Geography History and Concepts
Geography History and Concepts
UNL
TNTRO "
NALIS
2VR t rAiaptc V
I DIA
WAKE P'ACIiEvN
RRA
TCRRA
A PARLS
Panadigms and Rezolutions
69
cm concept. Kuhn was trained as a physicist, and his theory derives largely
s t u d y of the history ot physics. How tar is the history of physics relevant to
ro and quantitative sciences? To a n s w e r this question we will
the less theoretical
in the light of Kuhn's model
now look
at the history of geography
PARADIGMS IN GEOGRAPHY?
CHANGING
has argued that Kuhn has been the most influential scientific meth-
Rird (1977)
odologist as far as geography is concerned. Mair (1986) suggests that geographers
infuenced by Kuhn fall into two groups. First there are those who have used
Kuhn to legitimize their propaganda for a 'paradigm change' within the discipline
scientific 'establishment' (see p. 85). Secondly, several
and as a.weapon against the
historiographers have tried to
apply a kuhnian model to the de-
geographical
1978; Schültz,
velopment of geographical thought (see, among others, Widberg,
The
1980; Harvey and Holly, 1981; Stoddart, 1981; Martin, 1985; Johnston, 1997).
paradigm concept has taken on a life of its own beyond that originally envisaged
by Kuhn, and as such has been regarded asa useful 'exemplar (model orteaching
framework) for histories of geography.
Figure 3.6 attempts to systematize the theoretical development of geography up
to the 1950s, but it gives an incomplete and oversimplified picture as only the
main concepts in the subject's development are shown. Over the course of time,
these concepts have changed in significance and connotation. In Kuhn's terminol-
ogy (Figure 3.1), until Darwin's time geography was in its preparadigm phase:
Kant did not found a school of geography but indicated a role for the subject and
suggested its positionin relation to other sciences. Geography was, for him, a
chorographicand mainly descriptive science, distinct from the systematic sciences
and from history.
Ritter, on the other hand and contrary to Kant and his school, did notemphas
ize the distinctive roles of geography and history but instead emphasized de
velopments over time, linking history with geography. Ritter was, however, t
first geographer to describe his method clearly, and his account conforms to
Francis Bacon's classical model of how a scientist works (Figure 3.2(a)). However,
because of Ritter's teleological outlook, this first apparently active school of geo-
graphy did not lead the subject into its first phase of a paradigm: contemporary
in Darwinism meant the rejection of those ideas that might have
velopments
led to a
paradigm.
l tshould be emphasized that Darwinism did not representa complete break with
the major ideas upon which Ritter's geography had been founded. The study of
development over time was still regarded as very important and a deterministic
eplanatory framework was strengthened further. The break with Ritter was about
e forces that shaped development. After Darwin, scientists looked for the laws
wnch controlled nature (and for materially conditioned social laws) and so, to
aerable extent, they adopted a nomothetic (law-making) approach to science
7 p. 241) be
may when he
right that it was at this time that the
suggests
thelePrtant revolution took place in geography, when the universities subdivided
their acuties into separate disciplines and a cosmographic way of thinking was
d by the causal explanations characteristic of the developing natural sciences
to make geography a
nineteenth century,
halt of the recactPlabj.
Dunng the latter geography protessors
tried to
sacnoe the newly appointed method
as a
scieme.
The
hypotheic-deductive
was not,
pline as
nomothetic
here with Minshull (100
sense; w e may agree 0,
howerer applied in a strict
as well
as
geomorphologists,
stated genera eralizations firstp.81)
and
that deteminists, as proot. Unlike physicists
examples
es that involved geogra-
selected
then supplied a tew highly verification procedures a
test hypotheses by num-
phers could not statistical tests that might have played the san
tha
ber of repeated enperiments; to cope with Ole
w e r e not
as yet sutficiently developed
as epenments
eographical material.
Geomorphology and determinism may be said to represent geography's first para-
was eftective tor geomorphology
-it lasted for a
digm phase. This paradigm 0od
advanced the whole subjects scientific reputation through
ac- is
half-entur and could be put f
information until alternative explanations
cumulation of scientific
While geomorphology expanded of
other branches geography experienced
ward.
sernes of crisis phases. For this reason we can leave geomorphology to one side for thee
in human geography.
time being and concentrate on developments
As the dominating paradigm in human geography, determinism had a short
the possibilists and the French school of regional
life, being challenged by
geographers. These geographers stressed the idea that humanity has free will and
participates in the development of each landscape through unique historical pro-
cesses. Methodologically, geographers were trained to concentrate their study on
the unique single region. This inevitably limited the development of theory (as
normally understood in science) and made the hypothetic-deductive method re-
dundant. The appropriate methodology under this approach would be to try to
understand a society and its habitat through field study of the ways of life and
attitudes of mind of the inhabitants. Such methods (in the form of participant
observation) characterize the work of many social anthropologists today.
Fieldwork was regarded as of the utmost importance in the French school of
regional geography. Vidal de la Blache based his Tableau de la Géographie de la
France (1903) on studies in each
département. Albert Demangeon walked every
lane in Picardy before publishing his regional monograph on that pays in 1903.
This fieldwork was, however, mainly concerned with presenting a picture of the
naterial ways of life in the
regions and had to be supplemented
with the colec
tion of factual material from
statistical, historical and archaeological sources. In is
handling of data in the data's
-
organization,
classification and analysis the -
regional apPproach to
geography resembled the inductive method very ciost
Regional geographerS also sought general causal
unwilling to identify these as laws'. More explicitlyrelationships methods, sucn
but were rant
to survive ilism.
side by side with poss1D
Paradigms und Revolutions
71
For a long time, however, geographers continued to stress the central position
of regional geography. Georges Chabot declared in 1950 (p. 137) that 'Xegional
raphy is the centre around which everything converges. It is, however, fairly
obvious that the greatest advances in geographical research during the twentieth
century have taken place within systematic geography. In geomorphology, bio-
geography, economuc geography, population geography and many other
branches of the subject, a range of new theories and methods have evolved.
During the interwar period, landscape ecology and landscape morphology were
subdivided, and many specialist studies were made on urban morphology. Re
search into the morphology of rural settlements was also separated from general
studies of agrarian cultural landscapes.
Regional geography flourished in such countries as France, where in school and
university teaching geography was closely associated with history and where the
educational system fostered a national self-image of sturdy peasantry and
cultured townsfolk. Regional studies were also important to the academic leaders
of the emergent nations in central and eastern Europe, who were seeking to
establish and preserve the uniqueness of their national heritage. This was to be
achieved not just through their native languages but also by studying a whole
range of traditional relationships with their lands, which had survived centuries
of foreign domination.
While the peace settlement of 1919-21 created many new European nation-
states, arguments over boundaries between the 'winners' and losers' of the war
continued to draw externsively on local historical and geographical relationships
The economic revival of western and northern Europe from prosperity to afflu-
ence after 1945 has, however, been associated with the growth of essentially
similar urban industries and services organized nationally (but today greatly
influenced by the globalization of the economy). "Regions have come to be
defined in strictly economic terms: 'regional policies' are devised to help areas
thatlag behind current norms of economic growth.
In the USA, Edward A. Ackerman (1911-73) argued that 'taken as a whole,
those geographers who had mastered some systematic field before the war were
notably more successful in wartime research than those with a regional back-
ground only' (1945, p. 129). He went on to point out ways in which emphasis
upon systematic methods would best serve geography in the future. Although an
immediate impact of his work is difficult to trace, his analysis encouraged the
subsequent move towards training on the systematic side (White, 1974, p. 301).
Another reason for the limited progress of regional geography was the basic
philosophy for the subject held by Hettner and Hartshorne. While both regarded
ne regional geographical synthesis as central to geography, they discouraged
ustorical methods of analysis, arguing (with reference to Kant) for geograpny to
be
regarded as a chorological science. Hartshorne was strongly criticized by
of The Nature of
n g others, Carl Sauer who, within a year of the publication
Geography in 1939, said: 'Hartshorne.. . directs his dialectics against histoncal
giving it tolerance only at the outer fringes of the subject. Perhaps
.
apny,
.
had develo
however, adopted
of by a large
the
Hettner and Hartshorne
generalizations in the form of laws are useles if not impossible, and any prediction in
geography is of significant value. For Kant geography is description, for Hartshorne it
naive science' or, if we aCCept this meaning of science, naive description,
(Schaefer, 1953, p. 239)
C-haefer maintained that objects in geography are not more unique than objects in
her disciplines and that a science searches for laws. Having eliminated some of
of a rigorous scientific geography, Schaefer
arguments against the concept
sOught to set down the kinds of laws geographers ought to seek. He also urged
all branches of knowledge (ibid., p. 231). As early as 1925 Sauer had suggested that,
although geographers had earlier beern devoted to descriptions of unique places as
such, they had also been trying to formulate generalizations and empirical laws.
Both Hettner and Hartshorne made a distinction betweensystematicgeography
(which seeksto formulate empirical generalizations or laws) and the study of the
unique in regional geography (whereby generalizations are tested so that subse
quent theories may be improved). Hartshorne (1959, p. 121) suggests that geograph-
ical studies show 'a gradational range along a continuum from those which analyse
the most elementary complexes in a real variation over the world, to those which
analyse the most complex integrations in areal variation within small areas. James
(1972, p. 468) emphasizes that there is no such thing as a 'real region'. The region
exists onlyasan intellectual concept which is useful for a particular purpose. Later
critics have read a much more metaphysical significance into the concepts 'unique
and 'region' than was intended by the geographers who were practising between
the wars. Incorrect quotations from Hettner and Hartshorne have, however, gained
an amazingly wide acceptance: 'It is discouraging to find some writers who con-
tinue to accuse Hettner and his followers of defining geography as essentially
diographic, thereby obscuring the underlying continuity of geographic thougnt
ba, p. 228). James thus maintains that what has been caled the "quantitaive
revolution' did not represent such a major change in direction as many think
It can hardly be denied, however, that the interwar generation of geographers
Were sceptical of the formulation of general and theoretical lawS, partly as a
TownF0of
****.. .
OBank *******. **
*********D -
*
****.
********** i treet
-High S Mar
70:E Coquet.
Place
T/V6
O:
Magistrate's Railway
Court Station
Church Yard
hildrens Playground
The changes
rapid from
vertical to horizontal connections dunng the second half of
twentieth century are illustrated from Rothbury (Figure
the
3.7), a small service cenue
2,000 inhabitants, 50 km north-west of Newcastle upon Tyne in an upland tami
region. In 1950, Rothbury and its valley were substantially self-sufficient. Most p
living in the village tound work locally, all the nationally provided services were avaiau
in the village and most goods could be rom
bought there. Now Rothbury is govemed
Alnwick, 25 km away, and the high school is in Mopeth, also 25 km away. 1he
cou
and the railway station have closed and the future of the hospital is not certain. A cent
survey showed that 38% of the villagers did little or no shopping in Rothbury and ou 6of
clothes and hardware shopping was done outside the
village. One
third of the war
force now drive over 25 km to work and a further 10% work from home, most usig uter
computer inks. Five local businesses either design software. provide local compus
facilities or sell their products nationlly via the Intemet. Village economy is now 2*
dependent on high levels OT car ovwnership and on telecommunications
Paradigms and Reiwlutions
75
1947 1947
1970 1970
traditional self-sufficient
By the end of the nineteenth century, however, the
economies of Europe were giving way to an
international market economy, and
Horizontal connections,
the value of this type of regional study was reduced.
state and international policies, market forces, the interplay between regions,
local development than the local
Cues and countries, became more important for
noted earlier in Chapter
Connections between humanity and the land. This was (as
interest in horizontal, spatial
4) Tealized by Vidal de la Blache and it led to greater
structures. and
horizontal, spatial relations
the concept of relative space,
.Dy introducing explanatory power.
Distance
could be given
e measured in different ways travel time, mileage througn a
COuld be measured in terms of transport costs, "The shift to a relative spatial
distance:
aport network and even as perceived most fundamental change in the
in progress and is probably the
hic til an almost
infinite number of
new worlds to
It was only
after the Second World War that theoretical
considerations on tho
relativity of space (and also research issues such as the study of diffusion modol.
and location theory) came to
occupy a dominant position in geography. One
factor in the adoption of the new
tion many
geography was the critical institutional situa-
departments geography found themselves in, particularly in the
ot
USA. In 1948, Janmes Conant,
come to the conclusion that
president of Harvard University, had reportedly
'geography is not a university subject' (Livingstone,
1992, p. 311). The Department of
and the discipline was also
Geography at Harvard was closed soon after,
gradually eased out of some of the other more pres-
tigious private Ivy League universities.-
Among the
practitioners of the ever more theoretical sciences, the claim that the
regional synthesis constituted geography's essential
dilettante image. After the Second World identity lent the
subject a
War the North American
were
expected to produce problem-solvers or social universities
increasingly complex economies (Guelke, 1978, p. 45), technologists
and
to run ever-
slow in adopting
theory building and modelling that geographers were not
their science and their own academic
might promote the status of
Gould (1979, p. 140) standing
recaHs how the new
generation of
and ashamed of 'the
bumbling amateurism and geographers were sick
nearly half a century of opportunity in the universities antiquarianism that had spent
unstructured factual accounts'. piling up a tip-heap or
ation's vision, Moprill (1984, p. 64) claimed that the young gener
although it might seem radical to those
status for the
discipline,
in fact conservative in
was satisfied with inferior an
save the sense thàt we wanted to
geography as a field of study and join the mainstream
though, or perhaps due to this, the 'new' of science. Even
spearheaded by the geography the 1950s and 1960s
Americans. They were also
of
was
works in
Europe that, so far, had been inspired by earlier theoretca
The situation almost overlooked.
much less critical in
was
Britain because of the
independent position geography held in both very strong aand
the US states schools and universities. In
geography was more or less
absent from the curriculum as a many
discipline at high-school level, and less than discre
study geography. Geography 1% of students entered
research and graduates had to find career outlets in universid
planning.
duction based on Th continual threat of departmental closure or app re
the indepengent
frenetic search evaluations of research statlains
Än American
universities for
productivity also exP'h 2arch
programmes. new ideas and Te
We now
proceed to look at the
assess whether the
changes in
development of the spatial science scho
tion) really were a geography
scientific revolution (also called the
'quantitative revo
in the Kuhnian sense.
Paradigms and Revolutions
77
OF SPATIAL SCIENCE
GROWTH
THE
cation theory originates from The classic locat
economic theory. theories,
einrich von Thünen's work on patterns of agricultural land use
including Johan Heir
Alfred Weber's study of industrial location (1909), are economic the
1826) and
(1826)andAlfred
Later economists and regional scientists, including Ohlin, Hoover, Lösch and
ries.
rdeveloped theories of the areal and regional aspects of economic activity
ence developed in some universities as a separate discipline;
further. Regional scien
others, this research came to be linked with economic geography or re-
in yet
gional economics.
Walter Christaller (1893-1969) was the first geographer to make a major contri-
theory Die Zentralen Orte in Süddeutsch-
with his famous thesis
htution to location
land (1933), translated by Baskin as Central Places in Southern Germany (1966).
under Weber, declared in 1968 that his
Christaller, who had studied economics
economic theory. His supervisor when he was working on
work was inspired by
was Robert Gradmann, a geographer who had himself made an
Die Zentralen Orte
outstanding regional study of southern Germany (1931) which, however, closely
followed the current idiographic tradition in German Länderkunde. Although
Christaller's thesis was accepted, his work was not appreciated during the 1930s,
review of what had been going on in German
and when Carl Troll (1947) wrote a
Kuhn's terminol
geography between the wars, he did not even mention him. In central
0gy, Christaller's attempt
to explain the pattern and hierarchy of places by
a general theoretical model was not acceptable within the reigning paradigm.
Christaller never held an official teaching position in geography (Box 3.3; Figures
3.9-3.11).
Eventually Christaller gained following, notably in North America and Swe-
a
den when it was realized that his central place theory could
be applied to the
establishments (Figure 3.11) and also
planning of new central places and service
to the delimitation of administrative units. Edward Ullman (1941) was one of the
urt
uromberg
stutgano .
rastour
oO.o :
Munch-.o
O.
Zunca(o
Figure 3.9 The geometrical hexagonal
landscape of towns in southern
Walter Christaller's classic study of central places made in the 1930Os Germany from
en b C
lant etE9
MosryieA
frmtowd
olleteeb
Ur
,KInggnri
Karnpen 10 km anperi
pen
work American
to draw attention to Christaller's
-
first American
geographers urban struc-
the theoretical models of
were beginning to develop economists and
geographers that had been devised earlier by
tures and cities places
as central
and Ullman, 1945).
urban sociologists (Harris research discipline, the influential
as a fundamental
In an account of geography concentrate their
Ackerman (1958) encouraged
students to
American geographer A range
cultural processes and quantification.
attention on systematic geography,
into use in several systema-
methods was gradually brought
of different statistical of more refined theories and
the development
tic branches of geography, enabling
models. institutions led
The acceleration of theoretical work was especially marked in and
natural sciences, especially physics
who had studied the
by geographers were good
contacts with developments
in theoreti-
where there
statistics, and/or universities, the
the 1950s at several American
cal economic literature. During new ideas
became very productive of
frontier between economics and geography
and techniques. conducted by
use of
mathematical statistics
A seminar for PhD students in the
from 1955 onwards
willham L. Garrison at the University
of Washington, Seattle,
inter-
Garrison and his co-workers were mainly
Was of particular significance.
which they introduced location
economic geography, into
sted in urban and economics with associated mathematical
methods
from
eory based on concepts 1959-60). Many of the
students from Seattle
na statistical procedures (Garrison, USA during the 1960s,
including
leaders of the 'new' geography in the
came Garrison
Morrill. Both Berry and
L. Berry, William Bunge and Richard
Drian ). the inspiration Berry the
of
area. Through
moved to work in the Chicago or
of Chicago became leading centre
a
graphy department at the University students and publsne
number of PhD
ecal geography. It attracted a large other leading professors later
lett
series of monographs. Berry and o
where (D,)2
represents the interaction
populations of the two towns; D, is thebetween
distance
town i and town ;
P, and P ale the
The equation indicates that between them; and k is a
the interaction
between
constanu of
telephone calls, tlows of traftic) is proportionate to the the two towns (numoe
divided by the square product () of their popuau ons.
-()-of the distance between them.
The work of Christaller,
by Edgar Kant, an Estonian
August Losch and others Sweden
anl
'atad ms 81
.afare taking reluge in Lund atter the Second World War (Kant, 1946
homclanmd b e t o r e
rescarch Jsistant
assis in 1945-6
was Torslen Hägerstrand, brilliant young a
His
1951).
r.apher
who was working on migration processes. Through his contacts
also
geogrp dish ethnologist Sigtrid Svensson (who had made number of a
t hthe
e relation9
relations between innovation arnd tradition in rural areas using the
studies of
currently accepted metl ethodology), Hägerstrand became interested in the pos-
sibilities ot investigating the process of innovation with the aid of mathematical
statistical methods. In focusing on the process, Hägerstrand made a clear
and
break with
the current regional radition. His dissertation 'Innovations - förloppet
(1953, later translated by Pred, 1967, as Innovation diffu-
irorologisk synpunkt'
on as a spatial process') examined the diffusion (or spread) of several innova-
ians among the population of a part of central Sweden. Some of these
innova
ations concerned agricultural practices, such as bovine tuberculosis control
nd Dasture improvement, and others were more general, such as car ownership.
1AEth the aid of the so-called "Monte Carlo simulation, which involves the use of
andom samples from a known probability distribution, he was able to construct a
ceneral stochastic model of the prócess of diffusion. Stochastic literally means at
random; stochastic or probability models are based on mathematical probability
theoryand build random variables into their structure. Models may be classified
ochastic or deterministic.mdeterministic models the development off
set of
some system in time and space can bètompletely predicted, provided that a
initial conditions and relationships is knowD.
The stochastic Hägerstrand model enabled the spread of innovation to be simu
lated and later tested against empirical study. It was demonstrated that the form
of distribution at one stage in the process would influence distribution forms at
subsequent stages. Such a model could therefore be of use to planners in support
of future innovations they wished to bring about. The department of geography at
Lund University soon became renowned as a centre of theoretical geography,
there were
attracting scholars from many countries. Almost from the beginning
contacts between Lund and Seattle. Hägerstrand taught in Seattle in 1959 and
Morill studied with him in Lund, where his work on migration and the growth of
urban settlement (1965) was presented.
In the years that followed, Hägerstrand's technical and statistical procedures
attracted more attention than his theoretical analyses. He himself regarded his
work as less important for its empirical findings than for its general analysis of the
English-speaking
t o be fully appreciated. Initial
forms of quantification, such as the
raphy
frequency distribution scattergrams, parameters and index numbers, Were
of
applied around 1960. The introduction of factor analysis, notably in a classif
first
ica-
tory study of Swiss cantons by Steiner (1965), was the real introduction to new
quantitative approaches for most German-speaking geographers. The philosophi.
cal implications of the spatial science school were first presented by Dietrich
Bartels in his book Zur wissenschaftstheoretischen Grundlegung einer Geographie des
Menschen (1968).
Another reason for the delayed impact of the 'new geography in Germany was
that geographers tended to follow Troll's appeal in Erdkunde (1947) in that they
accepted the principle that worldwide research should be a normal component of
an academic career. Virtually all established geographers were attracted to em-
ploying their talents abroad, leaving their graduate students to cultivate research
at home. Research abroad undoubtedly contributed to Germany's international
reputation, particularly through the application of German methods of detailed
landscape studies and cartographical work. German geographers also found that
their existing techniques were well adapted to research abroad, particularly in the
Third World where the statistical basis for quantitative analysis was sparse or
unreliable.
Throughout the world there was marked opposition among established geogra*
phers to the learning and teaching of the new spatial science methods, and a
reluctance to open professional journals to contributions, the editors did not un
derstand. "There was
something electrifying about tilting with the dragons of tne
establishment' says Morrill (1984, p. 59), and for this reason the
young genera
of
geographers had the feeling of being revolutionaries. In the USA the lack of
publication outlets led to the establishment of a theoretically orientated journal,
Geographical Analysis (ibid., p. 65).
In
1963, Canadian geographer, lan Burton, arguing that what he labelled the
a
quantitative revolution' was over and had been for some time, cited the rateaat
which schools of geography in North America were ita-
adding courses in qua
tive methods to their requirements for
graduate degrees. It must be stae
however, that most geographers did not consider the theoretical develop
o
within the subject as a revolution, and that many 'revolutionaries' were at pains to
emphasize continuity in the ultimate objectives of human geography. Ineed.
statistics for the cepted,
making of relatively precise statements was generally ae
Paradigms and Revoutions
83
Human
ecology
B
2
iaure 3. 12 Geography and its associated subjects, A: Earth sciences, B: Social sciences, C:
CGeometrical sciences :The core of geography, 2: Geology, 3: Demography and other
social sciences, 4: Iopology With other geometric sciences
Source: Atter Haggett, 1965
c e nmeasured revolution in
one and only
comments that 'the
e irony, Bird (1993, p.11) us to date te
event in the literature enables
'An
Saphy took place in June 1966:
the -
was
overthroWn
bastion in geography
W h e n the last idiographic but unique
of the idea that locations could never be anything the eartn
rucion that all parts
of s surtde
article Grigg (1965) had tried to argue
dn
are includes the study
of the location O
1 da
e . It it is held that geography
84
Geography: History and Concepts
and that 'locations are unique, then geography cannot fully employ the
cientific
method. In June 1966, however, Bunge published a short commentarv toc
paper, asserting that locations are not unique', but general. Locations arecE8s
able as witnessed by such terms 'near, "far', 'close', 'distant' and
as
which describe the of locations. It is thus the
relativity relativity of spatialacent,
loca-
tions that can be analysed in a scientific way.
Quantification as such does not lead to any scientific revolution in the Kuhniar
sense. The change from absolute to relative
space as the focus of geographical
study had, however, basic philosophical implications and was in this sense re.
volutionary. It is therefore better to talk of the spatial science school rather than
quantitative revolution and quantitative geography to describe the new
of the 1950s and 1960s (Figure 3.6 trends
p. 68).
The major advances towards a
unifying methodological and philosophical basis
for the spatial science school were made in
the 1960s by British
notably Peter Haggett, Richard Chorley and David Harvey. Locational geographers.
Human Geography by Peter Analysis in
Haggett was published in 1965. The importance of this
book lay in its overview of much new theoretical
work in the subject.
(ioid, pp. 14-15) used the diagram reproduced in Haggett
Figure 3.12 to illustrate the
argument that there are three traditional subject associations of
the earth sciences geography: with
(geology and biology),
with the social sciences and with the
geometrical sciences. Haggett (ibid., pp. 15-16) maintained that:
The geometrical tradition, the ancient
basis of the subject, is now
the three. Much of the most
exciting
probably
the weakest of
geographical
applications of higher order geometries. .
work in the 1960s is
emerging from
ing aspects of human and .Geometry not only offers a chance
of weld-
revives the central role of physical geography into a new working partnership,but
cartographyin relation to the two.
Movements Channels Nodes
Hierarchies
Surfaces Diffusion
-t29
K
Figure 3.13 The basic elements in Haggett's model for the study of
and t, representing stages in ditfusion. spatial systems. li
85
heart of geography as a science is the distributional view.
indistance.
discipline in distan When we discUss space it is not Geography
the container y isa
is
'quantitative
revolution' may thus
the
about
l u h n ' s s e n s e . To talk
a provided
geography
give false
8ave false impressions.
impressic the 'new for ne
tor i
'exemplars
ew
that could
research projects
86 Geography: History and Concepts
students as, for instance, Hägerstrand's diffusion model. And the reneturss
discussion on the basic problems of the subject that followed in the wake of
quantification process may be regarded as a sign of a crisis phase. Individa
research workers felt themselves more or less obliged to take a stand and
clarify their own research situation, so there was little opportunity f o
straightforward puzzle-solving. The transformation to a spatial science on the
basis that locations are essentially relative may also indicate a paradigm shi
But the meaning of this transformation was not generally understood
appreciated by the geographical community. Old ideas continued to flourish and
new ideas cropped up as results of criticisms of the spatial science school. Bird
(1993, p. 13) has characterized the changes in geography as constant revisions:
they may also be regarded as a multiparadigmatic development, since different
schools of thought continued to live side by side.
It may, of
however, be characteristic social
a science that new paradigms do
become so well established to enable a relatively long
not
period of normal science.
Or rather, we may have reached a stage of mature science where we
revolution in permanence, in the Popperian sense.
experience
Opposing the so-called 'revolution', Stamp (1966, p. 18) preferred to call it a 'civil
war, and noted that quantification had many points in common with a
political
ideology; it was more or less a religion to its followers, 'its golden calf is the
computer'. Broek (1965, p. 21) stated that 'there are more things between heaven
and earth than can safely be entrusted with a
the advocates of
computer. Even Ackerman, one of
quantification, warned (1963, p. 432) that "the danger of dead end
and nonsense is not removed "hardware" and
by symbolic logic'. Minshull (1970,
p. 56) observed that the landscape was
that many of the models could
becoming a nuisance to some geographers,
warned there was a real
only be applied to a flat, featureless surface, and
danger that these ideal
relationships could be mistaken for statements aboutgeneralizations
about spatial
reality itself.
Fred Lukermann (1958) reacted
school to establish analogies with especially
to attempts
by the social physics
physics, maintainingInthat
by analogy cannot be tested: falsification is impossible. hypotheses
a series of papersderivea
in the
1970s, Robert Sack, a student of Lukermann,
criticized the view put forward by
Bunge (1962) and Haggett (1965) that geography is a spatial science and
geometry is the language of tnat
and matter cannot be separated
geography. Sack (1972) maintained that
space, time
analyticallyin a science concerned with
providi
explanations. The
geographical landscape is continuously
processes which have left historical relics and which are changing ne
the time must be taken into account as creating new inroads a
important explanatory factors. The laws ot
geometry are, however, static they have no
-
aroblem,
Another problem, Broek pointed out (1965, p. 79), crops up if we project a
o u r own surroundings over the whole world as a universal
d e r i v e d from
model fferent situations in other countries as 'deviations' from the
measure
diff
truth and
ideal construct.
Models based on research within the western cultural world
cannot be elevated
into geneera truths. Brian Berry (1973b) came to the conclusion
that a universal
urban graphy does not exist, and that urbanization cannot be
universal proces: 'we are dealing with several fundamentally
as a
dealt with
that h a v e a r i s e n out of differences in culture and time' (ibid.,
different processes North America and
1073h. D. xii). He divided the (1)
world into four universes:
(2)
Actralia. with their free market economies; with
western Europe, with its planned
Third its
World, between a
economy split
(3) the
welfare economy;
raditionaland modern sector; and (4) the socialist countries, with their rigidly
has its o w n urban geography, which again
will
economies. Each of these
planned
change through time.
also noted that 'the Russian translation of the
first
et al. (1977, p. 24)
Haggett clear how heavily the locational
of this book (Haggett, 1965) made
edition economics of the capitalist world.
rooted in the classical
explanations w e r e certain readers and
of the book will appeal to
Inevitably, the lopsidedness
condemn it to others.
supplied by the users of the park (see GIS, together with information
Advanced systems pp. 180-182).
and analysis has proved its usefulness
ecogeography
earth. Gregory (1985),
the study of
-
in physical
humanity's role in changing the face geograpny
of these
Goudie (1990) and Huggett (1993) of the
developments, and earlier editions of this
also included
provide many exampt
a
basictheintroduction to systems book (Holt-Jensen, 1981; 1980)
Here we restrict analysis geography.
in
the Sahel presentation to one example
catastrophe), and
that ecosystems were not agree with Unwin (1992, p.
(see Box 3.5 and Figure
3.1
more 129) that it is 'surpris
research by geographers. One extensively used as framework for a