(Socks, Shoes, Watches, Shirts, ... ) (Index, Middle, Ring, Pinky)
(Socks, Shoes, Watches, Shirts, ... ) (Index, Middle, Ring, Pinky)
First we specify a common property among "things" (we define this word later)
and then we gather up all the "things" that have this common property.
For example, the items you wear: hat, shirt, jacket, pants, and so on.
Notation
There is a fairly simple notation for sets. We simply list each element (or
"member") separated by a comma, and then put some curly brackets around
the whole thing:
The three dots ... are called an ellipsis, and mean "continue on".
So that means the first example continues on ... for infinity.
(OK, there isn't really an infinite amount of things you could wear, but I'm not
entirely sure about that! After an hour of thinking of different things, I'm still
not sure. So let's just say it is infinite for this example.)
So:
But sometimes the "..." can be used in the middle to save writing long lists:
{a, b, c, ..., x, y, z}
Numerical Sets
So what does this have to do with mathematics? When we define a set, all we
have to specify is a common characteristic. Who says we can't do so with
numbers?
And the list goes on. We can come up with all different types of sets.
There can also be sets of numbers that have no common property, they are
just defined that way. For example:
{2, 3, 6, 828, 3839, 8827}
{4, 5, 6, 10, 21}
{2, 949, 48282, 42882959, 119484203}
Math can get amazingly complicated quite fast. Graph Theory, Abstract
Algebra, Real Analysis, Complex Analysis, Linear Algebra, Number
Theory, and the list goes on. But there is one thing that all of these share
in common: Sets.
Universal Set
At the start we used the word "things" in quotes.
Now you don't have to listen to the standard, you can use something like m to
represent a set without breaking any mathematical laws (watch out, you can
get π years in math jail for dividing by 0), but this notation is pretty nice and
easy to follow, so why not?
Also, when we say an element a is in a set A, we use the symbol to show it.
And if something is not in a set use .
Equality
Two sets are equal if they have precisely the same members. Now, at first
glance they may not seem equal, so we may have to examine them closely!
A is the set whose members are the first four positive whole numbers
B = {4, 2, 1, 3}
Let's check. They both contain 1. They both contain 2. And 3, And 4. And we
have checked every element of both sets, so: Yes, they are equal!
A=B
A is {1, 2, 3}
B is {3, 1, 2}
Subsets
When we define a set, if we take pieces of that set, we can form what is called
a subset.
A subset of this is {1, 2, 3}. Another subset is {3, 4} or even another is {1},
etc.
But {1, 6} is not a subset, since it has an element (6) which is not in the
parent set.
In general:
3 is in A and 3 is also in B.
4 is in A, and 4 is in B.
That's all the elements of A, and every single one is in B, so we're done.
Yes, A is a subset of B
Well, we can't check every element in these sets, because they have an infinite
number of elements. So we need to get an idea of what the elements look like
in each, and then compare them.
By pairing off members of the two sets, we can see that every member of A is
also a member of B, but not every member of B is a member of A:
So:
Proper Subsets
If we look at the defintion of subsets and let our mind wander a bit, we come to
a weird conclusion.
This little piece at the end is only there to make sure that A is not a proper
subset of itself. Otherwise, a proper subset is exactly the same as a normal
subset.
Example:
Example:
When we talk about proper subsets, we take out the line underneath and so it
becomes A B or if we want to say the opposite, A B.
This is known as the Empty Set (or Null Set).There aren't any elements in it.
Not one. Zero.
It is represented by
Some other examples of the empty set are the set of countries south of the
south pole.
So what's so weird about the empty set? Well, that part comes next.
Going back to our definition of subsets, if every element in the empty set is
also in A, then the empty set is a subset of A. But what if we
have no elements?
A good way to think about it is: we can't find any elements in the empty set
that aren't in A, so it must be that all elements in the empty set are in A.
So the answer to the posed question is a resounding yes.
The empty set is a subset of every set, including the empty set itself.
Order
No, not the order of the elements. In sets it does not matter what order the
elements are in.
A finite set has finite order (or cardinality). An infinite set has infinite order (or
cardinality).
For infinite sets, all we can say is that the order is infinite. Oddly enough, we
can say with sets that some infinities are larger than others, but this is a more
advanced topic in sets.