Reference 2
Reference 2
KRISTIN DEAN
Contents
1. Basic Definitions 1
2. Axioms of Projective Geometry 2
3. Linear Algebra with Geometries 3
4. Quotient Geometries 4
5. Finite Projective Spaces 5
6. The Fano Plane 7
References 8
1. Basic Definitions
First, we must begin with a few basic definitions relating to geometries. A
geometry can be thought of as a set of objects and a relation on those elements.
Definition 1.1. A geometry is denoted G = (Ω, I), where Ω is a set and I a
relation which is both symmetric and reflexive.
The relation on a geometry is called an incidence relation. For example, consider
the tradional Euclidean geometry. In this geometry, the objects of the set Ω are
points and lines. A point is incident to a line if it lies on that line, and two lines
are incident if they have all points in common - only when they are the same line.
There is often this same natural division of the elements of Ω into different kinds
such as the points and lines.
Definition 1.2. Suppose G = (Ω, I) is a geometry. Then a flag of G is a set of
elements of Ω which are mutually incident. If there is no element outside of the
flag, F, which can be added and also be a flag, then F is called maximal.
Definition 1.3. A geometry G = (Ω, I) has rank r if it can be partitioned into
sets Ω1 , . . . , Ωr such that every maximal flag contains exactly one element of each
set. The elements of Ωi are called elements of type i.
Thus, these divisions of the set Ω give a natural idea of rank. Most of the
examples of geometries which are dealt with in this paper are of rank two, that is,
they consist of points and lines with certain incidence structures.
Lemma 1.4. Let G be a geometry of rank r. Then no two distinct elements of the
same type are incident.
Proof. Suppose not. Then there exist two distinct elements of the same type which
are incident. Then these elements, by definition form a flag. Now, these elements
must be elements of some maximal flag, F. But then F has two elements of the
same type, but this is a contradiction because G is a geometry of rank r.
Thus, as we saw with the Euclidean geometry, two lines are incident if and only
if they are truly the same line. Often for geometries of rank 2 the types of elements
are termed points and lines. This is the case for the projective spaces which are
the focus of this paper.
The above axioms are used to define the following general structures.
Definition 2.2. A projective space is a geometry of rank 2 which satisfies the first
three axioms. If it also satisfies the fourth, it is called nondegenerate.
Definition 2.3. A projective plane is a nondegenerate projective space with Axiom
2 replaced by the stronger statement: Any two lines have at least one point in
common.
It is not too difficult to show that projective planes are indeed two dimensional
as expected, although the notion of dimension for a geometry is defined further into
the paper. A projective plane is therefore what one might naturally consider it to
be. It is a plane, according to the usual conception of such, in which all lines meet
as is expected from the term projective.
PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY 3
Definition 3.7. Let P have diminsion d. Then subspaces of dimension 2 are called
planes, and subspaces of dimension d − 1 are called hyperplanes.
Finally, we give a very important theorem from linear algebra which appears all
over mathematics. The proof is not given here, but it is not too difficult and again
not far from its linear algebra counterpart.
Theorem 3.8 (Dimension Formula). Suppose U and W are subspaces of P. Then
dim(hU, Wi) = dim(U) + dim(W) − dim(U ∩ W).
4. Quotient Geometries
Another important question to consider when looking at finite and even infinite
geometries is how new ones can be found from existing ones. One method for
deriving new methods is akin to projecting down to a lower dimension by making
lines into points and points into lines. Thus, we define the quotient geometry.
Definition 4.1. Suppose Q is a point of the geometry P, then the quotient geom-
etry of Q is the rank 2 geometry P/Q whose points are the lines through Q, and
whose lines are the planes through Q. The incidence structure is as induced by P.
Once we have several geometries of the same dimension, it is quite natural to
ask whether they are in fact the same geometry. Therefore we need the notion of
an isomorphism of geometries.
Definition 4.2. Suppose there are two rank 2 geometries: G = (P, B, I) and
G0 = (P 0 , B 0 , I 0 ). If there is a map φ
φ : P ∪ B → P 0 ∪ B0
where P is mapped bijectively to P 0 and B to B 0 such that the incidence structure
is preserved, then this map is an isomorphism from G to G0 . An automorphism is
an isomorphism of a rank two geometry to itself. When the geometry has elements
termed ’lines’, such as for projective planes, the automorphism is alternatively
called a collineation.
Theorem 4.3. Suppose P is a projective space of dimension d, and let Q ∈ P.
Then P/Q is a projective space of dimension d − 1.
Proof. It is enough to show that P/Q is isomorphic to a hyperplane which does not
pass through Q. In the first place, such a hyperplane exists. Extend Q to a basis
{Q, P1 , . . . , Pd } of P. Then the subspace H spanned by P1 , . . . , Pd has dimension
d − 1 and so is a hyperplane not containing Q since Q was in the basis and is thus
independent of the Pi .
Next, we must show that H is isomorphic to P/Q. Define a map φ from the
points g and lines π of P/Q to those of H by
φ : g → g ∩ H.φ : π → π ∩ H.
Remember that the points of Q ∈ P are lines of P which are incident with Q and
the lines are the planes of P incident to Q. Now, we must show that φ is a bijection
which preserves the incidence structure:
Injective: Suppose g, h ∈ P/Q, meaning they are lines going through Q. Suppose
both intersect H at the same point X. Then they have two points, Q and X in
common. Since X ∈ H and Q ∈ / H, these are distinct points and thus distinct
PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY 5
lines. Similarly, if π and σ are planes through Q intersecting H at the same line,
then they must be the same planes since they share a line and a point which are
not incident.
Surjective: Suppose X ∈ H, then the line QX is a point in P/Q which maps to
it. Likewise, if π ∈ H is a line, then the plane π ∈ P defined by Q and the line π
is a line of P/Q which maps to it.
Incidence: Suppose g a point and π a line in P/Q. Then
g ⊆ π ⇔ g ∩ H ⊆ π ∩ H ⇔ φ(g) ⊆ φ(π)
Thus, P/Q is a projective space of dimension d − 1.
In particular, this lemma implies that all lines of a projective plane are incident
with the same number of points, making projective geometries particularrly nice.
Definition 5.2. The order of a finite projective space is denoted by q and is one
less than the number of points incident with each line (which is a fixed number by
the preceding lemma).
The dimension, d, one less than the number of points in the geometry, and the
order q are the two important parameters for a finite projective space. In fact,
two geometries with the same order and dimension are isomorphic. Additionally,
knowing these two numbers, many others calculations can be made regarding the
finite projective plane.
Lemma 5.3. Suppose P is a finite projective space with dimension d and order q.
Then for every point Q, P/Q also has order q.
Proof. By Theorem 4.3 we know that P/Q is isomporphic to any hyperplane, and
so we have that P/Q is a projective space of order q.
Theorem 5.4. Suppose P is a finite projective space with dimension d and order
q. Let U is a t-dimensional subspace of P. Then:
(a) The number of points of the subspace is:
q t+1 − 1
q t + q t−1 + . . . + q + 1 = .
q−1
(b) The number of lines of U through a fixed point of U is:
q t−1 + . . . + q + 1.
(c) The total number of lines of U is:
(q t + q t−1 + . . . + q + 1)(q t−1 + . . . + q + 1)
.
q+1
Proof. We start with induction on t to prove the first two claims. Suppose t = 1,
then from Lemma 5.1 and the definition of order, the subspace clearly has q + 1
points, and being a line itself, has one line.
Suppose the first two claims hold for t − 1 ≥ 1. Then, by Theorem 4.3 and
Lemma 5.3 we have that the quotient geometry is a projective space of dimension
t−1 and has order q. By induction the number of points of U/Q is q t−1 +. . .+q +1,
which by definition is the number of lines of U through Q, which gives the second
claim.
Then, because there are q points on these lines through Q which are distinct
from Q, and each point of the subspace U must lie on precisely one of these lines,
we have
1 + (q t−1 + . . . + q + 1)q = q t + q t−1 + . . . + q + 1
points in U, completing the induction.
For the final part, note that U has q t + q t−1 + . . . + q + 1 points and each point
PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY 7
is on exactly q t−1 + . . . + q + 1 lines which each have q + 1 points. Thus the number
of lines of this subspace must be
(q t + q t−1 + . . . + q + 1)(q t−1 + . . . + q + 1)
q+1
as desired.
Theorem 5.5. Suppose P is a finite projective space with dimension d and order
q. Then,
(1) The number of hyperplanes of P is exactly
q d + . . . + q + 1.
(2) The number of hyperplanes of P through a fixed point is
q d−1 + . . . + q + 1.
Proof. (1) Use induction on d. Suppose d = 1. Then the claim is that any line
has q + 1 points, which follow by definition, and if d = 2, then the claim
follows from the preceding theorem.
Suppose the claim holds for dimension d − 1. Consider a hyperplane H
of P. Then all other hyperplanes intersect it in a subspace of dimension
d − 2. So any hyperplane distinct from H is spanned by a d − 2 dimensional
subspace U of H and a point P outside of H.
The for every such subspace and point, hU, P i is a hyperplane containing
(q d−1 + . . . + q + 1) − (q d−2 + . . . + q + 1) = q d−1
points not in H. Likewise, there are q d points of P outside of H, giving
a total of q hyperplanes through every U which are distinct from H. By
induction, there are q d−1 + . . . + q + 1 hyperplanes of H. This means that
there are q hyperplanes of the space P corresponding to each subspace of
H. Thus there are
q(q d−1 + . . . + q + 1) = q d + . . . + q + 1
hyperplanes as desired.
(2) Suppose P is a point of P and H is a hyperplane not intersecting P . Then
every hyperplane of P through P must intersect H in a hyperplane of H.
By the previous part, there are precisely q d−1 +. . .+q +1 such hyperplanes.
Corollary 5.6. Suppose P is a finite projective plane. Then there exists q ≥ 2 such
that any line has exactly q + 1 points and the total number of points is q 2 + q + 1.
This number q is simply the order of the finite projective plane. The next section
investigates a finite projective plane of order 2.
References
[1] Albrecht Beutelspacher and Ute Rosenbaum. Projective Geometry. Cambridge University
Press. 1998.
[2] Lynn Margaret Batten. Combinatorics of Finite Geometries. Cambridge University Press.
1986.