tbc
kinp of the Feat itland aft bonowed from Homer. But heic Homer'•
world ii inverted: the land that bidl welcome hu become an empire
from which will Kt sail the armies dctcnnincd upon the. drstruction ol
Gree«; the parallclitm does not explain cvcrythin1 - ettn if it ougb.1
certainly to figun: in any dilcu11ion of Plato"• relation to Homer.
Then again, Paul Friedlindcr, and Joseph Bidez after him, ha.vc
strnscd the many reuons for supp~g Admtis, which Plato teLi II
the wcJtcm ed1e of the world, to be 1111 idealixd transposilion of CM
Eut and of the world of Pcnia (t'ricdlandcr,.,l958: 273-7; llld,s,
1945: Appendix II, S2--4). It ii ccru,inly pw,111,lc that Plato, dclcrij,-
1.ion of the walls of the capital city and chc city it.1elf ruy have bull
204
Athens ad Adntis
inlpind by Herodotus's description of Ecbatana md Babylon (Hdt.
1.91, 178; ad Critio.r l 16a ff.). The Greeks thought of m oriental king
• a lord of the waten. Herodotus dncribcs the legendary heart of Asia,
a plain, encirdcd by mountains, which gives rise to U1 imaginary mighty
river which flowed through the mountains in five branches until the
Great King built five sluice-gates that he alone could open (3.117). 11 I
need hardly recall what he says about the Nile, about Egypt U1d the
Pharaohs. The massive irrigation works undertaken by the kings of
Atlantis (Criti,u 117cd)and the scale of the kingdom itself arc sufficient
indication that Plato is thinking here primarily not of the tiny world of
the Greek city-states but of the universe of oriental despotism. Such an
interpretation might obviously lead one, as it has many (so Rivaud,
1925: 252), to view the strugle between Athens and Atlantis as a
mythical uansposition of the strugle between Greeb and Barbarians,
and the Persian Wan in particular. One can even show, as I do not think
it has been, that Plato was directly influenced by Herodotus. For in the
Timo:~w he says (20e):
And he 1okt my pandfather Critiu (.ccordinf to the 1tory the old man UICd to
repeat 10 wi) that then: ~ pul md admirable eaploiu perfonaed by OW' own
city long ..o. which have been loqotlen throupl i..,. ol dlae and the de,trv.clion
or b,ua.Ul We. (Tr. Cornford)
This is how Herodotus begins his history (1.1):
Tiie• ue the iaeudle1 ol Haodobll ol Thurii which be publiaha in tbe hope ol
thereby pn:IICl'\'iq from decay the remembrance ol what men have done, and ol
prcvcntiq: \he peat and wcmdc:rful actio111 of the Greet, and the Bubarianl from
Joline their du.c 111ccd or •orv ... (Tr. Rawlinson)
For his part, the historian tried to be fair to each of the warring sides. 11
But if the model is really the Penian Wars, then Plataea here comes
before Marathon. Athens starts out as leader of the Hellenes, but she
wins the victory alone, and she alone sets up the trophy and liberates
the Greeks and the subjects of Atlantis's empire (Tim. 25bc) - those
very cities and peoples over which the Athens of history had extended
her sway after the war. Should we find that surprising? The second
Penian war was for Plato maned by the naval engagements at Artemision
and Salamis (Laws 4, 707bc). When he discusses the matter, it is cer-
tainly not to praise Themistocles's daring and the decisive role or the
Oeet. While Xerxes made his preparations to invade Attica,
(The Athenians) eonlideriq di.al there wu no ulvation for them either by land ~·
by ICI .•. One chance of Alcly remained, llipi1 indeed and dnperatc, but _1hm
only one Th~ uw lha1 on the
former occuion th~
bad pined a 1eemmJI)
=-~:':.:a:~=:: u.:·,~:;:.::. ;:::c,'f',at their only refu~
But Plato's remodelled Athenian, do not get on board their ships: his
Athenians defeat the 1Cafuing men of Atlantis not on Lhe sea but on
205
Pi~~ Vidal-Naquet
Jand. An odd Athens; and an odd 'Orient'. But a closer look at the te.1111:J
leads u.s, without rejecting what we have learned •. ~o a more. cornpkx
interpreta.tion of the struple bctwC'en the tw0 c1ucs. ~lato I Athcras
meets and vanquiffles Atlantis; in so doing, she in reality ov~rcomes
herself.
That may sound strangl'.'; 11 but let us look once more at the facts and at
the texts.
On the west face of the: pediment of Pheidias's and lktinos's
Parthenon was represented the mythical dispute between Athena and
Poseidon. I think it no e~ration to say that this dispute was one of
the mythical foundations of Athenian history. The ironical funeral
speech in the Mnaexfflw dccla.res {237c):
Om COWlb'y U worthy to be pnikd. not cmly by u. bv.t by all mUlll:iftd; ftnt, and
abo~ all, u bdn& dear to the pelt. Thill i, proud by the nrife ;uid cOllikD.tion of
the sods tt1p«"tin1 her." (Tr. Jowett)
This passage is directly contradicted by one from the Critia (I09b):
In the day• of old, the 1ocb had the whole e.lh diltributed amon1 them by 111lot·
mcnt. There wu no qual'l'dllnf; for you cannat rishdy NppoK' that the pct. did
not Ir.now what w .. proper for eiach of than to h-,,c-, or. lr.nowin1 thh., that d!.cy
wouJd seclr. to procu.~ for cbnn1elvcs by contmtion di.at which more proped)'
bclon,rd to othcn. (T,. Jowett)
According to this. it was DikC who shattd out the allocations. Athcm
was assigned to Athena and Hephaestus, and Atlantis became the realm
0£ Poseidon (Cn.tias I09c and 113c). The two divinities wonhipped
together in the En:chthcum arc thus ,eparated; and Plato ttparates and
opposes likC'wisc: the two Greek forms of power: the Athenians, stem-
ming from th,c iced of Hephaestus and Gaia (Tim. 23e), inherited powa
on the land; th,c kinp of Atlantis, child~n of Poseidon, powe"r by sea.
But that very £act reveals to us that Plato i, prelt:'nting his native city
Crom two different points of view: the city of Athena and the olive·
trcic is identified with proto-Athens; and the city of Poseidon, Lord of
horses and of the 1ea, is realized in Atlanl:U.
Ut us take a closer look at the topography and the in1titutiom of
this idealized Athens. It i, cuentially an enormous .acropolis, which
include,, besides the cla.uical Acropolis, the Pnyx and Lyqb,ctto,, and
thus extends as far • tM Eridanus and the Lycabcttos rive~ and it ii
covered in earth. It is thus quilt di.ffeJ'C'nt froni tht' harsh rock. M'licb
Plato knew (Critw.J lllit-112a). Its summit fomu a)evd lift"
raolosed
by a sinfle wall (!-Pi •ep,lJo'l.f.f' •IIXJ•tPt.lSe~•= U 2b).» __.- ii
where thit second claa of t'hc population, the wvrion, live. Thir crafb-
men and the farmen live oultidc and work the field, Hyood. "*~
de,crib<t the cl.., of warrion (.-o "°""'°" .,....,
cAaro<te~1tioally b)
of an exprrnion dmotin:g what nitYCT th-.ai it im ff(t.1
206
Athens and Atlantis
ltatll' 11.uto. 11 Civic space is organized in a manner quite unlike that of
the classical city. There is no Agon. to be the me.son (centre) of political
lire; no tempk which might be the prototype of those built in the fifth
century. To the north, there arc common barracks, refectories suitable
apintt bad weather, and temples. To the south, gardens, gymnasia and
summer refectories (112bd). In the middle is the sanctuary of Athena
and Hephaestus, an evident transposition from the Hcphacstcion which
still dominates the Agon. today, and in front of which Pausanias
records that there stood a statue of Athena (which we know, like that
of Hephaestus, to have been the work of Alkamenes) - a conjunction
he found quite unsurprising in view of the myths of Erichthonius
(1.14.6; cf. Brone-cr, 1949: 52; Thompson and Wycherley, 1972:
140-9).
What docs this divine pair signify here? The Homeric Hymn to
Hephaestus sang of the God: 'With Athena of the glittering eyes he
taught men on earth wondrous crahs' (20.2-3). But this is not the only
tecllni which may be relevant.
Hephaes1w and Athena, who were brother and Pltcr, uad ,pran1 from the ,ame
father (llµa ,..0 tl&A¢,r)i, b: 1"111n'Ol/ 1rmpo('), h1.ving 1. common nature (1eO&J,q1,1 fuau,
tx:OIIT~(), and bein,: united allO iD the love of pbi1010phy and art (t,rtllnt), both
obtained u their common ponion this land. which wu natunlly adapted for wis-
dom andvirtue. 21 (Crit14J 109c, tr.Jo-It)
Hq,haeuus and Athena thus guavantcc the dose relationship between
the two cluses, guardians and produccn, of proto·Athens.
I have already observed that this Athens is land-based. The term
really applies to Attica as a whole, more extensive than Plato's city,
since it reached down to the Isthmus or Corinth (Cri#as llOe).u It is
a land wonderfullv fertile, covered with fields and forests, 'able in those
days to support .a vast army, exempt from the labours or the soil'
(CritUU llOd-l lle), and thus permitted soldien to be soldien only,
Plato hoped, proor of the development of military techni and pro·
fessionalism; while he was also eil.gCr to reconcile this evolution with the
ideal of the citizen-soldier, as nren Sparta had failed to do (cf. esp.
R~ublic 2, 373a ff.). To the very end of its history, the city of _the
Timaeus and the Critia.s is a republic of the land. When the temble
cataclysm comes, its army is swallowed by the earth (rO µQ):apo1,1 1r0'.1,1
Cl8p6o1,1 l6u ,ccrrO Tit), whereas Atlantis is engulfed by the sea (,ccrrO:
TTf( 6a:XaTTTlt 8Voa t,,t,avioBTJ) (Tim. 25d). It is hardly neccHary to
remark that in his account of prehistoric Athens Plato devoted no sp.in.""
to the life of the sea. The country is SU!Tounded by sea, but there arc
no harboun. A republic of the land: a republic united and unchanging.
Unity is the foundation of a11 Plato's 'constitutions';1• and here ~t is
assured by the divine pair and by community of wom~n and offspnng.
He stttues this unity and the lack of change even in tiny details: there
207
Pi.::Te Vidal·Naquet
is only one spring, and iu water is of a temperature c_qually con•enicnt
in summer and in winter.,. Changlcssnns appears Ill ~c nu,abcr ~
warriors which so far as possible shall nol alter; and m the way an
which the constitution and the organization of their land h• bcm
ordained once and for a.II. H And, more jokingly, in the a:rt of house·
building, which the inhabitant, pass down 'to othen like themselves,
always the same' (Cn.tias 112c).' 7 . •
One might ask whether there is any further connection between thu
structure based on the land, this unity and this changelessness, be!'yond
those that an: obvious? In~ cosmology of the Timaeus, of the four
elements, it is precisely earth that cannot be trmsfonned: OV "fClP Ek
lO.).o "Tf. Elba( {A_9o,. ,rar'li» (Ton. 56d). Movement in thi, cosmology
consists in the commingling, at every level, of the principle of changr-
lcssncss, 'of the indivisible Existence that is ever in the same sutc'
(~ ('}'QPJ &,upiDTav ,ccti lui ,cQTQ ndrm ~0007Jt OOOiat), the Sllmc
(TO a(,nf), with 'the divisible Exisu:ntt that exists in bodies' ("1( (IV
1ttpl nt oWµaro 7'7"°1'6'fJt l'EPt.OT'Tlt), the Oifftrent (TO tf'fpoll) (Tim,
35a ff.). One might sec prehistoric Athens u the politica.1 manit'.cstation
of the Same. The tenor of the myth is no le• evident at a politkal level.
It is not a matter of chance that Plato takes Solon as the intennediary
for his knowledge of this Athens: by the mid-fourth century lhe
Archon 0£ 59-4 had become the grand old man or the moderate,, tbc-
supporters of the p,arn·o.r polittilA. 31 The great cataclysm deprived.
Athens of the larger part o( her land. The small remainder, of fint·n.te'
quality, is a token of what once wa (Crituu l lOc}, just as among the
Athenians of Solon's day, 'a little of the 1n-d' of the Athc.nians 0£ for·
mer days was preserved (Tim. 25c). AtMns is not then 'lost', if the
word mean, anything in Plato's philosophy;but the city Plato describes
is the antithcsif of the ttal city or the fifth and fourth centuries - u, a
word, an Anti-Athens.
Plato prescnu in th.e Politicw:, in the fonn or a myth, two cycles in Ult
universc. 19 At times, 'God in person accompanies the movement of the
univenc,puttinghisown hand 10 the wheeling of iu circles' (tr. Taylor).
The world then comes to know what the poets haw called the Age ol
Cronus, men under the sway of divine shepherds. 'SoAI of lhc earth',
men lead a lire exactly the revenc of oun: lhcy are born grcybcwds
and die babie1. Then the cycle goes into rever,c- an.d God abandons tlte
helm. At fint rncn succeed rea.sonably well in organWD.g tbiap; 'b11t in
pr<Keu of time, as forgc"dulneu coma uw:r (thr world), tlM: old discol'd
prn.Ws ever more and morr'. The: threat is then thu the world will bli
swallowed up 'in thr boundles place of ~kcnca' (t!t( ,(it,, "1C
b,,o,-,.6n)'°" ft<<P°" wn, TCar<w) (Pol. 273d). God tun• band, .od
208
Athens and Atlantis
the world revenes itself ona= again. In book.s 8 and 9 of the Republic
Plato outlinet an analogous shift, from timocracy to oligarchy, from
oligarchy to democracy, from democracy to tyranny: the ideal model is
progressively distorted, yet each type preserves elements of the preced-
ing constitution. Equally, each stage is a little further removed from the
ideal of unity: democracy is like 'an emporium of constitutions where
one can choose the model he likes best' (Cornford) ( Wotrt:p t:k
'lf'CW1"0ll'WXwv ~OJl~"ct' 1toXtTEtW11, K.ai f1<.XeEcrµi&1ctJ oifrw K.atoU<itt:w:
Rep. 8, 557d). And Plato is especially fond of the adjective poihilos to
describe democracy and its logical consequence, tyranny (Rep. 8, 557c,
558c, 56le, 568d). These two forms of constitution push 'diversity',
'chiaroscuro', to the very limit.
In order to characterize this 'chiaroscuro' quality - or, in a different
image, this apeiron, this lack of limits - Plato uses oppositions, big and
little, hot and cold, pitched and unpitched, etc.:
WhcrC"Vcr they an pruent they exclude any definite quantity. They alw1y1 imbue
activitie, with Feater ,tren(th over a,ainst Feater mildness and convencly, render-
inl them more or leu whatever it may be (r01r).£0,.,1<crirOr>,JXT'TOV lrfftp-yBfto6ov),
&nd rulin1 out definite qu&ntity ... Ir they do not oblittrale definite quantity, but
allow decree and meuure to appear in the mids! of more or le11, or strongly &nd
mildly, they in fact abandon the terrilory they occupied. For in admittinl of
definite quantity they would no lon,er 1trictly be hotter or colder. For the hotter
goes on witl,out pa.u1e, a.nd thtc colder in the Jame way, while a definite quantity
comes to a. puticula.r point and IIXI no further. So on the pruent a.rrumenl the
bolter and at the 1:ame timtc its opposite would come ou1 as indeterminate.JI
(PAiileb., 25cd, t:. Goal.ins)
It is easy to recognize in thi5 passage the well-known 'indetenninate
dyad' (liucxc; b:dpw-roc;) of great and small, by which Aristotle defined
the material principle in Plato; and of course, the 'Other' of the
Timaeus. 32
It is in this last dialogue that we find, in close mutual relationship,
the two cycles which in the Politicus are sundered. The circle of the
Same corresponds to the movement of the stars, and moves from left to
right, while the Other, divided into seven unequal circles (the planets),
moves from right to left. But the turning of the Other is brought about
by the turning of the Same which it imitates (Tim. 36c ff.).n The har·
mony of the universe can thus be accounted for, but also the unfore·
seen eventualities to which it is subject.
If proto-Athens is the political express~o~ of the .t~umph of ~he
Same what of Atlantis? I do not say that 1t is the political expression
of ,h; Other, ~cause the Other does not exist i~ itself. _what is su~ject
to coming into being and is visible (-yiPECJW EX011 K~I ~p~11) is an
imitation of the model (µtpfl,..a 6E 1rapa&{-yµaroc;), which IS itself alone
intelligible and eternal (1J011TIW ,cai b:Ei K.ard: TOOl'T& l:i11) (Tim. 48e-
49a).>"
209
Piene Vidal-Naque1
To grasp what Atlantis is, it would be .Kns~blC'. fint of .U to loo~
oncC' again at the fate of Athens. The ptthuitonc city l~t ~at gave tt
permanence: 'for the fact is that a 1ingle ~ l of exetSs~e run ~ed
awav the earth and laid batt the rock' ( Cnh&f, l l 2a); m com pan.son
with what then was, there remain only the bones of the wutt:d body · · ·
the mere skeleton of the land being left' (lllb). It became lM rock
that Plato describes thus: 'The whole country is only a long promontory
extending far into the 1ea away from the rest of the continent' (•iroo
airo n?~ @.).fl( +r,,Elpov l"JlCi'O wponCJJOVaa. ek TO •f).«')'O( OUN' lbc.pa
,ce-tmt: Cntuu 11 la).u Athens is therefore condemned to seafaring and
all that that involves - political change, commerce, imperialism. But is
not that the fate of Atlantis? ls this extraordinary world, this island
'larger than Libya and Atia together' (Tim. 23d),M and whose Homeric
and oriental characteristics we have explored, A tltnsian ? 5 , Early on in
his account, Plato has ttcount to a very odd expPdient to nplain wh}·
the names he is going to use arc Greek: 'You must not be surpritcd if
you should perhaps hear Hellenic names given to foreignen' (ob Kai
n)& bvo,.am) (Critw ll3b): the story told to Solon came to him from
the Egyptian tongue and was then turned into Greek.. An entirely point·
less thing to say; unless the point is precisely to intimate that "lkUenic
names given to foreigners' might rn-cal rcalitie-s no less 1imilar. The
structure of Athens is fixed once and for all; that of Atlanti1, by con-
trast, is a continuous creation. First of all, it is on an island, and it hu a
fertile plain, like- that or Athens, which is close to the sea. Above this
plain, a mountain inhabited by a couple, Euenor and U:ucippc. 'born
from the earth' (Critics 113cd).H In the beginning, then, Atlantis w•
of the earth; and Poseidon, Lord of the island, ~fore he- became God
of the se-a, was a divinity of the aoil. To keep his affair with K.Jeito
secret, however, he fashioned round the mountain two circular
enclosures of e-arth, and thttc of sea; but Plato remark.a: 'no man could
get to the island, for ships and voyages were not yet thol.l8,ht or (Crifias
ll!de-). Th,: opposition bctwe-ie:n earth and water nonetheleu became
from that moment a fundamental aspect of the structure- of Atlantit. A
spring rises in the island's centre, no longu as a singl~ source which
could be used at any time of year as at Athens, but a, two fount.aim,
one hot, the other cold, which the God himtclf caused to flow.just u
he caused the famout 'sea' of Er«htheus to exist al Athens (Cn'WS
113e, 1 l 7a, cf. Herodotus 8.55).u Indeed, water appean on AtbnuD
in a rather less likely way, too: its soil is rich in every conceivable- mclal,
and especially in gold and the mysteriou,orichalcum (ll'K);andin the
Timaeus Plato tells us that meu.11, and the pwat metal, gold, in pit'
ticular, arc mnely v~eti.es of waur (Tim. 58b Q',).•
This temporal relationship between earth and water, which i• in iaiotlf
210
A.ehf'ntMld Atlantis
sipificant. ii only the most •t:rilwat: aspect of a dualism which Plato
stttacs constantly and which proves that the structure of Atlantis is
constituted by the play of the apeiron, of non-identity.
The island rcfuae in the centre is five stades across; then there comes
a strt:tch of water one stadc wide, and then two groups of enclosures of
earth and water, two md three stades across respectively (Cn"tuu 115d-
l 16a).0 Thus we have a sequence which is more or less that of an
inttrtcd fugue: 5(5+2),1,2,2,5,5; anyone who leaves the island's centre
rapidly enten the world of doubleness.
CIOICly corresponding to the five enclosures which protect the island
IN: the five pain of twins which K.leito bean to Poseidon. In giving us
the tally of these twins (one of which bean both a bubarian and a
Greek nune: Gad.eiro1·EumClos}, Plato carefully distinguishes elder
from younger {Cnti&s ll.5e-114d}. Again, he records that some of the
buildinp were simple (lnM!} and others of different stones ('lfOUl:iAa);
some of the cisterns were open to the sky and others covered over;
'twice in the year they gathered the fruits of the earth', making use of
rain during the winter, and in the summer water from the canals. The
kinp held their mcetinp 'every fifth and every six year alternately,
thus giving equal honour to the odd and to the even number' (T~ TII!
bpr",1 IC.Od Tfi, •~p,rrft) µipO( loo1,1 hoff,ml"R'c} (Critw 116b, ll 7b,
l 18e, l 19d).42 When he describes in the Timoew the formation of the
natural world, from the World&ul to man, and from man to ftsh, Plato
is also describing the advances of non-homo11=ncity, which is supreme in
nature (plnuis}. Nature appears in Atlanti1 in al.I its limitlessness: trees,
different sorts of plants, fruit, animals, and in particular the elephant,
'the largest and greediest of the animals' (Critias I 15a}. This structure
has a history: the ten sons of Poseidon give rise to ten royal dynasties,
and these dynasties perform construction-works which link the centre
of the island to the sea beyond (Critia, Il5b-l 16a);41 the kings build
bridges and open the land to seafaring (117e). They improve the plain
by means of a grandiose system of canals (l 18ac).-.. They provide
themselves with a large army (119ab). 45 And, finally, lhey lay out in
the centre of the island a monumental area complete with a palace, a
sanctuary of Po,cidon, and cven a hone-racing circuit, as one might
expect on an island consecrated to that god (Cn"tias I 16c-l 17a). Plato
givct us figures for most of these undertakings: the temple, for exampk.
was 'a stade in length, and half a stade in width, and of a proponionalc
height (aul,lld'f"PCW) (116d}. If we convert that into pletlera, ~e get
6:5:2 - a limplc example, one of many, of a play on the ten pnmary
numbers, and above all, on the number 10, of which Atlantis provides
many instanccs.41
The descendants of Poseidon established a political system of singu·
211
PicrTC Vulal-Naquct
larly mixed character (CriMI 119b-12~). Within his o~ ~ ·
each king is sovueign. with power ewer life and dn.~h, ~ ~ t
conespond as well, in the cue of a philmopbc:r• to the 1de~ 1i1Uabon m
the Politic• (292d-297b), as to tynnay, in the op~ate cue.~•
group, the ten lungs constitute an oliprchy or amtoc:racy, which
govcms collectively in accorda:"cc with the pre~'! e n ~ , by the:
first kings on a column of onchalcum at Poseidon s behest. When
justice hu to be done, thnc rule• are as1u~d by the lcpduy oath.
which comi1ts CIICfttially in the pouring of the consecrated blood of a
bull, the characteristic means by which non-philo10phcn are able to
maintain a comtitutional ordinance."• And when a member of the
royal family is 10 be pu.t to death, it must be dccickd by a majority
verdict. From its inslitutiom, Atlantis might then appear to be one of
those successful mixed constitutions dacribcd in the Politic•, the
Tim•"u.r, the Pllilebw and lhe Uws; and indeed, for many gienerations,
'the lunp wen obedient to the laws. and well-affectioned towards the
god, whose 1eed they wen:' - tKy even thought "lightly of thr
pot1C11ion of gold and other property, which seemed only a bunlai to
them' (Critia.s l20c-12h).49 But the divine clement withered. and the
kinp were rilled 'with unrighteou1 ambition and power' (d.eGNfi«
iW6c:ou ,cm &ul'lll,,ltw<) (l2lab). 1• And it wu then that, to punish them,
Zru5.called ,.._her the company of the gods to the ccnttt of the uni·
vene, lo a place 'which .•. beholds all crated thin.gs' (ft ... ~
dvra lloa Tft'8fc.,( Jlfffi~~P) and that ... The dialopae breaks off
(12lbc). 'The hittory of Atlantis thus re¥Cals the •l£ume advance
towards disunity that we hwc seen in iu phylical structun:.
At thi, point, it is -,propriate to slteU, mon: than I haw dan.c 10 fu,
the Athenian upccu of the mighty island. K.leisthenes'1 refonns divided
A.thens into ten triba; and it is into ten puu that Poseidon dividu hil
own domoin (61,ca "'"" ...,..,....,.) (Cnlilu !Ue)-" When Plaio
speaks of orichalcum, the metal which played so large a part in tlle
prosperity of the kinp of A.dantis. he mentions that it wu 6m.0tc
precio111 in those clay1 than anything except gold' (llk). 12 The
description. of the harboun and their fortmc:ations is gn:ady indebted,
• hu often been noted, lo the complex K.ntbaros, Zu, Mounychia.
the ••VII yords (SAnotliiii) and the Anmol. The naval dadtyanlo ol
Atlantis had trireme, lyi111 in them; and Plato obsrrves of the poru-:.
"they were full of YCSHls and rHrchants coming frOfB all parh, who,
from their numbcn, kept up a multitudinous ,cnand of human n,icd.,
and din ""d clatter of all ,on, night ..d cloy (......is, . - eo,,,tlM
flDJT'O&mrCW) (l 17c).11 In other words, just like tbe Pineus.
Unlike" the royal palace, the temple of Poxidtn i, detcribea at length,
And in spite of its notic decorarion, it reminds one MtoaitbinPY of
212
A.thfflS and Atlantis
the Parthenon. In the sanctuary stands the statue of Poseidon, mounted
in a chariot and surrounded by a hundred Sea-nymphs on dolphins; he
is 'of such a size that he touched the roof or the building with his head',
just Ii.kc Phcidiu's statue of Athcna Parthenos (116d;cf. Picard, 1939:
37-t). All thcsc statues were of gold. Wc att reminded of what Pericles
says in Thucydides: 'The gold with which the image of the goddess
was overlaid ... weighed forty talcnu pure' (2.13.5). All around the
tcmpk arc statues, and in particular those of the wives of the ten kings
(the tc:n eponymous heroes of K.leisthencs's city?); and Plato remarks,
curiously enough, that there were 'many other great offerings of kings
and of private persons, coming both from the city it.self and from the
foreign cities over which they held sway' (Critias 116c-ll 7a) - as
though he were thinking of Phcidia.s's two Athcna.s on the Acropolis,
Athena Promachos, set up by command of Pericles, and Athena
Lcmnia, which took its name from the Athenian clcruchs of Lcmnos
who dedicated it. 54
Finally, and most important, Atlantis became an imperial power:
Now in this idand of Adantil there wu a great and wonderful empire which had
rule over the whole idand and tnen.l othen, md over puu or the continent.
(TimMMS 25a;d. Crituu ntc)
Not satisfied with all this, i.ts leaders embarked on an overseas ex·
pcdition. Their clash with prehistoric Atheru brought upon them a
<2tastrophe comparable to that suffered by the Athens of history in
Sicily, or rccently experienced by her at the time when Plato was
writing the Timuw and the Critias, at the hands of her rebellious allies.
But we have still to explain, if we arc able to conclude the demon·
1tration, why Plato 1hould so oddly haYe mixed Athenian with 'oriental'
features in this historical myth. ln the Laws, he analyscs briefly the two
constitutions which 'are two mother forms of state from which the rest
may be truly said to be derived' (3, 693d): the despotism of Persia, and
Athenian democracy. The account is quite unhistorical, but Plato's
description of their development (Laws .3, 694a-70lb) c,tablishcs a
strict parallel between the two of them, strikingly reminiscent of the
history of Atlantis: the 1ame just, if precarious, equilibrium in the
beginning, the same disastrous evolution, which leads in the first case,
under the impulse of gold and imperialism, to the despotism of an
absolute ruler; and in the second, after the Persian Wars, and then the
abandonment of the old mowihi ( 'moral education'] to 'theatrocracy'.
I need hard.Jy add that the Persian king had by the fourth centur)
bccome enonnoutly influential in the Grcek world, whether directly or
through the Uit of satellites.
IW'II
•'*
A fflml may 9;0metima let meditations about eternal lhillp, and for RCrntlom
to eo111ider the truthl of pnen.1ion wbich ue proballle only; M wit thus . .
a pleuw-e not to be repealed of. and KC\lff rcw him.Sf wbile be ltYd • wiN ancl
modente putime (pi,'PfOI', . , •Gl&dlo .:Cli ~ ) .
A.II the same, the game is wonh it: at the beginning of the dialopc,
Critias crave, his hcarcn' indulF:nce by saying that he is aoin1 ' t o ~
of high mattm' (w< npi~.-,.!A""' /dllw• Ar,e") (Crilw JO&.:). II ie
more difficult, he says, to speak of men than of lhc: lf)ds, because •
man i1 alway1 demanding when a painter undcnakn to paint his por·
trait (107d). Poinllc11 -- if Plato were not say.ins to his contci:npo,aric•
what the seventeenth-century philosopher was nying to his: U ,,
/.bula UfflltlU'. n
214
12. Between Beasts and Gods
Mored DclieMC (1972; 1977)
Strong fcclinp were aroUKd at the end of the last century when the
English anthropological IChool claimed to have discovered. 'swvivals of
a savage state' in the thought, and in the society, which western civiliz:·
ation had confidently dcrmcd the tap-root of its own values and
principles. Could the Greeks - the Greeks, who had miraculously
divll\cd. Reason to be incarnate in man, and had thus been the first to
ttcogniu the privileged status of human beings in the world, ponibly
have luted human Resh, have been cannibals, like the Iroquois or the
savages of Melanesia? Tylor and his followers claimed that myths con-
tained evidence for previous st.ates of a society. If so, the banquet of
Thycstcs, Lykaon's sacrifice, the myth of Cronus, were now become so
many irttfutablc proofs that Plato's fordathen bort an uncomfortable
resemblance to the American Indians (Lang, 1885).
Though modem classicists may have insomnia, however, it is not
because they fret that Plato's great·grandpapa might have bem a
cannibal; and the problem is nowadays discussed in different terms. 1
With the exception of a quite unusual ritual such u that of the wolf·
man, during which initiates partook of human flesh mixed with pieces
of an animal victim, cannibalism in ancient Greece is now sem in sym·
bolic terms, whether in myth, religious thought or political ideology.
Consequently, its explanation can be in one of two forms. First, some
kind of thematic reading covering all the myths and stories in which the
motif occun, however incidentally: Dionysus eaten by the Titans,
Tc~ and Thycstcs feasting on their children, the Theban Sphinx who
ate the young men with whom she copulated, the offering by Tantalus
and Lykaon of human flesh to the gods, Cronus swallowing down the
offspring borne him by Rhea ... The motif of cannibal.ism is obvious
enough in each of these myths, but the very act of collecting them for
study is enough to meal fundamental differences. In each case the
meaning of what seems to be an act of cannibalism depends on the con·
text: only the context can make clear its true significance. Two
examples will scne to show that this first method offers ultimately no
solutions. Take the story of Cronus. A na'ivc reading of Hesiod may
leave the impression that Cronus is a cannibalistic father in that he
devours e..ch new-born child as Rhea presents it to him (1leogony
459-60). But the account takes on quite a different meaning when
21'
MaH-el Detienne
placed in iu proper context, the myths of so•,ereignty (d. Dcti~e ~
\'cmant, 1978: 64-7). Like Zau, who has an ickntical functl~ ~
Hesiod's myth, Cronus is a sovereign god fated to be d~roned b', h11
son, a child more powerful than his fathn ..To prevent tlus, Cronus and
Zeus alike devour (h.arapine-in) their offspnng. Cronus docs not ~at the
children Rhea bears him limb by limb: he gulps them down mbre and
alive, and so is able later to disgorge them under the influence of ~r
dru administered him by Zeus's accomplice Mc-tis - the selfsame Metu
wh!m Zeus, in his own twn threatened with dethronement by a more
powerful son, decides to ~ow a.ftcr their ~arri_age .so as to pounl
himself of all that swift cumung without which his reign would be as
bric£ as Cronus's. Neither Cronus nor Zeus ia a real cannibal. They arc
both 10vcreig:n gods who swallow their enemies so as to defend or to
establish their power.
Our second example is provided by the myths of Tpeus and Poly·
tcchnos (Mihailov, 1955: 77-208), two venioru of a story about a man
who unwittingly cats the flesh. of his own child served him by his own
wife. Taken out of context, this horrifying supper ia open to any num·
her of misinterpretations - it might, for example. be a Dionysiac
banquet or a cannibalistic meal. 1 But if we look at the mythological
context, we find that the stories bdong to a complex nf myths about
honey, and this allows us to define more closely the cannibalism of
Tcreus and Polytechnos.' The two myths att in fact parallel venions of
, story which begins with an uce.uiw- laon,ymoon and ends with the
duomposition of honey or its transformation into exc,~mnit. ln the
Tereus venion, the husband who abuses the honeymoon i, condemned
first to seduce and violate his sister-in-law, then to t:al the Oesh of his
son, and finally to change into a. hoop~. a bird which feed, on human
eitcrement. In the Polytechnos version (where Polytechnot is the wood·
peck.er, the master of bcu and honey), another e1tceu.ive honeymoon
leads the guilty husband by the same path - r..pc and cannibalism - to
death by honey: he is rolled in it and left to be bitten 11nd :1tung. The
punishment fits the crime perfectly, for he 'wallowed too long' or 'ate
too much' honey - both images used by the Greek., to refer to hon~-
moons and the pleasure given each other by a newly-married couple.
The myths of Tereus and Polytechnos tell how an improper u..w of
honey transforms wmething eatable into the opposite, cxcttmcnt or
rot. This transformation is mediated by a cannibalistic phlllC, defined i11
other myths of the same group as the state prior to the diKovcry ol
honey: in these myths, men ate each other until the Bee·Wo~n tautfit
them how to feed off honey pthered in the fordf.•
A structural analysis, then, aUowi WI to undentand the cannib.d.~
of these myths in two ways, ~ at one~ tM sign nf a RWH,ion to the
216
B~twtffl Beasts and Gods
period before honey and a., the fint stage of a break.down of the honey·
diet, bt:forc it turns into dung (in the case of the hoopoc) or rottenness
(in the case of the woodpecker).
An alternative to a systematic reading of the different groups of
myths to which the stories concerning cannibalism belong is this:
cannibalism can be defined within the structure of Greek thin.king -
located within the cluster of images which the Greeks constructed,
about thcmscl~s and about ouuiders, at the level of eating habits. For
them, the eating of human flesh was ont of a number of forms of
cannibalism. As such, it was an essential term in a dietary code which,
in their religious and social thought, constitutes a grid capable of
representing the structure of relations between man, nature and the
supernatural.' So we have to make use of the system as a whole if we
arc to rescue cannibalism from the siding into which it was explicitly
shunted by the Greeks. For although Greek society rejected cannibalism
utterly, yet, by virtue of what it did have to say about it, it compdled
dissident individuals and groups to express their rejection of society in
terms of this very form of illicit consumption.
We cannot, in other words, define cannibalism in Greece simply
within the system of politico-religious ideas. We must also ddine it
from •outside', by looking at different ways in which Greeks cxpresscd
thtir rejection of the city and iu values. These rcjtctions were of differ·
ent kinds. Sometimes it was simply a matter or more or less isolated
indivw:luals, such as the Orphics or the Cynics. But protest could be
expressed in more or less orpnized sects or groups - the Pythagoreans,
or the worshippers of Dionysus. It is impossible to say whether they
actually thought of themselves as alternative rystnns or were simply
protests against the city. Nevcnheless, these four movemcnt!II,
Pythagoreanism, Orphism, the Dionysiac sects and the Cynics, can be
sttn a.s a set or four tenns each of which projects a mirror-image or the
politico-religious synem of the Greeks, in which cannibalism is given a
particular stress, either positive or negative.
We may begin by describing the politico·rcligious system which was
dominant in ancient Greece. It wu based on a ritual of sacrifice which
lies at the heart of Greek political life and which codified Greek rules
about tating. In Greece, the consumption of meat was intimately
related to the sacrifict, to the gods, of a domestic animal. The flesh of
this animal men kept for themselves, granting the gods the smoke from
the burning bones combined with the scent of the aromatics burned
with them. Such a practice marks a sharp division bttween mtn and
gods at the level of rules about food. Men receivt the me.i.t because to
Jive they have to cat flesh, perishable flesh, such as they themselves
are made of. The gods alone receive the aromas, perfumes, the incor·
217
Ma. c"l Detienne
ruptiblc substances which constitute the superior foods reserved for the
im:~~~~- defines the human condition i.n one direction. But then is
another definition implied in 1acrificc - against animals. But .htre, for a
number of reasons, the boundary is less sharp. Mtn and. anunals both
need to cat, and both suffer &om hunger, which is a 'sign' of death.
Some animal species, like man, arc carnivorous. Moreover, wh.crc.u men
and gods are so far sepan.ted that it is necessary to bum mce~ to
attract the gods to men's sacrifices, men and animal& are dose neigh·
hours ~ sometimes so close that it may be difficult for a group to draw
a clear distinction between ill own membcn and, say, the plough-01.
Within the framework of the city, the dominant ,ct of idcu about
the relationship between man and the animal world in ancient Greece
is to be found in the writings of .-.\ristotlc and the Stoics. It is agreed
that animals exist for man's benefit. They arc thtrt to provide him with
food, to supply him with clothing and help him in his work. According
to Aristotle, it is a just law of nature that man shoulcfltusc animals for
these purposes.' This vi.cw is echoed by the opponents of vcgeu.rianiml:
to give up using animals, they said, would risk man's 'leading a bestial
life' (Porphyry, De obstinmtia 1.4). Man is free in sovereign manner to
divide the animal world into two groups: the animals he protects for
the services he expects from them; and those he hunts for fear of the
harm they may do him. But domestic or wild, animals are invariably
regarded as crntures lacking reason, with whom men can establish no
relation of law. For animals arc incapable of 'making agreements among
themselves that they 1hould neither inflict nor ,uffer harm'.' The
animal world knows neither justice nor injustice; and it is dli1 funda-
mental ignoranct which the Greeks ~gardcd as the essential distinction
between animals and mankind. Separated from men. who live under the
rule of dilf.i, within legally-defined relations, animals arc condemned to
cat each other. The kingdom of cannibalism begins at the front.in
where justice ends. 'Thia is the law which the Son of Cronus has
decreed for men: fish and wild beasts and the birds of the air mav eat
each other, for there is no justice among them. But to men he has aittn
justice, which is by far the best.•• Consequently, just as between men
and gods, so the true distinction between men and -.nima.la is to be
found at the level 0£ rules about eating - except tlq.t here there ii I
double distinction, two levels. The most buK: of these ia the iHuc ~
cooling: 'Man is not an .animal that eats raw fiah.' (Porphyry, CJ,
obstinnitia 1.13). ln all Greek thinking, human food it inextricably
linked "r'iUl the fitt of sacrifice; while even the leut wild of dQfflntic
animals, the hubivorcs, arc 1till condemned ft eat food that is ROI
cooked (Detienne, 1977: lS). In effect, the aotion of 'besu.i~··
218
Betwttn BetJJts and God.r
bepn, with the conaumption of uncooked food - and finishc1 up in
cannibalism.
Man's median position bctWttn beasts and gods is entrenched, but·
trcucd by the e11tire politico-religious 1ystcm, by way of the daily prac·
tice of 1acriflcc of animals whose flesh is then eaten. But in so rigid a
form.. this three-term mod.cl is neither adequate nor corTCct. It becomes
IO only when we accept that it has a dynunic dimension: the human
condition is dcrmed. not simply by what it is not, but by what it no
lonpr U. In the Greek city, where a proper history of culture usurped
the function of mythical discourse about how thinp began, there
developed a twofold tradition, according to which the Golden Age can
substhute for barbarism, and vice vcna. Sometimes, u in Hesiod, men
become caters of meat where once they had shared the food of the
god.1; and sometimes, as in the myth of the Bee-Women, men developed
their present eating-habits only after living for a long while like animals,
eating things raw and eating each other. We may put it thus: the model
contains two symmetrical starting-points, one at the 'top', the other at
the 'bottom'. They represent invcne orientations within the same con-
ceptual area, and their symmetry is emphasized by the presence at each
point, 'top' and 'bottom', of the same mediator, Prometheus. In the
one cue, through the invention of sacrifice, he brings about the tran·
sition from the Golden-Age fellowship with the gods to a diet of meat
(Vemant, Introduction to Detienne, 1977: xxvii-xxviii, and see pp.
59-62 above). In the other, he e:r.tricates mankind from savagery,
directs it away from an animal existence, by his gift of fire and by
inventing the difrerent trchnical sk.ills (Cole, 1967: 6, 20-1, 150). The
city does not feel compelled to make a choice between these two wa)'I
of putting it: it gives equal status to both venions. In its sacrificial
practice it implicitly assumes the process sketched by Hesiod's myth;
but in the various systems centred on its own history it tends to stress
the shih from cannibalism to a food-code characterized by the eating of
bread and meat.
The politico-religious system of thought, then, dearly proclaims
cannibalism to be a form of bestiality which the city unambiguously
ttjects. It sets it on the very margin of its history, in a previous~ of
human existence, or on the fringes of its geographical extension, among
the tribes which make up the Barbarian world. The geographical dis·
tribution 0£ 'savages' is organi:ted on the principle that the consumption
of raw food is a fonn of bestiality though it falls short of cannibalism
(d. Festugiere, 1972: 145-9). Eaten of raw meat are accordingly
found in remote areas of Gr«ce iuelf, such u northern Aetolia, the
home of the Eurytanes, 'who, it is said, speak a completely unintelligible
languaRC and eat raw meat' (Thucydides 3.94). Genuine cannibals live
219
~;u .:"1 Detienne
in £ar-orr lands. One exampk i1 the Scythians, who cat ~um~ fklh
and like othen or their kind, drink marr"1 milk (Ephoru.t. U'l FGrH 10
F 42 (• Strabo 7.3.9 (302C))). Herodo<us call, one tribe '!'•Man·
eaten (Androphagoi), and says, 'their cu1toma att utterly bestial; they
do not observe justice nor do they have any law. They arc nomads · · ·
and alone of these peoples, cat human flcth" (4.106). AriltotJc. 1pc~
qu.itc clinically about 'bestial dispositiom', and rmds them likcwuc
unong tbe people• of the Pontus area, who show 'a tendcn':Y t~ mur~
md cannibalism• sometimes institutionalized amo111 certain mbcs wd
to provide each ~ther with children for banquctl (NicotNClann Ethics
7.5, 1148bl9-25;Poliliu l,4, 1338bl9-22). All of theoe ott eumpla
of cuuuDUism on the margiru or the civili&cd world which the Greeb
can 1imultu1coudy chanctcrizc, with Plato. u survivals of a primitive
human condition or cite, like Aristotle's contemporaries, u the origin
of the Lamia., the bogtyfflUI who comes at night to devour foetu.sa
md diacmbowels pregnant women to reach them (Laws 6, 782b6-c2;
Anon. Scholi:ut on Ni.com. Erla. 7.6 • CA.C 20, p. 427'57--40).
1bit 10Ciolocical perception or cannibalism must be supplemented b,.
another, which confirm.I the city's radical ~jection of all cannibalistic
behaviour. In Greek thought or the fifth and fourth centuries, the
tyrant (tunmnos} is a type explicitly defined in terms of the three-fold
model which underpin• the city's sacrificial practice and eating ruln.
Because his pown- derives from himself, without hil either huing had
it granted him m being oblipd to ntum it to the 'centre' (n muon),
the tyrant sets hirnsclr above other men and above the laws. lie is all·
powaful, which puts him on a lnel with the gods. However, by tht
same token, he is ndudcd from the community, is banished to an area
within which political theory ceases to diltinpish .aupcnnen from sub-
mcn - where it oblitenta the chum between god and be•t (Vemant
and Vidal-Noquet, 1972, 116-17, 128-50). In Plato', R.,,..blic, the
tyrant's behaviour W 1een u the naked inuption into the world of
primitive lu1ts which orclin.ariJy arc aroused in us only in sleep, when,
under the infl~n« of alcohol, the animal part or the IOU.I (ta
tlairiidu) dreams that it commits incest with the mother, npc, .,cl,
man or beat, rnurdcn the father or devoun ill own children (9,5 7lc-
d; cl. I0,619b-<:). Oullido the &amo al the city ond 1he hlorarchiql
1tructurc with which it is linked, man, god and beast are IIHll'ely intcr-
chan,cablc obj«ts of the tyranl"s desires, which w:.Gm?D him to iDclll
and parricide and rmaP.y to a.1to-cana:ibalism. hi atin1 his own 0-
ed blood, the tynat proclaims that he ii oataidc the twcf, a lOCW
outcast - jult as Ille scapegoat was expelled fn,m tbc city in tm:' C!GQllf:
of certain 1pring festivals in various parts of Grp. ··
To eat humu flcth is to enter a nOft,hwna,n world from which1:bcn'
220
Bdwun Btasts and Gods
it usually no rctum. When, in his madneu, Cambyses detennined to
conq~r the 'Long-lived' Ethiopians, who were suppoted to shatt the
banquet or the Sun and live in bliss at the enda of the earth, his armies,
as they advanced further and further and ran out of food, were by
degrees reduced tint to eating their pack-anUllals, then to feeding on
grass and plants, and finally to eating nery tenth man, selected by lot.
Mad though he was, says Herodotus, Cambyses at once abandoned the
expedition, so much did he fear that his men would eat one another
and become as wild beasts;' like those Phoenician mercenaries and
Libyan dissidents who were reduced by hunger to eating each other
and whom Hannibal Barca, who conquered them, had trampled by his
elephants on the grounds that cannibals 'could not, without sacrilege,
continue to live with other men' (Porphyry, De abstinentia 2.5. 7). The
aamc mod.cl has proved its effectiveness as a means of exclusion in
countless polemics against groups whom it was desirable to denounce as
enemies of humanity. That they slept with their mothers or their
sisten; that they cut the throats of new-bom babes to devour their
Oesh, dipped bread in the blood and drank it - these were the crimes of
which the fint Christians were accused. The slanders were said by the
Greek Christian apologists Ori~n and Justin to have been started by
the Hellenized Jews in the second century AD; which did not prevent
their being used against the Jews in their turn more than once in cen-
turies to come. 10
However that may be, invenion is a basic mechanism in a whole area
of thought whose true significance lies in the dynamic relationship bc-
tw«n four kinds of anti-system, each of which converts the terms of
the basic model for its own purposes. By taking one of the two direc·
tions available in the original - up or down - the politico-religious
system can be transcended, in a movement either towards the gods, or
towards the beasts. The Pythagoreans and Orphics explored the first
possibility, Dionysiac movements and, later, Cynicism, the second. But
whatever the form taken by rejection of the politico-religious system,
or protest, in the city, those involved were invariably co~pelled. to
adopt a certain view of cannibalism and to define themselves m relation
toit.
In Greek religion Orphism and Pythagoreanism are of course. the ~e.st
known forms of deviance. Speaking generally, they were m ongm
religious movements which rejected the city's ~ystem of values, and
challenged its assumption of a fundamental relation between m~n and
gods founded on the division establish~d by Prome.theus at the moment
when, by reserving the meat for mankind, he depnved them for eve~ of
their former fellowship with the gods. The main thrust of Pythagorcan1sm
is directed towuds dietary rules; it insists, with varying degrees of
221
Ylarctl Detienne
strictness, on a diet which docs not contain meat ~Detienne. ~977:
40-57). In practice, Pythagorcanism adopted two diHermt ~rutu~
towards blood-sacrifice and the city. On the one hand, there 11 the ~-
transigent rejection on the pan or a sect which set it~Ir up a, an ann·
city. On the other, a milder form of rejection. prac~tsed by a group
which was political rather than religious, and which med to reform the
cit,· from within. The fint group rejected any form or meat; the second
co~promised by determining that some sacrificial vi~tims - pig, and
goats - were not 'meat' in the strict sense. True meat 1s the flesh of the
plough-ox, and its slaughter they strictly forbade. .
Of these two approaches, only the ftnt deserves to be descnbed as
'renunciation' (which is the basis of its claim to ~ an anti-systnn). The
strict vegetarians regarded all blood saaificc u murder, and in the
ntremc case, cannibalism. It was this that they attacked in their myths
about the bean. The mythical food of the goch and or the Golden Age
was spices. The bean, a leguminous plant, is the po'lar oppositt of
spices: because it has no nodes on the stem, the bean is in direct con·
tact with the world or the dead, to which it anyway belongs Mcausc of
ill associations with rott~ss. lnvcncly, spices, which Mlons to the
world of the gods by virtue of their solar nature and their dryncn,
effect direct communication with the divine. For the Pythagoreans,
however, the bean is even more: it is a creature of flesh and blood, W
double of the man by whose sidt it gro",, on the same dungheap, feed·
ing on the same decomposition. Cons~ucntly, it is for them as gnvt a
crime to eat beans as to 'gnaw the heads of one's parents'. They proved
this by a series of experiments describtd in the Pythagorean tradi1ion.
A bean was placed in a pot or in a closed vessel and covered in dung or
buried in the earth: this in some mysttrious way 'cooked' it. After a
gestation period of indeterminate length, the bean was transformed
eitbtr into a woman's vulva. with a partly-formed child's head a.ttached
to it, or into a human head with already recognizable reatutts.
ln these experiments the pot is a. matrix duigncd to reveal the be.n's
true nature; the same end could be achieved by biting or squcnin1 the
bean and then leaving it for a few momenu in the sun. It then 1ave off,
by all accounts, a smell either or sperm or of blood shed in murder. To
the vegetarians those who ate the sacrificial victims, the city·ca.mivortt,
are to be classified with one of the two extreme rorms of besti.!ity:
with the Lamia, who eau the foetuses she tears from the wombs of
pregnant women, or with the cannibal son who devoun the hea.da..ul
those who arc neatest and most pttcio• to him. The 'putt'
Pythagorcan1 rrvencd the model which .subtendtthe po IQ, and so mack
,11/11 their sect inlo an anti-system, a cowttcr-polis. They ftnt rcduttd that
model from three terms to two (meat : not-meat}; and thn said tlw
222
Bdween Beasts and Gods
cannibalism is nol rtlc:gated to distant savages but is to be found in the
polis itself, among the men who sacrifice on the altan in honour of the
gods. And that is the meaning of the tradition which say9 that
Pythagoras invented vegetarianism in order to wean his contemporaries
£ram their previous custom of eatU\g each other. 11
The Orph.ics were no less radical; their rejection of the world
involved them in the same sharp invenion as the utreme Pythagoreans.
There is a paradox in Orphic thinking: the most important teaching
that Orpheus left to mankind was the instruction to 'abstain from
murder' (phon.ot) - a sect symbolon for the rejection of the practice of
blood-&acrifice and the eating of meat. On the other hand, the Orphics'
~ntral myth is an account of a sacrifice involving cooking and eating.
The young Dionysus is the victim; the Titans his sacrificers. The victim
is eaten a(tcr being cooked in two ways: first by boiling, and then b)
roasting on the spit. Now this must n=main paradoxical so long as we
n=gard the myth as an account of some sort of communal meal. But
what if we sec: the Titaru' sacrifice in relation to that of Prometheus? It
becomes at once apparent that both arc primordial sacrifices:
Prometheus's sacrifice established the relationship between men and
gods; but the Orphic story presents the Titans' sacrifice as a cannibal
meal whose sacrificial character is underlined by the methods of cook-
ing employed. The Titans' sacrifice has two consequences: immediately,
their punishment - they arc destroyed by a thunderbolt; but from their
ashes is born the human race which, every time it offers sacrifice to the
gods, unwittingly repeats the murder and cannibal banquet performed
by its remote forebears. 12
The Orphics' distinction coincides exactly with the Pythagoreans':
'cannibals' arc those who cat meat and do not follow the bio:s o,philtos,
the Orphic way, that is, who do not attempt to purify the divine
clement imprisoned in man by the gTCCd or the Titans, or to overcome
the rift cut by blood-sacrifice between mankind and god. In effect,
then, cannibalism has for these two sectarian movements the same
negative connotations that it has for the polis itself, in spite of their
bc:Ulg inversions of the dominant politico-religious system in Greece.
It is quite otherwise with the other two protest movements which
constitute this group of four anti-systems in the: history of th.e Greek
polis between the sixth and the fourth centuries BC. Both in D1onysiac
cult and in Cynicism cannibalism is seen as an extension of 'eating raw'
md becomes a meam of achieving that subversion of the order of the
polis which is their shared aim, a subversion from within, the one at ii
religiout lC'\lel, the other at a socio-political one.
In relation to the polis, the position of Dionysiac cult is plain: it
~ffects from 'below' the rejection of sacrifice wh1d1 Orphics and
22S
,brccl Detienne
Pythagoreans effected from 'above'. In ~ion!aiac cult,~ utter contmapt
of the rules for polil-sacrm«, an anunal II hunted m th~ moun~
torn to pieces while still alive and con~ taW, ly thu mean,. tH
boundaries betw«n animals and men arc efCacccl. human and anilul
intcrpenetrate, become indistinguishable. The MKnadl ~ Bacchlimel
suckle young wild beasts at their breasu. At lbe same tune, du:y tev
panthen and deer limb from limb. It is as if, iD m attempt to become
IDOft utterly 'wild' the wonhippc:n of Dionysus had 6.nt to soften the
crn.tures of the wild, mate friends with them even to the point of .elf·
identification. But Dionytul the wild hunter is not simply an 'eater of
nw Oesh' (OmediOI, O,nilli1). The practice of eating n.w flesh which he
demands or his followcn lads them to imitate wild animals in pnfonn·
Ing the cruellest acts of cuanibalism (Schmidt, 1959: 580-2;Jeanrnaire,
1951: 256). A number of ritual details C011finn the betttr·knowa
literary accounH of tbe myth. On Chios, Tenedo1 and Lcsbot, DionylllU
hungen for human Oesh; the victim tom apart in his llonour is a m111.
In Euripides's BtKchu, Agave is pounsed by the god whom her IOR
Pentheu1 hu 1COmed; and wllen Pentheus come• to the mountains to
mock the maddened women, she hunts him down - seein1 him u a
lion-cub or young bull, 'lhlll)' like a wild uumal' (1185-9), a victim
which she tCll'I apart with her own hands and 1tart1 to devour. The
same frenzy attacks the daqhten of Minyu. They ~ \ttavin1, more
interested in getting married than in going off to bacchic orgie1 in the
bush. Dionysus mu.a them join the Maenads; in their madness they
conceive 'a delire for human flelh', and choose by lot one of their own
children, tearing him limb from limb u thouP, he were a yoUJll
animal."
In all these traditions, cannibalism appean within dte context o(
'eating nw Oelh'. It ckarly constitutes the ultimate form of the 1tate of
'savqery' to which Dionyliac cult claims to restore us. To eat htMDIII
flesh, to mp~ in cannibalism, seems to be pan of a pattcm of
behaviour designed to make men 'savaae', lo put them in do.er coal.Id
with the mpematural (represented here by Dionysus F..atcr of Men)
through possession.
But we should enq~ whether the cult of Diony.us 1n..w,q
attributed to cannibalim the aame positive Me it attached to the ,aw
consumption of a wild animal caught by huntifta.. la one wnioll of WI]
story of the dauah,ten of Minym, the llilliq of the duld prl1li0kai •
anFY reaction from odlcr Bacchmuea: they abando1I their wild ~
through the mountain,. and tam on th.e unnatural lbodlera (A.diM.
v• .;. ~;,,,,,;. 5.42). Lik<wi,., at di• •n~ • £uripida'• ploy, dlO
death of Pent.bew ii presented• a murder i.ncurriac p.UU.U.t A,pte,ii
amt into uilc (1674). On thil occasion, it it. Dionysus biauelf who
224
Betw~~n s~asts •ntl Gods
pronounces the aentcnce, thus condemning the behaviour which he
him.elf had apparently commanded. It is of course true that in each
cue ·the eater of raw flesh' only tunas those into cannibah who resitt
him and refuse to have anything to do with his 'savagery'. This does not
however mean that the pn.ctice of cannibalism is foreign to Dionysiac
wonhlp: it is rather an essential clement within it, but an ambiguous
one. Thu is clear particularly in the story of the Bassani, the wor·
shippen of Dionysus in Thracc. 'Not content with orfering sacrifices of
buU., the Basaani of old eng•d in the madness of human sacrifice -
even to the point of eating the victims' (Porphyry, De obstinentia 2.8).
Porphyry goes on to note that the Bassarai 'did in this respect exactly
as we do with animals, since we too offer the fint portion to the gods,
and cat the rest in the feast'. But the panllcl stops there. For, as he
continues, 'everyone knows the story of how they were stricken with
madness, anacked and killed one another, actually eating the blcedin!l
flesh, not resting till they had wiped out the family which had first
practised ruch sacrifice'.
At this point cannibalism reveals its inner contradictions. In the cult
of Dionysus it appears as the extreme fonn of 'savagery' which Dionysus
offers as a path for his worshippers. But here Dionysus docs not inter-
vene to condemn the eaten of human flesh: they destroy themselves.
Possessed by a manic hunger, the Bassarai arc not able to restrain them·
selves from attacking each other. Furiously they tear each other apart
and cat the flesh, a cannibal-crescendo. But, and this i.s my point,
cannibalism cannot reach illl crescendo without destroying itself. The
choice is simple. Either the Bassarai destroy themselves to the last
woma.n, or the cannibalism at the heart of Dionysiac religion must be
severely restricted. To end the epidemic of cannibalism, which threatens
to wipe the worshippers of Dionysus out, the Bassarai must kill those
of the group who arc known to have begun these dreadful rites. In its
pure form, cannibalism is impossible. Dionysiac worship, which nurses
it and lllte&Taks it into some of its rituals, can use it only under severe
controls ... And the extent to which it docs tolerate cannibalism
corresponds exactly to the degree to which the Dionysiac movement,
while maintaining 'transcendence through savagery' as an ideal, remained
an essential part of the religion of the polis. h was always oppose~, but
alway~ inside. It never took the fonn of an anti-system totally ahen tu
the official religion.
It was this 'impossible' cannibalism which was taken up by the:
Cynics as part of their programme. At first sight, this programme looks
• if it were parallel to the Dionysiac one, in that it too involves a
tttwn to primitive 'savagery' (Hauulciter, 1935: 167-84). But ~~ere
the Dion~iac movement operates mainly at the level of rchgion,
22,
~,reel Detienne
Cynicism is a system of ideu wbich attacks socll:tr at every In-el. In
theory and in daily life, the CyniCI dnelopcd amu~. not merely of
the polis, but also of social order and civilization: Thetr protest wm a
general a11ault upon civilized life. 1• It developed lft the fourth century
BC with the genenl crisis of the polu, and one of its main themes - a
return to a state of 'savagery'. 11 Neptivdy, it dc:aicd the life of the
city and rejected the material comlons of civilization. Positively_, it
tried to get bade. to the simple life of the first men, -.ho drank 1pnnr-
water and fed on acorns pthered on the ground or on planu which
they collected. It Cynia proposed two modcb for the procc• of re-
education so that men ffliabt be able to coosume raw plants: the uvaga
who had preserwd this way of life intact; and animals, who had nner
been colT\lptcd by Promethean rue:. In effect, Cynicism was pameatcd.
by an anti-Promethean current, directed apin1t the invention of manu-
facturing, civilizing, fire.I' To become '18Va8'' it was not enough to cat
raw like Diogenes (who paid with his life '#Mn he foulJht with IOfflC
dop over a piece of nw octopu1: Dio Chrysostom 6.~ j Plutarch, A9•
111n 1"'pu util. 2, 956b). It wa1 also necc,sary to dismantle the S)'ltclll of
values on which ,ocicty wu based. The journey back to •savapry'
bcpn with a aitiquc of Prometheus - not here the fint sacrificn
responsible for the 1cparation of gods and men, but the civilizing Titan
of cultural anthropology, the mediator RSp01Uiblc, by his Greek gift
of fire, for educating man. out of his primitive 1tate.
The cult of Dionyms 1printed into the slate of savagery, in punuit of
possellion and contact with th" supematu.nll; it wu quite otherwise
amon1 the Cynics. Amo111 them, we rand a rrtuat into 'savap:ry', a
p-adual descent in several staga. Fint. raw food and the condemnation
of fire. TMn two buic demands. for the abolition of the incest taboos;
and for toleration or auto-cannibalism. Both can be round in Diopna
of Sinope. The rust occun ironically: 'Why did Oedipus complain so
violently of being both brother and fuhcr to his children, at oner
husband and son or the samf: woman? Coc.U, dop and donkey• don't
make aach a fuu, nor do the Pcnian1' (Dio Cbry1ostom 10.29-:SO). lu
ror the 1econd demand. not conknt with obJcrving that at lcut 01'II
society bu no taboo on eating human flab, Diogenes wu IUppOICd: to
have actually 'taught children that they should herd their mothen and
fatbcn to the DCnracial llltan llld cat them IO ·dle lut ac:np'
(Thcophilu,, Ad A•rofy"'m S.5 • SVF S F 750). - .. puricide;
cannibalism: the buic interdictions are overthrown. The climn.utliac c,j
society reaches dowa to virgin IOil, to where Cynici• cauld f"md
nothinc but the putt individ\111, priOI' to IOdcty, prior to ..-Y ~
life. It ii only in this context of the radical ~niMBII of ciwliae:dlift
that cannibalisra could acquire an utterly politive nlue - a .&ue ii
226
Brtrvet'n Jfrasts and Gods
could never either so openly or so ea.,ily be Kivcn b} the cult of
Dionysus, a collective movement that was unalterably Greek. For it is
obviousJy only 'intellectuals' like the Cynics who can afford the luxury
of making the cannibal son an ideal so as to assert the rights of the
individua] against the collectivity, against any form of civilization.
These four solutions, all based on the dominant model of the polis,
differ in rt'lation to their judgement upon cannibalism, and can be
classified in two groups. The first, Pythagoreanism and Orphism, by
their own account anti·systcms. merely reverses the polis·modcl an<l
condemns within the poli.s the cannihali~tic activity the polis condemm
in the world 'beyond'. The other, ~tarting from within the politm>·
religious system of the polis, tric~ to use cannibalism against the polis ~o
as to destroy it or to introduce inlo it what Plato would call the Othn
At the same time, the four schemas do not exhaust the solution,
theoretically available by combining the elements offered h} the model
from which we began. We arc offerc-d in effect two solutions only. each
of which appeacs in two diffuent forms between the sixth .md fourth
centuries BC. :\11 the same, I am inclined for a number of reasons to
speak of a system of 1tkas. There is first the constant substitution, in
the mythical and le:,!;end.1.ry tradition concerning the aboriginal state of
man, be-tween Golden Aie and a state of 'savagery'. And there is the
character of Promethc-us, which shifts according to whether he effects
the mediation once men lost fellowship with the gods; or whether he
becomes the mediator by bringing about the end of the state of
'sa\·agery' which men once shared with the animals.
To these two arguments history adds a third. which confirms the
coherence of tJ1e system and the relation between its s) mmetrical
starting-points. This is the transformation of one solution into its
oppoi.ite, which can In: seen taking _p_lacc in the _sc_cond t~ird ol the
fourth century BC when, after pnhlical and rdigwus failure, some
Pythagoreans tum into Cynics almost before our_eycs. . .
By the end of the fifth c~ntury, Py_thagoreanism had finally ~ailed m
its political aim of reforming the city. Persecuted ,mil harncd. the
disciples of Pythagoras scattered. :\ small group managed to sur.·~v<" al
Phlius. Archyta.s went to ma.kc a career at Tarentum. rhe m.aJont)
abandoned ~lagna Graecia (von Fritz, )963: 214-19). As a group th
P) th.i.i,;oreans were finished: neither sect nor brot~erhood r:mamcd \
fe\\ sunivors g.i.thcred in Atht'ns, and some details o~ then c!1d1.1(_tn
anJ wav of life arc prc~ervcd in fragments of the Athenian comic poets,
Antiph~es, Aristophon and Ale,tis (:\Ieautis, 1922: 10 18; Burke-rt,
1972a: 198--201). Extraordinarily, the Pythagorc.m h,u beco_mt' a
character in comedy. :,.iot a trace of the !o:r.1H. wh1tr robed f11-,'tlre.
227
M::!:f'CelDetieMe
dedicated to asceticism, who strove after holiness within the sect's
nUTOW rule,. The new Pythagorean is a tramp. Bucfoot and fdthy, he
drinks from sucams and goes down into ravines to fttd on wild herba
such as sea-pu.nlane. 11 A beggar-bag on his back, a shabby short cloak
slung over his shoulden, he wean his hair long and 1lecpt rough summa
and winter. People couldn't gt't over it. Could thC'SC' shabby unsha,-cn
hoboes still be called Pythagoreans? There was nothin1 whatner in
their behaviour to diltin111iah them from Cynics; they even borrowed
the Cynic's characteristic labels, the bcgpr·bag and the short cloak. 11
This very question was ulr.cd already by anml\t historian, 0£ phil·
osophy; and their perplexity is often shared by modem scholan.Jt
Thett Jived in A.thens in tbc fint half of the fourth century BC a
stranF philosopher named Diodoru.1 of Aspcndus, who claimed to be a
disciple of Pytha,oru but who dressed and Hhaved. like a Cynic.
According to a contemporuy, he 'wu a follower of Pythagoru, but
pthcred a large following by his pachydermous fatuity tnd repertoire
of insultl' (Stratonik.01 ap. Athenacu.s, Dn/fflo1oplaist. 4.56, 16.5c-f).
But do we really have to follow the author of the little-known Pl&ilos·
ophrn in Sequenu in accusing Diodorus of affectation in wearing l q
hair and a short cloak, 'where in former times the Pythagoreans dreSIC'd
neatly, practised mauqc, cut their hair and trimmed their beards in the
usual way' (Sosicrates, op. A.thcnacus, Dnf'rao,oplwlltt 4,56, 16.5c-f)?
ls it not more likely that Diodoru11s ambipity is to be sccn as an.
example of a shift cvidmced. at the 1&111.e period in the Comic writen,
whoK" most successful st.it on it is the scene in which strict ~urians
fight greedily over bits of dog's flesh (Alexis, TGHAti,u,s frs. 219 (CAF
2, pp. 377-81)?
It looks very much• if, with the failure of the solution from 'above:',
the lut Pythagorean, had to make a choice between two, md only two,
possibilities. They could either go bac:lr. into the polu md be ablorbed;
or they could atttmpt from the 'bottom', talr.in.g the individualist tack.
that transcendence of the polis which they had failed to achieve from
'above'. And there can be little doubt bu.t that the model pm:,,.....:
luuu allows us to accoumt most satisfactorily for the fact that the
im.p of the child eating ill parenu should haw been na.luated, over a
time-span of two centuria, tint neptivdy and then positively by tbc
u.me diuidcnt movement of the ancient world.
221
Abbreviations used
229
.Abbreviations
M.L. Wnt (ed.), /.,,abi tt Elt,i Gr.eci-1• Ak..... drw• , .. r.a,
IEG
2vob., 1971-2,0:dord
JG
/JG
~~'~!::. 1
~-~:-~~i!;", ·~rinach (edl.), '!•naril "'1
i,ucriptioru juridU,uu ,ncques, 2. 11'011., 1191-1, P_an• .
JdAJ
JESHO
Jt11&,bud1 de1 dnt.ldrn Arcl&iaio~clu_• f,unt,,ts ( ~ )
Joumal of llst Ecoflo1"fr artd So,ial Hutory of Ille
(Leiden)
°"'"'
/HI /011,-1 of tlit HUt--, of /tutu (Ephn.ta, h)
/HS /011""'1 of HtUtnic ~tudu1 (London) .. . .
J6At Jt1lire1lief1e du 611nnicliUclsn1 Arclaaolopchne [,uhh,t.,
(Wien)
/WCI Jou,.,,.J of the W•hrf t111d Coul'Uuld /,utitt,te, (Lo~don)
LGRM W.H. R.OIChcr (ed.), Aw1fiilsrlic~1 Luico11 der Gried11d•11
un.d RO,,.isdtn Mytl&olo,U, 8 vob., 1184-1931, Leip&ic
MEFR Mii...,ts d'Arclsiolol't d d'HUtoire de l'lcolt Fnuu;ime 4t
Ro,,.• (Paris)
OF Otto Kem (ed.), 0,ph:o,,.,,. fraptfl.ltl, 1922, Berlin (repr
1963)
KPltS Proceedinp of tlst Ct11"brid1• Plsiiolof'cal SQcitty (Cambri.)
PG J.-P. Mipe (ed.),Patrolo~ - 1fflt1 , , _ ,•• Puis
,MG D.L. Pace (cd.),Poet•• MeliciG,111ci, 1972,0xfOl'd
Tiit 0KyrliynchWI Pt1pyri, 1898-, LoDd-
'°"'
"'
QUCC
Lt1 Pt1rolla dtl Passato: RWistt1 di S,..di a11Udi (Napoli)
QNtld,mi Url,irtali di Cadt•ra Clt111kt1 (Roma)
RA Rtntt Ardiolof'qi,tt (Paris)
RBPH Reuut Belft de Pliifolol'f' ti d'Hiltoirt (Bnis:eUe,)
RE Wis1owa, G., K.l'oll, E., etc. (eda.), Pt1uly1 Rtal-Encyclop,idM d~
ct.s1ilr:h.e" Altertum:rwi.ssnur:lit1ft, 1893-, Stuttpct
REA Rtuut drs t,-d,1 AP1cit11fl.tl (Bordea~)
REG R,.,..e dtt l1Mdtt1 GrecqMts (PW)
RGVV Reli,ion1~1eluchtlichr Venucht 11nd Vorubciten (Giutcn, latl'r
Bai.in)
RHDFE RtT!Nt HUtoriqi,e d, Droil Frn,;.;,, ti £ir-,tr (hri.l)
RhM RluiJtisclm MIUHlfl (FrMllr.fun)
RHR Rtrn,t dt l'Hisloirt du RtliJio,u (PW)
RIDA R,1111, lntntMtio1111lt des Droils tu l'Antiqa,ili (Bnutd.la)
RPIIFE Rn,i,, Pliilo,oplsiqa,t dt l• Frt1Jtct ti tu l'i,,,_I" (PUU)
SMSR Stadi ,t M11ttri.ali di Storill dtlu Rtlip,11i (Roma)
SVF J. •011 Amim (ed.),Stoicon,;,n
lndn:, I 90S-24, Ldpi;if
V,,e,,.,.. Frqm,.,.111, !, IIOU. wilh
230
Notes
=e~=~e~~;:':~~e::.<~::!:d"=~!"~:1!!
henelr Into a few drop• of liquid which he coald e.dly take. 1'11111 ~kl be ~e
inRrR of the 1Wailowinl we find ln the cue of Croa111: Medi ptl bua to *iDll
7 Io chil version, Hen lD l'fffllF p,e1 off 1nd producet BcphaNtu1 pglbnlo-
FJICCially. Hephac1uu ii IUJ'ffme amoQf the ,ocb ln knowlcdre and llr.ill .r a
pnctical-tn:hnical order, whlk Athena, to whom Ze111 P• birth analded, .ii
111Pff!De in all fonn• of pnp,.atic intelliplla:. (On dw thcme ofHen"I ·.-,.
taneou' parturition, we DOW Detienne, 1976: 75-111. Ed.)
I The tn.t haa llo>.ti 6ll'fUIILICIGII 'for 1111 hn t11min1', for ~ h letp n-MI
n>.P5QM'/ hucJal, 'c:lever thou,h ,he w•'· If we retain wc,M ~ . tbe
'turainl' mut be u.ndmtood co meaa Medi'• metlP!lorphOIH. her cmatant
lhiflinl from one lhapc to another.
9 The 1Choliut ..y1, 'Metil hM the power of chutprll into any lhapc lhe willlcd'
(on line 1116, p. 110 di Grqoriol.
10 Thetb and Pelcu: ICC Apollodona, BiW.'olla•u S.IS.S; cf. Pindar, Nna ....
4.61 SncU; ICholiMt on Lycophron, Al•,qnn 175, 178 (I, pp. IJ and II
Schca); tcholia on ApoDonhu or Rllodn, .4,,..._Hu 1.512 (p. SO. 19-20
Waadcl): Qwntua Smymu,u. Tltr F.U of 1hry (die ·c-tulu#o,. of R•"'ff'°)
9.618-24;0vtd,N•ltll"'orf'A.u, 11.Ht-65.
Pro1eu1 and Menelau: <My,rey 4.119-570.
Nimw and Heraltln: Apollodonal, .au,uouaec:• 2.5.11; Kholiall a11
Apolloniu1 of R.bodc1, A,p,...dh 4.1996 (p. 9 IS.2!-S Weacld).
II See Odyur, 4.4'7, 459 (dolo,, 'Uicli.'); 441, 469 (lodao.r, ·.,.bu.lb', 'tnp'I.
The dolo, which ldothca 1ugcata • to dllpllc Ma.elm, Uld hil lricncb by
pu.Uinc on tcal·lkln•. Maybe, when die hu.man1 llip into the pelts of ltelhly·
11Linncd 1ea-creatura, they don 101111cthlna: of their M l ~ ' • llippcrineM IIIUI
lh11tt in hil dniou "'""· '
12 ApoUodoru.1, li6l. 2.S.11: a u ) . ~ M abrO. .cofl.lWJIUO', •,ettin1 a pip oa
bim u he llcpt '.
IS llwul 585-91: Ara ii lhu.t up for thirteen month• in a broue jar, hOf"tied by
Oto, and f.pblaltn the 1Dn1 of Aldcu, and would la.ave perilhcd (hdMwo).
imatiablc 1od of wv thou.,h he be, had Hemtc1 not fCM1Dd a wsy of me. . .
him; 1111.d when he doa C1Cape, he ii lhri\.~Ucd 1111.d raded (ij&,J ~ -
14 Note the expreaionl ~ 6o>.ditaoGII Hc.,&ijl', 'alter ••tins t.be food ol
deception" (OF ,.,._ 141) and Tdl, 5'd: 1,11).,roc 16).om,, 'the trick wl&b the hoeey'
(Porphyry), for e::ir.unple; d. Wu~nll, 19'0: 699-H. ·
....... u.--.......-a..................
15 The fint pauap h• llo,,:OII -,~ ohr(j.l NII (.lngp ~ ; the aecoad
~=~~
fonnid.ablr only beca1t1e he ia ID lwp. Suicdy ~ . hr ia. lib ladllll
Vru, a l)'mbol of pallffe l'ma1UIU, a fon:e of ln«tia, lht Obllaclc • , .
1
17 ;g,"~~~•lhl•iacm.•nobnotnery cOftCCD'-
~ ~ · ~ ~ ~ t o n i n u 1 LibmU,, .w..-._,,,.,.,.11 frvphoa.J.l,
252
Not•s to pp. 8-20
II N01111m of hnopoH11, Diotly,illi• 1.157-62; 2.250-7, !67-70; ICholiut on
Aetdl.yhd. Prbffltihh.l lloa,,,d 551 (p. 125.12 Heriqton); ,ee alto Wen., 1966:
'"·
19 Heliocl'1 tn:t heffDy ltJ'eUel the d'finity between the chaotic pit of Tutanu,
the di8ordcrly Htwe of Typhocua and tht whirlwincb' coafUllon: co1:11parT
n11opt1y 742 (Tanaru.1), 152-& (Typboeu.1) IDd 875-6 (whirlwinch).
20 In the 1tchlUCal lfflk in which 1he word i, ulltd by hUltorian1 of relipon.
21 Sec on thill point lludhardt, 1971: 94--7, who ma.Ir.a 'the co1Telatioo between
the myth, .bout Styx and thote conccnuaa U1brolia' quite plain.
22 My whole utument pnrridu, l think, l(>Od n:uon, for acceptin1 Cook'•
n:tmtion of ,rucpd,,, 'antidote', in the sc:hoUoa to Th1101ony 886, in 1r.cepinf
with the DlEIUICript readinf (set n. 4 above).
2. ne 'ka·Qow'
1 Ste for e•ample Keller, 1909-1': 2.243; Steier, 1952: 2412-ll;Thompton,
1956: 27-9, and 1951: SS5-9.
2 A 1imilar coDfution ii ehan.cterittic of the Latia term '"""''· gull: AndrC,
1967: 101-3.
5 Scholiut on the Odyuey &.66 (p. 248 Dindorf) (cf. on 1.441 too) .and
Hesychiu1, 1.v. cll'8uai I, no. 11193 Latte. We diould pcrhap1 identify thi1 '1ea
crow' with a mbtpecit1 of the Mans. Shearwattt, Pv./jintU pu/fintU yefJiouan,
with ThomP'On, 1958 and Andri, 1967: 61. (nil bird is local to Wand, and
couu of the Aclrial:ic, Aqu..a and Black Seu, and i1 certainly compatible in
behavioUJ and deru.ity of population with ancient account.I of the 11ithvi.1; 1ec:
moet n:ccntly Cnmp, 1977: 145-50. Ed.]
4 Slldi an a,ceount is Pffl by Dlonyd111 Pfflc,etn, btvtfron 2.S (p. 26, 15 rr.
GllffYa), of the taro,; but the lerml lmo1 and ...,hUN au IO cl01Cly ut0eiatcd,
and CYtn confuted, that the #lift from one to the c.thcr ii cuy: ,cc Steier,
1932: 2414-16. [Such a cont.won 1ten11 to mt more likely in learned tra-
dition., 1n11on1 .chol~ for whom all 1ea-birdl are mOl't or le• indimtinll'Whablc,
than amon1 actual ,ea-faren in the Archaic period: we h1Ye ollly to ttmcmber
Uvi-Strawt's obRTVation that tnad..itional 10Cictic1 tend to be n:tn:mcly
ob.enant or n.atural dilti.nctiom (1966a). Ed.)
5 Thcophrutu,, On w.alher-sips 2.28; Antu., Phat110,n11n11 950 Martin;
St"holiut on Antw,P.11-o,n,,,., 918 (p. Sil. 10 ff. Maau).
6 Two 1tudie1 hffe been devoted to Atheru1 •itllvi.s; one or them (Kioclr., 191§:
127-33) collected a number of rclevant plJIIICI, and the other (Anti, 1920:
270-!118) drew attention to a number of monumenu which could be repruen-
tation1 of a marine Athena either clad in , doalr. covered in •t~ (cf.
ph6S,h.on,1) or accompanied by a sea-bird. Neither of them paid any attcnl:ion
to the r61e of ,nllu in Guclr. thinkinl about Athena of lhe .ea.
7 In thUI contea.t, the er6idio1 ia doubtleN ,ome specie, or heron, perhap, the
Nip,t Heron (Nyelteo""" 11:yetfronu) jor the Squacco Htfon (,fr<kola
,o/louks). Ed.).
I Cf. fliad 10.242-7 (Diomede• ,peaking):
'If indeed you tell me mytd( to pklr. my companion,
how then could l foriet Odyaeus the godlilr.e, he whose
heart and who,e proud spirit are beyond all other, forwud
in al] hud c1:1deavoun, and Palla, Athene loves him. .
Wuc be ID to with me, both of u, could come bac,lr. from the b_lu1ng
of fire ittcl!, since hit mind LI bet! at dcrict1' (hr11!1 ffll!Piot& JVQOCU).
(tr. Lattbnotc)
9 Tha-e i, a definite parallditm between Juon "with one 11ndal' ("'o~o•npu)
an,d the ,A.ffO that losct part of ic.. 1tem: jut u Juon lo,n one of hb und.&11
233
,\",,t,s to pp. 20-J
while c:rouinJ a ford (a poro,) and th111 beconan flt to ~ndc~e Ute a·
pt,dition to retch the Golden Fleece. IO the A,p (ud. the bird ~~ P ~
it throqh the Symplqade1, a poros 1t tn) ii laU'lled 111 • very umil~ ~~Y m •
very limilar location. Roux, 1949: 92-5, hu riptly poincecl - t the unuatory
---"""""
<allrolo:11>-~allrox... llMII,
rl1erc.w, fOffOII
..,;xop--·
..-be facher I uqe of my 1ffC11 life l Whoae own huad hu ,own me I Lord I
Aadent in wildom l Who crafted my people I Allhdp I Whose fair bftath hu
lpCd me' (tr. Lembke, linn 794-10)). Mlt:l,ar in SM UI connected with the
word MklUrfll, 'contrwancc',
24 Akaew, frs, 149 Lobel-Pap (• 1'0•'1 2291, fr. I, I. 6ff.), with Bamer'1
eueDent commentary (1967: I U-26).
2S Note Pindar, N,,,.,.,.
7.17-11 (Saeli):
ODfGi &! ,->.>.wra
f'p,nllliw ..,~
t,...,, o65' tnrd Upk,IMIJe,.
'Wile mm know whea the third wind ii corain1, and aHrice doe, not dbtort
their juclcanmt' (tr, Uoyd-Jonn. (By iporiq the context, D. mi1interprett
thine Unn, wfllch have nothine 10 do with 'wincb that will blow in two day1'
drae' u he 1uae1u (p. 2U n. H of the on,inal). 'The third wind i1 the wind
that will 1tir u.p the thbd and mo.I formidable of three 1uccellivc wave, ...
"Wile mm" in Pindar often mcuu "poeu", bv.t the wile men hen: are dearly
not poets; they are men who haw clone noble deecb, and are not prevented by
av.rice &om 1pmdinf money to ffllllff that the memory of theK deecb will
live in poetry' (Uoyd-Jone1, 1975: ISO). Ed.) But acconlin1 to Pau.uniu,
when the wind which WOllld enable the Greeb to leave Awil fcw Troy
Nddenly ( t ~ ) llarted to blow, everyone wa WI.en by 1urpriae and conK·
quendy .aerif"1eed to Artcrnl, the fint anUDal 10 come to hand, whether male
or female (9.19.7). Cf. C.Uimadnu, (r. 200b ,reilfer (on Artunil Colaenll,
wonhipped at Amarynthua in luboeaJ.
26 UnnSSS-7Jebb: n:IUr01em,roA&oulJ#,-
1rwrotl~p",J~
XCJPfi.ffPilf'r.,xil,u,111
ff~" w· ol'lµaow . . . (• SS4-7 Peu10n)
'(Man ii) the poWff that O'OIICI the white Ha, driven by the 1tonny touth·
wind, makin1 a path under ,mp1 that threalen to enpU him' (tr. Jebb).
.....
27 Pindar, Oly,n,,..,. 7.94-S Snell; cf. l'),11114111 !.104-S; l1tliJftMft S/4.23-4
235
Noies to pp. 24- 7
eye not dropped in deep' (tr. Gmtc, diplly duapd), with Van Na, 196!:
so
!1
(Co,,.., fHWOcrttiof. ,,..,~.• «Id. IAuudt. utcl
~·=
~!~ tfffpaip~a&,,, or cn,jll!IOlida:a, 'lo cmc,alatc from die 1un', it •
vcrbill aprcuion for thoee wbo unciatake loai DitarY voya,n: ~
~;s~);~w<;,;.,:;..~'":'!~.5Sd&Dcidnrin, l:
Lcubeh'1 note1): twi11thi111, Co1,1111.-1 bl Ho1'1. Od. J.216 (p. 1555.H-
\~.:i·
:.i°'+°'!"'W-=.4r!ccmo~=-~~r,:.;~:1~,~:i~
H Calllnuchu, B•III o/ r.lu U-12 mentions Atheu NIUIUIS in the tlnlor
(once up and do- the lladium, abov.l 400 yudl: Gardiner, 1910: U. 210,
HI), which enable, him lo IUIIL her with the DiNcwi, one or whom, CMtor,
wu auppoted to haw-. lbe very llln foot-nee•• Olympia (haaniN 8.1.4):
l f f Cuen', corameaury, 19!10: 22!.
H
l.omua Ute to 1n epipun by Philmen• (At1U&ol. ,,_,. 9.119 •
H,IWJUStic Efli,anu p. 16!; ? wcoad half of third century), line. S-4 of
Gow-••·
it.lbcl 79!, quotinl , - . . . . .U6.4. kdtel -.0 compun lllil d&idit•don of
wllichn:md:c.AM1rCMm/lJll).b.GO'k~a,&:..,~.·ltlffl:dtcn.
drivin1 ,oft Nluc1ance r,- your liacea!' (1ee abo the rcmm'U of Gow-hp,
II p. 479-10. Ed.I.
S7 In die Glllf of Mapi.nia dlCTC wu II pi.cc called ..tpllela. HnodDtu1 7.11!,
_,,, th•t the Arpnavll Intended lo lake on Waler dlcn and 'la&nc:h Ht' into
the open mea (Ek~ • I ~ ~II').
JI COIC by thCft were two alt.an of 19da with th, epid!.ct ......... ..,.., ('COllftoo
tcllor'), one of Zeua .uld Athena jointly, the other of tbe DiokW'i.
19 'Good 1tar11' would abo irapty '19od r.milha' too; 1Duau1ch u bodl ~ poinu
of ehan,c, they me bodl danlffll'u11 note for example Greek ritullh CClllftfttecl
with cmb.rklas and dilnabarkin&, OI' th.e pnc1icc of aakms ueriflcet befon:
oae narud off (Popp, 19!9: &Sff.).
40 'Illeword,_. ii uacd (in thC' plural) in Ody,w, I.In to ,nem tM -kcr
indicllWlf die point at which a dbcu1 Ide, dM: poud: Ody-, 11\Nw dlC
dilcul r.r t.yond ncryone me, aDCI. Alhena, ill N . . . ol 11 ...._ 'l'Ulbd
th, &hrvw' ( ~ M Np,-r· MtiMJ), In the PIHi dncrilNd in llW Z!,.,......
meUY the tunlin,-pcnt (c.1, !51: 'Achilla poinled - • the hlfflintPoM',
~~ ripl/ll,ff· A):&llaic, to tbe compctiac ~ I H n • lhe"J llaC" .p Ill
ti There Wffe 1nmc eacepuoaL fora:aNpk de Ridder, 1112: US-I, 1&wbff•
256
,:otes to pp. 27 33
•1
Lhe Athena who prurrns the law,, 'the august guardian of the city' (Athcnil
flw~aio: ('with a 1tatue in the cou.ncil-chunber'f'giving 1ood coun.cl'I or
ffDXioiixo:: ('prote(tor of the wy.j ). He 1uppo1ed hu to Ix pr.in1 at an inscrip-
tion on the stria.
42 Fairbank.1, 1902: 410-16 had cuiirr advocated the thcsiJ that this w;u an
Athena who pre1idcd over the games in the Palae1tra.
4' To the Qtcnt that hr rrcognizts that the notion of .liairu1 i1 important,
Cham.Ola docs allow mltu iU proprr place in uplaining Athena's relation to
the palaum. (1972: 266)
44 Ser Rayet and Collignon, 1888: 143 52, and the fuller ducription in Furl·
wingler, 188~: 1. nos. 347 -473 (Po5eidon alone); 474-~37 (Poseidon with
Arnphitrite) + '920, 3921; 646-61 + 3924 (ihips); 787-845 (double-sided
pPlaJu1 with the ume 1u.bjecu).
45 At Acliua Aristeide1 point, out, Athena hu a dou.ble relation to Poseidon, lfl.
urnu.ch u he is 1od 'of hor1e1' (tmrux:) and 'o( the sea' (ll'OVTUX:): Oratio,i
!7.20 Keil.
46 Ships can~ said to be the 'ho11e1 of the ,ca': Odyn,y 4.707--9; .'\rtemidorus,
lntnprrtauo,i of Drraim1 1.56 (p. 64.17 Pu:k.); cf. the dire(t comparison be·
tween chanot-houcs and ,hip in Ody11rv 13.81-5. The hone is 'yokc-bcarin1'.
or 'cndunng' Ot'P~fV')'O( (lbycus fra. 287.6 PMG). just :u the Ulip is (Alcacus
ftJ. 249.3 Lobcl--Pq;c). Hcrodotu, UJ('1 the word JuUs to rnc•n °ridtng hone'
(7.86) u wdl u,. fut, light pllcy (8.94) !- a usage commonplace in the fifth
ccn1u.ry I have 01m11cd the rcsc of thiJ nott which i1 m11lndm11. Ed.].
47 The anchor is sometimes called~. 'bit and bndle', as in JG 11 2 1610.2.14;
E.uripidcs. lfrrnbo !>39 (xaAWWT'llpia); Pindar. Pythio,i 4.24-5; Oppian,
HaJiri,t1J1.Qn l.229. In a deniaely m('taphoncill pu1a11c, Aeschylus ca.lb hones'
bits •uccrin11-ous in hones' mou.th,':
i.1Tffu.:oir 0'IIVOI' ffT7bQ>..iwv&O: ar4u,.a
0
fl'Up1')1'~io,XC1Awoi
(S,v,11 a,flinsl Thrbrs 2067:l)ric)
an 1ma«c picked up by Eu.ripidl'1 m illl extended compui1on of Hippolytlll
IT)mg 10 stop his chano1-honc, from bolting with a man hauling at the oar
(Hippoi)II.U 1221-6). A fragment of Sophoclu, twice qi,oted by Pluurch,
UICI oiat Stc('ring oar' and );:Q~U'O( 'hll/~ridlc' :LI virt_ual synonrms (frg. 869
0
Ruh), ;, UlafC Plutarch .i.ppropnatn to h1m9e\f ([), /11dc rl Usind, 4!1, !16!k).
{I hav(' made some ;1.heration1 to thi1 note. Ed.] .
48 Apollodorus. Bib/1othcco 2.1.4; Hyg:mu•. Fcbu/or 277 (end); Eullathnu,
Cornmrnt. ,... Hom /11adrm 1.42 (p. 37, 22-8). d. W:ucr, 1901: 209!1, and
49 ~::~~~ Hesiod, H'orlts ond Dr,ys 430-1 ('sn> .. nt! of Athcn.11' makinJ
plouihs); Diodorus Siculus 5. 73.8 (Athena as the u ..,hn of all lr.mds or
c-piJth1IOJ, 'knowhow'); .4,itho/o,io Poioli,ia 6.204, 20!', ("' Gow-Page,
H,llr>1t1tic l:pigrams, Lconidu VII, VIII IP- 1_09] ). , ,
!,O AiBwl- &!, i:in ..:cu. 11).oia 11 fpol'f/01( kQ'TfOkflOOf 1tC11 but:rw Clt01.kQ(; Mi6att T ~
~PWffotK vavr(A).ea6c:a hr" ailfwv 6iafl'tPCIUIOJitVOv,;: Tl')V Oci).ciaaOIJI (Schol. 1n
237
Notts to pp. JJ-40
'I'll walk • path ur.1.lght u a line, inclining to neither -'r: r,:,r all my th~ta
2!8
Nole• lo pp. 40-57
er du: murdff of A.p,vr:tv.1 and Znl'• lllbequent snpr (4.5!17-61 etc.). In
dlll lkulioa lllCl'Cly human lkill, . . .fed or not by Athena, can ~ of little
-.e.l.d.J
70 llt Iha.kt be noted that '.U lha1e 'Rob"' abou.t lhips' qree with Anuioe'1
poiat h~ (4.1177-1) - u well they 111.tcht, ~ dlC A.lfonauu end 11p by
havint to carry lhe Art• bodily to Lake "fritonia (4.1§66-9). Ed.)
71 lnia is lllilleadlftl, Ille prophetic bnm uy, thatPolycleuteaandCastor (who
se o6 COIDR IDeMb.n of the es.pedidon) are to pny the pell to open 'paths
(thr-,h the Id) of A.uonia', whne they wW tlnd Circe. They do so, and the
lhip fmda iu way 10 the riYcr llhodaa111 wilhou.t diffacu.lty (4.627). While the
lhip ii kl lhl' 'dt,. . of the Di01Cmi.', it ill COIIIWldy aided by Hen - iadwli!lf
one of lhe , _ , . . D. hu lln:ady qaotcd lO lbow how 11selc11 Ankaia, UI
(C.640-4). 1 aee no n:uon to Nppote that it UI uiythinf b111 the ,pccial
relationship betweeft the Dio1euri and Zeus d:aat makes ii appropriate for
Apolloniua to ilatroduce them hl're; and thl'y arc cenainly not heard of apin.
Then- ill .,. obriCMll 'airtiolDpCal' point too: Apallonim can es.plain the origin
of the calt of the Dloecari on the Stoichadcs {651-5). Ed.)
72 {In fact It wu lhe prophcW:: beam which told dt.c Ariona11u to do thil. Ed. I
75 It ls in tena1 or the !ame contrast, of black apinat whi&e, that another rnuim:
dhinity, Thetis, it praenU:d in Boot F011r of the Ar,ouulila. whCft' lhe plays
a role in the pusqe of the no...h11i, tbe Wandcrinf llocb, analop1 to that of
Adlma in Boot 2.Lite Medi, the ii a111uine deity;and 1hcfi111rcs inAlcman"s
coamolOfY u a peat primordial todde• whOM: emcqence at the heart of •
dlac>tic world wnpped in darkne11 pve1 bir1b to daylqht and the brillianl
lhin.mcr of the stul. A. a divinity or the primordiAI waten, her power, older
llill than that o( Polddon, partially double, hb in ,ome pans o( the Greek
world. r or n:uoplc, when a tnrlble storm pou.accd on the Pcnian ftcet off
C.pc Sepias (In lhpaia. to the north of Euboea), the Mali aicd to ltop it by
ucrifldnl to '1beaa and the Nercidl, bclida naalr.ina: offcrinp and chanWl1
praycn at the IOp of their .oiccs to lhe howling windl (Hcrodotu.1 7.191). But
in the pauqe of lbe ..i1,,.,._tiA11, The tis acu just like Alhena - with the help
of the NCl'Cim (who are cxplicidy Wr.eacd lo .;dauiai: 4.966- 7), lhe tat.a hold
of the Arp by the •tan and lhovea it forward;jut lite Alheaa earlier, she
opc:111 up a path fOlf lhc Araona11b' lhip and pidh it lhroup! the crooked
rocks (9in< S" rflM d ~ : 4.9S8). [lnnncdiatdy afterwards, however, the
Nereida arc uaqincd u girt. playin1 ball on lhe beaeh - they pu11 the A,.,.o
from hand to h1111d over lhc rocks and w1.1n, for lhe lc111'h of a sprin1 day:
4 ·9:!;:~:,:;)lhe rcscsnblancc ill dNC, the co1npari10n cannol be punucd, al
lcut - the ICV'CI at which I PD workin1 - • 1tnactural analt·iis or lhe Olympian
deitia. for tboush,. like Alheu, Thctil is• sc,ddel! who employ, Mttis, she
don not bdOllf to the sam.e 1cneration - unlike Poseidon or lhe Diolcuri. Al a
primCRdbl pc,wtt pollC'IICd of MIN. lhe trantccnds, likc Mdis hcrHII. the diC-
r ~ t mode• and particular forms or ~e naltU or the Olynapian 101U •• as
revelled by the !lp1ECif1C cate10ricl of ac:aon of Athena, Hennes. Aphrodite,
HcphHIIIIU and Zeus. "lllat bcinf 90, Thelis -)' intervene in the ume way as
Athena docs - the mish,t equally ha...e appeared u a lhip-wright; but her mlti,
ia fundamentally non-1pcc:mc (ICC fu.nher, Vernant in Detienne ad Vcmanl.
1971: 141-2).
239
Note1 top. 59
tn:hJ'UCal langu.a,e is uaed of wbat hi' docs: "'1ttG ~ ~ · ·. · ~~
K.trrE&r,u .1a>.ti"1Cli: QP,m ~ (H-0-1). Abcnoe .0, hi, Nncoo.111': t o , ~
u.11:, to divide M:iong the onloolu:n, the parts of ~e ~ f i ~ ~ :
6®"~MX in S3 7, 5ct,S6:ooao JJl1lpa( ia S...... Tliil fanction, wh~b • q,rnml,
if hardly hipU,hted, in the riNal of ucrifice, iii hurily ttrc*1i an the contn.t
'llftbcbown to Zai.s'. The lattff a.Nreaes the Titan 11'1 the foUoWMS words:
'It 1iva you joy to han Holen rwc .id to han cozened my wits (,t_... ~
fln'po,rtuocl(: SS).' If WC abould .ccept Ullat Zew hu fOTaetD all, - IOU.I It
once add that thb Corceicht Ulvolved Promedm11', &Mins dtc initialffe in et1&er-
inf into competition with hirn, ,a.cccedin1 in dKciriftc hllll, the kin, of the
rods bcia1 fwiou, and brinPft1 to pall evil for IIICQ, not clirtttly, bu.I by
mean• of the very advabtaee• that thrir prolL"ctor hid '"""I,,,,_ hinL U one
fed, tcrnpted to find Nd!. ari intapTetation too ',ophisticated', one may
ft'lll.embn that Chriltian theololY aff"um1 aimllltaneea..dy the 0111nipotatce and
om1U1dcnce of God and a freedom or choice for man, which implin dlat hu
decu.iont are not prcdC'lltined. To 10 bad. to He.;od, let ,ne j111t point 011.t thal
if, in the 77uo,-y, Cronu• dcYoun hi, f,nt children, he .does eo bccMIIC he
hu diacovued from G1111 and Ounnos th,t hie destiny is fixed: his doom ti .nc
day to fall to his own ion "by the plan or ndlhty Zeu,· (46S). Yet Zeus hu no1
yet been born. Thinp ~ then 1oin:1 to happen accwdin1 to the plan, of Zcua,
4(0( ... hi OouMk. C¥en be(ore Zeut cnten the world oft.be foda, and befon
he co11kt pouibly IIUW: pllll.L
S The c-pilode as a wbok-" chuactcriucl by thil eccuw effect: h 11 uly .c thf
a1d of the mua,lc. when the pint is played and over, tbal the a.ertioa tha1
everythin1 that happen, ii at cvay rrton1ent the c ~ c e of dle will ot
Zeu1 become, true. Thi, doa not raean thal PrOJDCthcq1 hM not ,cClftd pomi,
durina hi.I cooh-1ation, any more than that, in the ..u be,wen Olympian,
=~:
and Titan,, the fact that the iuue ii decided ia advance (Cl'OQU'1 clcstinv to be
own:oine by Ju,. .on) muas th.lt the b:atde CMU1.0t remain IIIKffla.l lor ten
whole yun (657-8). The nill'n.tiYt techJ:lMl'le Is to ptopo,t' trom dle wtMt a
:~=edtobe!ot::.r~~oi: c=~~~..:.:
Zet11 who tee. cverythin1 in adwance, onJy to lhow Ima latff IWice JWl!dlcd
240
Notes to pp. 60-2
'4 71.. 555, 552, 564, 581, 592, 600; WD 92. 105.
...................
l! 711. 74, 112:W("f'·~Mc,om,rolll:li.W(npck&/).(wro;B8!:b~T"OtOUI
241
NoU1 to pp. 62-5
14 711. 535-6: '(It - ) when ,och and monal ram ltpUIIU'd Ulnntdtta,
;:t"h~= ~ ~ C : ! . / ! ! 5 ; , ! ! ~ ! ) ~ ~ ~ c ~ ; e : : ! ~~
crntutt1' (5S9), accordinc his rival hit OW1> propu rp1thrt. Dunrc lhdr ron-
frontadon, th, two antafCNU.Su nnoer ceur 10 be countou1 to QIIC anoOu!r;
indeed, thry pl1y thr ptleman by conauin1 their mmity bmmlh ~iltt,
and doakinl .greuion with raillery. U in Won\:r .nd Dr,:r Ullt., funolltly
an,rr (lCo).~. 59), l1u,h1 out loud (r)'l~-~~. 59), in tbt" l1111oprt-,
the Titan'• small lfflile (~aht'/o«, 547) ill his n,pon1r .to Zn.'s taunai
(up-rC¥,llwt1, S45), while he pW11 his ~u.herou, move (llo>.tfl TQl'fl), IIWLl"t
rrady hU drcq,tion (t~jfflJOftl, 565). The ffU betwem the t - pd9 ttau1
eraploy1 the 10fdy llt"<Nctift trraehny of lanp•, the entkftnent of tweet
nuon, not physical violence: an nis in the COllfttry ordinarily of Aphrodite,
£N111 and Khano-. For the IJlht"rC of thac pdcleM, brllidu 10ftneu and twcel
dtlipt, it the thouchb of YOIUII -en. Kfft"t PDalrs, l , l l ~ Q , lilllc
drcq,tiona, f ~ (711. 205-6). •
One OUJht to add hown-tr that, in rdabon to hil division of the MCrifke,
Promrtht"UJ caricalllff• the manner ol a Jood II.inc who ttnden ,Ju.t:ii:c bl the
iwne of Zeu in 'maipt lt"lltence.': 6-p....,... lf,aOTOfi: .:nm 6ic1JC11P (8!-
6). In adjudicatin, • quunl, the 11.lnt who 11 lmpiRd by the Mutrt tu.nu. not
to force of anna. bv.t lo - e t nuon, ,oh co11nny, the IOOthbaf honey of
lilten word&. The rouic of h.is j1111 uttennce hu the power of aimllble
rel0lution1, it lffct ttlc pla!nti!C rcdrc•, re1ton1 1 proper eqv..ilibriura,, but
IIUldJy, witho111 viole11ee, without opp.-elliolll: 1KfOT"pnG l/l"fO. T"~MVOI ~
(H-90). So far from tutorinl equilibrium, bown-u, PfOfQe1ltcwl eo11Jow11:k It
by hil putial acijudicuion (cf. Ht: h"fpoN).w,; ~ µoipclc).
17 Cf. 711. S92-6 and 423-1. which dc,cribr th, objt"ct and the fomu ot Zewi',
"-'"os with rcprd 10 the 1odt (cf. 88!).
18 One may compare Til. 657: Cottu1 pRMCS l.ail for h,,... ',pared' ( ~ P l
the homortala from chill doom; and 614: 'kindly Promelhn..' (to. rdation to
111en),6adf(,rra~OI;".
19 Cf. Th. '86 fr. In the diYinc world ordned by Zn.,, Z,/01 (tmuladcm,
Rivalry) no loa,er h» hi.I old place, no lonF 11in up confrontatio111 and
dillt"nljo11. Like hil br-other and liattr, Xr-.to1 (M.ipt) ud BW (Foree}, w,bo are
Zru1'1 lhadow1 and eccompany him w h ~ be ,oes, Ula, n-iippelll'S u
the p1r1111or of the 1Up.-e1111ey of the new K..mc of the Gock. He b d-ll"
UIOClllted with NiU (indccd, they fon:a a pair), md bit job ii le brins to
nou.rht any 11tcmp1 by a rival of Zeut ,o dupute bu -ercipty.
20 TA. 782-806. If wt compare thil p--.,e wilh Wo~ - " Dq, lto-200. wt
can 1re de..ty the diffGl!nce rn the «abu of #if bttweca lk dirili,e -.! the
hllm&D world&. When IOT!le ITU VN unon, . . aom. dlc O ~ y &11.0·
maticllly rneal1 the pilty puty, who 11 forced to pcrjwc bimadf (hiQoltoc,
79!). The lin.ner it a1 ODCC 'bidden' in an nil, dhd Mcp (791) 11114 a:pdkd
from lhe divine company (801-4). A--. IBft, wb.~ the lime ...all CCJl'IWI IAI,
• wicked nu lhall fmd iu way ffetywherc and ....Ric the iucparablc co..
pllli- of poor man.Jund, there will be 1M> value, no dcltp.1, Ill aa oatt. (WD
242
Not,s to f>p. 68- 18
Ito); the wicked will plle Un on pajwy, hri'.li' ~O,U,irCII. (lH) - but thit
time ii ~ not ~ the ,inner who ,rill be hidden 1way and apelled. 011 the
conll'Uy. It wiU be .A.id61 {Re,pect for the Rulu} u:ad Ntmnis (Appropriate
Anfcrl, the two dcitia ,till praent on earth u the Jut link yet connectin1 the
world ofmm to that of the 1oda, who will them1elvn hide (198), andUlandon
men cleY01cd to nil, in order to n:pin the company of heaven (199-200),
21 Eril come1 into bcinf 1111.ong the goda with Cronu1'1 attack upon hi.I father
Ourano,. Oi.nno1 chidct hit childttn (PrWiww: 208), &nd tell, them that in
return for thil crime thett will one cby be a risu, vell(Cancc. And the tisis ii the
connict between the Titant and the Olympian,, thU ~ and nriJao, ('quurel',
'feud'). For when Rhu. i, about 10 give birth to Zci.11, she a,lu Gaia and
O\ln.not to dnri,c with her a plan to 1,ave Zcu, and to repay the debt to the
cr"Uly, of her fatba (niacrro li" t,ou,tic 11trrpi,t; !oio: 472). A 1trv.qle for power
then m,un. betwccn Cronu, the i.in1 and mipty Zeu, (476), until the l•ttcr
ii victoriou,. With that vktory, the tisi, iJ paid and order rc-e1tUllilhed.
22 WD IIS-18: in the Ate of Gold men lived litrt:p 110$/Wv, without toil th.at
wcariea; h.1ppy with what they had, MIEA11µoi.; and at peace, flauxo&. tha! it.
without envy or rancour, without irrv.
2S Bencdctlo Bravo hu pointed out to me that the words crp, cr1uo,ncnoi are
twice in the Worlt, tftd O.ys u,cd of navij.ation and te.a·tn.de, at linct 45 .and
6-41. It rcnaa.iru U'QC that within the poem thetc word.I arc buinl.ly connected
with ~C\lltural labour: there arc •bout 50 Pua.IF• in which thil is 10.
24 Cf. Iliad 5.'39-4): ' . lhilt immonaJ fluid,
ichor. . the blood of bliufu.l IJO(ls
who cat no food, who drin.k no tawny wine,
and thereby beiq bloodle• have the name
of bcinf in1111onaJ.' (tr. Fiu1cn!d)
Pluwch, in Co1u,IP. s~pte,n Sap. l60b2-J, commenll on thb p.aua,e: "He
me-.n1 by thU th•t food is a precondition not only of life, but aho of death":
wt AllJ 1,.10l'Oll r-OL' tr,v &Ua Kai TOO tmotwoaaw rl/v r-poi;ip} f ~ o!,am,.
2S After notinj; th.at qricultutt cook, the nutriment of plant.I and activate, it,
Aristotle 1tatt1 (Prabltmota 20.12, 964d9-21): 'the productl of thil tillqc
.an called 'cultl\l1ted', hlmnu, bcuusc they have pined .advanu,c- from bcinl
tilled, u thouih they had been educued by it (~17'11'~P ft'~J.'Cr).'
26 Cf. Odyury 5.488-90:
A• when 1. man burica , bumin1 lo1 in 1. bJack alb heap,
in .a rernote place in tht country, where none live nc.ar I I nci,lhboun,
and pvca the aced of fire, h1.vin1 no other place to act• li,tu
from... (tr. L•tti111.orc)
Al,o Hom. Hymn io Hcrm,~ 2)7-8; Pin<br, /"ytlt. J.66;_ uid above all,
Olympi,,n 7.86-7 (Snell): when they instituttd the fin111.Crifice to Atherur.,
the people of Rhode• 'went up, h.avin1 not the bri1ht 1ted of 11.ame (~ip$,Ul
f).ay()()' (tr. Lattimore). They were thu1 rc,pon1iblt for th, inb'oduct1on of
.aailice without fue; .and Pindar commcnU on this forgettina: the ICt~ of
fue, 'Rc~ece for Pro111ctheu1/f0Tethou,t.1 pu.u. on 111an go~incq and delight
alto' (79-81). {Snell't tc:111 print.I ft'po,IIJ/Not, forethought; but ':he.contelll,
with iu dear rdercncc to Prometheu earlier, 1ugau at le".111 All ~blfll1ty. Ed.)
27 Sec Herodolut S.16; The E1Yptian1 'bdicve rue to be .a live .an~al, whach cau
wh.atn-er ii can ,ci:r.e, .and then, ,iutted with the f~d, die.• with the m11trr
which it fcnb upon' (tr. Rawliuon). The Creclr. 11111ude UI lo be foun_d m
Ariitotlc (Pon,a ntil.: Dt iw11t11t, d JtHd. 5, 469b21-6): 'When there I~ n~
mOl'e foocl/ruet (tropAI), l.rld the heat can no Jonser fe«I illtlf, the fuc dieL
28 For the Ult oflt:O'flibcrlx 1,1 an epithet for fire, tee Graz. 1965: 104-8. .
29 ju.ti u "° oac call any of the uwn.i. al.aUJhtcred on the pyr~, whether edible
(lh~ep and c1tde) or nol (hones and dop) - let alone the TroJ1.r11.
243
Notes to pp. 76-80
!10 Sc-c- Iliad 23. 76: fflll' Jlf np« M~E- For tbe •• or nip in du p-nitit,c
244
Not~s to Pf1i 80--2
5 WD 167-75. rcttorina: )69 (on the rule ofCronu1) to ittpolition in the lftmlO-
Kripltl (• l 75a Sohn1en, whote-,,,,...tus
Mou.Id be couulted.. Ed.).
4 Vcmant, 1971: 1.52-5 and eap. 51--4, hu demonstrated the dose connection
between thla myth and th.at of the nce1,
& Linc 95, which I hSYc rn:tond hen,, lt a quotation from Od. 19.360.
6 Commcntaton haw: perhap1 been too qWCk to reject WD 108 u an inter-
polation (Lehn, foDowed notabJy by Mazon, 1944 (and Sohnsc:n, 1970] ). For
Ulc WU' inttoduce1 the myth or the racn by connecting it with the myth of
Pandon: W( ll,.,di9o, ~ lkoi 8vrrroi, ,.· WP<o)lrOt: 'for god.I u:id morla.11
have the same ori,m'.
7 II is well known that thc1t formulae: ;i,ppcar frequently in the tall of oath1:
lee in putkular the oath of the Amphictyone in Actchi.nee, Al"',ut Ctesiplaon
Ill, and the oath of the people of DrcroJ in IC 1.9 (Drero1).l: 85-9. And
when .\1i1bris ia triumphant, u at the end of the myth of the racc:1, we ue told:
'the father will no \on,er rc1emble hlt so11.1, nor the 90n1 their Cather' (WD 182).
8 Vcm11111t, 1971: 1.33, rcmarlu that Pandor.a's double, Ane1idora, is depicted in
paDtinf and ICU.lpture u riling out of the srouad. Pandora herself is pen 10
brin1 'unhappineu to bread-eating men' (1"¥1' Wpckau> li>..~au,: WD 82).
It may be relevant that lllp#ll1tl1, 'bread-eating', which ii a Homeric adjectiv~.
is formed from the root ••df•od, 'to cat'; and lt a formation pan.lie! (and in
1enw: opposite) to""''•"'· 'nw-eatins' • 'camivorow': sec Chantn.ine, 1933:
51!1.
9 The panlleli,m QI emphuized by the reputed u,c or lrrnro irl Th.. 536 lr'ld
562. The whole affair tun plact in th, AJfte period or timt: 'It was in the
time when the quarrel betwtto god.I and mortal men wu beinf 1ttded' (&'
f~ . (535] ). I uo ,nteful to Jc.an Bollaclt for drawin1 my attention
to thiapoinL
10 Note that the Huiodic: ac:countJ luvt no space Cora nomadic period irl the hit-
tory of man: man is eidi.er a cultivator, or no 111111 at all.
11 A typical n:ainplt .i. Haveloc:lr., 195 7, the second chapter or which. 'Hi1tory u
Repe11' (pp. 36-51), anal.y1t1 tht 'myth of tht race,' lide-by-aide with the
mydu Ql Plato'• Poliriau and Law,. It should ,c.arccly be nece,ury to observe
that neither the idea of 'prOITft,I' nor that of 'revcu' wu tbirllu.bJe in Hesiod'•
time: for there w• no idea of 'binory' in our 1m•. Thil objection doc, not
however apply to a very u,c(ul boolr. by a follower or Havelock, Thomu Cole
(1967), which conceatntCI on a prcciae period and deala with JCn11ine ideo-
JGpCal
disputes.
12 The moat useful collection or matcriaJ for 111ch • 1tudy i.a certainly Lovejoy le
u ~-!~;le (thCR arc many othc:n) i.a Empc:doclea, r,,nr~a,i,,,u rrr. 128
Dids-K-: 1n the ,eign or Kypril (Aphrodite), all ucrificn consi.atcd or
myrrh, incenK and honey.' Blood-iacrif'Jccs, ~d indcc~ _.u eating or meat,
were conlli.dered aboininationL Plato's myth in the Po/111ciu (272a-b) 11y1
much the umc;and vcscurilftUrD. ii implicit in what Hesiod says. For a 1cnen.l
245
Notes to pp. 82--4
15 er.Oiofcnc• LKrtius, UH, of tM Pltilo,opltnr 6.H. 72-_5; mo a.~-tom
I0.29-50;J!lli.an, ()NtioMS 6.191-5. See Nttbcr, HaulkittT, 1955. 167-14
,o
29 A point not noticed bf Ric:hta, 1961.
I cuinot wulentand why HSIUlleik'I' thoupt daAC die CicOMI- were C--W.
(19SS: 21): the tnil docs not meation it.
U I owe tlUI refrrenc:e to Y•on Carl:m.
52
-:!~;;c.:~ ':t:::e~~~="'~:':rZ ,::··.;.n::.~~
246
Nore, to pp. 84..;.:a
worth, of ame occ:unmcu in the Odyur,, only dllft: Ider lO a pnciH place
{ldlaca: IS.Hf; ftl-.rla: 5.415; EIYJ)t: t.229}. Tbe rest hne a more pen!
referm1. rCJlllllly • 'lwse below'.
H 1'heN: is abo-.olc coftUltl from Cfte'a houae (lO.IH-7); and when Ody11e111
appromihn ldlaca dter leaYiDa; the illlDd of Acohu, be can Ke mea aro11nd a
lin(....-,1o.soJ.
J4 The idmtificatioa of the ftprell caccnmteftd by Odyueu with •nae aibel ii
esplicitly nued • a poaaibili1y ln l.lH-9, when: Adieu. ill the pile or
Men1e1, wondcn whether he ii the priloDer of men who are XQ).nol, &ypux
("hanh', 'brv.tuh1; and whm Ody111r111 blmldf uka what dau of men the
lnhabltantt of Cydopbi bdoac to: 1.#/HON' t'f ,cGi 6ypl0l or 6imlot, t,.
~ . "w>lm1 ad hruciah' or 'ripteou men who welcome 1tnqen'
(9.17&-6). Tbe Allle quation recun •• 15.201-2, on Ithaca, before Odyue111
n:copian that be bin rac1 bact home; and earlla, when he landl on Phaeacia
(1.120-1). Compwe die n:cellenl chapter OD the Cyclopea In Kirt, 1970:
162-71.
S5 h b acarcdy mflldent to NY, with Hav.llieiter, 1955: 2! a. 2: 'lhe cannibalbm
of the Cydops Polyphem111 1te1111 on the wbolc to be an iaolated cue.' ne
Incident dncna more than a mere footnote,
S6 Tbae and other de1&ill b11n bn:a -U 11rt11Cd by Paac, 1955: 1-20. who
comparea Ho1Der'1 Cydopt wi1h the Cyclope1 of folklore.
S7 On the Abioi, G•bioi or Hifl,IMot,oi, .« allO Nkolau of Dunuc:111, FCrH 70
F 104.
H Tbe main tata are collected by Lovejoy and loa, 1915: 504, '51, 411. ne
mmt curiou of them ii do11bdc. the lpCCCh Plutudl pull into them-th of
-e of OdyaK111'1 CCNDpaaiou who wu turacd into a pi( on Cir«', illand.
Tuter of both hulllUI and ulim.11. ailtentt, he pniae, the 'life of the Cydope11',
compuiq Polyphem111'1 rich earth widi the thin IOill of llhaca (GryU'" 91&r-
987a).
H Note .11.IO the Anlb'ophlpl ('Man-Eaten') in Herodot111 4,11, who li¥e on the
edcc of the dcKn, and are dlelllldve, at the Umitll ol the human. (On thac
Scythia.. and the Androphqoi, 1ee now R.ONUiai and Said, 1971: 955-74.J
40 Sec p. 12 abOft; ia the lu.d, when Ach.illu and Hecuba mada a.treme1 of
picl and llftfff, they fataaiH about eatinc dr.dr enenaiel: 22.S47; 24.212.
41 There ii no n:uon to alter the Offlf) or the •.mu:rip111 in line 255.
t2 In line 217, Hermea am.ply aay, to Ody-111 dlat ii he 'carrin lhil accllcnt
remedy', nl6e . , , . . _ ftlf).dp lxc,.w,he willbe aafe.ltilthenDOt achann 10
be ucd but a taliamanic objecL
45 It ia Hermn, Lb.e pd clolnl to hwnantiad, who pe1 OdyDt"111 the •"'1: and
it ii to Hananthal Eumaewaac:rificuapit (14.f!S).
44 Sec l.1111illhiw'1 comment on 12.559: "'1i nii tf'l1C 711( •oA>.a:,crxj &,Aw8ri0'1(
""1a1k &sac,uu;k, 'and throqbout the rouowin1 dclC'ription or the ucrif"JCial
prepantiom'; and on 557. On lhe role or the ouW-011.locllura· in Homeric
uc:ril"ace, aee Kudhardt, ISi.Si: 255.
t5 The moat Cllria.1 fatutt of thi,; cplaodc ii that whereu waler i,; nonnaUy in
Homeric uicrir1ee ucd to prepare few lhe actual killin1 (it it contained in die
~ C . bronze YCIICU) (Rudhardt, 19SI: 2H), Homer here dew, not
mention water. lnnead, he eoncentntn on die libation of wine whldl r0Uow1
the tillinl, Thil paau,e wu noticed by SamlOn Eitrem, 19U: 271-10, who
believed I.hat it prcsentcd ICYidence ror I rite IAOl'C ancient than bload .-r-rifice,
u did thucancriaa:of leave, att.ntcd In - e fv.nenl rttuab: 'They (OdyACu1'1
compuuoDII} knew that ill a prma111 period or iD odr.er placn, thil form had
been ucd. • or coune, when aplaiacd (I) in this way, the tnt lo1e. .lhignin-
- . . Ziehm, by cona.t, 1aw it • 'an Idea of the poe1'1, influenced by die
iiaaadoa' (1959: SU).
247
!'llot~s to pp. 88-·91
~~I!!:!~ ~:~:~t:'c!o::~:~~O:!o(!!:)~ · = : . : I E ~ ~ n
relation to the Nn, th')' ue pe1u. not uttff ltl'Utlffl ~ ue ~?d>'.-u•'•
paniolll (.« al10 Vn11ant. p. 78 above, and 1972: :uv-a:vu; and RoeeUisu
-49 On thb tat, which NgaU a conception of kinphip very arcbaic even in
Homcr'1day,1ee Finley, 1977: 97-8.
50 Nott the details: barley uad lu1tnl water, 5.+40--7; the riD.Lal cry of the
women, -450-2; cl. allo 15.222-:S.
51 By contrut, OdyltCIII AY• "I un not a ,od' (16.187).
52 Dctpilc the nineteenth-century urumenb recently nvivcd by Kinoncn, 1968:
US-62, there ii nothin1 in the- treatment of Pcndopc to ,»a,d.ty • rdenncc to
matriarchy - or nm 'trace,· of it. hndope'• 'mpec:iu po,ition' ia to be::
c:a:plaincd ,imply by the abtcnc" of OdySMUa.
n See 2.56: 1-4.74; 16.-45-4; 17.181: 17.600 (W*l:20.S;20.250--S.
54 Sec 11.414-28. Antphin-UI Q killed at 22.19-94; th, hecatomb of 20.276-
IS ii anonymou,ly olfcrcd, but clearly not by the JUlton.
55 Liodct, the 1u.i.ton' d&soltoOs, ii lulled by Ody1KU1 at 22.SI0-29, mak.ing it
cit• that the 1111Crir.ee1 performed in the put on the tuiton' bchul haft not
been accepted. A lliuo,••Os ii a Ker: Jee Caabona, 1966: 118-19.
56 Sec alto 2.425-SS (TdcmachUJ); 4.761-7 (Penelope); 14.~--t (IU1BacU1);
18.151 (Odyuew); 19.198 (Odyl:lnll't 'fabe' 1tory); 1.60-2; -4.762-';
17.2-41-S (Ody1KU1'1 pul 1¥rir1ee-1); 19.591-8 {lilt of Mcrif1ee1 offered by
Au.10lycu1, the p-andfathcr or Odyacu,). And we ahould rcmembn the IK"ri-
r..:e1 promiKd by Ody1KU1. u well (p. 85 abo¥e).
57 Cuabona obKrvca (1966: 2:S); 'th" idea of "banquet .. b«Gma predominant'
- an ca:ccllive litotn. {Ct. Vcrnant, p. 61 abov,.)
H Sec alao 1962: 27: The: PbaeacWU ... while the inltNJDnit or Ody1KUS'I
return to the world of reality, are U90 the lut aftttpow of the ph.ntuy real.JD
bt ill leavina.' I bcline that the- whole of St:pl'1 c - lhowd be acccpkd., but
without the ',ymbolitt' ud psychological 1-lpqe he aometimc1 cmploya, Sc,r
al.lo Sepl, 1967: '2l-'2;Clarkc, 1967: 52-6 uul.Hartos, 1970.
j9 Thoupl he wa, bdpcd by lno-Lcucothea mid the rivn'IO(I of l'hactcia (5.S!!-
53, -445-53). (Cf. DeciC!IIDI!', p. 18 aboft.J
60 The two tn'CI shaft the Ame trunJr... The MC:icnt world llllMUlloualy undrr-
lJtood f,lt'Wlii u 'wild olive' (1ee Jt.ichter, IH8: 155); it i1 oaly in the 1"ocleffl
world that a few aitic, h ..c tbourbt that myrtle - Nltcnded (Peur, J9S7:
2006).
61 Ml&Ch hu been mMic of this line by biltoriam of cololl.iution; ' " Mi,n,
1966: 5, forauaplc.
62 h mldt be dcu that we cui.no1 n:dle thil faaKIUI ducriptioa &om lhc
()d,yur, on the irtaucrinclv inadeqvatc arouD4J that the 'toUd bit.I ft¥TP'
Notes to pp. 91-1
pndncu' of the Mycenaean citie1 could nc,ver have had 'room within thc,r
Wllllt for the fo11r acre, ol thi1 otchu-d. double vineyard and ._itchen·gardrn
U, Berard, 1961: 1.186). h iJ instructin to note that the puu.gc's utopian illl<l
mythic.al ch.ncter was cleuly rccoiinized in antiquity Jamboulu1's hcUcnistic
Utopia quotes lines 7.120--1, for cxunple (Diodonu Siculut 2.56).
6S There ii here a dil"ficulty which I frd incapable of H"tolving. All the com·
puilons made in this article tend, it ,cenu to me, to 1uppon those who accept
Ill lcut an overall 'u-chitect' - whil Kirlr. cal.It a 'monumcnu.1 compo1er', who
pvc the Homeric poems their present stn&cture (1962: 159-270; to be 111p-
plemmtcd by Pany, 1967: 175--215). Thi.I ii also my po1ition. Bui it m11st be
admitted that there u-e many anomalies, cspcdal.Jy in the lilllguag,:, of Book
24, and th1,t it prnenu special problems (ice Page, 1955: 101-36 - illl
extreme v;cw - and K.irlr., 1962: 248-51). We alto Ir.now th1,t the hcllcnistic
critics Arittarch111 of Samo, illld AIUtophanc1 of Byzantium regarded the
Ody11c-y u ending at line 286 of Book. 23. If, for the Ille of argument, we
acccpl these criticisms u Vlllid, docs it follow ncccs»riiy that the parallel
d.-awn between Book 7 and Hook. 24 is nonscn1e? For 1ho1c who practilc 1\TUc
tural anal} si$ on 1he basis of linguistic cri1cria alone, the question hu little
meaning; .ind indeed it ii difficult to sec why they should not '11tucture' a
complc• compo1cd of the Iliad, the ,\foliahliONta and Paradile I.osl . At this
point. the h11torillll must make: a gncc:f11l exit. But a quite different approach
i.s pouiblc. Th.- worlr. or Propp .uid his ,mmcdi,uc, and later. followers (1ec
Propp, 19611; Hrcmond, 1964: 4 32 md 1968: 147-64; .and 1he whole of
Corn'"11nicalio11s 8 [1962J) 1u111uu th.it, within a common cultural area, a
complu of uor1c1 may be reduced to a ,mall number of simple clemcnlJ which
may occupy a vancty of different 1trucrural po1itions. It 1ccm1 clear to nae
that, in th.- Odysuy, the naorif or the golden-age garden is parallel to that of
the garden cullivatcd by mcn;juu a.s the motif of the hospitable Jirl ii parallel
to that of the: gul who prepares vi11tot1 for death. I also believe 1hat thematic
ilnaly,i, of epic narrative of the kind practited by the followers of Milman
P;u-ry lcalU 1n the end in the umc direction (Lord, 1960: 68-98), by abowfnt
that an ancient theme - and it is hard to unagine the long-awaited mcctinfbe-
twecn Odyucus and Lacrtc1 could be anything b111 an ancient theme - m.ay
have acquired a r1..1:cd form only relatively late. These 1wo approachc1 would
benefit from mu111al acquaintance.
For these reasons, I do nol bclitvc thal an Od':,SSl!"'J which ii pu-tly COID•
po11tc, historica.l.ly ,pcalling, ca..nnot alto be, from a 11J"ucturali.u point ofvie'w,
homogeneous; though I admit that a nrict proof hu yet to be offered.
64 More accurucly, these are the cquivalcnlJ of thoM" 1u.10 to which Hc1iod and
hi• 1ucccuon Ji~c the na,ncs 'qc of Cronus' and 'ace of z .. u1'; for of cow1e
the land of the Cyclope1 11 al10 tended by Zcu1 (9.111, 3!18). Homer'• Cron111
is the father of Zeus and ii impri10ncd in Tartaru1 (/l,ad 11.4711 ·81).
65 Eumuus, too, hu dogs which arc quite real illld bark· 14.21-·2. . .
66 Thal 15, 1hc Ph.lcacia.ns have the umc pri11ilc1n u the_lc11cndary Eth10.p1~1
(1.23 6), sec also 6.203-5: 'We arc very deu 10 the 1mmortal1; we !we In
11ecluiion in the midJI of the 1wclling 1ca, ;i\ the edge of th,. ~arid (nch.a,011,
a.nd no mortal, ,·isit us' (uc Eitrem, 1938: 1523). n,,.1 f~ili.a.rity with the
gods ..·hit·h ii 1 ymbolired by diucd feuu is corrdated with i1olation from
mo:~.. ;:';~hcna ta.Ii.rs par! in the fint sacrifice offered by N~stor and h11 1on1
{3.41- 44) . .tic docl 10 in dagu.itc (at Mcn1orl, whereas Alcmo~I •i:i-cuc1 ,the:
fact that unonr the Phacxian• th, god, d~ not au:umc dugu.1-c: OU n
ICOf"Qa,PVlffOUOUI (7.205); they e•t !he ~ficial meal m <um?'"on (7.20,).
Similarly, Potc1don u pre1ent at the Ethiopians" f~ul (liarr1 :Pl"CtPT!1'EPOo;": 1.26).
lt mi.at,! ,aecm u 1ho11gh Athena doct the umc 111 ;,.,.,tor", p•l~<"C (h).6( .. , f(
249
.V,it•s to pp. 92-8
.s.;;,.. 'the came
to lhe re.t': 5.420); but aflff llhe h• l'fft!alcd hcndf...,.
~ iDto a bird (S.571-2), lbe I.aka hn lhare Ill .n iawiliWc clhWIJ"
(S.4H-6). NntM and Telcmac:hw de not thenfDR .r dN: ............. •
=-=~:: ;:!:=-::;
warnall of counc, bu1 Nawicai bu jwt Nici (6.205) dlat few mortal• vWt
dlena (.:_ 66 above): and Adieu. co.-en Odyllftll wish • milt 'in cue one of
~~-~;;.w,:.11:r:;:·
pilality ii the im1p of a Phaeacia conapuabk widl the la.d of the Cydopn.
61 A ICholialt nota &bat "11.niod' rcpnkd Alciaou Uld AffU' • bl-other Md
Iida (tee Schal. Ody-. If (7), H, (I. p. 525, Dindorf) • Hniod, rrs-
222
Nertelbach-Wat: (rcpr. Solm•n, 1970: 115") ; ICC alao Em1athb11 oa 'I (7),
64 (p. UUI). Th.ii tea.a two poaible IOluliom: 10 ap-ee with what the
ldloliut •Y•, 1lM'O ~ 'f'OK lfipc, 'lhia coaDk:u .tlh wha1,lolloW1'. and
then, u hu been done liDce the time or IUrdloff, 1169: M-6, ftPl'd u inln·
polatcd Hui 56-61 aacl 1f6 (wheft Affte ii caUcd she daqbkr or l\hcxenor);
m to Kccpt that die poet: PH the royal couple aa .ppeannce of iocell, whidt,
w• lalff COll'l'Clcd., IO • to draw • parallel between Aeohu •d Aldaoua (1eit
Germain, lt54a: 295).
69 Mo.t olwiov.dy, of coune, the kin1 md qaem: dt,e amc formula att 1Ulrd lO
delCribc the royal coupln' ~tirclllau fM die aipl at Pylol, Spll'II and oa
Sdleria: S.402-5; 4.SCM-5; 7.546- 7. .,.
70 For auaplc, lhere ii a hOllll!lr.cepcr - Scberia (7.166, 175; 1.449), u oa
Ithaca (17.94) &a.d •• PylN (5.592):aHIN (7.7-12) UOD lth.a(ll.SJJ-6,
412-S); • bard (l.261 ff.), al• • on Uhiaca (22.55~ l). lhe Ph-.ctu.
cpilode and the .:ma - •t11ac• bn.: oltea beat. compand: aotc, lot nmnpie,
the .....-nt1, IO aariowily limilar cletpile dae dme-iap• of H ,an Alld the
cllffacnce in the aplU1•tioD1 offered (• IUII el •1a111rpoladom' apiml: • •
compoliidoa), of Eitnm, l!NM and I,1111, 1969: 119-61.
71 M will be ICal by re..U., 7.1% ff. fn:e of dae kind of prttOIICleption11bCN1t
naalriadly to be fouad in L11111, 1969: 115.
72 Compa,T Ec:henewi'• 'PffCh with that of old Aeffptiya, 2.25-54.
75 A point rnade 10 iae by IU. Pinley.
74 I flllly accept the aeMIIII tenor of Pinley', re..arlui heft; but it *'Ollld be
l'ffllelllbcnd that by die tune of the later heUeniltk period v.top&. 1&1Cd a
complex rnbtv.re of adt.u: Uld raillenurian raytha md polldal . . . .
(Gcrnet, I !Nia: 151-53). The aituatioa WM dlffem1t in die fifth ctaNry ac:
a v.tapia like Chat of Hippodama1ofMDetu1 (Aristotle,r•li*• 2.5, IH7bSO ff.)
cmnot be a.plained by appal to mythical thinki.._
76 I would like to thmk llidtft Sn.ford for re..U.. ........ lhu ftnioa of tu
sdckwidl.me.
10
....,,...
9 Claude U\ot.Suaua, 1977: 60-7, hu detcribed 10111e upecu ol thU method of
252
Not~s to pp. 124-34
27 Sec Un:, 1922: 149-52 (the story of Gylft ii dllcuaed OD p. 151); OD 1t.b,
Laun, 1924: 159-0.
21 lA1 me mention IIZI intereittin1 panlld &om a C(Wte different cultlll'c, China:
.ee Mutre, 1957: J!l-61.
29 The fonn of the urcraoay i, the aame u that in the atory of Polycratn (p. 12!1
above) (~ TO RAlr((J(. lD,,nr;\,ei.A.,..hri, 6.19.S - 111tt. 5' bfrcrycrrtU' E1t.iMW
f( TO l ' i ~ Rffodotut J.41.2. Ed.)
!10 The ICUll.itar i, hen conceffcd u tometb.Ulf precioua: Xcrxn mU.e, a pit ol
Olle dRwherc, and it is dearly a very lsvilh one (Hcrodob.11 8.120). (Note that
tbi..t latter tdmitu i, UPffaly Mid to IN: made of 1old; the other gift which
accomparun it i, a 'tiara' made or gold-thread. Ed.)
!1 fl am not tun that the tat .U.owa one to make this inference: Aman tay• (He
threw the bulb into the lea after sacrificUlf them) Kai O'fffiorP. hri ro 9uoiq 1TIV
t.>il)aA.no E( TO ,rck,r°" ... Ed J
¢ila:;\,11f.' •••
U For a:arnplc, Pausan.iu ].20.9 (a aacrifice nonh of Sparta by Tyndarcu1):
ni.41 21.171-2 (at Patrochu', fU11cnl pyn). Tiie 1Wnptuo111 ritual offerin11 of
chariott and chariot·honet com:,pondi to their statul in myth.
J!I fot the Homeric world, ,ce Bruck, 1926: 28-52, 7S-100; cf. Wein, 192!1:
l46-9;Wntrup. 19!4: 167-72.
!14 The 11et h111 a number of rnananccs: bulb w~ Aerificcd by throwina: them
into a river-head nea:r Syracu1e where Had.et weDt back into the undCJWorld
afm the npe of Pcnephone (Diodorua Sicuhu 4.25.4); hone1 were aacrificed
to Potcidon by beint thrown into the eea off the cout of the Arplid neu a
6"1ellalwff. a 'place when: birth1 talr.e place' - perbapt whe~ 1oul1 att re·
incarnated? (Pauu.n.iN 8.7.2 (mni rO r~veffNOl'J): in Pindar, PyU.unt 4.42-3
Sndl. the b,Uos it called "the immortal ,eed of wide Libya': ~ ... A ~
«lpuxdpauniPl,lll.
!5 H~. 11 often cbewhe~. hone, att connected with Pote:idon, particularly in
hit capacity u god or the eea: but bone1 are alao rdated to Hadn, god of the
underworld: cf. Stm,el. 190S: 203-13.
)6 In the Jtory connected with the house of Pdopt, tbe ,oun:ea unally speak of
the animal it.el[ (the 'toldm lalRb'), but iD one or two placet i~ Oeeee D
thought of u aoroethinl; quite independent; the R'l'CTle D IJ'\le in the llory we
know u that of the 'golden Reece'.
37 Note illso the lyric pusae,e1 in Euripidct'• o,.,,u,, 812-18, 995-1012 di
Benedetto.
58 Some memory of a fctttv-1 of royal invntiture, with acrtfieee and choiMinJinl,
pomii,ted into fifth-century Sputa {Gemet hen: ~fen to Thucydides 5.13.6,
which has nothiq to do with hi, point hce«. and I cannot thinlr. which
lbuc:y~dean PMUF he meant; but compuc:, Xenophon, Corutitulioff of tfar
L«rdumOPlicm.s 15.9. Ed.).
!9 The lqendary plot hc.-e on« :,,pin allow, u, to ttt a royal dnm1 eonnec~cd
with inve,titW"C u lung. with an idcentical 'opposition• becw«n brothen wl'lich
ii mtittly typical of the theme.
40 To thi, md he hu eeduced (u in Ewipidcs'• venion) Aue1u"1 wife. I limply
not.e hc.-e the ugnif'u::aace of the theme of the woman's riile in the tra111fcr of I
talilrnan or prccio111 object from one pcnon to another. . ..
41 On the mythical notion of sterility [a1itu1tion c,u..:d by offence apuut~nc
rules and marked spedtlcally by the inability of crop,, Ooelr.s and men al1lr.c to
repr~ducc succutfully J , which D the oppo,itc of wealthfw~ll-brinr - and so
· 1tructurally homoloiou• - .cc DekoW't, 1938: 9-28 (an unportant.1tudy).
,1 42 Then ii a dramatic ,ymbolic 1ubstitutiou in Hcrodotu.1 9.197.!-!! which con·
can, practicea (allc,cdly human sacrifice) which wc.-c cun-cnl m a p~ of
Thn.ly when: the lcepd i, ,ometilnet 1et. The story seenn to be a Ir.ind of
homoloeuc of thew prKdcc,.
253
NA'ft to pt,. U6 f1
4! The Unk wu made IOIII' IF by SffliFr, ll8.f-a:i74icf.Nllloa, J90I: 11-
12. (FOi' • dilcu.uion of 11be Clllt, 1ec Cook, IIH--40: I.ft~: 1.2..171 ff.
44 :!] mOlt dculy the dcdkation prelffl'ed • .Allli\.lo,-_ .._..,... S.. 10 (19-
priatal by Bond, 196!: 141-9 witll • bdtcr tat dillla Dibaer, 1 pp. 42-9,
Hypmpf'lc'• i,c,m Kem to have bea ~ by __. of dle IDlda fllN
(Mc Bond. 1965: 19, with fq. 765 Nauck (• p. II BOMIJ and~ 7.Ht
r'I- 6f line 111 f• p. 49 ao.d]; ICC 100 aond.'1 BO&n IO frs. 57 line 10 UMI
u i~ !:,~ ;~! !td.lact
4 8 to Apollo Hyperboftoe. wbo pw the arow tD
Abml, who Pff it in Nm to Py1bap1111. Ed.)
fl OD mytho&..,. u • rona of tlablkmc, ICC UM'III•, 1907: 57-65.
47 (Oedloff'• ctymoloff ii di favoured by both Frilk, 1954-72: 2..171 , ..... and.
by Cballtnw, DELG 4.1 .. 1106-6 l.'I', Ed.)
fl T1til ii jull a pnce towsdl the enor1DOUI importAace in 'primi.Uft' (Gftclr.)
retilion of waTinC - a c:mlwlW tbat bclonp cacbuiftly lo,.,.__
49 Let me hen call aneadoa to a rekvant item of la&e cnclmcc, coaarllUlf •
fcMI beld by a relipous conln.tcmity, IO be faund. in • curiou ~ of dw
,,.,,.,,._,,..,. ('Mcmoin1 of Ptolemy VlD E1*ptCI JI (• F,J;rH ZSf 1 9)
recordecl by AtheftMUII, Dnp,toseplw6" 12. 75, lfte-HOa; note .&.o die
Macedonian IUfflll'C-rcutdncribcd by Hippoloch• of Macedon in AlhCIIHIIL
Dnf#L 4.1, Ula-lSOc: aad • rrapneat of PCNll!idoaiu1, FGrH 17 f IS•
Ath-,Dnf'11. ll.U,461b-c:.
H Oii clulkal pnclicct in relation to the olffflnl; - 'IYmboUc offffllllli'; Uld on
the fKt that in mOlt cua ffud• which were conaccratcd lo the pdl 'Mer
from choec ID domatk ..., anly by their iDlcribcd dcdica&iOII uul f ~ l l ' ,
-
lee Homolle, 1117-1919: Sll-78, OlpKlaUy 571-S o•fumiture, tripadlud
51 It ill allo wonh aotinl; tbat tbe hero Mlcletea"• 'IHc-wrety', the lot takm hm
the !ft, WU kept in a,-_,. KCOrdiat to IIKdi.ylida 5.140-2 Snell (d'.
Robert, 192~6: 1.110 11-6. l.d.).
52 er. llcilch, 1905: 1117--li Schwa1ck......_ 1921: 161-11; a.Dion, 1943:
9~1.
SS On the tripod u ApoUo'1 winFc1 'l'chkle, .ee Cool, 1914-40: l.JH-1 ( ~
SS5 n. 5), picked., by 2.1.204--5 wnlt. r11, 144.
!If The chanp o f . , . or the word M.i.,..o, ia/Mcl f.141-!1 ii worchy ofll01C:
it mean.I hen: 'work-room' (to Cunllf&); rDonoftl', in Homer, 1111 .,.,,_ ii
racrved udu,h,dy f• • 'lr.in1' (tha1, ac any nte, ii the burdca or thill ,......
l.d.] 1 an laatruc:tift mndnomy.
!15 Dlopan Lacnlll,. U,e1 •I rh• pluloso,,llff'a l.Sl (ql.lOtlq • well-known tail
by Akacu1 (rq. 560 Ible 2 Lobel-Pap) UOut tht lparlaD ArutlNliun•:
x,tplr' ilw, fflqpOC I" a615' l'l~ ffi'A.rr' lo8)ac dlM ~ . 'Wealth b dM
••i no poor man ii a tnae man, no poor man hu liffll ('.........1' - -.ely Ill
una:eeptionably uiltocntic 1entbnent of a ChdtllDnal kJad. &d..l,
254
Note, to pp. 148-51
dma: of tbe imaipUOII whicb R.ebm!.llh relin Oii. hu been quntloned by
Mitd!.eU, 1975: 255--45; but dae ld:iolm wbo faund die 1tone,M. Mlt101;, wu
.In II J)Olilian 10 defend 8.dnmv.ch (cf. J. and L. Robert, 1976: no. 194). And
INlt important of .U, Philippe O.U.thier bu lhowa deciliYely ia hb diKv.uion
of Xaaophon, w.,, aul MHtU 4.51-t (wlaich blld.ao1 hitherto been adduced
in the clebale) both tbat the .pli•IHNI mtedatn Lyeurgu, - the w.,, ...
d
MHIV WM written in 155 IC - 111.d that, prior to LYCW'l'II. it wu not a daty
impoted upon .U yo1111111dk dliaea1 (1976: 190-5).
I On fHripoloi pnenlly hi tbe Greek world, l f f Robert, 1955: 28!1-92; we may
add two recent itelft9 from Acunaaia and Epinu: cf. J. and L. Robcn, 197!:
not. 229 and 260.
4 Xenophon, w.,., ... tt Ncau 4.52 thw IIIC9 the verb pelW.i'11 nthn than
llopli"'""'· the pdu bdn1 a lipt lhxld (and lu,plik11rirt refmint: to the
performance of military aervice equipped wil:b hemvy hop]ite umour, e,pcdally
the lhield, ltofd-.1.d.J: cf. Gauthier, 1976: 192-!.
5 Youn1 men wc,e only wed to ript U11da eueptional circu11utance1, and 10
arc nonnally !peeir.cal}y mcnlioned: note the epbode in the rnt Pelopon·
nc,ian Wu, a baule apinlt Mcpn. involvlns the IW6t.lloi (the YOWll men not
aonnally callff. up) and the pre1b1daloi (the older mm no lonirer normally
called up): cf. Thucydida 1.105.4 and Lyaial, OrllliOfl 2.50-S, with Lorau.ll,
JHO..
6 I am not here eonccmed with the mutual lncouiltencie1 of the.e pauqc1.
7 See IC 1.9 (Dn:NM), 1.126-7; and for 01irnut • 'be a YOIIDI loldicr in the
froDtier foru·, van l.ffenlflle, l941b: 1055-4. 11r.ucydida 5.41.2 repro·
daced la Be....-,n, 1912: IN-5, no. 191} ollcn a dear.cul, offic:ial du-
I
........
1inctlon betwem the fronlicl' areu and the territory proper of Aqoa and
The teal Id• formal com.bat ,pinlt 11niap1D, an oppolition whme lipif°1-
caace UI ducUNd bdo•.
9 Hen: la a U.1 - ~ y iltcompJete - ol the 'IOUl'Ce1' (a quill: iaadeqv.all:
term, u will al once be reallRd, fm fflOII of d:rew tcai.): Hdlanicul, FGrH .f
F 125 • S2Sa F 25 (• Scholiut Ton Plato, s,,...
po,i..... !Old) witbJacoby'I
connnealUy; Ephorv.1, FCrH 70 F 22 (• Harpotn.tion, LV. mrcrrrot)pca (I, pp.
t!-S Dindorfl); ~ - . DilftluU iD FGrH H F 1, S9 (Ml).,sf~)\ Slnbo
1.1.7 (S9SC)I Fnmlinu, s,,_,.,..,...,_
Z.5.41; Prondmu, SINk'p,qY 1.19;
Jwtin 2.6.16-21; Pauaniu !.18.8-9; 9.5.16: Kuebn,, CAl'OIIIK°OII p. 56 (ed.
Sc:boene);Jobn of Anl:ioch, in THG .f, p. HI§ ll;l'l'ocl111,ffl Tiffi•..,,.
21b
(1.81.11-90.12 Diehl); Nonn111 of Paaopolil, Dio11y...... 27.SOl-7;Michad
Apo9toliu, a.v. 4rlru.JII' t( : A . ~ in cm,. paro,.111io,r. ff'., edd.. Leuuch
and Schneickwin, 2, p. 294; Michael P1Cll11S, De .Aclionufll 11omi11i61U 40
(• Mipe, l'C 122, coll. 1017d-!Oa): Joh. TUeU!ct, Com11u•11,..n·11m i11
..en:..,.,...., RllftM 7Ha (4..5, pp. 907-9 ltoalcr);Lycophron,.All'xand,w 767
with 1eholla (ed. Scheer): EtymoloFon ..,.,.....,. 1.v. tm:m,lipca (cob. S!l6-7
GailfonS). and LY. I C ~ & ( (152!-S Gailford); Luic• Sl'prrMIII.& 1.v.
~ - (in Bekker, ..C11ecdor. fNCC• I, pp. 416-17); Schollut on AdiUI
Ariateida, I (P.-,hl'llllilw) lJl.20 (S, pp. 111-12 Dindorf); Schaliut on
Arilaophutet, A.cA-iaou 146 (p. 7 Diibner), and h.cl' 890 (p. Sl!I
255
Notes to pp. 151-5
but V.•N.'• F•aal poiDt rauim w~d, cf. Suda 1.v. Miw (S,p. '50.o. 451
11 ~;): !°:: inm~~= r. •Jt! ::!.!;: ~
9 DD wordL Al_ Pauliat
Schmitt illfomH me, then: wM accordinl m ,--.mu 2.~s. 7, on die ~ d or
Sphllltria nHr Troeun, a tnDPk or Athena Apatouria. which plmyed ~ un_pon·
~ ~o~~~l::!.£:\fi=:':e~J~;a;~\:St
12 ~;ncr, 1912-Ua: 4.292-7, roUOWUll a ..,..aon by MUii, 1189: 105 n.
15 }!;,:,~~~9 ~~1S~e4 ·~~~~; (1951--60a: 1.61-110, 111-16),
:::..-= ~-:-,
wbil:h or coone he did not blow.
H Marie Ddcowt.'1 raurb in 1965: 11 are completely W1founded, beinf; hNd
256
Notes to ff. J 56-7
24 Oa the Otehophoria, tte Momnuicn.1898: 56, 278-82; Rut,envan der LoeH,
1915: 404-15; Deubnrr, 19!12: 142-6;Severyn,, 1958: 2.24l-!14;Jeanmaire,
1959; 546-7, 524, 588; JKoby, FGrH 3 b I: 285-!104; !I b 2: 193-223;
Fame, 1964: 170-2.
2S The entire literary tndition on the OICbophoria and Slr.ira i, printed in Jacoby,
FG,.H !I b I (Suppleme11t): 286-9 in hU commentary u.pon tome or the mo,t
important passage• (Philochorus, !128 F 14-16). The only 1ignificant lNCrip-
tion relevanl lo the 0.Chophoria is that bclonpng lo !163 BC which give, 11' the
nc::ord of an lll"'emmt between the two KpDtnll or the Salaminia!:I 1rno1
which had been in di,putc (fint publiUled, with a full commmtary, by W.S.
Ferpson, 1938: 1-H; conveniently R"printtd in Solr.ofow1ki, 1962: 49-54,
no. 19).
26 Sec Solr.olowllr.i, 1962: 50, line ~9. The ,a,ne fAoJ provided two female
dripnophoroi ('food<anien') who broufht food to the youn1 people '.lhut
away' during the tcclu.ion ceremonies in Phaleron; cf. Nillson, 1951-60c·
2.731-41.
27 Jacoby, FGrH 3 b 2 (Supplement): 200-3. The nnctu.ary of Athen1. Skir;u i,
taid to be 'outaidc the city' (Et rit<; rrOAtw(): Etymoloficon Ma,num p. 71 'i
28 ("'Jacoby, FGrH !I b I (Supplemenl): 287 no. 7. Ed.).
28 Amplti11udt1 has two mcanints: 'a child with both p.l.ffnb alive'; and 'one who
CU.ti and huulle1 grem branche1 or twip in riNabor procet!D.oru': .« Rober!,
1940: 509-19.
29 See Pluwch, Life of Thtuus 2!1.3-4, quotinf the Anhidognphtt Demon [c.
300 BC); Proclua, Chrtnom•tll~ 88-91 (pp. S6-7 Severyn,) [• Photius,
Bihliollltca 239).
!10 Thete poinu tttm to have 1onc unnotked.
31 Proclu1, Clirrslomalll.ili 91-2 (p. 57 Scvcryna): Ei'ffETO /,E Toi<' vrm>M:11.( b
~ 1taihMTO:J.iEAT1. tt b:Q0111( Ci 4111.\flt f4'rllb 6uJ~.\Wvro rrpo( Q:.\Afl).Otl(
6.od,Jl.jJ ('the chorv.1 followed the youn1 men (the procession with the two boy,
dre-d u ptl1 V.-N.) and .-n1 the sonp; q,hebc1 from each tribe competed
apinat each other in a runnina; nee'); .sec alto the ICbolia,t on Nicandcr of
Colophon, Afuiph.rmab J09 (p. 36 Abel and Vui: Waxojaclp°' SE Ai'ycwrcta
~ a , rrui&( ~ M i ( o,u.\AWµoa drG: -.,~, o l . ~ e ( , c ) . ~
t»,.mll.ou EK Toti Wpo6 TOli ~ frprx,w d( ro riK Iiupd6o( MQVQ( i.fpciv:
'O,cll.ophoroi meant al Athen, boy, who carried tacnd br.1.nche1 and who
competed by triba; they ran with vinc.branchct from the temple of Diony1u1 to
the temple of Athena Slr.iru.' Ed.]. The inscription of the Sal.iiminioi, quoted
above, apparently alludet to thUI compeli'!on (hamilfo1) in line1 61-2
(Sokolowdli, 1962: 51): TO 6t l l ' P ~ TOV fiJ.u),),QJ h, ,idplft fl((tffpov,;
'"'1d:.oXfa6o:a: 'Each puty (ie. the two Klfflen!.I of thr Salaminian 1e11os
whoK dispute b heR' rnolved) ahall perform i.a !um thc 11,acrificc which prr·
cedct the cont,..t' (cf. Fer1J11.an, 1938: 37. E.d.J.
Thc 1i1erary uadiuon is hopdCMly confo1td, iiJlcc the 1ource1 teem to mil:
up 11 lcu1 folll fe1tivah. the Oschophoria, the Skua, the Skiraphoria and the
Thcsmophoria. The fin! and last of these took place in thr month Pyanep1ion
(SepternbcT-Octobcr) and the ThC'Smophoria w.u confined to m~ed wom~n.
But what about the Slt.ira? Ariltodcmus of Thebc,, a late hcllengbc Boeotian
writer, auicncd the ephebi.c race, which I have ~ c d lo the Oschophoria <rn
the authority of Proclu1, to the ft1tival of the Sk>r1. which wa, connected .... uh
Athena Skiru JU•t a, the 01ehophoria was (FG~H .583 F 9, from Athen .. ctH,
o~,p,aoiQplt.~,;,& It, 495e). The 1,eholiut to Ari1to.phanca. Ec.,lenafu.&or Ill
(p. 31!1 Dubnrr) u.y, that the Skira W&I a Junt fesuval (12 Skll'Ophonon). If
to, it• impouib.le to 1uppo1t that the youth, carried fJsrlloi, b~nchc1 af.~p,
papet. I cannot theR"foR" llft'e with Jacoby when he wn1cs:. Our tradition
ii pedcc:Lly dear: lhe procnaion ill attcncd for the Oschophona, the nee for
257
.\'ot~s to pp. I 57-61
the Skin.phori2' (or the Skin. ped:iap,); Uld tbna clm&a thu 'lnditioft' by
arpinc that pan or l'Todu', tat ii Ulltapolated. (T~H 5 b ~ (Sllppl~t~,
commnr.ury on 521 f 14-16). Additional-~ for •Y ~ •
provickd by the n:Ultcnce at 5,-U of a rinLIII nee .rry doe ID dlD
described by our ,ourcet, linked to a fcstinl of tbe pltntrin (die Camria), mid
in which the runner, cany bv.ncba o r ~ UII jut CM' ..,..e way ( - P· 157
bel~:).tbc S.kiTa. K'e Dow uui1 Hcalcy, 1965: 16-17, 55, 59--41, +t., ,__.,
and commnr.linl upon /G II 156!1 (thoufh tbe book must be ued with
cautio11 : cf. J. and L. llolMl't. 1967: 481-2 (IID. 217) and tbe authon they
dtc, cq,edaDy Jean Poullou:I: and GcOrJCI llous.).. . .
[V.-N.'1 commc:nu 011 Jacoby hen· arc .w-dy JWtificd; but I ~ riot thm.k
we can be certain that lbc pvalld Mtween the Otchophona and die
Staphulodromia U1 Sparta w• qu:itc u a.act • he. arpea. The ~y IOW"Cll!_
which ttatct catctoricaDv thM the ,rphebcs who ran JO tbe race csrned oaclio,
ia the Scholwt on Nicander of Colophon in the p-,e, I ha..r truubted.
aboff. hoclut him.di ay, only that it w• the two YOWll men ~ U pk
who carried vinc-b.-ancha and snPft: TOii ~ 6' 6t.'io ~ ~ -,wmm(
~a,oNOl'f.o. ,c).tpl .,. ~ 1COJU'tovr« ,-Uf'GI ~ jlorptJWI': 'nwo
youna: men from the cllonu, ~ u WOIMO and carrying a Yinc-bnndl
conrcd with fat snpa ... '. In view of the mull peata maunatan.tialily of
di.ill puaqc, and KCtion 92, it seem• cuier to 1Uppo9C" that it ii tbc 1ehotiut
on Nicutdcr which hM compttlled a fuller aecoant to the poiDI of confuioa,
or muddled • proccNioa in. the 01ehopb.oria inTOMI\I (1) n.v YOIUII men
carryinr vinc-branchca and (2) a nee between ,pA,k, witlu lisailar ooe in the
Skinphoria, when the papcs wen: just startiq to xt. ln th.ii c ~ it is
innn&cdw that this tcholian thought that ~clll iaeant Pply 'a rine tn.b',
and by cnenaion the brudl of any ni:e, thu millet the poiat .na.,:d, fOI"
n.amplc, by Ptodm, and by the EtymfHofK-"'-P•""' 619.52 Gaill~ tbM
the branch carried rlpt, bancbn of papa. Ed.)
S2 See d.o Arilto&:mu,. or Thiebet, TGrH SIS F 9 and PToc:lw, CAra11o-UIM
91-2 (p. 57 Severyn,,).
S9 '(They call the cphebee) •odro'"oi iD CreflE becau1e they do not yet tt.ke part
in the runflina ncn': ho ... K,om,J, ~ , 6io: 'td ,nJ6hw rWI' &OIIIWI'
6pq.iwt' IJET"ixEW: Euau.thiu1, Co'"'"'"'W'AU ffl Hom. Od)'JS. 8.247 (p, 1592.
58), quoted by Willem. 1955: 11 a. 8.
54 It will ~ recalled that then wttc fefthoab, ,uch u the hn11ye.\i, dwinr the
Athenian. Pan.athmaia, from whM:h all but ~ yoang wcrc ntdwkd, ad whkh
were hdd 1t night (d. Euripides, Her•driW 710-5); nott too the ritual
ramtioned by HttodolUI 5.41, dileuacd by Schmitt, 1979: 216- 7.
55 Stt IC 1,9 (DrmM), 1.11-12: 98-100 (p. 85); 1,19 (Mallot), 1.17-18, with
Guardu.cci's commmtary onpp. 87, 2!2;cf. Schwy.11:r, 1978: 257--48 m1idvan
Effeatem:, 19!7: 55~2.
56 The ruin work on lnuuin,: in cluocal Grttee 1-m11im OUo Mana1, 18U:
7-Sa; 1189: 5-20; 1890: 5- 21. The-re ii IQlll.e infonn.atiaft to be PflMd
from Aymud, l"l (motdy about llornu buntial}, aad cf. lnlidl, 1958:
iadn, .LY. Caccia. When thia snide _ . fint publ.Wted, I did aot know
ltcren)'i, 1952: ISJ-<f,2, which r.iset • llUlDbcr of the prohk:11111 dlac-..d
hne. Sec DOW abo Schnapp, 197' (ttill 1111pubUahied); lrelidl, 1919': IH-9;
and Picket, 1969: 281-98, which i, thoucht·pwN>kiaf.
J7 ID the wd.1-known oppolition betw«11 hoplkc -d. .Ca ill Emipidrl'•
t
Henlcl'1, the archer is rtjectcd, lince he hWlU wild MilaUI (155-1).
SI [7o the •ountaint' truulatcs ,._.,.. ~( t,w,.,.., I lliw mi( ltpeou, ~ : "be
went to the wild land, and chHlt in the mOWlWll:I' (Unu 716-7). f.d.J
The litcrar,, texu concernina: Alalaau arc pvea, for n:-pk. bf b o ~ r .
. 59
,
2§8
Notesto l>f). 16/ ... 1
1185: 1-11. Bown., 1950: 52-69, thOllp devoted to Swinburne', poem
Ar..,.,,., ii Ngative; but the hmdunental dilc\lmon ii aow Arripni, 1977;
d, Detienne, 19791: 27-:54, .a-2, f4--51. On the cpilodc or the .ppk:1, 1tt
Trumpf, 1960: 20.
40 'A half-child man' {Wpoirm.t ~ ) . . .y, AeKhyhu, S111e,i. a,lli,a,it T/wb,r
5!5; the very name, P.rtbcnopiwu, mean, 'with a lace like a prt•,·.
fl A.pollodoru.1, BilHwU..1e• S.9.2; Ovid, M,M'"c>fJ'hor,s 10.560-607; Virlic:4ffl
M'1tho,rophn 1.S9 (ed. Mai); Hy,:inw, F•lniliu 115;Serviu1 in Vnfil. A:,mnd.
5.11 J. The 10un:e1 differ conceminf the aame or Atalanta', hu,band.
42 Thia type or D,urc ia myth should be com.pued with the whole nn,e of tho,e
who rcfue truuition. That b a .ubject which has not yet been eir.plorcd.
4S Stu"tln( from hnc, I have tried to lhow tbat one can iaterpret SophocJc1'1
Pltilocter,, in term, of lhc,pA,beUI (1972: 161-14) (,cc n.. 27, p. 261 below).
44 Xenophon·, worlr. on war and hunting ~eab thi, 1:11odifk11ion of the hoplitc
tradition eir.u-aordinuily well. Many ,cntence1 - for Wtancc thoite which
advilc the traininf of youth, and older rnca (or WU by the practice of hunting
- have I polemical. liptili.cance which h1,1 hardly btta aoticed.
45 Tiw it u ru II l fO alons with the remuluof Plckct, 1969: 294 on the ephebe
u a hoplitc-in·the-raakln1- On the cpbebic oath u a hoplitc oath, ,cc Siewert.
1977: 102-11.
46 See Du.mt!zil, 1942: S7; 1956: 2'; and more tmenlly, Vian, 1961: SS-61. In
the properly Roman c~tcltt, ln'cn! 1tudic1 by J,·P. Morel have tN'Own nc:w
lipt on the tole of the iu11n1"'1 (the AF-clu, ol youn1 men) in the a,e-cl111
atruc;turc: d. 1969: 52'-!15; 1976; 66)-13.
:"~ !:Cth~o:!: 0
: ! : o : 1::u':;
11
!i~~~~~:t::u:~':
and the Beu;,o, ule11t, Morgan, 1177: 156. Ed.) . .
~:;'!~c:;~
.
5 de Aco1ta 1954: S4. The trulll1tion of 1598: 50 111 a mollifi.::auon of the
oripnal. {On
de Aeosu and Lafita11, 1« brieOy in Enpi&h Meek., 1976: 42-9,
: : :~ ~ : ~ e ~ o n ~ : : : : : r : .
11
~!.;';~t~~t~~:i;:nm~:
259
.\'otes to pp. 167-74
&om .a few primU"V llff"II of thou,hL Mockrn illltiNtionl plaftl their - b ill
thr period or barbvilm, into wblcll their Pftlll Weft ~ltttd. from the
~':~U::=.O:r:O~~!'eJi
I Stt for a.ample, thr
..~ro!c-:i~~:ra,h
durulliom ID Ganudy, 19'9,
* ••·
Godma', 1170; WD
aDCl
vkbl-Naquct, 1964, and Sofrl, 1919. (laE..,u.b,aoce AIMknoD. 1974: 597-
451, 462-549; and Hoblba-, lDtradiacdoa lO Man:, 1964: 9~. Ed.)
9 Note- the ,on of '111anif'e1l0' edited bJ LR. Msett. 1908, tn.otria1 Oft
clallicilu (A.rUl.ur Enns, Gilbert Marny, F.B. J - . J.L Myen.. W. W....
Fowler) aDd an anthropoJGpt-blnoriaa, Andrew t..Ds. The- maail'estD ..,..
mlriud the- won. or a pcntiaL
10 See Glido'r:, 1114/15: cola. 17-9. (For ma k'COUllt ia Eqluh, 1e-e Sbalpe,
1175:J5-46UICl47-71,,...... Ed.} Onthil.aadlffenlother~lff
DedtMe, 1979b: 12-7.
11 Tylor, 1901: 1.7;ch.,cen I 1911 4 are dffotcd lO 'Surmal iaCulNn' (Ito!:
1.70-159). Oa Tylor mdhllcaatcmpanrie,, sec Mader, 1971: 5~79;then:
ii 10me- illJonaadoa on &be notiaa or 'IIU'ffl111" in Tylar to be! foua ..... Hodpn,
1956: 16-66, utd apecilllly 'hnow, 1970: 221-51.
II Tylor, l!IOJ: 1.469. (The p-,e coadnllCI: 'Mea to whom tbcc:rk!tolbeub
1111d Wrdl 111:eta like hu1111111 ~ . a11d cheir Kticrall pklird u it wen by
hwun tllousht, lop:ally moutll aDow the nillteac:e or ..... lO bnl.._ binll.
aad ,eptila. u to mm. nae lower ,-ycholo1Y canoe bus ~ .ia bal•
the very chancteriltia whida it attribata to dt.e h...._ 1Dul, nmaety, the
phenomena or life md clead!., wl1 md
vilion or in drcua.' Ed.)
Ju....-, utd the phalltora WGI In
U Lui, 1117: 2.255-11. Note die re1pect accorded ta 1.afitaa.: '(He) WU per--
haps I.be llnt writer who nw aplained cnula ra.tura. in Glftk and other
ancient rnythl and pnc1ice1 • .-ntvak &o.. tote'lmllll. The Clailllera. • com·
pallite cnatwe, lion, fOlll and •rpe11t, fllilbt nptittaal, Lalttau thaqp.c, a
le.,ue or daru totem tribet. Jut u wolr, be.- Md t1111.le- ~ t e c l die
lraquoil le....e' (l.75). for a cdticlll 1111odna fleW, let Detienne,pp. 215-17
~,:."\~i"' Lut,'1 adln,polapal wort, .re ill Eqlilh, ROM!, 19!Hidc Coe..
14 See Lffl.Stnu.11'1 flaue, ill 1971: 559-'21, whidt. Up.lei the poia.t la •trikhtal
fuhion.
15 For 1111 n&111ple which ii not Bretoll but rrom Poitou, 1ee Le Goff ..d Le Roy
Ladmk, 1971: 517-U2.
11 Leach, 196611: 125; on - Gmaep IIDd rir.s fU ,-u-,, l f t 'lelnulnt:, 1974:
69-11.
17 Ith• been demomcnteclbyMmprido, 1971, thacinialtiadoarilulltheldl-
mne area can 'be' 1amdm111 Ge WGrld or die wfld, u.d ~ tile lamnan-
ize-d world; iadffd, the hmction of ritv.als of lnkiation ii to h.....ia both die
11111:-cta.n IIDd the- 'wld·.
11 See C. Baud, 1970; al1a RoDey, 1974: 507-11; Uld Auhenoa, 1975
(apec:ialty the- rernarb or Aabenon, Mele, Mania IIH 'l,epcll'e), . . . . . . J
think tbu B&vd bu ....,cred thne objfcdou. Men punlly. BOie
Snodsrua, 1977.
19 An:haealoptl haw habicully lpored buri.a. of clll*o _. ~ n a
bec&ule the bodie1 wen
Nlly reicoYeffll die l'dlUII
Wd.,....
bent:Mh lhe llll'IKle - thOIIP lky 1111-.e nn-
Df.__ (wbidl ~ pa.a4a.....-J mdor
Mkll• (wluch were placed io. dltaay - , . ••c ..,.......,, ....
betweca the IIF' ol n,o ad ....,lffft: 1ee C . .._., lf71h 5.Z.
bff' dllill
20 See Lllbllrl,e, 1951: Sll-94; ·Vldal-N.,...c. 1811: 161--11, ~ J1P- 14e-lO
abo,e; Vaunt, l97f: 91-51.
21 or IIMdllliapartmcc-.JDIIIIUlire, 1111: 12t-10and 1H91......._ 1,e1-
260
Not•, to /IP· 174-83
IOb: 2.116-691 llouiel, IMl: 115-1; 1951: 115-221; Thomlon, IHI:
Brelkh, IHI md. 1965: 222-Sl. 011,,.., • hrlltnfli {1969),u well Mon
ndiu wodl by NU.0.., jllDC llaniloa, JCIIUDare etc., l f f c.lame, 1971:
7-47;C. SDllfflllou.-lawood, 117h: 172-l;Vklal-Naquet, 1968: 111-11 and
pp. H7-12 abcne:Vauat, 1974: U-56,
22 See tt.ou.el, 1941: 115-5; VicW-Naquct, pp. 155....fi llbove; MaweU-Stuart,
1970: IU-16.
2! nacre II .. a:lclllivc litentl&n:, but DOh: Geraet and Boulaapr, 19S2: 59-40:
JClilllllaft, 1919: 442; Dekoun, 1961: Vmumt, 1974: 54-40 and VidaJ.
Naquet, pp. 165-8 above.
H In the Greek world, u in the mediaeval., there were bowa and bowa; the bow
dn.wa by Odyaew at the end of the a.,..., ii lhc type.cue of the bow
dulirted 'potllively'.
26 See the \ICf'Y detailed ccnnmeatary on Co111litutio11 of lh, Alh,11Mnl: 42 br
Pclflr.idil, 1962: IS-6 cf. 17-152; aJ10 Brelich, 1969: 216-27. For the date:,
Rtp.14711, 2abowc.
27 See VicW.,Naquet, 1972: 161-14, wbOlt handammtal conclUlionl I 1tand b,,
dapite the up.111cat1 of di lenedeuo, 1978: 191-207. ·
21 Liten.D.y, 'I srouad the snin for om Arclllpli,-', which refen to Athena,
dnpitc Souvinou-lawood, 197lb: 541, who upe,. for Artcmil; ollly Athena
could be Archtsetu at A.them,
29 See Bnticb, 1969: 229-SO, wJao pn,perly c:rilici&e:1 Che Mlllmpli-;J continue
to -cree wt.th Brdich, dapitc Cawnc, 1977: U7-9.
SG Tbe Nlldam.aual Int ii huaniu 1.27.S; the cridaacc ii collectcd in Coot,
1914-40: 5.165-91 (with u a:traonliaary commeatuy) and elptCially ill
BIIDen, 1"6: 1-25, who iaclecd enaphuiaet the initiatory upcci. of the cult,
but bill, I think, lo relate it to the trudtion between one ap-c:WII iand
another. On the number of -,1ioroi, 1tt Brdich, 1969: 235, 212.
SI EVCD thOllp Ariltophaaa chODkl to pre-t the limation II tho!IF it were,
ror dramatic: aad conaic: rc_n, that hr,e aot really been undentood; 1e1:
l.olau..,lNOb.
52 The IWo periocb arc 10metima telc1eoped iluo oae.
SS ('EICheat' ii a feudal, not 111. ~icn1 lepl ICml, and ii technically inappropri·
au: hffC bccaue or coune the land did DOI lfffft to the Cl'OWft in clU1ical
A.lhem in def.Wt of direct hcln. Nevcnhcltll the wonl convey, a K111C or lhc
dulff of a fuaily'1 lud bcffll dilpcncd beyond ltl control in IUch a cue. The
Frateh ia 'to•ber ea dilb.Cl'ence' (p. 156). A.a ,piUho, wu a woman who, on
the death of her father, found hcndhhc: tole 1urviviq dirc:1:1 heir, 1111.d wbo in
A.thclliaa law wu compelled lo ffllll}' her lltuat ,pack kin. See further,
Haniloa, 1961: 10-11, U2-H. Ed.)
54 Finley, 1971b: 161-71. ['Beneath the muk oCLycurru1· Uthe title of Chapter
I ofJcumairc'1 Co,m,i •J Couri111, pp. 46:S-SII. Ed.)
55 Perida in Thucydidc1 2.S9.l, play, on the: doubc 1t Spana for the benefit or
the Alhcmaal when he dedara that the Spania1e1 'by din1 ol h.-.h lnininf
pw111t the ,ca1e of maAhood [or JDMly thinp) wble 1till youthl', ffiwdlH,.J
~~WO& &.ff(' t'O ~iwv.n'P'1(0!"0a;d. Lonu•. 197&: ~- .
S6 Xenophon, Co1111. L«.•tl. 2.9. Thill CIIIIOID II noi to be confuNd with what 11
became in the R.omu. period - a mere ,pct:ucular.
57 fluiart:h l.if• of L1tu,p1 16.4-5; Xenophon, Clffllt. LM,d.. 2.11. Niluon,
1151-IOb: 2.151, ii of the opinion t.hat Plutardl'1-,.lo ii I 1r11r11lation of illl.
The olf"adal &idc, attc11:cd cpip'aphic:ally, of the pou.}Mea_dtt wu Bo~.,01,
'llenllm.•' 1c1. flarcbiu.11, u. ~ : «Yf~. o rrrc *"'l.lK i.Oxc..111
Mlk. t\alw.Jtlff J, no. 8'7 Wue. Ed.I
261
Notes to pp. 184-9
SI Pau,aaiu 5.14.I, 20.1. 0.,, of dac competition.I bennn. the YOUIII M m ~
we 1r.n- from tbe dedk:adrml to Ancmil Onbia - Clllkd bf • ume wbida
indilputably meam 'bunt'; the olllen Nan to bSft bem •.-.I eompethl,cml:
the
59 ~ ~ ~ 9~ : 5 pa.,, of thc.e imtim.doulbed ~ o n : d:iua, • Nkolc
I.emu. bu noted (1977: 116), ta lhe lut atqcl o f t h e b a n l e a t ~
(410 BC), the dme hUlldred 5,-dala - that ia ~e f ~ "'Yf!'"'
now
NfflDI • Hi#N - fol.IP• "witb their bandl and with thm tfftll , or 'lib
boars -..rpaainf their nub': Haodotu 7.225.S: Ariltaphana, L1....,.
1214-6.
40 Seelrdkh IH9: 157-16,..ciiCaJame, 1977: l.211-H7.
41 [would no~amoqdacbnteft'ort:1 In thil.ue, Wachtel, 1971: 795-140 md
Zalclema. 1171 (with a pnface by Wachtel).
41 Moria, HNi5: 225. (See alto Ille Milar poin.t l'Ude by Rolmld l.rthn, ~
llueGuidc'in 1972: 74-7. Ed.}
:!:-:-;~l~.~C,:,":l~=
Schaeldewin, 1, pp. tls-t •
...~,.(~:'°-=!'!.~;..~~~~
p. IH, frr. ,S};Somaatet,
FHG !I, F FGrH4'1
2 (quoted by the Swla);fliny, HN 5.f4;0lylllplan1U,q110tedbyStqlwnuof
lyuntium, 1.v. Sau).c.w ~ (p. 2'7 Meinecke); ApcNt.., 6.55 (c..,_
fN'OH•. f'·, edd_ Leutaeh ... Schnddewia, f, p. 5711.T, ~ ~ ) . Mcwl
of tbae refernca se to be foaad cOfflltlliaady bl dlree laka, a.w. Wl.w.
NN(: Havchiua. p. 457 Sduuk;Sleph.mlm of ~thm,p. H7Memecke;
die Sada. no. 1425, t, p. IH Adler.
.,_._
6i A fabaloua city ...,,.... 1o haw.: been roltlUkd by Pblip of Mael'doa •
262
Notes to f>P. ~-95
I POllib~ CDUJ1ter-uunpla aft the llave-camp on Chiol n:aeationed" by
Nympb.odcmt11 (1ec FUU in n. 4 .bon), or the Jrlaye,.kiJl1dom act up in the
lffOrtd centia,' BC roWld Etna in Sicily: but the1e were imt:itution, created by
111..a, not 'dtia' dclCl'tbcd u tnVile.
9 Sec Pcmbrolu:, 1965: 217--47; 1967: 1-55; 1970: 1240-70 (which dcll..h with ,
die tnldl.tionl concc:rnins £pizepbyrian Locm and Tanntum), Hit arsumcnu
llft' not affected by the duartation of Jtaarle ffin,onen, 1968, which anyway
ipgrc.tthem.
10 Set the te1:u -bled by Dwnb.il. 1924; at lcut one tat u1e1 the term
~~ ('ruled by women') in connection with Lcmno1: Apollo-
doru1, 6ibliotluu 1.9.17.
11 On Cytcmnenn in Gr«k tn,edy u the IUlllpCr of male powcn, ,cc Vcmant,
1971: l.1!4-5, and ZcidiD, 1978: 149-89.
12 There it • ntt, though oftm qW.tc worthlc11, litcn.turc on thit topic. There ul"
how"er fWO u.cfw articles I may mention, Luria, 19H: 210-28 and Willl"lts,
1959: 495-506; and a,1,unmuy of the problem in Crahay, 1956: 172~5. Thi1
ta:t of Hcrod.otu.1, and m.ny other puallcl one1 includin1 a number of thosi!'
dbcuucd hett, hive now been du.It with by my friend David Ashcri, 1977·
21-48. Hu commonacDIC pcnpc.:tivc ill very diffcrcn1 from my own, but his
full collection of cvidcnc:c may II.low a ff-eJtunination of the probll"m. Let me
alto mention the eritkum1 md of my ankle by Van Compcmolle, 1975:
!55-64.
U Cf. Willen,. 1959: 502: 'It it well to bcu in ,nind that f) 9rj>..t"uz ,-OJI tiput:vo.
~ ('lhe fnnalevictorioll9 over lhc male? rcprc1enu a proverbial idea for
top1y-tuny condition,.'
14 The 111ajor IOIUCCI aft Dionylhu of Halicamauu.a, .A:ntiq. Rom., 7.2-12 e,p.
7.9.1-11.4 Jacoby, lllld Pluwcb., Dt ,nulw,vn, wlvtibu.r 26, 26lc-262d.
(FIU'Ulcr reference, uc to be found ira Bcnc, 1967: 2.611, thoul(h hit db·
cuaion (1.168-.5) U not illwninatin1J ;t« nowAllhcri, 1977: 22-.5.
15 Sec the ducuNion by Lcra1, l9S2: 2.22-5: he favO\lff the wc1ttl'II (01olian.)
LoaianL
16 Polybiw 12.S-ll; tht pauagc of Tim1Cu.1 appeani u FGrH 566 f 12. An
accowu ainiilar to Polybiw', (i.e. Al'Utotle'1) it lffen by the 1choliut to the
1CC0Dd-centwy AD 1copapbcr Dionylli.111 Pcriqetc1, .566 ('" GGrM, 2, p. 495
line JO). Sec Walbanlr., 1967: 2. .5.5.5-41; Pembroke, 1970: 1240-70
(apcei.11.ly important) uid Sourvillou-Jnwood, 1974: 188-94.
17 More or le• tbe eame n:pruuon occun in Athcnanu, Dtipnotophi$tu 6,
264c:272a (• FGrH 566 r 11).
18 The nHntial do,;wntnt it the iu..:riptioo 'of the Locrian ml.idem' (reprinted
in Schmitt, 1969, no. 472 (pp. 118-261), brilliant!)' elucidated by Wilhelm,
1911: 16.5-!56. F'wthcr reference, to the rt,kvant Uteruy tnll, ll.lld romc
idea of the enormous modern bibliography, can br found in Sehmiu, 1969:
12.5, 125-56 and in Vidal·Naque1, 1975b: 496-507. .
19 J.cprin1cd in Meigm uid Lewi,, J969: no. 20(pp. 5S-40), who 1trangcly omit
the important commcnlary in/JG 1.180-92 (no. 11).
20 ThU point i, randy uublilhcd by Pc":'brolr.c,.1970: 125.5:--4; he alao llho"".1
that no .u.ppo" for matrili11eal de..:cnl in LocnJ can be denvcd from thr ep•·
IP'IID in .A:11t.ho/ofY P.Utrn. 6.26S (• _2801-2 Gow andP.a,e). Lcratalso came
to the aamc concl\llJon 1bo111 the Locrian1 (1952: 1.59_.0).
21 Source, 1t1d biblio,raphy arc to be found in Wuillcumicr, 1939: 99-47:Jcan
Bttu'd, 1957: 162-7S. I have relied ht-avily upon Pembrolr.c'1 d.itclua.ion,
263
Notes to pp. 195-7
~==:'~~~~(;.~~=~~_:;
bom from thcte indilaiminate coaplinp1. Nole UO 5C1'¥1111,-' Y ~
,trnft&"III J,551: '""~ ulto disfflmirle 1111p,..,..111 ('tbe,-e wen: noni.lnat.O ffl
24 :~:.:;;.tc::r::~2,;h~i:::-::-o!:.~·=:w~semm.~
,t..arid. S.551; ad vnp. Eclof. 10.57; Hcrackkln Ponncua, Pm poburdrt
y~
~:: ~ ~coaz.,-;;~-:.:=~
T ~ ...,,..., Tbc 1e1m or the apr.-ioa d: rlrt llo111oU11 here ii
unclear. Al wdl • 'dc1eellclanbl ol the Ho,,...01" it coald iaeu. 'wlto beionfed
to the Homoioi', but tba1 -u1c1 mU.c tbe pauap meanialle& On my
lntcrprdacion, it may be rcpnkd .. ,;.... compatible wit.It. Epbonu'1 KCOunl;
aad ft'CIII with lhat or Antiochw ol S y ~ .
26 Anodr.cr p--,c in Diodonal Siculus, U.6', mOl'C or le• follows 8phanu.
Ju.dm S.5, which ill p....Ud to Diodoru1 Siculw 8.21, rdcn a.plicidy to ih.e
Second Me•nian Wu.
27 Commmtaton on thil ,_... 111Ually cont.. lhem; credit for diadaphhlns
the111 mustp to Simon Pcmbrakc, 1970: 1146-7.
21 Cl. DionylRU ol Halicanaaalu 19.1.5-2.1 Oacoby): lhe budr.-pu: motif ii
pMully bowcllcriaed 10 • (mlllc) wild n,.a.e Cffl'elopcd by • (female) vine.
29 Tkc 'dear N.y' ii Aithra. the wife of the fomadcr of Tarentum, ftwmtbOL
Shew-,. while holdini bn hlllband'1 bead ID her lap (Paauaai. 10.10.7).
JO Ariltopbance. Frop IM-5 wilh lhe a:boliUII; Lyairp9. d ~ I L•tKNM1
41: cl. Roben, 1911: 111-26; Gut., 1172: 29-ti7 and Welwt:i, 1974.
Jl Opllihl, which in the llllplle of lhc Athenian. comedy·writcn IDHIU IDIIH-
lh ... lilr.e 'to Nck', ii in the Oortyn Code the technical term for the aaritll
union. The n:m::t . . . . of the "6lo, hu beea lhe 111bject of cnclle• dlacu,aion,
liac:e tbe law, of Gcmyn mention another llave, the a,oi,lnu. who ill. evfl'yone
qree,, dmllar to the Sp11un helo1, Effentem, 194.la: 92, condlldn lhat
d,Jlln .inclicatn the jvidkal aspect and y,a,.., the -=W upect of the mne
indmdual, while Finley, 1960: 168-72 arpae, ror the li1111plc equ.tnhnce of
the term•, dffclopinc a point of l.ipsiw'1. The latat edit.or of the Gortyn
Code, Willette (1117), ii more heli.&IDt: 'lhe word dlllos i,;,omedmiu IY••J·
nu,111 with woil:na, lftd IDlllletitnet denota a ch1tteHlawe' (p. 14); a dalo,
could, for a.uapk, be purdl..ed la the aeon (col. VU, 10). My owa concha·
lion it that by the time die Gonyn Code wa writlen dowa, IGCill reality h ...
al&erccl (in pwtkul. bcc.ue of chaa1cl...aa.c,,y), but the vocablllmy lud no.I
roUowed lllit aacdy.
JZ Sec Dwaftil, 1970: 2.611. The In.la IN: MKl'Dbiu. S.fllnlaM 1.12.7;
Joltannn Lyd111, De ,,....... J.22 (Wi-..cll);. Jllltin 41.1.J-J (lo, the
Sahlmllia); and M.acrabill1 &lld Johanaes Ly. . ~ (lor lhe M.........).
SS Dio,eaa Lacniwi, Liva o/ ... Pliiloaoplten 2.ll;AtflnlaNa.0.....,~.:,,_.
U, 556a-b, quotiq die WJN d,r,wiac: ('On Good lttnh') ataibuled IO
Ariltode; Aul... GeUilu. N•i•1 dHicu U.!0.6. 0. t:hil matter,.- Jqn
Pepin in Schuhl, lHlb: 121-J; and on the audlenticky of &lac 'dccl'ee' q110kt1
a.,. Hi1::roay111111 of IUaocka, Harrbon, 1968: 17. A.dacuaaa .-cl Allla:1 ea.n.....
INt ne1 DiopDeS Lunlu, mpeak ol a HCOnd .......,. {TIM 11efaencA ii ro
Atll.-) · ii!
264
Notes to pp. 197-aQl
H Dnaidl, IIN: 51-!1 reprdcd thil mylh • the aetiolo1Y of a Spartlate ritual
with aprac...,.. anddilpue;,ee aleo Pembroke, 1970: 1266.
!15 Dumbl, 1924: 11-12 .en hue u. •tiolOIY ror a ritual or ,epan.tion and
Initiation. My own interpretation ii not intended to be n.clu.dve: I ani ,imply
tl'Vint: to 1t1e1a why thia acc:011Rt LI Alht:nian.
H Cleucho1, quoted by Alhmaeus, 0..,,aosopllistu 15, 5S&d (• FHG 2, p. !19,
frs. 49);Juttln 2.6:Charu orPerpmum (FGrH 105 f !11):John of Antioch in
F'HG t, p. 547, fls. U.5; Nann111 of Pmopolia, Dion7IWI• tl..S85;scholiub
onAriltophane1,l'hihi.r 775.
!17 Sec Willetta, 19H: 496. [Pfhc: k,w sh.all be exalted over the hiah' tramlatn
nli: 6' fm,nepo. llfpnp,a. Ed.]
!II It ii IIOt pollible to say cr.acdy when. It wu a proceu which ended only with
Pcricla', law of 451 BC. Clearly, if we could c:ftdi.t all 'laws of Solon' quoted
by Plutan:b, one could point to UI implicit contn,t between two pUI~ in
the Life of Solon (21.4 uad 1,6), between lhe proYilion of the Law on wills
which dilqualifia lhe tatator who acts 'under lhe inftueac:e of a wom1n'
(')'IIIIQIIU ll'ftfJdr,wl#OC'), Md the law which foibidl llavn to oil themadve. for
e:xffdle in the 1Ymnabua or to pnclilc pedauty with citizen minon. Thia
leO:llnd rnlriction ii twice repeated by Plutan:b (Co1111illiuJJ1 7, IS2d and
A,...1onu 4, 751b). Then: II u qi~ic ~ I , for in lhe illlcription c:on·
c:erninl the 'My1teric1 of Andania' (S)'Uop 3 7S6 line 109 I• Sok.olowtki,
1969: no. 65, pp. 120-HI), dacrc oc:c:un W caprHDOII. 6ClliAoc 6' ,rrrlJ!k
11Aflif'o8w: 'no . i - may oil bimtdr.
Thac 'law, of Solon' arc not to be U'Ulcd, but they do provide a Sood
W1111ntioo o( the teat or Ariltotlc cited earlier. 1t ill qllitc b'1le that Plu.tarch
ay1 immediately aftcrwardl ill dtc Alfl•loniu dlat Solon 'dxl-t forbid ICKu.al
rdatiou bctWffD IISYCa uad (he) womm': ~ M 011MJUOK11C ~
olM: ~ I bu.t dUI nepthc affirmation, ii' I may caD it dlat, ii not to the
point heft, bcc:U11C the contat lhow1 quite dC.y that ror Plutarch lllmldf it
ii merely a matter or an infcn:nc:e dnwn b y ~ in the dialo111e, not of
a tradition bcllCYCd to be utdcnL
2 ~'!' ~~=::::=:C!·!~
Dawlft, 1971: 525-6. For my
f"Wation are by
I un illclined to think that Plato took a
part,
diKwHd
:, ~neer=~• but nrdy been eilher 11!.ctchcd or aucmptcd. 1 liDcl it quite n.tra·
ordin.-y, for cum.pie, that tbac probkm• arc ilCUCdy nm mnilioocd In the
pelt commnatarice by Taylor (1921) and Cornford (19'7). But note
CqcNc:han (IMS), wbo at leMI ICCI that~ ii a problem.
4 ncn: ,.,.. ror 1o111 ~ litdc wlittcn on Proto-Athen1 - one ac:cp-
•••
.Votes ta pp. 202-4
w•
::ac:::::. :!!c..i:=~-: ~:,.::,~er: me•~
tion Bronecr, Ifft: 47-H, .ithou,b be WM ~ : . ~ :
=·79-IJ:)
6 ::t 2.S.6 (102C); lS.1.56 (591C). Couim., 1927: 29-71 cOldabu auy
refcrcnca 10 •ndcru opiniom about Adantil; d . .llo - · · U171: S-t5.
7 c-u Jndicvplcu,ta QruUII Tt1'0JNIM7 452all ff. W..-lt. Wal:III.&.
IHI: 270, ripdy pobai. oat that c-u·, Platoaic reference1 me lty DO
mon, completely 1p. . .1: •d thUI Byzutiac maak 111 at leut 100Dat,
a:eptical of the hiltoricity of Plato', accOUDL It ....W. ia bet be lDClll'alDI co
cumiac the tncet of die mytb of Atlantia in palliatic dlauctat.
I 1.uclbeck, 1619-91: ctpedaDy 1.144-.502. l.udbedi. eaaptic:llly m;ctKU
tho• who limply - e d that Atl-tis wu America. [Thc n.t edhion. of
thia book -,pcU'Cdin 1675,iDSwedilh. V.·N. qNta from dleawpd.NCOlld
edltioD, in three voluma wkh a YOlwnc of plata, wluch Ml • Lam lat lty
ADclrHI Norc:opeull. Tiu: Swediah Ian ii mNI canwfflieedy ....... ill the
edition by A::11:d Nill- (Lych.-Bibliodlek: Saadiel and .un:a pablilbed by
the Swcdilh Hiltory of Scimce Sodcty: 2.1-1: Uppala,,Stockholm. 1917),
1.91-190. Ed.] Oa l.udbedL, RC SinaOII, 1960: 217-507 (• refaac:e I owe
10 H..J. MUTCN), J UIII at the monim.t WOl'Ullf - a 1c.dy of RWDtftnd!.· mid
elp&ecnth-c:mtury Jnterprewion, or Adaati&.
9 HaYUll llad occuion to rad PierTe Benoit'• mollltrCMu fic:lioa, I coal11::11 that
at Ont I toot die pc,snpber Bcrliou:a: to whom he often reren to be the
lpODtalleOIII pnduet ol Bcnoh', imlpUdot1. Tut WU aimply lparnDce. I
ma - able to refer lhe reailn 10 Batiomr., 1114: J-70, whicb ii one or
llenoh'• 10urc:,e1. And one adpt reeall thal tU piece wu written at abOIII tile
266
Nous to pp. 204--8
207-17. It it llao necaary hOWft'er to lhow how thu 'iD.formado11' rdatet to
Plato"• llt.oql1.t, ud I wou.ld cri.tk:b.'! R. Weil, 1959: np. 51, far only half
pcrf'Oftllq that talk.
14 See Pallotdno, 1952: 228--t-O, who, howner, unfortu.11ately CODl.bined 1ennblt
omer"\'adon1 with mlldt. more pn,blcmatic the.a con«mm1 Atlanti, and
Cffle. Ont of the indr.potl, J. Spu.u.th, 195!: 165, hu no pm:tptibl.e heli·
talion in writing: -rhe uaalope1, even in detail, ve IIO 11:riling, that one
wolMkn whether Homer dkl not make: u1e of th, oricinaJ account of the his·
tory .nd diuppearance of tbe: iJland of Atlaatil whm he wu telliq the 1tory
of Ody11CU'1journey to the land of tbt PbaeKiam.'
15 Oil the 'hydnu.lic' upecu of orientlll dapot:iam, ' " Vidal·Naqaet (1964).
16 I am pretty Ntt that Pb.to even borroWfli the name Atlantia from Herodotu,.
The Jana pLatt. hil Adantu at the w"tem e:dae of what he: knew of the bulre
of the Sahan; of which he aay1 that it atcnch rtiU further west, beyond the
Pillan of Hen:ulet (4.184-5). The,c Atlantct lived on a mountain in the lhapc
of a column. It wu cnoup. for Plalo to pu.ti. the geographical myth a link
fvthtt by tnnafnring hil ialand "in front of the 1tnita wbxh a« by you called
die pillan o{ H ~ a ' (Tim. 24e).
17 There ii no need to streu tbe dildain which the IIUtocratic Plato felt for the
wa and nittythina: connected with it: ~, Lllccioni, 1959: 15-47 and Weil,
1959: 159-64.
11 The thesis UI not entirely new. lbc: Athenian upcc:ts of the accoant of Atlantil
hPe often been noted, putkv.b.rly ill Hippodarnian ,eometrism: cf. for
o.arnple, Kl\ll', 1910: 2H; Friedlindn. 1958: 1.27.!-7; 'kivau.d, 1925: 249-
50, ud, more p~dvcly, Herter, 1928: 28-47. lnoW"comparilonbctwecn
the impttialmD of the Atlant&DI and that of duaial Athent, Uv~que .nd I
(1964: US) are in accord wnh C.H. Kahn, 196!: 224. Tho1.1sh he upc:t on
., .......
the - e line•, O. Bartoli, 17'19: H rr., combina dc:ft intuition• with a cloud
19 Note:- that according to tradition the arbitrator of the dispute: Wal Ccaop, -
whom Plato mU.e, one: of tbe military leaden of hil proto-Athcm (Critw
110.).
20 The ezpraaion IUF•ts a cin:ular enclolW'c:.
21 Jlin.ud \ln.Kcouni.bly trarulate1 ',cpantc &om the: re1t'; if the n:preaion is
indeed tnmlatablc, it mum rather 'always identical to iuclf'.
22 fl.ato d - DOt mean to 111.Lgttt that Atht11.1 ia a p\lff pbi1010phc:r. On the con·
tnry, 1Utue11 of Athena a1 warrior prove: to him that in tho1t day• women
fouthtjull u men did (CritiAI I !Ob). .
25 Nonhwlll'I», the frontier tta,;he1 u fa:r u the: pea.Ju of Cithacron and Parnn.
and lndudc1 the territory of Oropua. . . . . . . .
2, Cf Ariltotle PolilK1 2.2, 126Jal!i f.: >.r,w « ro llJJ:III ewm fTII' ,rci).w W(
~ Oii lh",
IIQMUTG ffQom, . ~ ' ')'op TQV'll')II imdSt'aW b I w ~ .
"I am IPCU,ins of the premisl from which the: a:rrumcnt of Socratet procccct:-,
"that the areatc:r the 1.1nicy of the llatc, the: bctter Thc_re are m~y ~lato~ic
0
'.'
puuaa; "' above: all Rrpc,Wic 4, 462~. Of count .no tnbal or,~auon lilr.e
~=.:~~~~e =~·i.,"'1C:~1t;, =i~i,.1:, ~~~c"'_:dc;~.:t:!:~t
25 ib9:\. i!:i\J.
1
(ll2d) (with
undcntand tbc: phnac mcPlk ~ ,rpi,,;;. X~~JIO re ,cal, 8cpo<;
Moniau, in hil Pliiadc: truulauon); ~nlilr.e R~~d, wh~ tun1
lat es 'tQ\lallY healthy in .um mer and winter', thw wnply O~lltllll the: •~ea of
bicndiDJ - which oc:aus in relation _10 the: ~-~ ( ~ ,llffpuJrQTQ
~ llle;cf. aJ.oTima,M624c: rt711ri.lKpaOUllllTW,,Wpw11).
26 Critilu I 12d: 'And they toolr. cHe to prncrve the 1amc num~ of m~ 1111d
women • could already perform, or could .till perform, military J19'VICt -
267
Notes to pp. 20lJ-JO
that " to ..y about twenty tbouand.' A moment ea,lia, - le.am d'l•f dse
AtheltWUI wr:c'the leaden or tbe Hdkncs, who ""'1'e thrir willins ronowen·
(rWl'fwlillw~·Enf!M""fnt'~hdt,,r""")· .
27 AD thilitwdl undentood by Proehl•. in rm,._.,'" 1.1'2 ff. (Diehl).
28 Cf Liwque and Vidal·Naquet, 1964: 118-19, wsd tbc 11111:hon cited thcrt .
.E•. Jh1tchenbwch, 19S8: 400, h• noted that aD the lllluliotu to Solon in di~
Attic orato111 aft with three eaceptiotu, latn than 556 BC, dte date of Adieu,
defeat In the S~ial Wu and tbe break-up of the Sn:ond Athenian Empiff. T11c
n'".utu' and the Criti,u can be dated precilely to this period.
29 Politiau 269c-274e; cf. on the relation betwttn the 1t:ructuff of thia myth
and Empedode1', thoqht, loU.ack, IHS: ISS-6, and Vldal-Naquct, 1971:
157-9.
SO I cite the tat of the mmucripu. The indittct tradition (hodua. Simplk:nu)
uaualty cites the p - . with the suh.titution of ,rOl'rCJII fM TOlfCW, which bu
been ucq,tcd by many editon, for cum.pk A. Diet, wbo tnnllata; 'In the
bottomlna Ocean of dillimilarity'. The pa.ace h• bccn much debated: cf. In
particular, J. Pepin, 19H: 257-9. My prefen:ncc for f"Oll'cao uinerdy UN"tic,
IUICe 1fQPfOI;> b too Ni.table ror my own thnia for me not to be conlCl"Tlltivc,.
There it no doubt that the earlia- Pnaccs, of the pilot and the bclm, and of
1ton11, mipt nananlly C"Mkc: the imqc of Ocean (• D~, ays); no • -
natunlly, howe"t'a-, rnic9n they have ln1pired a corttot"tion.
SI Note th.at Plato here ue, the dual number throuplout.
32 On lhe r61e of the flf)no, in Platonic t~inf. ,cc the vuy deu diaamion. of
GaiKr, 1963: 190-2. The 111:cond hypothelU of the ,._"ides ii a ,nacty of
die dilution of the One In the world of the Dyad; cf. al.a 11lc1NIC~ 155bc.
U The tame characteristic dmliOIU of the World Soul ue reproduced at eedl In-cl
of the hierarchy of 10WI. Eacb of the two cirde1 U formed, aceO'fdiar lo fbed
proportions, from the 11111,ta.nee of the Suae, or the Other, and of that whidl
retults &om their blendinf. It b its poailion ill the unffcne which cktffllUllet
the primacy of the cirdc: of the Same.
54 I omit here any dilcUJion ol the cA6,.., the DMterial rttcptade which makes it
po..ble ' • differmdation to proceed: TPIIINIII &Ob ff.
55 Plato at once roe• on to make a compariton with illandl.
S6 There ii n.othiaf un11M1al in a compuilon between imperial Alhau and an
bland: Peride1 tdla lhe Athenian, at the bcpnninf of the Pdopon.aaian W.-
to behave u if they were b.Jandcn (Thcydiu, 1.92.!);the ..,_ imap ia l1M:d
by the 'Old Oliprch' (p1eudo-Xenophon., C,nul. Alllf'l"I. 2.J4) md by Xeno-
phon (Pm-oi I).
S7 Othcn ~ 111:m hne, perhap1 righdy, fffftinilcen.ce, of Pia.to'• Tilit: to
SYlKUIC: 1tt Rudbcrf, 19S6: SI-72.
58 The nrilcat inhabitants of Atlantis were thus autochthonou,, jwt u the
inhabitant, of Attica were (Critiu 109d). Plato underlinn the point by Pint:
one of the Unp of Atlantis the name Autochthono, (IISc). Ddibente play oa
the erymolorr of proper naniet i, charactni,tic of the entin account of
Atlantil: Eu.enor b 'the pd man', l.cQcippe 'the white hone' (of POMidon),
their dauchtcr Kleito 'tftlown', and ,o on.
59 I have alftady rnenOoned (p. 204 abo\oe) thil Horn«ic rcminuc:eacc: a ,oocl
n;mnple of the many-layered cip.Ulcance of Platonic tea ta.
40 Stone1, of which there att IO many la Atlanl», are- aimilarty the remit of
pulUlf earth throuth water (60b ff.). 1bC9C lcimtilk: ideu about the orlipn gf
mnalt Nrcly have a mythical b.cql"ound.. One ii 1"CIQindcd gf the Int liaa
of Pindar'• fint Olympiaq ode:
""Apurro,,f'i~Lowp,bk ~ ~ r i p
6'1 6mrl)hf1 J.'tlffi ~ ftoxo: •AIMW·
268
Notes to pp. 211-12
But of •II thinp i1 water; but ,old, lib a ,tcamina fltt
by !Upt, ouuhilm all, pride of wealth bead,. (u. Lattimore)
ThCR ..e of eoune no m,tal. in proto·Atba11, and they an anyway forbidd,n
by th, law• (Critlu ll2c).
41 Su th, diagram in u ...Aqu, and VicW-Naqu,t, 1964: 1!7. Not, abo the rol,
played by dcMtbl, and trip!, int,rval1 in th, 1tructur, of th, World Soul
(Tin'luw !6d); th, doubl, interval co1Tc1pOndti to the octav,, th, r,l.1.tion !:2
toth,fifth.
42 Equal and unequal, Ii.kc hot Uld cold, dry Uld w,t, were pvt of the famous
table of oppoidtcs (.nutoidu4) which Ari,tod, •lb'ibutca to the Pythagorean•
(M,r.pll'1riCJ 1.5, 986a15). I thinlr. that th, interpretation of Plato', many
nuniben in hia account of Atlanti, in Brumbaupl'• stimulatinc boolr. (1957:
17-59) QI highly debatable. I do not thinlr. that Plato intended to provide 111
with I world badly connn1.ct,d in tcrmt of an archaic mathematic.I. But
Bnunbaugh. ia n,ht to ~u the rOlc o( th, numbc:n 6 and 5 in Plato',
d,Kriptiou: there uc five pain of twin,, and rn-, enclosures; the centre of
the illan.d ia five 1tadc:1 acroa; th, relation between the tot.al area of the rinp
of watn and that of the rinp of evth ia 6:5; the ttatuc of Po1tidon showt him.
dririns ahl. horsc:1 (ll6d); th, c:c:ntnl lcvcl area mCU\U'CI 6,000 1ladc:1 ,quarc:
(118); it ia rc:cluil',llar, not 1quuc, which puu it on the 'bad' tid.t of the table
of oppo1itca•. Th, number ti.a and ill multiple, play a fundamental fOlc in 1he
mililuy orpniiation ( l l 9ab). I have no dcllU"C to interpret the1e poinu in
detail here; but simply note that Plato hinuclr 1tre9ac:1 that the oppo,ition be-
twCCD 5 uid 6 ii a Iona or the oppolition bctwcc:1:1 the equal and the unequal;
whtc:h ii to ay, accofdina to the Pytbqortan table of oppoaitct, between 1ood
andevil. (Forthctablc:,1eep. l76ab,gyc,J
4! The kinp build both the ellWI and tbe bridfct at the .amc time, thu1 end.inc
the euJicr isolation or KJ,i10·1 ill.1111.d. Thil i, yet another 1tcp in the provcu
ofdieunity.
44 Note that in the L•1111 :,, 68ld ( .• the constitution under which nien colonize
the plain• dtn the catadyant ia 'one in which all other fonn1 and conditions
or polidet and citie1 arc lr.intlcd t•ther· (quodq ltlll.d 20.216~18): iu
,,,.......
r;., 6q 1JOl>T'a ErMJ m i " ~ 11'0Alf"E~II "'1i. ~ ll'dM(o.11' avµffiffTEl
45 Thia anay has both Greelr. and bubarian char:actni.nict: hoplitet and chariot·
fipter1 c:ailt lide-by-aide. It ii wroq to claim, at doc, E. dct Place, ad /oc.
(cf. Gcmct ct al. (19511), that llinp were alto I barbarian weapon: note the
Rhod.ian alinlffl mentioned by Thucydide1 6.9!.
46 The nwnbcr 10 ii the rum of tht fint fow primary numbn1, :uid COl'l"flpon<U
to ll"h'Mt)I•. on whoic J"Oi, in Pytfucorcsnilm and in Plato, ice L"°(que and
Vldal·Naquet. 1964: 100 and the wortu by P. Boyance, A. Delatte and P.
Kuc:hanlr..l cited there; I.I.to Gai11ct, 196!: 118-2!1 and the Ariatottlian tCJ<U
cited on p. 542. Sec alto Brunte:hwie:, 1956: 149-!12 (usinr tom,: unpubliahed
worlr. of mine). for Plato. the ttlrmA:tys ii s form of ttntsis: cf. t:1P. Ti'"oeu,
5!c; to •Y nothin( of the con,tn,.c:tion of the World Soul, in the form of a
double tdr"IIIU)'S (Tins_, !12b-!5bc:). It .cemt to me. in the cue of the
Crihlll, that the genesis of number. corre,pond. clo1ely to the play of pllusis.
47 One QI reminded of the Jn~rb,-is on which wen engraved the law1 of Solon.
48 The rOle of the oath in tht eo111titution of Atlantis ii an.&1010111 to that or
incanr.atioru and myth• in the Lows. To ,cho an ellprtnion from E.R.. Dodd1.
1951: 207. the obj,:c:t UI to ttabUizc the lllhcritcd Conflomcn.tc.
49 There i, probllhly .Qothina; in the typolo(Y of IOCW dLd'llrmony in Republic
8-9 quite '° 1urp1"'1ift( u the an.al.yait or the tole of 1old. Gold did not n:ilt
ill the dmocra.tic city of Spartan type (8, 547b-548b), but it malr.CI ic,
269
,"'lous to pp. 212-18
appearance in the oU,ardllc dty, whc~ it proridi:1 lbe b.t ol the rifht to ruk
(8. 5.50de) and b<comH the object of envy on the pU1 of ~-who bPc to.I
their potition and who fow,.d daDocn,cy (I, S.5.5b f.); bat 11 it not enouch to
Incl rich and poor, and I Jut for pin dri¥e1 the latter lDto the UffUI or t.he
.........
!i6 The caebatolopcal myth of IAws 10, 90!e-9CMe, depe-ncb upon an analopw
5 7 The problen11 dbeu.cd iD thil oN'lide hne alaee ~ taken up dtewbCft and
devdoped, 10111ctisne1 iD a 11.i(titly diffanit directioh; Me Bna9CNI, 1970:
to2-H;GW, 1976: 1-11 and 1977: 217-104.
270
Notes to f>fJ. 221-8
9 fferodot,u !.2.5; cf. Vemant, 1972; aiY-,r.vil • Detienne and Vemant. 1979:
2'9-49.
10 Waltdnf, 1925: 205-59 (and,inEn,1.ub,Cohn, 1974: 1-59. EdJ.
II Cf. Detieq.ne, 1977: 149 n. 98.
12 This urumt'fll ll furtherclabontcd in Decienne, 19'19a: 68-94.
I! Pl11wc:h, Q""1fioM1 ,-.ca !8, 299e: Antonin111 Libenlis, MttamorpJaous
10 fMinyadet). For the evidentt u • whole, ,cc lc..mbibis, 197.5.
14 Ota a number or iA11ct, it is cloubtlca appropriate to tee similaritie1 ~tween
Cynkt and lhe hippia of the aixde1: tee Shmw:li, 19'10: 490-514.
15 'Baclr. to the jllJllle' ii the aprcaion IIICd by Pl11tudl, Dt t111 c4n11i.,m
99.Sc--d, rdcfflnl to Dioaenea. fThc litmd meanine: of the G~ct., ton bion
-,,othlriOslll&, ii 'to pu1 cmli&ed life back amoqthc wild beut1'. Edi
16 Dinscnes L~w. Live, of tJae PJailosopJa,rrs 6.56, 105; Julian, Orationrs 1.
214c; Dio Chry,01tom, Or.tiOflts 6.62; 21-2.
17 Dio Chryto1tom, Or. 6.25; P111tarch, Aq11a Mi i'pis 11tiliOT 2, 956b; cf. Cole,
1967: U0---1.
lB Tramp: Arittophon f'I. 9 (CAF 2, p. 279); AlcU frp. 196, 197 (CA.F 2, p.
!70); cf. Al"Ultophon frs. 10 (CA.I' 2, p. 280). Sea-punlanc: Antiphilllcf frg.
160 (CA.F 2, p. 76).
19 Ptra (Antiph.-nCJ in hia Mn.,,s•W u,e, the synonym A:6,.,.tos) and t,ibt>n:
Arillophon hp. 12, 13 (CAF 2, pp. 280-1).
20 See Tannery, 1925: 201-10. Altho11gh 8urlr.crt, 19'12a: 198-208 pereeiYct the
link& betwctn thc,c comic Pytba,orean1 and a ri.,un ,u.ch ., Diodorw of
Aspendw, he is mOl't conceJ11cd with their continuity in n:lation to the
'Aaumatiot' than in their bn:ak with tradition. The new type of Pythqorcan
Cynic wu • rnarsinaJ ripre, oUtcNt now by the polis and radically e11t off
from the old Pytha,on:an co1Dmunity 1nd iu membcn.
Works cited
Aco,ta, Jo1C de. 1954. Obnu tkl P. Josi de A,od• (ed. FranciK"o ~l-). M.irid.
Thlll includa de Mo.ta'• Histtmll 114,u,oly ,,..,,..,4,,-1,.r&u (l590).~
Jaled into Fmteh by llobert Re,nault C-.ui:oia: llutooY - ~ ~t .,,.,,,..a,
,u1 Jntu1 t.Nt 0..W,.r..1Jc1 qu 'Ocddnt.11.t (PW, ISH). [ Rqw. hris. 1979. J
·-
Andcnon, Fcny. 1974, Lilt,., o/ Uie ,4b,oltdist S1au. London. .
Andrl:, Jacquu. 1967. Ltt Nor,is d'o.:Stozu:ir ,,. L.tin. tu1dn ct commcntall'a 66.
Anti, Carlo. 1920. 'Athena marina c llicau', .Vonumfflti -tidai tUU. Rt.It Ace•·
de111t,I thi lfflcri 26.270-511. •
Alri90Eli_ G. 1977. 'Ataluna e ii ciftghialc bianca', Ser. Piii/. 1. 9--47.
Aahni Doid. 1966. Didribu.ri- di tnn PU'll'A,.AC• G"N. MmLOl'W dell'
A.cc.:lcm.ia dcllc Scienn di Torino: CIUle di lcicnzc monli, 1,toric:hc c
filolopchc, Ser. 4a, no. 10, Torino.
Ashcri, David. 1977, 7ynnnie ct mviage ford: clDI d'hiltoitt toCUle irr«quc',
A,,,..Jn£SC .52.l. !1-41. .
Aubenon, P. (ct al.) 1975. Co11Nib11tfo11 d l'itudt fU l,r toniU ti de hi ,:ofonil·
ado11 n,bc!',1111cs. Cahien du Cen1:n, Jean Bhard 2. N,ipkL
Ayman:I, Jacque,. 1951. EuM ,ur 1#1 cA4n,J ,o..._,.,, rh1 ori6i,i,s ii Iii /iA ""
n,ded11A1.to,iiru - Cyrufdic•. BEFAR 161. PW.
Blldaoren, Johann Jalr.ob. 1861. D-.s .41uttnrwclu. EPJe u.. ~e,h111 a.ibn dk
i,li,...,
Gy ...... o.li111tii, dn- altr,i Wdt n.a.:-lt ,...filio1u. r,,id r,dtli,:,U,i N•hu.
Snn~ (lle-t:dhcd by Karl Mc:uli, 2 wok., Bud, 1948 (• J,J. Bachofcn',
c,.,.,,.,,.r1u Wnle, ...ola. 2-S).I
Barner, Wilfricd. 1967. Nnurl' AIJt.•io1-P-,ryri-, O•yrlly"elto,. (Diuert•tion.)
Colla:tion Spu.dum.ta 14. HildeahcUII.
Bunctt, Richard D. 1957. 'Euty lhippin, in the Neu Euc', A,itiquit)' '2.%20--,0.
8.uthc1, Roluid. 1972. M,tAolofin. London [ET, U>bn:viated, of M'1tllol4~1.
Paris, 1957.)
8.utoli, Giu..eppe. 1179-10. ES#Ji "" l't•Plic•tio" lli,toriq~ 9tM PliltOte • do"nir
dr 1• Ripubliq,u l't lU 1011 At/1111tidf! ,t 9u'on 11'11 fNS co'ui4nir jtuqr,'.tl:
,,..,.,l'ft.llPlt (1799). Bound with DUcOllrr pc, /#9url S• M.jr1U tr ,oi tU
Suirh • /•it l'ouorrh,r, d, UI diilr, t" tuidoU. md•it en fN,t,ou rt"" NT:I
iwJW,u. 2 pan, in I •ol. Stod.holni. and Puia. (Fm full detda. .ee c.,"ro""
f"lhfli dr lor BibliotM(fuit N•rio,wlr (1901), vol I, p. 5J4. Ed.)
Bcllu, Jacqu.c:linc:. 1970. ' "Orpbt!c" au. X!Xc et aa XXc: alcclc; iaurfbencn
liltenircs ct rnu.Dcalu', CA/£1' 22.229---46.
Be:Uc:uon, Andr.!. 1920, Yirfiu, son onn,rtr rt 1011 titm(». Puia.
Bdmont, Nicole. 1974. Af71old NII Gr,initp, CTTotrMr di' l'e,,_,._,,,.;. /rM,(MM.
Colltttion tcimcc dr l'homme. Paris.
di Benedetto, V. 1978. 'U Filonctr e l'dcbia eeeondo Pkrtt Vidal·Naq1MI'.
Bitlfqor SS. 191-207.
Bcn,uon, Hrnn.nn. 1962. Diit St..llW11Nfit de, Alkrhli.u, Ml. 2: Ditr Ynlhlfl'
dn f",cllUch-,o,,.Udlftl Wdt 001t 700 bi, JJI ti01' CA,ut. I ' - ~ Ila
altc Gctcbichtc 1.and Epi(nphllr., M\Ulehen. MU.ochc111-8arti»,.
lknftnielC, !mile:. 1966. hob/e,nc1 tU li"f'UiJtiq,., fhtht,Jr. Pub.
lhvd, Claude. 1970, L'HhOon G M por«c de l'O,,.,t. ~tria. fouilln cl
Rcchcrchc, S (ed. I.art Schdold). a...
272
Worl, citnl
Mnnl, Jan. "'"'eu
1957. £a ColofWllltio,a de I'll-'" Mbidiouk •t ti. I• Siciw
dc,u l'fl•riq,.iU. L 'llisloirr et I• lilfflde. 2 ed. hblicalioa1 de LI Faculti de
Lettrw de P..-U, Saie lt.udn el mithodH J. Paril.
llavd,Jnn. 1961. Ho~; Od>•nh (ll'UlL V. Bavcl; inaoduction and notnby
J. B«-d). Bibliothequedela Niack 115. Paril.
lcrlioua, F. 1884. Le, Adnte1: Hi,ti,itnt de l'Ad1111tu lf'I tU l',Ula pri,,.iti'f ou
l11trod•ctiu11 j l'laidoin 46 l'Europe. An.nu.ire de LI faculti de Lcttru clc
LyoD 1.1-70. Ly-.
Bnthi.a&me, G. l 926. 'Vimde1 pecque,: le 1tabat .acW et rc1ipewr; du cuimuff.
uaific.uW' (mapiro,) CD Gftce ancifflllC.' Thhe .5e cycle, Ullivawitc clc
Pam VDI. (To be pllhlilllcd u •a.drr'W, cuU'i11e el ,cc."'"• 4Nn, J. Grhe
•11NRIN.)
Berw, Hllmut. 1967. DW TyrannU Ni der Gri,UJ,n. 2 vols. Miinchen.
Bettelheint, Bnuao. 1962. Sy1t16oHc 1110NIWU: pubel'f) rik, N tll• •l'Wiow ,_,,._
I ed. (CoUMI' BooU) New YorlL.
lnaiey, Robert. 1705. Tlw HUtory •11d Prcrnd Srlll• of Vw,in.il., i11 /our,,.,,, . •.
a-,• nalwlf' •"" inAabi&M1 of Ill• pl•ce. 4 partl, sepuately pasinatcd. LoDCloD.
(2 ed.,-.,DJIIICMIII, A.mllcrdam, 1772.)
Bidn, JOICph. 1946. Eos OU PflllOfl ,., ,·arw111. {Gifford Lectures. 19.99) Appcndb:
II, additional pages 19-40:L'A..lll111id,. Bruxella.
Blillkenba1, Chrisl4n S. ;aacS ~ch, K.r. 19, 1-60. Lhtdos. Fouille1 ,, rffllm:lt,,,
1902- 14 a11d J9S2. Copealusm CarllbergfoAdet. S vols. ill 6. Copcnhacen
~nd Berlin.
Bliimncr, Hup. 187!1--87. T,c1&nolol/WulMfTert11i110lofNd•rC,wnlt,un4KMuk
b,i Gri,dlf'fl und RO,,.tnt. 4 ¥Ob, Lcip1ia:. (Rcpr. Hildabeim, 1969.J
BoUJ.c:IL, Jean. 196'. Coran1cntary to Plato's Ph•..t"" (trulllated into Gcrmaa by
I. Salin). E:11t:n1pla cluJica 81. Frankfurt ,JM.
BollaclL, Jcu.. 1965. Erraptdocle, I: l•troduclion j l'•ncNRn, plt'1ff'lue. Paria.
Bond, G.W. (ed.) 196'. Iuripidu' H.,,...,,.. o.ronS.
Bown, C. Maurice, 1950. 'Atalaa&a in Calydon.' Ea•11 b'1 Diffrs H-4s, ... 25
(ed. Sir Edwud Manlt) • r,...,.,tion, of ,,., Ro-,., Society of Li1,ntu,. •I
rl11r United Ki-,,lo,n N.S. 25, pp. !12-69. Oxfonl.
lrandelaltein, W. 19!11. Ado11tis. Cron• 11,w:I Uni..-, ri1111 ph•i1t111inolk11
lllfflr,iclt,i. Arbeitea am daa lnni1u1 (i.ar all,emcinc und YapCicheadc
Spnchwiuemcllaft, Haft S. Wi.-a.
Bn.'IO, Benedetto. 1979. S ....... R'fl"•ilk1 d jNstic• p,eh conw ks ,1n"P"
nw, pre,.,.•.
ct., les Paril.
Bttlich, Anldo· 1958. Cli ,.,-oi ,,.,hi: NII probleon• lloricO·flf'ljfio10. Nuovi Sagi
21. Roma.
11:elic:II, Ancdo. 1961. Gu""'· .,.,.; , culri nella Cr,cNI •rc•icG. AntiquiW, Reihe
1, Bd 7. Bo-.
Brelich. Anplo. 196!1. 'lnitialioa cl hiltoire', ill /,Utialio11: Contributio... lo the
tlscmc of lbc S1udy.COnfercnce held al Strutnu1, Sept. 1964 (ed. CJ.
Bkcka-), pp. 222-Sl. S1udie1 in the b.Utor, of rcli,ion1 10. LcMlt:11,.
.-Clich, Antelo. 1969. P•i4,s e p,,rtl&eaoi. lncunabl&la p-aeca ,6. Ro-.
Bremond, Claude. 1964. 'Le a:ie-,e auntif', Co,nonainicalions 4.4-S2.
lkemond, Claude. I 961. 'PoJt.ffitC .uaericaine de Propp', Co,nont111K"afw111 11.
147-64.
Briuon. Jean-Paul. 1966. Virfil•· Son l•rnps lf'f le ,w,,... Textes 11. l'appui 17, Pilfi•.
Briason, Luc. 1970. 'De la philo1aphie politique • r,Epopie: le Criliu de Platon·,
RnN, d.11 .v,,.,,.y""lu• ,, d•Morwlt 7!1.402-SI.
Broneer, Osc.ar. 1949. 'Plato'• dcKripttoa of Early Athens and the qin of
Me11rpitaia", H,q,nia, Supplement a (Co,nm,...,..tiw sr.di111 i11 lao11a11r uf
r.L. s4-) pp. 47-!19.
lnld., £babard f. 1926. Tollf'nleil •,ul Sullmit im f""chuch1111 lt,cAI. £illlf'
273
Works dted
'"twid/urtflftrcl,iclltlic/u Urt~chrtf na"'. V~alt1'U t,Ofl R,cltt 1rlld
Rel;,i4rt, '"it B,itr96, a, GeJCl,1chtt dt1 Ei,,rtlM"':" 11,wl d,i E~llt,
Miinchcnff Britr111c ZW' Pmpyrudonchung Wld Annken RccbUfndricbtc,
---
Cole, Thomaa. 1967. D1111ocritw •""' tU 1o•rus ofC,ult Htlt.ropol•I)· Pkilo·
lopc&J Monosnphli no. 26. Cleveluad.
274
Worli cii~d
Coot.
.,.,._.
~ Baurd. 1914-40. Z..,. A •""'1 M -dnt rdi,iOfl. S woll.
Conford.,l'nadlM.19lt. n.oript of Allie roMH1. London. (Rcpr.Camlmdp,
in 5 .
19.M:Gbacat.-,ai..., 1968.]
Camford, FEUICU II. 1917. rLlto ', Co,,,.olon. London.
ColUIIIUII, P. 1927. 'Le mythe de L'Atludde.' Mnrau ti• F,anc• 15 Febnaary,
29-71.
.........
Cowlda, P. 1921. L'Adil11tiu tt. l'l.to,a •t II, orici11•1 fU k ci,,ilwtio•. Abr:-cn-
275
...
Wo'*s cit,d
Dodd•, E.R. 1951. Tlar GNH• .U lier Jm,lioul. ht ed., with-""" ........
Dow, ==·and Hcalry, Robat f. 1965. A •e,.«J ealffl4, o/ ElftUU. Hrnnl
=~
ThcololPCal Studict 21. Cambridrc, Mui., and Lo~a. . . ,
Ducat, Jean. 1974. 'Lei tbCmes des rb:itll de la (Giida~ de Rhqiom, M"-,,•
......
Dumhil, Georp1. I 956. A..,,,.eu d• ,. forKlion ,-,.,.,..;,.., eltrz l•1 lttdo.£r,,o,,hru •
276
Wor4., cit.d
, ~ . A.·J. 1972. •A propo, cla uilalopa d'lais', in t1uu, ,,. ulip,11
f;:!';...i'
llt'Ulnisliqw, pp. Ul-64. Puil. (Rcpt'. from. IITAR 42 (1949),
Finley, MNU I. 1'60. °11r,e 1c:nile 1tabun of Anc:iml Greece', RIDA., Ser. 3,7.
16!1-19.
Finley, Mo1n I. 196'164. 'Between Slffery and Freedom', CSSH 6.23!1-49.
Finley, Mole• I. 1975a. 'Utopiur.Ulm Anc:imt and Modtra', in UH .,.d A.6wl!' of
Hi:ltory, pp. 171-92. Lolldoa and New York. (Repr. &om TM Critical
Spirit. Enr,, i11 li.0110, of Hfffl•rl M11rcutt, edited by K. Woltf and Burintton
Moore jl'. Bolton, 1967, pp. 3-20.J
Finley, Mo1e1 l. 1975b. 'Spana', in TM Utt Md Ah,• of HUtor,, pp, 161-77.
~-jdon and New Yorlr.. (Repr. &om. Vmwu, Jeaa-Pimc (ed.), 1968, 14!1-
Pinleyi::;)~ I. 1977. Tli• World ofO,t,yu.,.,. 3 ed. London and NewYorlr.. (I ed.,
Frialr.el, Hamann F. 197~. £.rly Gru* po,try 11ruJ plailosoplly: 11 li.iltor,. of Gret"II
~K. ly,U 1111d prtn11 to 111.e fflidtll• of IA• fifth cnlu')' BC. Osford; (ET of
Dklaluflf uruJ Pliilosop/aie d•s fr'lat"Pt'II Grit'clanlums, ed. 3, MWIChen,
1969.J
Frazer, Jama Geo,.e. 1898. P1111111n.iu's De1criplio11 o/Gre•cr (1rt111r• ..,,,, cor,im.).
6 YOl1. London.
Fricdlinder, Paul. 19!18. Pkto:""' U11rod11clio11. I. (ET of n.11111: snm-1tr1a,.;1
11,uJ L•H,uwirlllicl,11,il, 2 ed., 1954.) LoDdon.
Fri.t, JOns Ivan Hjalmar. 19H-72. G,;,.cAilclaes Ety ... olotiJcA•, WO,r,.,.11cA.
lndogermaaische Bibliothek, Abt. I, Reihe 2. ! .oll. Hciddba):.
Fria, Kmt VOil. I 96S. An. 'Pyttmcweer.' R£, cob. 209-61.
Fro,1, K.T. 191!1. Toe Critw and Mino&a C.-Ctc',/HS 33.119-206.
F\lb, Aluander. 1961. 'Slawc war and llave troubles in ChiOI in the lhirdcc:ntmy
8C',Allil'llll•11,111 46.102-11.
FllftWUllla, Adolf. 1185. •nclar,i611"1 de,- l'•e11111111ml•ftf im A11tiq11pi°111f1.
lton.ii;lichc Mweea au Berlin. 2 wvl,. Balin.
Gaiclor., Hmri. 1884-85. 'La MytholoplC comparic: WI mot d'oplic:ation',
Milui11e 2, coll. 97-9.
G.ber, Kcmnd. 1963. Pfato111 "••tcArid•11• L•hr•: Studit"11 .rur r,1t1rn.tisch•11
uruJ 1e,claiclltlicMn ••lf'MM11"1 dn WiJ1•111elacft i11 ,,.,. P,.1011UcMn ScAule.
Stuttprt.
Garaudy, Rota (ed.). 1969. Su, le '111odt' d• p,od11.ctio11 uillfiq11.e'. Centre d'£tudn
et de Rccberdt.c, Maniltcs. PU"U.
Gardiner, Edward Norraaa. 1910. Gre•.l Atllllllic Sport, 11M Ferrw.11. Handbook,
of Arcbacolorr. London.
Gulan, Y11011. 1972. 'Le, adave1 FCCII m tempi de sucm=', in ActH du Collo911e
d'HU10;,•,ocwl• (Be~n, 1970), pp. H-fi7. Ba&JM;on-Paria.
Carlan, Yvon. 1975. W• in IA• A11c9"ftl Wo,ld:• 1ocilll ltU'lol"")'. London and New
York. (ET of L• Gwrtt ""1tJ l'A1ttiquili, ParD, 1972.)
Gaudio, A. 1962.Lt'IE'MpiNi NI• ,,,.,.Pari1.
Gauthier, Philippe. 1976. U11 co111111,,.,11;,. hi.toriqH de, '/l'o,oi' de X•11opho11.
CcntR de Rccherchc1 d'Hi1toin: ct de Philolofie de la IVe 1ectioa de 1'£cole
Pntiqac de• Haute, £tudc1, !I: Hauta trudu d11 molldc snco...-omain 8.
GcJICYe-Paria.
Ge1emchatz, Em,t. 194!. PI.10111 A1Z.111it. :Z:iirich,
GcMcp, Arnold nn. 191!1. 'Contribntiom l l'hutoirc m France de la raiihode
277
Works cited
Germain Gabriel. 19541. Gn.tie d, l'OdytJh: I, f••t•"'fwt ~t I, -,.,./. PR
Germain: Gabriel. J 9Hb. Ho,,.m "i. "'ysti.qu, d,s "7"'~i.'aru~ 1 ck l'D.iade)'
Gnne~H~~: :;!~!; 1
2t~1~11:.r ~:~~ct9.":-9;5, 9~1:.J . . ,
Gnnet, Louis. 1955. Droil ,t 1ociltl dlffll ~ GrTc,_ •11orn11l': Publicatuu1, de
l'in,titut de Droit romain de l'Uuiffnire de Pan• ~': Pans. [Rcpr. ~96<4.I
Gemet, Louis. J 968a. 'La citC futllH et le pll)'11 de1 n,on1 , 111 A ,.,11,..,..111,u th lie
Griu 11111iqu1, pp. 1-'9-52. PW. [Rq,r. from REG 46 (19-'-'), 29S-
278
Work., cited
HlffOllen, Karle. 1968. M11triarclual n,,i,i&,,111!, Mid ctrt11i11 trt111U 111 Homer's
f,..,au d111T111ctn1. Annaln Ae&dc111iac Scicntia.Nm Fennicac (Suonia.l~1cn
1iednlr.atemian toimituluiaJ, Svja-ff'I'. 8, nide-tom. 152. Hebinlu.
Hodcen, Marprcl TrM>uc. 19!6. TA, doctri11t of ni"'iual1; 11 r:l111ptn in tlat history
of 1cieY1tific method Ill tlit st14dy of m11n. London.
Homolle, Th. 1882. 'Comptc, des Hikope, du Temple d'Apollon dClien', BCH
6.1-167.
Homolle, Th. 1887-1919. An. 'Donarium' in Darembaa·Saglio. 2,l.!63-82.
Hornell, Janae,. 1947. 'The role of bird, in early navigation', A11tiquity 20.142-9.
Humphrey,, S.C. 1978. A11tlaropolorv llffd tlif' Grtf'b. London.
lmmawahr, Walther. 1885. Dt At11/11nt.1. UIIS •• Da-1111.
Janni, Pietn>. 196!1. 'l:Wrapa e awrl,p in Pinduo', StMdi Urbinati. n.1. '9.104-9.
Jaulin, Robert. 1967. La Mort IIP'II, L'oran fU ta lilt ou la p,nsif' d, la 171orr 1111
Trliad.Paria,
Jeanmaire, Henri. 191!. 'La ayp1ie lacCdCmonicnnc', REG 26.121-50.
Jeanmaire, Henri. 19!9. Couroi ,t Co11rltn Euai nir l'lducatio111partiat" It nir
ltJ ritt1 d'adolesctnct danl f'11nhqMitl Jif'fliniqMt. LWc-Parit. (Repr. New
York, 1978.J
Jcanrnaire, Henri. 195 I. DionyJos. Pari1. {Repr. Paril, 1970.J
Judm, Brian et al. 1970. 'Le Mythc d'Orphie au XIXc ct au XXc sieclc.' (Proceed·
inc• or 21st Con,rcss or the Association in1ernationale de, £1udu fran4iai1e1,
23-25July 1969.) CAIEF 22.157-246.
JWim, Charle1-Andrl. 1964. HUtoirt dt l'Algbit contf'171porainf', L,111 conquitt et
leJ dib11U dt /11 colorcU11tion (1827- 71). Patu. {Ed. 2, Paris, 1979.J
Kahil, Lilly G.- 1965. 'A11tour de l'Arto!mi, 1ttiq11c'. Anli,h Kunst 8.20-33.
k..ahil, Lilly G.· 1976. 'Al"to!m.U utiq11r', CRA.l 126-30.
Kah11, C.H. 196!. 'Plato', funrn.l oni.tion: thr motive of the Menr:11:enu1', CPh
58.220-H.
K.ilin, K.aspu. 1943. Jrcdi4nrr und Urvotl1tr n•ch /01. Fr. L11fitau (1681-1746).
FrcibUJJ, Switzerland.
K..am.bitm, 1. 1975. Minyade1 lr.a.i PToitidn Ioannina.
Kauel", Sicrid. 1959. Die Gc,b11rt drr Atlit"4 im 11ftpiuhUthtn Epos. Wiin:burg.
Kdlcr, Ono. 1909-IS. Die Anlilit Tinwt/1. 2 vols. Lcipr.i(. (Rrpr. Hildt1hrim,
196'.)
Kcrcnyi, Karl. 1952. 'II dio c.cchiatore.' Dionisio 5.131-42.
K.iocli.,A.1915. 'AthenaAithyia',ARW 18.127-33.
Kirchoff, Adolf. 1869. Di, Contpositiori d" Odysu,. Gt1amn1tlt1.Aufs11tu. Brrlin.
K.iz-k., Geoffrey S. 1962. Tht Sonp of Homtr. Cambrid(c.
Kirk, Geo£frry S. 1970. Mytli: itJ nttaning 11nd fimctiorc in ancient 11nd otlirr cul·
tarf'S. S.thcr- Classical Lecture, 40. Cambridie. Brrk.elry and Los '.'n1cle1.
K.intcn, Ernst, and Kn.ik.cr, Wilhelm. 1967. Gri,chc,nfandliu11dc,: ti,i Fi.lire,,""
lllassi.sclitn Stiitttn. 5 rd. Hridrlbug.
KlulC, Friedrich. 1910. Dt Pt..foni.s mnco. Dincrbltionrl philologic:w: Halentct
279
Wori.scitt:d
L.a.bube,Jule,. 1953. 'L'ife correlpOGdant .au uailicr d u ~ r1 la domieel
historiqur, du 1i~!rne ditcOWI d'hec', B~RB, 5 ICl'._.59.558-!M.
Labubc, Jule1. 1957. La Loi -.le de Tl&/'lfUSloc:11. BibliGthlq11e ~ b Faadti de
Philosophic rt Lrttra de l'Uniffn.itC de Litp, fuc. 10. PMW--Gemblo111.
La Coste-Mrucllib-c, P. Frotier de. 19.56. ,h, Ntuie tU Dd_plt,1. R,clt,rcbs ~,
qMelques mo11U1P1ent, .cMJq .. ,u et /ftr dlc:or 1culo~. l~FAR IS8. ,.,..
L&fitau, jo1tph-fr3.11~oi,. 1724, Mo""n ~J f"•HfCI AIPl"7'.'qu.011.1 COIPlp.r/CJ ft:I
IPID4'1'tJ de, prnniltn te'lflpl, (2 ¥Ole. UI .f ; later .f TO_b. m I~ .) •
Laffnnquc, Marie. 1964-. Po1ridonnu d'AP•"'''· UI• de ~"' n pmn_t. PuO-
liations de b, F.J.cuhC des Lettre• et Science• bl&ftl&!DCII ck Par11, Ser.
'Recherches', YOL 13. Paril.
Lana, And.-ew. 1885. CiutolPI ad Myth. 2 ed. London. (J ed. 1884; then 1193;
1898; 1904.)
t.an,. Andrew. 1887. Mylh, RitMal IPld R1lifion. 2 \'Ols. London. (2 ed. 1899).
Lane:, Mabel. 1969. "Homa and on.I teduuque·, H , ~ 38.159--48. _
Laum, Bnnhard. 1924. H~,s Giid. Ei,w laisttlflSc:1'1 Untnn,cAMnf ul,,r 4,,.
sdf'ltlffl Unfml"I d111 G1ld11. TUbiafen.
La VUle de Minnont, H. de. 1895. 'Le na'rirc NJO ct la ICXDCC aau1..1qu,
d'Apollonio1 de Rhoda', Revue intenu,tionale th l'e,u.-ipe,nenl 50.230-85.
Leach, Edmund R. 1966a. R,tAfflAifll Artrltropolor,. 2 ed. LSE MolKll"l)h,; m
Soda.I Anthropolo1Y 22. L-don.
Leach, Edmund R. I966b. 'Fruu and MlllinoW1ki: on the .. Fo11ndin, F.athcn" ·,
CMrrrnt A,d/iiropolor, 7.360-7. (Repr. from E11c:ou,.t,r, 25 May 1964,
H-!6.J
Le Goff, Ja.cqun, and Le Roy Lldurie, Emmanuel. 1971. 'Miluainc n.atemelk d
di£richeuse', Aulll1:1 ESC 26.58 7-622.
Le Goff, J., and Vidal-Naquet, P. 1979. 'Uvi-Stnuu en Brodlluuk', ln Cl-.th
Liui-Stnum (cdd. R. Bellour and C. Climmt), pp. 265-519. Paril.
Lcrna.y, E. 1976. 'HUltoift de l'antiqu.iti et dCCou-,crte du Nouvuu Mo!Xle cha.
dad auteun du XVllle aikle', Studies 011 Votta~ •nd t/iie EifAt,,"'"
C,:ntury 151-5, pp. 1313-28.
Lent, Luden. 1952. L,:, Louinu d, t'Ouast. 2 pub. BEFAR 176. PUU.
Uviquc, Pime, and Vidal-Naquct, Pierre. 1964. Clist1t;11, l'Atltb,W>I: ,uci "" lo
r,prb1:rtt•tio11 de l',sp•u et dll tf!fflPJ """' lo pnui, poh'tU,u, ,r,tq11.1 4, lo
fin d1t VI, siicle .i lo .,.o,t da Plofo11. Anaalu littirattfl de l'Uni¥cniti de
BeNn~on 65. Pa.ria.
Uvi-Stnuu, Claude. 1966a. Tli, s.,.., Mind. London aad New York. (ET or LG
Perui1:1•U11"1'I, Pari,, 1962.J
Uvi-Strau11, Cl.aude. I 966b. 'Le triancle culinauc', L'..Crc: 26.19-50.
LIM·Stn.uu, Claude. 1970. TAe R.w •nd tAe Coo••d. London a.ad New York. (ET
or L, Cru ef le c:Mil (Mytholoeiqua 1), Paril, 1964.J
Uvi-StnUN, Claude. 1971. L'Ho'""'' ""· MytholGpquee 4. Puia.
Uvi-Stn.uu, Claude. 1975. F,o,,. Hartry lo Asl&a,. London uid New YOl'k.. {ET or
Du Miel • ., r:e,sdtts Mytholosique• 2), PW, 1966.J
Uvi-S1rau11, Claude. 1977. 'Con.parative ttlipou or non·litcntc people.', m
S,,,.ctu,..J A111Ji,opolor, 2,pP. 60-7. Harmondsworth aad New Yoa.k (1976).
{ET ol A•thropolofi111tnictufWI, 2, PUU, 1975.J
Uvy-Bruh.l, Henri. 1947. N0'1,IJll~I truth,"'' le trl1 ..will• droit ro..-... Pub-
lic:ations de l'institut de Droit rottwn de l'Uniftnili de Paril J. PW.
Lindsay, J.ack. 1965. Tit• Cl-.1laiJ16 Roe.tr. A study of ,llrly G,,d. ,,lilion ""4 nJ.
,.,,., a11d tit, of'16i,u of dr•,no. London.
Lloyd, Geoffrey E.R. 1966. l'ol1Jrity •"4 A-1011: huo fypes of a,p.,._t•i- ffl
rorly Gr111• 1/iioufht. Camb~.
Uoyd, Geoffrey E.ll. 1979. M-,..C. RHJon •rtd E,q,ff'WJUa. S""-s i11 ,,v o,;,in
••" Deri1lo/1fflffll of Grw~la Sc~a. Cambridp.
280
Works cited
Uoyd·Jo11e1, Hu,tl. 197.!. 'Modem i.atapntation1 of Pindar: the Second Pythi11n
and Snc11th Neman Odct',JHS 93.108-!7.
LonuA. Nicole. 1975. 'HIH ct nd'rri:11. Dituz vcnions de la mort du combattant
athbuffl.',A"rinat Socidy 6.1-51.
Lonwi:, Nicole. 1977. 'La belle mort lpVtiate', Ktt"'o 2.105-20.
Lonu:, Nicole. 1978. 'Momir dnu.t Troie, tomber pou.r AthCne1. De la r(oi« du
h~o• a l'idife de la citl!', lftfo,..,,,atio" m, /,r 1cinact1 1ocialt1 17.801-
17.
Lon.us, Nicole. 1980a. L'iMnatio" d"Athi"u HUto" dt l'r>raiso"fa"'~b,t CUfflsUI
'ciU clauiqvt'. Pari,.
Lonux, Nicole. 1910b. 'L'Acropole comique',A11cW"t Socl'tty I I (forthcomina).
Lord, Albert B. 1960. Tht Si"f" of Taln. Hartud Studic1 in Compan.tivc Litcn·
tw'c, no. 24. Cambridcc, Mui., and London.
Lotze, Oetlcff. 1959. ~ 0..tt,tltpwv mi Swl'-111: Stvdit11 .rv, Ruhs1ttlluit1
v,ifrevr Larulb6110lli-"frit i" G,Ucht..J.rul biJ .tV"' 4 //tdt. uor ChriJt.
Dcuuchc Audcmic der Wincntchaftcn zu Berlin, Schriftcn dcr Sclr.tion fiir
AlterturnJW.inen,chaft 17. Berllll.
Lovejoy, Arthur 0. and Bou, Gewrc. 1955. A doc1n11t1stary hi.story of P,i,,.itivum.
a,sd Rdattd ldtos, I: Pri"'itir,is"' •IMI rtlattd idtos
[llcpr. New Yorlr., 1965.)
in
Antiquify. Baltimore.
Mav.u~~s~:~.· l970. Tia, Gi/1: forms and fu~tio111 of uc~11fll' i~ ar,~aic 1~cUlti~1.
i!J,~!. ~~. ~~~5o~~)E~2';j, 1;/oi"~6.f:~r.:~e! "r:1a~~.n;::i:;;;~
ttt1P1eh.ropo'4P (Paris, 1950, ed. 4, 1968), 145-270.J London.
281
War.ts cit~d
Muwell-Stllart, P.G. 1970. 'Raam"M on the black coatJ of the Epbebci&', l'CPU
0! s;::iq~::;,:,r ~ Af,~~~--
Pfist:.0 ; : , : ~ ~0 : ; ~ ; : 3
1
(2 parts.) RGVV 5.
~,~~!.ffi:4;~~-~G1!.~tica
piAfti~ 0 pattrp, 7. Gruca mioon'. R""1i,o"ti dtt•
/dittdo Lo,,.6.-do di Sd4flH e LettnT, Cl-t di LtllrYT. Ser. W, I.I.
SZ9-70.
Picket, Hf:N'i Wi.lly. 1969. 'Collet"'"' /•U<11Uffl N""tsiorv'ffl: a nou:·on uciena
youth orpnisation', M'tltfflOS,U, IC'I'. 4, 22.28)-98.
PJey, Jakob. 1911. De ,-,uu j.,. 4"1"f110111"' rilibiu ~ · RGVV ~I, 2_- ~~
Polialr.OY, Uon. 1974. T,., Ary•" ffl}'rll: • ,.u,ory of r,u:ut '""' MhOflalUt ~ '"
E•rop,. Colun,bu Centre Serie1. London. (ET o( Lt Myth -,,-. hrll.
1972.)
Popp, Huald. 19S9. D~ Ei'tlWiriunt "°"llon:tkla"9, Opfff'ft "'"" F•sk" n/ di#
X,Wlfwltrv"I dn Grirc,\en iffl 5. nd 4. J•larAultderl "°"
CWt. Diu.
Erlancm. Neu1tadt an der AiKh.
hopp. Vladimir. 1968. TA, Morpholoc, of 111, Fol/H.Je. (Truaa. L. Scott,'"· ed.
by Loui• WlfDff,) Publication, or the American Folldon Society, 81,lio-
~hical and SpeciaJ Serie,, vol. 9. Amtin -d London. (ET or M..,,,\olo,W
sltarl,.)
Pu,lie-c.untdli, GioYU:1ni. 1970. ''O).~ iu.p6(', l'P 25.248-9.
Pu,ljne--Cun.tdli, GioYUtni. 1971. 'Fraintendimenh: ed erTOff: 1 propo1lto di
Olympit» K.airot c de Scpokro di S1n Pietro', PP 26.:!147-,,.
Radamacher, Ludwif. 1958. Myrllos •M s-,,
bei dtfl G""ecAt'II. 81dca-bei-Wial/
Ldfn.il·
R.ldlte, Gerhard. 19:!16. DW BedndV'llt ~ wei,s,,. und dn ,cAw•ru'tl Fn, ;,.
X•lt ,.,.d Br-ncl• <Ur- Gri,den "'"" R01ntm. Dilt., Berlin.
Ra.mate, Edwin S. (ed.) 1978 . ..4d4i'tltir, /act or- fi.rtio'111 Bloominflon, lndiam, ind
London.
Rawson. Elizabeth. 1969. Tiie s,,..,.,.n Trwditio1t i1t £ur-op,- tliollfAI. Odard.
Rayet, OliYic:r, 1nd CoUipon, Mu. 1888. Histoff"e de t. cb•fflU/u, c,ycqw. Pari,.
Rehm, Alben. 1919. An. 'lunopo1', RE, cobi. 1881-S.
Rdnach, A.·J. 1910. 'hano, et l'illDt1ttio 1cuti: itude "'' J'hoplolatric primltin en
GrCcc • .!I', RHR 61.197-237.
Reinrnuth, Otcu W. 1971. TA, EpAebic lrucriptu,,u of tA.t Joun,\ ce1ttvry BC.
Mnemorync Supplements 14. Leiden.
Reilch, Emil. 190S. Art. 'Drdfuu.' RE, cohi. 1669-96.
Rc.elr., Cul. 1960. l,wU He'tlry /rl0Pp1t, Afflerica'tl ulloW. Chiap.
Richter, WiD. 1968. Die La'tltlwirtscli•ft iffl .lioff1trirdn1 Uitalrn-. Mil e!M:m
Beitnc VOD Wo1r,ane: Scbieriric- Archaeolosia bomerica Bd. 2. GottiaFD.
Ridder, Andre Hcari P. de. 1912. 'L'Athbia. rnilanchotique, I', aCH 56.375--8.
RMud, Albert. 192S. Ti,,,/t. CJ'9tm. Platon: CoUcc:tion de• Uahocnltb de Fl'UIC'I:
(Blldc). 90), I 0. Tr1111l1tioa and notes. Paru.
Robert, Carl. 1909. 'Die l&IODalC in der Hypsip-,le des E.uripida', Hn,,,u ff.
376--402.
Robert, Cati. 1915. Oidipus. Ge,clai.clit, e1.,. .., po,tuclt..- Swlfs;,,,. f"'Vcliuli••
Alt""'"''"· 2 vol.. Bntin.
Robat, Cut. 1920-26. ~ tri1eliiscli, H,ld,rua,,. S voll. (Conttitutiat"Part 2 or
Ludw:if Preller'1 Gri,dlUdt M-,tl&olofU) Bfflill.
284
Worbcitnl
Roba1, Louil. 19SB. lit.de, lfnlrapl&iq•111 et pllilolofiqtm. Bibllothftlue cle l'lcolc
ck• Ha11lC1 !t11cle1: Scieaca hiltorique, et philolotiqua, fuc:. 272. Paril.
Robert, LolUI. 1940. ' ~ , k . ' Athenian Sa.din pre1ented to William S.
Fffl"IO'l,PP· 509-19. Hanan:!. Studia in Clue. PhilolOfY I. Cambridp, MUI.
Robert, LoWI. 1955. Hellt1flic1. Recueil d'lpifr-plde, de ,.,.,,.irmatiqH et
d'.,.tif•ilis fNCfllt!I 10. Pui1.
Rohen, Louil. 1960. 'l."herchn ipip'aphique.', REA 62.271-S&t.
Robert, Louil. 1962. Ville, d'Asie ,...-,..,.,.,_. l1Mde1 de po,-,Aie ""'"· 2 ed. Paria.
Robert, Jeanne and Loui1. 1966. 'Bulleti.a epicnphique', RBG 79.SSS-449.
Robert, Jeanne and LoWI. 1967. 'Blllletin lpicraphique', REG B0.·t.S.S-57S.
Robe-1,Jeanne and.LoWI. 197S. 'BuDetin Cpipaphique',REG 16.48-211.
R.obn1, Jeanne ud Louil. 1976. 'Bulletin lpipaphique', REG B9.4H-595.
R.obcrtlon, D.M. 1951, 'Bouzyp1 and the fnt ploup on a kn.ter by the painter of
tbe Naple1 Hephauto1', AJA 55.152-60.
lloder,Giln.ther. 1919. An. 'Kanobu1' (2). RE, cob. 1870-3.
llolley, Claude. 1974. 'Fouillea l Eretrie. Auheolosie, hiltoirc et n:Lipon' (rniew
article). RA, n.,. S07-ll.
RoK, Herbert J. 1951. .Cfldr,u, Laf11: Air piMe ifl a'Atllropolor,. Edinbuqh.
Rote, Haber-t J. 1961. A Handl,ooll of Crull LiteratMrw, from Homn to tlu ap of
LKcia11. London and New Yorlr.. (R.epr. or 4 ed. U50, with conec:tio111.
I ed. 1954.)
Rotellin.i, Michlle, and Said, Suzanne. 1978. 'Usa,e de remma et autrc1 nomoi
cbez les "sauvqe." d'HCl"OdolC: ellli de lectun: 1tru.cturale', ASNP, KT. S,
B.3.949-1005.
R.oume, WJI.D. 1902. Crwd uotiH offerinp. An eury on the history of Grwd
nlifio,..Cambrida:e.
llouuel, Pitrn", 1921. R.niew or Alice Jkenot, R,cAnde, rur l'ipM6W11ttiq1i, ct
'" ,_.nrulkr .rur Ill dat, de l'iiutihitio11 (l'ffll, J920). REG !4.459-40.
Ro1111el, Pierre, 1941. 'La chlanayde1 noire, dn l!phtbes atbCniem', REA 4!.
16S-5.
ROUlld, Piene. 1951. 'Euai IW" le principc d'anciennete dam le monde helUniquc
du St llilcle avllQt J ..C. a l'q)Oque romaine', Mbnoint dt l'Ac.di"'W de,
liuniplio,u ttl Bril111-Lcttr1114S,2.12!-221. (Tnie date, 1941.]
Rom:, Rcni. 1949. Le Probli'"'e dtt Ar,ou11t,1. Rerllnclitt ni, I,,
a,p,rt,
rwlifi,Mx dt la 1'PJ1dt1. Pub.
R.iulbecll., Olaf (Rud.bell., Olf). 1619-98. Atlartd ,Un Ma11h,im, ded•n. J11p~tz
aflo,n,ic, de {Omii,,.,t, b-,snlip orh liMnfdif, Sltcliter .. ·.; (LD Lat1?)
Atla11tira ,;.,, M1111Ai•i111, v,... /-,Aldi posterort1"' r,d,r ar patna · · · (LaUD
::=:1~J~.6·1';;~~"t:::O':'j.;:=!':;,
lHl by Andreu No,copcmilJ. S vols. in 4. Uppale.
285
Wor4s cited
Schacherracyr, Friedrich [FritaJ. 1950. Posridofl 11,ad ,w • ...,,.,..,., fk, Gnttlt-
=:·~.i.'~::,~i,. ..":~~!;~~~=;~:
Ud1,n CiiH"'1,.11brru. Bcm.. •
Schacrer, Rau!. 1948. Lo f""'Aofl pl.toflicilt1ra,. NNCbitel.
Sub,,,'!,~!~~~!: D, Mffc•rioc,"'"'9•• M
dftl l)fflll.-C-.
llrWlfl pnn,.""'-
Snodpul, Antony M. 1977. ArcWolon o,ad tll• ,.;,,. of th
lceturc.Cambrid,e-.
c,.,.,., ,t.t,.
1...,..i
-
So&i, G. 19,9. II 111odo di p,oduzio,.. IIIMI.C•. Ste,_ Iii 11:u co,......,....
,,..,..u,•.
Torino.
286
Works cited
Sot.oloWU.i, Frandau:k. 1962. Lois sor:,lt1 dtr cith ,ncqius; Supp~"''"' ...
!cole fraru;-.1.te d' Athffla. Tranull. et mlmoiru de. a.nciens membret
Ctn.ncen de l'lcole et de diver, aavanta, fuc. 11. PW.
Sokolow1k.i, Frvidaiek. 1969. Lois ,ocri,, de, citls ,..,cqu.ei. tcole fran9',iff:
d'Athenea. Travaull. et mCrnoire1 de1 ancien1 membru ltrani:en de l'tcole et
de diver, uvanu, fuc. 18. PW.
Solmltll, Friedrich (ed.). 1970. H,:iiodi ThtOfOftia. Optrtl ttDit1, Sc11.t11.m (with
fra(n:lmt Select&). OJI.ford.
SMlffinou·Inwood, Chriltia.o.e. 197la. Review of Anselo Brelkh, 1969. }HS 91.
172--7.
Sourrinou{-lnwood), Chriltiane. 197lb. 'AriJtophane1, Lyriltrola, 641-647', CQ
n.1.2I.H9-42.
Sourrinou-lnwood, Chriltia.ae. 1974. 'The votum of 477/6 BC a.ad the foundation
lqcnd of Locri Epinphyrii', CQ n.s. 24.186-98.
Spanuth.JiirJen. 195'. Diu ttttriitstltt Atl11tttis. 2 ed. Stuttgart.
Sperba, Dan. 1968. L, Strt.ictw,olismt tft 11n,hropolop, in Qu'tsl·ct qu.t It
str\lcluNZli:imt1, td. Fra.ru;oit Wa.hl, pp. 167-258 (and 1tpanrtly). Pari1.
Stanford, William B. 1965. Tht Uly11t:i thtmt. A study in tht lldoptabilily oft
lnlaih'o,u,l hero. 2 ed. O:dord. (I td. 1954.)
Steier, Aucwit. 1952. An. 'MOwe.' RE, cob. 2412-18.
Sten,tl, Pa.ul 1905. ' ; \ ~ KA.l)f"Oft'wM("',ARW 8.205-13.
Sttqtl. Paul. 1920. Dit friahischtn Kull11.stlttrti'1ntr. !I ed. (MU.lier's Handbuch
der klanischtn Altenun:1.1wiueruc:haft 5,5.) MWlchea.
Strohm, Ha.ru. 1944. Tycht. Zu., Schiclt.sllist11.ffiusu11f bti Pindilr 11.l'td dit
frl.hpi,chi:iclttn Dichtrm. St111tprt.
Taillardat, J. 1968. 'La triCl't i.thcinienac ct la 111errt 1uc mer', in Vtrnanl, J.·P.,
1968,pp.183-205.
Tannery, Paul. 1925. 'Sue Oiodort d'Asptnde [1896J', in Mbnofr•s 1citntifUf11t1
(edited by J.L. Heiberg and H.-G. Zeuthen): Philo10phit ancienne, pp. 201-
10. Pacil-Touloutt.
Taylor, A.E. 1928. A commtntllry on Pt.to'1 Timuu:i. Oltford.
Thompson, D'Arcy WtntwO!'lh. 1956. A Glossa,-., of Gred Birth. 2 ed. Oltford.
(I ed. 1895.) (Repr. Hildesheim, 1966.J .
Thompwn, D'Arcy Wentworth. 1938. 'Wu ist aiBur.a:?', Sudhoffs Ardiv far
Gnehkhtt dt1 Mcdiiitt 11.nd de, Ntt11."'1i:istnsth11fttn !10.535-9.
ThomP'On, Homtf A., and Wycherley, Richard E. I 972. ThtA10~ of .Athens; tht
history, 1hapt and ustJ of tn tnt:itnt city ,c_ntcr. Arn~can School or
Qus.ical S1udie1 at Athcn1: Athenian A,on. 14. Princeton, N.J. . ..
Thorn 90 n, George D. 1941. Aesch-,111.1 ond Ath•,u· .A s111.dy i11 thtsocual ongs11sof
Vian, Franci1. 1968. 'La fonction pcrriac dam I.I mytbolOfic pccquc', in J ..P.
Vcnwi.t, 1968, 55--68.
Vidal·Naq11et, Pierre. 1964. Foreword to IC.A. Wittlopl, L, D,,poti,rn, tnffllul
( French translation of Wittfo,cl, Ori.en.ta/ Dl'l'potint: • eoffl,.,..tiw ,11.t1y of
tol#I pow,,, New Haven, 19.57.) Parit.
Vidal-Naquet, Pierre. 196.5. 'f..c:onomic ct IOcieti clan, la Grice ancicnnc: l'oeuwc
& Mo,a I. Finley'. Arcllivn Europi1,.,w1 M Socio/olfl' 6, 111 --48.
Vidal·N~uc:t, Pierre. 1968. 'La tradition de l'boplite athftun', inJ.·P. Vunant,
1968, 161--81.
Vidal-Naq11et, PierTc. 1972. 'Le PliiJoctiu de Sophock Cl l'q)hlbie', in J.·P.
Vcmant 11.nd P. Vidal-Na.quct, 1972. 161-84. PillU. [Repr. with altentiou
froniA""ol" ESC 26 (1971), 623- 38.)
Vidal-N1qucc, Pierri:. 1975~. 'Lei nclavi:t vecque, lw~t·ill une clauc1' in Or,dn
111 CWll's (edited D. Roche}, pp. 29·--'6. The Ha111, -Paris. [Ri:priatcd hom.
RtruonFr,,,.,, 6 (1968), 103--12.I
288
Wor~citf!d
VidaJ..NaqUC"t, PiGTe. 197Sb. 'R.C8n:iont NI' J'historiogn.pbie srecque de
l'tadaQfe', in Act,, du CoUoqu,: d, Bit.Jd"fO" svr l',.1c:""1,,1, (1971), pp.
25-42. Baan1;on-hru.
Vidal·Naqu.ct, Piene, 1975L 'Bh", homme1 ct dicwt chi:% In Crea', in Hommit1
,.....
et bilit1: "'"~tinu .J1o1r le rac:iim, (ed. Uon Polia.lr.ov), pp. 129-42.
Vistchc:r, Funand de. 1951. 'Du.cue dona iube: tne"ide 5, 385', inllMdes d, droit
ro"'oi", pp. 555-7. Pari.J. (R.epr. from RBPH 1 (1928), 579-85.J
Vodlr.c, AJ. 1966. 'Un point de vuc nouveau 1ur Posidoniu1' (review of Laffranque,
1964). ASSPli 26.281-9.
Waclumuth, Enut W.G. 1846. Hdle..Uclie Alterhuns..\:und, aus de"' Ge,ic:htspudt
dit1 St.atit1. 2 ed., 2 vob. Halle. (l ed. 2 vol,., Halle, 1826-50.)
Wach1muth, D. 1967. n4nrlµO( b ~w1,1: U"tnsvcli,mf ru den anli..\:en Sabtd·
lulrutlunf bt1" S,n,U,n. Diu., Berlin.
Wachtd, Nathan. 1971. 'Penate u.u.vqe ct ac:cultun.tion: l'erpace et le -temps chet
Felipe Guaman Poma de Ayala et l'lne1 Garcil&Jo de la Vep'. Ann8'es ESC
26.793-840.
WalbanlL, Franlr. W. 195 7- 79. A HiltorictJJ Co"'"''"&al")' OPI Polybiiu. 5 vob. Oz ford.
:~:~~e;;:.;i~~~- ~·;~~~~=~t~:::~:~~::r:~
8ARB,1b. S, Il.205-39.
chrttiens du lie si(ele',
289
Worbcilffl
Wilamowitz..MocUcndorff, lJlric:b ""· 1955. Dff' Gln6,rlUPH.._,,.. 2 ..ta. 2 ed.
Bald. (1 ed.1931-2;repr.o..mdt, IH9.J
Wilhdm, Adolf. 1911. 'Die Lobudle Midcbcniuc:lldft', JOA.I 14.113-256.
Wilkiftlon, Liond Paaick. 1969. n.Gnrfia o/ Viop. A ailic.J MfN7,
Will, ;;:~·955. Kori11tllidA. R,rcl,,nlm ,.r l'IIUtoin •• la Ol1iliMtitM IU
Cori11III• ,1., twifirw• ..._. pwr.1 1111diqw1. Paril.
Wilktu, Ronald F. I US. AFVtoowtk Soci,ty i11 A..cN'llr CNi.. Loadotl.
WiDctt1, Ronald F. 1959. "Tiie Knilc iDtarcp11111 at Arpl',H'""a 17.415-HI.
Willetu, llonald F. 1962.CH,..11 C..111•,ul F,r1tiNb. London.
Wlllnu, Roaald F. 1967. TML.•COU0/Gorl711. K.admOI s....,a-a., l. llerlla.
Wolna, Wanda. 1962. L• topor,IIW ffl"tw"- dir Co••• IIWlicopMUU1:
llliolofW •' KWJ&e, n Vlir riidir. Bibliotb~ue byzantine, !tllda 3. Puit.
Wuilkl&micr, Pian. 1939. T.rir111ir, d,- m,j,ws O la co119•ilir ,.......,. Paria.
Yalman. Nu. 1967. nc ll.a•: the Cooked:: N•t1m: Culture. ~•dou on
IA C,w: ,r I• ct1it', in TM S1n.ctw,wl Sfluly of MyUI _,, Toi.fllU111 (ed. £.A.
Leacb), pp. 71-19. ASA Monosnpta. 5. London.
Yalouria, Nikolao9. 1950. 'Athena at. Henin d• Pfcrde'. MIISnlfll ffdNlinu11 7.
19-101.
Zdtlla, Froma I. 1978. 7bc dynamicl of ftUIOf)'lly: myth ud mydl-makilrc iD die
On1kY',AnoM11N 11,1-2.lff-19.
Zichen, Ludq. 1959. Art. 'Opfa"'. R£, coll. 579-'27.
Zuidcml., ll,dner T. 1971. £Ulflolopa e1IOfN: CU,o ,,.,,,.,,..,..M'irr,/Hro-.
(with • preface by N. Wacbtel), TOftllD. (Italian 1nD11atian by H. Mau&i
:n::=:t.:= ~~:{tlU.
and M.V. MalYUlO of Zuidem•'• TM CetN fY6MII of C,,.co: Tlw ~
latenlaeioul Arcbifta of Etuotnl*Y
290
Index
'"
adolncmcc: andeph,-beld, 147-52,
156-60, 174-8; and lirypteUI,
llid61, 100, 121, 242 n. 20
Aiem(kingofColchis), l.54, 1.57, 1.59,
140
J5S-S, 18l-4;ofSpananiirl,s, Aifipan, 10
184-S;of Athenian girl.1, 178-80; in .4:iso, 231 D. 2 (in Aleman)
Crete, 1.57-8, 177; marked in funer- Aju, 1on ofOileu1, 25-6
uy pncticc, 17'-4; and hunting, Alcibiades, 178 (oppose, Niciu)
160-2;Tclcmachus, 90; the Alcinou1, .54, 91-4; palace or, 89, 204;
HUU.anaw in Virpnia, 17l;uc abo uperiecl oiJtos,95-4
a,~clauct; childhood; masquende; Alcmacon, 121 (murdrn mother)
ritcsofpusqc Aleman: on .4:iso and Poro,, 251 n. 2;
Adoni.a, 101-2 on T-yclit, 22
AclU, 86, U6-7 Alexander the Great, 125-6 (ucrifice
Aeolus (Muter of Wind1), 40, 246 n. 24; to sea)
and incest, 87, 92-S Amalthea, 136-7
Anchylus: Ata,,.emnon, 120-1, 190; Amazons, 190 (lopsy-tu.rvy world)
Chocphoroi, 190-1 ;£11mer1irkt, 140; ambi(\lily: of the human condition, 50,
on Typhon, 9; navigation, 24;incclt, 53,55,65-S;of Promethean!irc,49,
198;Pu-thenopacus, 161 n. 40;ai1- 59, 75; of Pandor:a, 51, 55, 81; of
nificancc of f1tt (Prom,-flltwt), 54, 74 Elpi1 (Hope), 55-6; of tris, 68-9; of
111•/lrUI: u prcdous object, 114rf, 119, nou.r, 78; of objtcu, 120-3, 138-9,
125, 126, 128, ISO, 141-2 142; of .A:itluu:.:i, 17-18; of bees, 98;
Apvc (mother of Pcnthc111), 224 oCnumpht, 102-3; of 11atu1 of
qe-d&nc:1, 175, 178-84, 255 n. 5;city Giantl, U;of T-yclit andKotros, 2Iff;
cancel, opposition betwttn, 178; stt of Golden Age with 1odt, 86;of
•bo adolescence; hoplite cannibalism in Diony1i..:- euh, 225;
ace or Cronut,; qe or gold, stt Golden of ,:phebe, 147rf, 149 -50 (double);
.....
.plll,inCn:tt, ISS, 157, 177, 18.5
of Juon, 149; of Scheria, 91-2
ambrollia, 14, IS, 72, cf. 54
-,,,,1. in Sparta. 181, 182rr Amphian.us, 121-2
11fon, 44, IS7-8, l84;stt -'so Efll/tris Amphitrite, 122, 1!10
qon., 68, 84, 94, 1.52- 3; abtcnt in Andropompo1, 152
prot<>Athcru (Plato), 207; at Sparta, An&opha,oi, 220, 247 n. 39
24--5;inPhacaci.1., 34 Anesidor:a, 5.5, 245 n. 8
agricu.ltun:: defines tht human con- animal akin: wearing of (ahe,:p,kin), 136;
dition, 49, 54, 71-4, 78-9, 80-.5, (Jeopard-1ltin), 149;(1,:alP.in), 252
89-91; in prot<>Atheru (Plato), n. 11; {1oaultin (aegis)), 1.56; ,olden
206-7; iDvmted by C«ropm and Reece, I3Hf;hideofJ&Crificial
Bou~.12; r:llcluded from world animaJ, 156-7;bu.11'1hideuba,,
or Ody.ev.1'11torin, 84. 86- 7; and
" 291
Index
an.im\11, cWlificllt l.On of: 11itA11W, 193-4: onA,sot., 192;onAthC01,
17--1 8 ; bcc1, 9Sff; wild--domcstic 13S, 197;on~bN, 147, 176-7,
hiqvcht, 75-4; 87-11, 218;1f'it 180; on canaib.l tribe,, 220: on
•llo mtn in rtlation to llll.imab; walth, IIS;c,t1fta'riptio11, 25:oa
aninaab in fft1""'1, 218 - 19:on bftt..
1ac~ficial &nlffl.als
Ank.aio.. (,on of P01cidon), .52: (hclm,- 98; on the coincidmcc of bipol&r
man), '8fr ICU, I 7S, 189; on the Pyth..orun
&nthr!)polorv : l'Ulc of comparat.in- , in 111.1toid ... l 7S, 269 n. 42
rdllt,ion toiniti.ation, 147, lSS, 172, annour: 'omuncntal', 120; dt"rica Oil.,
1119 :. Fonccm with Gttccc in oin~ 141-2:r•it llbo p,,1110,; hoplite
tctnth centwy.161, 21S;c:ambridft: aromatict: in ..aifa,cc, U, 57, 61,
School, 171:in early twentieth cm- 217-11, 22!;~1CCOr, lflrdpof
tury:, l68.-9; ,1n1.ctu.nali.t, l69-70: AphTodhe, 24S o. 15; bated by bffl.
m'l,l r include hiltory, 1U: Hit .Uo 98- 9
L"ivi~ tru~; myth, csplanation of: Arffphoria. 179
J\-f'lctunlilm Artcmil: attempted npe or, lOS, cf.
Antilo<hUs 1 2§ 161; hwnan .-crif1ec to, 245 n. 14;
.AntinoW-~ 99 auod.11cd wilh bcv, 161, 17t-10:
11p111 .12 o. U, 44, 1Sl, IS2 - 5, 16t)....2, at Bn1U"OJ1, J79;ortphawi, 164;
171 , 182 ,ru -'sodcception H1pmo11•, 256 •· ,S; of Mouaycbia,
,.tp1110111W, ! ) Oft', 156, 175; ctymolo,v 179: O,.tAi.., 115-4, 262 n. 51
or. 1st At.lant.. 161-2 , 241 n. 7
Aphrodit 1r7, JO • \{tred. fotAul.anta. Athena. 5, 16-42 ,....n,.., 44, 19, 90,
16 1; golden a!Spll: \ of, 161:.rdpof, 249 n. 66, ISi, 179, 202;k,r,epa kcy1
245 n. l5 oruorchouc, 140;acp.lof, 1!71
Apo llo, 11 Ll9 lJ51 19 lffoW Q/, tttulll'C of, 144; patroo or Athena.
159-40; e(()iSln:.tic powff of (tripod), 191. 20,-1,rnt sacrif'i« to. at
145; A.i(/dc1~ 59_.f.0; Hybw60~01, R.hodu. 24, n. 26;..f,..101<,..., 2S6
245 n. 4~ a. 11 ;A.rcAitplU, 178 n. 28; ••"'-·
p ONI , 5, 2) 2,6 n. 4l;H;pp;., 29;Hori9, 27-8;
arch ai1m, 8 ~ ~Q. 95-4, 142, lS5, of Dion, 195-4;1C.dntAda, 24ff;
U9 - 60, 171 IC.A-'nutis, 29, Ul , 142;L•"'n .. ,
A m , 252 \,5 (U'111111p in jv) 21';/.ffldMI, 57-8:Poliu , 179;
Pol~11,d.01, 256 n. 4;,.,.olftMAoz,
'Yi" 2 ,~i ~~~:·
rcl t (wifo; of Akinow), 95, 204
9a.u~
Ario• (CaJl?CUter}, 52, 59
n6 n. 57. san.
2u;su,..,, U6, 200,so1111.:.,, 57
Athena: bo\Uldaria of, 148-9, UOfl;
orifin of democracy at (,myth),
'101 , 120ff, 131, 162, 191-2, 198-9:. 191-9;8oUokk)n, ISS;O.C-ho-
\rgolid, COUI of, 2S5 n. H phoriaat, l56-7;~d pl"Phtc
· ., ~11,: myth of, u told by VirJil, at, 154;Jlcnm.eUtoa, 17S;kiap
'JU -7; attempted rllpC of Eurydice, (Aqcu,) 1!17, 2S6 a. 16, (Cea,,pt)
•19 , 103 ; v 'mutff of honey', 99; 12, 191-9, 267 a. 19, (Codru.) lSl,
mtdiator between Orion ud Orphcw. (Ercc:bthcw) 210, (Mdanthot) lSI,
105',H.1.01 (P1i1dion) 16, (Thymoita) I.S0 ~-1,
~f!SI OO'JICY,. 90, 115-14, I IS, Ul, 146. (Hit 111..a Th~);war (with
RocotiaN), 110, (D'l'fl SJccua), U,2,
Ari!:o~e!!!; f~~a';;, 2:r Cu'~u), 1\2..., (withP"*),2M, ............. ol
ft.riltomtnn, sltidd or, 120, 130 city i• clu*al period, .... 110,
Aritton K\11 (<o f Pti:11.mon), 189 ltl-9; adoJHCGIC'C ta, ]16-1~
,Arutoph&nt1~ ltxplained' by, Carii.b1"1c!,t m.riale ia, 197rt;U¥ery in, 19i:
S-chooJ, 171 ; o rt"'Womcn 11 Athc;:n,. -..d.nuiom al(ecldl,y ,......._,
178 80 1 J98f/;o rl'ilavn, 199- 2.00 ; 177-l;Plato',vkw of, 2'06··9,
11teofrcvcual , J 18 , 199 209:110.ry 21S--14;oppolltdtaSs-n,., 176-11,
-o!Mcl~i9 n,} 6t;1' I 191, IK-200; de:bue oa tidy ia
Anu otlt : on Spart._ 111-9; on Locru, 4U, • .c.. 111
292
Index
athktic1: illtdlipncc in, 2fff; for pi. Boeotia, 67, 142, 150
andboy,atSparta, lBf:ueflUo
bonn: in aacril"i.cc, 14--15, 57, 60-1,
public p,ne1;.running
86;opp-d to red meat, HI n. 12;
Atlantis: modem tcholanhip, 20!£f; do not rot, 60-1; in funeral
ancient view. of, 202f; and Homer, ceremony, 76-7;of Pdop1, ll8
204:az,d the Ea,t, 204-5;uima,c lotphoru,, 22, 59. cf. 29
of the ""1eiron, 209ff: ln relation to BoMltolrion (at Athen1), IS5
Athm1 of hUtory, 212ff; origin of bounduy, 2, 2ll;neptionof, 17, 105,
name, 267 n. 16
224;11'1' al.so clUW1eation; mediation
A.mu,, 132-S, 1S5, 1!9 Bou.zY1t1,82
autochthony, of the earliest lnhabitant1 bow, q a weapon, 175, 251 n. 37
of Atlantis, 268 n. S8 Brauron, 178-80
bread: eating, define, man, 71-8, 82;
Babylon, Herod.otu1'1 dc,cription, 205 'eaten or, 92, 241 n. 7, 245 n. 8,
B.-:,hoftn,JJ., 166-7, 190 cf. 72; eaten in Circe', houac, 87; not
i».nquct, 12, 54,87, 117 eaten by Lotw·Eaten, 85; claaifi·
barbarism: u .11 catq:ory of comparilon, cation of flour, 78 n. !4;ttt alto
16!-8, 175; of Cyclopes, 92; bar· agriculture
barian location for 'City of Slaves', Briattiu, 7, 14, 67
l89;forcanniba.l ,ocictie1, 219:ru bri<De: of Btl!C'rophon, 29, 131-2, 142,
IIUou~ 145;offeredbyCirnon, 131
Buan.i (ln Thr¥e), 225
ba,tard, 11, 195 Cadm1&11, ll, 122
bcan, ln Pythqorun theory, 222-S Calypao, 85, 88-9
bur: suckled At.alant&, 161; u rinw Cunbysc1, 221
mtut ,t Brauron, 179-81 caniculu period (Doe day1), 51, 96, 136
beard: faltt, 155, 156-7, 200;jult cannibal.um, 81-2, 86-7, 92, 198,
powll\1 (Diony1w), 152:yoUI\( men 215-28;ttt also Golden Age
without, 157;ruaho hair Canopu1 (Canobw), 57-8
bta.uty: of Pandon. (.talon Aa.ton), U, Cameg (Sparta), 157-8
51, 59; object of, 137 ca,pentry, !Irr, 41-2
bee: metamorphosis into,!; death of, Carthqe, sacrifice at, 245 n. 14
911;claailication of (fipre ro, chute cave: n..il.c of a god to, 7; Zcwi prilonC'r
wife a.ad n111n/llu'), 96ff; born from in, IO; of Typhon, 12: of Ny111ph1,
dccompolin1 ox, 96- 7; a, imq:e of 90; of GY1e1, 124-5; Trophoniw'1
plenty, 81; opposed to homet or-.cle,l!l
(fJCUl'C for male), 46; a.ad Poly· Cecrop1, 82, 198-9, 267 n. 19:u
teehnos. 216 'culture hero', 199
Bee-woman (Mdina). 1oorr, 216, 219 Cent.1111.r: Chiron, 5-6: tric1 to rape
BdlC'rophon (and m~ bridle), 29-SO, Atalanta,161
Ul, 157, 142, 145 Ceo,, 99
bU11, 47, 49, 51, 60, 73, 77, 81 ;see also chariot,!, 10, 269 n. 45; racin1, 26-7,
apicv.ltuu 29-30; buildin1, !Orf; dc1truetion
biosor,liilr.os, 104, 22! of, I27;ofP01eidon (Plato), 21'
bitch...oul (of Pandon.), 51-2, 55 chattel ,lave, 194; in Crete, 264 n. SI;
blaclr.: cli.Ml"'Y', 15!, 156, 174;oppo,cd '1trict' form of slavery, 189;clcarly
to whhc,41, 87, 150-1; Diony1u,, defined in 'developed' 1ta1e, 187,
151- 2, US;hunt (with net), 159-60; 200: doc1 not make political
ilMOciatcdwithguik,151,153,162, demanda, 187; emancipated if u1cd
177;with fronlieu, 150-l, 16l;tt, in war, 196;,tt aho davery, dave1
also darl<m:u;Mdainai;Mdantho1
bJood: on alw. 61, cf. 212;orpn•
,.,
che1t(i.oma.11:), 118,13!,135-6,U9,
29'
Index
childbirth(cont.) animaZ-Wn; deception; dilpitc
Hl4; 1cneral tipiricancc of. 52-J; cool:cd: meat ill 1acrifice, 15; cllldnacd
1ee -110 ma,rlafc pJa.1111 ,e-en u, S4; uad the
154;~f,.,H2n.16;oppc,trdto
t"'''°'·
childhood.147-8, 17S-4, 176ff(at
Athcn1 and Sparta); defined by Plato, 'raw', 155, 170, 17J;roaat,,,boied,
174; parallel between children and 75, 22S
wheat, 7S cool:cry: sipif"lCaricc: of, 49-.50, M,
Chicq; Orion on, 105; davcry in, 189, 74ff, 11-2, 2I8-19;J)f'etcnded,. by
26S n. 8: Dionyaiac cult on, 224 Pytha,orcans, 222; double:, of pluu,
Chiron, 5-6, 149 78: of teed-com, 134
Chwny1 (of ephebet), ISS, 156, 174, Corinth, SS, 122, 207
176 c:orp,e, 7.5-6, 124, 248 n.. 46
Chrylippu1, 3 c01111ol0ty: or the: Ti,..anu, 208, 209,
Cicone1 (in Thrue), U 211; of the Polilictu, 208-9; of
Cimmeri.a.iu, 87 Aleman, 2!1 n. 2
Cimon, 131 Cott\Q, 14, 242 n. 18
Cilicia., 10 Crc:te: ill OdYNCU'• 'lyin,: Wes', 85;
Circe, 40, 8', 87-8 and Atlanllil. 20S; 'philotophic.al',
citizen.hip, 147ff, 176-7, 182;women 214;andTbncw, 124, 15', 156-7;
not cilizer1,1 at Athens, 178-9, r111cs upttNtd in cauldrona and tJi.
197-9;., rnc:rabenhip of an es:clu.,- pods, 11!: 1ite of Doulopolil, 119;
ive 'dub', 188 adole.:c:ncc ill, HI, 155, 159, 172,
civilization; chilRCter denned by con- 177, 182, JU;ll.avcry in, 117,
trut, urr. 174, 119. no-1, 199: 189-90, l!M, 196
oripn of. 82, 199; partly defined by Cron111, 2, 7, 11, 66-7, 82, 215-16,
(bee-kccpinc), 105, 216, (tc:chnoloCY), 2'4' n. 14; DCl:.lc: of, 10; ace of, 80ff,
54, 71-2, 78-9, 179, (c:atint cooked 208-9;ue also Golden Aac
food), 71-8, 82, 218;Cynic rejection C,khulainn, 162
of, 82, 226- 7; oppoltd to aavqery in culhu'c:: oppoted to Nahu'c:, 1.55, 17!,
nineteenth century, 168 174, 179, 188; but not completely •t
Cluhing Rock1, 19-20, 21, 29, 38-9, Spvta, 185-4
40,2S!I n. 9 Cumae, 192-S
c:Lu.lincation: obliption of mydiolop!t, Cybele, tm:iple or, violated, 161-2
lOl;Grc:el: difrCTent from ours, Cydopet, U-4, ISH, 90, 92, 244 n. JI;
lll-12;by neption, 85-90:of once nc:irhboun of Ph.c:aciM1, 92;
Sod• in diHettDI 1enention1, 8, lffc: Zcw the: thunderbolt, 66- 7
l!l-14, 62-7, 2!19 n. 73:of fodl' eynicmll: theory of n•Nnl wtiy of Ufc,
fOlc:1, 30-42:ofrituab, 172-S;of 82; attitude towvds ca.nnibalima,
women, 49rt, IOOrf; ctamnc:atory 2!1, 225-7; 'Py\ha.prn.o', !27-8
brothc:n, 173:seeobo a,c-cbacl; Cyrcne (city), 128
codc:1, myth, panllc:1 motih in Cyrcnc (nymph), ff
Ocilthc:nct (reform, of), 177, 212-U
Clytc:mncstta, 120-1, 190 OUM, U6, ltO
codct (11:Nctural), 48-50, 53£f, nn, Dan•w: lint a8or, 16, H, JO; lbJdd
106-7, 155-6, 217(( of, l20;ia Anc:bylw, 198
Colchi,, 40, 1!14 darknea, 11, 18, 52, .... 6!,, 154-5,
collective: representation., 112, 1!5-6, 158-9, !84, 25911. 7!;1.tolioi, 151;
142, 217fr papnul,87
c:omparativc:mc:thod, 111-16, 166-71. OcN, The:: iD Od,ary, 1.5, 87-1;
175-6, 115, 266 n. U ondc of, 127-8;bnn-plaat in coa-
concealment: ill Hcaiod. 44--50, 51-1, tact with, 222; treatment o(, 75-'1,
69, 71-!, 81; of bonet in fat (Juau. 17S-4:l(OOdtof, 128
ary), 76-7;ofmqic:allambby death, IS, 56, 60, 64, 217; Thuaataa,,
AtJC'U.1, US;ofpreciawobject/pa- bJGthff of H1.1pno1, 6: ,ec .t,o
,011, U6-7, U9-40;su e'6o funerary ritual
294
Index
decqidon, 4tr, 12-lS, 4Sfr, 57f£, caniculu pfflod
61-9, 121, 151-2, 157;foodof, Dolon, 151
7-1, 10-11, U;rule1 for, Niii· IUJlo1, 12, 14, 4'-4, 49, 51
n,ma; up Jolie of 1torie1, 44-5: rtt Ooulopoli, (City of Slave,), 189
.ho concealrnent;~ Dovc-worncn, 1u Pleiadct.
dtiptio(MoN./-oi, 15 7, 25 7 n. 26 dream, 17, 151
Delphi, 119, 122, 151, UB, U9, Drno1(Crctc), 157, l58, 177
191-2, 195 duel: to 1ettlc &di,p11tc, 150-1, 152-5,
Demeter, 69, 71, 18, 100, 144;and
(cf. 162); between Zeus and Promc·
cacab, 7lrr;called Aneaidona, 51; the1.U1, 44;.ec oho Eris/erii
Tltttmopltoror, 100-1 Dumbil, G., 162, 171, 175-6, 256
dcmocr&Cy: orifin of (rnytb), 198-9; n. 21, 263 n. 10, 264 n. 12, 265 nn.
fwfilmcnt of, in EcclttWU&uat, 200; 54, SS
Plato on, 209, 215; Ariltotlc on, dung; on racetrack, 25-6; broken-down
181-9 honey, 216-17; 'cooking' in, 222
dill, 7S, 81, 206, 218. 270 n. 8
Diodoru1 of Aapendua, 228 eqle, !I, 270n. 8
Dio,enca of Sinopc, 226 cd(c of world, 7, 65, 80, 204, 219,
Dionyliac e11h, 1trv.cturc of, 221, 249 n. 66
225-5 EIYPt, 9, 37, 83, 245 n. 27, 251 n. 5;
Oiony1u, 175:marriaa;eof, atAthent, and AtlantQ, 201, 203, 205, 210
1!5;ju1t sn,wint beard, 152; eaten dldcN (Affcmbly): at Athcnt, 178;
by Titan.I, 215, 225; as canniba.l., EcckrilUiuac (Aristophanes), 156- 7,
224; u hunter. 224; in Oschophoria, 178-9
157;Mtlar1aif'r,l51-l Elculil, My1terit1 of, 172, 174
Diotc11ri, 26, 28, '9. 40-1, 151, 216 Ely&ian Fields, 89 (de,tiny of Menelaus)
di Enalot, 129-30, 143
diappcarancc from this world, 75, Eqd1, F., 167, 190
76-7, 118-19. 121-4, 129-51, envy, 121, 121, 269 n. 49
U6, 208:by dc.truction, 126ff; Enyalio1, ucrif"u:e to, 183, 192
thins• underground, 119-40 Eo1 (Dawn), 88
dbgu.itc, 11, 47-8, 49-50, 5Hr, 55, Epaminondu, 190
200, 247 n. 14, 249 n. 66, 265 n. 14; cpltcbcit,, 147-85 po,rim; d&te of, al
,u aho concealment; deception Athens, 254 n. 2, 176; age 0£ entry
di.memberrncn1: of primeval o:r..14-U. into, 149-50, 177;cha:rter myth for,
45, 48, 51-2, 57-61, 61, 65. 76-7, 150-!I; charactcrittic type of combat,
{cf. 81, 217); of Diony,111, 215; of 154, 162, 177;see4Uo hair;hunting;
OrphtlU, 97, 106 initiation;.lr.ryptcia;marginality;tile
dieordn:coarnic:, 2(Mctis),8rr, ofpuuge;running
(Typhocu);political, 90, 94, 155 cphon, 154, 181, 194
(.byptti.z), 162 (individu.al), 200 tpiltltro1 (hcirenal Athcn1), 147.176,
(women), 208-9 (Plato); n&tun.1/ 180n.!l!I
IOCia.l, i.n,tiptcd by Orphcu, Orion, Epimetheu1, 43-4, 47-8, 52, 56
105; oppotcd to order, 2, 8, 90, Ernria, necropolis at, 171--4
155, 162, 200 Eriphyle, nec.lr.laccof, 121ff
dirination, 125, Ul, 157, U8 Erit/enl (Strife), excluded from world
drrinc in.lo .ea: oithui.z, 17-18;Thc,eu1, of god,, 63; between gods, 14, 66,
J24; Enalo1 of Lcsbo1, 129-10 242 n. 20: bclwecn Zcut and Prome-
Dodona..142 thciu, 44, 65- 7; between Hctiod
dot;: hunting, 91.161-2;without, 159; and Pcnct, 61;doublc, 68-70;
common property in Sparta, 160; man a,child of, 72;suaho oion;
.uvenccn, 76, 226; wolVCI li.lr.c dop, duel
17; flcah of 228; bu.Ir. imitated by trOidio1, 19-20
8;
T}"Phocu,, imitalion, on Schcria, Ero,, II
91;1ccf1Uo bltch-ec,ul; -day1,,ee Etcoclct, 121-2
295
Jndn.
EthiopiaN, 78-9, 221, 248 n. 46, diffcnnt modes, 75; Like a woman.
52:datructionby, IH-·-7, 121;
249n. 66
Eu.phemu.., st, .UB n. 67, 128-9
animaJ1 unr;onupted by, 226; ia
E,uipida: on ,olde11 lamb at ~ EJYPt, 24! n. 27
U2-S, 142;on maniafe to a fuh, 12 (llluyantu), (cf. (Polyaw.tn',
roreipcr, 198 ; on pq>lo1 u • pit, rina;), 125, 127)
122; ritual of rejection, 252 n. 2!; fllllln,, 12, 17. 87; diuppn:wed of by
on 10n1 of Hyp.ipyle, 159; on Plato, 159:net, 118
Phaethon, J4.0;on.Atalanta, 161; fodty, 1-2, 6-7, U-14, 19, !6
compuilon Mtweea hoplite and folklore: motif1, !, 128-9, 1'6, 247
l.fcllcr, 258 n. 51;B•allu, 82, n. !&, 25 l 11. 9: Propp and contiau-
224-5 aton, 249 11. 6'
Eurydice: rape of, 99, 105; u Nymph, fOJ:, 12, }01, 270 IL 8
IOO;brideofOrphn11, 10!-4 Frucr,J.G., 161-9
Eurytann, 219 frontier: area, 148-9, 150-2, U4, 1'6,
achan,e: of women, 8 7; offcrin1 pftl, 151, 162, 172, 174, 177; fo....
ll!-U, 141, 14!, 146:with the Athenian, 148, 177;Cntan, 141-9;
othff world. 118, 12.,ff, 128ff, of proto-Athen1, 207
1511-9, 142, 14';of one victim for fruit, 19, 91:'1>11-~o,u,po,, 10-11,
anothff, 15"-4;philo10phiea.l U; fMUt tret planted by ,od, Ul-9;
theory of, 145-6;,re -1,o pit fnaitlu.laem,52-l
acluaion: of Athena, !16; of mm from funerary ritual: in /liMA, 7!-- 7; iabu-
conu11cnality with IJO(U, 45, 47ff, matlon, incineration, 128, 175--4;
51, 54-5, 56, 70ff, 80-1, 217; from ue-'to,nwt1
, civiJiudlife, 105,22l;ofwomen,
'J,06, 178-9, 184, 188-9, 197ff:of G•bioi, ,u A.bioi
adidu, 258 n. .,4; of free men, 262 Ga.ia (Gt), I, 52-J, 69, 91, 104, 20C;
n. 7: ~f ephebes from cit4cn rifhts, mothffofTyph~. lff, ll;protectt
147-8, 176-7, (cf. 155):ofadol- Gianti1 1 I!
c1emt1, 17l, 174;of Phaeacianl p,den (m-,X), 91
from world of mm, 92; of nee of prlic, 102 (eaten at Skinphoria)
,old from Hade1, 80; of men from Gennep, A. YUi, U5, 172
cannibalism, 81, 219; of qriculhlft Pf'-01, 1!4, 147;Salam.lnian, 156
u..:I Md'U1ec &om world of seosraphical concep11, U, 87, 190, 202,
Ody1aC111'1 tn.vd1, 84-5; aduaive 205, 207--3, 210
,oft.ff (Wit: Typhoeia, 8ff; Ze\11 and, 15;
CllC!'ffDCDt, tel' du.DI food, 15:0rion, 92, 105
Ji.ft: In Helliod, 4!, 44ff, 49-50, 51,
fastina:, 102 (in ThHrDOphoril) 5!-4, 69, ll;between lU,efl-friende,,
fat: in 1aaifice, 45, 51, 52-5, 57, 77; ll!;wtddin1Pf11. Ill, 122;d-=mt
in funerary ritual, 76 of £riphylc'1 n«t.bce, 12.J...-2;
fate1,1uMoirai
father,45, 17!,207
father-ill-law, 105, (cf. 107)
~~r=~:.f·1!~~~~~~.;,.
~~m anothff world, ISO;
feutinf, 12, !4, 60-1, 87, 14!1, 197: on rdated to ofCerlnc, 145;,e.4'$0
human Ooh, 220; perpetual, 17, 94 offcrinf
fCOMI (llalt), "2, 74, 78 Glaucw. J!O
fCIUYIII, U2-S, 179:cekbndnfretum ioat, 89, 196; Aawthea., 1!6-7; hiddu
ofyowi1 mm, 150;at nipt, 251 below pound. 140; KapefOat. 220
n. 54;10ci.Uy invened, 262 .._ 7 pd,,u_..,#1~-u;.i.o
Finley, M.I., 90, 9-4, 15'4 n. It, 169,
181, 117, 204, 264 IL !l
rn, 5, 54, 218;thdt of, 45, 45-6,
41-9, !2, SI, 70-1, 74-5,11, 219;
in aemation, 75-6; cdru I.a. three
...........
clulification; immOl'\allty; •••-
morpho-.t: aaatficc;~t.loa ol
296
116:arrow, IH-40: ltab&n, 215; Hcralda, !, 4-5, 15, 24, 119
hone-bk, Ul;Yinettock, Ul-9; Henne,, 85, 164, 2S& IL !!;a.ve1Zcu.1,
odlcrlOOCk, 126-7, UO, ISS-9; 10, 12;1avnAre1, 2!2 IL l5;u10Ci·
Aphrodite'• applea, 161: fleece, ated with l)'mnuia, 24; and Pan-
151-tO;lhoweror, 1:s&; tulld1, dora,47
1!7;thhainffllll, 152:Sun, 157; Herodotv.1: on Spana, 191 {Corto),
walth, l44-5;clertftd &am water, l!M-5 (hrrllllffl;..1, 196 (Helot1) 1
210: forbiddm 10 proto-Athen1, 18! (ICftflh o(hair);onAndro·
261 IL 40;in Plato'1Rq,uWic, 269 phagoi (Scythian1) 1 220; on Argo,,
L49 191-2;Thyrcatul, 162; on El)'pl,
Golden Ap (ap of Cronu), 49-50, 60, 190;on Lyc:ia, 166, 190;on Al'JO·
69-70, 72, 77ff, IOff, 19, 91, 94, nautl, 119, 121; on the Lcmnian
219, 227;1H lll10 canniballma women, 197; human sacrif"tce, 255
Gorp (clauchm of Cleomene.), 191 n. 42;Ethiopian1, 78-9, 221:
Gorpn, 141
Ma,ian cen:snonic1, 259 ... 7!,
Gonyn, Law-code of, 196 125-6;1ift1fOl'1enalfavours.252
Gncu, 1be, 44, 47, (cf. 51) n. 21:Polycratn, 12!-51;Periandcr,
pmn, 47, 49-50, 52-S, 54, 71ff, 14, 127-1
16, 19, 91; srain·lirinc eanh, 12-S; hcroe,, 159 (u hunters)
111.J,o bread Haiod: 1lnlctv.re of poem,, 1 n. I,
lffl'U: good,, l lS-14, 125, 127-8, U-14, 4!-50, U, 58-61, 62-!,
l ! I , 17 ! ; necropolis at Eretria, 64, 65-74, 77-9: U1C or folk.Jore,
17!-4 2-!;or Near Eutem model,. 8-9;
peed, 12 (of Typhon) deliberate omillion, 241 n. 12; no
pat-friend (isfflo,), 11!, (cf. 86)
fHlffOI, 154, 160;p .. n,,.i at Al'fOI, ~.~fo~~:i~e!~n~:~~~:.r
192. (cf. 194);,e•cl,o hoplite rpi:ran1or of Zeu1'1 lc1itbnacy.Jf0, '
1Ymouiu111 (divinitie1 of), Hff {cf. 10-12);eannibali1m in, 215-16;
diffn-entiation between men and
Hada, 41, 76, 84-.5, 97;entnnce to, beuu, 7!, 81, 218
129, (cf. 25! n. S4) Arlllinia, 155, 177
hair: J..,n•,, uncut, 149;offeriq of, Hippolynu, 160-1 (u m&rJUlal hunter)
149-.50, 152, 17!, 177, IU;daaved Hhti1emytht.1cr, 12
atAqoa, l.5.5;tluiviqhnd for holoeau11, 75-6, 126fr
purity, lO!:lona,atSparu., us, Homer: on _.rariq, 11-19,52,!5-7;
l8!;pl'1cutoffat man-lap, 1.55; pmn of Patrodu, 25-6; funeral of
ev.t by Pydlapreuui, 221; not cut by P., 75-7;craft1manlhip,5lff;U1Cof
......
Pythqornn Cynic,, 228;ne Wo
..,
penc,tai;lla'lff'Y
Hq,hantu1, 40, 47, 75, ll, 94, 118,
Ul-9,206, 252 a. 7;tcmplcof, :=;=.a;;~ (! ~~:ane,'1
5
216-17 (feed, on dun&)
Birds),
Hna, 4, !I, 40, 120, 2!2 n. 7 hoplile: entry into 1tatu1, 148, 151, 174;
297
Jnd~x
221, 22J, 2'2 n. 4;1u .UO rn'a.l
hoplitc (cont.) invuibility, 47ff, 51ff, 76-7, 124. %49
ideology or, IS+-5, 159 n. '7, 174,
180, Ill, 269 n. 45;ac Sparta, 18Uf; n. 66
cphebc u anti-hoplite, 162; late Vff- Ionia, 150, 191, 198
tion of urliC"r distinction, 175-6, Iris, 14
2.55 n. 4, 256 n. 21; contrutrd with Iroquois, 16.5, 164, 166-7, 215
'naked', 160, 192 Jthab, 82-!, 89ff
Horatiw, 162
hornet, 46, IO! (oppotcd to Bee) Juon; and Arton•uU, 16, .50, '9,
hone: Athena, tamu of, 16, 29; in J.54--5, 1.59 (.oDll of); u an epbebe,
Spvta uad Pylos, 89; of bronze 149, 2.,., n. 9
(mqical), 124;aacrifice of, 127; of JeaDlll.aire, H., J47, 150, 15'-4, 17f
Poseidon, 129, 269 n. 42;ha.mra, n. 21, 181
l!l-2, 142, 145;~mbol of IUIOnl, judfement: (alll', 68-9. 242 n. 16:
I44;collcctive property •t Sputa, true, U8;atAtlanria,2lt;of
160 Dionysu1, 224-5
honc-ridinl, 29-!0, l!J, 180; rthot of,
159, 181 Ko;,.o,, 22-J; youncc,t ch.Id o( ZNt,
hunting, 12, 84, 86, 87, 104-5, 158ff 2.54 n. 19
(twoKim), 177, 182;nisht·huntia1, K•mfH, 10
161 ;Atalanta, 161; in Diony,iac kin,: idealized, 89, 9!-4, 242 n. 16;
cult, 224-5; .nd Will', 162; Al'Utaeu1 and tali1n:1an, 152-.5, U5-6; dil-
at hunter, 105 tributet com, 1'4; carriet aceptn,
Huskuaaw, 171 l'8;objcct1 ror invt:Wne:, 140;~11
ltybristilta (u A1101), 192, (cf. 19!) at Lelbo1. 129; ten on Adandl,
204-5, 2ll-12;o(Tbe~.. 99;,n
llluyanlr.at (Hittite dncon), 12 IIUo Athens, klnp of
bn-,c, 28, 1!7-8, 14Hf;ofSparta, k.inphip: competition for, 124; in
180-1; in Plato, 202-!; mirror- Ody11ey. 89ff. 9!-4, 204; pre.,,..:
im., 217 o(, U2;mqkal, l!.5, U5-6,
immonaJity; denning chukteriltic of 144-5; myth, of, l '8-9; orlental,
1od1, 15, 56, 60-1, 62-!, 217-18; 205; on AtWltU, 212;iet oho
of inhabitanu of a,e of gold, 80; of M>ffTeifnty
Herd.I of Sun, 88; of Mcnelau,, 89; •Ja,6t.i (in Crete), 187
food of (Wutory), 14-15, H;of Kleito, 204, 210, 211, 268 n. '8
dop in Alcinou1'1 palace, 91; of knowledf;e of the h.ituft, 1-2, 5. U,
Glaucut, I!O;Cottu1 not morul, 14 17-18, 40-1, 240 n. 2, SS-6, 119
ince1t, 87, 9!, 198, 220-1; abolition of Aiouroi, 90, 17.5
taboo, 226 ltrypttW, 147. 15J--5, 174, 181-2, 184;
Jndo-European: etymololY of tnu, form.er •"'ptai become hippN, 181,
142; warrior, 162, 175 262 n. .59
inheritance: of tali:iiman, 1!9; of
nobility ac Locrit., 19!-4; In rch.tion labour, 46- 7, 49-50, .51, 52-9, S6,
to ephebct, 147, 180 114, U9;sr, IIUo qricwtwe; poNHI
initiation: into phratry, at Athens, Lame., 91, 9'
149-50, 152, 17!, 177; in pcnl, LutrrySonn, 14, 17, 92
154, 171-!, 17S-6;ofptb(at Lafitau,J.F., 16!-72, 174, 114
Athens), 179-80, (at Sputa), IH-5, L&naia, 220, 222
(on Sphaaia) 256 n. I 1;~,phON, Lanj, A., 161
179; into marriq;e, 155, J 79, 18!-4; ~•,utchelt
into manhood, 156-60, 174, 177-8; Lato (C1e1e), 15 7
al Athen1, 180; at Sparta, 111--4 legend, 116, 111, 119, 122-J, J241f,
innrlic,n, 61, 65, 71, 92, 155 (double), 127, 128-9, 1.54, 1'8-9: f11nd>
162, 171, 172-!, Ill, 184-.5, uo. mental deQlenU in, UO; conu-a-
191-2, 196, 199-200, 2CM, 2DI, dictiont in, J.5&; dUtUlfl.lillhrd from
298
Jnd,x
myth, 181, 200, 251 n. 9; rrom folk- or forelper,, 148-9; or l'flr1lae11illi,
lAle, l2':1ubclaaofmyth, 116-19; 196; in1pac:c, 16!1, 172, 190, 219 (1ee
can n:YCIJ mythical imagination, dio cdp of world): of cannibali1m,
Ul-2, 155, 14l;pan.llel1with 219:of PythqoreanCynic:1, 271 n, 20
ri1uaJ., S6-7, 41, 1!4, 1!6, 150-1, rnuriqc: Ze111 and Mctil{l'hcti1, J(f;
156-7, 179-IO;about female power, hurnan, 47-8, 49-50, 51-.5, 5.5-5,
191-i 241 n, 7, 99-100, 102-!1, 148, 180,
Labo•, 129, 224 199; Naulicla, 92: di1tincuilhe1 rnen
[.eucothea, 11-19, 41-2, 248 n. 59 from anirnll1, 54; rejec:tion or,
Lcuctn., 120 160-l;abolition or, 188, (d. 195);
UY._Stnuu, C., 95-6, 106 n. 9, 155, patholo,y or, 107-1, 216: prepar-
170-1, 187-1, 23! n. 4 ation ror, 174, 179, 180:at Arp..
lie, 26;mbr.edwith uu1h,uaun.tiYe 155;atSparta, 155, ll.5, 196-7:a1
technique, 246 n. 25 Athen1, 197fr; between alave and free
Up.t, 11, 40-1; Opting by daylipt, inGonyn, 196:mot.irinlqcnd, 124
154, 174, 181 ;huntinl; by dayllpt, Manr., K., 260 n. 8:Manr.ism, 167, 169
159:contruied with duknu1, rnuquerade, 172, 174
151-9, 174, lll;JH8lsop/i6· matriarchy, 166-7, 190, 248 n. 52
plloro, M•1rtut111lill, 197
lilrtoplaoroi, 144 Mawi1,M.,112,12.5
lion, !I, 5, I, 17, 105, 160, 161-2, 191: rneat, eatins of, 15, 54, 71(f, 11-2,
cub, 224 217K, 221ff;sce a&o mon.iity, rood
Lmn1 like aom. 60, 64-5, 69, 80K, of;1acri6ce,rule1ror
Medea, 122
86-7, 91-2, 224-5
LOffll, 19!1-t, (d. 184 (Epizcphyrian); mediation, ti, 51-2, 5trr, 64, 70, 74rf,
(helotl,ft:atOzolianl.ocril), 194 a!I, 9orr, 91, 102rr, 1.sm, 216-17,
Lotu, Ealcn, 14-5, 87-8 219, 222, 227:in Neflltce, 60
Lycanthropy, 111, 215, (d. 154) Meduaa, 1.59 (hair kept in Jiydril)
Lyc:ia, 'rnaaiat'c:hy' in, 166-7, 190 Mcpn., 16, 255 n. 5;Salarni11eized
LYCl&fllll (Athenian politician), 144, hom,157
147 Mekonc, 4.5, 67, 77, 19;ue•IJo ueri·
Lyc:urgu,, (Spartan lawsiver), 110-1, ficcat
182 Melainai, 150-1, 152-!
Lydia, 124 Melanscit.(Areadian¥illa,c), 161
Lykaon, 215 Melanion, 160-1
Ly1ittrata, 178-9 Melan1hio1, U.5
MelanthN, 150ff
MeliNa, 127-8 (wil'eo£Pcriandt'r);
Maenad1, 224-5
raqic: tran1fomJation, t, 5, 87, 124; sec alJo Bee-woman
worid,l!I, 81;objeet1, lll-l9,
124-5, 121, 1!11, 1!16-7, 159-4~;
::::;·!;;!1ion 85;retcntion
of,
lllleep, 14: do11, 91:prdcn, 91: .Jneld, rnen or,17
in relation to UWllaJ1, 15, I 7K, 46,
120, t!IO-l;kinphip, l!l!l, 141.'. 51-2, 54-5, 56, 7.5-4, u. 198-9,
YOk:corOrphcu1, 96, 104-5:divmc 216-17, 218-19, 224, 226
intervention, 19, fl; bindiaf or a men in rel,,tion to death, 15, 5!-4, 56,
fOcl, 7; mean• to ilnmonaJily, l~O; 72-!,217-11,22!;uco/Jo
powcrllltbnately IOCial, lff;CYiJ
monality
eye.121;rncteoro101inl, 1!16; . men in relation to food, 14-15, 45-6,
etymoloSY or,..,.,, 141-2: wunor, 49, 51, 52-4, 241 n, 7, 71ff, 217-28:
5, 120. 1!10-1 Jee fflo monality, food o(
M•ncli.l,, 149, 2!16 n. !17 men in rcladon to land, 47, 49-50,
Malinowllr.i, B., 161-9 52-4, 61ff, 80-94
Malla (Cme), 158 rnen in relation 10 women, 46- 7,
... _,145 49 _ 50 , 51-2. 55, 11, 121rr, 115,
nwpnalll.y: of cphebc, 147-1, 149-50;
299
-
Index
men in relation to women (co111.) function of, 169, 215; 'INIIH'
189 (atSputa), 198-9;,euUo
tbeorin of, 151, 205, Ma a. 2';
..
Mcnclaua, fff, Hff, 19-90
Mentn (Athcnadi,p.iKd u), 247 n. H
Mcuenia, 181-2, 190, 2!8 n. 58;
mi.eaten aplanatiouot, 57-8,
151-2, 1'8, 215;..-ycholoeicaJ
upccuof, lllff, 142-S, 251 n. 9;
thcma of ffDlr.ed in difl-nt ~
Mcucnianwan, U0-1, 182, lt!, 1ion1, 4-5, 7-8, U-14, 50-S,
l!K-5,199 I Sfff, 220-8; thnna dilplKcd.
racta111orpholit. Sfl, II, 16-18, 96,40, ISl-9, 145; narndveofbrol;n up
87, 196, 247 n. M;,,-.-auo mqk; by lyric, I S2: n&rTalft'c lope of, 51,
phylical tnnslonution 51, 240 n. 3, 66-7, 72-S, Ut6;
metapho,, 29, 251 n. f, 262 n. 99 Plato'• UK" of, 201-2, 206- 7.
mtllr, 102 208-9, 2H; panllel motJl1 in. S-6,
Metil (Soddcu), 1-6, 10, 12-15, 216, 8-12, 15, 11-20, HS n. 9, 29fl,
(d. 20, 28);a.nnin,, 9, 6-7, 11-lf, SS-4, !14ff, 45-50, 59, 80-94,
29rr, 28, 911r, 57, 59, fS-f, 64 12Stt, 129ff. u2rr. 1f0. 1u,
millr., 86, 220 191-6, 221-l;incompletc, HI
Mino, (tine of Crete), 124-5, IU n..7S11•e.J,o lh'llcturalllm
Minyadca, 22t mytbopaphy (ancimt), 97, 108, 132,
Minyan,, 197 150;,•• .Z.o HcDmiltic mycholOfY
model, SS, 228;-,e ofpld u, 80; mytholoSY: na1uft or, 95-6, 107-9;u
mythical modcll in lqend, I 16ff, a kind or laap9F, 116; vviaab in
128-9, 1Sl-2;lortypnohodal analyWof, 141, 150-1, 179;bnapl
cnpni&ation. 117, (cf. 162); in Plato, indilpcll•bJciD, lff;l'O&colcoatat
20lff, 209;5a11au.rian, 169, (cl. 116) lft, 215-16
moira (at Sputa), lU;MeirG, 1-2, Mytiknc, Ut
10, 12-U, 15, 291 n. 2
mo,.,,17 IIU.cdnaa, 124, 127-1, 179, lMi
moncy,oripnot, 11211, 125 duallcalory, 151, (cf. 154, 175,
mo1U1tcr, llf, lfl-2, 175-6 111)
Morpn, L.H., 167-8 nature: wUcl, 149, 179: 111m'1 pllft in
mortality: lood or, 51, 54, 60-1, 71-4, {Plato), 202;in Atlantia, 21l;opprNeli
217; dcfmct man, 62-9, 6t-5, 90; tocultuft, 155, 17J-4, Ill, 1H.
apparcn1, II; anirnll, i,Donnt of, 216; incompletely al Spau, 11!1-4;
56; of fire, 74;r,e •UO dcceptioa; ..... also . . al p,ld; -.rklllture
mm in relation to death Naupamu, 190, 194
Mi.Iller, M., 95, 161 Nauaicaa,91-2
murder, 120-1, 124, 190-1, 192, 197, naYiptioa, 20-4, 28, S2-S, U-4,
220, 222-4 S6ff;ttl!.t.o pi.101
mlllical inatnuncnt, 11 (ftute, lytt), 192 Nnnail, US, 242 n. 20
(pipn. nutn) Nestor, IS, 160, 249 n. 66
Mycenae: lhronc of, U2; lqren,dary h• ne1: hu•dna, filhU,., 7, J 11, 1&9-iO;
tory or, I S 7 ; period, 12.5; collapN immpfortrid.ay,Sl-4;~
of, 174 by '11.10, 159i DOI ued in c.lyclonia
my11terin: ot Elcuaia, 172, 174, (cl. bouhunt, lH;orbyPhDio., l&O
256 n.. l6);ofSamo1hnce, 18 Niciu,J78
myth: thrtt 1tqc1 in Oreccc, 111; con- nip1: Dlony11111111Aitffino1, UJ;hunt·
UUtcd with lqcnd, 116, 122-9, 141, mc1,y, 15t;r1p11ncb,, HI, 154,
Ill; lilclVy, !1-41, 97, 107-1;.ia
relation to "hldory', IOI, 121, ISO,
~!!:· 181;•,.,,•Wac•i
ISS--4, 177, 187-1, 191, 19tff, 20I, IIOMOI (GppOMd IOp.ltui,), J75
219; u nidcnec fGr IOcilll orpam- 1111•pAI, 102-S
ation, 174, lll, 200;uuciolotY,
150, lH, 179, !15 n. J4-5;power n~s':.'2':;,9/,~~9:;-..,t0,
of dcrtwcd from. IOCifty, lff;synabolic
500
Index
o•th: dirine, 14, 242 n. 20; hoplite, Orphilrn: aa a ICCt, 221, 223; Orphic
l48-9, U6, 162, 174, 180; not at myth, 7, 10, 62; rejection o f ~ . -
Spart., 182; not to lllttp with win,, 104;uealso bios orphiliqs
19.S;not to ~ho11:1e1111tilvic· 01thophori.a, 156-8, 19..J ·
torio11,1, l95;falecto, 1!3,242
n.. 20; 'Great Oath' at Syrac....tc, 252
os.: prim~a1. 14-U, .,tr. sore, 57ff:
worltins, 73, 84, 218, 222; bca froni
n.. 19;ofkinp of Atlantit, 205, 212, dead, 96;uelliso dismnnbemaenr,
266 n. IS uaificialanimals
Oce1.11w, I, 7, 14, 66;0cean, 4-0, 80,
126 painofdivinitiu,1,2Sln.2,20ff, i
Ody-.eu1, 18fi, 25ff, 82-94puri,,,, 29ff, 239 n. 73, 242 n. 19, 206-7
164; build1 lhip, !12; dnoUes Trojan palace, 89, 9!1--4, 120-1, 159, 204, 211
hone, !l!l-4 Pan, 11, 192
Oedipus, 121, 226 ,------ Puw:ton, 150-1
o r ~ ~ u , 121, 1 2 3 ) j,~..;;;;~-~;.._:-:-:-:-:~:--.::-:-
o~~rd{!~;t~t~~
human life within, 8l;murlaae and,
anc!=~~:.8;9;:;:r:~~!o;~j
p,;.0-1/~ Aoeaidora, 53;1,eaJs?womarl J1
197; non-human, 87: perfect but field,, 89; image of in Bacchu, 82:
impoaible, 95-4; rift enterint;, under the tea, 130
121-3 Paros, 100
old a,e, 60, 64, 72 puricide; dream, of, 220, Cynic
Old Man of the Sea, 4--6, 96- 7 recommendation of, 226- 7
olffe, 84, 90, 149, 162, 206:wild, 90-1 Parthenon, 206; temple of Poteidon on
Olyrapi.a, 27, 131, 161. (d. 254 n. 19, Atlantia like, 212-U
2.56 n. SS);Olympio,, 22 Parthenopaeus, 161
omen,, 20, l.52-2, 137; linked to parth,rios, 49; ,,,,, lliso women, clanifi·
notion of'mon.,ter', 141-2 cation of
oppo1i1e1, 5, 9, 10-11, 12, 17-IB, Parth~Uli, 194-6
2!-4, 29-.50, 34, 41, 52, 65, 82, putoraliam, 86, 105, 192
87,90,94, 101-2, 104, IS2-S, puh,5,21,36-7.41,66
154-5, 158, 172, 190, 199, 216, PauanW, Dt!1cription o/Gnt!cr: on
222, 269 n. 42 Attiea, 16, 37:Aq:o•, 127, 137, 192;
oppo.lidon, 8, 13fl, 19, 20-1,41, Mencnia, 120, 130-1, 190;Sparta,
43-4, S4-5, 61-2, 70, 7.5-4, 76, 24ff, 125, 182-3;a1 Delphi, 122:
71-9, l!ll-2, 1!14-5, 88, 91, lU, PhocLI, 126- 7; foundation or
157, 159-60, l 73ff, 178, 11!11-2, Taren.turn, 196: bones or Pdop1,
11!14-5, 11!19-90, 198, 206ff, 209rt, Ill!l;movin(statue, 118;Cypsclus'•
218-19, 253 n. 39;cance11ed, 78; chc.t, 123 n. 22, 161:thlMUros,
notclear, 182-3 140;mqic&!relocationof1Kri-
onc.le, 1, 13, 117-18, 125, 129, 151-2, ficialanimals, 142:Andropompos,
191-2, 196, 191!1-9, 231 n.. 2;ofthe 152
dead, 127-8 pederasty, 158, 265 n. !18
order: coimic (ThcmLI), 1-2, 62, 65; Pquu,. 29; ,,, also BeUnophon
myths of, 188; imparted by windt,_ Pcitho, 44, (cf. 2!14 n. 17)
10; political, 90, 94, 162. 200; ta,n,, Peli.at, 30
US;1upported by lf.ryptt!UI, 182; Mt Pelion, 136
oppoKd to duordcr, 2, 8, 90, 155, PeJop,: shouide1bJadc of, 118; houac of,
162. 200, 208-9 1!12-3;,ceptre or, 1!18
Orion. 88, 104--5, 161 Pendope, 25, 26-7, !S, 1!13
Orphcu•, 95-109 pa,A'"; oblitente11 pni.,stt1i (in Thcsaly), 187
bo1&ndarin between the wild and the Pcntheu, 82, 224
~ltivaaed, 105; 'author' of Jl"l'fO• pt,plo1, 121-2, 142, 144, 179:uc.Uo
...,,.,._, 19-20 weaving
301
lnthx
Periandn (of Corinth), 127-1 the ttate, 201, 207-1, 212-14;
Paicle1, 144, 179, 261 n. S!i, 265 LSI CC*aolOl'Y, 202, 20l-9, 211;.e of
Pcriclymcnw, S Homer, 204, 210; of Hnodottu.
perioibi: atSparu., lll;atArpi, 192; 204-6: awnber theory, 211; ur of
in Ariltotlc, 192 model-. 201-2, 204, 206, 212-U;
pnipolo,, 141, 177;,u 8llo ..,..,.amo, clillike of 1ea Uld dcmocncy, 206,
Persephone, 100, 255 n. Sf 207, 210, 212-IS;n ...,..ion, 24
Pn,eu1, Ill Pleiada, 52, 105
Penianl: ritual, 125-6, 259 n. 7!; plou,h, plOIIPinc= mall.inc. 51-Z;
rnodel of de•odmo., 215; royal 1)'111· plou,hiac/lCll, 52-5, (ct 49, 71, II,
bolo", 252 n. 17 H-7); Cyclopn ipor-t of, 86;
Phaeac:ia: land of l&ilon. Sf-5, 41, IS: .IIICffll. 194-5;02., 75, 14, 211, 222;
stn.cture of fantuy, IS, 90-S; and u ordeal Uuon), 1!4;0dy9'NI M
Adanbl, 204 plOUplm-. 91: cCNUtella&ion, 52
Phaertu.1 (Crete), 151 Plutarch: on Spana, llS--4, 197
Phaethon, 140 (nwriqe), 154, Ill, llS-4 (eda-
~ ..
Ph&leron, 156- 7 (in 01ebopboria)
poUl"lll•l-. IS-14, 16, 252 n. 4, 247
-
Gia lipt 195;mariitce, 101
phratry, admillioa to, 149-50, 155, polllicy, 174-5, 191;in IOcial imti-
l 77;1e1 ma ...c,-,..,r;. hltioa11, 155; tt• -160 opp0Ute1,
Phrb.01, US-4, 155; land of, U6
pllron11U,21, 51 polu: • .cropolis, 17, 91; 111en.benhlp
Phronti1, Sf, S6ff ofclUlical, ltl-9, 174, 117-8;
Phrynichu,, murdff of, 141 definition throuP, boullday r...
phylic&I 1nn1fonmtion, S, 5-6, 17, H, win, 16- 7, 190, 219-20; cuteell
75, 71, 97, 156-7;andNCk llpm, coallict between -ce-ciu... 171:
17; ,,.,.mo mcumorpholb 'dCYCloped' DI 'ucbaic', 117-200;
fJIIIUU: in Plato, 211 (on Atlantu);and Platonic, 20Uf, 207;1fl m,o
no11101, 115 rejection of
pilot, 20, 22, 24, 52-S, 5911; without, polludoa, 121-2, 191, 224
95: "" mo naviption Polycnces ofSamo, 12Sff
Pindu: Tyde, 22; nr,iptioa, U; Polyadcfl, 121-2, 191
Bdle,ophon, H, Ul, 142: Arp- Polyphem.111, 15-6;,umo Cydopa
nauu, 29, 121-9, 154, 140, 149; Polyicchot. 216
'shieldofArpt', 120;Juonu Po•,.ios, 22
ephebe, 149; AcbiDc1 h-tina,. 159:
pbatSparta, 114
,_a,, 47, 49-60, 56, 70ff, 71-9,
10-l;KCOIUl.dlildolf.ria, 72;.Nf
planu: cultiHtcd, 49-50, 55-4, 75-4, mo acrkuJNR; labour
71-9, 19, 90-l;wild, 15, 15, H, Pa,.,o,, 20
75, 71-9;catin1 wild hcrbl, 226, Poro,, 5, 21, 29, ISi 11. 2
228: naturally cooked ia qe of pld, Poeeicloa, 16-42 ,.,ri,,., 16, 19, tl,
71; double 'cookiq' of, 71 lH;aacl Amphitrite, 150;.Udu.,
Placo: on cannib.U.., 12, 211, 220; on 256 L 11; PeriboJa. 204; Peridy-
buncin1, 159;1lory ..tGnu., 124-5; menw, 5;TMlft ofKortea. 29, (cf.
lire, 54;.,,.ono•oi, lfl, 151;on 129, 206, Hin. f2);dilpuae wilh
prepancy, 52-9; on childhood. 174; Alh..-a, IN, 206,atteadl 14..,._·
female dtil:cn1 fi&ht, 114, 267 n. 26; faac, 2ff n. 6 6 ; ~ by
on hdou,c, 117: o• 'YDDDY, 220; oa PhMIICWMI, !14-5, 206; by Alc,uader,
!02
Index
125-6; by Atlantil, 204, 206, 210ff: Sputa, 155-4, 181-2;runnin(u,
temple at Sounioft, S6-7;aphllldor, 156ff;huntin1 u, IS9ff: rejection of,
214n. 19 162 n. 42;van Gcnnep, ISS, 172; in
Pnaap1'11(inEccWriuurN), 156-7 Africa, 154; in VirJinia, J 71
Priam, IJ9 ritual, 120-l, 125-4, 125, 162, 172,
printhood, 180:ofpno.r, 147, 176 184;tne1:1of, l2';vc.tmen1, 157,
priniitMmn, 81-2, 226, 228;re, lll.ro 144; of 1celu1ion, 157; colour in,
Goldm Age;rcjcc:tion ofpolir; IS.S;rulllsoproce11lion;.acrilice,
Utopia rulcafor
pri,.e, 112-U, 117, 120, 142 Rome: archaic, more like Spana than
proccuion: O.chophoria, 156-7; to Athens, 197;'ephebe'at, 162;com·
Ileu1i1, 174; Panathcnaia, 179; It puilon between Grcclr. and Roman
Iplacphyrian Locri1, 194; in honour inititudom, IU, 154, 162. 251 n . .S
or Demeter, 144-5 rottcnnen, 18, 96, 98, 216--17, 222,
Promcthcu1, 10, 14-U, 4J-S6, 57-79, (d. 6l);not ronin1 (bone,), 60-1
81, 219, 221, 22!, 227;,,,lllso rue: rule of women, 166-7, 184, 187-200
PCnrice at Mckone rule1, 28, 54-5, 59ff, 85, 18, 98ff,
property: private, IISU;claim to, 121; lllfr.122, 1'4, ISI;dictuy, IOOff,
1crlllso oilior;wcalth 217ff; 1n:ual, 101-2, 226; for
Propp, V., 249 n. 65 lcacnd, 12Brf
Protcu,, 4rr, n, 96-7 runninc, u mark of adulthood, 157-8,
publicpmc1(othla), ll2ff, 117, 159, (er. 161 (invcnion))
IJ9-20, 142, 146
purity, 91-9;11, ,lro Orphbm sacrifice: meaning of, 53--6, 59-65,
putttraction. IH rottennca, 70-4, 81-2, 217-19; burial of knife,
Pylo,, 19-90, 94; Nddd.l or, 198 IS9; to marlr. ApMoc,rio, 150;
Pytha,oru, 22S, 254 n. 45 ll~uo, 61; Pcrlian, 259 n. 75: or
Pythacornn,, 217, 222-5,227-1; kinp or Atlantl.1, 212; human,
table or oppo1ite1, 174-5, 269 n. 42 129-30, l!S-4, 179, 224-5, 245
~ 14
nee or women. 55 u.crilicc It Mckone, 14-15, 45. 57-8,
npe: attempted, or Eurydice, 99. IDS; 61,62ff,69ff,22S
of Plei*9, 105;of Anemll, 105;or ucrifice: rule, for, 44-!I, 51, 54, !17ff,
Danae. U6;o(Ganymcdc, IJ9;or 7lff, 86, 81, 90, 217-18, 224-!I;
Cretanboy, 151;ofAtaZuta, 161;by total de1truction of objecll, 126- 7;
Tcrcu1, 216, by Polytcchno1, 216; invenion or, 226; failure of, 18;
dttam,or, 220 'veaetari1n', 104,24!1 n. JS
n11ionaliPn, 111-16, 14'-6, 177-8, 1&erilici.al animal,, 14-15, 29, 41, 44Jf,
85,97, 113, 12!, 12!1ff, 130, us.
"'
rationality, laclr. or, derane1 animal1, 211
11w, 76, 88;oppo1cd to 'cooked', 77fr,
Uf-5, 183, 212, 223, 225, 2!1S
n. S4;reprctcnta1ion1of, JS8;rc-
us, 159, 110, 11s. 211-19, 22srr, 1ppcannce or el,cwhcre, 142;
226,245 n. I Pythq:orcan view, on, 222; complc:·
rejection of polis, 199-200, 217-28; mentarity between 1nimll and bio1,
rejection ol ttanllition, 162 n. 42;sH 7.S-4
!Ibo Golden A,.:; primilivbm: Utopia Ailor: flnt ..Uor, 29ff; Phacacians,
revnNl. 24, 28, 154-62, 166-7, 172, 54-6, 9!, 204;1l!'f' a/Jo n1via"alion;
174, 181-2. 184·-5, 190-1, 197, pilot
201-9. 227; or run', counc, 192-S: Salam ii: battle of, I! I; ,cir.rd by
1r,1U,o in\·enion
Athenian1, 1!17;a11.. i,.., J56;Slla·
Rhu, 1!. 2U-16, 245 n. 21 mini.aftff'IIOI, 156
Rhqium,196 Satumali.a, 197
rin1. 12Sfr (Polycratct), 124-5 (Gncs), S1u11ure, F. de, 116, 169
252 n. 21 (parantor of lc,itimacy) u.vq:ery:a1compara1ivec11cgory,
ritcofpu.... 171fr, 179;,.ryple141 in 16'-4, 166, 167ff, 171. 174-6,
303
Index
uvagery(co11t.) 178, 188-90, 194, 200; tcillt" powtt,
185, 199-200, 215, 219;0rion 184;ru.lt-of, 191-6;ciryof, 189,{c(
unable to escape from, 105; Dioll)'· 19S);dealt"n, 19S;tubctiNtt- Corcid-
aiac, 224-S;su obo barbUUJD; 1m in war at Sputa, 195-6;flpt at
dvi..lizati.on; culture Man.than, 17S;marriafrcof.at
Scberia, ru Phaeacia Gortyn, 1%
Scyll,. and Charybdu, 85 llecp, 6-7, 9, 11, 14, 24, 242 n. 20
Scythiana, 86-7, 220, 245 n. H; ancll: of acrifict, 15, 60-1, 75,
udler, 199 217-IB;offuung, 102-S:oflll)Cl"IR
,ea: home of Typhon, 12;na.vcl of, 88; Of blood, 222: IWttt-lmcJlinc CO'l)"I,
tripod found in, ll8; throwinc 248 n. 46
ob_;«u Ullto, 12scr, 129-SO;hcro or, 1111oke, II, 15, 61, 75, 84. 211
150;Atheaao(, 16--42;111e.Uo snau, '· 5, 99; hcad1, 8, (cf. 11);
naription; Oceanu,; Potcidon Umb1, 10; wOmiln (Dt"iphynt-), 10
,cuom, 2, 24, 144, 267 n. 25;absntc:e K1Cial formation, 167-11, 18Hf
or, 91 Solon: mediator of Atlantit myth, 201,
tcclu1ion, 156 n. 26, 174, 176, 179, 181 205-4, 208, 210; law1 of. 265 n. 38,
.eduction, 47, 51-2, 92, 98-9, 10.5;of 269 .._ 47;alluliona 10, in fourth
Lawfulwife, 105;oflister-iftolaw,216; century, 268 n. 28
oflUll'4a,e,242n.16 Sophoclc1: Anhta"t, 'praise of rnan',
1ecd, 49, 52-S, 69; metaphorically, 2011 2!;PhiJo~ltlti -d tphcM, 177
1epantion of mu, froin beuu, 54--5, Soun.iOII, !6-7
111-2, 218ll;rre •lso men in relation 10WTCipty; or Zau, 2, 7, 10, 12-U,
to animab 15, 62, 137.140, 216;UI Ody.rtty,
,cplnlion of man from rod, 50-5, 89-90, 9'--4; ICq,tr'C U lip of,
H-6,57-79, 80ff, 2I7ff, 241 nn. lSl;su IIUo lr.inphip
7, 9; in Orphic bdid, 22!;ambipou1 Sputa, 24-5, 26-7, 89-90, 94, 115,
llatUI of[thioplana, 79, 248 ti. 46; 125, 172, 177-8, 191, 195, 207;
of Scheria, 91-2 oppo.cd to Atht-u, 176-85, 191,
Sepeia (battle of), 191-2 196-200; aa 'male city', 191 ;adol-
Sepia, (Cape), 2.59 n. 7!I Hccncc in, 180-5;lt,yptria, 1U-S;
IQ chance, 1.58 (aetioJorv for fatiV"al), Cwfft-ia, 157-1; PlataNlllall, 18!;
(cf. 190, 200);.rer lWo tnmvatisrn P.tlinti#li, 194--6;women, 184-5,
1eaual: abttcntion, 98ff; intcrcoune, 188, 191, 1H-5, 196-7;oripio(
5lff, 161-2, 215: rationally ordncd, llavC!)', 194--S;huotinJ, l60;royal
20l;forct-d, 6 (set- dso rape);acc11, in'VctliN~. 255 n. SS; 'philo.o·
51-2, 99, 105-4, 161, 216, 220 phical', 214
Shamans, UO Sputiatn, U5, 181-2, 1117, 197;
ahidd: of Danau,, I20;of A.ri,tomne1, ,.,onam, 114, 196-7
120, 130-l;dt"Vicc, U7, 141-2 Sphim., 215
ahip, 16-I7, 19, 22ff, 205, 212;ttlation .,,,_.,._,.., 241 .._ 12
bttwecn lhip and hint, 20; builclin,, 1prin1: on Scheria, 204:Atlantis. 204-&,
SO((; of the Phaeaci.ana, 55-0, (cf. 210;proto·Athcn,, 208
204) t former abtencc of in AdUIUI, st.llyl,odramM (atCoPnrir), 157--1
210 ~•. 9, 24, 52, S7. 59, U!-S. 259 n.
liclr.nu., 47, 52, 55-6, 60, 64
Slttn1, 84, 87-8, 92
SILiraphoria, 102, 257 n. SI, 200;
"
1ratu,e: mO'riac, 118; declicatiq-. 24-5~
de1tructioa, U6-7:-,.hu, 11S;or
Sir.iron, 156 Athena, 207, 2U;Pmddon, 215
alavt-ry, 167;in Athau, 187, 196-7, 1tealinf: Proinetheul, 44__.0, Sf,
199-200; LD 'U'Chaic' nact-.. J96-7; H-9;Typhon, IJ;lmab ltolm.by
,\ristotleon, 175, 181-9;Tiaan11 Thyata, 1!2-l
on, 19!; tcnninoJol)', 189-90, l!M, 1tcp-mothcr, lll-4 (of l'b.rb.N)
196; IU .L,o chattel llava; hdOtl staility of land, l!S-f
tlavcs; cs:cluded &om dti1e11 rif.hU. Stobi acdb&dc t o ~ alW1lalt,
211-19; Chryrippwi', theoaony, !I Teltph1&1, 118
rtomuh, 14,51,d.52-!I _Tduilla (of Arpe), lff
rtonr,, 9, 18, !6, 41, (cf. 126) ten1ple, l20, l22, 156, £57, 161-2,
rtrattcem, 4ff, I0, 149 n. 8, 151, 206-7, 211, 212-1!1; treuure, 1!1~_,_.
152-!I, 174 n. H, 177 l<h ~- -
lll'UCtunliJm: snmmv or narntin, tmdon1, 10 (of Zan), 76 (or corpse)
4!1-50, !l!I, 58!f, 106rf;homolOfY Tere,n,215-16
of patterning theme,, 12ff, 20ff, Ttthy1, 22
!!ff, 50ff, 7!1fr, 106, 116, 185, Thalet, 117
201-2 (Plato); demancb auumption Thcbe1, 99, 121ff
that nothint UI non-significant, 62, ThemUI, 1-2, 2!11 n. 2
I 15-16;demands aplanation at Thera (colonUlu of), 197
levd of myth iuelf, 58-9, 98; pou- The1eu1: and Ariadne, 122; Minos, 124,
ible even in ablftlce of major myth, (er. l!IO);motherof,256 n. ll;for-
l6:a1a111etahiatoricall)'1tem, get• to change ail,, 15!1, 156;
169-70, 18S;utrulyhittorical, mounu Aegeus, 1!17;on marriage 10
97-8, 187-8;demand1 attentl0n to foreignm, 198;,tone or, 140
the concrete, 127, (er. 62-!I, 97-8); Thetmophoria, IOOfr, 180
1u: also anthropology; Livi-StruUI; Thetit: and Peleus, 4fl; •aifice to, !O;
my<h helpt Argonaut,, 40, 2!9 n. 7!
ltrv.ch&ttdtpace, 28, 127fr, 172, Thyeltes, U2-3, 215;tornb of, 157
206- 7, 209ff;10· 4/.so geo,nphical Tiphy,, ,srr
concepu Titans, 10-11, U-14, 62-3, 64, 137,
Styi:, 14 215,22!1
mufferinl, ,er Golden Age; laboUl'; old tool: of olive-wood, 84; agrieuhura.l,
qe; sepan.tion or men from ,od; uted for odd p1.&1J>111t1, 106;,hip'•
1idr.near; women in rela1ion to men cable &1 hanging-rope, 9!1; oar mi.-
111rnmer, 51-2, 152, 154, 181, 207-8; ta.Ir.en for winnowinr-lhovel, 89; non-
1u: •160 canicular period poHenion of, a ,ign of barbarism, 86
,un: father of Phaethon, 140;herdt or, transformations, 8-14, 106
118; City of, 189; table of, 79, 248 trantgrenion ofruk,,81-9, 98ff, 151,
n. 46:and ,old, 1!17; and tpi(:et, 222; 161-2, 2!6, 219-28
influenced by kin(, U2-!I, l!IS; tranaition, 102-!, 147ff, 160; refuAI
prayer to by Xerxe1, 125-6 of, 162 n. 42;stttolio initiation;rite
,urvinl: u n:planation of problem, in ofp.uuge
myth, 168, 215;ofprimitive world, transmiai.on of 1ift, 117-18, 128-9,
220 1!11, 132-!1, 134;sualso n:chan,e
,wallowing whole, 1-2, 4-5, 15-14, tranffestism, 142, 155, 156-7, 192-!,
240n. 2,66, 216 197, 199-200;,uobo invenion;
symbolism, 17, 2!1, 59, 71, 101, 112, reverul;1e:,r.changt
118-19.1!15, 177;pluticityof, 1S7; trap, 11, 15, 2!, !11;sualso Pandora
symbolic explanation milt.a.Ir.en, 152 tre.uun:-houee, 89, U6, 140, 142
l)'Dtu: (of'langua,c:' ofinitiation), 185 tree: tnruformation into, 5; for lhip-
Syro1, 248n. 47 buiJdjng, !Off; ftre on uh-trees, 49;
ryuitio,., 154, 160, 181 honey in, 98, (cf. 100); capable of
divination, l!8;plantedby1od,
taboo, 120-1 ; ,u: ollo incell 1!18-9; ,acred, 144; &1pect of
...
Tantalu,. 215 n11t11n:,211
Tarentum (foundation of), 19!1, 194-6, Truanttt(atSpana), 195
tripod, 113, 116ff, 127, 128-9, 140,
Tananu, 7-9 143, 14!1;notoriginally 1acrttd, 14-f
1ttcl,..1. 4-5, 4!1, 207; of hdmaman, 2!, Troezen,256n. 11
2!14n.18 Trophonnu (oracle of), Ul
twin1, 4-f (Promethe111-Epimethe111),
Teluon, !I
Ttlemac:h1&1, 16, 18-19, 8!1. 89-90 211 (fivepair1 bom to IUeito)
,o5
htde•
Tyd,I, 21-2;oppodte or,,.,-,i. d1nysolephebe1, 155;P,·~
Thucydidc1, 256 n. 22 robes. 2%7; oppolCd to black m
Tylor, E.I., 95, 101, 161, 215 ritual/myth, ti, 150-· I: in hut.
Typhon(I'yphOClll,l-12, U,U 161; ... ol)', 161
tyrant: Periudcr, 127-1; Polyaa1e1, wife, 46, 52-S, 60, 89, 9S, 97, 19,
125ff;Gyaa, 124-5;Aril&odfflt.UI 101-2, 105-6, 120-1 (Cytem-
ofCwnac, 192-S;modcu f,x, 1211; natn), 12ur (Eriphy~);lfffflup
u imqe oflawlcunea, 220;ueon- Dah of children, 216
ltitutional fOIIII., 111-9, 209 wild bo..-: Calydoftian, 159. 161; kiD·
Tyn..-1, 154 1n1, u rite or.,._.. i• Macedon-.
l59;rip1 be-twH:n, at Sputa,
UUilr.11mi, I llS-4, (cf. 262 a. '9hcmblfln of
unity (uPlatonic Y&lue), 206-7, 214 Tydew, 191
U.ener,H., 195, U9, 152 wine, 54, 76, 16, II, 91, 157, 255 a. 10
Utopia, 94, 114, .... 199-200, 205,
204, 248 n. 62;,u . 0 Golden Ace·
rejection of po/ii
winier, 152, 154, Ill, 207-8
woodRK.br..2.lL"'_ ·I
w'
•
vri~~~~~t5~ 7
Tiner uaon1Cydopn,16;oaSchaia,
\
I
\1::~1::~:c;::;.~,:~=oaor
1t11N1al Athem,J79;orl.e'laaa.. ;·\-';!
9l;onlthaca,19;amon1Ciconn, JIO-J,(d.197)
14:pldea, IH-9;Athemal\,pro- women UI relation lo mea, 51-2, 65, II
0
~':;..~!;,!6 1/,atlboworaea, ~~~:,'12e:7·:~Mo,', 140;~ I
.onailln1, IS, 66, 216 t
water: dettruction by, 126-7;drin~,[:::"~e=11:..:":::i11teii'1~{w:!' n:rm'=-- ~
9 .;;e'w;;.;;..;;r,:;,
~J=.~~.iri~i;~~o-
Athen,. 207-l;u orip.ofraetal,
xe~-~:s;'.!r.~:=~~:
J96-7;huntin1(aad war), 180, 112,
210:lflU.e, 97, 99 259 n. 44;Melanicm.161;royal
walth, 19, 120-1, UI, 155-6, HS, invelt:itllre al Spana, 255 IL H
• 110;,yraboll or,
lfS;eutie1taotio11
of, lff:lharint.200;onAtlaada.
Xen.-. 125-6
212
wcavinc, 16,S!l, 100, 109, 142, 179,
224; imap of, f• Plato, 201
white: bona ia ucrifice, 14--15, 57,
77, HI IL 12;boaain pyn, 76--7;
fat, 51, 76-7;robe olfU1clota. !II;
306