100% found this document useful (1 vote)
606 views545 pages

LIVRO GEOGRAFIA HUMANA Ron - Johnston - James - Sidaway - Geography - An PDF

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
100% found this document useful (1 vote)
606 views545 pages

LIVRO GEOGRAFIA HUMANA Ron - Johnston - James - Sidaway - Geography - An PDF

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 545

Geography and Geographers

Geography and Geographers provides a survey of the major debates, key thinkers and schools of thought
in human geography in the English-speaking world, setting them within the context of economic,
social, cultural and political, as well as intellectual, changes. It focuses on the debates among
geographers regarding what their discipline should study and how that should be done, and draws
on a wide reading of the geographical literature produced during a seventy-year period characterised
by both growth in the number of academic geographers and substantial shifts in conceptions of the
discipline’s scientific rationale.
The pace and volume of change within the discipline show little sign of diminishing; this
seventh edition covers new literature and important developments over the past decade. An
insightful and reflective examination of the field from within, Geography and Geographers continues to
be the most comprehensive and up-to-date single volume overview of the field of human geography.
This seventh edition has also been extensively revised and updated to reflect developments
in the ways that geography and its history are understood and taught. Providing a thoroughly
contemporary perspective, the book maintains its standing as the essential resource for students and
researchers across the field.

Ron Johnston is Professor of Geography at the University of Bristol.

James D. Sidaway is Professor of Political Geography at the National University of Singapore.


Praise for the fifth edition of Geography and Geographers:

‘[Geography and Geographers] has probably done more to shape human geographers’ collective sense of
what geography is and has been about than any other single source.’
Murray Low, Political Geography (2004)

Praise for this edition of Geography and Geographers:

‘This new edition of Geography and Geographers is especially welcome. By providing what the
authors call “wider discussions of the contexts” within which geographical endeavour has
been located, it shows that the historical geography of geography has come of age. As a working
map of the territory, this is a superlative piece of intellectual cartography that no geographer
wanting to orientate themselves can afford to be without.’
Professor David N. Livingstone, Queen’s University Belfast, Northern Ireland

‘Geography and Geographers is a living classic. It provides a compelling and subtle narrative of the
key intellectual shifts shaping contemporary geography, one that is sensitive to the range of factors
that shape academic knowledge. An invaluable resource for scholars from students to professors,
and an intellectual achievement in its own right.’
Professor Clive Barnett, Professor of Geography and Social Theory,
University of Exeter, UK

‘Tony Blair once said that the Beatles produced the “music that was the background of our
lives”. Geography and Geographers is the constant in the background of the busy and changing life of
geography. You can always count on it, and it is a comforting and reassuring presence. Like the
Beatles’ music you never tire of it, and it seems to get better with age.’
Professor Trevor Barnes, Department of Geography,
University of British Columbia, Canada
Geography and
Geographers
Anglo–American
human geography since 1945

Seventh Edition
Ron Johnston and James D. Sidaway
Seventh edition published 2016
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 1979 R.J Johnston © 2016 Ron Johnston and James D. Sidaway
The right of Ron Johnston and James D. Sidaway to be identified as authors of this
work has been asserted by them in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised
in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or
hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information
storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered
trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to
infringe.
First edition published by Edward Arnold 1979
Sixth edition published by Hodder Arnold 2004
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Johnston, R. J. (Ronald John)
 Geography & geographers : Anglo-American human geography since 1945 /
R.J. Johnston and J.D. Sidaway. — Seventh Edition.
   pages cm
  Includes bibliographical references and index.
 1. Human geography—United States—History.  2. Human geography—Great
Britain—History.  I. Sidaway, James D.  II. Title.  III. Title: Geography and
geographers.
  GF13.J63 2016
  304.2—dc23 2015027516

ISBN: 978-0-415-82737-9 (hbk)


ISBN: 978-0-340-98510-6 (pbk)
ISBN: 978-0-203-52305-6 (ebk)

Typeset in Joanna
by Keystroke, Station Road, Codsall, Wolverhampton
For Lorna, Josh and Heather
And commemorating Jasmin Leila and Joseph Trevor
This page intentionally left blank
Contents

List of figures xi
Preface xiii
Acknowledgements xxiii

1 The nature of an academic discipline 1


Academic life: the occupational structure  2
Disciplines and institutionalisation  9
The academic working environment: disciplines and the academic
  division of labour  12
The external environment  26
Conclusions  35

2 Foundations 37
Geography in the modern period  38
Paradigms in the modern period  42
Historical geography  52
Geography in the early 1950s  54
Conclusions  55

3 Growth of systematic studies and the adoption of scientific method 57


The critique of regional geography  58
Schaefer’s (1953) paper and the response  59
Developments in systematic geography in the USA  64
Scientific method in human geography  76
Spread of the scientific method  83
Conclusions  98

4 Human geography as spatial science 100


Spatial variables and spatial systems  101
Spatial theory?  105
Systems  110
Spatial separatism?  121
Behavioural geography  124
Spatial (or geo-)statistics  145
Geographical Information Systems to Geographical Information Science  157
Conclusions  166
viii Contents

5 Humanistic geography 169


Humanistic geography’s antecedents in cultural and historical geography  171
Alternatives to spatial science  174
The practice of humanistic geography  186
Conclusions  194

6 Radical geography 197


Geography from the left  199
Radical trajectories  201
Structuralist Marxisms, regulation theory, localities and regions  207
Critical realism and structuration theory  219
The production of ‘nature’  221
Radicals in debate  223
What’s left  235
Conclusions  239

7 Postmodernism, poststructuralism and postcolonialism 242


Posts- and turns  242
Postmodernism  246
Poststructuralism: power, representation and performance  257
Deconstructing maps and critical geopolitics  262
Poststructuralist geographies  265
Actor-network theory (ANT), affect and non-representational theories (NRTs)  268
Postcolonialism: decolonising human geography?  272
Conclusions  278

8 Feminist geography 281


The other half  283
Diverse strands  285
Reassessing histories of geography  288
From the geography of women to socialist feminisms  292
Feminist geographies of difference  296
Sexuality and space  300
Queering geography 302
Conclusions  304

9 Applied geography and the relevance debates 308


Disenchantment and disillusion in academic geography  310
Relevance to what and for whom?  313
Liberal contributions  319
Inequality, justice and ethics  325
Environmentalism  326
Geographers and policy  332
Changing contexts and applied geography  336
Continuing debates: grey, public and participatory geographies  340
Conclusions  344
Contents ix

10 A changing discipline? 345


Human geographers and models of disciplinary progress  346
Geography and its environment  355
Geographers and their networks  360
A structure for the discipline?  364
Human geography’s response to challenges  366
A generational model?  373
Geographies of geography?  375
Recapping: human geography as paradigms, streams or traditions?  378
An abundance of turbulence  389
And the future?  398

References 400
Author index 493
Subject index 507
This page intentionally left blank
Figures

  1.1 The academic career ladder 3


  2.1 The foundation of departments of geography and of chairs in geography
in British universities 40
  3.1 Two routes to scientific explanation 70
  3.2 The geography matrix: each cell – ij – contains a ‘geographic fact’,
the value of characteristic i at location j 88
  3.3 A third dimension to the geographic matrix: each cell – ijt – contains a
‘geographic fact’, the value of characteristic i at location j at time t 89
  3.4 Geographic flow matrices – one per commodity (Cl – Cn) per time period 90
  4.1 The elements in Haggett’s schema for studying spatial systems 102
  4.2 Types of system: A, B and C indicate system elements, I represents input,
O represents output, and in the control system A is a value 112
  4.3 Various types of feedback relationships in systems 113
  4.4 The time–space prism 131
  4.5 The behavioural matrix 136
  4.6 Choice sets in the spatial decision-making process 139
  4.7 The society–environment interface 143
  6.1 A geographical interpretation of Lévi-Strauss’s cam-shaft for structuralism 210
  6.2 International financial links of South East England 218
  6.3 Models of the relationships between society and individual 231
  7.1 The shrinking map of the world through innovations in transport that
‘annihilate space through time’ 253
  7.2 Cage’s score for Fontanta Mix (1958) 270
  8.1 Interwoven strands of feminist geography 287
10.1 Geography’s context 357
10.2 Schools of modern and postmodern thought 392
10.3 Disciplinary space: the ‘map’ of changing approaches in human geography 393
This page intentionally left blank
Preface
Situating Geography and Geographers

I remember being at a party in Minneapolis, sitting on the floor with other guests in a loose
circle, taking turns saying what we did. There was a nurse, a medical researcher, a planner . . .
When I said I was a graduate student in economic geography, one of them burst into
uncontrollable laughter. ‘So what do you do, find new places?’
(Trevor Barnes, 2002, p. 9)

I do think that sometimes we have written the history of geography as though it were something
quite exotic but harmless, consigned, at the very least, to the last century, if not to oblivion:
from our lofty positions as postmoderns, postcolonials or whatever, we detach ourselves from
our predecessors without so much as a backward glance. Isn’t it about time we took a more
modest view? Perhaps that history which we want to transcend is precisely what makes our
own geographies possible? Now there’s a thought.
(Felix Driver, 2003, p. 230)

Geographers themselves have been very bad at writing their own history.
(Neil Smith, 2003, p. xxii)

the story of . . . geography . . . cannot be narrated in isolation from a much wider global and
historical framework.
(David Livingstone, 2003a, p. 13)

The digital age means that many of the correspondences vanish the moment they are sent;
even the fax paper we used has disintegrated 20 years on. So we offer this historical narration
in order to begin the process of active remembering of the recent past in an attempt to avoid
what has plagued the history of geography – its erasure of women and gender.
(Mona Domosh and Liz Bondi, 2014, p. 1068)

Human geography has been through many changes – in terms of its foci, practices, methods and
styles of presentation. Reflecting aspects of this, between 1979 and the end of the twentieth century
there were five previous editions of this book (1979, 1983, 1987, 1991, 1997), all sole authored
by Ron Johnston. When a further, sixth, jointly authored edition appeared in 2004, we explained
some of the changes made and the rationales behind these. By way of an entrée to this seventh
edition, we first cite from that Preface to the sixth:

Since 1979, the book has expanded considerably. In order to contain it within reasonable margins,
in this sixth edition we have cut back some of the details on behavioural geography that appeared
in the earlier editions (veteran readers will notice that this no longer has a chapter of its own)
and shortened some other sections. These selective cuts have allowed us to accommodate more
on poststructuralism, postmodernism, postcolonialism and feminist geographies (through two
xiv Preface

new chapters derived in part from what hitherto was a single chapter entitled ‘The cultural
turn’), as well as to rearrange the chapter on radical geography and update others. In all cases
we have sought to strike a balance between length and scope. Nor are we trying to write-out
episodes of the history of the discipline. More or less everything covered in past editions remains
here. We have however – with the benefit of hindsight – shifted the emphases somewhat. As with
previous editions, the specific trajectories of significant subdisciplines, such as population,
development, medical/health, or political geography (to name but four) are neglected here – on
account of our word limit; such reviews appear annually in the journal Progress in Human
Geography and are a feature of Gaile and Willmott’s (1989, 2004) collections. However, we are
aware that from such subdisciplinary vantage points, the shifts that Geography and Geographers
outlines would be illuminated in different ways. In part, this is because the respective
subdisciplines have been influenced by changes in the subjects with which they (sometimes
uneasily) share affiliation; development geography with development studies and branches
of area studies, for example. In part, it is because paradigmatic change in human geography
has always been profoundly uneven, with individuals in some places, departments and fields
of study setting agendas that only later came to have much wider influence across a
heterodox discipline.
  The addition of new material on recent trends in the discipline is complemented here by wider
discussions of the contexts within which earlier disciplinary debates and developments occurred.
The last decade has seen an increase in the amount of research and writing on the history of
human geography since 1945 – especially on the decades prior to 1980. This has included not
only retrospectives written by those involved and other biographical works, but also by scholarly
interpretations of some of the major events and personalities produced by those interested in
applying the perspectives and methods of the history of science to geography. As in the previous
editions, however, the book depends almost entirely for its source material on the published
record, on ‘the written statements of others’ as it was described in the original Preface (on which
approach see also Keylock, 2003, and Lorimer, 2003). But that published record now includes a
substantial volume of historical and interpretative material, which means that this current
edition is less a history created from the contemporary debates and substantive contributions
and more reliant – particularly in the earlier chapters – on biographical and autobiographical
recollections of the conditions of their production.
  The growth of historiographical work on recent human geography is in itself indicative of the
importance that many geographers give to an appreciation of their discipline’s past. Some
authors contend that this is unnecessary: Barnett (1995, p. 417), for example, has ‘doubts about
the value of expending energy studying the history of geography as a means of throwing light on
the state of the discipline today’ (see also Thrift, 2002). We are not so sure. Appreciation of a
discipline’s history – of where it has come from, and why it has its current contemporary form –
is not only valuable when, as Barnett accepts, it is deployed in a ‘political’ context to sustain its
professional identity, but also for an understanding of the discipline’s present condition. To
paraphrase Marx, ‘geographers have made – and continue to make – geography, but not in
conditions of their own choosing’. Geographers are socialised into intellectual communities with
accepted bodies of knowledge and practices, and their orientations are constrained, though not
determined, by the nature of the communities they join – as argued by one of the theories (of
structuration . . .) which a number of them have adopted to guide their work. Furthermore, the
practice of geography itself illustrates one of the discipline’s major contributions to the
deployment of Marx’s dictum: the ‘conditions not of their own choosing’ within which geographers
operate are themselves spatially variable. Studying the history of geography – especially the
recent history – is valuable not only for the light that it sheds on what geographers are and do
today, but also for the case study it provides of a wider concern – the geography of knowledge
production and the importance of context therein.
Preface xv

  Finally, what of the ‘Anglo-American’ in the subtitle? In recent years, the Anglo-Americanness
of human geography has come under increased scrutiny. In the first place, several geographers
have pointed to the continued (indeed in some ways increasing) relative dominance of English
language geography vis-à-vis geography written in other languages (Desbiens, 2002; Garcia-
Ramon, 2003; Gutiérrez and López-Nieva, 2001; Minca 2000; Short et al., 2001; see also
Rodríguez-Pose, 2004). Thus Vaiou (2003, p. 136), writing from Greece, notes that: ‘the power-
knowledge system, in which Anglophone scholarship can posit itself as international and even
universal has not (yet?) totally subsumed local initiatives’.
  Others have questioned what is excluded and included when the term Anglo-American is used
(Samers and Sidaway, 2000; Minca, 2003). Not only are the USA and the UK (and geographers
working in these countries) far from being exclusively ‘Anglo’, but geography produced there
contains many ‘foreign’ influences – as will become clear in the chapters that follow. The way
that other predominantly anglophone contexts and geographers (for example, Australia, South
Africa and New Zealand) are marginalised has also been critiqued (Berg and Kearns, 1998). The
fact that one of the co-authors of this new edition is based in neither the UK nor North America,
but in Singapore (although he was educated in the UK and has held academic posts there), and
that some of his own geographical research has been conducted in Portuguese- and Spanish-
speaking milieux has sharpened our sense of this (as Gregory, 1994, has also written regarding
the impact of his move from the UK to Canada on his ‘positionality’); the other author spent the
first eleven years of his career in Australia and New Zealand, to which he has frequently returned.
Nevertheless, we have retained the subtitle ‘Anglo-American Human Geography since 1945’. But
the book should be read with the caveat that it remains a survey of key debates within English
language human geography in the past sixty years, with a primary focus on the UK and
anglophone North America. Even within this particular geographical tradition, we cannot
adequately cover everything, however. More than twenty years ago, in a debate on the place of
Marxism within radical geography (one of our concerns in Chapter 6), Walmsley and Sorenson
(1980, p. 137) reminded readers of the UK-based journal Area that: ‘To speak of a “Marxist
approach” [in geography] is therefore to distil a highest common factor from a variety of writings.’
Our distillations here mean that this is not the story of anglophone human geography (which is
itself is certainly not the story of human geography tout court over the past sixty-odd years). To
pretend otherwise would take us into the realm of the mythological map described by the
Argentinian Jose Luis Borges in one of his extraordinary fables. In Borges’s story, the
cartographers of an imaginary empire draw up a map so detailed that it ends up exactly covering
the territory so that the ‘real’ territory underneath the map is obscured. The people of this
empire came to relate more closely to this map than they did to the original territory underneath
(they live, work and play on it, etc.) When eventually the map frays and disintegrates, the people
are unnerved and nostalgic for the map they once knew and lived upon, feeling that they have
lost something of their reality.
  Our account of Geography and Geographers makes no such claims to be a replacement for an
encounter with the original writings that are précised here. Moreover, readers should not be
unnerved if they find – as they venture out into the broader fields of human geography – that some
things are not quite as neat or clear as they might have been led to believe from this text alone.
(Johnston and Sidaway, 2004, pp. x–xii)

This conundrum crops up in the prefaces or introductions to many other textbooks or edited
volumes on geographic thought. Most recently, the introduction to an edited Handbook of Human
Geography (one of the multiplying quantity of such multi-author compilations) invites readers ‘to
engage with the current structure and contents of the text through critical reflection on extant
closures and absences, distortions and reflection on the ways in which these limitations might be
addressed’ (R. Lee et al., 2014, p. ix). Such invitations perform some of the function that warning
xvi Preface

readers of incompleteness and compression does in prior textbooks, such as James Bird’s (1993,
p. viii) advisory that ‘Where this guide tries to summarise the arguments of whole books and
papers, there is a danger that compression will have telescoped stages of those arguments’. An
introduction to Philosophy and Human Geography (Johnston, 1983a), which one of us wrote as a
companion to the second edition of Geography and Geographers, similarly begins with a declaration
that ‘All that is attempted is an introduction to the nature of the philosophies which human
geographers are now exploring; any student wishing to join the quest will need to read a great deal
more’ (p. vii). The challenge multiplies along with the caveats that preface other recent textbooks.
Thus, Nayak and Jeffrey (2011, p. xv) claim to be providing ‘an aperture with no attempt at closure’,
and Cresswell (2013, p. 3) wants to:

make no claims to completeness. Geographers, like practitioners of many other disciplines, are
constantly arguing about ideas. Often it is the people who are supposed to be in agreement that are
doing the arguing. We are used to the idea of advocates of competing ideas clashing with each
other. In these arguments large numbers of people are lumped together as ‘positivists’ or ‘Marxists’
for instance. But if we look closely we find that these groups are constantly arguing with each other
too, over what it means to be a positivist or a Marxist. A book like this cannot hope to recount each
and every one of those arguments. Such a book would be an encyclopedia of many volumes . . .
This is a road map and there are many small towns and hamlets and even some major cities that
these roads do not connect. You will have to go off road occasionally to find them.

In providing our own fairly fine-grained ‘road map’, we also realise that at times Geography and
Geographers risks becoming a crammed and wearisome atlas, especially for those ‘off-roaders’.
Some readers might prefer either a detailed map of their particular area of interests or a simpler
sketch of the whole of disciplinary territory. For those who do want a (portable and printable)
disciplinary atlas, however, we do our best to provide a serviceable one here: within the limits
afforded by a single volume. However, the sheer impossibility of doing justice to the entire
substance of anglophone human geography looms even larger more than a decade on from the
last edition of our book. Many of the debates and changes that we flagged in that 2004 Preface
have continued to rage. New historical work on the discipline has appeared, opening up the
range of and contexts to what counts as geographical scholarship. When the first edition was
published in 1979, the breadth and depth of work on the history of ideas and debate in human
geography was much smaller. The Preface to an earlier survey, first published in the UK in 1961,
but later republished in Chicago (1962) and subsequently reprinted several times in the 1960s,
could begin with a note that ‘The history of geography is not an over-tilled field . . .’ (Freeman,
1962, p. 9). That relative paucity of such scholarship meant that Geography and Geographers found a
ready market in 1979. The author of what would later become a key work on The Geographical
Tradition (Livingstone, 1992) has noted how the attempt to sample and describe the evolving field
of human geography registered in the first edition of this book was a source of ‘consolation’ to
someone interested in geography’s history:

When Geography and geographers first appeared in 1979, I was still a graduate student working
in a rather isolated situation on the history of geographical knowledge in nineteenth century
America. I well remember the sense of excitement I felt when the book came out that matters
of history and theory were beginning to be taken with much greater seriousness in the
discipline. Geography and geographers, together with one or two other recently published
items, were opening the door to a greater critical spirit, to a desire to connect the subject with
wider currents of intellectual moment, and to a concern to locate human geography’s
coordinates in a broader scholarly landscape.
(p. 45)
Preface xvii

Fifteen years later, he added:

The appearance of Ron Johnston’s Geography and geographers in 1979 did an enormous service
in recovering and imposing coherence on human geography’s collective memory, and thus its
identity, since 1945. It had a major role in reawakening the subject’s historical consciousness
and injecting new life into the study of its narrative.
(Livingstone, 2007, p. 43)

The task of recovering and imposing that coherence has increased exponentially over the
thirty-seven years since the appearance of the first edition, reflecting not just the expansions in
human geographical scholarship and the ever-broadening canvass of geographical research, but
also a growing volume of biographical and autobiographical works, providing new insights to
specific events in disciplinary history and much changed (and still changing) economic, political
and institutional contexts in which those practices were situated. When the lecture course on
which the first edition was based was first given in 1975, subsequent twists in ‘the intellectual
diversity of the discipline, the contingencies of its historical trajectories, and the stresses and
strains of its institutional architectures’ (Livingstone, 2007, p. 43) could hardly have been
imagined.
Reflecting on those previous editions, one of us (Johnston, 2007a, p. 48) indicated that not
only was he reluctant to produce the sixth but also that having done so he was even more convinced
that there should not be a seventh – not least because commentators had indicated that after thirty
years there needed to be ‘a profound recasting of the venture’ and ‘a more compelling and expressly
geographical argument about human geography’ (Johnston, 2007a, p. 50). He agreed, being not
only ‘very unsure whether such a major project is feasible’ but also even more certain that, as a
senior, he no longer had a broad and deep enough appreciation of the multifaceted discipline to
undertake it: it was ‘time for somebody else to take up the challenge’ (p. 50). Yet here he is, having
been convinced by James that a further edition was both desirable and feasible, with some
restructuring. Geography and Geographers is, after all, just two authors’ take on seventy years of disciplinary
histories: others take different positions – and our appreciation of history advances by bringing
them into contact: out of different theses a new synthesis might emerge, which in turn will
stimulate further anti-theses. And so the book’s structure has remained largely unchanged, but what
became clear in its revision was that one of us is much more comfortable revisiting the earlier
decades and the continuation of certain types of work in the light of more recent publications while
the other has kept pace with changes in the last decade. Thus the overarching message – as
transmitted in the final chapter – endures (though not unaltered in the light of events), but the
material on which it is based continues to broaden and deepen. However pessimistic we may be
about the state of the world and the challenges universities face as contexts for geographical
scholarship since the sixth edition was written in 2003, we remain enthusiastic about and impressed
by human geography’s continued flowering and vitality. And we are glad that others join us in
arguing that

teaching the history of geography matters to the disciplinary present – not because it offers a
neat and Whiggish explanation of how things came to be as they are now, but because it functions
as a whetstone against which students’ critical thinking is honed. At its most effective, such
teaching offers insight into the complex making and breaking of ideas, into the complex social
circumstances which govern the production, circulation, and reception of knowledge, and into
the ways in which questions of race, gender, and class permeate and inform all we do. It is
precisely the messy, nonlinear and conflicted nature of geography’s history that provides its
most valuable and transferable lessons.
(Keighren et al., 2015, p. 3)
xviii Preface

Today, there are several new books that tackle the same or similar ground as Geography and Geographers
(e.g. Couper, 2015; Cox, 2014; Cresswell, 2013; Nayak and Jeffrey, 2011; Holt-Jensen, 2009, a fourth
edition of another that is translated from Norwegian) adding to the crop that appeared (sometimes as
new editions) in the 1990s or early 2000s (Bird, 1993; Cloke et al., 1991; Martin, 2005; Peet, 1998;
T. Unwin, 1992 – we have been unable to incorporate the many insights offered by Geoffrey Martin’s
(2015) magnum opus, published at about the time we submitted this manuscript, but we are flattered
by his chosen title), and others that add to our appreciation of the discipline’s recent history (such as
DeVivo, 2015, and Pacione, 2014), not to mention the increasing number of departmental histories,
many either privately published or available on the internet (http://old.geog.psu.edu/hog/dept_
histories.html provides a listing of those available in North America). Recently, too, the histories of key
moments and trends in human geography, especially the quantitative revolution and advent of spatial
science (the focus of Chapters 3 and 4) are subjects of fresh scholarship and debate regarding their
causes (e.g. Barnes and Farish, 2006; Barnes, 2008a, 2008b; Johnston et al., 2008). More recently,
there has also been deeper historical scrutiny of the emergence of radical and critical geography (our
focus in Chapter 6 as well as some of the discussion of applied geography in Chapter 9) from the
1960s and ‘until the mid-1980s, when key decisions were taken that moved radical/critical geography
into the mainstream of the discipline’ (Peake and Sheppard, 2014, p. 305). Moreover, among the
implications of feminism in geography (our focus in Chapter 8) have been significant challenges to
the way the history of the subject is recounted, who is included in such accounts, and what and who
has tended to be systematically neglected. In the words of a key book that challenges exclusions, by
focusing not only on what are taken to be the major debates and figures, but also ‘minor’ figures,
including those who may not have published much, but whose teaching and impacts have to be
recovered from archives such as university records, oral histories or even obituaries:

Those who held office in geographical societies, those who taught at universities and those who
wrote influential texts will be represented here, but so too will the work of school teachers,
teacher trainers, non-academic authors and those who might be called public servants, both
‘major’ and ‘minor’ figures.
(Maddrell, 2009, p. 12)

All this needs to be reckoned with. And it challenges us (and we trust our readers) to reconsider
the histories that Geography and Geographers recounts. In addition, some new (or rather renewed) cross-
cutting fields, around nature and the environment for example, have returned to a more central
position in disciplinary debates. Yet we cannot refuse the challenge of producing an updated survey.
The caveat is that we recognise more than ever that this cannot be comprehensive. However, we are
confident in claiming that the basic structure we decided on for the sixth edition still serves useful
purposes. Chief among these is encouraging readers to find paths into and through the realms of
human geography; to offer them a sense of how the parts, which they might otherwise not see far
beyond, might be fitted together and relate to those of the past.
Moreover, reviews of the sixth edition were encouraging in seeing value in the venture. Rogers
(2006, p. 546) notes how ‘Like the discipline it seeks to understand, the book shows no sign of
slowing down or losing direction’, while also complaining that ‘By being so thorough and
authoritative, there is a sense in which the book crowds out alternative readings, or at least
discourages curiosity’ (p. 547). That is not our intention. We don’t see a contradiction between the
arguments that we advance here and other ways into the discipline. Or, to be more exact, where
there might be, we encourage readers to mix and match and pick up other texts and the original
sources. In similar terms, Mark Boyle (2005, p. 161) declares that:

Geography and Geographers has undoubtedly been the formative text for many teachers currently
charged with the responsibility of delivering courses on the history and philosophy of the
Preface xix

discipline. Nevertheless, the addition of a whole series of new textbooks has opened up fresh
opportunities for those keen to deliver material in more innovative ways.

Those opportunities, he notes, might include:

1 Contextualist approaches, more explicitly locating geography in wider social, political and
economic backdrops. Geography and Geographers has always done some of that: in particular, the
account of the structure of disciplines and the regulation of universities has been a key to these
material backdrops. Blending this with sufficient account of wider social shifts remains a
challenge, given the primary focus here on how these were mediated in debates in the discipline.
2 Thematic approaches, which introduce how geographic thought impacts on and is read
through an object, such as globalization, or a region, such as Europe, or a theme, such as
nature–society or scale, that transcends a single subdiscipline and has been the subject of
changing approaches (such as Castree, 2005; Herod, 2009; Hinchliffe, 2007; Zimmerer,
2010). Such texts and accounts are not new. But Geography and Geographers works through a coarser
frame of reference, with the account organised according to the macro-framework of approach,
rather than the objects of the analysis per se.
3 Subdisciplinary approaches – accounts of, say, political, health, economic, cultural or
environmental geography as mirrors to the wider course of the discipline. There are very many
of these subdivisions, and they offer distinctive vantage points both on the wider trajectory of
geography, and on overlaps with and differences from other disciplines. For example,
investigation of these has formed the subject of a book-length study of the relationship
between history and historical geography, for example, in which Baker (2003, p. 206)
documents how ‘The academic battlefields of geography and history are littered with aphorisms
about each other, as well as about their “mysterious” offspring, historical geography’.
4 Speculating on the future rather than the past. In practice these date quickly (one of us edited
one, Johnston, 1985a) but nevertheless become useful mirrors to the issues at a particular
moment (as in Dixon and Jones, 2004).
5 Focus on the wider performance of geography, rather than its canon of writings or concepts
(on which a conference was held in Oxford in June 2012 which contributes to a special issue
of the Journal of Historical Geography: R. C. Powell, 2015; see also the commentaries introduced by
Keighren et al., 2012). To some extent, Maddrell’s (2009) important account, as noted earlier,
moves in this direction. Others, notably Philo (1998), have pushed this in other directions,
charting student writings in a geographical magazine as a mirror to the consumption and
reproduction of the discipline. And for Sullivan (2011, pp. 2–3) geography is:

fraught with a perpetual identity crisis and thus overtly vulnerable to pre-emptive acts of
performance as geographers attempt to stake out geography as being determined by this or
that methodology or philosophical perspective. The history of geography can be viewed as
one long performative struggle, as ideographic and nomographic, qualitative and quantitative,
cultural and physical agonists feint and parry their way to some imagined dominance of the
profession, suing speech acts and other assorted performative acts (articles, presentations,
as well as hiring and tenure practices) as their weapons of choice.

6. Biography as an approach (such as Hubbard et al., 2004; and Lorimer and Withers 2007, 2014
– the latter is the 33rd volume in a superb series of Biobibliographical Studies of geographers
launched by the International Geographical Union’s Commission on the History of Geographical
Thought), sometimes supplemented by a focus on key texts (Hubbard et al., 2008).

These do not exhaust the possibilities. Matthew Gerike’s (2012) Ph.D. thesis on ‘Explorations
in Historiographies of Geographical Knowledges’ draws on biography and autobiography, but also
xx Preface

on correspondence (both published and unpublished), symposia and content analysis (of textbooks
and journals). Greater attention to the historical geography of geography has emerged, along with
further perspectives on international connections and flows (Best, 2014), though Seemann (2015,
p. 16) still laments the way that ‘The teaching of geography wrongly emphasises time over space.’
Similarly, in reviewing the range of ways that geographical theory can be represented, Cresswell
(2013, p. 12) suggests that:

It could be written through places where theories were developed: German geography in the late
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, radical theories in Clark University, Massachusetts,
spatial science at the University of Washington, or even the new cultural geography in Lampeter,
Wales.

In similar spirit, Trevor Barnes (2014, p. 204) wants to:

stress the importance of the geography of geography’s own knowledge, which is bound
inextricably to the history of the discipline. Geography’s geography is not mere background
colour, a gazetteer-like list of places, but must be conceptualized, theoretically connecting the
history of the discipline’s ideas with where they were produced and travelled.

Barnes joins those who are critical of this book’s chronological approach:

If their goal is to know what geographers ‘are and do’ [citing from p. xi of the 2004 edition of
Geography and Geographers] – that is, their work now – why do we need to study history? Wouldn’t
it be better to learn about geographers as they are currently, focusing on what they do in the
present?
(p. 205)

Furthermore, others who also approach geographic thought through narrating its historical shifts
(or, if preferred, Dt1–t2) have classified the structure and trajectory of geographical thought in
different ways from that developed in Geography and Geographers, such as the ‘four traditions’ (‘spatial’,
‘area studies’, ‘man-land’ and ‘earth science’) identified by Pattison (1964) and subsequently
revised by J. Lewis Robinson (1976). We touch upon and briefly return to some of these alternative
ways of studying the history of geography in the opening and concluding chapters. At this point,
however, we should reiterate that the focus of Geography and Geographers remains (as it has been since
1979) on the overall corpus of published writings in the field, and on claims and debates about
how geography should be practised rather than the subject matter of its practices. The book is
broadly chronological, though with inevitable jumps, discontinuities and interconnections.
Moreover reviewers have pushed us to reconsider and supplement the meta-framework inherited
from earlier editions – the account of paradigms and disciplinary structures/change that forms a
large part of Chapter 1 and which we also re-evaluate in the last chapter.
Our overall challenge is both enhanced and enabled by the continued vitality of human
geography in the last few decades. While the discipline has faced significant challenges regarding
its identity (in the UK, for example, increasingly ending up being merged with other disciplines
into university departments or Schools of the Environment, or Environmental and Earth Sciences,
and in some countries, such as Australia, almost disappearing as a single subject discipline), the
number of undergraduate students taking degrees in the subject has grown (in tandem with wider
growth in student numbers). The volume and range of specialist and generalist journals devoted to
geography has likewise increased (new, entirely online ones, have appeared, such as ACME:
An International E-Journal for Critical Geographies and Geography Compass), as have the number of text-
books, readers, encyclopaedias and companions offering guides to the field (see the accounts by
Preface xxi

Demeritt, 2008, and Johnston, 2010a). The vast archive of ‘Geographers on Film’, compiled
between 1970 and 2004 by Maynard W. Dow, is also being digitised and made more readily
available; it is likely to be a valuable research and teaching resource (G. Martin, 2013). We believe,
however, that there is still considerable value in this single-volume survey of the evolution of
human geography, paying attention to where it has come from. Such texts can be influential
(Johnston, 2006) and will never please all readers. But to abandon an attempt to survey human
geography through the means and methods of Geography and Geographers seems to us to miss an
opportunity of enriching debate, including or inculcating new voices – hence this seventh edition.
In short, we judge that the original rationale (as well as the limits) of such a survey are still valid,
approaching four decades on from the first edition. These were described in the Preface to that first
edition (that full Preface and all subsequent Prefaces also appear in the fifth edition) as follows:

Most students reading for a degree or similar qualification are required to pay some attention to
their chosen discipline’s academic history. The history presented to them commonly ends some
time before the present. This has advantages for the historian, because the past is often better
interpreted from the detachment of a little distance and there is less chance of hurting scholars
still alive. But there is a major disadvantage for the students. In virtually every other component
of their courses they will be dealing with the discipline’s current literature, and so if the history
ends some decades ago, they are presented with the contemporary substance but not with the
contemporary framework, except where this is very clearly derivative of the historical context.
  This state of affairs is unfortunate. Students need a conspectus of the current practice in their
chosen discipline and should encounter a relevant overview which describes, and perhaps
explains too, what scholars believe the philosophy and methodology of the discipline presently
are and should be. Such an overview will allow the substantive courses comprising the rest of
the degree to be placed in context and appreciated as examples of the disciplinary belief system
as well as ends in themselves.
  As a discipline expands, so the need for a course in its ‘contemporary history’ will grow too. In
the last few decades, for example, most disciplines, and certainly human geography, have
expanded greatly, with expansion measured by the number of active participants and their
volume of published work. And the more active members there are, almost certainly the greater
the variety of work undertaken, making it difficult for individual students to provide their own
conspectus of the discipline from their own reading. Hence the need for a ‘contemporary history’
course at the present time.
  The present book is the outcome of teaching such a course for several years (in the 1970s–
1980s and then, briefly, the late 1990s), and is offered as a guide for others, both teachers and
students. As with all texts, it has many idiosyncrasies. The course on which it is based is taught
to final-year students reading for honours degrees in geography, and is probably best used by
people at that level since it assumes familiarity with the concepts and language of human
geography. Further, my view is that students probably benefit most from a framework after
experiencing some of its contents; this book provides the matrix for organizing the individual
parts rather than a series of slots into which parts can be placed later, which would be the case
if the course were taught early in the degree.
  A series of constraints circumscribes the contents and approach of this contemporary history.
First, it deals only with human geography, for several reasons. The most important is that I find
the links between physical and human geography tenuous, as those disciplines are currently
practised. The major link between them is a sharing of techniques and research procedures, but
these are shared with other disciplines too, and are insufficient foundation for a unified discipline.
(What price a department of factorial ecology?) Further, my own competence, work and interests
lie wholly within human geography and although I have been trained with and by and have
worked among physical geographers, and have obtained stimuli from this, I am incompetent to
xxii Preface

write about physical geography. And finally, much of the human geography discussed here is of
North American origin, and many geographers there, especially in the USA, encounter no
physical geography as it is understood in UK universities. To a considerable extent, therefore,
human and physical are separate, if not independent, disciplines. Throughout the book, I use the
terms ‘geography’ and ‘human geography’ interchangeably.
  The second constraint is cultural; the subject matter of the book is Anglo-American human
geography. Most of the work discussed emanates from either the USA or the UK: there are some
contributions from workers in Australia, Canada and New Zealand, but the efforts of geographers
in the rest of the world are largely ignored. (A partial exception is Sweden, which has major
academic links with the Anglo-American tradition; much Swedish geographical work is published
in English.) Such academic parochialism in part reflects personal linguistic deficiencies, but it is
not entirely an idiosyncratic decision. Contacts between Anglo-American human geography, on
one hand and, say, that of France and of Germany, on the other, have been few in recent decades,
so to concentrate on the former is not to commit a major error in separating a part from an
integrated whole.
  The final constraint is temporal, for the book is concerned with Anglo-American human
geography during the decades since the Second World War only. Again, this is in part a reflection
of personal competence, for I have been personally involved in academic geography for the last
twenty years. But the Second World War was a major watershed in so many aspects of history,
not least academic practice, and much of the methodology and philosophy currently taught in
human geography has been initiated since then.
(Johnston, 1979, pp. ix–xi)

We close this Preface with another extract from the one written thirty-six years ago. In
acknowledgement of how supportive personal and professional ‘contexts’ had aided its production,
the Preface of the first edition of Geography and Geographers had the following to say: ‘I make it clear in
Chapter 1 that the progress of any individual’s academic career depends considerably on the actions
(and sometimes inactions) of others. No academic is an island’ (Johnston 1979, p. xii). Very many
have assisted Ron Johnston over the years and are named in previous editions. Ron has continued
to benefit greatly from interactions with his colleagues at Bristol, with Derek Gregory and the
co-editors of the Dictionary of Human Geography, his many co-editors of Environment and Planning A and
Progress in Human Geography over a quarter-century of ever-increasing workloads, and Charles Pattie,
Dave Rossiter, Dave Cutts, Kelvyn Jones, Rich Harris, David Manley, Mike Poulsen, Jim Forrest, the
late Andy Trlin and others who have kept his nose to the ever-enjoyable research grindstone. James
D. Sidaway would also like to thank Robina Mohammad for her encouragement and feedback
arising from using the sixth edition to teach an honours-year module on geographic thought at the
University of Strathclyde. He also thanks those he has worked with over the last two decades in the
UK and Amsterdam as well as his co-editors at Political Geography, and once again thanks colleagues
and students at the Department of Geography of the National University of Singapore, a stimulating
and relatively diverse intellectual environment (see Olds, 2001) from which to reflect on the
dynamics of Anglo-American human geography since 1945. Both of us are also grateful to the
publishers of the past editions (Arnold) for commissioning a new edition and providing us with
anonymous reviews by other academics who had used the sixth edition in their teaching. At
Routledge (who have purchased the rights to publish Geography and Geographers from Arnold), we also
thank Sarah Gilkes and Andrew Mould for their patience while we finalised the seventh edition,
emailing numerous drafts between the port cities of Bristol and Singapore.
Ron Johnston and James D. Sidaway
Bristol and Singapore
Acknowledgements

The authors and publisher are grateful to the following for permission to reproduce figures
included in this and previous editions of the book:

Allan Pred and the Department of Social and Economic Geography, University of Lund, for
Figure 4.5.
Association of American Geographers for Figures 3.2 and 3.3.
Barbara Kennedy and Prentice-Hall for Figures 4.2 and 4.3.
Chris Philo for Figure 10.3.
David Harvey for Figures 3.1 and 7.1.
Derek Gregory for Figures 6.1 and 6.3.
Geraldine Pratt for Figure 8.1.
Olavi Gräno for Figure 10.1.
Oxford University Press and Taylor & Francis Group Ltd for Figure 4.6.
Peter Haggett for Figure 4.1.
Peters Edition Limited, London, for Figure 7.2.
Reg Golledge and Guilford Publications for Figure 4.7.
Richard Peet for Figure 10.2.
Royal Statistical Society for Figure 3.4.
Taylor & Francis Group Ltd for Figure 6.2.

Every effort has been made to contact copyright holders for their permission to reprint material in
this book. The publishers would be grateful to hear from any copyright holder who is not hereby
acknowledged and will undertake to rectify any errors or omissions in future editions of this book.
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 1

The nature of an academic discipline

[M]ost effective academic communities are not that much larger than most peasant villages
and just about as ingrown . . .
(Clifford Geertz, 1983, p. 157)

The history of geography involves many stories that start at different times in different places:
they slowly become intertwined, and their narrative threads can be unpicked and rewoven into
many different designs.
(Derek Gregory and Noel Castree, 2012, p. xxv)

[Th]e distinctive cultures within academic communities . . . refer to sets of taken-for-granted
values, attitudes and ways of behaving, which are articulated through and reinforced by
recurrent practices among a group of people in a given context.
(Tony Becher and Paul Trowler, 2001, p. 23)

[Geographers] appear to live in an intellectual world characterized by groups of people


plowing their own theoretical furrows, with little outright objection to others doing their
own thing.
(Tim Cresswell, 2013, p. 196)

This book is a study of part of an academic discipline, particularly of changes in its approaches
and content. Approaches and content cannot be appreciated fully without understanding context,
however, which this chapter provides. To study an academic discipline is to study a miniature
society, which has a stratification system, power structures, a set of rewards and sanctions, and
a series of bureaucracies, not to mention occasional interpersonal conflicts (some academic,
others not). An outsider may perceive academic work as objective, but many subjective decisions
must be taken: what to study and how; whether to publish the results; where to publish them and
in what form; what to teach; whether to question the work of others publicly, and so on.
Studying an academic discipline involves studying a society within a society; both set the
constraints to individual and group activity. Two questions are focused on here: how is academic
life organised; and how does that academic work, basically its research, proceed? Use of the
term ‘society within a society’ strongly implies that academic life does not proceed independently
in its own closed system but rather is open to the influences and commands of the encompassing
wider society. A third necessary question, therefore, is: what is the nature of the society which
provides the environment for the academic discipline being studied and how do the two interact?
Answering these three questions is set within a framework of studying the ways in which academic
life is institutionalised. These are the basic material frameworks within which disciplines
evolve. Much of this is not particular to human geography, although its relative novelty as a
discipline (a theme considered in more detail in Chapter 2) and relatively small size in terms of
2 The nature of an academic discipline

overall numbers of students and teaching faculty (especially when compared with disciplines like
English literature, history or physics, for example) does reflect back on the structure and perhaps
reinforces the sense of community/networks. We therefore start with some details about how these,
and attendant hierarchies, are configured in all academic life.

Academic life: the occupational structure


Pursuit of an academic discipline in modern society is part of a career, undertaken for financial and
other gains; most of its practitioners see their career as a profession, complete with entry rules and
behavioural norms. In the initial development of almost all current academic disciplines, some of
the innovators were amateurs, perhaps financing their activities from individual wealth. There are
virtually no such amateurs now; very few of the research publications in human geography are by
other than either a professional academic trained in the discipline or a member of a related
discipline with interests in some aspects of geography – indeed, there has been a recent trend for
scientists in a number of other disciplines to become increasingly interested in research topics that
many professional geographers tend to consider ‘their own’ (see, for example, Bettencourt and
West, 2010; Clauset et al., 2009). The profession is not geography, however. Rather, geography is the
discipline professed by individuals who probably state their occupation as university teacher,
professor or some similar term. Indeed, the great majority of academic geographers are teachers in
universities or comparable institutions of higher education; ‘university’ is used here as a generic
term. Academic geographers are distinguished from other professional geographers (many of
whom are also teachers) by their commitment to all three of the basic canons of a university:
to propagate, preserve and advance knowledge. The advancement of knowledge – the conduct of
fundamental research and the publication of its original findings – identifies an academic discipline;
the nature of its teaching reflects the nature of its research.

The academic career structure


University academic staff members, termed faculty members in North America – hereafter termed
academics here – follow their chosen occupation within a well-defined career structure, of which
two variants are relevant to this discussion: the British model and the North American model
(Figure 1.1), although they have tended to converge in recent years (so the title associate professor
is increasingly tending to replace reader and senior lecturer grades in the UK). Entry to both is by
the same route. With rare exceptions, the individual must have been a successful student as an
undergraduate and, more especially, as a postgraduate. The latter involves pursuing original research,
guided by one or more supervisors (in North America, an advisory committee with a chair plays
this role) who are expert in the relevant specialised field. The research results are almost invariably
presented as a thesis for a research degree (usually the Ph.D.), which is examined by relevant
experts; possession of a Ph.D. is now an almost obligatory entrance ticket for both models. Along
the way, publication of research findings in specialist journals is expected.
While pursuing the research degree, most postgraduate students obtain experience in teaching
undergraduates. Some universities finance many research students through such teaching activities,
notably those operating the North American model. The individual may then proceed to further
research experience (such as a postdoctoral fellowship or as a research worker on a project directed
by a more senior academic), or may gain appointment to a limited-tenure university teaching post,
offering an ‘apprenticeship’ in the teaching aspects of the profession while either the research
degree is completed or the individual’s research expertise is consolidated.
Beyond these limited-tenure positions lie the permanent teaching posts, which is where
the two models deviate. In the British model, the first level of the career structure is the lectureship.
For the first years of that appointment (usually three) the lecturer is on probation: training
The nature of an academic discipline 3

THE THE
BRITISH MODEL AMERICAN MODEL

PROFESSOR PROFESSOR

READER ASSOCIATE
PROFESSOR

SENIOR
LECTURER ASSISTANT
PROFESSOR

LECTURER

POSTGRADUATE
STUDENT

JNDERGRADUATE
STUDENT

Figure 1.1  The academic career ladder. Note that whereas in the American model it is very unusual not
to progress up through the stages in an orderly sequence, in the British model missing steps is quite
common (i.e. some lecturers move direct to readerships, even to professorships, without first being
senior lecturers – there are no senior lecturers in the ‘Oxbridge’ universities – and many professors are
recruited from the senior lecturer rather than the reader grade). In recent years, many British universities
have adopted the terminology of the American model.

in teaching and related activities is provided (with, increasingly, satisfactory performance on


accredited programmes required), annual reports are made on progress as teacher, researcher and
administrator, and advice is offered on adaptation to the demands of the profession. At the end of
the probationary period, the appointment is either terminated or confirmed.
Appointment in this model is almost always to a department, which in many cases is named
for the discipline which its staff members profess; others may be in a broader school or division –
of social sciences, say. The prescribed duties involve undertaking research and such teaching and
administration duties as directed by the head of the department, though frequently negotiated
through a variety of committees. The lecturers are on a salary scale and receive an annual increment;
accelerated promotion may be possible. In the UK there is an ‘efficiency bar’ after a certain number
of years’ service; ‘crossing the bar’ involves a promotion, and is determined by an assessment of the
lecturer’s research, teaching and administrative activities.
Beyond the lectureship are further grades into which the individual can be promoted. In the
universities that were established before the 1990s, the first was the senior lectureship for which
there is no allocation to departments but competition across the entire institution. Entry is
based again on assessments of the lecturer’s conduct in the three main areas of academic life, and
in many universities these include evaluations of research performance and potential from outside
experts. (The universities of Oxford and Cambridge are exceptions to this; they do not have a senior
lecturer grade, and their salary scale for lecturers is much longer.) The next level is the readership,
a position generally reserved for scholars with established research records. The criteria for promo-
tion to it require excellence in research (as demonstrated by their publications and influence)
alongside satisfactory performance (at least) on the other criteria. In many universities it is now
possible for promotion directly from lectureship to readership. In the post-1990 universities (most
of them originally established as polytechnics), the promotional grades were principal and senior
4 The nature of an academic discipline

lecturer, with readerships only very rarely created. In both, the North American category (see
below) of associate professor has increasingly been adopted since the turn of the millennium.
The final grade (associated with academic departments as against administration of the univer-
sity as a whole) is the professorship. Although superior in status to the others, this may not be a
promotional category; until the last few decades most professors were appointed from open
competition preceded by public advertisements. Initially, the posts of professor and head of
department were synonymous, so a professor was appointed (from a field of applicants after public
advertisement) as an administrative head to provide both managerial and academic leadership.
With growing departmental sizes and restructurings, however, and the development of specialised
subfields within disciplines, each requiring separate leadership, it has become common for
departments to have several professors. In most, the headship is a position independent of the
professoriate to which other grades may aspire, although many heads are also professors. The
post-1990 universities had very few professorships while they were polytechnics, but have since
converged with the older universities in terms of these structures. Finally, in the British
model, promotion is possible to non-advertised, personal professorships. These positions became
increasingly common in the 1990s onwards; in most cases, a personal professorship is awarded for
excellence in research and scholarship.
The system under the North American model is simpler. There are three permanent staff
(or ‘faculty’ as they are known there) categories: assistant professor, associate professor and profes-
sor. The first contains two subcategories – those staff on probation who do not have ‘tenure’ and
those with security of tenure. Each category has its own salary range but no automatic annual
increments. (In the USA, these scales vary from university to university; the UK has a national salary
scale that applies in all universities with only slight local modifications, although individual univer-
sities have different scales above the agreed minimum for professors.) Salary adjustments result
from personal bargaining based on academic activity in the three areas already listed, and salaries
for the three categories may overlap within a department. Movement from one category to another
is promotional, as recognition of academic excellence. Professorships are simply the highest pro-
motional grade and do not carry obligatory major administrative tasks. Heads (more usually termed
‘chairs’) of departments in the American model are separately appointed or elected, usually for a
limited period only, and they need not be professors (usually referred to as ‘full professors’).
Elsewhere in the world, the structures may be some combination of these models, invariably medi-
ated through local norms. And, as we have mentioned, there has also been considerable hybridisa-
tion of the original templates in recent years, with a few universities in the UK and elsewhere now
referring to those of their academics who would hitherto have been designated as lecturers, senior
lecturers or readers as assistant or associate professors.

The nature of academic work


Academic work has three main components: research, teaching and administration (the latter
is more often termed ‘service’ by USA-based academics). Entrants to the profession have little or no
experience of academic administration and their teaching has probably been as assistants to others.
Thus, it is very largely on proven and potential research ability that an aspirant’s initial potential for
an academic career is judged, especially in universities that present themselves as ‘research driven’
and where, on average, staff members spend less time on teaching than is the case in other
institutions. Research ability can be partly equated with probable teaching and administrative
competence, since all require some of the same personal qualities – enthusiasm, organisation,
motivation, incisive thinking and ability to communicate orally and in writing: most universities
provide appointees with training in teaching and administrative skills. Increasingly, in the British
system such formal training has become compulsory and is completed (among many other tasks
and much ‘learning by doing’ in the first few years of an academic appointment). To a considerable
The nature of an academic discipline 5

extent, however, academics gain their first position on faith in their potential (as demonstrated by
their letters of application and curricula vitae, references, and their performance at formal and
informal evaluation processes, such as interviews and seminars, plus their initial publications),
hence the usual probationary periods before tenure is granted.
Once admitted to the profession, academics undertake all three types of work, so that promo-
tional prospects can be more widely assessed. Teaching and administration have traditionally carried
less weight with those responsible for promotions than research. This is partly because of perceived
difficulties in assessing performance in the first two, and partly because of a general academic ethos
which gives prime place to research activity in peer evaluation and wider recognition.
Although not necessarily progressive in terms of increasing level of difficulty, administrative
tasks tend to be more complex and demanding of political and personal judgement and skills as the
academic becomes more senior, although not necessarily less onerous in terms of time required.
A person’s ability to undertake a certain task can often only be fully assessed after appointment or
promotion to the relevant position (this has been called the ‘Peter principle’: Peter and Hull, 1969),
so decisions must frequently be based on perceived potential; although it is possible to point to
somebody whose administrative skills are insubstantial, it is not always easy to assess who will be
able to cope with the more demanding tasks.
It has long been argued that assessment of teaching ability is difficult (although clear inability
is often very apparent). Student and peer evaluations are increasingly used, as is external scrutiny of
students’ work. But criteria for judging teaching performance at university level are ill-defined, and
expectations of a lecturer, tutor or seminar leader often vary quite considerably within even a small
group of students, as well as among external assessors. Thus the majority of teachers are usually
accepted as competent if undistinguished. Indeed, the ‘inspections’ of teaching sessions – most of
them lectures – undertaken during the 1995 quality assessment of teaching in geography in
UK universities invariably rated the majority as ‘satisfactory’, with a substantial minority being
deemed ‘excellent’ and very few – none in most cases – ‘unsatisfactory’ (Johnston, 1996a). In most
universities now, promotion exercises require proven excellence in at least two of the three criteria
generally considered – research, teaching and administration; some add a fourth criterion – service
to the wider community.
Research performance is a major criterion for promotion, therefore, although a relatively
undistinguished record in this area can be compensated by excellence elsewhere. Some argue that
teaching competence is not only undervalued (despite the promotion of geographical pedagogy,
notably through the Journal of Geography in Higher Education), but that as a consequence of the increasing
emphasis on research and its financing in most universities, it has received less attention from the
1980s onwards (Jenkins, 1995; Sidaway, 1997). How is research ability judged? Details of how
research is undertaken are considered in the next section; here the concern is with its assessment
rather than with stimulus and substance.
Successful research involves making an original contribution to a field of knowledge. It may
involve the collection, presentation and analysis of new information within an accepted framework;
it may be the development of new ways of collecting, analysing and presenting material; it may
comprise promoting a new way of ordering facts – a new theory or hypothesis, or simply
new interpretations of and insights into existing material; or it may be some combination of all
three (on the definitions of research and scholarship, see Collini, 2012). Its originality is judged
through its acceptance by those of proven expertise in the particular field. The generally accepted
validation procedure is publication, hence adages such as ‘unpublished research isn’t research’ and
‘publish or perish’.
The main publishing outlets for research findings in most disciplines are their scholarly
journals, which operate fairly standard procedures for scrutinising submitted contributions. Some
of the major journals are published by academic learned societies and others by commercial
publishers (on the shifting relative status of these in geography, see Bosman, 2009), with many
6 The nature of an academic discipline

learned societies now contracting out the production and marketing of their journals to com-
mercial publishers while retaining full editorial control (Luke, 2000; Johnston, 2003a). Manuscripts
are submitted to the editor, who seeks the advice of qualified academics on the merits of the
contribution; these referees will recommend either publication or rejection, or revision and
resubmission. When accepted, a manuscript will enter the publication queue, which may be up to
two years long, although increasingly journals are publishing accepted papers on their websites as
soon as they have been accepted for publication.
Although widely accepted, this procedure is subjective because it is operated by human
decision-makers. The opinions of both editor (on the manuscript and on the choice of referees) and
referees may be biased or partial, so a paper can be rejected by one journal but accepted by another,
even without alteration. (On the canons of editorship see, for example, Hart, 1990, and Taylor,
1990a; for a radical alternative, see Symanski and Picard, 1996.) Most disciplines have an informal
prestige ranking of journals, and it is considered more desirable to publish in some rather than
others, because of the stringency of their review procedures, their circulation, readership and hence
visibility, and their generally-assumed status (Luke, 2000; Johnston, 2003a). In addition, over
recent decades much effort has been put into the development of citation indices to rate journals,
individual articles in journals (plus books) and authors. A corporation (Thompson Reuters) scans
all the items referenced in a large selection of journals. Originally known as the Institute for
Scientific Information (ISI), the index compiled by Thompson Reuters has since been joined by
others: Scopus (owned by the publisher Reed Elsevier) and others whose datasets are free to access
for all, such as Google Scholar and Publish or Perish (set up in 1999 by the then Melbourne based
academic, Ann-Wil Harzing).
Collation of this material allows these organisations to provide data on the number of times
each author is cited by others – taken as evidence of the impact and importance of her/his work;
the number of times each item is cited – taken as evidence of its importance in advancing knowledge;
and the number of times each journal is cited – taken as evidence of the importance and impact of
the items it publishes. (Yeung, 2002, details how these citation counts and impact factors
are calculated and Paasi, 2005, examines their influence on academics’ publishing practices.
Several geographers have deployed them to identify the most influential geographers according to
their citation frequency – e.g. Bodman, 1991, 1992, 2010; Foster et al., 2007; Whitehand, 1985;
and Belgian geographers have debated – in English – the impacts of these English-dominated
citations metrics across the linguistic divides in Belgium: Derudder, 2011; Meeus et al., 2011;
Schuermans et al., 2010.) Citation counts for individuals and the journals in which they publish
are often taken into consideration by appointment and promotion committees. The issue of
the standing of journals and the use of citation counts became crucial in the UK after the mid-
1980s because of the use of publication data as a proxy indicator for the periodic national
assessments, which not only rate every department but also determine its future funding
(the higher rated received more money, see Johnston, 1993b). The relationship between
citation numbers and quality and impact of scholarship is, however, rather complex and, as we will
describe, contested.
Some research results are published in book form, rather than as journal articles. Most academic
books in geography are texts, however, published by commercial companies whose main interest
is marketability among the large student population. The textbook may be innovative in the way
that it orders and presents material, and can be beneficial to its author’s reputation (and bank
balance), but it is not usually a vehicle for demonstrating research ability, although, as we detail
below, textbooks can significantly shape fields of scholarship, by virtue of how they chose to present
things to their student readers from whom future generations of potential researchers are drawn
(on types of books published, see Johnston, 1986a, pp. 165–6). Many companies, including
university presses, publish research monographs, however, presenting the results of major research
projects or theoretical elaborations to relatively small academic markets. Their decisions on whether
The nature of an academic discipline 7

to publish are made on academic as well as commercial grounds, usually with the aid of academic
referees, and their output is validated through the journal book-review columns. (Some concern
has been expressed on the future of monograph publishing in geography, generating considerable
debate: see Harvey, 2006 and Ward et al., 2009. On the relative standing of books in discussions of
a discipline’s influential outputs, see Johnston, 2009a.)

Processes of promotion and appointment: patronage


Whatever the weighting given by appointment and promotion committees to the three main aca-
demic activities (others are pursued by some, such as consulting for outside bodies and contribu-
tions to the work of learned societies), how they make assessments is frequently contentious. One
of the main sets of ‘objective’ information that can be presented to them is lists of publications,
most of which have been validated by academic journals. But how is such information evaluated?
Two modes of assessment are widely used and relied upon: the written opinion of a third party
(either a referee, selected by the applicant, or an assessor, selected by the appointment/promotion
committee) and the interview, sometimes associated with presentation of a lecture or seminar. The
British model places considerable weight on the former. Applicants must supply a list of referees
who will provide opinions on their suitability for the post: applicants are likely to ask people,
especially senior people they have worked with, and are believed to be favourably inclined towards
them, to act in this capacity. As appointment committees tend to be influenced by such evaluations,
especially when preparing a shortlist of candidates to be interviewed, the opinions of well-respected
referees are often crucial. Thus, certain leaders in a subject often find it easier to get their candidates
appointed to posts than do others: there is a considerable element of patronage involved in obtaining
a university post, especially a first university post. Increasingly, too, it seems that appointment
committees for junior posts are influenced by where candidates obtained their postgraduate
training: attendance at a highly rated graduate school is considered an advantage.
Promotions under the British model are frequently strongly influenced by the head of the
candidate’s department, although in almost all places now she or he is expected to consult senior
colleagues before making a recommendation. Reports must be made on each lecturer: annually
during the probation period; at the confirmation stage after probation; on reaching the ‘efficiency
bar’; and for either accelerated promotion within the lecturer scale (or beyond it, to ‘discretionary
points’), or promotion to senior lecturer. This also contains a strong element of patronage, although
constraints are built into the committee system to promote fairness for all, including the right
either to present one’s own case or to appeal against a decision. Many universities use outside
referees and assessors when considering promotions to senior lecturer; promotions to readerships
and professorships almost invariably involve such consultation.
Referees, assessors and interviews are also used in the appointment of professors. Referees
nominated by the candidates provide a confidential report on their potential for the job in question.
Assessors nominated by the university evaluate the list of candidates, suggest other worthy
candidates who might be approached, and in many cases attend the formal interviews: their
potential patronage power is great.
Procedures are slightly different under the American model. For appointments, more weight is
usually given to an enlarged interview, with candidates giving seminars to the department and
meeting with its existing members (such procedures are increasingly used in UK universities). The
reference is still important, however, especially for aspirants to first teaching positions, and a letter
from a respected leader in a field, especially one working in a prestigious graduate school, can be
very influential in gaining an appointment for a former student (Morin and Rothenberg, 2011; Liu
and Zhan, 2011). The individual candidate is more active in this system than in the British, however,
perhaps canvassing for interviews during the annual conferences of scholarly societies, for example.
For promotions and for salary rises there is considerable bargaining between individual, department
8 The nature of an academic discipline

chair and university administrators; external referees’ opinions may be sought when tenure is being
confirmed, or promotion to full professor proposed.
In all these procedures the applicants depend to a considerable extent on the opinions of senior
academic colleagues in evaluating their potential, performance and prospects. Some opinions carry
more weight than others, so it is important when developing a career to identify potentially
influential individuals, to keep them informed of your work and to enlist their support for your
advancement. Because of the lack of truly objective criteria for measuring research, teaching and
administrative ability, such patronage is crucial.

Other rewards and the sources of status


The tangible rewards of an academic career are the salary and the relative autonomy of the work
(which beyond teaching and administrative commitments enjoys fairly flexible hours), the relative
security of employment plus the occasional extra earnings that are possible – for examining,
writing, lecturing and consulting. These are experienced unevenly; by no means do all academics
experience job security and for many the relative autonomy of academic work has been eroded by
growing pressures and measures of performance (on which more follows). And in many places
part-time academics and those on temporary contracts perform significant roles, but without the
same levels of tangible rewards or security as others (Binnie et al., 2005). Nonetheless, for many the
hours are still relatively flexible, the possibilities for travel are often considerable and the constraints
on when, where and how work is done are relatively few compared with most other professions.
Other, less tangible, rewards include involvement with the intellectual development of a
discipline and its students, or the excitement of research and attraction of sustained immersion in
intellectual ideas, practical challenges or both. There is also the charisma associated with recognised
excellent teachers, and even more so for leading researchers, whose publications are widely read,
whose invitations to give outside lectures are many, and whose opinions as examiners, referees and
reviewers are widely canvassed; a few attain the status of ‘public intellectual’ with their views
published widely through various media (Castree, 2006a; Ward, 2007). The conduct of research
brings its own rewards, apart from the charisma; the satisfaction from having identified and solved
a significant problem is often considerable, as is that from publishing a widely – and positively –
cited article or book. And for a few, a successful research career is recognised by honours such as
the annual prizes and medals awarded by learned societies such as the Association of American
Geographers and the Royal Geographical Society (RGS) (with the Institute of British Geographers);
international recognition such as the Prix Vautrin Lud, awarded annually by the Festival International
de Géographie, the Anders Retzius Gold Medal of the Swedish Society for Anthropology and
Geography, and the Laureat d’Honneur of the International Geographical Union; and election to
national honorary learned societies such as the British Academy and Academy of the Social Sciences
and, in the USA, the National Academy of Sciences and the American Academy of Arts and Sciences.
Academic life also offers a reward common to many social systems: power. Patronage is power,
as is work as examiner, referee or reviewer. Others’ careers are being affected, and exercise of this
power can bring with it the loyalty and respect of those who benefit. Because the academic system
is so dependent on individuals’ opinions and some individuals’ opinions are more valued than
others’ are, and because power is a ‘commodity’ widely desired in most societies, many academics
seek positions of influence or service. These may include journal editorships or other similar broker
roles that in turn shape the structure and trajectory of disciplines (on one aspect of power within
the academy, see Hammett, 2012).
Among the most influential positions in an academic discipline are the administrative
headships of departments.Their holders can instruct other staff members (usually after consultation)
in their teaching and administrative duties; they are frequently used by staff and students as referees
for job and other (such as research grant) applications, and their reports are crucial in the
The nature of an academic discipline 9

promotions procedure. The departmental organisation of universities is a bureaucratic device which


makes for relative ease in administering what may be a very large institution. (It also tends to
fossilise disciplinary boundaries, as discussed later.) Departmental heads not only have power over
members of their own discipline’s staff, they also participate in their university’s administration,
and they treat within its committee system for departmental resources. As in all bureaucracies, there
is a tendency for the status and power of the various departmental heads to be a function of the size
of their ‘empires’ (Tullock, 1976; large departments in UK universities certainly get the highest
research ratings: see Johnston et al., 1995). Heads of large departments, especially those which are
also growing (growth being widely considered a ‘good thing’) and those attracting large numbers
of students and research grants/contracts, are very often the most influential within a bureaucracy.
Their heads have the incentive to build up their departments, which usually means increasing
student numbers, since universities tend to allocate at least a major portion of their resources
according to the numbers taught. This brings power and prestige, both within the university and
beyond; it is an added reward for the academic bureaucrat, and the power over resources which it
involves usually benefits the whole department. The successful department head may find that it
leads to appointments to more senior positions within the university, such as a deanship, overseeing
the work of a group of departments.
Finally, the academic bureaucrat can gain power beyond the home university through, for
example, positions on committees. These may be concerned with the subject through professional
bodies, with the allocation of research moneys by public or private foundations, including
government-funded Research Councils, or with a wide range of public duties. Again, the status and
power obtained can spill over to others, since patronage is important in all of those roles.

Disciplines and institutionalisation


By far the most important contemporary identifier for an academic discipline is that it is taught in
universities – it has departments named for it, degrees are awarded that carry its name, and the
teaching for those degrees is undertaken by individuals who have been trained in and identify
with the discipline. This identifier is related to what Morrell (1990) associates with the ‘professiona-
lization of science’: scholars in full-time paid positions; specialist qualifications; formal training
programmes; specialised publications; disciplinary solidarity and self-consciousness; and professional
reward systems. Golinski (1998) added a firm boundary between amateurs and professionals
(see also Barton, 2003). Geography exists as an academic discipline because there are people who
call themselves geographers, who have geography degrees and who teach on geography degree
programmes. These programmes may not, however, always be in departments of geography.
Especially in recent years, many departments have been merged into larger ones (most combining
geography with earth or environmental sciences: see Holmes, 2002, on the situation in Australia,
and for the UK see Wainwright et al., 2014, and Hall et al., 2015). This has raised questions about the
future prospects for the discipline and what strategies will be required in the context of a rapidly
changing university system, especially one under pressures to be relevant, accountable, and make
broader social and economic impacts. Reflecting on this from the UK, Castree (2011, p. 298)
reflects that:

A century ago, a small number of university geographers in England and elsewhere worked hard
to create a subject that is, today, far larger and more buoyant than they could possibly have
imagined. Is this one of those critical moments when concerted and coordinated action of the
sort we’re nowadays unaccustomed to taking is warranted?

A university presence has long been an indicator of a discipline’s existence: it is the key element
in its institutionalisation (Johnston, 2003b). It indicates that the discipline meets a felt need, in
10 The nature of an academic discipline

particular that there are students who want a higher education in geography and scholars who wish
to teach them. This, however, for geography, as with many other disciplines, is a relatively recent
phenomenon: it dates only from the late nineteenth century (as illustrated by the chapters in
Dunbar, 2002). That doesn’t mean that geography didn’t exist before the first courses were launched
in universities: as some of the work briefly discussed in Chapter 2 indicates, it has a long and
sometimes distinguished tradition as a form of enquiry and practice (Withers and Mayhew, 2002).
But it was only from the 1870s on that it was formalised as an academic discipline, separate from
the science and humanities study that characterised the traditional universities, significantly
supported in the British case by the RGS (who were able to fund a number of geography lecturer-
ships in UK universities; Powell, 2011). Moreover, as Chapter 2 describes in more detail, until
expansion commenced in the early twentieth century, there was only a handful of geography
departments in the UK.
Most disciplines are established in universities to teach a body of knowledge: they are identified
by their subject matter. Their existence indicates a demand for instruction in that material, by
people who are expert in it. Being an expert almost invariably means playing some part in producing
and reproducing that body of knowledge, which involves undertaking original research in some
aspects of the discipline and publishing the findings to inform other researchers and their students.
Academic disciplines in universities involve teacher-researchers, people interested not only in the
propagation of knowledge but also in its advancement; indeed, the production of new knowledge
is considered an essential component of university teacher-researchers.
Although the creation of departments for training students by experts is a necessary com-
ponent of the institutionalisation of a discipline, it is far from sufficient. In order to promote both
their discipline and their own work, academics need to be able to interact with colleagues inter-
ested in similar issues, most of whom will work at other universities. Some organisational structure
is needed to facilitate this. It is invariably done by academic or learned societies, bodies established
to promote a discipline through a variety of means, of which the most important include the
holding of meetings at which research issues and findings can be discussed and to facilitate the
publication of research results, through books, journals and other media. All academic disciplines
have such bodies, most of which are nationally organised; in some countries there may be several.
Some of those societies may predate the creation of the academic discipline, having been inaugu-
rated to promote its study before it achieved a separate identity and a body of professional scholars
associated with it. Indeed, in many cases those societies were involved in promoting the discipline
and lobbying for its presence in universities – perhaps even paying for the creation of teaching
posts. Others were established after the formal institutionalisation of the discipline. Most are open
for anybody to join if they are prepared to subscribe to the discipline’s advancement, but in effect
membership is very largely confined to university staff and (postgraduate) students – especially if
there is no named profession linked to the academic discipline which retains the practitioners’
affiliation (as with medicine and architecture, for example). Some societies have closed member-
ships, limited to those who meet certain criteria (such as a postgraduate degree in the discipline);
others have several membership categories which separately distinguish the professional academics
from those with a non-professional interest in the subject.
Those societies have been central to the development of disciplines as individual academics
create their own research agenda. Their conferences and seminars, journals and other publications
have been the main media until relatively recently (when commercial journal publication on a
large scale took off), whereby knowledge has been disseminated and debates about its production
and interpretation conducted. They also undertake other important functions, one of which is
the promotion and defence of the discipline as a whole. Even when established in a country’s
universities, a discipline is not necessarily secure. There are struggles for wider recognition, for
greater resources, for expansion into institutions where the discipline has yet to be established, and
so forth. The learned societies play crucial roles in these tasks, acting as lobby groups for their
The nature of an academic discipline 11

discipline and seeking to ensure its health by influencing public and private decision-makers
concerning its utility and value. And above them are even broader societies, representing a range
of cognate disciplines, such as the Royal Society and the British Academy in the UK, and the
National Academy of Sciences and the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in the USA; these
play a wider role in advancing the interests of their subject groupings.
The institutionalisation of an academic discipline involves creating an identity, a subject
with its own niche within the academic division of labour with which individuals are affiliated.
In some cases, the discipline – like geography and history – has a name whose interpretation
extends beyond academia, its vernacular definition (Johnston, 1986b). This may create some
difficulties in establishing an academic identity, because while the two definitions and/or
interpretations (or understandings) almost certainly overlap, they may not coincide (see, for
example, Harvey, 2005a, on the various forms of ‘geographical imagination’). This is certainly the
case with geography. Much popular interpretation of the term is associated with the acquisition of
basic information about the earth – what is where (what has sometimes been referred to as ‘capes
and bays geography’) – and not with the contemporary concerns of academic researchers. Such
interpretation is sustained by magazines such as the widely circulated National Geographic (Lutz and
Collins, 1993; Schulten, 2001; Rothenberg, 2007), which carries much informative material about
the earth’s environments and peoples, but little that reflects geographers’ current research. Similarly,
periodicals such as New Zealand Geographic are closer to natural history than to geography; its definition
and coverage of the subject has very little in common with the academic discipline whose practices
are represented in the New Zealand Geographer (Johnston 2009b, 2009c). One of us has suggested that
it is therefore analytically useful to distinguish between these forms of geography:

There is a strong thread not only in the USA but also in the UK of geographical imaginations that
have exerted . . . and continue to exert . . . very considerable popular and public influence,
shaping and re-shaping views of the world . . . But their links to the academic discipline are, at
best, relatively weak. The various worlds of geography seem not to intertwine – indeed some
stand rather aloof from each other: the National Geographic has virtually no links with academic
geography in the USA, for example. Magazines such as Africa Geographic, Australian Geographic,
Canadian Geographic and New Zealand Geographic hardly recognise the existence of the academic
discipline in their respective countries . . . The current existence of separate geographical
imaginations raises a number of issues . . . such separate imaginations have existed in the past
and . . . their relative strengths in different places and at different times may have been crucial
influences on variations in the nature of geography as it is currently taught in schools and
practised in universities. Those who write about the history of geography may recognise the
existence of those separate imaginations as foundations upon which an academic discipline was
built but then, once that discipline has been founded, focus almost entirely on it alone, very
largely ignoring the other imaginations . . .
(Johnston, 2013, p. 90)

Despite these issues of representation, boundaries and appreciation, however, geography is a


substantial academic discipline in the countries that we focus on in this book. In the UK, for
example, by the end of the twentieth century there were about 1,600 staff in university and college
departments offering geography programmes, with some 7,000 places available on undergraduate
degree programmes in geography each year, plus over 170 taught postgraduate programmes with
nearly 3,000 places available; in addition, there were more than 800 full-time students registered
for postgraduate research degrees, and a further 640 registered as part-time students. In the early
2000s, an increasing number of British geography departments were merged with allied subjects,
usually environmental science, geology or earth science, but the overall numbers studying for a
degree in geography have not declined. In the USA, the majority of universities lacked a geography
12 The nature of an academic discipline

department and there was a graduate programme in only a minority, including just one (Dartmouth)
of the prestigious network comprising some of the older East Coast universities known as the
‘Ivy League’. Richard Wright and Natalie Koch (2009) chart the history of geography at these eight
Ivy League universities, noting how in the first decades of the twentieth century geography was part
of the curricula at them all, but then lost ground owing to the relatively low status of the discipline
(on the closure of Harvard’s geography department, see N. Smith, 1987a; Cohen, 1988; Martin,
1988). The exodus of academics from the closure of their programmes, however, meant that some
capable geographers (such as Edward L. Ullman, see p. 70 in this book) either moved into public
universities elsewhere where geography remained, or moved to planning or allied programmes at
the Ivy League:

Increased demand for practical education and the attack on environmental determinism was
devastating for geography in the Ivy League universities; these institutions increasingly
emphasized the importance of theory and held technical instruction in low esteem. In contrast,
geography departments in the new land-grant colleges of the Midwest prospered in this
environment . . . designed in part to support . . . the Midwestern agricultural economy and serve
the broader public, they welcomed the applied elements of geography.
(p. 618)

Despite this uncertain start, today a large number of geographers are active in the USA: the
Association of American Geographers (the AAG) has over 10,000 members (although not all are
based in the USA, for the AAG promotes membership internationally) and its annual meeting
regularly attracts several thousand participants, including hundreds from other countries. For many
human geographers in North America, including Ph.D. students, participation at the AAG meetings,
which may mean presenting papers, acting as discussant re other papers or organising and chairing
panels of papers and the like, is an important site of networking and recognition. Other ‘national’
conferences, such as that of the London-based RGS (with the Institute of British Geographers),
and similar events in other countries are also significant venues for this kind of professional
interaction, but the sheer scale of the AAG means that many geographers will travel far to attend –
it is held in a different American city each early spring (Hsu and Sidaway, 2009). (The AAG was
very much a small, closed elite organisation with high barriers to entry before 1950, when it
merged with the American Society for Professional Geographers – see James and Martin, 1978;
Miller, 1993.) This large number of practising academics is part of a buoyant discipline whose
interests are wide-ranging and whose contributions to knowledge advancement are substantial
(Thrift, 2002). The nature of those contributions over a period of some seven decades is the core
of this book’s concerns.

The academic working environment: disciplines


and the academic division of labour
The continuing goal of an academic discipline is the advancement of knowledge, pursued within its
own particular areas of study. Its individual members contribute by conducting research and reporting
their findings, by integrating material into the disciplinary corpus, and by pedagogical activities
aimed at informing others, promoting and reproducing the discipline; they may also argue for the
discipline’s ‘relevance’ to society at large. But there is no fixed set of disciplines, nor any one correct
division of academia according to subject matter. As David Livingstone (1992, pp. 28–9) puts it:

The idea that there is some eternal metaphysical core to geography independent of historical
circumstances will simply have to go . . . geography has meant different things to different
The nature of an academic discipline 13

people in different places and thus the ‘nature’ of geography is always negotiated. The task of
geography’s historians, at least in part, is thus to ascertain how and why particular practices and
procedures come to be accounted geographically legitimate and hence normative at different
moments in time and in different spatial settings.

Those disciplines currently in existence are contained within boundaries established by earlier
communities of scholars. The boundaries are porous, so disciplines interact. Occasionally the
boundaries are changed, usually through the establishment of a new discipline that occupies an
enclave within the pre-existing division of academic space. Moreover, the boundaries are not
necessarily the same in all comparable institutions.
Just as there is no immutable set of disciplinary boundaries, so there is also no right way of
undertaking research nor, in many cases, any exact criteria for determining whether research
findings, and even more their interpretations, are correct. The ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ ways of doing
research, the ‘correct’ and ‘incorrect’ interpretations of research findings, and the ‘proper’ ways of
presenting knowledge and training students are all the product of decisions by academics themselves
within the culture that they are constantly reproducing. Thus, not surprisingly, there is considerable
debate within disciplines over these issues. At any one time, there may be consensus within a
disciplinary community regarding both its subject matter and its research methods. But controversy
is just as likely, as academics discuss the relevance of particular research findings, the validity of
certain research methodologies, and so on. Indeed, there is controversy over the nature and
definition of knowledge itself.
The study of the controversies and consensuses that characterise academic disciplines is the
function of historians of science. (Science is used here as a very broad term encompassing the entire
range of academic disciplines in the natural and social sciences: the Oxford English Dictionary
defines science as ‘an organized body of knowledge on a subject’.) To the outsider, the workings of
a science are generally mysterious – especially regarding disciplines that require a great degree
of prior training before original research is undertaken and whose literature is virtually impene-
trable to the untrained. It is generally believed, however, that science is an objective activity
undertaken within very strict rules, involving the continuous excitement of the search for
new discoveries. Indeed, scientists frequently present themselves in this light. Certain values are
universally subscribed to within academia, it is argued, with the main five being:

1 The norm of originality: academics strive to advance knowledge, and conduct original research
designed to discover and account for aspects of the world as yet not fully understood.
2 The norm of communality: all information is shared within the academic community – it is
transferred through accepted channels (notably the research journals) and its provenance is
always recognised when it is being used.
3 The norm of disinterestedness: academics are devoted to their subject, and their main reward
is the satisfaction of participating in the advancement of knowledge – a reward that may bring
with it charisma and promotion.
4 The norm of universalism: judgements are made on impartial criteria, which take into
account the academic merits of work only and make no reference to the personalities of the
researchers.
5 The norm of organised scepticism: knowledge is furthered by a continuing process of
constructive criticism, in which academics are always reconsidering both their own work and
that of others.
(Mulkay, 1975, p. 510)

According to these five norms, therefore, academic work is carried out neutrally; there is a
complete lack of partiality, self-seeking, secrecy and intellectual prejudice. Objective assessment
14 The nature of an academic discipline

criteria are assumed, as are high levels of ability and humility on the part of members of the acade-
mic community.
Against this ideal view of science and scientists, which many of the latter promote, are the
results of studies in the history of science (most of which refer to the physical sciences: Mulkay,
1975; Mulkay et al., 1975; Latour, 1987, 1999; Latour and Woolgar, 1979). These show that the
procedures adopted are seldom straightforwardly objective or neutral, and they present a picture of
disciplines growing ‘by gathering more detail in areas already investigated, and by stumbling across
new sets of facts in areas of experience never previously investigated’ (Barnes, 1974, p. 5). Science
is a culture, with each discipline comprising one or more subculture(s). It has its own rules and
procedures which are open to change and hence are the subject of debate, even conflict. Furthermore
(as suggested in more detail below), scientific cultures are parts of wider cultures, and although to
some extent scientists – because of their (self-imposed) expert status – can impose their own views
of themselves on their host societies, they are also subject to external influences (see Barnes, 1974).
Each scientific discipline is a separate academic community, therefore; many are groupings
of several related communities. Their goal is the advancement of knowledge, but the definitions of
advancement and of knowledge itself are influenced, if not determined, by the community’s
members. Thus, study of a discipline’s history is not simply a chronology of its successes. It is an
investigation of the sociology of a community, of its debates, deliberations and decisions, as well as
of its findings. (See James Watson, 1968, for an example of this; for a fictional account, see William
Cooper, 1952; an excellent introductory history is in Gribbin, 2002. Livingstone, 1992, p. 30,
suggests that ‘it might be helpful if we were to think of geography as a tradition that evolves like
a species over time’.) Most of those communities – including geography – are divided into a
substantial number of subcommunities involving individuals working on a particular subject
matter, and/or set of problems, and/or particular methodology. Indeed, Geertz (1983, p. 157)
argues that:

most effective academic communities are not that much larger than most peasant villages and
just about as ingrown . . . From such units, intellectual communities if you will, convergent data
can be gathered, for the relations among the inhabitants are typically not merely intellectual, but
political, moral, and broadly personal (these days, increasingly, marital) as well. Laboratories
and research institutes, scholarly societies, axial university departments, literary and artistic
cliques, intellectual factions, all fit the same pattern: communities of multiply connected
individuals in which something you find out about A tells you something about B as well, because,
having known each other too long and too well, they are characters in one another’s biographies.

Untangling such biographies, individual and collective, is the key to understanding geogra-
phy’s institutionalisation and contemporary practices: its history indicates where it has come
from and why it currently takes the forms that it does. Furthermore, the history of most of those
communities involves both conflict with others (within a university, for example: Johnston,
1998) and within the communities (Johnston, 2000a) over the allocation of resources and rewards.
Such communities are frequently territorial, in the defence of their portion of the academic
division of labour, and sometimes aggressively so in strategies to expand their portion of the
whole.
But once it is established, why and how does the content of a discipline change? What
accounts for this, beyond clashes of interest and the ideas or biographies of individual
academics? What forms do such shifts take? What triggers them? In the first half of the period that
we consider here, most of the models available for explaining and interpreting changes
were developed for, and tested on, the physical sciences, revolving around the idea of paradigms.
Their relevance to human geography was soon suggested, however (e.g. Haggett and Chorley, 1967;
Harvey, 1973), and they are presented below as a backcloth for a later evaluation of the substantive
The nature of an academic discipline 15

material arranged in Chapters 2–9. The final chapter of the book will return to debates about
interpreting the evolution of human geography.

Kuhn, paradigms, normal science and revolutions


A framework for studying the history of science that has received much attention (indeed, the
book became highly cited by social scientists) is provided by T. S. Kuhn’s (1962, 1970a) The Structure
of Scientific Revolutions. Reviewing its impacts fifty years on from publication, Gordon (2012, p. 73)
notes how:

Anyone who works at the interstices of intellectual history and philosophy and the history and
philosophy of science will be quick to rank Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions
amongst the most influential works of the last half-century. But its influence extends well
beyond these disciplines as well. First published in 1962 as a contribution to the International
Encyclopedia of Unified Science, over the last fifty years it has enjoyed a rich afterlife, leaving in its
wake an immense if contested inventory of ideas whose significance has transcended the well-
policed boundaries that often separate the natural sciences from the social sciences and the
humanities. Even more surprising for a book of its academic character, it has enjoyed a reception
in popular discourse that exceeds its disciplinary bailiwick. Its trademark terms – not only the
celebrated ideas of a paradigm and a paradigm shift but also more technical themes such as
normal science, incommensurability, and anomaly – have been naturalized into mundane English
with a degree of success that puts to shame just about any other work of recent scholarship.
Paraphrasing one of its characteristic claims, one may be tempted to observe that, since the
publication of Kuhn’s Structure, we all live in a different world.

The fact that Kuhn’s book appeared just as human geography was on the verge of significant
changes probably encouraged those charting and advocating the changes to adopt Kuhn’s language
of disciplinary revolutions, thus describing human geography as undergoing a ‘quantitative’ or
‘scientific’ ‘revolution’ – a series of shifts and debates that we describe in Chapters 2 and 3.
Yet as Kuhn (1970b) and many commentators have pointed out, his book is a study in the
sociology of science: it is a positive interpretation – presenting what scientists actually do – rather
than a normative programme – an argument for what scientists ought to do. It generalises from its
observations, identifying common elements in disciplinary histories: Kuhn’s goal was to identify
‘what science, scientific research as it is actually practised, is really like’ (Barnes, 1982, p. 1).
Following Kuhn’s death in 1996 a number of books on his life and work have been published and
provide valuable introductions to, and critiques of, his work (e.g. Bird, 2000; Conant and Haugeland,
2000; Fuller, 2000; Sharrock and Read, 2002; Nickles, 2003).
Kuhn argued that scientists work in communities of researchers and teachers who share a
common approach. They operate within an agreed philosophy, concur on the theoretical focus of
their work and use accepted methodological procedures. They deploy those procedures to solve
problems identified within the theoretical framework, thereby adding to knowledge (the store of
problems solved) and extending the range of their theory. The framework, its procedures and its
empirical substance are codified in their textbooks. What they share is termed a paradigm: ‘a
scientific community consists of men [sic] who share a paradigm’ (Kuhn, 1970a, p. 176).  As Popper
(1959) expresses it, this means that once scientists are socialised into a research field they can
proceed directly to its unsolved problems.The existing framework defines these problems, providing
both a context and a methodology for tackling them. The researcher does not set out to tackle a
problem de novo, therefore, but based on what is already known in the chosen field. A paradigm is
thus ‘an accepted problem-solution’ (Barnes, 1982, p. xiv), which by its very nature poses the next
problem. Progress in science is achieved by problem solving, by the current generation of scientists
16 The nature of an academic discipline

agreeing that ‘If I have seen further it is by standing on the shoulders of giants’ who preceded them
– a phrase used by Isaac Newton.
To undertake research within a paradigm requires understanding and acceptance of its
philosophy and methodology. This involves a period of training, during which the potential new
researcher is socialised into the paradigmatic culture – that is, its way of thinking about its scientific
problems – its language, literature, and methods of research, result presentation and argumentation.
The key is provided by the paradigm’s textbooks, the summaries of its literature which set out what
is known and how further knowledge can be obtained. The training prepares individuals for work
within an accepted mould:

Scientific training is dogmatic and authoritarian . . . [it] does not generate or encourage traits
such as creativity or logical rigour; rather it equips scientists so that it is possible for them to be
creative, or rigorous, or whatever else, in the context of a specific form of culture.
(Barnes, 1982, pp. 1, 17)

Having been integrated into the paradigm, the scientist joins a research community.
Such communities, sometimes termed ‘invisible colleges’, operate through close interaction involv-
ing attendance at specialised conferences and the private circulation of research papers in pre-
publication form: their existence is reflected in citations to each other’s work (Crane, 1972).
Increasingly, electronic communications media allow community members to be in frequent,
almost constant, contact and collaborative work without regular meetings is now common
(Johnston, 2004a). Individual members receive recognition for the value of their work and attract
the patronage of leaders who may assist their career advancement; some communities have only a
few patrons, perhaps even one, and may be identified as a particular school of thought – perhaps
focused on a single leading individual.
Research within a paradigm involves filling in the gaps; the researcher ‘has to make the
unknown into an instance of the known, into another routine case’ (Barnes, 1982, p. 49).
The paradigm provides the needed resources – guidance but not direction. Success, which
brings the rewards of recognition, patronage and status, involves conforming to the paradigmatic
norms (Mulkay, 1975):

It is clear that the quality or significance of a scientist’s work is judged in relation to the existing
set of scientific assumptions and expectations. Thus, whereas radical departures from a well-
defined framework are unlikely to be granted recognition early under normal circumstances,
original contributions which conform to established preconceptions will be quickly rewarded.
(p. 515)

Thus, the dominant norm of academic life is not one of the five listed earlier (p. 13), but rather
conformity or convergence. Science is not the constant search for novel discoveries but rather the
careful application of agreed procedures to the solution of problems in order to extend existing
well-structured bodies of knowledge. Judgements about relevance and importance are being made
all the time, but within an academic environment carefully structured by the training process.
Science progresses through filling the gaps in a predefined framework.
This operation of a paradigm is known as normal science:

Perhaps the most striking feature of the normal research problems . . . is how little they aim to
produce major novelties, conceptual or phenomenal. Sometimes . . . everything but the most
esoteric detail of the result is known in advance . . . the range of anticipated, and thus assimilable,
results is always small compared with the range that imaginations can conceive . . . the aim of
normal science is not major substantive novelties . . . the results gained in normal research are
The nature of an academic discipline 17

significant because they add to the scope and precision with which the paradigm can be
applied. . . . Though its outcome can be anticipated, often in detail so great that what remains to
be known is itself uninteresting, the way to achieve that outcome remains very much in doubt. . . .
The man who succeeds proves himself an expert problem solver.
(Kuhn, 1962, pp. 35–6)

Within normal science, therefore, the researcher has available:

1 an accepted body of knowledge, ordered and interpreted in a particular way;


2 an indication of the puzzles that remain to be solved; and
3 a set of procedures for puzzle-solving.

Training within a paradigm provides the tools for extending the paradigmatic body of
knowledge. The result is ‘conventional, routinised practice’ (Barnes, 1982, p. 11). This does not
imply that normal scientific activity is necessarily one of ‘long periods of dreary conformity’
(p. 13), however, because extending and developing knowledge are not simply ‘a matter of
following instructions or rules. Rather, normal science is a test of ingenuity and imagination, with
paradigms figuring largely among the cultural resources of the scientist’ (p. 13). Solving problems
is rarely easy; Kuhn (1970c, pp. 36–9) uses chess-playing as an example, arguing that much
ingenuity as well as existing knowledge (practice) must be brought to bear if the problems posed
in individual games are to be solved successfully.
Scientists are not omniscient. They do not understand everything – even within a particular
paradigm – so their predictions occasionally prove inaccurate. While the process of normal science
continues, therefore, slowly accumulating extra knowledge as problems are solved, it sometimes
throws up anomalies, findings that are not in accord with the paradigm’s assumptions. These must
be accounted for:

Puzzle-solving activity frequently attempts to show that what is prima facie anomalous is either
the spurious product of bad equipment or technique, or a familiar phenomenon in disguise. And
most anomalies are successfully assimilated in this way.
(Barnes, 1982, p. 53)

Either the work was badly done or the researcher interpreted the results wrongly. Minor adaptation
of the paradigm may be needed, but the general process of normal science continues.
Some anomalies cannot readily be accounted for, however, and they may continue to worry a
few scientists, whose persistence leads to work on alternative paradigms, potential new frameworks
that structure knowledge so that there are no anomalies. This is extraordinary research, conducted
outside the bounds of the accepted paradigm. When it is successful, a ‘revolutionary episode’ is in
progress. Regarding such research, Kuhn notes that:

Almost always the men who achieve these fundamental inventions of a new paradigm have been
either very young or very new to the field whose paradigm they change . . . obviously these
are the men who, being little committed by prior practice to the traditional rules of normal
science, are particularly likely to see that those rules no longer define a playable game and to
conceive another set that can replace them.
(1962, pp. 89–90)

The result is an alternative paradigm. Adherents of the current normal science are then asked to
choose between two competing views of their subject: either the accepted mode of working is
to be maintained, despite the anomalies, or a new subculture is to be adopted. The invitation is to
18 The nature of an academic discipline

discard existing authorities and habits and to take up new ones, which are claimed to be superior,
because they are better predictors of that aspect of the world being studied. If the need for change
is accepted, then a revolution in scientific practice occurs; one paradigm is replaced by another.
That choice between competing paradigms is an extremely difficult one because of their
incommensurability; there are no common standards against which both can be compared. As
Kuhn (1970a, p. 148) points out, ‘the proponents of competing paradigms will often disagree
about the list of problems that any candidate for paradigm must resolve. Their standards or their
definitions of science are not the same.’ The new paradigm will almost certainly use some of the
language and procedures of the one it is seeking to replace, but in slightly different ways, giving
rise to considerable misunderstanding in discussions between the rival paradigms’ protagonists.
More importantly, however, the two groups of scientists may be looking at the world in very
different ways:

Both are looking at the world, and what they look at has not changed. But in some areas they see
different things, and they see them in different relations one to the other. That is why a law that
cannot even be demonstrated to one group of scientists may occasionally seem intuitively
obvious to another.
(p. 150)

Thus, any switch from one paradigm to another is not forced simply by logic. It is what Kuhn calls
a ‘gestalt switch’, a decision to abandon one way of viewing the world and replace it by another on
intuitive grounds, rather than through the application of strict scientific criteria; a subjective
decision has to be made that one is better than the other. Not all scientists may come to the same
intuitive decision, therefore, so that some continue to work in the context of a paradigm that others
have discredited. One of the often-cited examples of such a paradigm shift – on which Kuhn, 1957,
wrote his first book – was the Copernican revolution in astronomy, as promoted by Galileo.
Likewise, within Western geography, Columbus’s ‘discovery of America’ forced a revolution in
world cartography.
Kuhn represents scientific activity as researchers trained to employ a proven mode of looking
at their subject matter using an accepted methodology for solving problems. They proceed in a
steady, cumulative manner, adding to the store of knowledge: small modifications may be needed
to accommodate minor anomalies encountered en route. Occasionally, however, anomalies are
detected which cannot be either explained away or accommodated. Some researchers may focus on
these, developing new paradigms to account for them, as well as everything else that was already
known. When this is achieved, the new paradigm is presented for approval. A revolution is invited,
for the alternative paradigms are incommensurable: the community is asked to redirect its work.
Science proceeds in a steady fashion along well-trodden paths, therefore, with occasional major
breaks in its continuity marked by important changes in the organisation of its material, in the
definition of its problems,and in its techniques for problem-solving.

Criticisms of Kuhn’s approach, and his response


Kuhn’s work quickly stimulated a great deal of debate among philosophers of science because it
challenged orthodox views of scientific progress and implied, especially in the concept of
revolutions, that some scientific decision-making was ‘irrational’ (see Watkins, 1970, on Kuhn’s
analogy between scientific and religious communities, and Barry Barnes, 1982, for a wider
evaluation of Kuhn’s impacts). Indeed, the introduction and treatment of the concept of the
revolutionary episode attracted much of the attention (see Stegmuller, 1976), because most of
the views that Kuhn was challenging were normative rather than positive; they prescribed what
science should be like, whereas Kuhn claimed to describe what it was actually like.
The nature of an academic discipline 19

A major problem with Kuhn’s original presentation for many commentators was the varying
use of the term ‘paradigm’. Masterman (1970, p. 61) identified no less than 21 different usages,
which ‘makes paradigm elucidation genuinely difficult for the superficial reader’. From these, she
distilled three main groups of definitions:

1 the metaparadigms (or metaphysical paradigms), which can be equated with ‘world views’, or
general organising principles;
2 the sociological paradigms, which are the concrete scientific achievements of a community
defining their working habits; and
3 the artefact or construct paradigms, the classic works (exemplars) that provide the tools for
future work.

The second provides the structure within which individual scientists work, whereas the third
presents their means for puzzle-solving; the first comprises their overall view of the nature of
science and its objects of study. Kuhn accepted Masterman’s representation of his work, and later
writings clarified his views, focusing almost entirely on the second and third of Masterman’s
definitions. He indicated that if he rewrote the original book he would give primacy not to
paradigms but to scientific communities (Kuhn, 1970a). These operate at various scales: the
global community of natural scientists, for example; the main professional disciplinary groups
(physicists, chemists, etc.); and intradisciplinary groups working on particular empirical problems
(such as nuclear physicists). He focused on the last: ‘Communities of this sort are the units that
this book has presented as the producers and validators of scientific knowledge. Paradigms are
something shared by members of such groups’ (p. 178). With regard to the use of the term
‘paradigm’ in this context, Kuhn (1977, p. 460) suggested a two-part definition, the second
component fitting within the first: ‘One sense of “paradigm” is global, embracing all the shared
commitments of a scientific group; the other isolates a particularly important sort of commitment
and is thus a subset of the first.’
The global, or sociological, definition is of a disciplinary matrix: ‘what the members of a
scientific community, and they alone, share’ (p. 460). It comprises (Kuhn, 1970c, pp. 152 ff.): the
accepted generalisations, shared commitments to particular models, or guiding frameworks for
the construction and validation of theories.
Revolutions can therefore involve:

1 the replacement of one exemplar by another;


2 modification of the existing set of exemplars to accommodate new material; or
3 the replacement of the disciplinary matrix.

The last, a revolution in the sociological paradigm, is likely to be a major event in the history
of a science; the first and second can occur without affecting the fundamentals of the
disciplinary matrix. Others, such as Lakatos (1978a, 1978b) and Popper (1970) responded to
Kuhn. Writing about Kuhn years later, Alexander Bird (2000, p. 50) suggests a continuum of
changes.
Lakatos not only recognised but also required theoretical pluralism (which led to criticism
from Barry Barnes, 1982, that his is a normative view of science, not a positive one like Kuhn’s).
Within this pluralist situation, ‘Criticism of a programme is a long and often frustrating process and
one must treat budding programmes leniently’ (Lakatos, 1978a, p. 92). Although Lakatos denies
Kuhn’s concept of normal science as one of paradigm dominance in a discipline, he accepts that
progressive research programmes comprise relatively routine extensions to knowledge through the
testing of new hypotheses derived from their positive heuristic. Refutations are rare; the aim is
verification and progress.
20 The nature of an academic discipline

Popper argued against this, claiming that ‘science is essentially critical’ (1970, p. 55) and
characterised not by normal science but by extraordinary research. To him, the normal scientist is
really an applied scientist:

‘Normal’ science . . . is the activity of the non-revolutionary, or more precisely, the not-too-
critical professional: of the science student who accepts the ruling dogma of the day; who does
not wish to challenge it; and who accepts a new revolutionary theory only if almost everybody
else is ready to accept it – if it becomes fashionable by a kind of bandwagon effect. To resist a
new fashion needs perhaps as much courage as was needed to bring it about . . . The success of
the ‘normal’ scientist consists, entirely, in showing that the ruling theory can be properly and
satisfactorily applied in order to reach a solution of the puzzle in question.
(Popper, 1970, pp. 52–3)

For Popper, science consists of bold conjectures and the conduct of empirical research
(he had experimental science in mind) designed to refute them. In his view of science (Popper,
1970, p. 77) hypotheses can never be wholly verified, only falsified. It is the testability
of any concept that matters. The ability of concepts to endure attempts to disprove them is
at the heart of what science ought to be. Kuhn’s (1970a, p. 243) response was that ‘[Popper] and
his group argue that the scientist should try at all times to be a critic and a proliferator of alternate
theories. I urge the desirability of an alternate strategy which reserves such behaviour for special
occasions’.
Popper’s arguments were extended by Feyerabend (1975), who claimed that science is a
series of accidents – which is how it should be. Science should be allowed to evolve in that way,
since this is the best means of ensuring progress. Most discoveries have been made by individuals
who either deliberately or unwittingly flouted the rules, but modern scientific education tries to
prevent this by constraining its practitioners into myopic paradigms. Feyerabend (1975, p. 187)
claims that the only rule in science should be ‘anything goes’, in a scientific anarchy whose
hallmark, like a political anarchy’s, is ‘opposition to the established order of things: to the state; its
institutions, the ideologies that support and glorify those institutions’. Like Popper, however,
Feyerabend presents a normative model, concerned with major scientific developments and not
with their everyday extensions. Regarding the latter, if Lakatos rather than Kuhn is correct,
revolutions take a long time, so a discipline could be characterised by dissensus rather than
consensus over much of its history. Is it likely that a body of scholars (especially a large body) will
agree on ends and means, and will not differ at all on fundamental interpretations, except very
occasionally and then only for fairly short periods? Branches may break away, however, establishing
new communities – by ‘quiet revolutions’ (Johnston, 1978a). Such breaks may not be favoured by
the parent community on political grounds, for they are likely to be against the interests of the
disciplinary bureaucracy; separate communities competing for students and research funds, yet
covering similar subject-matter, are unpopular.Thus, communities may be prepared to accommodate
dissenting groups, even potential revolutionaries, rather than risk breakaway success.
Such dissent is often contained, however, and may be marginalised or ignored (see
Lichtenberger, 1984, for an example from within geography). The results are frequently complex,
comprising interconnections, disputes, disjunctures and alliances which can be approached from
a variety of perspectives – for example, along the different lines indicated by Mark Boyle (2005),
that were described in the Preface. Reviewing a similar range, including analysis of the social
relations between individuals within scholarly institutions, the development of the subject in
universities, patterns of citation, biography and the one taken here, that of the history of ideas and
themes, Stoddart (1986, p. 27) noted how: ‘Each of these approaches has its own validity and its
own strengths. I claim here only that the history of geography is an infinitely richer and more
varied landscape than acquaintance with the standard works on the subject would suggest.’
The nature of an academic discipline 21

Stoddart is among those who critiqued the way that the paradigm concept was being applied
in telling the history of geography, or being used to bolster the case for new ways of doing human
geography. We will return to this issue in the last chapter of the book. But it should be noted here
that he has since been joined by others – drawing on a variety of other frameworks of interpretation
of the history and structure of disciplines.

Other frames: Bourdieu and Foucault, and other interpretations


All of Kuhn’s examples come from the natural sciences (as Kuhn, 1977, himself stressed). Indeed,
Steve Fuller notes that:

Kuhn observed that social scientists could never agree on what counted as an exemplary piece
of research, and so could never establish a common frame of reference for anchoring their
disputes . . . Accordingly, Kuhn concluded that the history of the social sciences has not
witnessed a clear succession of paradigms because social scientists have been unable to agree
on research exemplars to underwrite the activity of normal science. . . . the peculiar character
of the social sciences can be traced historically to the social scientists’ having been guided by
larger, conceptually unwieldy social problems that cannot be reduced to well-defined puzzles.
Consequently historians of each of the social sciences have portrayed their disciplines’ trajectory
as pulled in three distinct directions that can be characterized independently of any intrinsic
concern for the nature of social reality:

1. From above (in an administrative or managerial capacity, as the trustees of state or business);
2. From within (in an ethical capacity, as the secular successor of pastoral theology);
3. From below (in a rhetorical capacity, as the voice of politically disenfranchised groups).
(2000, p. 228)

Working more on social sciences, humanities and professions (such as law) which have a basis
in university disciplines, the French sociologist Pierre Bourdieu (1988) proposed that they comprise
semi-autonomous ‘fields’. These are structured social spaces, with power structures that relate to
but have a relative autonomy from other class or social structures. Bourdieu’s book on these,
focusing on academia in France, with most of the material drawn from his own discipline of
sociology, appeared in French in 1984 and was translated into English in 1988. It thus entered
English language debates about disciplinary change at a time when Kuhn’s had already been debated
for a quarter of a century. Bourdieu has since been seen as a rich entrée to thinking about power
and structures of the academy (Swartz, 1997; and for a reading of his work into geography, Sidaway,
1997, 2000b). But his work is less of a template for studying changes in a discipline than a mirror
to its structures that links them to contests for authority, distinction and power. Swartz (1997,
p. 273) notes that for Bourdieu, ‘it is the material and symbolic reward structures, not the normative
ideals, that more decisively shape scientific behaviour’. In other words, the focus on ideas and
explanations that Kuhn foregrounds needs to be supplemented with nuanced accounts of power,
influence, connections and status.
Changes in geography have also been interpreted in terms of intergenerational struggle
(whereby one paradigm becomes associated with a particular cohort, who seek to advance their
careers in opposition to their forebears), as in Peter Taylor’s (1976) account of debates about
quantification or John Mohan’s (2004) claim that change in human geography resembles a product
cycle, with new theories quickly replacing older ones, in a succession of trends. We return to these
and other debates about the evolution of the discipline in the last chapter. At this point, however, it
is important to note that another potential framework for analysing a social science discipline
without the particular world view of Kuhn and his critics is outlined in Foucault’s (1972) The
22 The nature of an academic discipline

Archaeology of Knowledge. This offers an analysis of the ‘pure description’ of discourses, unified
systems of statements (however expressed) that can only be understood within their context
(Foucault, 1972, p. 97): ‘One cannot say a sentence, one cannot transform it into a statement, unless
a collateral space is brought into operation.’ Anything said or written can only be understood
by those privy to the context of the discourse; as with a language, one can only comprehend
the words, and the sequence in which they are used, because one understands the rules governing
their use.
According to this view, the history of ideas is the history of discourses, of systems (somewhat
akin to languages) used for the discussion of subjects that are defined within the discourses. There
is, for example, no fixed definition of madness; each discourse that discusses it has its own definition
and any discussion of madness is particular to that definition and the discourse in which it is set.
The nature of a discourse is deposited in a collection of texts and practices, and it is the function of
archaeology to reconstitute the discourse from such ‘archives’, to describe and understand what
was being done in a particular configuration (Foucault, 1972, pp. 138–40, 157–65). As Foucault
describes it, nineteenth-century medical science:

was characterized not so much by its objects or concepts as by a certain style, a certain constant
manner of statement . . . medicine no longer consisted of a group of traditions, observations and
heterogeneous practices, but of a corpus of knowledge that presupposed the same way of
looking at things . . . [in addition it was] a group of hypotheses about life and death, of ethical
choices, of therapeutic decisions, of institutional regulations, of teaching models, as a group of
descriptions . . . if there is a unity, its principle is not therefore a determined form of statements;
is it not rather the group of rules, which, simultaneously or in turn, have made possible purely
perceptual descriptions? What one must characterize and individualize is the coexistence of
these dispersed and heterogeneous statements; the system that governs their division, the
degree to which they depend upon one another, the way in which they interlock or exclude one
another, the transformation that they undergo, and the play of their location, arrangement, and
replacement.
(1972, pp. 33–4)

Discourses are therefore sets of mutually agreed rules that govern description and discussion
among the members who agree those rules, and are similar to the scientific communities given
central place in Kuhn’s (1970a) later statements. They are not independent of wider conditions,
however. Archaeology may identify separate discursive formations, but these must be related to
what Foucault calls the episteme:

something like a world-view, a slice of history common to all branches of knowledge, which
imposes on each one the same norms and postulates, a general stage of reason, a certain
structure of thought that the men [sic] of a particular period cannot escape.
(1972, p. 19)

This sets out how a particular world view (metaparadigm?) predominates during a period and
influences the contents and determines the parameters of ‘individual’ discourses (the idea of an
individual is itself the product of a particular discourse, for example). Presumably, too, there must
be periods of competition between epistemes (which may involve a similar process to that outlined
by Lakatos). Foucault is less interested in how such change occurs, however.
Foucault’s ideas set the study of scientific disciplines more firmly in the context of the wider
environment in which (and for which) they are practised than is the case with the other approaches
discussed here, all of which very largely abstract the study of science from its social milieu.
(As Berdoulay (1981, p. 9) expresses it, ‘little interest is paid to historical contexts or intellectual
The nature of an academic discipline 23

climates since the focus is placed on the internal evolution of each science’.) Such abstraction is
especially unfortunate for the social sciences, the disciplines that investigate and interact with their
milieu and whose contents, in the broadest sense if not in detail, are likely to be strongly influenced
by that context. Just how social science and society interact is challenging to map in detail (as, of
course, is the interaction between natural science and society because the contents of the former,
too, are clearly influenced by the environmental constraints), and the reception of Foucault’s
proposals of shifting epistemes has generated much debate.
That human geography should be studied in its social context appears an irrefutable claim,
however. The latter section of this chapter outlines that context.

Daily life, texts and authority in the (social) sciences


Many of the major approaches to the history of academic disciplines, including those summarised
here, focus in particular on changes in their practices rather than the everyday pursuit of research
within agreed frameworks. This – what Kuhn saw as ‘normal science’ – occupies most academics for
most of their time; they conduct research within an established matrix of practices, and rarely
become involved in more general debates about the nature of those practices and whether their
discipline or subdiscipline is pursuing a ‘correct path’. Revolutionary calls are rare; revolutions are
even rarer.
That matrix of accepted disciplinary practices may be very diverse, comprising a substantial
number of the ‘villages’ that Geertz (1983) identified with each group’s members undertaking
their original investigations of specific topics and/or subject areas in a particular way. These are not
independent entities – many of the ‘villages’ have no specific identity – but their interdependence
is often limited. In their day-to-day teaching activities and interactions with students and depart-
mental colleagues, academics encounter other approaches, but many of their formal interactions
tend to be with colleagues in other institutions, who they meet only rarely at conferences and
similar gatherings but with whom – given the benefits of electronic media – they can be in regular
impersonal contact, sharing ideas and manuscripts. And many of their formal interactions will be
directed at relatively limited audiences; although the general journals published by the major
learned societies are among the most prestigious for placing one’s research findings, there is now a
plethora of journals directed at specific subfields and which are the main destinations for special-
ised research findings.
The presentation of ‘normal science’ suggests that for substantial periods of time academic
disciplines are relatively untroubled by debates about what, why and how their members’ research
should proceed. Their academic space is divided up into a series of overlapping specialisms
in which practitioners pursue new knowledge without challenges regarding the means of
production that they deploy. And as disciplines have become larger with the expansion of higher
education, so that archipelago of academic villages has become more extensive – and pluralistic
in its orientations.
This is not to say that there are no debates about disciplinary means and ends and challenges
to the status quo. In part this is because of the contest for resources within a discipline, especially
in the locales where it is mainly practised – university departments. With few exceptions these will
be relatively catholic bodies in a discipline where a range of paradigms (disciplinary matrices and
exemplars, if not world views) prevail, and although the representatives of each may co-exist in
reasonable harmony for much of the time, there are invariably tensions over resources. If a teaching
position is to be filled, for example, different research groups may compete for it to be allied to
their specialism – and there will be similar debates over degree curricula, the allocation of research
funds, and so forth. Political contestation if not conflict is thus common, as academics with different
views on what their discipline’s dominant practices should be seek a significant – if not dominant
– place for them within the department’s activities.
24 The nature of an academic discipline

Such politics are local and may have no implications beyond the particular institution, with
the result that university departments in the same discipline often differ substantially in the
particular aspects of the discipline that they promote – and also in those that they (relatively at least)
ignore. But occasionally the politics becomes a large-scale activity, because groups want to promote
changes across the discipline more generally, for a variety of possible reasons: they may have
identified what they consider a superior set of practices to that currently deployed, for example.
Such challenges to the status quo almost invariably involve collective action and, as Frickel and
Gross (2005) argue, are necessarily contentious and political: groups are competing for the ‘heart
and soul’ of a discipline.
According to a model of such intradisciplinary contestation developed by Latour (1999; for its
application to the history of regional science (p. 83 of this book), see Trevor Barnes, 2003a, 2004a),
four interrelated, largely sequential, processes are involved in mounting such a challenge:

1 mobilisation, which involves the announcement of a new agenda for the discipline, stressing
its novelty and claimed superiority over (at least some of) current disciplinary practices;
2 autonomisation, involving strategies to promote the new agenda to various audiences, seeking
to attract a broad support base for the project;
3 building alliances by winning space for the project within the discipline, such as in teaching
programmes, through which support from students – and thus the next generation of
researchers and academics – can be gained; and
4 public representation – whereas building alliances involves intradisciplinary politics wider
support in the academy and beyond can help those promoting the new agenda (if, for example,
research funding bodies accept the new approach as part of the discipline’s portfolio).

The result of such a challenge is usually that room is found in the discipline for the new approach,
and its size and influence spread over time as those it seeks to replace slowly wither. (All members
of a discipline are unlikely to be converted – although this may be the case in the natural sciences
where a proposed change leads to a fundamentally new paradigm because those it challenges are
totally discredited. Given the subjectivity that underpins most of the social sciences, that is unlikely
to happen there.)
In the challenge for intradisciplinary status it may be that the logic of the new agenda
wins over adherents in an entirely uncontroversial way. That is rare, however, because any challenge
to the status quo raises doubts about not only current practices but also the standing of their
practitioners. Thus a variety of strategies may have to be deployed in the politics of potential
disciplinary change, including:

1 the politics of denigration, whereby the promoters of the new agenda argue that the practices
they wish to displace are unworthy of a place in the disciplinary portfolio;
2 the politics of critique, which are less assertive than the first strategy and seek to win over
converts by argument and demonstration rather than assertion;
3 the politics of dismissal, in which previous practices are simply dismissed as no longer
viable;
4 the politics of silence in which dismissal is assumed because the ‘to be replaced’ practices are
simply ignored in the writings and arguments of the new agenda’s promoters – a strategy
particularly valuable in the autonomisation stage of the process involving students: if they are
not made aware of particular practices their choice set will be constrained and their own
practices hopefully focused on the new agenda;
5 the politics of accommodation, whereby advocates – having mobilised considerable support
– seek a place alongside established practices (which they hope will subsequently wither)
during the building alliances and public representation stages; and
The nature of an academic discipline 25

6 the politics of unity which involves arguing that the discipline, and its ability to attract
resources, will be stronger if the commonality of various approaches is presented outside the
discipline, rather than a view of a fissiparous discipline with no clear trajectory.

The tactics employed in these strategies will vary according to the local context. While much
of the initial debate over alternatives may take place in the relative privacy of seminar rooms and
similar locales, if a major shift in a discipline’s orientation is to be achieved, those debates will
almost certainly become public – in the discipline’s journals and other publications. In the politics
of silence, for example, textbooks may be the vehicle deployed for mobilising student support; if
certain practices are not presented in the volumes that tell students what their chosen subject
studies and how, then they are, in effect, captured by those approaches that are represented to them
– until such time as they may begin to question the status quo (see Johnston, 2006). The extent and
intentionality of such textbook omissions/foci in propagating geography’s agendas is contested
(Hubbard and Kitchin, 2007; and the response by Johnston, 2007b). However, the fact that a
leading disciplinary journal (Progress in Human Geography) regularly contains an article on classic ‘text-
books that shaped generations’ indicates that many academic geographers recall, retain and are
sometimes still responding to those texts that inspired them when students.

Geographers, Kuhn and contexts


Soon after the appearance of Kuhn’s (1962) classic volume, the concept of a paradigm was
introduced to the geographic literature by Haggett and Chorley (1967). Since then it has been
widely used in discussions of geography’s history, not least in previous editions of this book
(on which see Mair, 1986). Its notion of normal science punctuated by revolutions was soon
discarded, however, as it was realised that several incommensurate (or entangled) paradigms were
co-existing within the discipline, and more seemed to be added on a regular basis without others
being dropped; the discipline was seen as what Alexander Bird (2000, p. 31), following Hoyningen-
Huene (1993), terms an ‘immature science’: a ‘mature science’ is one wherein normal science is
practised within a single paradigm, whereas an ‘immature science’ has ‘several competing paradigm-
like schools’. Maturity only comes when there is consensus, when:

one school scores a victory over its competitors by producing a signal achievement. That
achievement wins defectors from other schools and attracts the favour of younger scientists.
Support for the competitors dwindles and they eventually die out.

This suggests ‘political’ decision-making, at least in part. It may be that all members of a
community accept the ‘achievement’ (with those who do not perhaps defecting to other
disciplines), or it may be that those with power within the discipline impose it, by declining to
make any appointments of people who challenge it, and by stifling dissent from within. According
to Bird (2000, p. 32):

Immature science is that initial period in the history of a science that occurs when for the first
time sufficient interest in a phenomenon or set of related phenomena crystallizes distinct groups
or schools around particular theories or approaches; the schools not only pursue research on
the basis of their favoured ideas but also compete with one another for intellectual, social and
professional supremacy.

This book clearly demonstrates that on those terms geography has been an immature science
throughout the period surveyed. It also, at least implicitly, poses the question whether it will ever
reach maturity, as defined by Bird.
26 The nature of an academic discipline

Indeed, unless such ‘maturity’ is imposed on a discipline by preventing dissent and debate, it
is doubtful whether any discipline can be termed a mature science in a strict sense. That certainly
may be the case with the social sciences. As Bird (2000, p. 267) noted, Kuhn’s book ‘had little direct
influence on the functioning of the natural sciences but its impact on social science was enormous’.
That impact included the provision of ‘a template whereby the histories of the social sciences,
almost entirely ignored in Structure itself, could be described’. We return to the uses of Kuhn in
human geography in this book’s final chapter; at this stage we merely note that too much emphasis
in geographers’ discussions of Kuhn has focused on the concept of cycles of normal science
punctuated by revolutions and less on that of communities, their struggle for dominance and their
promotion of alternative discourses, which Derek Gregory (1994, p. 11) identifies as ‘all the ways
in which we communicate with one another . . . that cast networks of signs, symbols and practices
through which we make our world(s) meaningful to ourselves and to others’ in local contexts, ‘the
contexts and casements that shape our local knowledge’.
Nor do we seek to resolve all these issues in Geography and Geographers. Our contribution to the
task of charting the history of Anglo-American human geography over the last seven decades
involves identifying the major features in the various debates. That is the role of the next eight
chapters; they are followed by one which evaluates those debates, not by trying to reconcile the
various positions, but rather by setting them in context and seeking to appreciate why and when
they occurred and were settled (to the extent that they were). Moreover, these frameworks for
interpreting the evolution of geography have relatively little to say about how it has been mediated
through places, its geography. While recognising the unevenness and power structures that
accompany it (Paasi, 2005), some have argued that national trends or national ‘schools’ in geography
are less important than hitherto in an increasingly globalised academic arena, dominated by the
English language (Claval, 2009). Even within anglophone universities and predominantly
anglophone countries, however, there have been key nodes, centres and relative peripheries. Writing
from one of the latter, Andrew Wilson and Matthew Henry:

argue that the evolution of geography in New Zealand cannot be simply read off from geography
as conceived and practised in what Johnston and Sidaway [2004] identify as the centres of
Anglophonic geography. Rather, it has been constituted between the rhythms of a wider
Anglophonic tradition within which geographers in New Zealand have been firmly embedded and
the situated pressures of an evolving context in which geography has often been framed by a
colonial legacy and emerging projects of national development.
(2011, p. 116)

A fuller account of these, and other, geographies of geography and geographers are beyond our
scope here (though we will return to them in the final chapter), for the focus remains those broad
rhythms, which in turn are themselves situated, not least among wider social, political, cultural and
economic environments.

The external environment


The discussion so far has suggested that scientific disciplines (and/or discourses) comprise
communities and subcommunities, small societies which are microcosms of their containing social
systems. As such, the proper study of how they operate is sociological, although philosophy may
provide a normative framework.
Sociological studies of academic disciplines accept that such communities are not autonomous.
Their members are not isolated and they need the support of a wider society in order to exist:
society employs academics to teach and research – either collectively, because universities receive
The nature of an academic discipline 27

public funding to teach and undertake research, or through market systems, whereby students pay
for their education and sponsors pay for research. Whereas scientists may to some extent be able to
impose their own priorities over what type of work is done, they are strongly influenced by external
factors:

Social, technical and economic determinants routinely affect the rate and direction of scientific
growth. . . . It is true that much scientific change occurs despite, rather than because of, external
direction or financial control. . . . Progress in the disinterested study [of certain] . . . areas has
probably occurred just that bit more rapidly because of their relevance to other matters.
(Barnes, 1982, pp. 102–3)

The study of a discipline must be set in its societal context. It must not be assumed that
members of academic communities fully accept that context and its directives and impulses.
They may wish to counter them, and use their academic base as a focus for discontent and
promotion of alternatives. But the (potential) limits to that discontent are substantial. Most
university academic communities are dependent (indirectly if not directly) for their existence
on public funds disbursed by governments which may use their financial power to influence, if not
direct, what is taught and researched. Some universities (notably in the USA) are dependent on
private sources of finance, so they must convince their sponsors and students that their work is
relevant to current societal concerns (as Taylor, 1985a, suggests).
In that context, the Second World War is more than a convenient period from which to
commence this chapter on the history of human geography; it marked a major watershed in the
development of the societies which are the prime focus of the book – the UK and the USA. It
cannot be considered in isolation, however. Just as important for the present discussion are the
worldwide economic depression which preceded it and the Cold War, the economic boom, and
then the recession and restructuring which followed. For the first time, a major international con-
flict was not determined solely by sacrifices in battles on land and sea, although there were many
of them during the Second World War. And the extra dimensions of this war did not just involve the
development of air space as a further arena for conflict – as well as restructuring views of spatial
relationships (Schulten, 2001; Abrahamson, 2010). The war was fought not only between military
forces with guns and bombs but also between scientists, and victory was hastened, if not ensured,
by the scientific superiority of the Allied Powers, most obviously at Hiroshima and Nagasaki, as well
as in the cracking of secret codes. Science and technology had long been major elements in the
developing industrialisation of the Western world, but their dominance was established between
1939 and 1945, and there was to be no retreat from the many technological advances made by the
researchers involved in the military effort. Thus, the war heralded the predominance of technology
and ‘science’ in human affairs, not least in the militarisation of academic research during the
subsequent Cold War, in which, according to Trevor Barnes (2008b), some geographers were
implicated.
Associated with this growth in scientific activity, and its consequent prestige (with govern-
ments and with society at large), was a parallel development of social engineering. The major
economic depression of the 1930s, inaugurated by the Wall Street crash of 1929, had a massive
impact on governments and stimulated many measures aimed at relieving poverty and deprivation,
simultaneously assuaging the liberal conscience. In the USA, this was represented by the New Deal
legislation of President Roosevelt’s governments, which aimed at relief and encouragement to
industry and, through the Social Security Act, providing public support for those who, by no fault
of their own, were indigent. Similar measures were introduced by the national government in the
UK; more were foreshadowed by plans formulated during the war, such as those promoted in
the Beveridge Report on social security, and the Labour Party’s landslide election victory in 1945
heralded the introduction of many social democratic policies which gave government a much
28 The nature of an academic discipline

greater peacetime role in the organisation of the economy and society than previously envisaged,
let alone achieved.
This development of social engineering was associated with a rising status for the social
sciences, and a great expansion in their activities. Economics achieved prestige first, notably through
the contributions of Keynes and others to solving problems of the depression, the organisation of
economies during wartime, and participation in the planning of a new world economic order after
the war. Others followed. Social psychological research was widely used in the evaluation
of personnel by the armed forces, and after the war opinion surveys proved valuable to govern-
ments and political parties while market research was increasingly used by industry and commerce
(along with psychology in its advertising efforts). All these fields adopted the ‘scientific methods’
of the more prestigious hard sciences, and their successes were envied by other disciplines, such as
sociology, social administration and, later, geography. To be scientific was to be respectable
and useful.
The war years saw the end of the extreme economic deprivations of the depression, as manu-
facturing output was boosted to provide the machinery of war. Afterwards, there were many years
of doing without to be compensated for, and with full employment, government direction of, and
increasing involvement in, economic affairs, plus the need to re-equip industries, the two decades
following the war were characterised by an economic boom in the Western world. Technological
developments which had emerged in the 1920s–1930s, and which had been finessed in wartime,
found wider applications in mass markets and continued to be fostered by Cold War research and
development. Apart from the greater government involvement, this era in industrial development
was marked by another major new characteristic, the advance of the giant firm, including the
multinational corporation. The concentration and centralisation of capital proceeded rapidly;
the average size of firms and factories increased and the economy of the world became dominated
by a relatively small number of concerns. The decline and eclipse of the overseas empires in the
context of the rise of the American and Soviet superpowers and the birth of the ‘Third World’ out
of the debris of war and imperialism, all reinforced the sense of a fast-changing ‘new world’.
Rebuilding the ravaged war arenas placed new demands on societies, and the planning profes-
sion emerged from earlier obscurity to take on a major role in preparing the blueprint for a new
social order. The need for such action in the UK was realised during the war with the preparation
of a series of reports concerned with future land-use patterns, and with the spatial distribution of
economic activity, at local and regional scales. Cities were to be rebuilt; new towns were to be con-
structed; a more balanced interregional distribution of industry and employment was to be ensured;
agricultural land was to be protected and residential environments were to be improved: all of this
made great demands on social scientists, as well as engineers (an opportunity recognised by some
geographers: Johnston, 2002a, 2003b, 2003c). The greater degree of commitment to the private
ownership of abundant land in the USA led to slower acceptance of the need for spatial planning
there, but its heyday came with the rapid growth of problems involved in catering for the upsurge
of automobile ownership and use: transport planning and engineering soon became major activi-
ties, allied with the automobile industry and the companies which constructed the major highways
(many of which were designed for ‘strategic’ defence purposes in the Cold War). Suburbanisation
(and later gentrification) and other new socio-spatial structures of mobility changed landscapes in
much of North America and Western Europe in striking ways. A baby boom after the war and new
migration flows (e.g. among black and Hispanic communities in the USA, and from the former
Caribbean, Asian or African colonies and parts of the Balkans to Western Europe) shifted the social,
‘racial’ and cultural dynamics of many cities. Many of these trends had begun before the war, but
they accelerated and some of their vectors shifted afterwards.
All the associated tasks of governance – related to economic growth and planning, spatial plan-
ning, social administration, technological change, management, etc. – generated a need for edu-
cated personnel, and the universities received unprecedented demands for their graduates to serve
The nature of an academic discipline 29

the new needs of society. Existing universities and colleges expanded and many more were founded.
Science and social science departments grew in numbers and size to meet student demand.
The additional academics were involved in research, which became a salient component of
academic life and so increased the tempo of paradigm development and questioning. Rather
than places where a small elite was educated for the professions and a few privileged individuals
followed their research interests, the universities became centres of society’s development –
the ‘white-hot technological revolution’ which Harold Wilson promised the British in the early
1960s. Research projects became bigger, supported by large grants from outside bodies (including
government-established research councils) and carried out by specially employed graduates; the
rate and volume of publication increased exponentially (Stoddart, 1967a; Johnston, 1995a, 1995b,
1996b).
The years from 1945 to about 1965 were a period of scientific and technological dominance,
therefore. It was argued that the problems of production had been solved, because enough goods
and services could be provided to satisfy all (and such benefits – it was argued – would soon accrue
to the ‘developing world’ too). The problems of distribution were still being tackled, however, for as
yet there was inequality of provision at all spatial scales. But these could be handled, it was argued,
through a combination of market processes and state provision, and the prospect of a prosperous and
healthy life for all was widely canvassed. Academic disciplines were contributing substantially to this
problem-solving by their own – scientific – progress. Advances in the natural sciences and technol-
ogies were solving the problems of production – of food, housing and consumer goods – as well
as of ill-health. Meanwhile advances in the social sciences were aiding in the management of success
and the delivery of well-being. Investment in education was thus investment in social progress
(as well as an investment in the life chances of the individuals involved).
The deprivations of the 1920s and 1930s produced political responses two decades later, char-
acterised by a determination not only to ensure no return to economic depression but also to
provide permanent protection to those who suffered short- or long-term deprivation. The Beveridge
Report in the UK identified five causes for concern: want, disease, ignorance, squalor and idleness.
Policies aimed at their removal led to the creation of the major edifice of the Welfare State, which
offered basic minimal standards of living for all, through such mechanisms as a National Health
Service that was free at the point of demand; a universal education service for all aged between 5
and 14 (later 15 and then 16), plus subsidised further and higher education systems; subsidised
state housing; universal child allowances; unemployment benefits; benefits and care for the sick and
disabled; and universal pensions. Other countries created different structures, but the overall pattern
in the ‘developed world’ was of a major state role in sustaining its citizens (see Johnston, 1992).
Growth of the ‘interventionist state’ involved a major change to the nature of polity as well as
society. A much wider range of activities came within government orbits, and the public bureau-
cracies grew accordingly – with consequent benefits in both employment opportunities for
graduates and outlets for applying scientific and social scientific research. The decades after the
Second World War saw the dominance of the welfare–corporate state in public affairs, with policy
advisers and analysts provided by many professional groups (including scientists and social
scientists).
Despite the successes of this initial postwar period, some doubted the desirability of such an
all-embracing state. These concerns were growing during the 1960s, and by the early 1970s were
having a major impact on the world scene. The seeds of doubt were many. Initially they focused,
especially in the USA, on the problems of nuclear weapon development and of war, particularly the
increasingly unpopular intervention in Vietnam and surrounding countries where technology was
not carrying all before it against strong popular resistance; the casualty rates, destruction and
corruption were increasingly deplored. Alongside were a number of major humanitarian concerns,
including doubts about the inequalities that continued, both on a world scale and within the
‘successful’ capitalist societies. Poverty was not being alleviated; if anything, the disparities between
30 The nature of an academic discipline

rich and poor were being extended (and continued to be experienced through ‘race’ and racism),
and absolute standards of living remained appallingly low in many parts of the world. The prospects
for solving these problems were much less rosy than they had been a few years earlier, it seemed.
Furthermore, it was increasingly realised that success was being bought at considerable cost.
Scientific and technological advancement required the dominance and discipline of the machine
and the large factory. Work for large proportions of the labour force was being made more repetitive
and boring as skilled tasks were taken over by automated production and assembly lines. Alienation
of the individual from society was increasing. Particular groups suffered more than others did, as
the result of prejudice and discrimination. The status of black people and women became the foci
of emerging civil and human rights movements, which extended later to other oppressed groups
within Western society. Finally, interest was kindled in the growing degradation of the environment
to fuel the production goals of advanced capitalist societies.
The problems of the dignity of the individual, the repression of minorities, the quality
of life and the depletion of environmental resources were not new in the late 1960s. What was
realised then, however, was that the form of social ‘progress’ advanced during the previous decades
was in many cases exacerbating and not solving such problems. As the realisation grew, so the
proposed solutions varied. To some, the problems could be solved by greater state involvement, on
international and national scales. Human and civil rights must be protected; greater equality must
be achieved through the redistribution of wealth; the environment must be conserved, and
where necessary preserved. In the language of the previous section, the research programme was
maintained, but major efforts were made within its positive heuristic to solve the many anomalies.
To others, this solution was insufficient. It would simply generate new anomalies because, according
to the developing critique of capitalist systems, these are necessary to social ‘progress’; capitalism,
it was argued, necessarily survives on inequalities, on alienation and on the degradation of the
environment.
Universities were the focus of much of this developing concern. There were major
confrontations between students and the authorities in the late 1960s, in particular, for example, at
Berkeley, Chicago, London and Paris, and the student body was at the forefront of the anti-war
movements. Some academics, notably in the social sciences, focused on the ‘managerial’ issues
involved in producing a ‘better, more equal’ society, and these were considered more crucial than
the ‘production’ issues covered by the natural sciences and technologies. A threefold division
developed. In one, the need for social scientists to become more active in developing solutions to
the problems of distribution and environmental depletion was advanced: social science must
become more ‘relevant’, more ‘policy-­oriented’, within the constraints of the proposed societal
‘research programme’. A second argued for greater concentration on the problems of individual
alienation; people should be released from the overbearing dominance of the machine and the big
organisation and encouraged to take a much greater part in creating their own lives. The individual
needed protection against the increasingly distrusted expert. Finally, a third group developed a
critique of capitalist society, seeking to show that while specific problems may be soluble, this
would merely lead to others, while the general problems of inequality and injustice (Dorling,
2010) would remain because they are endemic to that mode of social organisation. The call was for
major social reform – from some, revolution (the vanguard of which was often identified with the
Vietnam War and other Third World liberation struggles) – as the only long-term solution to
the problems of human dignity and inequality. Feminist and civil rights movements in Western
societies emerged out of similar radical commitments. These would influence and inspire other
movements – for gay rights/liberation and native/indigenous/first people’s rights or advocating
self-determination for small/colonised nations or linguistic minorities, for example. Much talk of
freedom and revolution was in the air. Changes in popular culture (music, fashion and art) and
academia soon embodied these changes. Indeed, academia would be at the forefront of ensuing
contests.
The nature of an academic discipline 31

The force of these arguments can be identified in a variety of ways, not least the declining
popularity of scientific and technological subjects among students, and the growing demand for
places in the social sciences and humanities in the 1960s and 1970s. A further major problem then
arose, because Europe and North America spent substantial periods of the 1970s in economic
recession, punctuated by periods of increasingly speculative and inflation-prone growth. This was
accompanied by shifting geographies of production and consumption as lower-end service and
many industrial or extractive industries moved to cheaper sites of production overseas (Dicken,
2011). These shifts would be heightened in subsequent decades. The long boom of the 40s–70s
was over. And countervailing tendencies to the leftist radicalism of the 1960s developed – for
example, right-wing evangelistic forms of Christianity in the USA (themselves linked to the decline
of organised labour and the socio-spatial shifts, as dissected by Moreton, 2009) and Islamic
fundamentalism elsewhere (for example, the Iranian revolution of 1979).
The recessions were argued as reflecting the failure of state policies of demand management
employing Keynesian principles, and the search for an alternative saw a growing divergence
between political parties. In the UK, for example, the relatively high degree of cross-party agreement
over demand management broke down after 1974, with the Conservative Party promoting a greater
emphasis on markets and a reduction in the direct role of the state. The postwar political consensus
(in which Labour and Conservative policies had converged) was thus breaking down and the sense
of crisis and change was reinforced by the revival of violent conflict over Northern Ireland and of
nationalist claims in Scotland and Wales, all of which contested the established arrangements of the
British state (Nairn, 1977). This growing polarisation added to problems in the UK, some claim,
because of the uncertainty it engendered about the future; a change of government would bring a
major shift in policy. In the USA, similarly, there was a rise in support for ‘new right’ policies
promoted within the Republican Party, which countered the liberal policies of the Democrats
in the 1960s.
To some social theorists, recession and its major impacts (notably unemployment) should accel-
erate the demands for reform and revolution. Both the UK and the USA at the end of the 1970s elected
right-wing governments dedicated to programmes of economic regeneration by a reduction in public
expenditure and a liberalisation (or rather a deepening) of those capitalist forces that produced the
inequalities so widely condemned only a decade earlier. The role and size of the state were to be sig-
nificantly reduced (Gamble, 1988); its task was to enable a buoyant economy (particularly through
sound management of public finances and the removal of restrictive practices – notably, though not
only, by trade unions). ‘Enterprise’ was to be encouraged by a system which rewarded successful ini-
tiatives and risk-taking, and the result, it was claimed, would be a wealthier society from which all
would benefit, while the state provided protection only for those in proven need, whose ‘rights’ for
such assistance were balanced by state-created ‘obligations’ (Johnston, 1992). Elsewhere, communist
and socialist regimes either collapsed (as in the Soviet Union, and many regimes it supported in
Eastern Europe and some elsewhere, such as in Afghanistan and South Yemen), abandoned all socialist
commitments (as cases like Angola, Mozambique and Ethiopia) in the face of crisis and armed resist-
ance, or embraced many aspects of capitalism and became much more integrated into a globalising
economy (as in China and, to an extent, in Cuba and Vietnam). These developments continued (under
governments of a variety of political stances, but all committed to continue the shifts unleashed in the
1980s) until the latter part of the twenty-first century’s first decade, when, after a period of financial
and real-estate speculation, the failures in the banking system and the inability of a number of states
to sustain their very large budget deficits stimulated a major crisis and political response (Hendrikse
and Sidaway, 2010). In many countries, including the USA and the UK, the response involved a
fresh range of restructuring and marketisation (policies that have been termed ‘neoliberalism’ – see
Chapter 6), alongside attempts to stimulate a private-sector-led economic recovery out of recession.
Meanwhile, those cuts meant that few universities were recruiting additional academics (Franklin and
Ketchum, 2013), and the funding and governance of universities underwent further shifts.
32 The nature of an academic discipline

The contemporary situation


Education and research has been subject to significant policy changes since the 1970s because of
these deep shifts in the political context. For the first time for more than two decades, expenditure
on higher education in the UK was cut in 1981, for example, and the numbers of students
undertaking undergraduate degrees and postgraduate training reduced. The cuts were selective,
with relative protection for science and technology – growth in which was seen as necessary for
economic progress – alongside substantial reductions in the social sciences, believed by many
politicians to be the homes of left-wing radicals and the fomenters of discontent. Research funds
were similarly cut and redistributed. The reaction to these policies took the form, in part,
of attempts to defend academic freedom and independence and the need for a ‘critical
conscience’ within society (involving curricula designed to develop critical intellects as well as
foster ‘transferable skills’ to be deployed by graduates in the labour market) but there was also a
desire to reorient work within disciplines and make them more ‘relevant’ to current societal
concerns.
The educational system within which the research components of academic disciplines are
located benefited from the boom years of the first three post-1945 decades. Expansion was rapid
and academic activity was considerable. It was then cut back, especially in the UK, as – to some
decision-makers at least – expansion, especially expansion in the arts and social sciences (excluding
business studies and management), was seen as an unaffordable luxury. Economic progress did
not require large numbers of students and potential researchers being trained in disciplines with
little relevance to perceived societal needs and working on topics that were critical of societal
structure. Disciplines and scholars had to prove their relevance and sell their skills in the market-
place. Academic freedom was not entirely removed, but was to be curtailed, simply by denying
it resources. The result is that after participating gleefully in the booms of the 1950s and 1960s,
academia went into deep depression by the late 1970s, suffering internal and external crises of
confidence and subject to considerable political direction.
There was a reversal in political attitudes towards higher education at the end of the 1980s,
however, if not also in the funding provided. In the UK, for example, there was a growing realisation
that national competition in the restructured global economy required developing human resources
to their full potential, through a substantial increase in the participation rate of the 18–25-year-olds
in further and higher education and an expansion of continuing education for older people. It was
argued that the UK had a lower percentage of its population in higher education and obtaining
relevant qualifications compared with competitor, more successful, economies such as the USA and
much of continental Europe. More qualified students were needed and universities should be
allowed to expand, though in a more rigorous market system. (For an evaluation of these policies,
see Wolf, 2002; Palfreyman and Tapper, 2014.) When a Labour government was returned to power
in 1997 after eighteen years in opposition, it built on the expansion of student numbers during
the preceding decade with a goal of half of all school-leavers proceeding to a university education.
(The then percentage attending universities was in the high 30s, compared to less than 10 per cent
four decades earlier.) During its period of office, however, it ended the tradition of that university
education being free: students were required to pay an increasing proportion of their tuition costs,
with universities being given some flexibility in the amounts charged, though with a fixed
maximum (which most adopted).
Higher education was implicated in the post-2008 restructuring of public finances after the
banking and financial crises. Although a well-educated society was seen as necessary to national
economic prosperity in a world where many manufacturing and routine clerical jobs had been lost
to emerging economies, for example, the UK government decided that most university students
would have to pay fees towards their degree courses through publicly funded loans (later sold off
by the government to private firms) to be repaid once they passed an earnings threshold. Although
it was recognised that there was a public as well as a private gain from education, further direct
The nature of an academic discipline 33

public money (in the form of subsidies to the costs of degree courses) would only be made available
for those studying science, technology, engineering and mathematics (the STEM disciplines); there
would be no subsidy to universities for social science and humanities students. Research funding
was also reduced, especially in the non-STEM subjects, and there was an increased emphasis in
grant-making on the work’s potential impact, especially on ‘wealth creation’ and ‘wider impacts’
(see Collini, 2012). Since geography frequently bridged the science–social science/humanities
divides (given physical geography), the immediate negative consequences for the subject were
somewhat contained, but the longer-term ones are uncertain.
Thus, despite a demographic downturn (which particularly affected the size of the teenage
population in the socioeconomic classes from which students traditionally moved into higher
education), universities, polytechnics and colleges (most of them later elevated to university status)
in the 1990s were expected to expand their provision and numbers. However, they were expected
to become more efficient in doing their teaching (i.e. to take more students without additional
resources – Jenkins and Smith, 1993), and to obtain more income (especially for research and
continuing education) from sources other than the state, including their students (in many
countries overseas students are charged more than the standard fee for ‘home’ students). Further,
there was an increased emphasis on the ‘customer pays’ principle (for long the norm in North
America), with students meeting more of the costs of their education (in part, it was argued,
because they would benefit from higher incomes as a consequence of their qualifications and
expertise), so being more concerned with getting ‘value for money’; courses with a clear vocational
orientation became more popular. Again, geography fared relatively well in this respect, since the
mixture of qualitative and quantitative skills developed by its graduates conferred advantages in a
competitive labour market
The UK government also became increasingly concerned over accountability for the funds
provided to the universities for research. These were thought to be too widely spread and their
use subject to insufficient evaluation. From the late 1980s on, therefore, funding for research in
each discipline was to be concentrated on those institutions where work was evaluated as of high
quality internationally, and a series of regular Research Assessment Exercises (RAEs) was instituted
which grade all departments on the quality of their research outputs and environment; the
higher the grade achieved, the more money provided, and the greater the amount of time and
resources available for research. At the same time, the Research Councils, which provide funding
for individual projects, were restructured to promote ‘user interests’ and were directed to focus
their funding on areas of national economic importance identified through a regular Technology
Foresight exercise. Financial pressure was thus used to promote a particular orientation to
research (and teaching) within universities, one that was sympathetic to the ideology of the
‘enterprise economy’ (Johnston 1995a, 1995b). In addition, the ways in which universities were
funded meant that whereas success in the RAEs brought substantial financial rewards, teaching
activities did not; indeed, student numbers in universities were capped for some years, so that no
extra income could be obtained, and research – both income from external sponsors and the
public money allocated according to RAE grade – was the main source for new income.
Not surprisingly, research occupied an increasingly important place in academic life, putting
pressures on individuals, which many believed was to the detriment of their teaching roles
(Sidaway, 1997).
There have now been seven RAEs (later renamed Research Excellence Framework, REF) in the
UK. After each, the distribution of the rewards has become increasingly concentrated on the highest
graded departments. This increased the pressure on departments and their members to be successful
according to the criteria employed by the RAE/REF panels. These are supposed to recognise research
quality, both retrospective and prospective, but the main ‘evidence’ used in those judgements,
especially in disciplines like geography, is publications. There were claims that papers take
precedence over books and that papers in certain journals are considered of higher quality than
34 The nature of an academic discipline

others (e.g. Short, 2002). Certainly, some journals have been cited much more than others among
the four publications that staff members are required to submit as indicative of their best work
(Johnston, 2003a), although those involved in the assessment for geography in 2008 refuted a
straightforward correlation between impact or reputation of the journal and the quality they
ascribed to submissions (Richards et al., 2009). In addition, other ‘indicators’ are deployed to assist
in the subjective judgements, such as research income and studentships gained, and citation indices.
The ability of the procedure to produce a result significantly different from a purely quantitative
audit has been debated (see Kelly and Burrows, 2011, on the case of sociology). As well as the long-
standing evaluations of excellence based on peer review of staff research publications, the quality
of the research environment and various indicators of esteem, a substantial portion of the 2014 REF
evaluation (20–25 per cent) was based on an evaluation of ‘research impact’, on indications that the
work undertaken has achieved ‘demonstrable benefits to the wider economy and society’, which
excludes its impact on other academic researchers. ‘Research users’ therefore played an important
role on the assessment panels, seeking to evaluate how academia is generating substantial returns
beyond those purely scholarly (on, for example, ‘the take-up or application of new products, policy
advice, medical interventions, and so on’: Collini, 2012, p. 170; Sayer, 2015). The implications for
much work in the social sciences and humanities, its future funding, are unclear. Debate in human
geography about impact, however, took place in the context of earlier discussions about the merits
and nature of applied geography – our focus in Chapter 9.
In part, as a response to the claims that the RAEs were over-emphasising research at the
expense of teaching, a parallel external evaluation of teaching quality was established in the mid-
1990s, though those departments that were highly rated received no rewards other than the
status of the perceived distinction, and very few indeed got the ‘unsatisfactory’ grades that
threatened their ability to recruit students (Johnston, 1996a). Furthermore, although some of the
evaluation involved external assessors observing and grading actual teaching sessions, much of
it focused on other aspects of curriculum design, student success and so forth. The assessment
procedure was as much a bureaucratic inspection of bureaucratic practices as it was an evaluation
of the quality of the student learning experience. Its impact has been to further increase the
pressures on staff, alongside the increased pressure to obtain research grants and contracts, and
publish high-quality research to win high RAE grades. This has occurred during a period of very
significant reductions in the resourcing of universities on a per capita (student) basis; research
and teaching productivity has been increased, at substantial, if unmeasurable, costs (Johnston
1994a, 1995a, 1995b).
This audit and accountability culture in UK universities (Johnston, 1994b) has spread, with
similar assessment procedures introduced in Australia and New Zealand, and elsewhere in Europe
– for example, Castree et al. (2006) consider their consequences for the production of geographical
knowledge. In the USA the decentralisation of responsibility for higher education, the existence of
a large number of private universities and the market-orientation of education provision has
precluded the introduction of centralised evaluations. Nevertheless, as Luke (2000) demonstrated
with regard to political science there, there are similar pressures to win grants, produce high-
quality research papers in the ‘right’ journals and gain high citation indices as universities compete
for the best staff and graduate students, and the reputations that go with them. And although there
aren’t centralised bureaucratic evaluations as in the UK, there is a variety of reputational exercises
that result in rankings of departments and institutions in ‘league tables’ which are widely used to
promote institutional prestige. As Luke puts it, these exercises, and the inputs on which they are
based, involve ‘arithmetical economies of professional correctness [that] drive or stall careers’ on
the basis of which ‘universities and disciplines . . . track their various cases of success and failure,
growth and decline, winners and losers in this complex symbolic economy’ every bit as much as
do companies listed on the Stock Exchange (Luke, 2000, pp. 212–13). It is the outcome of his
description of academic life as:
The nature of an academic discipline 35

an existence pegged to perpetual examinations: seminar discussions, research papers, disser-


tation defenses, conference papers, journal submissions, book contracts, teaching evaluations,
committee assignments, tenure hearings, academic promotions, annual reports.
(p. 217)

These are now routine components of the academic profession. Its members are compelled
to ‘trade actively in the sign-value economies of professional correctness’ and forced ‘to adhere
correctly to very clear disciplinary expectations in order to succeed’ (p. 226). Academics research
and publish in order to succeed in their chosen careers: the results of what they do – their
publications – form the store of knowledge that represents their discipline’s achievements. What
they have chosen to write about, and why, determines the contemporary nature of their science.
An example of a USA assessment exercise is the National Research Council’s (2010) data-based
evaluation of doctoral programmes across 62 disciplines and 212 of the country’s leading
universities. (For a long-term analysis of geography doctoral programmes and their success in
placing graduates in leading universities, see Liu and Zhan, 2011.) Its results, like those of many
others, including the UK’s RAEs, have been widely publicised in the form of ‘university league
tables’. Indeed, the production of such tables has become a feature of the specialist media (such as
the UK’s Times Higher Education) as well as some newspapers and universities and other institutions,
using a wide range of indicators – designed, it is claimed, to assist students in their choice of
university. Those tables – and the politics of their construction – are now a focus of considerable
attention: universities and their departments enjoy the charisma of high rankings, whatever the
quality of their production (on which, see Foley and Goldstein, 2012).
Departments of geography and their individual members have had to respond to these political,
institutional and potential market changes, therefore, and to restructure their course and research
offerings accordingly. The nature of the science that they practised and taught was necessarily
always strongly influenced by the ‘culture of the times’ (which does not mean that all conformed
to it). As Livingstone (1992, p. 347) expresses it, this is because, ‘geography changes as society
changes, and . . . the best way to understand the tradition to which geographers belong is to get a
handle on the different social and intellectual environments within which geography has been
practised’. As we seek to appreciate the history of geography over recent decades, we have to do this
in the context of the constraints within which it has been practised.

Conclusions
The thesis of this chapter is that the history of an academic discipline must be set in a context
comprising three elements: the occupational structure, the organisational framework for research,
and the societal environment. These three interact in a complex variety of ways. The occupational
structure is very much enabled and constrained by the societal environment – for example, as
indicated by the expansion in student and hence numbers of academics to teach them in the 1960s,
negligible opportunities for promotion in UK universities in the late 1970s and early 1980s because
of the cuts in educational funding, and the uncertainty that prevails today, after another period of
relative expansion (albeit not with a commensurate increase in funding) in the 1990s and the first
decade of the twenty-first century. Similarly, the framework for research, although established by
and for academics, is subject to societal support. Some frameworks are much more acceptable than
others and so are more likely to receive the needed public finance. The governance of academics and
academia through metrics that seek to quantify their achievements and qualities, however, has fed
into a system that was already structured by hierarchy and more informal reputational judgements.
These metrics mimic markets (and combine with more conventional markets in the hiring
of academics or the charging of student fees, for example). Writing about the UK case, one
critical observer traces how ‘their performative character contributes to the generation of the
36 The nature of an academic discipline

[commercialised and quantified] structures of feeling that have come to increasingly define
academic life’ (Burrows, 2012, p. 357).
In the following chapters, the content of human geography in the UK and North America since
the Second World War is reviewed, within the context set by this discussion. The pre-war contexts
and making of the modern discipline (as well as some of its antecedents) are also briefly documented
in Chapter 2. In all cases, however, the emphasis is on ‘extraordinary research’ rather than the
cumulative achievements of what Kuhn termed ‘normal science’, stressing the debates over how
research should be done in human geography. No attempt is made to test the models outlined in
the section on ‘the academic working environment’, although the ideas outlined there have clearly
influenced the organisation of the book. The main purpose is to present a reasoned summary of
debates in human geography (the discipline being defined as comprising that which is claimed as
human geography), based principally on the published record. The relationship between this
summary and the models of disciplinary change only resurfaces in the final chapter.
Chapter 2

Foundations

the central core of our discipline – why we call ourselves geographers and why what we
do has so much in common – has been essentially European in derivation and characteristics
. . . developed over a remarkably short space of time at the end of the eighteenth and
beginning of the nineteenth centuries . . . these characteristics have persisted as enduring
concerns through the series of ‘revolutions’ to which the discipline is said to have been
subjected . . .
(David Stoddart, 1986, p. 28)

any analysis of how nature is understood in geography is necessarily one about the nature of
geography.
(Noel Castree, 2005, p. xix)

geographical imagination A sensitivity towards the significance of PLACE and SPACE,


LANDSCAPE and NATURE in the constitution and conduct of life on earth. As such, a
geographical imagination is by no means the exclusive preserve of the academic discipline
of GEOGRAPHY.
(Derek Gregory, 2009, p. 282)

For all the battles which geography has witnessed since the nineteenth century . . . none
has been anyway near as profound or thoroughgoing as that which destroyed the empirical
descriptive geography of the early modern age and replaced it with the connective causal
discipline of modern geography. Modern geographers are all, to ape A. N. Whitehead on Plato,
merely a series of footnotes to that moment.
(Robert Mayhew, 2011a, p. 44)

Although this book is mostly about human geography since 1945, a brief outline of the nature of
the discipline in preceding decades is necessary, for several reasons. First, although 1945 was a
watershed year in many aspects of the social, economic and intellectual life of the countries
considered, it was not a significant divide in the views on geographical philosophy and methodology.
Not surprisingly, the war years were not a major period of intradisciplinary academic debate.
Most academics spent the time either on active service or in associated intelligence activities:
although some of the latter retained their teaching commitments, for most the everyday activities
of teaching, pure research and administration were replaced by commitment to the war effort.
(On UK geographers’ war activities, see Balchin, 1987; Clout and Gosme, 2003; and Maddrell,
2008, who focuses on the roles on women geographers engaged in cartographic work in
wartime; on the USA, see Stone, 1979; Hohn, 1994, focuses on one geographer’s specific role;
on European geographers, see Clayton and Barnes, 2015.) After 1945 it took a few years
for academic life to return to something like normality, to assimilate the new staff needed to
38 Foundations

replace war losses, to teach the student backlog and to react to new social and economic
environments.
A second reason for retrospection relates to the processes of change discussed in Chapter 1.
New practices are responses to perceived failings of those currently in favour, not inventions
produced in an intellectual vacuum. Thus, post-1945 changes were reactions to the philosophies
and methodologies developed and taught in the preceding decades about which some knowledge
is necessary.
Finally, academic changes are not instantaneous. New research programmes may take years to
mature, while experimentation with alternatives takes place, the programmatic statements are
written and converts are won over. Meanwhile, the current practices prevail. Adherents continue in
their accepted ways, researching, publishing and teaching undergraduates according to the conven-
tional wisdom. Even when a new paradigm has been crystallised, it may co-exist with its predeces-
sors for several years, while competing for support; it is quite feasible for several world views to
have adherents at the same time, quite possibly in the same academic department, especially in the
social sciences and humanities – indeed, that could well be a virtually permanent state.

Geography in the modern period


The hallmark of an academic discipline is an educational organisation which provides
specialist training in the subject. James (1972) dates the beginning of such an organisation for
geography around 1874, when the first ten university geography departments were established in
German universities (Wardenga, 1999; Schelhaas and Hönsch, 2002; see also Taylor, 1985a). Claval
notes how:

Towards the 1860s the economic development of Germany had been accompanied by the
development of applied sciences, and the accompanying development of the universities itself
demanded that they redefined their functions. . . . it was the presence of geography in primary
education that was the main stimulus to the growth in numbers of university teachers of
geography after 1874. . . . Certainly the new situation created by the unification of Germany
between 1864 and 1871 imposed new demands in terms of texts and geography courses at the
primary and secondary level. To this must be added the requirements of German imperialism . . .
the formation of the German empire in 1871 and the acquisition of colonies from 1884–85 (after
the Congress of Berlin) gave birth to a new politics which was the impulse to the creation of new
university posts in and departments of geography.
(1981, pp. 96–7, our translation)

Berdoulay thus describes the intellectual influence of the German example (which also stimulated
responses in France and then elsewhere in Europe):

German and French geographic thought and achievements played a foundational role in the
development of geography as a discipline in European and American academic institutions
during the late nineteenth century and the first decades of the twentieth.
(2011, p. 74)

Previously, geography was investigated either by amateurs or by scientists trained in other


fields. In the UK, for example, geography was a recognised area of scholarly work for several
centuries, even though it had no separate disciplinary or departmental identity in the small number
of universities then operating. Map-making, exploration and chorography (the description of the
characteristics of different areas) were all taught at English and Scottish universities by the end of
the sixteenth century, for example (Cormack, 1997; Withers and Mayhew, 2002; Withers, 2001;
Foundations 39

Mayhew, 2011a). Geographical knowledge was important to traders who, along with bankers and
private individuals, invested in expeditions in the expectation of benefiting commercially from the
new knowledge obtained – about new lands and potential resources, for example, as well as new
and quicker routes to known destinations. Increasingly, exploitation of such resources called for
state support and protection for their activities and contributions to the national wealth, which
stimulated state-sponsored settlement, colonisation and the growth of imperial naval power. The
practice of geography was central to this imperial ethos of much of nineteenth-century Europe
(Driver, 1998; Butlin 2009; Bell et al., 1995; Clayton, 2011).
Promotion of geography in this context involved the establishment of geographical societies in
many national capitals and major trading cities. Among the first were those founded in Paris (1821),
Berlin (1828), London (1830) and St Petersburg (1845), with later creations in Manchester
(1884), Newcastle upon Tyne (1887), Liverpool (1891) and Southampton (1897) (see Johnston
2003b; Heffernan, 2003; McKendrick, 1995; Butlin, 2009). Many of these societies had royal
patronage and were strongly supported by members of the mercantile, diplomatic and military
classes as well as audiences drawn from the upper and middle classes who attended their lectures.
The societies’ main roles involved collating and publishing information, sponsoring expedi-
tions and fostering relevant scientific developments, as in navigation and cartography. The
American Geographical Society was similarly established in New York in 1851 as ‘a merchant’s
information bureau’ (Koelsch, 2002, p. 253; Wright, 1952; Morin, 2011; Crampton et al., 2012;
Johnston, 2013).
Some of these societies became involved in educational activities, promoting geography as
a subject in their countries’ schools and universities. In the UK, the RGS lobbied for geography’s
presence in the evolving school curricula (Keltie, 1886; Ploszajka, 1999; Wise, 1986). It then
turned its attention, in the late nineteenth century, to the universities, realising that to sustain
the subject’s presence in schools required trained teachers who had a university qualification in the
discipline while its presence in those institutions gave it status. The society’s attentions focused
on the universities of Cambridge and Oxford, on the argument that geography would only be
recognised as an academic discipline if it were taught in England’s ‘ancient universities’; posts were
established there, with RGS financial support for nearly forty years, in the late 1880s, although
chairs were not filled in either until the 1930s (Stoddart, 1975a; Scargill, 1976; Pawson, 2009.)
Other universities took the lead in establishing full departments and degree programmes (Slater,
1988) – the first was at Liverpool in 1917 – as a result of varying pressures for geography teach-
ing. Some of this pressure came from cognate disciplines, notably geology and economics,
which required geography courses within their syllabuses; the first permanent chair was held by
L. W. Lyde at University College London, for example, who was appointed to teach geography for
economics students in 1903 (see Dickinson, 1976; Clout, 2011a), whereas at Glasgow a newly
appointed professor of geology pressed strongly, and successfully, for geography to be taught there
too. The growth was hence fast, as charted in Figure 2.1. By the Second World War, there was a
geography department (albeit invariably small) in virtually every UK university and university
college, plus many of those in the British Empire. (For more detail on this aspect of the discipline’s
institutionalisation there, see Johnston 2003b. The essays in Steel, 1987, discuss British geography
in the 1930s.)
There was no national pressure for geographical education in the USA, largely because of the
decentralised nature of educational systems there: the American Geographical Society showed very
little interest in geographical education in the latter decades of the twentieth century (Wright,
1952; Morin, 2011), and the same was largely true of the National Geographic Society until late
into the twentieth century (Schulten, 2001). The establishment of geography teaching in some of
the country’s universities resulted from perceived needs in other degree programmes (many of
these can be traced through the increasing number of departmental histories available online at
http://old.geog.psu.edu/hog/dept_histories.html). One was geology, and some of geography’s
40 Foundations

100

Cumulative number of
geography departments

10

Cumulative number of
chairs in geography

1
1880 1890 1900 1910 1920 1930 1940 1950 1960

Figure 2.1  The foundation of departments of geography and of chairs in geography in British universities

Source: Stoddart, 1986, p. 46.

early protagonists – such as William Morris Davis (p. 43, this book) at Harvard – were trained
geologists. Departments of economics and schools of business and commerce also identified the
need for geography teaching (Fellmann, 1986); indeed, the first fully fledged department of
geography – at the University of California Berkeley campus – emerged from such an origin, in
1898 (Dunbar, 1981). Many of those courses lapsed by 1920, but by then geography had been
established elsewhere in a number of universities, although to nothing like the same relative extent
as in the UK.
Most of the initial teachers on those geography programmes were trained in other disciplines
and were attracted to geography by its core interest in the relationships between people and their
environments. Many of their stimuli came from early work in Germany and France, where a number
went to study (Berdoulay, 2011). By virtue of their primacy in establishing geography departments
and the intellectual heritage of Alexander von Humboldt and Karl Ritter (see p. 46, this book),
French and especially German influences were strong in the original formulation of geographers’
core agenda (Claval, 1981). Others were trained by the discipline’s pioneers – such as the many
who took the certificates and attended the summer schools offered at the University of Oxford by
Mackinder and Herbertson (who, like many of the other pioneers, also wrote innovative school
textbooks); Mackinder’s (1887) paper ‘On the scope and methods of geography’ was an early,
influential essay in defining a particular niche for geography within British academia (see also
Kearns, 2009): as Withers (2010) discusses, it was important for British geographers at that time
to establish their ‘scientific’ credentials in order to win recognition (and respectability) for their
discipline’s prospectus. The late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries thus saw the transition
from what James (1972) termed geography’s classical age into its modern period; he termed post-
1945 its contemporary period. James’s modern period is virtually co-extensive with the decades
surveyed in Freeman’s (1961) A Hundred Y  ears of Geography, which identified six interrelated trends in
the geographical literature:
Foundations 41

1 The encyclopaedic trend covered the collection of information about the world, particularly areas
little known to Western Europeans and North Americans. Although the great age of discovery
was over, and by the late nineteenth century much of the world had been visited by European
explorers, there remained vast tracts, notably in Africa, which if not terra incognita were almost
empty on contemporary Western maps.
2 The educational trend, in which the nascent academic discipline was establishing its role and
relevance in educational systems, thereby ensuring its reproduction. (On the role of the RGS
in this in the UK, see Freeman, 1980a, 1980b; on the Geographical Association, founded in
1893, see Balchin, 1993, and Walford, 2001. Johnston, 2003b, overviews the discipline’s
institutionalisation in UK universities.)
3 The colonial trend reflected a major preoccupation during the modern period’s early decades,
especially in the UK (Driver, 1998; M. Bell et al., 1995). Organisation of the imperial world
required information, whose provision became a major task of geographical research while its
propagation was the keystone of geographical education. Furthermore, part of the creation of
an imperial national identity and ethos involved educational activities, which gave children a
sense of their identity in the world – and, by implication at least, of their superiority and that
of their environment. (On school texts in the period, see Ploszajska, 1999; J. M. Smith, 2001;
Kearns, 2009. Buttimer and Fahy, 1999, p. 179, argue that school geography in Ireland has
been taught ‘as an instrumentum regni, to transmit political, economic, and social attitudes of
prevailing regimes . . . transmitting images rather than evoking curiosity’. On geography’s
wider role as popularly understood in the creation of world views, see Schulten, 2001.)
Geography was centrally involved in the creation of this imperial identity in the UK. In the
USA, however, geographers were less involved at this stage, and a particular notion of American
identity and destiny was created by historians such as Frederick Jackson Turner, who associated
the American nation with its expanding frontiers (Kearns, 1984). The entanglements between
USA imperialism and geography would come later (Morin, 2011).
4 The generalising trend describes the use to which geographical data were increasingly employed.
Academic study involved more than collecting and collating facts; these had to be interpreted,
and the methods and aims of such interpretation defined the early paradigms of the discipline’s
development, as will be discussed.
5 The political trend was reflected in the contemporary uses made of geographical expertise. For
example, Isaiah Bowman, trained at Harvard under Davis, became Director of the American
Geographical Society in 1915, and was selected as an adviser to Woodrow Wilson at the
conferences (notably at Versailles near Paris) which redrew the map of the world after
the First World War (Martin, 1980; N. Smith, 1994). Bowman subsequently wrote one of the
first books on political geography (Bowman, 1921). According to N. Smith (2003, p. 183):
World War I forever transformed U.S. geographical research, and no one sensed this more
acutely than the chief territorial specialist of the U.S. delegation at Paris. The new world
that confronted everyone after 1919, Bowman understood, required a new geography . . .
human rather than physical fashioning of the world’s landscapes was now preeminent. For
a U.S. geographical tradition heavily modeled on German geography and umbilically
connected to geology, this was a dramatic paradigm shift. It was not his physical but his
political geography that was most exploited in Paris.

In the UK, the first appointee to the School of Geography at the University of Oxford, H. J.
(later Sir Halford) Mackinder also wrote on political geography, which later informed a wealth
of writing around the theme of geopolitics (though Mackinder himself did not use that term).
His heartland model (Mackinder, 1890, 1904; Kearns, 2009) presented the Eurasian continent
as the fulcrum of world power, hence the ‘geographical pivot of history’ as encapsulated in the
triplet:
42 Foundations

Who rules East Europe commands the Heartland;


Who rules the Heartland commands the World-Island;
Who rules the World-Island commands the World.

Mackinder later became an MP and then was involved in diplomacy, but continued to write on
geopolitical issues until the 1940s; his Democratic Ideals and Reality (Mackinder, 1919) summarised
his views (on his career, see Blouet, 1987; W. H. Parker, 1982; Kearns, 2009).
6 The specialisation trend was a reaction to the growth of knowledge and the inability of any one
individual to master it all, even within the single discipline of geography. Prior to the modern
period, many scientists and other academics had catholic interests and expertise. As the volume
of research literature increased and the techniques of investigation demanded longer and more
rigorous training so it became necessary to specialise first, in this context, as a geographer and
then within geography.

Clearly, these trends overlapped. However, three major paradigms (as disciplinary matrices)
characterise human geography’s modern period. The development of each was strongly influenced
by a few individuals who left lasting impressions on the discipline. Until after the Second World
War there were only small numbers of geographers working in universities, and many of the
pioneers had no training in the discipline (Johnston, 2005). Their main role was as teachers, and
many did relatively little research or publication of original work. A small number took up
leadership roles, however, defining geography’s academic agenda and strongly influencing what the
discipline studied and its methods (Mackinder – e.g. Mackinder, 1887; Kearns, 2009 – and Davis,
1906, were especially influential in the UK and the USA respectively). Almost all of these early
definitional essays focused on geography as a whole; human geography emerged as a separate
subdiscipline relatively late in the modern period (Johnston, 2010a). Those who occupied
powerful positions within the discipline – as professors and departmental heads, for example –
were able, through combinations of the force of their personalities, the strength of their arguments
and carefully chosen appointments to their own and other departments (including their post-
graduate students), to play crucial roles in setting the discipline’s academic directions. There were
differences and debates, but in small communities only a few ideas generally prevailed – a very
different situation from the pluralism that developed in the second half of the twentieth century as
geographers became much more numerous and key individuals, though still important, were less
dominant.

Paradigms in the modern period

Exploration
This first approach was carried over from the classical period; exploration was the major activity
popularly recognised as geography through most of the nineteenth century. The collection and
classification of information about ‘unknown’ parts of the earth (unknown, that is, to Western
Europeans and North Americans) was undertaken by explorers and navigators, many of whose
expeditions were sponsored by geographical societies. Information gained was used to enhance
cartographic knowledge and disseminated widely through lectures and books. The map of the world
was completed and filled in at an increasing pace.
The importance of exploration within geography declined in the late nineteenth century,
although soon after his appointment at Oxford, Mackinder (who had been trained as a biologist
and historian) felt it necessary to establish his geographical credentials by becoming the first
recorded person to climb Mt Kenya (Kearns, 2009). Much terra incognita remained on European maps
of the rest of the world, however, and the geographical societies maintained their interest in and
Foundations 43

sponsorship of expeditions throughout the period. The exploration tradition is maintained in the
USA by the National Geographical Society (NGS) and its popular publication, National Geographic
magazine. Like other magazines, such as New Zealand Geographic and the Geographical magazine, National
Geographic concentrates, though not exclusively, on material illustrating the relationships between
people and their environments (with copious high-quality photographic material and maps). In
such media, the boundaries of geography and natural history are imprecise. (The NGS also has a TV
channel devoted to similar material, and has given large sums of money in recent years to develop
geographical programmes for schools in the USA, after surveys revealed considerable ignorance
about what is where in the world: Johnston, 2009d.)
Although most of it was not strictly exploration, the work summarised by Freeman under
the colonial and encyclopaedic trends can be included here, since its aims were the collection,
collation and dissemination of information. Much of the material was about commercial activities
and infrastructure, as in volumes such as G. G. Chisholm’s Handbook of Commercial Geography
(first edition, 1899) and Gazetteer of the World (1895), which were aimed at the world of commerce,
with companion volumes for schools (Wise, 1975; Barnes, 2000, 2001a). Their content comprised
statistics and descriptions of production and trade, and a training in this type of geography involved
the assimilation of large bodies of factual knowledge (‘capes and bays’ geography). Similar texts
were produced in the USA (Barnes, 2001a; Fellmann, 1986; Lawton and Miller, 2001; Johnston,
2010a).
The value of such geographical information and expertise was widely recognised, and was
called on during both world wars when geographers were recruited into intelligence services. In
the UK, for example, they were responsible for the preparation of reports about areas in which
Allied troops were likely to be engaged, and their Second World War British Admiralty Handbooks
(edited at Oxford and Cambridge under the leadership of Kenneth Mason and Clifford Darby
respectively: Clout, 2003a; Clout and Gosme, 2003) were put on sale afterwards. The comparable
volumes produced in the USA by the Office of Strategic Services (of which Richard Hartshorne was
Deputy Head) – the Joint Army-Navy Intelligence Studies – remained classified documents, however
(Barnes, 2006a).

Environmental determinism and possibilism


Environmental determinism and possibilism represented the first attempts at generalisation by
geographers during the modern period. Rather than just present information in an organised
manner, either topically or by area, geographers sought explanations for the patterns of human
occupation of the earth’s surface. Their major initial source for explanations was the physical
environment, with a general belief that the nature of human activity was controlled by the
parameters of the physical world within which it was set.
The origins of this environmental determinism lie in Charles Darwin’s landmark On the Origin of
Species (first published in 1859) which influenced many scientists (Livingstone, 1992; Armstrong,
1999, argues that Darwin was influenced by the pioneer geographer–naturalist von Humboldt).
Darwin’s notions regarding evolution were taken up by an American geographer, William Morris
Davis, in his cycle-of-erosion model of landform development (Chorley et al., 1973; Beckinsale
1976; Vale, 2002). Ideas of natural selection and adaptation formed the basis of statements regard-
ing environmental determinism, including Davis’s (1906) programmatic paper identifying the core
of geography as the relationship between the physical environment as the control and human
behaviour as the response (Stoddart, 1966; Martin, 1981; Campbell and Livingstone, 1983; and
Livingstone, 1984, discuss the related influence of Lamarckism in the development of geography;
see also Peet, 1985a).
Chief among the late nineteenth-century speculations on environment-society was the work
of the German scholar, Freidrich Ratzel, who was trained in zoology before taking an interest in
44 Foundations

geology and ethnological (the classification and study of ‘races’/peoples) research on the diffu-
sion and distribution of peoples. Ratzel began lecturing on geography in Munich in the 1870s, then
become professor of geography at Leipzig (1886–1904). Before Ratzel, geography had largely been
seen as a natural (physical) science. According to Berdoulay (2011, p. 76), Ratzel’s ‘breakthrough’
was key ‘in setting geography within a scientific-evolutionary discourse’. His Anthropogeographie
(Ratzel, 1882–91) related the course of history to the earth’s physical features (illustrating organic
notions that had been stimulated by Darwin); and his Politische Geographie (Ratzel, 1897) adapted
Darwinian arguments to states, which he treated as organisms that struggle for land (Lebensraum,
or living space), with the strongest states able to expand territorially. Although others had also
elaborated the idea prior to Ratzel (see Halas, 2014), these arguments were later taken up by a
Swedish conservative political scientist (Rudolf Kjellen) who coined the term ‘geopolitics’ to signify
the codification and study of this mode of political geography. In the 1920s and 1930s, a German
military officer and geographer (Karl Haushofer) expounded such geopolitics to provide an
element of the putatively ‘scientific’ underpinning for the 1930s–1940s Nazi policy policies of
territorial expansion, although sometimes in tension with the ‘racial’ ideas about space and power
that became central to Nazism (Kost, 1989; Natter 2003; Parker, 1985; Barnes and Minca, 2013;
Barnes and Abrahamsson, 2015). In turn, however, geopolitics soon acquired a life of its own with
work in many European countries (from Italy and Portugal to Denmark, the Netherlands and
Romania) and Japan, as part of a wider conversation about empires, sovereignty, space and power,
in which geographers played a central (though not exclusive) role (Dodds and Atkinson, 2000).
After the Second World War, such classical geopolitics continued in right-wing military circles from
Turkey to Portugal and in many South American countries, and it has more recently been adopted
in post-communist Russia as well as in parts of Central Asia.
To return to the development of anglophone human geography, however, Ratzel’s ideas were
promoted in the USA by Ellen Churchill Semple, who opened her book lnfluences of Geographic
Environment (1911) with the statement that ‘Man is the product of the earth’s surface.’ Semple, who
was Davis’s student, had travelled to Germany to consult Ratzel. In Europe, she connected also with
British geographers via seminars at the RGS and RSGS. Indeed, there was a transatlantic commerce
in these debates about environmental determinism. Ellsworth Huntington advanced theories
relating the course of civilisation to climate and climatic change (Huntington, 1915, 1945). In
some hands, the environmental influences adduced were gross, and with hindsight it is hard to
believe that they were taken seriously; Tatham (1953), for example, illustrates the extent to which
authors were prepared to credit all aspects of human behaviour with an environmental cause.
The reception of Semple was complex, however; the wide range of debates that her work triggered
has been dissected by Keighren (2006, 2010; see also the survey conducted by John K. Wright,
1962, to identify the extent of her influence on other geographers in the first part of the twentieth
century). There were frequent links with discourses about ‘race’. Though not all those who took
part were explicitly racist, it is evident that the wider framework in which debates evolved was
shaped by racialised assumptions about categories, lands and peoples that owe much to the wider
imperial moment (as in various essays and books by T. G. Taylor – e.g. 1927, 1937; on Taylor, see
Strange and Bashford, 2008). Livingstone (1992, p. 221) notes how ‘The idea that climatic regions
on both local and global scales implied an ethnic moral topography was an idea that weaves its way
through the corpus of nineteenth- and early-twentieth-century writings.’
The debates lingered in the form of ‘tropical geography’ into the postwar era, when the
prospects for the development of tropical regions (mostly colonies and former colonies) re-entered
the debate. Indeed, there was a wider conversation – resting on translation – between anglophone
and francophone geographers writing about these themes (Power and Sidaway, 2004) of tropical
geography.
Such debates were informed by reaction to the extreme generalisations of the environmental
determinists which had led to a counter-thesis, that of possibilism. This presented individuals as
Foundations 45

active rather than passive agents. Led by French geographers, themselves followers of the Annales-
school historian Lucien Febvre, the possibilist argument had people perceiving the range of
alternative uses to which they could put an environment and selecting that which best fitted their
cultural dispositions. Taken to extremes, this approach could be as ludicrous as that which it
opposed, but possibilists generally recognised the limits to action which environments set, and
avoided the great generalisations which characterised their antagonists.
Debate over environmental determinism and possibilism continued into the 1960s
(Lewthwaite, 1966; Spate, 1957, for example, proposed a middle ground with the concept of
‘probabilism’). And it was not only in tropical geography that they were registered. The doughtiest
advocate of the determinist cause was T. Griffith Taylor, foundation professor of geography at the
University of Sydney, whose views so angered politicians interested in the further white settlement
of outback Australia that he was virtually hounded out of the country (Powell, 1980a). He argued
that possibilists had developed their ideas in temperate environments which offer several viable
alternative forms of human occupance. But such environments are rare: in most of the world, as in
Australia, the environment is much more extreme and its control over human activity accordingly
much greater. He coined the phrase ‘stop-and-go’ determinism to describe his views. In the short
term, people might attempt whatever they wished with regard to their environment, but in the
long term, nature’s plan would ensure that the environment won the battle and forced a compro-
mise out of its human occupants (Taylor, 1958; Sanderson, 1988; Strange and Bashford, 2008).
Many debates begin as two opposing, extreme views, and end with a compromise accepted by
all but the most fervent devotees of each polar position. Thus, the lengthy discussion among
geographers about whether people are free agents in their use of the earth or whether there is a
‘nature’s plan’ slowly dissolved as the antagonists realised the merits in each case. Some geographers
studied human–environment interactions outside the confines of these debates (see Fleure, 1919;
the debate’s deep foundations are the subject of Glacken’s (1967) magnum opus, Traces on the Rhodian
Shore). While some geographers strongly promoted environmental determinism, however, respect
for their discipline was relatively low in the wider academic community. As a consequence,
geography’s next focus, which nevertheless had some roots in environmental determinism, was
very much an introspective and conservative one, alongside other attempts to develop an alternative
paradigm, which lacked extensive support, such as Barrows’s (1923) presentation of geography as
human ecology.

The region and regional geography


This third approach dominated British and American geography for much of the middle twentieth
century. Like environmental determinism, it was an attempt at generalisation, but it lacked structured
explanation and so was of a very different type from the increasingly discredited law-making
attempts of the previous writings. This drew heavily on contemporary developments in Germany
and France. Of great importance in Germany was the work of two individuals who many identify
as the founders of modern geography. Both died in 1859, one having established the modern roots
of what became known as systematic geography and the other having performed a similar task for
regional geography. Both accepted the definition of geography set out by the Enlightenment
philosopher, Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), who lectured on physical geography at the University
of Königsberg (Harvey, 2009). He argued that knowledge can be organised and classified in two
ways: because of similarities in origin wherever they occur (the logical classification, which is the
basis of the various sciences); or because of similarities in when or where they occur – the discipline
that looks at similarities in terms of time is history, whereas that which looks at similarities in terms
of place of occurrence is geography (J. A. May, 1970).
Alexander von Humboldt (1769–1859) was a naturalist with very broad scientific interests.
He spent five years travelling in Central and South America, amassing information about the
46 Foundations

environment and its exploitation by humans. He assembled this material (over a 20-year period in
Paris) to show how environments varied, with differences in agricultural practices and patterns of
human settlement, for example, reflecting interactions among altitude, temperature and vegetation.
This approach to the discipline emphasised field collection of data and its synthesis through maps,
leading to inductive generalisations. Sachs (2007, p. 49) describes von Humboldt’s

effort to see new things deeply, in context, and in connection to everything else he’s seen and
learned. The juxtaposition of his literal acts of observation and his philosophical observations,
his adventures and his scientific ‘tangents’ leaves us with a sense of swirling intellectual currents.

The remainder of his career was spent assembling similar materials from a wide range of sources,
which were synthesised in the five-volume Kosmos (von Humboldt, 1845–62). The first volume
(1845) provided an overview of the universe, which was followed by one (1847) on representations
of the earth in art and literature and a history of scientific writing on the earth since Egyptian times.
The third (1850) was largely concerned with astronomy; the fourth (1858) turned to human
interactions with the earth, with a vast range of observational material described and used to derive
generalisations about those interrelationships; and the final volume (published posthumously in
1862) dealt with geology and volcanology. (On von Humboldt, see G. Martin and James, 1993;
Bowen, 1970, 1981; Rupke, 2005; Sachs, 2007.)
Karl Ritter (1779–1859) was trained in a variety of disciplines – during which he met, and
was impressed by, von Humboldt – and by 1811 had published a two-volume work on the
geography of Germany. He was appointed to a chair of geography in Berlin in 1820 (a year after a
similar appointment in history in Frankfurt). After early field work in Italy and Switzerland, as well
as Germany, he travelled little and his teaching was largely based on secondary sources. He focused
on the connections between phenomena in places – of ‘unity in diversity’, which he believed
represented ‘God’s plan’. This involved defining regions, separate areas of the earth’s surface with
distinct assemblages of phenomena. The material accumulated was used to produce his 19-volume
(unfinished) Erdkunde (Ritter, 1817–59).
Regional geography was also the main focus of an influential French geographer, Paul Vidal
de la Blache (1845–1918) who, unlike von Humboldt and Ritter, obtained a higher degree in
geography after initial training in ancient history and literature. He was appointed to a post at the
Sorbonne in 1898, where he maintained close links with the Annales school of historians. French
geography had strong early connections to both mapping and history (Claval, 1999), which
were sustained by Vidal’s concentration on defining and describing regions, relatively small
homogeneous areas (pays) whose distinctive genres de vie resulted from the interactions of people with
their physical milieux. Unlike some German contemporaries, however, he did not see those inter-
actions as predominantly determined by the physical environment. He was attracted to possibilism
(which he first encountered in Ratzel’s Anthropogeographie). The environment offers people a range
of options, and they choose how to modify nature according to their cultural and technological
inheritances – as Lucien Febvre put it, ‘nowhere necessities . . . everywhere possibilities’. Vidal’s
major contributions were his Tableau de la Géographie de la France (1903), an introduction to the
multi-volume Histoire de la France (see Ozouf-Marignier and Robic, 1999), and the 15-volume
Géographie Universelle, finished in 1948. Many of his students wrote dissertations on individual pays
(Clout, 2009); they dominated French geography through the first half of the twentieth century
(Buttimer, 1971) and fitted into the conservative and nationalist milieu of interwar France amid
territorial threats from Germany (see Gregory, 1994; Heffernan, 2001). French regional geography
thus emphasised France’s essential ‘unity in diversity’, blending climatic and cultural influences
from the Mediterranean and the Atlantic into an essential élan français.
The early development of geography in Germany and France relative to the UK and the USA
meant that as the academic discipline was being established in the latter countries, some of those
Foundations 47

attracted to it sought inspiration and training from French and German sources. There was
considerable personal interaction, and it was the norm at both UK and USA universities during the
first half of the twentieth century for would-be geographers to be fluent in either if not both
German and French. Ideas about the nature of geography thus infiltrated the English-speaking
world from continental Europe. They were modified to fit local circumstances, but dominated
contemporary thinking for several decades. (On a major institutionalised interaction between
American and continental European geographers – the 1912 American transcontinental excursion,
in which a small number of British geographers participated – see Clout, 2003b, 2004; Clout and
Stevenson, 2004.)

Hartshorne and American views


The ideas and methods of regional geography were taken up in the USA after environmental
determinism had been largely rejected. In the late 1930s, two non-geographers published a major
survey of American regionalism (Odum and Moore, 1938) and in 1939 the Association of
American Geographers published a monograph – Richard Hartshorne’s The Nature of Geography: A
Critical survey of current thought in the light of the past – which was rapidly established as the definitive state-
ment of the current orthodoxy (Stoddart, 1990; Martin, 2015). As Hartshorne (1948, 1979) later
made clear, there was much debate among American geographers during the 1930s (most of it
apparently unpublished, though see James and Mather, 1977) about the nature of their discipline. He
was concerned about both the tone and the content of that debate (particularly in Leighley, 1937),
and in 1938 submitted a paper to the Annals of the Association of American Geographers as a contribution to
the philosophical discussions. He then proceeded to Europe for political geography fieldwork on
boundary problems. This was frustrated by the political situation, and he spent his time reading
further European, mainly German, work on the nature of geography. He used this to extend his 1938
paper, adding the crucial subtitle; the result was a ‘paper’ of some 230,000 words which became the
major philosophical and methodological contribution to the literature of geography in English then
available.
A synopsis of Hartshorne’s book, and his interpretations of others’ works, notably Hettner’s
(Harvey and Wardenga, 2006), is not possible in a few paragraphs, and only the main conclusions
can be highlighted. Hartshorne’s statements were positive ones – of what geography is. They were
only normative in the sense of him saying that geography should be what others (notably Hettner,
whose approach to geography reflected a line of thinking through Kant and von Humboldt to his
own mentor, Richtofen) have said that it is. Thus, Livingstone (1992, p. 306) describes Hartshorne’s
project as seeking ‘to determine the nature of geography from scrutinizing its history’, and
Lukermann (1990, p. 58) claimed that the Nature was ‘a search for authority to validate the
conclusions drawn from selected premises – largely formulated by Hettner, who had philosophical
associations and leanings rather than historical associates’. Butzer (1990) argued that Hartshorne
was selective in his use of Hettner’s material, and Derek Gregory (1994, p. 51) claimed that
‘Hartshorne’s views were developed through a highly selective exegesis of a German intellectual
tradition. His approval of Hettner (in particular) was unrestrained, but the regional geography that
he constructed was purged of both the physic–ecological and the cultural–historical implications
that were indelibly present in Hettner’. In sum, Hartshorne transmitted to an American audience his
interpretation of a particular German argument as to the nature of geography.
Hartshorne argued forcefully that the focus of geography is areal differentiation, the mosaic of
separate landscapes on the earth’s surface (see Agnew, 1990, on the representation of Hartshorne’s
focus as ‘areal variation’ rather than ‘areal differentiation’). It is defined as:

a science that interprets the realities of areal differentiation of the world as they are
found, not only in terms of the differences in certain things from place to place, but also
48 Foundations

in terms of the total combination of phenomena in each place, different from those at every
other place.
(Hartshorne, 1939, p. 462)

The discipline ‘is concerned to provide accurate, orderly and rational descriptions and interpretations
of the variable character of the earth’s surface’ (p. 21) and

seeks to acquire a complete knowledge of the areal differentiation of the world, and therefore
discriminates among the phenomena that vary in different parts of the world only in terms of
their geographic significance – i.e. their relation to the total differentiation of areas. Phenomena
significant to areal differentiation have areal expression – not necessarily in terms of physical
extent over the ground, but as a characteristic of an area of more or less definite extent.
(p. 463)

The principal purpose of geographical scholarship is thus synthesis, the integration of material on
relevant characteristics to provide a total description of a place, or region, which is identifiable by
its peculiar combination of those characteristics. Hartshorne identified a close (Kantian) analogy
between geography and history; the latter provides a synthesis for ‘temporal sections of reality’,
whereas the former performs a similar task for ‘spatial sections of the earth’s surface’ (p. 460). From
this separation of their roles, Hartshorne concluded that there was no need for geographers to study
change, since that was the province of historians.
To Hartshorne, ‘the ultimate purpose of geography, the study of areal differentiation of the
world, is most clearly expressed in regional geography’, so that the discipline’s research methods
had to focus on regional definition and depiction. Regions are characterised by their homogeneity
on prescribed characteristics, selected for their salience in highlighting areal differences.
Identification of such regions ‘depends first and fundamentally on the comparison of maps depict-
ing the areal expression of individual phenomena, or of interrelated phenomena . . . geography is
represented in the world of knowledge primarily by its technique of map use’ (pp. 462–4). Others
followed his lead, as in the editorial chapters in a later overview of American geography (James and
Jones, 1954).
Hartshorne emphasised map use. Although it is valuable for geographers to appreciate the
methods of map construction, the sciences of surveying and map projections are of only secondary
interest to them; their prime task is map interpretation. Much information to be interpreted may
have been placed on the maps by geographers during fieldwork, whose role and nature were of
considerable interest to his contemporaries (Johnston, 2010a); they established detailed methods
for mapping land use as the bases for regional delimitation, developed at a series of intensive ‘field
camps’ (see Whittlesey, 1954).
Preparation of a regional synthesis required materials from both other sciences specialising in
certain phenomena (though usually not their areal patterning) and the emerging topical systematic
specialisms within geography which complemented, but were eventually subsidiary to, regional
geography. Physical, economic and political were the main systematic subdivisions recognised at
the time Hartshorne wrote (Johnston, 2010a), although a later survey, set firmly within the regional
paradigm, identified many other ‘adjectival geographies’, including population, settlement, urban,
resources, marketing, recreation, agricultural, mineral production, manufacturing, transportation,
soils, plant, animal, medical and military, plus climatology and geomorphology (James and Jones,
1954). A number were of only minor importance, however, so that despite the apparent diversity
of interests among geographers of the time, the ‘classic’ regional study usually followed a sequence
comprising physical features, climate, vegetation, agriculture, industries, population and the like
(Freeman, 1961, p. 142), and was summarised by a synthesis of the individual maps to produce a
set of formal regions.
Foundations 49

To most geographers of the period spanning the Second World War, regional geography was
at the forefront of their discipline’s scholarship and systematic studies were the providers of infor-
mation for that enterprise. To James, ‘Regional geography in the traditional sense seeks to bring
together in an areal setting various matters which are treated separately in topical geography’
(1954, p. 9). Urban geographers studied towns because they ‘constitute distinctive areas’ (Mayer,
1954, p. 143), in line with the regional concept; political geographers studied the functions and
structures of an area ‘as a region homogeneous in political organisation, heterogeneous in other
respects’ (Hartshorne, 1954a, p. 174); and in defining a ‘new’ field of social geography, J. Wreford
Watson (1953, p. 482) saw it ‘as the identification of different regions of the earth’s surface accord-
ing to associations of social phenomena related to the total environment’ (see also Johnston,
1993b). Each topical specialism produced its own regionalisation and each had links (although
often weak) with the relevant systematic sciences. The key differentiating factor between geography
and other, systematic, disciplines was the geographer’s focus on the region. For Hartshorne, every
geographer should have not only a substantive specialism (he considered himself a political geo-
grapher and wrote the chapter on that in American Geography: Inventory and prospect – Hartshorne, 1954a.
He also made an early, prescient, apparently original – since it made no reference to any of the work
of early location theorists discussed in the next chapter – contribution to the study of industrial
location – Hartshorne, 1927) but also a regional specialism. It was the latter that distinguished a
geographer from scholars in other disciplines.
There was a tension within this promotion of regional geography, however. On one hand,
there was the presentation of regions – following Vidal’s example – as small (usually rural)
homogeneous areas, with many countries comprising a patchwork mosaic of such separate districts,
even though in many cases their boundaries were relatively indeterminate. In this view of the
region, the geographer’s field of study was inherently local, save in areas of little physical variation
over large distances. On the other hand, the argument that geographers should be regional specialists
was made at a much larger scale – an individual country, perhaps, but more commonly an entire
continent or major subcontinental area. In this context, geographers presented themselves as
specialists on, say, Latin America or the Indian subcontinent. Their teaching was at this scale even if
their research and field knowledge was on specific parts only and textbooks were structured at the
larger scale. There was thus a hierarchy of regions: the large areas used to structure considerable
sections of many degree programmes (courses on the regional geography of ‘x’), and the myriad
small areas which had their own unity and whose identification was the focus of much geographical
enquiry and writing (following Vidal’s emphasis on small regional units with distinct physical
characteristics, notably in soils and drainage, and associated agricultural specialisms – Buttimer,
1971, 1978a).

British views
Examining the period between its nascent establishment as a university discipline in the 1880s and
the middle of the twentieth century, Stoddart (1986, p. 51) describes it as ‘pragmatic, concerned
with practical issues’, as well as ‘pedagogic: all were deeply connected with education in the schools
and with the training of teachers’. He also noted that

they brought to bear on the problems selected for study an almost bewildering range of
formal training and interest, obtained before geography had itself become established as
a formal discipline, but unified through a shared belief in geographical methods and objectives.

Stoddart adds that there was a strong emphasis on fieldwork and planning issues in the UK.
Hence, British geographers were less concerned with philosophical and methodological debate
than were their American counterparts during the 1920s, 1930s and 1940s (though see the
50 Foundations

exchange in the Scottish Geographical Magazine during the late 1930s, initiated by Crowe, 1938). They
were apparently more pragmatic, less prone to contemplate the nature of their subject and more
prepared, perhaps, to adopt the well-used adage that ‘Geography is what geographers do’. But they
too generally accepted that geography’s raison d’être was synthesis, integrating the findings of various
systematic studies, but with a strong emphasis on genesis distinguishing their approach from their
American contemporaries’, as in the studies of geomorphology and historical geography (Darby,
1953; K. J. Gregory, 2003). According to Wooldridge and East (1958), ‘geography . . . fuses the
results, if not the methods, of a host of other subjects . . . [it] is not a science but merely an aggre-
gate of sciences’ (p. 14): ‘its raison d’être and intellectual attraction arise in large part from the short-
comings of the uncoordinated intellectual world bequeathed us by the specialists’ (pp. 25–6) and
‘in its simplest essence the geographical problem is how and why does one part of the earth’s
surface differ from another’ (p. 28).
All these statements indicate some transatlantic common body of opinion (Stoddart (1990)
discusses Hartshorne’s influence on Woodridge) although, despite a statement that ‘The purpose of
regional geography is simply the better understanding of a complex whole by the study of its
constituent parts’ (p. 159), Wooldridge and East did not elevate the regional doctrine as much as
their American counterparts (nor were they carried to excesses of environmental determinism in
earlier decades). Nevertheless, Wooldridge (1956, p. 53) wrote in 1951 that:

the aim of regional geography . . . is to gather up the disparate strands of the systematic studies,
the geographical aspects of other disciplines, into a coherent and focused unity, to see nature
and nurture, physique and personality as closely related and interdependent elements in specific
regions.

He argued that in any university department of geography each staff member should be committed
to the study of a major region (p. 64; Mead, 1963, 2007).
As in the USA, much early development in the UK involved work at two scales (Freeman,
1961, p. 84; Johnston, 1984a). The large scale is exemplified by Herbertson’s (1905) exercises
dividing the earth into major natural regions, usually based on climatic parameters and thus having
some links with the earlier determinism. At the smaller scale:

The fundamental idea was that the small area would legitimately be expected to show some
distinct individuality, if not necessarily entire homogeneity, through a study of all its geographical
features – structure, climate, soils, vegetation, agriculture, mineral and industrial resources,
communications, settlement and distribution of population. All these, it has often been said, are
united in the visible landscape, linked into one whole and dependent one on another. And more,
every area, save those few never occupied by man, has been influenced, developed and altered
by human activity, and therefore the landscape is an end-product, moulded to its present aspect
by successive generations of people. The practice has therefore been to take an evolutionary
view and . . . to attempt to reconstruct the landscape as it was a hundred, or a thousand years
ago.
(Freeman, 1961, p. 85)

The delineation of regions at these two scales also included attempts to devise hierarchies
(or ‘orders’), whereby smaller regions are grouped into larger units – with the various orders given
separate names, such as ‘tracts’ and ‘stows’ (Unstead, 1933; Johnston, 1984a).
Although much regional definition and description was undertaken for pedagogical purposes,
the practical value of appreciating regional divisions was also pressed. Notable was the work
of L. D. (later Sir Dudley) Stamp. A University of London geology graduate, Stamp made the trans-
lation to geography when working as Professor of Geology and Geography at the University of
Foundations 51

Rangoon (his initial employment in Burma was as an oil geologist). He returned to the UK in 1926,
to the London School of Economics, where he developed wide interests and published a large
number of school textbooks on all parts of the world, as well as a much revised text on The British
Isles (Stamp and Beaver, 1947) and several revisions of G. G. Chisholm’s Handbook of Commercial Geography
(1895). In 1930, Stamp launched what was then by far the largest research project undertaken by
British geographers – the Land Utilisation Survey of Britain. Over four years he mobilised some
250,000 students at about 10,000 schools to map land use over the entire country (a later survey
was organised in Northern Ireland) at the scale of 6 inches to the mile. These provided the data for
maps of land use at the scale of 1 inch to the mile, a series of county reports, many written by
academic geographers and including regional summaries, and for his summary volume on The Land
of Britain (Stamp, 1946a; see Rycroft and Cosgrove, 1999; Wise, 1968). Stamp promoted the survey
in particular, and geographical skills in general, as valuable for planning land use (as in Stamp,
1934, 1946b, 1949), and this was one of the main foundations for his later advocacy of applied
geography (Stamp, 1948, 1960). His expertise led to him either serving on or advising a number
of important government commissions regarding land use and related issues during the Second
World War and after (such as the Royal Commission on Land Utilisation in Rural Areas, of which
he was Vice-Chairman, and the Royal Commission for the Common Land – Buchanan, 1968). We
reconsider Stamp’s contributions again in Chapter 8 where his arguments for an applied geography
are evaluated.
In addition to the definition of what are generally termed formal (or uniform) regions – areas
of any scale that are relatively homogeneous on the selected phenomenon or phenomena – there
was also interest in functional regions. These are also homogeneous areas on criteria regarding
interactions between places: the unity of a functional region is provided by links to a common
dominant node. Functional regions were introduced to British geography by Fawcett (1919), who
suggested that the main cities’ hinterlands should be the territorial framework for regional
governments. One of his students identified the hinterlands of both large cities – Leeds and Bradford
(Dickinson, 1930) – and market towns – in East Anglia (Dickinson, 1933). Dickinson travelled
widely in France, Germany and the USA during the 1930s, assembling material on this aspect of
urban geography and developing his argument – crystallised in his postwar text, City Region and
Regionalism (Dickinson, 1947) – that functional regions should be the basis for dividing up a country
for the purposes of public administration (Johnston, 2000c, 2002a). Dickinson was a strong
proponent of the regional approach and saw no tension between the formal and functional regional
concepts, arguing that the view of the region as developed by what he termed the ‘landscape
purists’ (Dickinson, 1938, p. 12) was ‘the “objective manifestations” of economic circulation . . .
men and things in movement’.
A significant difference between British and American geographers by the 1950s was in
attitudes to physical geography. Both groups had strong traditions of work in this field, and
many geographers had academic roots in geology. But this tradition had slowly dissolved in
North America (the USA much more than Canada) and interest in the physical environment
waned, particularly its understanding as against its description (Leighley, 1955). This may have
been a consequence of the excesses of environmental determinism, with a subsequent desire
to remove all traces of that connection and to see society as the formative agent of land-
scape patterns and change. Thus, with regard to geomorphology – the science of landform genesis
– Peltier wrote:

the geographer needs precise, factual information about particular places. What landforms
actually exist in a given area? How do they differ? Where are they? What are their distribution
patterns? The geomorphologist may concern himself with questions of structure, process, and
stage, but the geographer wants specific answers to the questions: what? where? and how much?
(1954, p. 375)
52 Foundations

Geographers, according to this view, were only interested in the geography of landforms:
geomorphology, the genetic study of landforms, was a part of geology and deemed outside the
geographical enterprise.
Similar reactions saw reduction, if not removal, of material from climatology and biogeography
from American geographical curricula, and their replacement by introductory physical geography
courses that described landforms, climates and plant assemblages – usually in a regional context –
but paid little or no attention to their origins. A substantial revival of physical geography in the
USA after 1970 reflected its perceived relevance to understanding and resolving environmental
problems, realising the potential of technological advances in remote sensing and associated
technologies (see Marcus, 1979, and the essays in Gaile and Willmott, 1989, 2004). British
geographers did not follow this American trend. According to Wooldridge and East:

To treat geography too literally as an affair of the ‘quasi-static present’ is to make both it and its
students seem foolish and superficial. It is true that our primary aim is to describe the present
landscape; but it is also to interpret it. . . . Our study has therefore always to be evolutionary. . . .
It is unscholarly to take either landforms or human societies as ‘given’ and static facts, though
we must not let temporal sequences obscure spatial patterns.
(1958, p. 47)

Geography students at UK universities in the 1950s rarely specialised in either physical or


human geography, except perhaps in the final year of their course. Both were considered essential
parts of a geographical education (Johnston and Gregory, 1984; Cosgrove, 1989a). By that time,
however, most British geographers were research specialists in either physical or human geography
(though rarely exclusively so), although most also practised a regional specialism in which they
‘integrated’ studies from ‘both sides’ of their subject, as in the regional textbooks of the period. The
‘dogma of regional synthesis’ (Darby, 1983b, p. 25) was being softened, however, and geographers
were increasingly turning their attention from regions to systematic studies, identifying themselves
as either physical or human geographers.

Historical geography
One systematic specialism which stood slightly apart from the others was historical geography.
Two separate approaches operated from the late 1920s on; indeed one (predominantly American)
was not presented as historical geography.
The first approach was closely associated with the work of H. C. (later Sir Clifford) Darby in
the UK (Perry, 1969; Darby, 2002). Darby was very much influenced by Cambridge historians in
the 1920s, and his Ph.D. (the first to be awarded in geography at Cambridge) was on the medieval
Fenland (Darby, 1940a, 1940b). He then turned his attention to the 1086 Domesday Book, editing
a multi-authored set of regional volumes depicting the geography it disclosed, county by county,
with a summary volume (Darby, 1977; Perry, 1979). He also enunciated a broad approach to
historical geography which combined detailed cross-sectional analyses of particular times – selected
according to the availability of source materials – with linking narratives describing the intervening
changes (as in two edited volumes: Darby, 1936, 1973). Darby’s approach was set out in major
essays (1953, 1962) and posthumously in a volume assembled from his surviving lecture notes
(Darby, 2002; he also left notes on his course on English landscape change – see Darby, 1951—but
without the illustrative material, which prevented these also being published in book form). During
his career he supervised a large number of research students, establishing a strong presence for
historical geography within the discipline (Prince, 2000); indeed, he restructured the department
at University College London after his appointment as head in 1949 to reflect the importance he
gave to historical geography (Clout, 2003c).
Foundations 53

Largely contemporary with Darby’s was an approach centred on the works of Carl Sauer
(on whom, see Williams, 2014) and his associates. Sauer was a Chicago geography graduate
and strongly influenced by German work but, unlike Hartshorne, he did not elevate the regional
focus and concentrated on change rather than pattern. (On the differences between Hartshorne and
Sauer, see Lukermann, 1990, and Butzer, 1990; for critical assessments of Sauer, see Stoddart,
1997b, and Symanski, 2002.) Some of Sauer’s early work has environmental determinist tinges
(e.g. Sauer, 1918, pp. 421–2), but after his move to Berkeley in 1923 he focused on the cultural
processes leading to change as reflected in the landscape, beginning at the prehuman stage of
occupance (Mikesell, 1969); most of this work was conducted either outside the USA (particularly
in Latin America) or in its less industrialised parts.
Sauer’s (1925) first methodological statement constrained geographical endeavour closely to
the generic study of landscapes, emphasising their cultural features (although work was also done
on the borderlands between geography and botany, his main interdisciplinary links were with
anthropologists – see Kroeber, 1952); there was no glorification of the region, however. In his later
‘sermons’ – as he called his methodological and philosophical statements – Sauer (1941, 1956a)
encouraged research over a much wider field, but emphasised the study of cultural landscapes,
through field-based studies (Speth, 1999). It was a creative art-form whose hallmark was that it
was not prescribed by pattern or method: the human geographer is obliged ‘to make cultural
processes the base of his thinking and observation’ (Sauer, 1941, p. 24).
This genre of work involved neither detailed reconstruction of past geographies nor
close consideration of regional boundaries. Instead, it led to a catholic historical geography
(‘The elements of the landscape that have a cultural origin . . . cannot be understood rationally,
but only historically’ – Leighley, 1937, p. 141) whose rationale was that ‘through its study we may
be able to find more complete and better answers to the problems of interpretation of the world
both as it is now and as it has been at different times in the past’ (A. H. Clark, 1954, p. 95). Not all
American historical geographers followed this lead – Brown (1943), for example, worked on
detailed reconstructions of past periods (Meinig, 1989) – but the ‘Berkeley school’, which Sauer
founded and led for almost five decades, had many followers, and a particular point of view focused
on a single iconoclast (Hooson, 1981). Sauer’s influence was continued by his students, notably
Leighley, Parsons, Kniffen and Clark (Bushong, 1981; M. Williams, 1983, 2014).
A major statement consistent with Sauer’s approach was a 1955 Wenner-Gren symposium
‘Man’s Role in Changing the Face of the Earth’ (see Glacken, 1983) which brought UK and USA
practitioners together and resulted in a substantial publication (52 chapters plus discussions: 1,193
pages in all – Thomas, 1956). Sauer identified its theme as:

the capacity of man to alter his natural environment, the manner of his so doing, and the virtue
of his actions. It is concerned with historically cumulative effects, with the physical and biologic
processes that man sets in motion, inhibits, or deflects, and with the differences in cultural
conduct that distinguish one human group from another.
(1956b, p. 49)

It presented no grand methodology or general findings – indeed, Sauer’s closing statement (1956c)
criticised the tendency of American authors who ‘have an inclination to universalize ourselves’
(p. 1133). The volume stressed cultural differences as the basis for both diversity in human response
to environments and its impacts on them. Mumford’s (1956, p. 1142) conclusion has affinities
with that advanced in the 1980s by adherents of structuration theory (see p. 221, this book): ‘the
future is not a blank page; and neither is it an open book’. The symposium was updated some
30 years later (Turner et al., 1990).
One Berkeley school contributor to that symposium was Glacken (1956), whose magnum opus
Traces on the Rhodian Shore (Glacken, 1967) surveys interpretations of nature and demonstrates ‘how
54 Foundations

all-pervading teleology has been in the history of Western interpretation of nature’ (Glacken,
1983, p. 32). Like the 1955 symposium publication, this book is widely recognised as a classic on
society–nature interrelationships. But by then that topic was receiving diminishing attention
among geographers; its impact was less than might otherwise have occurred, as was Tuan’s (1968)
monograph on vernacular interpretations of The Hydrological Cycle.
The body of work stimulated by Sauer is set in a wider frame of studies of human–environment
interactions concerned with anthropomorphically generated change rather than the influence of
the environment on people which characterised the early twentieth century (Turner, 2002).
Geographers’ basic concerns became the environments that we encounter and the changes that we
create in order to make them more comfortable for our desired lifestyles (Sack, 2001). Increasingly,
concern with the deleterious consequences of those changes focused attention on conservation
(Manners and Mikesell, 1974), for which one stimulus was George Perkins Marsh’s Man and Nature
(1864), widely recognised as a pioneer statement on environmental abuse by humans and the
needs for conservation (Lowenthal, 2001).

Geography in the early 1950s


Two early 1950s edited volumes characterise geographical practices at the end of the modern
period. American Geography: Inventory and Prospect (James and Jones, 1954) was a ‘semi-official’ compilation
celebrating the Association of American Geographers’ 50th anniversary with ‘a progress report on
the objectives and procedures of geographic research’ (p. vii). Although each chapter has a named
author, all had been commented on in draft by others, with some collaborating in their production.
All but two chapters deal either with a systematic field within geography (urban, political etc.) or
with geographical methods (field survey, air photo interpretation and cartography). But the first
two – on ‘The field of geography’ and ‘The regional concept and the regional method’ (by Preston
James and Derwent Whittlesey respectively) – dominate the book.
Geography is defined as ‘concerned with the arrangement of things on the face of the earth,
and with the association of things that give character to particular places’ (James, 1954, p. 4); the
region is ‘the geographic generalization of phenomena associated in area’ (p. 9) and the map is
‘the fundamental implement of geographic research’. Whittlesey (1954, p. 21) claimed that
‘Geographers are in general agreement that regional study is an essential part of their craft’ and
concluded that regional study ‘underlies and is applicable to all aspects of geography’ (p. 65). These
views permeate the entire volume, covering subject matter as diverse as political, agricultural,
geomorphic, soil and zoogeographical regions, and regions in marketing geography. (On the
dissolution of this core to geographical study provided by regions and maps, see Johnston, 2004b.)
Geography in the Twentieth Century: A Study of Growth, Fields,Techniques, Aims and Trends (T. G. Taylor, 1957 –
this was an expanded version of one published in 1951) had a wider range of authors, from Canada
(6; T. G. Taylor – see p. 45, this book – was then a Professor at Toronto), the USA (6), England
(8, including Darby, Stamp and Wooldridge), and one each from Czechoslovakia and Poland.
T. Griffith Taylor defines geography as ‘the discussion of the causes of patterns of distribution’
(p. v), and introduces the book as

an attempt to answer questions which are engaging the attention of all geographers. What are the
salient features of modern geography? What are we trying to accomplish? How have our ideas as
to what are the important fields of our discipline changed during the last fifty years? How do our
studies touch the fields of allied disciplines? Have America, Britain, France, Germany, and the Slav
nations and even Canada produced special contributions? . . . Broadly speaking, are there different
schools of geographic thought which cut across national boundaries to some degree?
(p. 3)
Foundations 55

The book has three parts, with five further introductory chapters on the history of geography, ten
on ‘the environment as a factor’, and thirteen on ‘special fields of geography’. This structure –
particularly the ordering of the last two sections – reflects Taylor’s position as a ‘stop-and-go
determinist’, and although there are no chapters on regional geography or the regional concept per
se (there is one on regionalism as regional administration) and the term ‘region’ does not appear
in the book’s index, Taylor states that ‘Most geographers accept regional geography as the core of
our discipline’ (p. 8).
These two books clearly illustrate the transitional situation of Anglo-American geography at
the beginning of the post-1945 period. Systematic studies were coming to dominate its internal
organisation, but there was still a very strong tie to the regional concept and the belief in regional
synthesis as the core of geographical knowledge and, for some at least as exemplified by Taylor’s
book, the remnants of environmental determinism in the primacy given to the ‘environmental
factor’. Later work on environmental geography would trace some of its lineages to these earlier
human–environment debates, while losing the baggage of determinism/possibilism. Indeed, as
subsequent chapters will chart, nature, landscape and environment have continued to be key themes
in human geography, albeit from very different vantage points (or paradigms if you prefer) from
those we have considered here.

Conclusions
This chapter has presented a brief outline of geography during its ‘modern period’, as a foundation
for studying what followed. Three major approaches have been identified, although others also
attracted attention (Taylor, 1937). All three lasted into the contemporary period, but the regional
dominated in the years before and just after the Second World War. Its main focus was areal
differentiation, the varying character of the earth’s surface; its portrayal of that variation was built
up from parallel topical studies of different aspects of physical and human patterns. Kevin Cox
(2014, p. 21) judges ‘human geography in the first half of the twentieth century’ as ‘an extremely
conservative subdiscipline’:

There was an odd disinterest in modern urban society, apart from a few visionaries like Fawcett
and Dickinson. The notion of methodological or theoretical debate was utterly alien. There was
no sense of forward movement. And lacking a strong sense of the social, human geography
found itself closeted off from the other human sciences.

Yet by the 1950s, initially in the USA and then in the UK too, there was growing disillusionment
with the empiricist philosophy of regional geography. The topical specialisms slowly came to
dominate disciplinary practice and regional synthesis was increasingly ignored.
In both countries, those developments were produced by only a small number of active
geographers. In the UK, for example, there was no separate academic learned society organising
conferences for geographers alone until the mid-1930s (Johnston, 2003b; Withers, 2010), and by
1946 there were only about 120 employed in the country’s universities – many lacking any formal
training in the discipline. Darby (1983b, p. 17) cites from an unsigned 1934 obituary that
‘geography is far from having consolidated a definite position, British geography particularly so’.
In the USA, the discipline was larger (in absolute terms). The Association of American Geographers
(which was small and difficult to join without an established research reputation) had been founded
in 1904; in 1949 it merged with the Association of Professional Geographers and ended its
restrictive entry requirements (the RGS was the focus of considerable debate for a number of years
before it was finally agreed to allow women to become Fellows – Bell and McEwan, 1996).
Nevertheless, the discipline was not strong in the country’s universities with American academics,
according to Schulten (2001, p. 125), finding ‘little incentive to join the fight for their subject’s
56 Foundations

independence even as they bemoaned its position within the social studies’. Writing about Oxbridge
(and by extension, the longer established Scottish universities, comprising Aberdeen, Edinburgh,
Glasgow and St Andrews) in the 1920s, Hodges (2014, p. 77) claims that ‘there was a great deal
about the ancient universities which had less to do with learning than with social status, with
courses in geography and estate management for those of a less academic turn of mind’. While
according to Cox:

For the most part, complacency ruled. In Great Britain, this was absolutely the case. In the
United States, though, there had been some rude shocks challenging that self-satisfaction and
reflecting a view in some universities that geography was marginal to their intellectual purpose.
The most notable of these was the closure of the department at Harvard, the most prestigious of
American universities, in 1948.
(2014, p. 21)

Thus, the changes discussed in subsequent chapters of this book were built on fairly shallow and
sometimes shaky roots, but when they came they coincided with a massive growth in the size (both
absolute and, in the case of the UK, relative) of the academic geographic enterprise.
The modern period saw the institutionalisation of geography as an academic discipline,
with a particular focus. The nature of the subject matter appropriated to that discipline, and the
associated research and pedagogic practices, formed what Harvey (2005a) terms a particular
‘geographical imagination’ (the term draws from Mills’s (1959) earlier discussion of a ‘sociological
imagination’; see also Gregory, 1994). The nascent academic discipline focused on a particular view
of ‘geographical knowledge’, one that served the interests of states, nations and empires and
associated commercial interest groups during the apex of imperial capitalism, so that the academics
involved became ‘tacit agents of state power, captive of a particular national and geopolitical
vision’ (Harvey, 2005a, p. 222); as different countries had different geopolitical and military
agendas, particular ‘national schools’ emerged. But other geographical imaginations were emerging
alongside these, reflecting alternative deployments of geographical knowledge. These included the
growing tourist and travel industries that promoted a ‘particular kind of geographical understand-
ing marked by adventure, engagement with difference (and hence liberation from self), exoticism
(the romancing of the other), eroticism (the themes of “sea, sun, sex and sand” are widespread)
and culture (presented as unique and authentic to some locality)’ (p. 232). Associated with this
are the imaginations promoted by the media – increasingly by the cinema and TV, alongside
geographical magazines (many of which promote the exotic, especially in wildlife and local culture
– Johnston, 2009d) and the many local knowledges generated as part of daily life. The type of
geographical knowledge produced by academic geographers, and disseminated not only by them
but also by school teachers, thus co-exists alongside a number of others that use the name
geography – and which some academics might think improper (Harvey, 2005a, p. 240). By the
beginning of the end of the modern period in the 1950s, however, there was general appreciation
that all types of geographical knowledge were concerned with ‘what is where?’ or ‘what is it like
there?’. With the movement into the contemporary period and the explosion of a variety of
academic geographies, as described in subsequent chapters, the distancing between what
many – arguably most – academic geographers do and vernacular understandings of their
discipline increased.
Chapter 3

Growth of systematic studies and


the adoption of scientific method

Some carried the idea as far as to believe that the ‘core of geography’ lay in ‘regional
synthesis’, in which the facts of geology, climate, agriculture, industry and so on could, by
some artistry, be fused into a delineation of ‘the personality of a region’ . . . one must remember
that much so-called regional geography was in no sense a synthesis, but simply a way of
handling the facts of, say, agriculture or morphology.
(H. Clifford Darby, 1983b, p. 15)

The fact that one can do little with the unique except contemplate its uniqueness, has led to the
present unsatisfactory position . . .
(Peter Haggett, 1965c, p. 3)

The realization dawned that where a qualitative and descriptive approach had previously
sufficed, it was now possible to press analysis much further than had previously seemed
conceivable. Although the roots of this change can be traced back to the early decades of this
century and even earlier, the adoption process undoubtedly accelerated during the 1950s
and 1960s.
(Michael Chisholm, 1975a, p. 172)

The aim of geographical research is to provide laws and theories about the spatial structure
of the earth. The task is formidable and modern efforts to develop geographic generalis-
ations have a relatively recent origin. Progress has been slow . . . there was a solid, but
rapidly declining, aversion to theory-building and mathematical methods within the ranks of
geographers . . . there has been a process of trial-and-error, using methods developed in
other disciplines . . .
(Maurice Daly, 1972, p. 98)

Every beginning is difficult, holds in all science.


(Karl Marx, 1867 Preface to the first German edition of Das Kapital)

Dating the origin of change in a discipline’s orientation and practices, or even a part of it, is
difficult. Several pieces which contain the kernel of the new ideas can usually be found in its
literature, but often these are derivative of the earlier teachings of others, whose views may never
have been published but only disseminated to their students; others may promote the ideas that
are widely adopted later, but have no impact on those developments for a variety of reasons
(see Johnston, 1993b, 1996b). Change can also emanate contemporaneously from several
separate, though usually not entirely independent, nodes. An attempt to locate the first stirrings
58 Systematic studies and scientific method

against the regional paradigm would be a futile exercise, therefore. Instead, the present chapter
identifies the most influential statements, published by geographers.

The critique of regional geography


Major change within a discipline involves both dissatisfaction with existing approaches and the
promotion of an acceptable alternative disciplinary matrix (if not world view, see p. 19, this book).
The 1950s saw widespread dissatisfaction with the regional approach, as indicated by Freeman:

disappointment with the work of regional geographers has led many to wonder if the regional
approach can ever be academically satisfying and to turn to specialization or some systematic
branch of the subject.
(1961, p. 141)

He suggested three reasons for this. First, much regional classification was naive, particularly on the
broader scale; its generalisations contained too many discrepancies. The second, and perhaps most
important, was the ‘weary succession’ of physical and human activity ‘facts’ which characterised
much regional writing: ‘The trouble has perhaps been that many regional geographers have tried to
include too much’ (Freeman, 1961, p. 143). Third, one of the most influential models of regional
writing, derived from work on the French pays, suggested that the whole of the earth’s surface could
be divided into clearly identifiable regions, each with its own character; that this proved false was
reflected by many pedestrian studies of areas lacking such ‘personality’. A satirical essay high-
lighting the poverty of much regional geography was published anonymously in an early issue of
the IBG Newsletter (Anon., 1968). The author’s name was given as Llwynog Llwyd, ‘an exiled Celt . . .
[working in] an Antipodean University’– it was Keith Buchanan (Johnston, 1999). Buchanan’s
critique emerged in two book reviews (Buchanan, 1958a, 1958b). He concluded that Harrison
Church’s West Africa: A study of the environment and man’s use of it (1957), ‘fails to capture anything of the
quality of West African life or the vividness of the West African scene. These are lost, veiled in a grey
harmattan haze of geological details and climatic statistics, of catalogues of towns and production
data’ – K. Buchanan, 1958a, p. 278. (For his own quest to portray the ‘vividness of the scene’, see
Buchanan and Pugh, 1958; Buchanan, 1966.)
An earlier critique of regional geography as practised in the UK was Kimble’s (1951) essay on
‘The inadequacy of the regional concept’. He claimed that most geographers would ‘contend that
the highest form of geographical enquiry was a kind of “hunt-the-region” game, in which
(provided we were offered enough clues) we were bound to discover that life in a given land or
continent resolves itself into a neat pattern of cultural entities we call regions’ (p. 151). But
geographers had no agreed definition of a region (he had found no less than a hundred in the
literature) and so they were unable to present a united front regarding their discipline to the wider
academic world. He concluded that not only was there no agreement on how to define regions but
also the concept was largely obsolete in the contemporary world:

From the air it is the links in the landscapes, the rivers, roads, railways, canals, pipe-lines,
electric cables, rather than the breaks that impress the aviator . . . regional geographers may be
trying to put boundaries that do not exist around areas that do not matter.
(p. 159)

His later reference to the situation in Germany that ‘If the only type of regionalised unity possessed
by modern . . . Germany was its circulation pattern, then the day of the region is nearly at the end,
since mobility is the catalyst of regional diversity, and must sooner or later dissolve the whole
compartmental structure of our civilization’ (p. 168) makes clear that he was referring only to
Systematic studies and scientific method 59

formal regions (see p. 89, this book); functional regions may well exist. (The reference to Germany
was based on Dickinson’s work: see Johnston, 2000c.) Formal regions were of little contemporary
interest, however, even in work on different parts of the globe:

Whatever the pattern of the new age may be, we can be sure there will be no independent, discrete
units within it – no ‘worlds within worlds’. There will be no neatly demarcated ‘regions’ where
geographers . . . can study a ‘fossil’ community. Man’s ‘region’ is now the world. This does not
render superfluous the continued organization of geographical studies on a systematic areal
basis. . . . But it does mean that we should be well advised, when making these studies, to refrain
from searching for ‘unitary patterns of living’, ‘entities of distribution’, and from assuming, in the
manner of determinists, that ‘regional unity’ is the goal towards which civilized society is
moving. . . . At best a regional study can be only a personal work of art, not an impersonal work of
science – a portrait rather than a blueprint. As such, it can have substantial value, but its value will
lie in the realm of illumination and suggestion rather than of definitive analysis and synthesis.
(p. 173)

Alongside these critics, in the USA Ackerman (1945) forcefully argued that insistence on the
primacy of regional geography was undermining the associated systematic studies. Drawing on his
experience of working in the wartime intelligence services (American Association of Geographers,
1946; Harris, 1997a), Ackerman identified two major failings among professional geographers
there: their inability to handle foreign languages and the weakness of their topical specialisms.
Regarding the latter, he categorised much geographical work as undertaken by scholars who were
‘more or less amateurs in the subject on which they published’ (p. 124), so that when called upon
to provide intelligence material for wartime interpretation what they produced was extremely thin
in its content. Regional geographers could provide only superficial analyses, and the division of
labour within the discipline whereby people specialised in different areas of the earth was both
inefficient and ineffective. (Gould, 1979, p.140, called the geography of the 50 years prior to 1950
‘shabby, parochial and unintelligent . . . bumbling amateurism and antiquarianism’.)
Ackerman suggested that rectifying this major deficiency required much more research and
training in the systematic specialisms. This was not necessarily contrary to giving primacy to
regional synthesis, he claimed, since more detailed systematic studies could lead to greater depth in
regional interpretations. There is little evidence that his paper had an immediate impact, however,
as illustrated by the abstracts of papers presented at the Association of American Geographers’
annual meetings (published then in the Annals each year). These indicated that no major shift in the
orientation of academic work with the return to postwar ‘normality’, save in the case of the abstracts
presented by Garrison and McCarty for the Cleveland meeting in 1953, which were clearly based
on a different methodology to that widely used (see Garrison, 2002, p. 108, and also p. 72, this
book). The systematic fields had undoubtedly been gaining in importance prior to Ackerman’s
statement, and continued to do so, as indicated by their extensive treatment in the review volume
edited by Preston James and Clarence Jones (1954). But it was not until the mid-1950s that this was
matched by widespread changes in disciplinary methodologies and philosophy. A few geographers
who had shared Ackerman’s wartime Washington experiences, such as Chauncy Harris and Edward
Ullman (Eyre, 1978; Boyce, 1980), did follow this lead and were among the pioneers of the ‘new
geography’ launched in the early 1950s.

Schaefer’s (1953) paper and the response


A substantial (and ultimately successful) revolution against the regional paradigm got under way in
the USA in the 1950s, initiated through debates over philosophy and methods. The first major
60 Systematic studies and scientific method

contribution was a posthumously published paper by Schaefer (1953), often identified as one of
the origins of the ‘quantitative and theoretical revolutions’ (on its impact, see Cox, 1995, and
Getis, 1993). Schaefer trained as an economist: he joined the group of geographers teaching in the
economics department at the University of Iowa after his escape from Nazi Germany (Bunge,
1979).
Schaefer claimed that his paper was the first to challenge Hartshorne’s interpretation of
the works of Hettner and others. He criticised Hartshorne’s exceptionalist claims for regional
geography and presented an alternative case for geography, adopting the philosophy and methods
of the positivist school of science (Martin, 1990, p. 72). He first outlined the nature of a science
and then defined the peculiar characteristics of geography as a social science. He argued that a
claim for geography as the integrating science which put together the findings of the individual
systematic sciences was arrogant, and that its products were somewhat lacking in ‘startlingly new
and deeper insights’ (p. 227). A science is characterised by its explanations, and explanations
require laws: ‘To explain the phenomena one has described means always to recognise them as
instances of laws.’ Geography’s major regularities refer to spatial patterns: ‘Hence geography has to
be conceived as the science concerned with the formulation of the laws governing the spatial
distribution of certain features on the surface of the earth’ (p. 227). These spatial arrangements, not
the phenomena themselves, should be the subject of geographers’ search for law-like statements.
Their procedures would be the same as those employed in other natural and social sciences:
observation would lead to a hypothesis which would then be tested against large numbers of cases,
providing the basis for a law if it were verified.
Schaefer criticised Hartshorne’s exceptionalist position that geography does not share the
methodology of other sciences because of the peculiar nature of its subject matter – the study of
unique places or regions; this puts geography in a similar situation as history, which studies unique
periods of time. Using analogies from physics and economics, Schaefer argued that geography is
not peculiar in focusing on unique phenomena. All sciences deal with unique events which can
only be accounted for by integrating laws from various systematic sciences in particular
circumstances, but this does not prevent the development of laws, although undoubtedly making it
more difficult: ‘It is, therefore, absurd to maintain that the geographers are distinguished among the
scientists through the integration of heterogeneous phenomena which they achieve. There is
nothing extraordinary about geography in that respect’ (p. 231).
Schaefer traced the exceptionalist view in geography back to an analogy drawn by Kant between
geography and history, an analogy repeated by both Hettner and Hartshorne (Harvey, 2009). Kant
argued in his Physische Geographie (Vol. I, p. 8) that, ‘Geography and history together fill up the entire
area of our perception: geography that of space and history that of time’ (Schaefer, 1953, p. 233; on
Kant’s geography more generally, see May, 1970; Elden and Mendieta, 2011; Harvey, 2009). But
when Kant was working, Schaefer claims, history and geography were cosmologies, not sciences,
and a cosmology is ‘not rational science but at best thoughtful contemplation of the universe’
(p. 232). Hettner followed Kant’s views and developed geography as a cosmology, arguing that both
history and geography deal with the unique, and thus do not apply the methods of science.
Schaefer argued that this is a false position, for in explaining what happened in a certain time period
historians must employ the laws of the social sciences. Time periods, like places, are unique assem-
blages of phenomena, but this does not preclude the use of laws in unravelling and explaining them.
History and geography can both be sciences, for ‘What scientists do is . . . They apply to each con-
crete situation jointly all the laws that involve the variables they have reason to believe are relevant’
(p. 239). Schaefer further argued that Hartshorne disregarded one aspect of Hettner’s writing which
was nomothetic in its orientation, and in so doing misled American geographers. (Müller-Wille,
1978, p. 55, claims that Hettner predated Christaller in the development of ideas regarding central
place theory – see p. 72, this book; Hartshorne made no reference to the paper by Hettner cited by
Müller-Wille. On the same point, see Butzer, 1990, and N. Smith, 1990.)
Systematic studies and scientific method 61

The final part of Schaefer’s paper reviewed some problems of applying a nomothetic (law-
producing) philosophy to geography as a spatial, social science. He recognised difficulties of
experimentation and quantification, for example, and suggested a methodology based on car-
tographic correlations (a topic explored by his Iowa colleagues: McCarty et al., 1956). He argued
that geographical laws are morphological (i.e. concerned with spatial forms), whereas those from
other, ‘maturer’ social sciences are concerned with processes (hence morphogenetic). In order fully
to comprehend the phenomena assemblages described in morphological laws, therefore, it is nec-
essary to deploy process laws from other social sciences, a procedure which requires team work
(the last point was also made by Ackerman). Thus, geography, according to Schaefer, is the source
of the laws on location, which may be used to differentiate the regions of the earth’s surface.

Hartshorne’s responses
Schaefer’s paper did not produce much direct reaction in print, despite claims that it was a major
stimulus to later work in his proposed genre (Bunge, 1962). It drew considerable response from
Hartshorne, however, first in a letter to the editor of the Annals (Hartshorne, 1954b) and later in
three substantive pieces (Hartshorne, 1955, 1958, 1959). The last was another major book which,
although not as influential as the 1939 volume, showed Hartshorne’s continued importance to
American geographers as an interpreter of their subject’s methodology and philosophy.
The purpose of Hartshorne’s first (1955) paper (which subsumed the earlier letter) was to
indicate flaws in Schaefer’s scholarship (see also D. Gregory, 1978a, p. 31). He begins with a
discussion of the mores of methodological debate (Hartshorne, 1948). Schaefer was limited in his
references, drew unsupportable conclusions, and misrepresented the views of others, so that ‘In
every paragraph, in nearly every sentence of this third section, there is serious falsification, either
by commission or by omission, of the views of the writer discussed’ (p. 236: this statement refers
to the third part of Schaefer’s paper, which focused on Hartshorne’s interpretations of Hettner).
More generally, Hartshorne claimed that Schaefer’s paper ‘ignores the normal standards of critical
scholarship and in effect offers nothing more than personal opinion, thinly disguised as literary and
historical analysis’ (p. 244). Since Hartshorne himself (1959, p. 8) strongly believed that ‘geography
is what geographers have made it’, to him all methodological and philosophical statements should
be based on a close and careful analysis of others’ published works.
Although most of the 1955 paper examined Schaefer’s ‘evidence’, in the final section
Hartshorne turned to the anti-exceptionalist argument. He pointed out that in concluding that
geography should take process laws from the systematic sciences and use them to produce
morphological laws, Schaefer came very close to preaching the sort of exceptionalist claim that he
sought to destroy, so that his critique ‘is a total fraud’ (p. 237). Schaefer’s position is summarised
as: ‘geography must be a science, science is the search for laws, and all phenomena of nature and
human life are subject to such laws and completely determinable by them’ (p. 242). Such scientific
determinism is opposed to the summary of what geographers do set out in The nature of geography,
which was treated in a most cavalier way by Schaefer.
Hartshorne’s second paper (1958) addressed Schaefer’s claim that Kant was the source of the
exceptionalist view. Literary analysis suggests that both von Humboldt and Hettner reached the
same position independently, being unaware of Kant’s views when they were writing. May (1970,
p. 9) suggests that both Hartshorne and Schaefer could have misunderstood Kant’s conception of a
science, however, and of geography’s status as a science, although he confirms Hartshorne’s
dismissal of Schaefer’s interpretation of the source of Kant’s ideas (see the later exchange between
Hartshorne, 1972, and May, 1972).
The third and most substantial piece in Hartshorne’s rebuttal was a further monograph
(Perspective on the Nature of Geography, Hartshorne, 1959) whose production was stimulated by requests
from colleagues that he respond in detail to Schaefer’s argument, but was also used to discuss other
62 Systematic studies and scientific method

issues raised during the two decades since publication of the original statement (Hartshorne,
1939). The discussion used a framework of ten separate questions/topics; the aim was to provide a
methodology by which geography could meet its need for ‘new conceptual approaches and more
effective ways of measuring the interrelationships of phenomena’ (p. 9), which could only develop
out of an understanding and acceptance of the subject’s ‘essential character’.
The first set of questions concerned the meaning of areal differentiation, the definition of the
earth’s surface, the particular geographical interest in the integration of phenomena – ‘the total
reality [that] is there for study, and geography is the name of the section of empirical knowledge
which has always been called upon to study that reality’ (p. 33) – and the determination of what is
significant for geographical study. His answers led Hartshorne to define geography as ‘that discipline
that seeks to describe and interpret the variable character from place to place of the earth as the
world of man’ (p. 47). Human and natural factors do not have to be identified separately – any prior
insistence on this was a function of environmental determinist arguments – and a division into
human and physical geography is unfortunate, because it limits the range of possible integrations
in the study of reality.
Turning to processes operating over time, Hartshorne argued that geographers need only study
proximate genesis, since classification by form of appearance rather than by provenance is central
to investigations of areal differentiation. As most landforms are stable, or virtually so, from the point
of view of human occupancy, for example, then study of their change is irrelevant to the aims of
geography (see p. 51, this book). According to this argument, geomorphology, insofar as it is the
study of landform genesis, is not part of geography, but the study of landforms is. With regard to
cultural features in the landscape, Hartshorne drew an important distinction between expository
description and explanatory description: ‘geography is primarily concerned to describe . . . the
variable character of areas as formed by existing features in interrelationships . . . explanatory
description of features in the past must be kept subordinate to the primary purpose’ (p. 99). Thus,
historical geography should be the expository description of the historical present, ‘but the purpose
of such dips into the past is not to trace developments or seek origins but to facilitate comprehension
of the present’ (p. 106); studies of causal development and genesis are the prerogative of the
systematic sciences. By this statement, Hartshorne at least partly bridged the gap between his and
Sauer’s views of the discipline perhaps reflecting that one of Sauer’s students, Andrew Clark (whose
Ph.D. was on the European colonisation of New Zealand (Clark, 1949)) had joined Hartshorne on
the staff at the University of Wisconsin-Madison.
In answering the question ‘Is geography divided between systematic and regional geography?’,
Hartshorne modified his position from that in The Nature of Geography. He accepted that studies of
interrelationships could be arranged along a continuum ‘from those which analyse the most
elementary complexes in areal variation over the world to those which analyse the most complex
integrations in areal variation within small areas’ (p. 121). The former are topical studies and the
latter regional studies, but whereas ‘every truly geographical study involves the use of both the
topical and the regional approach’ (p. 122), there is no argument that the latter is superior and that
to which all geographers should aspire. Hartshorne thereby somewhat downgraded his earlier view
regarding the centrality of regional synthesis in the geographical enterprise.
Regarding Schaefer’s important question ‘Does geography seek to formulate scientific laws or
to describe individual cases?’, Hartshorne argued for the latter, largely by pointing out the difficulties
of establishing laws through geographical investigations. He did not argue against geographers
seeking and using general laws for understanding individual cases, however: it is an ‘erroneous
presumption that to focus on studies of individual places and to focus on generic concepts are
opposing alternatives mutually exclusive’ (Hartshorne, 1984, p. 429). Scientific laws must be based
on large numbers of cases, but geographers study complex integrations in unique places. Scientific
laws can best be established in laboratory experiments which allow only a few potential influences
to vary, but such work is rarely possible in human geography. Interpretation of such experiments
Systematic studies and scientific method 63

requires skills in the systematic sciences which are beyond the capability of geographers, and
scientific laws suggest some kind of determinism, which is inappropriate to the human motivations
that are in part the causes of landscape variations. For all these reasons, he argued, the search for
laws is irrelevant to geography. Laws are not the only means to the scientific end of comprehending
reality, however, instead:

Geography seeks (1) on the basis of empirical observation as independent as possible of the
person of the observer, to describe phenomena with the maximum degree of accuracy and
certainty; (2) on this basis, to classify the phenomena, as far as reality permits, in terms of
generic concepts or universals; (3) through rational consideration of the facts thus secured and
by logical processes of analysis and synthesis, including the construction and use wherever
possible of general principles or laws of generic relationships, to attain the maximum
comprehension of the scientific interrelationships of phenomena; and (4) to arrange these
findings in orderly systems so that what is known leads directly to the margin of the unknown.
(pp. 169–70)

This, he says, is a perfectly respectable scientific goal. Its empiricist base is very similar to the overall
goal of positivist work and is the reason why several commentators see very little difference in ends,
if not means, between Hartshorne’s work and that of spatial scientists.
Finally, in discussing geography’s position within the classification of sciences, Hartshorne
returned to the Hettnerian analogy of geography as a chorological science with history as a
chronological science. This is valid, he argues, because it describes the way in which geographers
have worked, on both topical and regional subjects (this view was revived by Harris, 1971; see
Earle, 1996).

Reconciliations?
The major basis of their methodological and philosophical differences was that Hartshorne had a
positive view of geography – geography is what geographers have made it – whereas Schaefer’s was
normative, of what geography should be, irrespective of what it had been. Over the decade after
Hartshorne published his Perspective, the view associated with Schaefer prevailed with many
geographers on both sides of the Atlantic, although his personal influence via the 1953 paper was
probably very slight and the real iconoclasts of the ‘revolution’ were those discussed in the next
section. (According to N. Smith, 1990, Hartshorne’s view that geography should be what (he said)
it had always been in effect ‘turned the discourse of geography into a museum and [Hartshorne]
appointed himself curator’ – D. Gregory, 1994, p. 285.) Indeed, in the UK, although Hartshorne’s
two books were clearly widely read and referenced, Schaefer’s paper was apparently not. It receives
no mention in Freeman’s (1961, 1980a) books, none in Chorley and Haggett’s (1965b) trail-
blazing Frontiers in Geographical Teaching, and only one in their major edited collection Models in
Geography (Chorley and Haggett, 1967) – in the chapter by Stoddart (see, however, Stoddart, 1990).
Thus, it is not surprising that relatively little attention has been paid elsewhere in the geographical
literature to the Schaefer/Hartshorne debate (Gregory, 1978a, p. 32: see also Martin, 1951 and
E. Jones, 1956, for a separate, British, debate). Interestingly, Schaefer is not in the index of authors
referred to in the encyclopaedic Geography in America either (Gaile and Willmott, 1989). Schaefer and
Hartshorne’s importance to the discipline’s history is not so much the influence of the two
principals themselves as the clarification they brought to what became a major debate over
disciplinary means and ends.
Guelke (1977a, 1978) argued that Hartshorne’s and Schaefer’s views were not as antagonistic
as they suggested (see also Gregory, 1978a, p. 31, and Entrikin, 1981, 1990). Hartshorne generally
supported use of the scientific method as later defined by other geographers, but created problems
64 Systematic studies and scientific method

for this method’s application in geography by his view on uniqueness. Schaefer, on the other hand,
not only accepted the full position of what geographers came to term ‘scientific method’, but also
showed that uniqueness was a general problem of science, and not a peculiar characteristic of
geography. Thus:

In extending the idea of uniqueness to everything, Schaefer effectively removed a major logical
objection to the possibility of a law-seeking geography and demonstrated that Hartshorne’s view
of uniqueness as a special problem was untenable for anyone who accepted the scientific model
of explanation.
(Guelke, 1977a, p. 380)

Furthermore, Guelke argued, Hartshorne’s distinction between idiographic (understanding the


individual case) and nomothetic (law-seeking) approaches was misleading; both he and Schaefer
ignored the possibility of geographers being major ‘law-consumers’. To Hartshorne, the alternatives
were either law-making or the description of unique places, while to Schaefer geographers had to
develop morphological laws, and ignore the interest in process laws which characterises the
systematic sciences.
Guelke (1977a, p. 348) claimed that Schaefer’s insistence on the need for geographers to
develop laws ‘created a major crisis within the discipline’. Within a decade of Schaefer’s paper being
published, however, many human geographers had adopted at least part of his manifesto with their
growing concern for quantification and law-making. Presented with a choice between such activity
and the sort of contemplation of the unique advocated by Hartshorne then, as Guelke (1977a,
p. 385) points out, ‘Not surprisingly, most geographers opted for geography as a law-seeking
science’ because at that time (Guelke, 1978, p. 45):

Universities were expected to produce problem-solvers or social-technologists to run increasingly


complex economies, and geographers were not slow in adopting new positions appropriate to the
new conditions. Statistics and models were ideal tools for monitoring and planning in complex
industrial societies. The work of the new geographers, however, often lacked a truly intellectual
dimension. Many geographers were asking: ‘Are our methods rigorous?’, ‘What are the planning
implications of this model?’, and not ‘How much insight does this study give us?’, ‘Is my
understanding of this phenomenon enhanced?’, ‘Does this study contribute to geography?’. The
last-mentioned question was considered of little consequence. Yet it should have been asked,
because one of the weaknesses of the new geography was a lack of coherence.

Developments in systematic geography in the USA


Whether because of or independent from the statements by Ackerman (1945), Schaefer (1953)
and Ullman (1953), systematic studies became much more important in the research and under-
graduate and graduate teaching in many American (and a few Canadian) university departments in
the 1950s. (On Hartshorne’s influence on systematic studies, see Butzer, 1990.) This did not mean
a total departure from Hartshorne’s contemporary views, since by 1959 he no longer gave primacy
to regional studies, but the trend towards the scientific method proposed by Schaefer marked a clear
break with the Hartshornian tradition.
The growing popularity of topical specialisms is illustrated in the review chapters in the
collection edited by James and Jones (1954). Very few of the investigations reported there aimed at
generating laws, however. Indeed, some could almost be categorised under the exploration
paradigm, since their major purpose was the provision of new factual material; such work is best
described as empiricist – it wants ‘the facts’ to speak for themselves.
Systematic studies and scientific method 65

Fundamental to scientific progress in Schaefer’s approach is the development of theory.


Geographers were aware of theory pre-Schaefer, as shown by their references to theoretical work on
space and the economics of location by non-geographers (on the part of August Lösch first
published in German 1940, intended as a contribution to economics, see Gregory, 1994, pp. 56–7;
Leslie Curry wrote his MA thesis in 1950 on the utility of location theory in economic geography:
see Johnston, 2010b) and a few – notably Chauncy Harris (1945) and Edward Ullman (1941) –
wrote review papers summarising that material (see C. D. Harris, 1978, 1997b; Ullman, 1962).
Stoddart (1986, p. 13) also points to a foreshadowing of the commitment to science in a paper by
James (1952), which ‘considered the problem of pattern, process and scale, and attempted to
reconcile them with the prevailing theme of geography as the study of areal differentiation’.
Although James was ‘a leader of the old paradigm’, according to Stoddart, the issues flagged in his
1952 paper had a considerable vintage, appearing in technical debates about the terminology and
approaches of regional description that had been published in the Annals in the 1930s and 1940s. In
Stoddart’s (1986, p. 13) view, therefore, ‘the revolution, if there was one, had long and respectable
antecedents: the precursors themselves were central features of the old paradigm’. As indicated
below, James was not alone.
Yet, despite these precedents, relatively little work was done in human geography prior to
the mid-1950s which explicitly followed the dictates of the ‘scientific approach’; there were
pockets of innovation and wider awareness of relevant work on spatial arrangements being
undertaken by other scholars, but relatively few geographers were utilising such approaches in their
own research.
Once a new idea gains circulation through the professional journals it is available to
be taken up by all. Initial development is usually concentrated in a few places only, however,
where pioneer teachers encourage students to conduct research within the new framework.
Thus, most of the methodological changes in systematic studies in geography during the 1950s
can be traced to a few centres in the USA. These were connected through the movements
of key individuals, and the dissemination of texts and technologies on location theory,
produced by Walter Christaller and August Lösch and others, originally written in German in the
1930s–1940s, were translated into English by the 1950s too, making them more accessible to
those seeking alternatives to the established regional tradition. The changes in American
geography were largely concerned with method, and their scientific underpinning was at first
little stressed, although law-seeking was the clear goal. Certainly, methods dominated the
writings of both the pros and cons; many early contributions by the former group were in rela-
tively fugitive, departmental publications, because of difficulties in getting such ‘new’ material
accepted by the small number of mainline journals (as described by Berry, 1993; see Barnes,
2001b; Johnston, 2004a).

The Iowa school


Although Schaefer was at Iowa until his death in 1953, he had little apparent influence on changes
promoted by geographers there, who for a number of years were members of the economics
department and thus exposed to the approaches deployed in that more established social science.
The group’s leader was Harold McCarty, author of a major text on American economic geography
(McCarty, 1940); associated with him were J. C. Hook, D. S. Knos, H. A. Stafford and, later, J. B.
Lindberg, E. N. Thomas and L. J. King (McCarty, 1979; King, 1979a).
McCarty and his co-workers wanted to establish the degree of correspondence between
two or more geographical patterns – to make map comparison more rigorous and generate
laws of association akin to the morphological laws of accordance discussed by Schaefer.
Interestingly, none of their publications refer to Schaefer’s paper, although they do refer to
works and assistance given by Gustav Bergmann, a positivist philosopher of the Vienna school
66 Systematic studies and scientific method

who also strongly influenced Schaefer and read the proofs of his 1953 paper (Davies, 1972a,
p. 134; L. King, 1979a; Golledge, 1983; see also G. Martin, 1990). These laws were to be embedded
in a theory, thus:

If we are to accept the idea that economic geography is becoming the branch of human
knowledge whose function is to account for the location of economic activities on the various
portions of the earth’s surface, it seems reasonable to expect the discipline to develop a body of
theory to facilitate the performance of this task.
(McCarty, 1954, p. 96)

Such theory could be either topically or areally focused, and in its early stages of development
would probably be restricted, both in its areal coverage and in the topics whose spatial
interrelationships it considered.
The purpose of theory is to provide explanations, of which McCarty recognised two
types. The first involved searching for the causes of observed locational patterns, which ‘can
never produce an adequate body of theory for use in economic geography. . . . Variables
became so numerous that they were not manageable, and, in consequence, solutions to
locational problems were not obtainable’ (p. 96). The second, and preferred, type focuses on
associations:

Its proponents take the pragmatic view that if one knew that two phenomena always appear
together in space and never appear independently, the needs of geographic science would
be satisfied, and there would be scant additional virtue in knowing that the location of one
phenomenon caused the location of another.
(p. 97)

Such laws of association are built up in a series of stages: (1) a statement of the problem and
the necessary operational definitions; (2) measurement of the phenomena (with consideration of
attendant problems of sampling in time and space); and (3) a statement of the findings, in tabular
or graphical form. These three descriptive stages precede analysis which seeks correlations between
distributions:

the nub of the problem of research procedure seems to lie in finding the best techniques for
discovering a, b and c in the ‘where a, b, c, there x’ hypothesis in order to give direction to the
analysis. But where shall we search for its components? . . . One source of . . . clues lies in the
findings of the systematic sciences. The other source lies in the observations of trained workers
in the field or in the library.
(p. 100)

In seeking morphological laws, geography is thus to a considerable extent a consumer of the


laws generated in other disciplines, which may be theoretically rather than empirically derived.
According to the causal or process approach to explanation:

Models may be created showing optimal locations for any type of economic activity for
which adequate cost data may be obtained. These models may then be used (as hypotheses)
for the comparison of hypothetical locations with actual locations. Divergences of pattern
may then be noted and the hypothesis altered to allow for them (often by inclusion
of factors not ordinarily associated with monetary costs). Ultimately the hypothesis
becomes generally applicable and thus takes on the status of a principle.
(McCarty, 1953, p. 184)
Systematic studies and scientific method 67

This statement, although not referenced as such, very faithfully reflects accepted views on
how science progresses by the continual modification of its hypotheses, so as better to represent
reality.
McCarty et al. (1956) discussed several statistical procedures for measuring spatial association
and adopted multiple regression and correlation, used previously among geographers by John
Kerr Rose (1936) and Weaver (1943), both apparently after contacts with agricultural economists.
McCarty’s empirical context was the location patterns of manufacturing industries in the USA
and Japan; other studies by the group included Hook’s (1955) on rural population densities,
Knos’s (1968) on intra-urban land-value patterns, and Leslie King’s (1961) on the spacing of
urban settlements. Edwin N. Thomas (1960) had used similar procedures in his study of population
growth in suburban Chicago, presented as a Ph.D. thesis to Northwestern University (where he was
a contemporary of Garrison); he extended the methodology with a paper on the use of residuals
from regression for identifying where the putative laws of association do not apply fully,
thereby suggesting further hypotheses for areal associations. (This last paper developed on an
earlier one by McCarty, 1952, which was not widely circulated.) McCarty (1958) later expressed
some doubts about the statistical validity of the procedure, but the method that he and his associates
pioneered, with its focus on the testing of simple hypotheses derived either from observation or
from theoretical deductions, became an exemplar for much research in the ensuing decades.

Wisconsin
The Department of Geography at the University of Wisconsin, Madison, had a long tradition of
research with a quantitative bent; its early products included John Weaver’s Ph.D. thesis on the
geography of American barley production, which included a major section – published in his
1943 paper with no supporting methodological argument – using multiple correlation and regres-
sion to identify the influences of climatic variables on barley yields. Weaver later taught at the
University of Minnesota, where he developed a widely adopted statistical procedure for defining
agricultural regions (Weaver, 1954). Other work at Madison focused on the quantitative description
of population patterns (e.g. J. Alexander and Zahorchak, 1943). A combination of these two
interests was furthered by a group led by Arthur H. Robinson, whose main interests were in
cartography; cartographic correlations were introduced to him by his research supervisor at Ohio
State University, Guy-Harold Smith (S. E. Brown, 1978). Robinson also worked with R. A. Bryson,
of the university’s Department of Meteorology, who was a source of statistical ideas and expertise.
(Cartographic work was for a long time called ‘mathematical geography’ by some.)
Robinson, like McCarty, wanted to develop statistical methods for map comparison, as
indicated by the title of an early paper –‘A method for describing quantitatively the correspondence
of geographical distributions’ (Robinson and Bryson, 1957). J. K. Rose and Weaver’s lead was
followed with the adoption of correlation and regression procedures. Particular attention was paid
to the problems of representing areal data by points (Robinson et al., 1961) and of using correlation
methods in comparing isarithmic maps (Robinson, 1962). Two such map types began to appear
more in geographic papers and books in the late 1950s and 1960s: isometric maps, based on a
point-occurring data, such as precipitation and temperature, and isoplethic maps, based on data
occurring over space, especially within geographical areas called spatial units. The latter were
normally represented by rate/ratio variables such as population density and crop yield per acre.
Like McCarty (1958), Robinson, too, was aware of difficulties in applying classical statistical
procedures to areal data, and he proposed a procedure to circumvent one of these (Robinson,
1956). Edwin Thomas and David Anderson (1965) later found this wanting, as it dealt with a
special case only and not with the more general problems. Interestingly, however, the main early
work on this topic was published by a group of Chicago sociologists, under the title Statistical
Geography (Duncan et al., 1961); perhaps even more interestingly, this work was virtually ignored by
68 Systematic studies and scientific method

geographers, even though Brian Berry (1993, p. 439) developed a close working relationship with
Otis Dudley Duncan in the late 1950s and persuaded him to give the book that title.

The social physics school


This group’s work was initiated and developed independently from the other three, and its early
publications preceded Schaefer’s paper by more than a decade. The leader was J. Q. Stewart,
an astronomer at Princeton University who traced the origins of social physics in the work of a
number of natural scientists who applied their methods to social data (Stewart, 1947). His
investigations began when he noted certain regularities in various aspects of distributions that were
akin to the laws of physics, such as a tendency for the number of students attending a university to
decline with increasing distance of their home addresses from its campus. These observations led to
his ideas on social physics, which he defined as:

that the dimensions of society are analogous to the physical dimensions and include numbers of
people, distance, and time. Social physics deals with observations, processes and relations
in these terms. The distinction between it and mathematical statistics is no more difficult to
draw than for certain other phases of physics. The distinction between social physics and
sociology is the avoidance of subjective descriptions in the former.
(Stewart, 1956, p. 245)

Stewart established a laboratory at Princeton to investigate a wide range of such regularities.


Stewart introduced his ideas to geographers through a paper in The Geographical Review (Stewart,
1947). Four empirical rules were adduced:

1 The rank-size rule for cities showed that in the USA the population of a city multiplied by its
rank (from 1 for the largest to n for the smallest) and standardised by a constant, equalled the
population of the largest city, New York (Carroll, 1982).
2 At various dates the number of cities in the country with populations exceeding 2,500 was
very closely related to the proportion of the population living in such places.
3 The distribution of a population could be described by the population potential at a series of
points, in the same manner as the potential in a magnetic field is described in Newtonian
physics.
4 There was a close relationship between this population potential and the density of rural
population in the USA.

From these regularities, Stewart claimed that ‘There is no longer any excuse for anyone to ignore
the fact that human beings, on the average and at least in certain circumstances, obey mathematical
rules resembling in a general way some of the primitive “laws” of physics’ (p. 485). No reasons
were given why this should be so (Curry, 1967, p. 285, called this a ‘deliberate shunning of
plausible argument’); the rules were presented as empirical regularities which had some similarity
to the basic laws of physics. Causal hypotheses were not even postulated, let alone tested.
Stewart’s main collaborator was William Warntz, a graduate of the University of Pennsylvania
who was later employed by the American Geographical Society as a research associate, working on
what he termed ‘the investigation of distance as one of the basic dimensions of society’ (Warntz,
1959a, p. 449; see also Warntz, 1984, where he remarks that he was introduced to Stewart’s ideas
via a book on Coasts,Waves and Weather (Stewart, 1945) that he was reading when working as a weather
observer during the Second World War. The book was ‘prepared primarily to explain to marine and
air navigators the physical environment . . . [but] Stewart could not resist the temptation to include
an exotic chapter describing potential of population and its sociological importance’.) The wide
Systematic studies and scientific method 69

range of empirical regularities which they observed (see Stewart and Warntz, 1958, 1959) was
used to develop their concept of macrogeography (Warntz, 1959a, 1959b). Warntz (1959a)
claimed that geographical work was dominated by micro-studies: ‘The tendency of American geo-
graphers to be preoccupied with the unique, the exceptional, the immediate, the microscopic, the
demonstrably utilitarian, and often the obvious is at once a strength and a weakness’ (p. 447)
because ‘the assembly of more and more area studies involving an increase in the quantity of detail
does not mean per se a shift from the microscopic to the macroscopic’ (p. 449). Geographers were
in danger of being unable to perceive general patterns within their welter of local detail, and to
counter this Stewart and Warntz suggested the search for ‘regularities in the aggregate’.
As examples of that search, Stewart’s concept of population potential was used to describe
general distributions, and was related to a large number of other patterns in the economic and
social geography of the USA. Although these findings were recognised as only empirical regularities,
they could be used as the basis for theory development (Stewart and Warntz, 1958, p. 172):
geography needed theory which, according to Warntz (1959b, p. 58), ‘has as its aim the
establishment and coordination of areal relations among observed phenomena. General laws are
sought that will serve to unify the individual, apparently unique, isolated facts so laboriously
collected’. Their approach to theory was inductive (see Figure 3.1) rather than deductive, although
there was a clear underlying belief in the importance of distance and accessibility as influences on
individual behaviour. The work of German geographer Walther Christaller was key for Warntz as
well as Garrison, Ullman and others (see Bunge, 1968).
These macroscopic measures, particularly population potential, were used in a variety of
contexts, as in Warntz’s (1959c) Toward a Geography of Price, which established strong relationships
between the prices of agricultural commodities in the USA and measures of supply and demand
potential; an early textbook in economic geography (Huntington et al., 1933) included a short
section of geographic variations in the price of and profits from wheat in the USA; and Chauncy
Harris (1954) had used the potential measure in studies of industrial-location patterns, having
been influenced by agricultural economist Colin Clark when he was studying at Oxford, noting that
the measure he adopted from Clark’s work was similar to J. Q. Stewart’s (Harris also acknowledged
help from Garrison and Isard); it was later taken up by a Chicago student (Pred, 1965a). The
‘macrogeographers’ also did much work on various distance-decay functions (see Chapter 4,
p. 101, this book) and extended early Russian work on centrographic measures (Sviatlovsky and
Eels, 1937; Neft, 1966); this was done both at the American Geographical Society (where its
pioneering, mathematical nature ran contrary to the Society’s general research interests) and later,
under Warntz, at the Graduate School of Design’s Laboratory for Computer Graphics and Spatial
Analysis at Harvard University, where it was the forerunner of later developments in computerised
cartography and GIS (see p. 158, this book).
These lines of work contrasted markedly with that of the other three groups reviewed here, in
a variety of ways. First was the issue of scale; Stewart and Warntz perhaps conformed more than any
others to calls for a scientific approach which aimed at a high level of generality. Second, there was
their approach to theory: macrogeography was largely inductive in its search for regularity rather
than testing deductive hypotheses. Finally, the analogies sought for human geography were in a
natural science – physics – and not in the other social sciences.

W. L. Garrison and the Washington school


By far the largest volume of work in the spirit of Schaefer’s and McCarty’s proposals published
during the 1950s came from the University of Washington, Seattle. The group of workers there was
led by W. L. Garrison, whose Ph.D. was from Northwestern University, where he was associated
with Thomas (the two returned to Northwestern in the early 1960s; Taaffe, 1979). According to
Bunge (1966a, p. ix), Garrison had been influenced by Schaefer’s paper, although his earliest
70 Systematic studies and scientific method

ROUTE 2

PERCEPTUAL
EXPERIENCES

negative
feedback IMAGE OF
REAL WORLD
STRUCTURE

A PRIORI
MODEL
(formal
ROUTE 1
representation
of the image]
PERCEPTUAL
EXPERIENCES
HYPOTHESIS
UNORDERED
FACTS
EXPERIMENTAL
DESIGN
DEFINITION (definition,
CLASSIFICATION classification,
MEASUREMENT measurement]

ORDERED DATA
FACTS

VERIFICATION
INDUCTIVE PROCEDURES
GENERALISATION unsuccessful (statistical tests etc)
successful
LAWS AND LAWS AND
THEORY THEORY
CONSTRUCTION CONSTRUCTION positive
feedback

EXPLANATION EXPLANATION

Figure 3.1  Two routes to scientific explanation

Source: Harvey, 1969a, p. 34.

publications indicate that he was applying the proposed methods to systematic studies in human
geography before 1953; his 1950 Ph.D. thesis was on the shopping centres of northern Chicago,
following the exemplar set by Proudfoot’s (1937) work, which identified a hierarchy of five
shopping centre types in a comparative study of several cities (Garrison, 2002). Also involved was
Ullman, who moved to Seattle from the closing department at Harvard in 1951 (he was previously
at Chicago, as was Chauncy Harris: Harris, 1977, 1978, 1990, 1997b). Ullman had already done
pioneering research on urban location patterns and transport geography (see Hay, 1979b; Morrill,
1984). Ullman was strongly critical of regional geography as traditionally practised and committed
to a ‘scientific approach’, as illustrated by a commissioned paper published in 1953. He argued
Systematic studies and scientific method 71

that spatial interaction should be the focus of work in economic geography rather than regional
definition:

Geographers conventionally spend much time mapping the characteristics and use of the land.
This is important to many problems, but sometimes I feel that we do this simply because it is
tangible and distinctive, in fact by now almost instinctive.
(Ullman, 1953, p. 57)

and:

areal differentiation [is] the current catholic definition . . . I cannot accept areal differentiation as
a short definition for outsiders because it implies that we are not seeking principles or
generalizations or similarities, the goal of all science.
(p. 60)

Ullman’s (1959) early work on commodity flows in the USA was seen as ‘mere description’
by the graduate students who went to Seattle to work with him (Morrill, 1978) but his earlier
paper in a relatively obscure source (Ullman, 1954a; see also Ullman, 1954b; Hay, 1979b) provided
a theoretical basis for analysing the observed patterns based on the concepts of complementarity
and intervening opportunities as well as distance (the 1954 papers included references to Zipf and
the gravity model).
Soon after Garrison and Ullman were recruited to Seattle a new chair of the department,
G. Donald Hudson, was appointed from Northwestern. He shifted its emphasis from teaching to
research, focused on four areas – cartography, economic geography, the Far East and the
Soviet Union, and Anglo-America (Velikonja, 1994). He supported the work of Garrison and his
students against some opposition from other colleagues (Berry, 2002a, notes that although Ullman,
as an established name, attracted many of the graduate students to Seattle, most of them chose to
work with the more approachable Garrison, who joined the department just before Ullman went
on leave and undertook his teaching, which included statistical methods). Hudson also worked
hard to place them in other prestigious universities after graduation, thus aiding the spread of their
pioneering ideas (80 MAs and 40 Ph.Ds were completed during his headship – 1950–63). When
Hudson retired, the Washington department was placed fourth in national rankings of graduate
programmes.
Garrison (2002, p. 105) records that a ‘fork in the road’ for him came in 1952 when he held
a visiting post at the University of Pennsylvania. Encounters beyond geography introduced him to
work on the spatial organisation of markets and he decided to take some courses in statistics. He
returned to Washington and recast his course in transportation geography. A large group of graduate
students soon joined him, with several becoming leaders in the new methodology during the
subsequent decade, including B. J. L. Berry, W. Bunge, M. F. Dacey, A. Getis, D. F. Marble, R. L. Morrill,
J. D. Nystuen and W. R. Tobler (Garrison, 1979, 2002). The group also benefited from a 1957 visit
by Leslie Curry, then a climatologist at the University of Auckland but with a background of
studying location theory (Johnston, 2010b) who later switched his interests to spatial theory,
another in 1959 by a Swedish geographer, Torsten Hägerstrand, who was developing methods for
generalising spatial patterns and processes (see p. 107, this book), and from Garrison’s contacts
with the university’s business and engineering schools (Halvorson and Stave, 1978). Berry (1993)
and Getis (1993) both provide accounts of the intellectual activity at Seattle during the mid-1950s:
Getis stresses Donald Hudson’s role, and his ‘inferiority complex that comes from being remote’
(p. 530), which led him to place Washington graduates as faculty members in several of the main
Midwestern graduate schools (such as Chicago, Northwestern and Michigan Universities) in order
to establish his department’s intellectual reputation. This was also facilitated by their access to the
72 Systematic studies and scientific method

department’s reprographic facilities, which allowed them to circulate draft papers very widely
(Velikonja, 1994; Morrill, 2002; Johnston, 2004a).
Garrison and his co-workers had catholic interests in urban and economic geography. Much
of their research was grounded in theory gleaned from other disciplines, notably economics,
although they were much attracted to Christaller’s central place theory, which Bunge (1968,
p. 133) described as ‘geography’s finest intellectual product’. Their efforts were directed towards
both testing those theories and applying them to planning problems. In the former activity they
drew on a much stronger mathematical base than was the case at Iowa and Madison. They also
searched widely for relevant statistical tests for analysing point and line patterns – the biological
sciences provided several, such as nearest-neighbour analysis of point patterns (Dacey, 1962),
whereas others, for grouping, classifying and regionalising, were derived from psychology
(Berry, 1968). Garrison (1956a, p. 429) argued that ‘there is ample evidence that present tools
are adequate to our present state of development. No type of problem has been proposed that
could not be treated with available tools’, which contradicted a claim by Reynolds (1956),
although Garrison (1956b) also criticised some uses of standard techniques. The dominant
thrust of the group’s work therefore involved importing relevant normative theories plus
mathematical methods and statistical procedures from other systematic sciences, with which to
develop morphological laws.
The wealth of the work done at Seattle is illustrated by their major publications. Garrison
(1959a, 1959b, 1960a), for example, contributed a three-part review article on the state of location
theory. The first part reviewed six recent books – none by geographers – addressing the question
‘What determines the spatial arrangement (structure, pattern or location) of economic activity?’
(Garrison, 1959a, p. 232). Each incorporated locational considerations into traditional economic
analysis and offered valuable economic insights to traditional geographical problems.
Central place theory was the dominant location theory on which the group worked, however.
This had several independent origins (Ullman, 1941; see also C. Harris, 1977, and Freeman, 1961,
p. 201, who notes that findings akin to those in central place theory were reported by the 1851
Census Commissioners of Great Britain). Christaller’s (1966) thesis attracted most attention,
however (see Müller-Wille, 1978). Working in Germany in the 1930s, Christaller developed ideas
regarding the ideal distribution of settlements of different sizes acting as the marketing centres of
functional regions, within constraining assumptions relating to the physical environment and the
goals of both entrepreneurs and customers; a translation by C. W. Baskin became available in the late
1950s and was formally published in 1966. Studies of functional regions were not novel, of course
(see p. 51, this book), and other geographers had tested Christaller’s notions regarding a hierarchical
organisation of settlements distributed on a hexagonal lattice (e.g. the work of Brush, 1953, at
Wisconsin). Related, more inductive, work on ‘principles of areal organization’ was reported by
Philbrick (1957). Dacey wanted to make the analysis of these spatial hierarchies more rigorous
mathematically (Dacey, 1962), whereas Berry focused on empirical investigations of the settlement
pattern north of Seattle and the retail centres in the city of Spokane (Berry and Garrison, 1958a,
1958b; Berry, 1959a).
The second part of Garrison’s (1959b) review article dealt with possible geographical
applications of the mathematical procedures of linear programming, which identify optimal
solutions to problems of resource allocation in constrained situations. He illustrated how neoclassical
economic analytic procedures could be adapted for investigations of ideal spatial solutions to six
problems of where to locate economic activities and how to organise flows of goods:

1 The transportation problem, which takes a set of points, some with a given supply of a good
and some with a given demand for it, plus costs of movement, and determines the most
efficient flow pattern of the good from supply to demand points which minimises the
expenditure on transport.
Systematic studies and scientific method 73

2 The spatial price-equilibrium problem, which takes the same information as the transportation
problem, but determines prices as well as flows.
3 The warehouse-location problem, which determines the best location for a set of supply
points, given a geography of demand.
4 The industrial-location problem, which determines the optimum location for factories from
knowledge of the sources of their raw materials and the destinations for their products.
5 The interdependencies problem, which locates linked plants so as to maximise their joint
profits.
6 The boundary-drawing problem, which determines the most efficient set of boundaries
(i.e. that which minimises total expenditure on transport), as with school catchment areas.

If these are used to investigate actual patterns and not as the bases for future plans, the purpose, as
Lösch (1954) put it, is to see whether reality is ‘rational’, whether decision-makers have acted in
ways that would produce the most efficient solutions: efficiency is defined as cost-minimisation,
particularly transport-cost minimisation. Relevant investigations by the Washington group included
studies of interregional trade (Morrill and Garrison, 1960) and the optimal regional location of
agricultural activities in the USA (Garrison and Marble, 1957).
In the final part of his review article, Garrison (1960a) dealt with four further books on loca-
tional analysis, which were empirical in orientation and shared a common interest in the agg-
lomeration economies reaped by industrial clusters. Several topics and techniques were discussed,
such as the use of input–output matrices to represent industrial systems, and Garrison concluded
by stressing the need for geographers to investigate location patterns as systems of interrelated
activities.
The empirical work with a planning orientation undertaken by the Seattle group is illustrated
by their research on the impact of highway developments on land use and other patterns (Garrison
et al., 1959). This book included four studies: Berry’s on the spatial pattern of central places within
urban areas; Marble’s on the residential pattern of the city (as indexed by property values) and
relationships between household characteristics, including location, and their movement patterns;
Nystuen’s on movements by customers to central places; and Morrill’s on the locations of physicians’
offices, both actual and the most efficient. In addition, Garrison worked on the impacts of highway
improvements and devised indices of accessibility based on graph theory (Garrison, 1960b: the
work was continued by Kansky, 1963, after Garrison and Berry moved to the Chicago area). He also
used the simulation procedures developed by Hägerstrand (1968) to investigate urban growth
processes (Garrison, 1962), a topic extended by Morrill (1965).
Somewhat separate from the work of the others in the group, although aligned with their
general purpose, was Bunge’s thesis on Theoretical Geography (1962, reissued in enlarged form in
1966a: see Cox and Macmillan, 2001). This displays a catholic view of geography, together with an
acknowledged debt to Schaefer (Bunge worked at Iowa for a short period, and also at Madison,
where he clashed with Hartshorne). Its basic theme is that geography is the science of spatial
relations and interrelations; geometry is the mathematics of space; hence, geometry is the language
of geography. The early chapters establish geography’s scientific credentials in a debate with
Hartshorne’s published statements, especially those concerning uniqueness and predictability.
Bunge claimed that Hartshorne confused uniqueness and singularity (on which, see P. W. Lewis,
1965); he opposed the claim that geography cannot formulate laws because of its paucity of cases
by arguing for even more general laws, and countered the argument that geographical phenomena
are not predictable with the claim that science ‘does not strive for complete accuracy but
compromises its accuracy for generality’ (1966a, p. 12).
Having established geography’s scientific credibility to his satisfaction, Bunge then investigated
its language. An intriguing discussion of cartography led him to conclude that descriptive
mathematics is preferable to cartography as a more precise language. The remainder of the book
74 Systematic studies and scientific method

looked at aspects of the substantive content of the science of geography, beginning with ‘a general
theory of movement’ and then a chapter on central place theory: ‘If it were not for the existence of
central place theory, it would not be possible to be so emphatic about the existence of a theoretical
geography . . . central place theory is geography’s finest intellectual product’ (1966a, p. 133).
Problems testing the theory suggested the need for map transformations (see also Getis, 1963), and
the final chapter of the first edition clarified the links between geography and geometry: ‘Now that
the science of space is maturing so rapidly, the mathematics of space – geometry – should be
utilised with an efficiency never achieved by other sciences’ (1966a, p. 201). Bunge’s Theoretical
Geography is peppered with maps and geometrical visualisations of spatial relationships.
The richness of the work done by this group during the mid- and late 1950s continued in
various locations after it broke up (only Ullman remained, although Morrill later joined the staff at
Seattle). Berry was one of the most prolific and seminal, not only in his original field of central
place theory (Berry, 1967) but also over a wide range of other topics in economic and social
geography. His work always had a very strong empirical and utilitarian base (Yeates, 2001), whereas
Dacey continued to work on the mathematical representation of spatial, especially point, patterns
(e.g. Dacey, 1973) and Tobler (1995) moved into computer cartography (on Tobler’s background,
see Barnes, 2004c, 2008b). In total, the work of this significant group of scholars influenced the
research and teaching of a whole generation of human geographers throughout the world. In
subsequent decades, the Washington department also provided a major lead in regional economic
analysis. Led by Morgan Thomas, a number of graduate students – some of whom were later
appointed to the Washington faculty – produced innovative work on topics such as growth-pole
theory, regional input–output analysis, and the spatial strategies of firms and corporations, and in
turn several of them became leaders in this area of locational analysis (Velikonja, 1994).
In a series of essays on the history of geography’s ‘quantitative revolution’ in the USA (e.g.
T. Barnes, 2003b, 2004b), Trevor Barnes has associated that shift not only to the experience of
Ackerman, Ullman and others interacting with other social scientists in the Office of Strategic
Services during the Second World War (Barnes, 2006a; Barnes and Farish, 2006), but also to the
Cold War interests of the ‘military-industrial complex’ which focused on the ‘received view’
regarding scientific method and its use of models as ‘instruments to think about the world, and
instruments to alter it’ (Barnes, 2008b, p. 6). The very centre of geographers’ discipline (T. Barnes
used the examples of Garrison, Tobler and geomorphologist Strahler) was ‘displaced, shifted, and
realigned, mangled, in part because of its connections to the military, its connections to the Cold
War’ (p. 15; see, however, Johnston et al.’s, 2008, rejoinder, which points out that the parallel
developments in the UK were not linked to the Cold War and the military-industrial complex).
(Barnes and Minca, 2013, similarly illustrate the Nazi regime’s use of Christaller’s central place
theory to create a replica of the German homeland in the eastern territories captured in the first
years of the Second World War.)

From Seattle and elsewhere to Chicago and further


The developments outlined earlier marked the beginning of major changes in the field of human
geography, which were rapidly taken up by others, within and beyond the USA. Although the focus
was on theory and measurement and the development of ‘geographical laws’, the work did not
deviate too far from Hartshorne’s expanded (1959) definition of the nature of geography (see
p. 62, this book); indeed, in a major programmatic statement, Berry (1964a) used the regional
concept as the core for a revised framework of geographical research. The main difference between
the new work, with its focus on systematic studies, and its regional predecessor was the greater
faith of ‘new geographers’ in their ability to produce laws, to work within the canons of accepted
scientific method, to master and apply relevant mathematical and statistical procedures, and to
move out of their self-imposed academic isolation (Ackerman, 1945, 1963).
Systematic studies and scientific method 75

Diffusion of the new approach was rapid, involving a number of graduates from the four
centres identified, especially Seattle, plus other willing change-agents. Ned Taaffe, for example,
trained in journalism and meteorology and, after experience teaching economics and statistics, was
involved in the development of spatial analysis at Northwestern University (on which, see also
Hanson, 1993) and then moved to Ohio State University ‘with a mandate to build a research
department’. Taaffe had studied urban hinterlands using air traffic data for his Chicago Ph.D. as
exemplars of functional regions and following the stimulus of his mentor, Robert Platt; his
supervisor was Harold Mayer. He then taught economic geography and statistics for four years in
the economics department at Loyola University (Gauthier, 2002), before taking up a joint
appointment with the Department of Geography and the Transportation Center at Northwestern in
1956 (Garrison was appointed to the latter in 1960). The graduate students that Taaffe worked with
(and to whom he promoted the ‘spatial view’ which won converts to geography’s role from other
social sciences;Taaffe, 1974) included, almost contemporaneously with the Washington department,
a number who were to become leaders in the field, such as Emilio Casetti, Ed Conkling, Lawrence
(Larry) Brown, Barry Garner, Howard Gauthier, Peter Gould, Frank Horton, David Reynolds and
Maurice Yeates (Gauthier, 2002, p. 582).
At Ohio State, Taaffe appointed ‘a group of geographers, each of whom influenced the
development of spatial analysis in geography in a somewhat different way’ (Taaffe, 1993, p. 423).
He names Howard Gauthier, Les King, George Demko, Kevin Cox, John Rayner, Emilio Casetti, Larry
Brown, Reg Golledge, John Arnfield and Harold Moellering. Golledge, King – Taaffe’s ‘most
influential appointment’ according to Getis (1993, p. 522) – Rayner and Bill Clark were all at the
University of Canterbury, New Zealand when Harold McCarty was a visiting professor there in
the late 1950s (see the essays in King, 2008). Taaffe was also involved in several summer workshops
conducted at Northwestern University with funding under the National Defense Education Act,
which introduced many other geographers to quantitative methods (Taaffe, 1979, p. 137, lists
some of them).
A further major centre to which the ‘new geography’ was initially transferred, and where a
great deal was accomplished in the 1960s and 1970s, was the University of Chicago, which
Brian Berry joined in 1958. (Indeed, several examples of early Chicago work, much of it inspired
by Robert Platt, Charles Colby and later Chauncy Harris – 1990 – foreshadowed the later
developments.) Already on the staff when Berry arrived were Chauncy Harris, who had published
pioneering papers on location theory and had used macrogeographic ideas in his research
(see p. 68, this book), and Harold Mayer, a leading urban geographer whose collection of
essays (Mayer and Kohn, 1959) was a pioneering early urban text (including in New Zealand,
which Mayer visited in 1961: Clark, 2002) and whose contents Berry lightly influenced
(Berry, 2002a). The research that Berry stimulated (some of it involving staff and students
at nearby Northwestern University) was carried forward by a large number of graduate
students. It focused initially on central place studies, extending his Seattle work, but was
soon expanded into a wide range of studies including the internal structure of cities,
ethnic segregation and housing allocation, and the definition of urban built-up areas and their
functional hinterlands. This work, much of which was undertaken for external sponsors – thus
demonstrating the applied relevance of the ‘new geography’ – was widely cited, and the large
numbers involved became nodes in what Yeates (2001, p. 524) has termed the ‘continental and
global network of professionals’ associated with a further ‘Chicago school’ that very strongly
influenced the development of human geography during that period. That influence
spread beyond the fields of urban and economic geography on which Berry and his students
specialised. Other research groups there were shaped by this, such as Ginsburg’s on patterns of
economic development (Ginsburg, 1961), especially in Asia, and the work by Gilbert White and
his associates (such as Ian Burton, Robert Kates, Thomas Saarinen) on issues of resource
management (see p. 126, this book).
76 Systematic studies and scientific method

Other centres were soon established. Two Washington graduates – John Nystuen and Waldo
Tobler – were appointed to the University of Michigan at Ann Arbor, for example, and William
Bunge to Wayne State University in Detroit. Together with others at Michigan State University, they
established an informal inter-university seminar group which met at a tavern midway between the
three centres at which they and invited visitors gave papers. Several of these were ‘published’ as the
Michigan Inter-University Community of Mathematical Geographers (MICMOG) discussion
papers, which were widely circulated, and which Tobler (2002, p. 309) reports were critical in
attracting Gunnar Olsson to Michigan. Their publication was halted when the journal Geographical
Analysis was founded, but several of them (such as Gould’s original paper on mental maps –
see p. 129, this book) had by then become influential ‘mini-classics’.
The role of certain individuals and institutions in the promotion of change was thus crucial
(on which, see the exchange between Morrill and Johnston: Morrill, 1993, 1994; Johnston,
1994c). Their publications influenced geographers, especially young geographers, around the
world (Adams, 2002; Clark, 2002). The work that they promoted succeeded, according to Berry
(2002a, p. 561), because (1) it was scientifically conducted, and thus replicable; (2) theory was
continually being improved, through the interplay of speculation and empirical analysis; (3) it was
multidisciplinary; and (4) it was continually applied, creating a successful tension between theory
and practice – to the benefit of both. They didn’t ‘take over’ the discipline – as James Wheeler’s
(2002a) analysis of articles published in major journals during the 1960s shows – but they were
highly influential in setting its research and training agenda for several decades.

Scientific method in human geography

A sense of a revolution?
The changes just described heralded a potential major reorientation in the nature of much
geographical research. This was not focused on any single blueprint, grand design or programmatic
statement, however. No paper or book published in either the 1950s or the early to mid-1960s
provided either a philosophy for the new approach or detailed how research should be conducted
within that framework. Schaefer’s paper said nothing about how geographical laws were to be
derived, and although McCarty and his co-workers discussed methods in both general (McCarty,
1954) and specific (McCarty et al., 1956) contexts, they provided no programmatic statement for
how the discipline should be practised. This exemplifies what Derek Gregory (1978a, p. 47) notes,
that ‘geography has (with some notable exceptions) paid scant attention to its epistemological
foundations’. Livingstone (1992, p. 328) suggests that ‘Geography’s confrontation with the
vocabulary of logical positivism [in the 1950s] . . . was a post hoc means of rationalizing its attempt
to reconstitute itself as spatial science’. What was promoted was very largely a technical revolution
which only later sought philosophical legitimation.
One piece postdating many of the early essays, but which was then widely quoted in the 1960s
as the new ideas spread, was Ackerman’s (1958) essay on Geography as a Fundamental Research Discipline.
This was mainly an analysis of research organisation. He argued that the ultimate goal must be
interdisciplinary integration, and that ‘If any one theme may be used to characterise this period,
that theme would be one of illuminating covariant relations among earth features’ (p. 7). As a
science, even one which is eventually an idiographic science since it deals with unique places,
geography, according to Ackerman, needed to strive for ‘an increasingly nomothetic component’.
Its fundamental research

need not necessarily be law-giving . . . Much fundamental research in geography has not been
law-giving in the strict sense but it has been concerned with a high level of generalization, and it
Systematic studies and scientific method 77

has given meaning to other research efforts which succeeded it. In this sense it has a block-
building characteristic.
(p. 17)

Such fundamental research ‘is likely to rest on quantification . . . accurate study depends on
quantification’ (p. 30) and should ‘furnish a theoretical framework with capacity to illuminate
actually observed distributional patterns and space relations’ (p. 28).
Ackerman issued a clarion call for theory development, the application of quantitative
methods and a focus on laws and generalisations to form the building-blocks for further nomothetic
research. But his essay lacked any detailed discussion of how such research should be undertaken.
Seven years later, a report of a National Academy of Sciences-National Research Council (NAS-NRC,
1965, p.1) committee on The Science of Geography set out ‘geography’s problem and method’ in the
statement that

Geographers believe that correlations of spatial distributions, considered both statistically and
dynamically, may be the most ready keys to understanding existing or developing life systems,
social systems, or environmental changes. In the past . . . progress was gradual, however,
because geographers were few, rigorous methods for analysing multivariate problems and
systems concepts were developed only recently.
(p. 9)

This, too, was a general statement on research orientation with no accompanying detail on
research procedures. And yet a paper published in 1963 had claimed that an intellectual revolution
– the quantitative and theoretical revolution – had been completed in geography: ‘The revolution is
over, in that once-revolutionary ideas are now conventional’ (Burton, 1963, p. 156). Something
had become conventional, but nobody had yet written a full formulation for the discipline of what
that something was. The groups of researchers who proposed changes in the nature of human
geography undoubtedly had a clear, if implicit, rationale for their arguments, but these were not yet
discussed in detail in print. If their citations in the published works are any lead, many did not
research deeply into the philosophy that they were adopting (though a few, such as Peter Gould,
regularly attended courses in philosophy throughout their subsequent careers: see Gould, 1999).
The exceptions are the references to Bergmann in the Iowa group’s papers (see Golledge, 1983) and
in Bunge’s (1962) thesis. Texts on statistical and mathematical procedures were widely quoted and,
although many relied on those written for other disciplines (e.g. Blalock, 1960; Krumbein and
Graybill, 1965; Garrison worked with Krumbein at Northwestern in the 1960s: Garrison, 2002,
p. 110), several were produced by and for geographers (e.g. S. Gregory, 1963; L. King, 1969b). But
there was very little discussion of either epistemology – the theory of what constitutes valid
knowledge – or of ontology – the theory of what can be known; these were largely ignored (or
considered ‘common sense’) and instead the emphasis was on methods.

Explanation in geography
The first major work on the philosophy of the ‘new geography’ was not published until 1969, by a
British geographer (who moved to the USA at about the time his book, entitled Explanation in
Geography, appeared), based on several years teaching the epistemology and ontology of science to
geography undergraduates at the University of Bristol in order to give a philosophical foundation
to the technical procedures (Harvey, 1969a; a parallel, but briefer, statement is Moss, 1970).
(On Harvey’s early work, see Gregory, 2006, and Barnes, 2006b.)
Harvey identified two routes to explanation (Figure 3.1). The first, the ‘Baconian’ or inductive
route, derives generalisations from observations: a pattern is observed and an explanation developed
78 Systematic studies and scientific method

from and for it. This involves a dangerous form of generalising from the particular case, however,
because acceptance of the interpretations depends too much on the unproven representativeness of
the case(s) discussed and, perhaps, the charisma of the scholar involved (Moss, 1970). Thus, the
second route in Figure 3.1 is much preferred (though see Bennett, 1985a and T. Barnes, 1996). This
also begins with observers perceiving patterns in the world; they then formulate experiments, or
some other kind of test, to test the veracity of the explanations offered for those patterns. Only
when ideas have been tested successfully against data other than those from which they were
derived can a generalisation be produced.
Scientific knowledge obtained via the second route is ‘a kind of controlled speculation’ (Harvey,
1969a, p. 85). Its philosophy, known as positivism, was developed by a group of philosophers
working in Vienna during the 1920s and 1930s based on procedures developed a century earlier in
France (Gregory, 1978a; Guelke, 1978). It is based on a conception of an objective world in which
there is order waiting to be discovered. Because that order exists – spatial patterns of variation and
co-variation in the case of geography – it cannot be contaminated by the observer (a position
known as empiricist). A neutral observer, acting on personal observations or reading others’
research reports, will derive a hypothesis (a speculative law) about some aspect of reality and then
test it; verification of the hypothesis translates the speculative law into an accepted one. (For a more
nuanced discussion of the search for order, see Symanski and Agnew, 1981.)
A key tenet of this philosophy is that laws must be proven through objective and replicable
procedures: ‘the plausibility or intuitive reality of a theory is not a valid basis for judging a theory’
(Bunge, 1962, p. 3). A valid law must predict successfully, so that having developed an idea about
certain patterns the researcher must formulate it into a testable hypothesis – ‘a proposition whose
truth or falsity is capable of being asserted’ (Harvey, 1969a, p. 100) – for which an experiment can
be designed. Data are then collected and the hypothesis’s validity evaluated. If the test results do not
match the predictions, then either the observations on which the hypothesis was derived or the
deductions on which it was based are thrown into doubt. There is thus negative feedback (Figure
3.1) and the image of the world has to be revised, creating a new hypothesis.
According to Harvey (1969a, p. 105):

A scientific law may be interpreted as a generalization which is empirically universally true, and
one which is also an integral part of a theoretical system in which we have supreme confidence.
Such a rigid interpretation would probably mean that scientific laws would be non-existent in
all of the sciences. Scientists therefore relax their criteria to some degree in their practical
application of the term.

After sufficient (undefined) successful tests, therefore, a hypothesis may be accorded lawlike
status, and fed into a body of theory, which comprises a series of related laws. There are two types
of statement within a full theory: the axioms, or givens – statements that are taken to be true,
such as laws; and the deductions, or theorems, from those initial conditions, which are
derived consequences from agreed facts – the next round of hypotheses. There is a positive feedback
from the theory stage to the world view, therefore (Figure 3.1), so that the whole scientific
enterprise is a cyclical procedure whereby the successes of one set of experiments become the
building blocks for thinking about the next. (Haggett, 1965c, had already used this argument in his
pioneering textbook.)
One stage in Figure 3.1 so far ignored is the model, a widely used term with a variety of
meanings (Chorley, 1964). Models have two basic functions: as representations of the real world,
such as a scale model, a map, a series of equations and some other analogue (Morgan, 1967); and
as ideal types, representations of the world under certain constrained conditions. Both are
used in the positivist method to operationalise a theory as a guide to the derivation of testable
hypotheses.
Systematic studies and scientific method 79

Quantification is central to this scientific method. Mathematics is particularly useful in


developing models, as in the linear programming procedures discussed by Garrison. Relatively few
geographers had strong backgrounds in mathematics, however (this was especially true in the
1950s), so little work involved representing the real world as sets of equations. Instead, the
central role was given to statistics. Two types of statistics are available: descriptive statistics
represent a pattern or relationship; inductive statistics are used for making generalisations
about a carefully defined population from a properly selected random sample. They use the same
procedures; the difference lies in how they are deployed. Many geographical researchers confused
the two. Inductive statistics employ significance tests to show whether what has been observed in
the sample probably also occurs in the parent population, so that if the data analysed are not a
sample, such tests are irrelevant (some disagreement was expressed over ‘what is a sample?’ – see
Meyer, 1972, and Court, 1972 – and debates continue: see Johnston et al., 2014a). Many geographers
use inductive methods in a descriptive manner only, however, using the significance tests as
measures of the validity of their findings, asking what is the likelihood of a relationship that they
have discovered arising by chance given the dataset’s contents (as argued in Hay, 1985b).
The main attraction of statistics to many early adherents of the ‘new geography’ was their
precision and lack of ambiguity – compared to the English language – in description. This was
expressed by Cole (1969), who annotated a quotation from a well-known textbook, The British Isles,
in which the text is Stamp and Beaver’s (1947, pp. 164–5) and the annotations in parentheses, to
show the ambiguities, are Cole’s:

The present distribution of wheat cultivation in the British Isles (space) raises the conception of
two different types of limit. Broadly speaking (vague), it may be said that the possible (vague)
limits (limit) of cultivation of any crop are determined by geographical (vague), primarily by
climatic conditions. The limits so determined (how?) may be described (definition) as the
ultimate (vague) or the geographical (vague) limits.
(p. 160)

Cole argued that the full quotation (only part is reproduced here) is so full of ambiguities that it
could refer to about one million possible combinations of some forty counties and it is impossible
to reconstruct a map from that description:

the correlations suggested are so tentative and imprecise that they leave the reader still
wondering why wheat is grown where it is. The application of a standard correlation procedure
. . . in itself would give a more precise appreciation of the relationship.
(p. 162)

Similar views became widely held during the 1960s, and quantification became the sine qua
non of training in research methods (LaValle et al., 1967). But they were only a means to the end,
as Gould (1979, p. 140) expressed in a later retrospective:

It was not the numbers that were important, but a whole new way of looking at things geographic
that can be summed up in Whitehead’s definition of scientific thought, ‘To see what is general in
what is particular and what is permanent in what is transitory.’

The scientific method increasingly adopted by geographers was a procedure for testing ideas,
therefore, but a highly formalised one, about which there has been a great deal of debate among
philosophers of science and others (Harvey, 1969a). Although many aspects of the method were
used by geographers, their citations indicate relatively little training or exploration in depth into the
full philosophy of positivism which, as used here, refers to what is often known as ‘scientific
80 Systematic studies and scientific method

method’. It is embraced by the philosophy of logical positivism, which claims that only scientifically
obtained knowledge is valid knowledge (Johnston, 1986a, 1986b).
An alternative to positivism is critical rationalism, a view of science associated with the
philosopher Karl Popper. He argued that any hypothesis can be found wanting by a single
falsification. Harvey (1969a, p. 39) gave only eight lines to this approach, however, preferring to
argue that only ‘severe failure’– which he does not define – discredits a hypothesis totally (see,
however, Moss, 1977; Bird, 1975; Petch and Haines-Young, 1980; Haines-Young and Petch, 1985).
Hay (1985a), Marshall (1985) and James Bird (1989) all present cases for human geography
adopting Popper’s critical rationalism. The goal is the same as in positivism – to develop
comprehensive theories which allow predictions with high degrees of certainty. The two differ on
means, not ends. Critical rationalists believe that hypotheses can never be comprehensively verified,
only falsified. If the researcher is a good observer and a logical thinker, falsification of hypotheses
should be rare. If the test is successful, then the speculation in the hypothesis becomes an acceptable
generalisation. One successful test will not turn it into a universal law, however, since, according to
Popper, all knowledge is provisional, subject to continued testing through critical experiments
(Symanski and Agnew, 1981). Knowledge accumulates through the falsification of invalid
hypotheses.

Reactions to scientific method


Despite (or perhaps because of) the lack of a clear programmatic statement of the ‘new Theology’
(Stamp, 1966, p. 18), at least until the appearance of Harvey’s (1969a) book, reactions to the
developments were many and varied. (James, 1965, p. 35, called the debate ‘continued, bitter and
uncompromising warfare’.) Two related issues were the main foci of contention: whether
quantification was sensible in geographical research, and whether law-making was possible. As
Peter Taylor (1976) points out, to some extent the debate was intergenerational: some of the ‘old
guard’ thought the proposals were just not geography and should be banished to another corner of
academia.
The quantification issue was the less important and few spoke out against it entirely, although
its extent was criticised. Spate (1960a, p. 387) recognised quantification as ‘an essential element’:

This is, like it or not, the Quantified Age. The stance of King Canute is not very helpful or realistic;
better to ride the waves, if one has sufficient finesse, than to stake attitudes of humanistic
defiance and end, in Toynbee’s phrase, in the dustbin of history.
(p. 391)

He identified three dangers, however.The first was a confusion of ends and means; some protagonists
wanted to quantify everything (after Lord Kelvin, ‘when you cannot express it in numbers, your
knowledge is of a meagre and unsatisfactory kind’: Spate, 1960b), but some things, like the
positions of Madrid and Barcelona in Spanish thought, cannot be treated in that way. Second, there
was the dogged analysis of trivia, producing platitudinous findings, a fault which Spate recognised
as part of all academia, and especially its revolutions: ‘Quantified or not, the trivial we will always
have with us’ (Spate, 1960a, p. 389), and the problem is usually the extreme positions taken up –
Arthur H. Robinson’s (1961) perks (the hyperquantifiers) and pokes (the hypoquantifiers). Finally,
there was the quantifiers’ vaunting ambition and belief that solution of the world’s problems lay
just around the corner.
Spate was more generous than many critics. Burton (1963) identified five types of criticism:

1 geography was being led in the wrong direction;


2 geographers should stick with their proven tool – the map;
Systematic studies and scientific method 81

3 quantification was suitable for certain tasks only;


4 means were being elevated over ends, with too much research on methods for methods’ sake;
and
5 objections were not to quantification per se but to the quantifiers’ attitudes.

He believed that quantification had already proved more than a fad or fashion, however. Geography
would soon proceed beyond a stage of testing relatively trivial hypotheses with its new tools so that
‘The development of theoretical, model-building geography is likely to be the major consequence
of the quantitative revolution’ (p. 156).
One episode regarding the reaction to quantification concerns Stamp’s response to Haggett’s
(1964) early paper on land use change in Brazil: Stamp suggested that Haggett’s quantitative anal-
ysis could be likened to using ‘an enormous steam hammer . . . in the cracking of nuts’. These
comments are included in the published record of the discussion of Haggett’s paper (Haggett,
1964, p. 380) and end with an exclamation mark, with the implication that these may not have
been Stamp’s own views, though his call for those using quantitative techniques to ‘tear up some of
their results’ suggests a negative attitude to at least some of the ‘new lines of thought’. Haggett had
defended his approach – prior to Stamp’s summing-up – by noting that ‘While method has loomed
large in this paper I hope that it has not blotted out the fact that . . . traditional problems of forest
depletion are reaching critical levels. Statistical analysis can help to clarify some of the problems
and provide some checks on intuitive solutions’ (p. 380). It is also recorded that a few days
after the paper was given, Haggett was told by the head of department at Cambridge that he was
‘bringing the subject of geography into disrepute by applying such mathematical methods’
(Chorley, 1995, p. 360).
More critical to many geographers than quantification was the issue of theory, and in particular
the role of laws in geography. For some, this continued the debate over environmental determinism,
which was still active in the UK (Clark, 1950; Martin, 1951; Montefiore and Williams, 1955; Jones,
1956; see Johnston, 2008). Emrys Jones, for example, extended the debate to cover scientific deter-
minism and its implications for human free will. Martin (1951, p. 6) had argued that possibilism
is ‘not merely wrong but is mischievous’ because all human actions are determined in some way,
so that in human geography:

Unless we can assume the existence of laws or necessary conditions similar in stringency to
those of physical science, there can be no human geography nor social sciences worth the name,
but only a series of unexplainable statements of bare events. . . . such laws cannot differ, except
in respect of . . . far greater complication, from those of physical science.
(pp. 9–10)

Emrys Jones (1956) indicated the impossibility of discovering universal laws about human
behaviour and pointed to the use of two types of law in physics: the determinate laws of classical
physics, which apply macroscopically, and the probabilistic quantum laws, which refer to the
behaviour of individual particles. The latter allow for the exercise of free will within prescribed
constraints, and their application in human geography would at least allow answers to be offered to
the question ‘how?’ if not to ‘why?’. But the question of causality clearly worried many, as indicated
by Peter Lewis’s (1965) counter-argument that ‘it is erroneously assumed that causes compel their
effects in some way in which effects do not compel their causes’ (p. 26).
Golledge and Amedeo (1968, p. 760) addressed this same problem, pointing out that critics
of law-seeking in human geography defined a law as a universal postulate which brooked of no
exception: ‘not all are aware [even among those who accept the nomothetic goal] of the nature,
types, and relationships of scientific laws developed by philosophers of science’. Scientists use
several types of law, however, and the veracity of a lawlike statement can never be finally proven,
82 Systematic studies and scientific method

since it cannot be tested against all instances, at all times and in all places. Four types were identified
with relevance for human geographers:

1 Cross-sectional laws describe functional relationships (as between two maps) but show no
causal connection, although they may suggest one.
2 Equilibrium laws state what will be observed if certain criteria are met.
3 Dynamic laws incorporate notions of change, with the alteration in one variable being followed
by (and perhaps causing) an alteration in another. They may be either historical – for example,
showing that B would have been preceded by A and followed by C, or developmental, in which
B would be followed by C, D, E, etc.
4 Statistical laws are probabilistic statements of the likelihood of B happening, given that A exists;
all laws of the other three categories may be either deterministic or statistical, with the latter
almost certainly the case with phenomena studied by geographers.

Having illustrated all four types, they concluded with regard to the existence of situations where
laws seem not to fit that ‘the idea of laws being strict universals no longer dominates in the
interpretation of the concept’ (p. 774); the goal is to advance knowledge by continually reassessing
the validity of assumed laws.
This discussion was not part of an ongoing, published, debate on quantification and theory-
building; it was a reaction to widely held and discussed attitudes rather than to published critiques.
There were none for several years in the UK, for example (Taylor, 1976), but there was one debate
in the American literature, initiated by Lukermann’s (1958) reaction to Warntz’s views on
macrogeography (see p. 68, this book) and a paper by Ballabon (1957). The latter claimed that
economic geography lacked general principles; it was ‘short on theory and long on facts’ (p. 218).
Ballabon stressed the utility of location theory being developed by economists as a source for
hypotheses. Lukermann responded that the main problem in Ballabon’s and Warntz’s arguments lay
in the assumptions behind their hypotheses (Warntz’s analogies with physics and Ballabon’s with
economics) which did not conform to his view of geography as an empirical science. Statistical
regularities and isomorphisms with other subject matter do not provide explanations, so that
hypotheses derived from such models test only the models themselves and (Lukermann, 1958,
p. 9; see also Moss, 1970) ‘the hypotheses to be tested are neither statistically nor rationally derived;
that is, they are derived neither from empirical observation nor from deductions of previous
knowledge in the social, economic or geographic fields’.
Berry (1959b) countered with the contention that models, for all their simplifications and
unreal assumptions, offer insights towards understanding the real world: ‘A theory or model, when
tested and validated, provides a miniature of reality and therefore a key to many descriptions. There
is a single master-key instead of the loaded key ring’ (p. 12). Lukermann (1960a) was not convinced
that models based on assumptions of perfect knowledge and competition, for example, could help
towards understanding if they were not empirically derived: ‘the crucial problem is the construc-
tion of hypotheses from the empirical realities of economic geography . . . more light is shed and
less truth is sophisticated through inventory than through hunches’ (p. 2). Leslie King (1960)
claimed that all laws are really only hypotheses and that deviation of observed from expected values
in their testing indicate where the assumptions are invalid. Lukermann responded three times. The
first paper showed the lack of consensus in ‘explanations’ of the geography of cement production
in the USA (Lukermann, 1960b) because economic analyses ignored ‘Historical inertia, geograph-
ical momentum, and the human condition’ (p. 5). Second, in response to King, he presaged some
of the arguments developed later by Sack, who worked with him at Minnesota (see p. 121, this
book), and pointed out that much of the theory being introduced to economic geography (such as
Lösch’s) was not based on providing understanding of, and explanation for, reality (Lukermann,
1961). Finally, a discussion of several aspects of the debate concluded with the statement that:
Systematic studies and scientific method 83

Thus, we see scientific explanation as far removed from the context within which the macroscopic
geographers would have us put it – the end product of geographic research. Science does not
explain reality, it explains the consequences of its hypotheses.
(Lukermann, 1965, p. 194)

He called for explanations in geography to be based on observations and not on imported analogies
which cannot offer explanations, only unreal assumptions. Lukermann’s basic point, never fully
tackled by his critics, was that tests showing conformity between empirical reality and a model
were tests of the model only, and could not indicate how empirical reality was created if the
assumptions on which the model was constructed were not themselves grounded in reality.
(See T. Barnes, 1996, Chapter 9, for an evaluation of Lukermann’s work.)
This difference of opinion was over the way in which geographers should seek explanations
and not about the positivist scientific method itself; it was concerned with the inputs to the images
of the real-world structure (Figure 3.1). It is doubtful whether papers such as those of Jones, Lewis,
and Golledge and Amedeo quieted the fears of others unconvinced by the quantifiers’ arguments,
any more than Berry and King convinced Lukermann. But the differences soon became a non-issue,
at least in the published papers resulting from the research activities of geographers in many topical
specialisms. As Burton claimed, by the mid-1960s the changes seem to have been widely accepted,
and the regional approach had certainly been ousted from its prime position in the publications of
American human geographers (see J. Wheeler, 2002a). Increasingly, quantitative and theoretical
material came to dominate not only the more obvious journals, such as Geographical Analysis (a ‘journal
of theoretical geography’ founded in 1969, to a considerable extent because those adopting the
new approach found difficulty in getting their work accepted by the established journals:
Berry, 1993; Barnes, 2001b), but also the prestigious general journals, notably Economic Geography
(especially after a change of editor) and the Annals of the Association of American Geographers. (The Geographical
Review was an early partial ‘convert’ through the American Geographical Society’s sponsorship of the
macrogeographers, although Berry states that it rejected his early papers with Garrison as ‘not
geography’: Halvorson and Stave, 1978; Berry, 1993; Barnes, 2001b.) Most of the work contributed
little to theory, however. It was quantitative testing of theory- or model-derived hypotheses in some
cases, but with little indication of how good the results were. In others, it was quantitative
description that could inform theory and model development, but in itself was merely a series of
‘factual reports’. By the 1970s, textbooks were being published which began with discussions of
scientific method and quantification before proceeding to the substantive content of the ‘empirical
science’ (Abler et al., 1971; Amedeo and Golledge, 1975); the ‘revolution’ was apparently becoming
the orthodoxy.

Spread of the scientific method


The initial development of systematic studies using the positivist scientific method in the USA was
very largely focused on economic geography and associated economic aspects of urban geography.
This reflects the relative sophistication of economics within the social sciences at that time and the
existence of several approaches to ‘location theory’ (see p. 72), providing models for geographers
to emulate, not only to advance their discipline but also to promote its cause in the search for utility
to the worlds of business and government. The long tradition of empirical work in human
geography meant, however, that with few exceptions research in the systematic areas mainly
comprised the statistical testing of relatively simple hypotheses, with little mathematical modelling
or writing of formal theory.
Contemporaneous with, and an important stimulus to, these developments in human
geography was the emergence of a new discipline in the USA – regional science (see Berry, 1995,
on regional science as a stimulus). This was very much the product of one iconoclast scholar
84 Systematic studies and scientific method

– Walter Isard, an economist who built spatial components into his models to provide a stronger
theoretical basis for urban and regional planning than had existed previously. In general terms,
regional science is economics with a spatial emphasis, as illustrated by Isard’s (1956a, 1960) two
early texts, but the Regional Science Association attracted relatively more practising geographers
than economists. To some, regional science and economic geography are hard to distinguish: the
former can be separately characterised by its greater focus on mathematical modelling and economic
theorising, however, whereas geographical work has remained more empirical and less dependent
on formal languages. (Initially Isard, 1956b, saw geographers as doing the empirical tests of the
regional scientists’ models.) Over time, the interests of regional scientists broadened (Isard, 1975),
but the strong theoretical base has remained. (The history of regional science, forty years after the
foundation of the Regional Science Association, is discussed in two issues – volume 17, numbers 2
and 3, 1995 – of the International Regional Science Review; see, in particular, Isserman, 1995. Subsequently,
Isard, 2003, published his own history; see also Donaghy, 2014.)
The nascent discipline did not create a substantial niche within American academia, however.
(Garrison, 1995, likened it to Moses’ forty years wandering in the wilderness!) Nor did it have a
lasting, substantial impact on geography and geographers, although the latter remain a considerable
proportion of the association’s membership. Berry (1995) argues that, for him, relative disillusion
with regional science was engendered by Isard’s categorisation of geographers as the empirical
workers who tested the regional scientists’ theories, which implied a subservient position for
geographers in a two-class academic society and would hinder the reformation of economic
geography that Berry sought. (This has an interesting parallel to the debates within geography on
the division of labour between ‘theorisers’ and ‘empirical testers’.)
The Regional Science Association has flourished internationally, however, and Isserman (1995,
p. 261) claims that, ‘Regional science has become a mainstream group within geography and
geography departments . . . [and] . . . so successful within geography that it became worthy of
caricature.’ He then notes major tensions between those geographers who remain committed to the
goals of regional science (almost certainly a relatively small number within the profession) and
those whose interests lie elsewhere. Warf (1995, p. 192) points to these – ‘Class and gender,
historical sensitivity, the politics of the state, the recovery of the living subject and everyday life, the
unintended reproduction of social worlds’ – and invites a rapprochement between regional science
and a geography inspired by what is now known as social theory. (Interestingly, the 1990s saw the
recreation of a form of spatial economics – termed ‘new economic geography’ by its adherents –
that has many parallels to regional science; on its relationships with geography, see Barnes, 2003a;
Martin, 1999; Schoenberger, 2001; Clark et al., 2000; and Bosker et al., 2010; a recent text in the
field is Brakman et al., 2009.)
The emphasis on statistical methods in so much of the new work in American human
geography led to its partial rapprochement with physical geography. (Several of the leading
‘quantitative geographers’ of the 1960s were introduced to the approach during their wartime
training, as essays in Gould and Pitts, 2002, illustrate.) More physical geography papers were
published in the leading journals, more physical geographers were appointed to university
departments, geologists such as Krumbein, Leopold, Schumm and Wolman were major sources
of quantitative ideas, and there was a common interest in the training of graduate students (LaValle
et al., 1967).This shared concern over procedures was illustrated at a 1960 conference on quantitative
geography, which resulted in two volumes on methodological developments, one for human
geography and the other for physical geography (Garrison and Marble, 1967a, 1967b). Other
conferences and summer schools to train geographers in quantitative techniques were held at this
time (on their impact, see Gould, 1969; Taaffe, 1979), and American geographers were to the
forefront in launching an International Geographical Union Commission on Quantitative Methods.
Nevertheless, the rapprochement was far from full, as Marcus (1979, p. 522), himself a physical
geographer, complained in his presidential address to the AAG which was given just after the
Systematic studies and scientific method 85

appearance of a special issue of the Annals to commemorate seventy-five years of American


geography: ‘not one article [of 30 in the issue] focused on physical geography, its roots, its
evolution, its practitioners’ (even though 42 per cent of all students enrolled in geography courses
at USA universities were studying physical geography and thirty-five of the AAG’s presidents had
been practising physical geographers at the time that they held the post). There was a need for
greater awareness and cooperation, with much hard work in order to generate a ‘rational geography
that fulfils the promise we hold for the study of earth and humankind together’ (p. 532).

The quantitative revolution and geography’s position in the academic


division of labour
The launch of the ‘quantitative and theoretical revolutions’ identified by Burton (1963) was
concentrated on a few topical specialisms within American human geography only, so an early task
for the ‘revolutionaries’ was to spread their ideas through the discipline, convincing others of the
benefits which quantification and the associated scientific method could bring to their special
interests. A major piece of advocacy was the NAS-NRC (1965) report on The Science of Geography which
was prepared in order to chart research priorities within the discipline and establish a place for
geography as a social science within the American National Academy (Johnston, 2000b). The case
was presented for more ‘theoretical-deductive’ work to balance the earlier emphasis on ‘empirical
inductive analysis’, the detailed argument being based on four premises:

(a) Scientific progress and social progress are closely correlated, if not equated. (b) Full
understanding of the world-wide system comprising man and his natural environment is one of
the four or five great overriding problems in all science. (c) The social need for knowledge of
space relations of man and natural environment rises, not declines, as the world becomes more
settled and more complex, and may reach a crisis stage in the near future. Last, (d) progress in
any branch of science concerns all branches, because science as a whole is epigenetic. The
social need for knowledge of space relations means an imminent practical need. As the
population density rises and the land-use intensity increases, the need for efficient management
of space will become even more urgent.
(NAS-NRC, 1965, p. 10)

The committee members (E. A. Ackerman, B. J. L. Berry, R. A. Bryson, S. B. Cohen, E. J. Taaffe,


W. L. Thomas Jr and M. G. Wolman) defined geography as ‘the study of spatial distributions on the
earth’s surface’ (p. 8) so it followed for them that, ‘Geographic studies will be irreplaceable
components of the scientific support for efficient space management’ (p. 10). The positivist
scientific method was being sold to geographers and at the same time geography was being sold to
the scientific establishment as a positivist science, from whom financial research support could then
be sought. (Until that time, geography had little access to major funding sources for large research
programmes, though the Office of Naval Research – surprisingly, given its title – did provide some:
Pruitt, 1979.)
The committee chose four problem areas to illustrate geography’s potentials as a ‘useful
science’. The first was physical geography. The second was cultural geography, which studies
‘differences from place to place in the ways of life of human communities and their creation of
man-made or modified features’ (p. 23), with a major focus on landscape development and the
diffusion of specific cultural features over space and time: ‘applying modern techniques to studying
the nature and rate of diffusion of key cultural elements and establishing the evolving spatial
patterns of culture complexes’ (p. 24) was identified as a profitable avenue for development. The
third was political geography, with proposed work on boundaries and resource management.
Finally, the committee recognised location theory studies, an amalgam of work in economic, urban
86 Systematic studies and scientific method

and transport geography in which the ‘dialogue’ between the empirical and the theoretical had
gone furthest, ‘revealing the potential power of a balanced approach when applied to other
geographical problem areas’ (p. 44). Location theory involved work on spatial patterns, the links
and flows between places in such patterns, the dynamics of the patterns, and the preparation of
alternative patterns through model-building exercises which identify efficient solutions.
In the development of the science of geography:

A major opportunity seen by workers in the location theory problem area is that of integrating
their work more closely with other geographers as they begin to deal with spatial systems of
political, cultural, and physical phenomena. . . . This could be achieved . . . by the accelerated
diffusion of techniques and concepts to other geographers, and communication on the definition
of research problems. The result would be to hasten the confrontation of empirical-inductive
studies by theoretical-deductive approaches throughout geography. . . . Testing the theory in a
variety of empirical contexts should aid in the overall development and refinement of viable
theories. It should also serve to connect geographic progress to local problems more rapidly and
more effectively.
(pp. 50–1)

The deductive-theoretical scientific methodology was central to the committee’s blueprint for the
advancement of geographical research, therefore. All geographers would have a role to play in this
movement forward, for:

Geographers have one other asset that should be capitalized on. Those who have been interested
in the study of a specific part of the earth (regional geography) develop competences for
interpreting the physical-cultural complexes of the regions that they study. Students of the way
a particular part of the earth has evolved (historical geography) have other competences for
interpreting the historical development and modification of a region. These two groups have
students that are particularly qualified to undertake the field observation and field study of
problems recognized in a more systematic way and to conduct field tests of generalizations
arrived at through systematic study. . . . The regional or historical geography specialist who has
mastered the technique of field observation and historical study thoroughly . . . can make himself
indispensable if he understands the direction in which the generalizing clusters are headed and
relates his work closely to their growing edges.
(p. 61)

A clear division of labour was being suggested, comprising theoretical-deductive ‘thinkers’


and empirical-inductive ‘workers’, a division which was apparently unequal in status and was
resented by some as such (James, 1965; Thoman, 1965). Berry (1995; p. 84, this book) reports a
similar reaction to a proposed division of labour between regional scientists and geographers
(all of which suggests parallels with a nineteenth-century division of scientists – reported in Colin
Russell, 1977 – into the original, whose time is taken up with their own ideas; the deputed: ‘men
of little or no originality of mind but who are well trained and competent to work out problems
suggested by others’; and the drudges: ‘men who can make analyses, calculate constants, collect
data, etc.’ – the quotes are from Barton, 2003, p. 105). Although not all of the committee’s
recommendations were taken up, it did win institutional recognition for geography within the
NRC with the establishment of a geography and regional science programme; one of its main
achievements, when under the direction of Ron Abler, was the establishment of a national centre
for Geographical Information Systems (GIS) in the 1980s (see p. 158, this book).
A somewhat similar report was prepared a few years later for the Committee on Science and
Public Policy of the National Academy of Sciences and the Problems and Policy Committee of the
Systematic studies and scientific method 87

Social Science Research Council (Taaffe, 1970). Also the product of a committee (E. J. Taaffe,
I. Burton, N. Ginsburg, P. R. Gould, F. Lukermann and P. L. Wagner), this was a difficult task because
(as pointed out by Gauthier, 2002, p. 577) there had been considerable debate over the inclusion
of geography because members of the other panels (for economics, sociology, psychology,
anthropology and political science) did not consider geography as a social science. The report had
to convince them otherwise – it succeeded and ‘changed people’s minds by making a strong
argument for geography as a social science that made contributions to society and the development
of public policy’. That strong case stressed human geography as ‘the study of spatial organization
expressed as patterns and processes’ (pp. 5–6), incorporating people–environment relationships
and cultural landscapes and stressing relevance to planning and other policy issues. Much of the
report promoted human geography’s cause that:

there are many opportunities for the expansion and improvement of geographic research. If
geography is to have a strong and beneficial impact on the constantly changing patterns of
spatial organization of American society, it will be necessary to continue this development.
(p. 131)

This led to six conclusions regarding the discipline’s needs: (1) greater collaboration among the
social sciences; (2) alleviation of geography’s manpower shortage; (3) establishment of centres for
cartographic training and research; (4) development of remote sensing and related data bases;
(5) greater support for foreign area study; and (6) programmes established ‘to strengthen the
mathematical training of geographers’. Human geography was presented as an integral component
of the social sciences, increasingly sophisticated in its analytical tools, focusing on spatial
organisation, and offering particular skills in mapping and data acquisition.
There is little evidence that these two volumes, plus the efforts of successive directors of the
NRC’s geography and regional science programme and the growing volume of work on the
geographical-regional science interface, had a major impact, however, and geography’s hold on its
place in the American scientific academy was tenuous. Thus, in 1997 a further report was published
by a committee of sixteen. It was commissioned because of a ‘well-documented growing perception
(external to geography as a discipline) that geography is useful, perhaps even necessary, in meeting
certain societal needs’ (NAS-NRC, 1997, p. ix). To provide a showcase for geography’s strengths as
‘good science and socially relevant science’ (p. vii), the committee was asked to:

1 identify critical issues and constraints for the discipline;


2 clarify teaching and research priorities;
3 link developments in geography to national educational needs;
4 increase the appreciation of geography within the country’s scientific community; and
5 communicate with that community about the discipline’s future directions.
(p. 2)

In doing that, it focused almost entirely on a role for geography, and of types of geographical
research, that was very similar to that laid out in the reports of thirty years previously (on which,
see Johnston, 1997a, 2000b). The message had to be repeated since the scientific credentials of
geography (both human and physical) were still not widely appreciated within the American
academic community; one result of its impact within the NRC was its establishment of a Committee
on Geography (Turner, 2002, p. 66).
Little more than a decade later, a further report essayed the same general task. A committee
was established by the National Academies at the request of the National Science Foundation,
the US Geological Survey, the National Geographic Society and the Association of American
Geographers, which sought to persuade the American scientific academy ‘how the geographical sciences
88 Systematic studies and scientific method

can best contribute to science and society in the next decade through research initiatives aimed at
advancing understanding of major issues facing Earth in the early 21st century’ (NRC, 2010, 2, our italics).
The terminology indicates that the coverage is wider than the institutionalised discipline of
geography, but the chosen adjective indicates that a political point was being made regarding the
discipline’s centrality to the more amorphously defined ‘spatial sciences’ (Johnston, 2011); inter-
estingly, the report’s authors identify archaeologists, economists, astrophysicists, epidemiologists,
biologists, geologists, landscape architects and computer scientists among the ‘geographical
scientists’ but omit sociologists, political scientists and a wide range of scholars in the humanities
disciplines that have experienced a ‘spatial turn’ in recent decades (Warf and Arias, 2008; Withers,
2009). Its brief was wider than geography sensu stricto – as indicated by the reference to the ‘social
sciences’ (though relatively little social science was covered) but its emphasis – as in the previous
volumes – was strongly on techniques and technologies, reflecting the recent rapid growth of
Geographical Information Science (see p. 157, this book). Much stress was placed on the need for
a research infrastructure (called a cyberinfrastructure) to enable spatial analysis of large and
complex datasets, and the need for training in the use and development of that infrastructure in
order to realise the potential. Although geography was by then a very much broader discipline, this
report, like its predecessor, continued to portray geographers’ role within the sciences as largely
technical (as argued in a symposium on the report published in The Professional Geographer: Sui, 2011).

Geography’s subdisciplinary fields


The argument advanced by proponents of the new methodology focused on a common set of
procedures to tackle geographical problems. Berry (1964a) argued that the geographer’s viewpoint
emphasises space, with regard to distributions, integration, interactions, organisation and processes.
Its data can be categorised in a single matrix (Figure 3.2) in which ‘places’ form the rows and
‘characteristics’ the columns; each cell defines a ‘geographic fact’. Berry recognised five types of
geographical study which focused on different elements of this matrix: study of either a single row

PLACES

CHARACTERISTICS Column j

Row i

Cell ij

Box or Submatrix

Figure 3.2  The geography matrix: each cell – ij – contains a ‘geographic fact’, the value of characteristic
i at location j

Source: Berry, 1964b, p. 6.


Systematic studies and scientific method 89

TIME 1

TIME 2

TIME 3 Places
Characteristics Columns

Rows

TIME PERIODS OR
CROSS-SECTIONAL
SLICES

Figure 3.3  A third dimension to the geographic matrix: each cell – ijt – contains a ‘geographic fact’, the
value of characteristic i at location j at time t

Source: Berry, 1964b, p. 7.

(a place) or column (a characteristic); comparison of two or more rows (places) or columns


(characteristics); or study of rows and columns together (regions). Adding further matrices, one
for each time-period (Figure 3.3), allows five further types of study, based on the earlier five but
concentrating on changes over time. Thus, he concluded, systematic and regional geography are
part of the same enterprise – a repetition of Hartshorne’s (1959) arguments – with neither sufficient
in itself.
Berry’s matrices referred only to the characteristics of places; further matrices (Figure 3.4)
show flows between places, with one matrix for each flow category in each time-period
(Clark et al., 1974). Berry used this extension, though he did not formalise it, in a fusion of the
procedures for formal and functional regionalisation (see p. 59, this book) to produce a general
theory of spatial behaviour – a field theory, which he applied in a large study of the spatial
organisation of India (Berry, 1966, 1968). The techniques employed became widely used in the
1960s, as access to high-speed computers became easier. They were given the umbrella term
‘factorial ecology’ (Berry, 1971; Davies, 1984), and were widely applied in several geographic
subfields, resulting in a methodological unity which was previously unknown across the various
systematic specialisms.
One systematic area colonised early by such new methods was that part of urban geography
which dealt with the internal spatial structure of cities. Until the 1960s, little work had been done
on this topic except with regard to commercial land uses (particularly the Central Business District
and the relationship of the pattern of suburban shopping centres to the postulates of central place
theory); almost no attention was paid to the human content of residential areas, perhaps because
geography was seen as the science of places, not of people. Recognition that ‘people live in cities’
(Johnston, 1969) generated interest in residential areas, which gained much stimulus from the
work of the urban ecology school of sociologists at Chicago (some of their works had been
90 Systematic studies and scientific method

TIME PERIOD
etc.
2
c2

C,

C„
TIME PERIOD
1
c2

C, PLACES

P
L
A
C
E
S

Figure 3.4  Geographic flow matrices – one per commodity (C1 – Cn) per time period

Source: after Clark et al., 1974.

introduced to geographers earlier – Harris and Ullman, 1945; Dickinson, 1947 – but with little
impact for a decade or so – Agnew, 1997; Lichtenberger, 1997; Harris, 1990, 1992, 1997b). Social
area analysis, and then factorial ecology, gained in popularity as a methodology (Berry, 1964b),
with the allocation of housing among competing groups being modelled, mapped and statistically
analysed (Johnston, 1971; Timms, 1971).
By the mid-1960s use of statistical methods to test hypotheses was common across many of
human geography’s specialisms. They were united by their methods, remaining very separate iden-
tifiable branches within the geographical enterprise in terms of their substantive interests. The
decline of interest in regional syntheses (see Taaffe, 1974) meant that human geography experi-
enced a centrifugal trend with regard to substance, contemporaneous with a centripetal one with
regard to procedures. Since positivist scientific method, and the statistical techniques with which it
was associated by many geographers, was used much more widely than in human geography alone,
the former trend was probably the most important.

Transatlantic translations
By the early 1960s the quantitative and theoretical revolutions were having considerable impact
beyond the USA, as the result of two agencies. The first was the publication of work by the American
iconoclasts in the major journals. Second, and probably more importantly, during the 1950s and
1960s a number of British geographers went to the USA, either as postgraduate students or as
visiting staff members (see Haggett, 1990); during the 1960s and 1970s many British academics
were recruited to teach on the intensive summer-school courses for part-time students. Some of
those visitors encountered the new ideas and disseminated them ‘back home’, in part via the newly
established (1962) Study Group in Quantitative Methods of the Institute of British Geographers
Systematic studies and scientific method 91

(Gregory, 1976). Several, including Brian Berry, stayed in North America after completing their
postgraduate training, and others were attracted to move there (on the attraction of America, see
Berry, 1993, 2002b).
Some UK geographers attracted to the ‘new approach’ had a local base on which to build.
For most, this was in physical geography, arising out of the early use of statistics by climatologists
(e.g. Crowe, 1936); as a result, perhaps surprisingly, the first undergraduate text in statistics for
geographers was written by an English academic, Stan Gregory (1963), in which the positivist
methodology is only implicit, however. His Preface speaks of the geographer’s raw material
‘becoming progressively more of a quantitative nature’ and ‘the need to present both data and
conclusions in sound quantitative terms’ (pp. xiii–iv); statistical techniques are needed, but their
use in hypothesis testing is not set out. In addition, there was some interest in location theory – it
was taught at University College London in the early 1950s, for example (Halvorson and Stave,
1978; Berry, 1993; Barnes, 2001a, 2001b), and at the London School of Economics (Johnston,
2003c). Some worked on industrial location (W. Smith, 1949; Rawstron, 1958, though see
Rawstron, 2002) and settlement patterns was influenced by theoretical work, too (Dickinson,
1933; Smailes, 1946; note, however, the unwelcoming anonymous review of Christaller’s thesis on
central place theory in the Scottish Geographical Magazine, 1934; on Dickinson and Christaller, see
Johnston, 2002a), but this was far from normal.
Although statistics courses were introduced to several UK university departments of geography
by the mid-1960s, and aspects of the scientific methodology were taught in at least a few
(Whitehand, 1970), the main focus for the introduction of the ‘new geography’ to the UK during
the early years of the decade was the University of Cambridge. The leaders were R. J. Chorley (an
Oxford graduate and geomorphologist who had studied geology in the USA: Beckinsale, 1997;
Stoddart, 1997a) and P. Haggett (a Cambridge-trained human geographer, although his early
published work was in biogeography; he had also visited the USA and experienced the developments
there: Haggett, 1965c, p. vi, 1990; see also Haggett and Chorley, 1989. Haggett’s interests in human
geography – and in particular on spatial diffusion – were stimulated by a footnote in Lösch’s classic
book, but he was only able to initiate that research when he moved to Bristol in the mid-1960s.)
Their impact on British geography was considerable, through innovative research and teaching
(Gregory, 1976); they supervised a substantial number of graduate students who proceeded to
academic posts elsewhere and ‘spread the message’ in the same way that the ‘space cadets’ did in the
USA (Hanson, 1993).
Chorley and Haggett worked on the adaptation of certain statistical techniques to geographical
(both physical and human) problems (Chorley and Haggett, 1965a; Haggett, 1964; Haggett and
Chorley, 1969), but their most lasting initial contribution was probably editing two collections of
essays which emerged from extramural courses that they directed, aimed at introducing the
‘new geography’ to teachers. (Note that Barnes, 1996, emphasises Haggett’s role as a change-
agent within British geography, but in so doing overlooks the substantial behind-the-scenes
impacts of others, notably Stan Gregory who was very influential not only in establishing the
Study Group on Quantitative Methods within the IBG, but also within the Geographical Association
and the Joint Matriculation Board, whose examinations were used for entrance to most UK
universities.)
The first of these books – Frontiers in Geographical Teaching (Chorley and Haggett, 1965b) – was
based on a 1963 course designed ‘to bring teachers and like persons into the University, there to
encounter and discuss recent developments and advances in their subjects’ (p. xi; see also Haggett,
2015). In it E. A. Wrigley (1965) discussed the changing philosophy of geography, identifying the
increasing use of statistical techniques as the contemporary development ‘of singular importance’
(p. 15). He pointed out that techniques of themselves do not form a methodology and that
‘Geography writing and research work have in recent years lacked any general accepted, overall
view of the subject even though techniques have proliferated’ (p. 17). He offered no outline of such
92 Systematic studies and scientific method

a view, however, arguing that eclecticism in mode of analysis was likely to be most productive: ‘the
best sign of health is the production of good research work rather than the manufacture of general
methodologies’ (p. 17) and ‘The final test of the value of any intellectual labour is its ability to help
men to understand questions in which they are interested’ (p. 19).
Many of the other chapters interpret geography as if the ‘revolutions’ had not occurred in the
USA, however. C. T. Smith’s (1965) chapter on historical geography, for example, is an excellent
British companion to the American statement published a decade earlier (Clark, 1954). Elsewhere,
Pahl (1965) introduced the models of the Chicago school of urban sociologists and suggested a
social geography in which the prime factor is distance (p. 108), but only the chapters by Haggett
and Timms introduced much of the transatlantic turmoil. Haggett (1965a) wrote on models in
economic geography, both those based on simple views of the world, such as developments on
von Thünen’s (Chisholm, 1962), and those derived from observations of particular cases (e.g. Taaffe
et al., 1963). Haggett noted that:

Perhaps the biggest barrier that model builders in economic geography will have to face in the
immediate future is an emotional one. It is difficult to accept without some justifiable scepticism
that the complexities of a mobile, infinitely variable landscape system will ever be reduced to the
most sophisticated model, but still more difficult to accept that as individuals we suffer the
indignity of following mathematical patterns in our behaviour.
(1965a, p. 109)

He introduced the notion of indeterminacy at the individual level (see also Jones, 1956; p. 81, this
book) and showed how random variables must be introduced to make models operational;
his chapter on scale problems (Haggett, 1965b) illustrated methods of sampling and of map
generalisation from samples.
Timms (1965) demonstrated the use of statistical techniques for analyses of social
patterns within cities (based on Shevky and Bell’s, 1955, social area analysis, and developed
independently of Berry’s work on this topic (see p. 89, this book). Later work in this mould
by Robson, 1969, followed a period spent working with Berry at Chicago, but earlier develop-
ments at Keele, also based on Shevky and Bell (Williams and Herbert, 1962) illustrated that
some at least of the changes in UK geography were largely independent of those occurring in the
USA, depending instead on accessing the relevant literature in other disciplines.) Timms pointed
out that:

The sciences concerned with the study of social variation have as yet produced few models which
can stand comparison with the observed patterns or which can be used to predict those pat-
terns. . . . Prediction rests on accurate knowledge of the degree and direction of the interrela-
tionships between phenomena. This can only be attained by the use of techniques of description
and analysis which are amenable to statistical comparison and manipulation. If the goal of geo-
graphical studies be accepted as the formulation of laws of areal arrangement and of prediction
based on those laws, then it is inevitable that their techniques must become considerably more
objective and more quantitative than heretofore.
(1965, p. 262)

The majority of the contributors to Frontiers in Geographical Teaching, almost all of whom were
associated with the Department of Geography at the University of Cambridge, were not as
committed to the ‘new geography’ as Timms (who later, like Pahl, became a professor of sociology;
E. A. (Tony) Wrigley became an economics historian/demographer, and President of the British
Academy). This cannot be levelled at the editors, whose epilogue presented a strong case for the
‘theoretical revolution’:
Systematic studies and scientific method 93

We cannot but recognize the importance of the construction of theoretical models, wherein
aspects of ‘geographic reality’ are presented together in some organic structural relationship,
the juxtaposition of which leads one to comprehend, at least, more than might appear from the
information presented piecemeal and, at most, to apprehend general principles which may
have much wider application than merely to the information from which they were derived.
Geographical teaching has been remarkably barren of such models. . . . This reticence stems
largely, one suspects, from a misconception of the nature of model thinking. . . . Models are
subjective frameworks . . . like discardable cartons, very important and productive receptacles
for advantageously presenting selected aspects of reality.
(Haggett and Chorley, 1965, pp. 360–1)

This view dominated their next, and substantially more influential, volume Models in Geography (Chorley
and Haggett, 1967), most of whose contributors were also linked with the Cambridge department.
This was a major synthesis of most of the work completed before the mid-1960s by adherents to the
‘quantitative and theoretical revolutions’. Individual authors were asked ‘to discuss the role of
model-building within their own special fields of research’ (Haggett and Chorley, 1967, p. 19), which
resulted in a series of substantive review essays, some dealing with topical specialisms (urban geo-
graphy and settlement location; industrial location; agricultural activity – there were similar reviews
for physical geography), some with particular themes ranging across several specialisms (economic
development; regions; maps; organisms and ecosystems; the evolution of spatial patterns), and
some with methods and approaches (demographic models; sociological models; network models). 
A catholic use of the term ‘model’ was deployed, as a synonym for a theory, a law, a hypothesis, or any
other form of structured idea (see Moss, 1970). The approach was strongly nomothetic, however:

the student of history and geography is faced with two alternatives. He can either bury his head,
ostrich-like, in the sand grains of an idiographic human history, conducted over unique
geographic space, scowl upon broad generalization, and produce a masterly descriptive thesis
on what happened when, where. Or he can become a scientist and attempt, by the normal
procedures of scientific investigation, to verify, reject, or modify, the stimulating and exciting
ideas which his predecessors presented him with.
(Harvey, 1967a, p. 551)

All the contributors had chosen the latter course: their focus was on models – on generalisations of
reality – and methods were very much secondary.
The orientation of this significant volume is given by the editors’ introduction. (Its significance
lay in its two uses: first, as a synthesis and argument, the volume was widely read and used by
researchers and teachers as a guide; second, as a series of major reviews, when republished in
separate paperback volumes, the book was extensively employed as an undergraduate text.) Haggett
and Chorley (1967, p. 24) presented the model as ‘a bridge between the observational and
theoretical levels . . . concerned with simplification, reduction, concretisation, experimentation,
action, extension, globalisation, theory formation and explanation’. It can be descriptive or
normative, static or dynamic, experimental or theoretical (see also Chorley, 1964). It forms the
basis for their proposed new paradigm, which made no attempt ‘to alter the basic Hartshorne
definition of Geography’s prime task’ (p. 38) but offered hope for much greater progress:

the new paradigm . . . is based on faith in the new rather than its proven ability . . . There is good
reason to think that those subjects which have modelled their forms on mathematics and physics
. . . have climbed considerably more rapidly than those which have attempted to build internal or
idiographic structures.
(p. 38)
94 Systematic studies and scientific method

Models in Geography stands as a statement of that faith. Although the editors and contributors
comprised many of the early active participants in the move to change British geography towards a
‘more scientific’ approach, others involved are not directly represented. Notable among them was
a group who graduated at the University of Cambridge in the 1950s, having been tutored by A. A.
L. Caesar. (Chisholm and Manners, 1973, p. xi, credit his role, one which continued until the end
of the 1970s, with a steady stream of productive research workers from St Catharine’s College.)
It included Michael Chisholm, Peter Hall, Gerald Manners and Kenneth Warren as well as Haggett,
who was the only one who worked within the ‘quantitative revolution’. Chisholm, for example,
focused on theoretical developments in economic geography (e.g. Chisholm, 1962, 1966, 1971a)
but with relatively little quantitative analysis (though see Chisholm and O’Sullivan, 1973), and
both Hall and Manners were more concerned, as was Caesar, with geographical analyses of
contemporary policy issues, although in some cases the analyses led to theory-derivation (Hall,
1981a, 1998).
Chorley and Haggett’s editing, and their joint work on technical developments, such as trend
surface analysis (Chorley and Haggett, 1965a) and network analysis (Haggett and Chorley, 1969),
reflected a belief in the unity of physical and human geography (further demonstrated in Haggett’s
(1972, 2001) major undergraduate text). This assumed that a shared interest in methods and
techniques could unite the two – Haggett (1967, p. 664) writes on ‘the basic proposition that a
wide range of different geographical networks may be usefully analysed in terms of their common
geometrical characteristics’. As in North America, if geometry (i.e. spatial form) was the focus of
geographical analysis, then physical and human geographers could find common cause (Woldenberg
and Berry, 1967). Explanation of the geometry required the study of very different processes,
however, and the two soon separated again.
The two books edited by Chorley and Haggett were the first major indication of change within
British geography – and they appeared too late to assist geography’s cause during the first stages of
a major expansion of universities there. By the end of the 1950s, there was a geography department
in just about every UK university and many of them were expanding to meet growing demand
from students. But as a discipline, geography did not appear to have a high standing within British
academia, and when a series of seven universities was founded in England in the late 1950s and
early 1960s, only one (the University of Sussex) included geography within its course offerings
from the outset (as a social science though including physical geography; there was no separate
geography department, however, only a ‘Geography Laboratory’). Two others included geographers
within schools of environmental studies, as did two further universities established a little later in
Scotland and Northern Ireland, but only one – the University of Lancaster – eventually established
a Department of Geography, because it was having difficulties recruiting students for other
disciplines. Thus geography, because of its image as not being closely linked with the burgeoning
social sciences and the lack of an influential pressure group, failed to gain a place in a new group
of universities, many of which soon became major research centres in the social and environmental
sciences. (On this episode, see Johnston 2003b, 2004c.)
This marginalisation of geography within the UK was exacerbated in the mid-1960s when a
Social Science Research Council (SSRC; it was later renamed the Economic and Social Research
Council – ESRC) was established to fund postgraduate and research work, and from which
geography was initially excluded. In response to this, a number of geographers (led by Robert Steel,
an Oxford graduate, then Professor of Geography at the University of Liverpool and later to be
Principal of University College Swansea) took the initiative of approaching the SSRC chairman to
promote their discipline’s cause. He invited them to make a detailed case, a task undertaken for the
group by Michael Chisholm (then a lecturer in the Department of Geography at the University of
Bristol). His detailed document and case – not accepted by all departmental heads – was successful,
and a Human Geography and Planning Committee was established within the SSRC (Chisholm
2001; Johnston, 2003c). Chisholm later developed his case for geography as a social science into
Systematic studies and scientific method 95

two books (Chisholm, 1971c, 1975a) and edited a third, which illustrated it with a series of major
case studies (Chisholm and Rodgers, 1973). The first of these (written specifically as a review
conducted for the SSRC) argued in its introduction that the real change in geography associated
with quantification was ‘a substantial tightening up in logical rigour’ (Chisholm, 1971c, p. 2)
involving three main themes (pp. 5–6):

1 All phenomena occur in a spatial context.


2 Economic and social processes require a built infrastructure (buildings and transport media).
3 Human activity takes place within environmental contexts.

There were only five chapters: one considered static patterns (points, surfaces, regions and their
correlation), another considered dynamic patterns (processes such as urbanisation and economic
development) and a third theories of spatial organisation. The other two were concerned with
research organisation and priorities with seven of the latter identified (by the SSRC’s Human
Geography Committee and not just Chisholm): perception studies; simulation models; forecasting;
regional taxonomy; environmental standards; population and migration; and processes of regional
economic and social development. (These brief chapters were the core of the later, more extended
treatment: Chisholm, 1975a.)

The relatively untouched: historical and cultural geography


The NAS-NRC (1965) report (see p. 85, this book) identified two main systematic specialisms
within human geography that had been largely untouched by the developments outlined here:
cultural and historical geography (see also Darby, 1983a). In addition, despite Berry’s (1964a)
attempt to reframe it, regional geography remained largely apart from the changes in methodological
emphasis. Furthermore, political geography was described by Berry, 1969, as a ‘moribund
backwater’ (though Muir, 1975, sought to apply quantitative methods to the field). Not all cultural,
historical and regional geographers ignored the changes occurring elsewhere, and some were in
the ‘revolutionary’ vanguard: two of the chapters in Models in Geography, for example, were written by
David Grigg and David Harvey, whose empirical research for their Ph.Ds was on historical topics
(e.g. Harvey, 1985c). But in general terms, the NAS-NRC report was correct; there is little evidence
of early success in winning cultural, historical and regional geographers over to the new
methodology.
Of the three groups, historical geographers were probably most concerned about their apparent
isolation within the discipline. This was summarised by Baker in terms of the approaches which
historical geographers need to consider in greater detail:

An assumption is necessary here: that methodologically the main advances can be expected
from an increased awareness of developments in other disciplines, from a greater use of
statistical methods, from the development, application and testing of theory, and from
exploitation of behavioural approaches and sources. . . . Rethinking becomes necessary because
orthodox doctrines have ceased to carry conviction. As far as historical geography is concerned,
this involves a questioning of the adequacy of its traditional methods and techniques.
(1972, p. 13)

All of these would have to be followed with care, and the potentials of the methodological
developments assessed cautiously, but Baker clearly believed there was considerable scope for
change as had already been shown in economic and social history, and perhaps even more so in
archaeology (see Hodder and Orton, 1976; Renfrew, 1981). Particular areas of historical geography,
including those relating to urban settlements (e.g. D. Ward, 1971), were more open to such changes,
96 Systematic studies and scientific method

if for no other reason than the better quality and quantity of available data (e.g. Whitehand and
Patten, 1977; Johnson and Pooley, 1982; Dennis, 1984). There were possible implications in such
work, however, as Baker noted:

Studies in, for example, ‘historical agricultural geography‘, ‘historical urban geography’ and
‘historical economic geography’ seem to offer possibilities of fundamental development,
particularly in terms of a better understanding of the processes by which geographical change
through time may take place. Such an organization of the subject would view historical geography
as a means towards an end rather than as an end in itself.
(1972, p. 28)

In the early discussions of the relationships between historical geography and the ‘theoretical
and quantitative revolutions’, most attention focused on quantification rather than theory. Vance
(1978) pointed out that the development of theory does not have to involve ‘quantitative
abstraction’, as his own work showed (Vance, 1970; see also Pred, 1977b, and Conzen, 1981;
Meinig’s (1986–2004) later four volume magnum opus on The Shaping of America was built around
graphical models). Available data can be manipulated to test theories regarding past spatial patterns
(e.g. Goheen, 1970), but Radford (1981, p. 257) argued that theory is the more important: ‘In the
cities of the nineteenth-century United States, a set of principles . . . was taken to something
approaching a logical conclusion.’ This assumes that theory is possible in historical geography. As
illustrated in Chapter 5, some dispute this – for geography as a whole and not just for historical
geography. The positivist method implies objectivity, but the geographer in describing a landscape
is subjective:

In describing a landscape, is he not committed by his past training and his past experiences – by
his prejudices, if you will? Just as the portrait an artist paints will tell you much about the artist
as well as his sitter, so the description of a countryside will tell you a great deal about the writer.
(Darby, 1962, p. 4)

Darby portrayed geography as both a science and an art:

[it] is a science in the sense that what facts we perceive must be examined, and perhaps
measured, with care and accuracy. It is an art in that any presentation (let alone any perception)
of those facts must be selective, and so involve choice, and taste, and judgement.
(p. 6)

Examining the subsequent evolution of historical geography, Baker (2003) was especially concerned
with debates about its relationship with history. Reviewing the impacts of the approaches that
would transform wider human geography after the 1960s, he claimed that:

the more explicit adoption of spatial and locational concepts in historical geography (and in
history) does not require us, Mao-like, to reject our traditions and embrace a brave ‘new’ world
of geographical history. The more energetic prosecution of a new geographical history in the
guise of spatial and locational histories is to be welcomed, but it does not of necessity involve
forsaking all other geographical perspectives upon history.
(pp. 70–1)

Cultural geographers were less concerned about their apparent drift away from the mainstream
of geographical activity than historical geographers, perhaps because of the lack of any parallel
developments to those affecting geography in anthropology, the discipline with which many
Systematic studies and scientific method 97

contemporary cultural geographers had most contact. As Mikesell (1978, p. 1) expressed it,
‘Stubborn individualism and a seeming indifference to academic fashion are well-known character-
istics’ of cultural geographers, whose preferences are for a historical orientation; a focus on the
role of human agency in environmental change, on material culture, and on rural areas; links
with anthropology; an individualistic perspective; and field work. In the USA, the Berkeley
‘school’, founded and led for several decades by Carl Sauer, remained an influential site of resistance
to the new geography, continuing to stress research on the Morphology of Landscape (Sauer, 1925).
This had rejected environmental determinism for a more open approach, examining for
example, human intervention in landscape evolution through plant and animal domestication,
the use of fire, the diffusion of ideas and artefacts, and the creation of settlements (all themes
reviewed in W. L. Thomas, 1956, and maintained by Sauer’s disciples, such as Kniffen: see
Mathewson, 1993). Sauer was departmental head at Berkeley from 1923 to 1955 and 27 post-
graduates completed Ph.Ds under his supervision in those years. His student, Jim Parsons,
succeeded him and more students continued to work on the ethos of ‘Sauer’s project of elucidating
the cultural landscape’ (Williams, 2009, p. 303, 2014). More traditional regional geography
continued to be written by others too; even if it could never recover the relative centrality it
enjoyed in anglophone geography before the mid-1950s. The field was surveyed by Paterson
(1974), whose essay had two main sections – ‘On the problems of writing regional geography’ and
‘Is progress possible in regional geography?’. The first investigated six problems, including
the growing shortage of subordinate materials (micro-regional studies), and the increasing
submergence of regional distinctiveness, though:

only a certain amount of innovation is possible if the regional geographer is to perform his
appointed task, which is to convey to his reader the essentials of his region; to illuminate the
landscape with analytical light. Landforms and climate are common to all terrestrial landscapes
. . . and human activities to most of them: how shall repetition be avoided?
(p. 8)

So long as contrasts between region and region [remain], and no matter to what they are
attributable, there is work for the geographer to do.
(p. 16)

Paterson did not conclude that there is no possibility of progress, however, despite the
constraints: regional geography can advance on two criteria – content and insight. Reference to
Wilbur Zelinsky’s (1973a) book illustrated the increased range of content currently being
introduced; discussion of Meinig’s work (e.g. Meinig, 1972) showed the ability of regional
geographers to produce fresh spatial insights, although Paterson concludes that ‘Adventurousness is
not a quality that most of us associate with regional geography’ (p. 9). Thus:

The way is open for regional studies which are less bound by old formulae; less obliged
to tell all about the region; more experimental and, in a proper sense of the word, more
imaginative than in the past, and covering a broader range of perceptions, either popular or
specialist.
(p. 23)

Regional Geography[’s] . . . goals are general rather than specific; it is not primarily problem-
orientated but concerned to provide balanced coverage, and its aims are popular and educational
rather than practical or narrowly professional. Such relevance as it possesses it gains by its
appeal . . . to the two universal human responses of wonder and concern. . . . One may recall
Medawar’s assertion that in science we are being progressively relieved of the burden of singular
98 Systematic studies and scientific method

instances, the tyranny of the particular, and in turn assert that there is a frame of mind on which
the particular exercises no tyranny, but a strong fascination.
(p. 21)

Elsewhere, Mead (1980, p. 297: see also Mead, 2004) strongly defended geographers who
‘adopt other lands . . . share other cultures . . . [and] make a contribution to the store of knowledge
about them’. Similarly, though with greater intensity, Hart (1982a, p. 1) claimed in his presidential
address to the AAG that: ‘Society has allocated responsibility for the study of areas to geography: this
responsibility is the justification for our existence as a scholarly discipline’.
This responsibility involves responding to people’s curiosity about places, promoting an
‘understanding [of] the meaning of an area [which] cannot be reduced to a formal process’ (Hart,
1982a, p. 2). Unfortunately, geographers were very insecure with that mission and so had retreated
into ‘scientism’ which involved studying ‘people abstracted from their real world contexts’ (p. 16).
The quantitative revolution was giving priority to ‘techniques and procedures rather than places
and people’ (p. 17) and diverting attention from geographers’ obligation to answer the key
questions of ‘how much of what is where and why it’s there, about the where and why of places
and people, about the land and how people have used and abused it’ (p. 19) – about which there is
so much ‘woeful ignorance’. Thus, to Hart (p. 29) an important element in the ‘highest form of the
geographers’ art’ (his term for regional geography) requires individuals to ‘adopt a region, to
immerse themselves in its culture, to acquire a specialist understanding of it’. Ten geographers from
the University of California at Santa Barbara responded by arguing that just as Hart claimed that ‘We
cannot allow ourselves to be intimidated by those who flaunt the banner of science’ (Hart, 1982a,
p. 5) so ‘We equally cannot allow ourselves to be intimidated by those who flaunt the banner of
anti-science, those who would reject all that is scientific about the discipline, and those who would
urge a return to the descriptive morass from which we have recently emerged’ (Golledge et al.,
1982, p. 558), especially at a time when geography was under threat in some American universities.
Hart’s (1982b, p. 559) response was that he was critical of shoddy work of any type, did not want
geography to be forced into any particular mould, and that ‘we should be most unwise to jettison
so blithely one of our grand traditions merely because some of our colleagues do not understand,
appreciate, or know how to practise it’ (see also Clout, 2003a, and Murphy’s, 2013, argument
for geographers to produce ‘grand regional narratives’ as a way of improving [non-academic]
geographical understanding).
The implication is that there was a strongly perceived difference between, on one hand, many
historical geographers and, on the other, most cultural and regional geographers with regard to the
degree to which they felt ‘left behind’ or ‘relatively untouched’ by the changes that occurred during
the 1950s and 1960s in other branches of human geography. Historical geographers, at least, seem
to have been impelled to consider the possibility of making methodological changes, whereas the
other two groups continued to work within their established tradition (see also Mikesell, 1973).
Not all historical geographers would agree with Baker’s analogy from systems theory that simply
‘Historical geography has a long relaxation time’ (p. 11), however, and Chapter 5 illustrates the
degree to which they mounted attacks against the positivist approach.

Conclusions
Critiques of the established regional approach began to crystallise in the USA during the mid-
1950s. The aims of research in human geography had been resolved around regions and description
until then, and relatively traditional definitions of the field were still observed: the main issues
concerned means and methods. Some of these debates were among those who would contribute to
the new agendas in the 1950s. The innovations of that period involved the strengthening of the
systematic and topical geographies, and their release from a largely subservient relationship to
Systematic studies and scientific method 99

regional geography, by attempts to develop laws and theories of spatial patterns, using models of
various kinds for illumination, and applying mathematical and, especially, statistical procedures to
facilitate the search for generalisations. Whereas regional geographers saw their discipline as, at
most, law-consuming, those of the new persuasion aimed at producing their own laws, which
could be used to explain particular regional outcomes.
These changed means to the geographic end were rapidly accepted in many branches
of human geography, particularly in those topical specialisms dealing with economic aspects
of contemporary life. They were soon accepted in the growing field of contemporary social
geography, but were relatively ignored in historical geography and almost completely shunned in
cultural and regional investigations, which, it was claimed, focus on unique characteristics of
unique places. They also spread into the corresponding fields of study across the Atlantic (and across
the Pacific, too: King, 2008), and within little more than a decade British geographers produced a
major review volume (Models in Geography) containing 816 pages of testimony to the innovators’
enthusiasm and their links (largely one-way) with other social sciences. It is evident that in the UK
there was some fertile ground for the reception and dissemination of this ‘new geography’; location
theory and quantitative methods were already being taught in some geography departments in the
1940s–1950s.
Everywhere those who promoted these shifts evidently judged the existing regional geography
framework inadequate. What, larger, contextual, forces prompted them has more recently become
the subject of debate, with Trevor Barnes (2008a, 2008b) pointing to the key role, in the USA, of
the wider scientific ethos of the moment linked to the Cold War. This had been shaped by the Allied
and especially American techno–military–science in the Second World War and would be further
bolstered by the Cold War. Others (Johnston et al., 2008) signal multiple causes and diverse points
of origin, especially in the UK, citing Stan Gregory’s (1976) identification of three groups who
became key to the development of the quantitative revolution there: those who had been to North
America (usually as postgraduate students), a few introduced to quantification elsewhere, and the
‘home grown’ advocates. Moreover, methods are insufficient to sustain an academic revolution
unless they can be applied to a coherent substantive core. The quests for such a core and some of
their ongoing trajectories are the subject of the next chapter.
Chapter 4

Human geography as spatial science

[O]ne of the greatest legacies that our discipline is endowed with is the frontier spirit that
accompanied the quantitative revolution.
(Trisalyn Nelson, 2012, p. 92)

Undoubtedly the 1960s have witnessed a major transformation in the subject; today, geogra-
phers are probably at least as numerate, if not more so, than most other social scientists.
However, the movement to quantification should not be regarded as an end in itself; it is but a
means to an end, a symptom of something deeper that is going on within the subject.
(Michael Chisholm, 1975a, p. 48)

[T]hese developments have been both exciting and disturbing. Exciting because they promised
to breathe life into traditional university geography which – with a few exceptions – remained
wedded to conservative regional or commodity lines or split-up into confusing sub-varieties
like ‘resource’ geography or ‘medical’ geography. Disturbing because they increasingly used
mathematical methods and were scattered with unfamiliar and unwelcome incognitas like
Eigen values or Beta coefficients.
(Peter Haggett, 1965c, p. v)

Our images – the maps and models of the world we carry around with us – need larger and
more relevant information inputs.
(Peter Gould and Rodney White, 1974, p. 192)

By our theories you shall know us.


(David Harvey, 1969a, p. 486)

The changes in human geography that emanated from several centres in the USA during the
1950s were very much concerned with methods of investigation. Systematic studies were in the
ascendant, however, and the implicit intention was to develop laws and theories within an, often
unstated, positivist framework.
In this context, human geographers promoting the changes increasingly sought a clear
identity for their discipline within the social sciences, alongside economics, sociology and
political science. Disciplines are sustained by their content rather than their methods, however,
since many of the latter (especially those involving statistics) were common to several disciplines
– or so it was believed. Geographers argued that their discipline provided a particular viewpoint
and contribution to the overall social science goal of understanding society. Their focus was on
spatial variables and the study of spatial systems, so that within their own discipline they elevated
the concept of space over that of place, while also redirecting its focus away from the idiographic
and towards the nomothetic. Other concerns and approaches, from the late 1960s and into the
Human geography as spatial science 101

1970s, 1980s and beyond soon yielded different ways of doing geography that were linked to a
series of adjectives – notably, humanistic, radical (and sometimes anarchist and Marxist),
postmodern and feminist. These form the foci of Chapters 5–8. However, while those discussions
developed, the adoption of scientific methods that we recounted in Chapter 3 was also carried
forward through a range of methods, debate and technologies. This chapter describes these,
which include ideas of spatial and systems theory, notions of behavioural geography and time-
geography, geostatistics and geocomputation and, arguably most influential of all, the advent of
Geographical Information Systems (GIS) and Science (GISci).

Spatial variables and spatial systems


Geography is a discipline in distance, according to a Scottish professor’s inaugural lecture
(Watson, 1955; Johnston, 1993b), with the relative location of people and places as its
central theme. Kevin Cox (1976) later argued that the contemporary importance of relative
location within society stemmed from alterations in societal structure consequent upon technical
change. The main interactions in less developed societies are between relatively isolated groups
of individuals and their physical environments, creating vertical relationships between societies
and ‘a spatially differentiated nature’ (p. 192) as an obvious focus for geographical scholar-
ship. With technological advancement, however, the main links are among individuals.
Interdependence within and between societies increases with the more complex division of
labour, so that the most important aspects of modern human existence relate to spatially
differentiated societies, not to a spatially differentiated nature. This ‘horizontal’ interdependence
between groups living in different places creates the patterns of human occupance on the surface
of the earth and provides the basic subject matter for human geographers.

The approach clarified: three pioneering textbooks


As noted earlier (p. 15, this book), textbooks play a significant role in the transmission of para-
digms within disciplines so that a clear statement of a major shift occurring should be provided
when new textbooks appear which codify a ‘new approach’. For human geography, this occurred
in the mid- and late 1960s.Three texts promoted the new approach, focusing on spatial arrangements
(the areal differentiation in human activities and the spatial interactions which this produces) and
on the role of distance as a crucial variable influencing the nature of those arrangements.
The pioneer among such texts was Haggett’s (l965c) Locational Analysis in Human Geography.
It presented material that he had been teaching to undergraduates for several years at the University
of Cambridge. (On the stimuli to Haggett’s work, see Haggett, 1990, and Chorley, 1995; on Chorley,
see Stoddart, 1997a.) Its depiction of pattern and order in spatial structures was placed within a
decomposition of nodal regions into five geometrical elements; a sixth was added in the second
edition (Haggett et al., 1977). The book contained little programmatic material either ‘selling’ or
‘justifying’ the new approach; he noted at the outset that any book reflects its author’s biases and
made clear that his were a preference for quantitative over qualitative analysis and a search for
‘order, locational order, shown by the phenomena studied traditionally as human geography’ (p. 2,
original italics).
Haggett’s presentation of spatial systems was based on a simple schema comprising its major
elements (Figure 4.1). This assumed a spatially differentiated society within which there is a desire
for interaction within regional systems, and which results in patterns of movement – of goods,
people, money, ideas, and so on – between places. The first stage in analysing nodal regions involves
their representation. Most movement is channelled along routes, so the second stage involves
characterisation of those channels as networks comprising edges and vertices; in a transport system,
many of the latter are the nodes, the organisational nexus. Their spatial arrangement forms the
102 Human geography as spatial science

A B C

D E F

‘2

Figure 4.1  The elements in Haggett’s schema for studying spatial systems: A: movement;
B: channels; C: nodes; D: hierarchies; E: surfaces; and F diffusion

Source: Haggett et al., 1977, p. 7.

schema’s third element, and the fourth investigates their organisation into hierarchies which define
the importance of places within the settlement framework. Finally, in the original scheme, there are
the surfaces, the areas of land within the skeleton of nodes (settlements) and networks (routes) that
are occupied by land uses of various types and intensities.
Patterns of human occupation of the earth change frequently and the spatial order to such
changes forms the sixth element in Haggett’s revised schema. Change does not occur uniformly
over space in most circumstances; it usually originates at one or a few nodes and spreads to others
(as with the ‘new’ geography in the USA discussed in the previous chapter), along the movement
channels, through the nodes, across the surfaces and down the hierarchies. The processes of change
over space and time thus involve spatial diffusion.
Haggett stressed his conception of geography as a science of distributions, emphasising the
regularities in various elements of these distributions: the first half of his book – entitled ‘Models
of locational structure’ – allocated a chapter to each of the schema’s elements. The first edition
(1965c) was very reliant on work in other disciplines; the second (Haggett et al., 1977) illustrated
the substantial amount of work done by geographers in the intervening decade. In his collection
of semi-autobiographical essays, Haggett (1990) frequently reiterated his view of geography’s
‘emphasis on space and on geometry’ (p. 5), which he expressed as personal, ‘though I hope not
wholly . . . quirky’. Maps, as demonstrations of spatial structure, form the foundation of his
geography, as illustrated by essays on ‘Levels of resolution’, ‘The art of the mappable’, ‘Regional
synthesis’ and ‘The arrows of space’. Thus, although he recognised that ‘there are other delights in
geography’ (p. 184), he retained a ‘simple delight in the beauty of geographical structures and the
challenges posed in finding them and mapping them’ (see also Gould, 1993, and D. Gregory, 1994,
for more reflections on the aesthetics of spatial science). Although Locational Analysis covered human
geography only, Haggett believed in the indissolubility of physical and human geography, as argued
in his biographical essays (Haggett, 1990) and introductory texts (Haggett, 1972, 2001). In 1991
he wrote that:
Human geography as spatial science 103

Geography is now too large, too multicultural and, hopefully, too mature, to be tempted by any
single orthodoxy. Yet even a braiding stream may sometimes converge on a few major channels
and I hope geography may ever delight in rediscovering how much it has to gain from allowing
environmental and societal themes to merge together.
(Haggett, 1991, p. 302)

Other texts produced in that period took a similar approach, although differing in emphases.
Morrill’s (1970a) title – The Spatial Organization of Society – clearly emphasised his view of the role of
geographical analysis in the larger task of the social sciences: human geography’s core elements are
‘Space, space relations, and change in space – how physical space is structured, how men relate
through space, how man has organized his society in space, and how our conception and use of
space change’ (p. 3). Space has five qualities relevant to the understanding of human behaviour:
(1) distance, the spatial dimension of separation; (2) accessibility; (3) agglomeration; (4) size; and
(5) relative location, which can be put together to build theories:

Virtually all theory of spatial organization assumes that the structure of space is based on the
principles of minimizing distance and maximizing the utility of points and areas within the
structure, without taking the environment, or variable content of space, into account. Although
the differential quality of area is interesting and its effect on location and interaction is great,
most of the observable regularity of structure in space results from the principles of efficiently
using territory of uniform character. The theoretical structures for agricultural location, location
of urban centres, and the internal patterns of the city are all derived from the principle of
minimizing distance on a uniform plane.
(Morrill, 1970a, p. 15)

Thus, all land use and location decisions are taken to minimise movement costs. The
spatial approach (i.e. geography) claims that one particular variable on which it concentrates –
distance – is a significant influence on human behaviour and seeks accounts for observed spatial
patterns within this framework. And so in Morrill’s book:

the explanation of spatial structure proceeds from the deductive – what would occur under the
simplest conditions – to the inductive – how local factors distort this ‘pure’ structure. To begin
with, all the local variation may introduce is a risk of missing the underlying structure. Modern
theory of location therefore stresses the spatial factors – above all, distance – which interact to
bring about the regular and repetitive patterns.
(p. 20)

Morrill’s summarising ‘theory’ of spatial structures proceeds as follows:

1 Societies operate to achieve two spatial efficiency goals:


(a) to use every piece of land to the greatest profit and utility; and
(b) to achieve the greatest possible volume of interaction at the least possible cost.
2 Pursuit of these goals involves four types of location decisions:
(a) the substitution of land for transport costs when seeking accessibility;
(b) substituting production costs at sites for transport costs when seeking markets;
(c) substituting agglomeration benefits for transport costs; and
(d) substituting self-sufficiency (higher production costs) and trade (higher transport costs).
3 The spatial structures resulting from these decisions include:
(a) spatial land-use gradients; and
(b) a spatial hierarchy of regions.
104 Human geography as spatial science

These are somewhat distorted by environmental variations to produce:


(c) more irregular but predictable patterns of location.
Whereas over time distortion may result from:
(d) non-optimal location decisions; and
(e) change through processes of spatial diffusion.

Like Haggett, therefore, Morrill focused on the geometry of human organisation of activities on the
earth’s surface. Whereas Haggett emphasised pattern, however, Morrill paid more attention to
decision-making processes which would produce the most ‘efficient’ patterns, as foundations for
appreciating the imperfect examples of such patterns which are observed in the ‘real world’. The
importance of economic and spatial variables is less dominant in the third edition of the book,
however (Morrill and Dormitzer, 1979, p. 7). Location theory is presented as providing:

fairly simple models that permit us to highlight some essential principles and factors of human
location. The real world, of course, does not correspond very closely to the patterns projected by
location theory because the human landscape is the complex product of many different forces –
historical, physical, cultural, political, and behavioral, as well as economic (spatial).

Nevertheless, location theory is presented as revealing, ‘the basic spatial order that underlies our
often confusing world . . . the landscape around us makes sense when viewed as the outcome of
human decisions to use land rationally in the context of a particular culture, level of technology, and
physical environment’ (p. xix). Later, however, in a paper on ‘Some important geographic questions’,
Morrill (1985) returned to a strong focus on spatial variables.
A third, highly influential text in this mould was produced by Abler et al. (1971; see Palm,
2003; an important difference is that whereas Haggett’s book was written for UK undergraduate
audiences, based on a course he had developed at Cambridge over the previous eight years, the
Abler et al. book was based on an introductory graduate-level course at Penn State University:
Abler, 1993b, p. 66). Spatial Organization has a stronger focus on positivist methodology (see also
Gould, 1977, 1978). Like Haggett, its authors emphasised the search for order, noting that this was
the prime goal of sciences, that in their view human geography is a social and behavioural science,
and all societies ‘impose order on our experience continual . . . order . . . is a fundamental
requirement of human welfare. The need for order must be fulfilled, even if the order must be
created where none can be discovered’ (Abler et al., 1971, pp. 6–7). Order can be produced in a
variety of ways. They identify four: theological, aesthetic and emotional, common sense, and
scientific; for them, the scientific is the most important because it is ‘adaptable whereas the others
are rigid. Its verification and replication procedures enable [it] to remain viable in the rapidly
changing world it creates. Far more than the others, it is a supra-individual, empirical ordering
system’ (p. 19 – i.e. it is ‘objective’).
For Abler et al. (1971, p. 20) geography’s ‘one basic question [is] “Why are spatial distributions
structured the way they are?”’ (p. 20). Like Haggett, tackling that question needs a textbook that not
only synthesises the relevant available knowledge, but also sets out the methodology for such a task.
Haggett has ‘Methods in locational analysis’ as the second part of his book, introduced by the
statement that ‘Further development of the locational models . . . depends largely on our ability to
test them against existing geographical patterns’ (Haggett, 1965b, p. 185); that ability is set out in
four chapters covering data collection and description, region building and hypothesis testing. For
Abler et al., however, methods take precedence. The first two sections of their book are on ‘Order,
science and geography’ and ‘Measurement, relationship and classification’; only then do they turn
to the substantive material, with sections on ‘Location and spatial interaction’, ‘Spatial diffusion’
and ‘Spatial organization and the decision process’. (Palm, 2003, notes that this emphasis on the
nature of geography as a science reflects Abler’s and John Adams’ experiences as graduate students
Human geography as spatial science 105

at the University of Minnesota, where their adviser was Fred Lukermann, who wrote on that issue
at the time: Lukermann, 1964a, 1964b. To Lukermann –1964b, p. 167 – geographers should focus
on interactions within spatial systems, with their discipline presented as ‘a catalogue of questions,
and the questions – not the phenomena, not the facts, not the method – are geographic’.) Morrill
focused on the substantive material alone, and in a slightly later book Amedeo and Golledge (1975)
used a similar organisation to Abler et al. (1992a) to introduce geographers to scientific reasoning,
especially theory construction.
These textbooks illustrate the centrality of space and distance as the major focus of geographical
interest in the 1960s. An emphasis on observed patterns rather than abstract theoretical arrangements
was noted in King’s (1969b, p. 574) review of ‘The geographer’s approach to the analysis of spatial
form . . . the mathematics which are used and the geometrical frameworks which are favored’.
He focused on descriptive mathematics, which represent ‘what is’ rather than ‘what should be’,
realising that, ‘when they are pursued to their extremes in very formal terms these studies [of ‘what
should be’] run the risk of appearing as seemingly sterile exercises in pure geometry’ (p. 593; see
also King, 1976, 1979b). Geographers had by then not proceeded very far in providing process
theories which would account for observed spatial patterns; however, they were working backwards,
identifying order that called for explanation rather than deducing what the world should be like
from knowledge of human behaviour.
In almost all of this work, space was treated as a continuous variable; there was very little on
its discontinuous nature in some aspects of human organisation. Bounded spaces, at a great variety
of scales, from the largest nation-state through to the ‘bubble of personal space’ around each
individual, were largely ignored by geographers promoting their discipline as spatial science,
perhaps because they found generalisations more difficult to identify than in work on continuous
space. The study of territories had been advanced by a French political geographer (Gottmann,
1951, 1952), whose work had little impact on his American contemporaries (Johnston, 1996c,
2004d); despite his periods of working there, he was ‘outside the project’. Interestingly, some forty
years later Cutter et al. (2002, p. 307) had asked ‘Is there a deeply held human need to organize
space by creating arbitrary borders, boundaries and districts?’ as the second of their ‘big questions
in geography’ (on which, see also Sack, 1986; Elden, 2013).

Spatial theory?
Just as the methodological developments reviewed in the previous chapter lacked clear guidelines
from programmatic statements, the growth of the spatial science viewpoint similarly lacked a
manifesto, at least until Harvey’s (1996a) Explanation in Geography. J. Wreford Watson’s (1955) paper
was not widely referenced (Johnston, 1993b) and the only attempt to provide a lead – apart from
general statements about geography and geometry, such as Bunge’s (1962) – was a paper by
Nystuen in 1963 which reached a wider audience when reprinted in 1968. His objective was ‘to
consider how many independent concepts constitute a basis for the spatial point of view, that is, the
geographical point of view’ (Nystuen, 1968, p. 35). Rather than analyse the ‘real world’ with its
many distorting tendencies, he sought clarity in considering abstract geographies.
To illustrate his basic concepts, Nystuen used the analogy of a mosque completely lacking
furniture (i.e. an isotropic plain) in which a teacher chooses a location at random. The students
then distribute themselves so that they can see and hear the teacher; their likely arrangement is in
semicircular, staggered rows facing and as close as possible to the teacher’s position.This arrangement
has three characteristic features:

1 directional orientation – all students face the teacher, to perceive expressions and to hear
better;
106 Human geography as spatial science

2 distance – the students cluster around the teacher, because audibility diminishes with distance;
and
3 connectiveness – they arrange themselves in rows, organised so that each has a direct line of
sight to the teacher.

The third is in part a function of distance and direction, but not entirely so:

A map of the United States may be stretched and twisted, but so long as each state remains
connected with its neighbors, relative position does not change. Connectiveness is independent
of distance and direction – all these properties are needed to establish a complete geographical
point of view.
(Nystuen, 1968, p. 39)

In addition:

Connections need not be adjacent boundaries or physical links. They may be defined as functional
associations. Functional associations of spatially separate elements are best revealed by the
exchanges which take place between the elements. The exchanges may often be measured by
the flows of people, goods, or communications.

Within the mosque, therefore, the connectivity between teacher and student involves not only
a direct line of sight between them but also a direct flow from one to the other, in this case
of ideas.
Nystuen presented these three concepts as both necessary and (probably) sufficient for the
construction of an abstract geography, grounded in the study of sites (abstract places) rather than
of locations (real places):

The terms which seem to me to contain the concepts of a geographical point of view are
direction or orientation, distance, and connection or relative position. Operational definitions of
these words are the axioms of the spatial point of view. Other words, such as pattern, accessibility,
neighborhood, circulation, etc., are compounds of the basic terms. For abstract models, the
existence of these elements and their properties must be specified.
(p. 41)

Nystuen was unsure, however, whether these three comprised the full set of necessary and sufficient
concepts for a geographical argument (see also Papageorgiou, 1969); boundary might be a
primitive concept too rather than derivative of the basic three, but bounded space was of much less
interest to spatial theorists than continuous space (albeit often transformed: Haggett, 1990; Cliff
and Haggett, 1998).
Nystuen’s general case, that arguments in human geography could be based on a small number
of foundational concepts, was implicitly accepted by much of the work in ‘the spatial tradition’,
although rarely explicitly referred to. Haynes (1975) suggested an alternative approach to writing
theory in human geography, based on the mathematical procedures of dimensional analysis. Five
basic dimensions – mass, length, time, population size, and value – were defined and manipulated
to indicate the validity of functional relationships, such as distance-decay equations (see p. 108, this
book), by checking their internal consistency. His defence of this approach is that:

Although most quantitative geographers would probably claim to be engaged in the discovery of
relationships, it appears that geography has not passed the first stage [in the development of a
science] with any degree of rigor. . . . With no clear idea of which variables are relevant and which
Human geography as spatial science 107

particular characteristics in a system should be isolated, it is pragmatic to define our


measurement scales with regard to a particular set of observations rather than the other way
round. The method of physical science . . . is a superior system, as measurements can be
interpreted exactly, different results compared, and experiments replicated.
(p. 66)

This deductive approach is not as closely tied to a ‘spatial view’ as Nystuen’s but has the same goal
– the derivation of a set of fundamental concepts which can form the basis for writing geographical
theory to be tested in the ‘real world’ (see also Haynes, 1978, 1982).
These attempts at isolating human geography’s primary concepts differed from most contem-
porary efforts at producing geographic theory which, according to Harvey (1967b, p. 212), were
‘either very poorly formulated or else derivative’. Central place theory, for example, was based
entirely on economic postulates about how people behave as ‘rational economic actors’ with regard
to the costs of travel, producing a theory about the size and spacing of settlements. Its attraction for
many was that geographers could contribute their own basic concept to theory development,
without depending totally on other disciplines. Harvey (1970) identified a group of concepts
which could comprise geographical elements in building integrated social science theories –
location, nearness, distance, pattern, morphology; most are compounds of Nystuen’s basic terms.
An example of theory development involving both derivative (from other disciplines)
and indigenous (geographical) concepts was research on spatial diffusion, which received
considerable attention in the late 1960s (Brown, 1968). The basic behavioural postulate, taken
from sociological research, was that word of mouth is the most effective form of communication
about innovations. Geographers introduced the effect of distance on this contact; much interper-
sonal communication is between neighbours, so information about innovations should spread
outwards in an orderly fashion from the initial adopters’ locations. Pioneer work on this hypothesis
was conducted in Sweden by Hägerstrand, who introduced it to the Washington school in the
1950s, where it was taken up by Morrill (1965, 1968, 2002) whose doctoral research was under-
taken in Sweden. Hägerstrand’s major work was made available in an English translation in 1968.
He was in many ways the pioneer of spatial analysis, working almost entirely independently in
Sweden for more than a decade before his ideas were taken up in North America and the UK (see,
for example, the essays on him by Buttimer and Mels, 2006; Persson and Ellegård, 2011); his
studies of migration fields were very early examples of Monte Carlo simulations, for example, and
he was one of the first to realise the potential of computers for spatial analytic research: Hägerstrand,
1967; Morrill, 2005; Buttimer, 2007.
Much subsequent research has been done on diffusion processes and, even more, on patterns
of spatial spread which are assumed to result from diffusion processes (see Abler et al., 1971,
Chapter 11; Brown, 1981; also p. 102, this book), in which the notions of spatial spread across
space and down settlement hierarchies is valid because of the role of direct human contact in the
transmission of many diseases (see Thomas, 1992). The lead in much of this work was provided by
Haggett and Cliff, and included classic spatial epidemiological investigations of influenza, measles
and AIDS, as well as more general studies (e.g. Cliff and Haggett, 1988; Haggett, 1994, 2000;
Smallman-Raynor et al., 2004; Cliff et al., 2009). Changes in communications technology, among
others, have had substantial impacts on these flows, introducing new technical issues (Cliff and
Haggett, 1995).

Social physics and spatial science


Two of Nystuen’s three basic concepts – distance and connectivity – received much more attention
from those advocating geography as a spatial science than the other. Direction was relatively
ignored, except for some work on migration patterns (Wolpert, 1967; Adams, 1969). A substantial
108 Human geography as spatial science

volume of work in spatial science followed the agenda established by the social physics school
(p. 68, this book). The relationship between distance and various types of interaction – migrations,
information flows, movements of goods, etc. – had been identified by several nineteenth-
century workers, such as Carey (1858), Ravenstein (1885; Grigg, 1977; Tobler, 1995) and Herbert
Spencer (1892). Their impact is unclear: McKinney (1968) suggested that Stewart and others were
unaware of the seeds of the ‘gravity model’ and ‘population potential’ ideas in Carey and Spencer’s
writings, and claimed that ‘current geographers could learn much’ (p. 105) from their publications;
Warntz (1968) retorted that Stewart was well aware, although McKinney’s rebuttal pointed out that
Stewart did not refer to them in his 1940s’ papers, only in the 1950s. Ravenstein’s papers, on the
other hand, were very influential on later research into migration patterns. Interestingly, the
pioneering work on distance-decay and the gravity model, as with much of the rest of spatial
science, was done outside geography; as Tocalis (1978, p. 124) expressed it, ‘geographers’
contributions to the theoretical evolution of the gravity concept were minor’, although one major
contributor – Alan Wilson – later ‘became a geographer’ (Wilson, 1984a).
Apart from Stewart’s work, one of the major social physics’ influences on geographers was
George Zipf’s (1949) ‘principle of least effort’. If individuals organise their lives to minimise the
amount of work undertaken and movement involves work, then movement-minimisation is part of
the general principle of least effort. To explain this, Zipf expanded Stewart’s finding that with
increasing distance from Princeton, fewer students from each state attended that university. Two
aspects of work are involved: (1) that needed in acquiring information about the university; and
(2) that needed in travelling there. Thus, the greater the distance between potential students’ homes
and Princeton, the less they are likely to know about the university and the less prepared they will
be to travel there. The validity of this argument was tested against many datasets; material on the
contents of newspapers and on their circulation illustrated the expected distance-decay trend in
information flows, for example, and data on movements between places showed that the greater the
distance separating them, the smaller the volume of inter-place contact.
Zipf called this regularity the P1P2/D relationship, and Stewart noted the analogy between it
and the Newtonian gravity formula, hence its popularisation as the ‘gravity model’. It was fitted to
flow data in many research projects, as shown in Carrothers’ (1956) and Olsson’s (1965) reviews.
To achieve reasonable statistical fits, the various elements of the equation had to be weighted
(P1P2 – the measures of mass at the origin and destination respectively, indicators of interaction-
generation potential; and D – the distance between the two places). Because different weights were
determined empirically in almost all studies, Olsson (1965, p. 48) claimed that the gravity model
of interaction was ‘an empirical regularity to which it has not yet been possible to furnish any
theoretical explanation’. (Wilson, 1967, 1970, later offered a statistical explanation and developed
a whole family of interaction models based on statistical mechanics.) Empirical studies showed that
the strength of the influence of distance varied from place to place, from population to population,
and from context to context, but it was invariably related to the volume of interaction to some
extent; the influence of distance on flow volumes seemed virtually universal, but no available theory
could account for the variability in the strength of its impact.
It was not only in social physics that distance was receiving attention at this time. Economists
and sociologists were becoming increasingly aware of its influence on behaviour (Pooler, 1977),
the former in location theories and Isard’s development of regional science, and the latter in studies
by the Chicago school on urban residential patterns (Johnston, 1971, 1980a). Thus:

a number of geographers became aware of the spatial enquiries that were being undertaken in
a social science context outside their own discipline and, upon realizing their relevance to
geography, proceeded to emulate them. The appearance of the spatial tradition was prompted,
not by discoveries from within geography, but by an awareness and acceptance of investigations
external to the discipline. The space-centred scientific enquiries of other social sciences became
Human geography as spatial science 109

paradigms for geographers, simply because those enquiries, being spatial, were seen to be of
relevance by some practitioners.
(Pooler, 1977, p. 69)

This fitted both the philosophical framework outlined by Schaefer (1953) and the ‘quantitative
revolution’. In adopting spatial viewpoints pioneered in other disciplines, however, human
geographers were frequently selective in what they imported. Work on urban residential patterns
concentrated on certain aspects of the urban sociology of the Chicago school, for example. Robert
Park’s dictum relating social distance to spatial distance stimulated much work on residential
segregation (Peach and Smith, 1981), but the social Darwinism and ecological theory underlying
this dictum was largely ignored (though see Robson, 1969; Entrikin, 1980) and the humanistic
concerns in Park’s work were only identified later when spatial science was losing popularity
(Jackson and Smith, 1981, 1984).
In their spatial analyses some social scientists looked not only at the influence of distance but
also at its meaning and measurement. Stouffer (1940), for example, established a relationship in
which migration between places X and Y was accounted for not so much by the distance between
them, but rather by the number of intervening opportunities. He measured distance in terms of
opportunities; the greater the number of opportunities available locally, the less work that has to be
expended in moving to one. (Berry, 1993, refers to contacts with Stouffer when he was a student
at the University of Washington.) Others followed this flexible approach to measurement of the
basic variable. Ullman (1956), for example, developed a schema for analysing commodity flows in
which the amount of movement between two places was related to three factors:

1 complementarity – the degree to which there is a supply of a commodity at one place and a
demand for it at the other;
2 intervening opportunity – the degree to which either the potential destination can obtain
similar commodities from a nearer, and presumably cheaper, source or the potential source can
sell its commodities to a nearer market; and
3 transferability – for complementarity to be capitalised on, movement between the two places
must be feasible, given channel, time and cost constraints.

This was not as easily tested statistically as the ‘gravity model’ (Hay, 1979b). Fitting such models
also requires accepting that the influence of distance, measured as either time or cost, varies from
place to place and from time to time, producing time – and cost – distance maps that are
transformations of the traditional grid (Abler, 1971; Forer, 1974; Janelle, 1968, 1969). This issue
was taken up by later work on ‘local statistics’ (Fotheringham et al., 2002; p. 153, this book).
Analyses of movement patterns were stimulated not only by their obvious relevance to
geography’s growing spatial science focus and its development of location theories, but also by
their applicability in forecasting contexts. Planning land-use patterns and transport (especially
road) systems became increasingly sophisticated technically during the 1950s and 1960s.
Data analyses showed both the traffic-generating power of various land uses and the patterns of
interaction between different parts of an urban area, with the gravity model being used to describe
the latter. Future land-use configurations were then designed, their traffic-generating potential
derived, and the gravity model used to predict flow patterns and identify needed road systems. Later
models, most based on Ira Lowry’s, assessed different land-use configurations in terms of traffic
flows, thereby suggesting the ‘best’ directions for future urban growth (see Batty, 1978; on the
extent of their application, see Batty, 1989).
The demands for sophisticated planning devices stimulated much research using gravity and
Lowry models. American economists initiated this but it was later taken up by British workers,
including Alan Wilson, who was appointed to a professorship of geography at the University of
110 Human geography as spatial science

Leeds in 1970. (He was trained as a physicist and became interested in traffic forecasting when a
city councillor in Oxford: Wilson, 1984a.) Wilson (1967) derived the gravity model mathematically,
thereby giving it a stronger theoretical base, and extended Lowry’s model into a more general suite
concerned with location, allocation and movement in space (Birkin et al., 1990: see also p. 72, this
book; these later became the foundation of a major commercial operation at the University of
Leeds–GMAP Ltd).
Collaboration between academic geographers and practising planners on these modelling
exercises led to developments which paralleled those in regional science in the USA. Two new
journals in the UK catered for these research areas – Regional Studies and Environment and Planning
(now Environment and Planning A); both attracted contributions and readers from other social
sciences (Johnston and Thrift, 1993; Johnston, 2003a). The new geographical methodology
was proving of considerable applied value, therefore. Careers as planners became extremely
popular among geography graduates in the 1960s and 1970s, and academic geographers’ growing
desire for their discipline to equal that of other social sciences in its policy-making relevance
seemed well on the way to fulfilment. Geographers’ analyses of spatial patterns and interactions
were resulting in applicable models which could be used to identify feasible future locational and
flow patterns.

Systems
The study of systems was introduced to the geographical literature by Garrison (1960a) and
Chorley (1962), although Foote and Greer-Wootten (1968) claimed that systems analysis was
promoted in Sauer’s (1925) programmatic statement The Morphology of Landscape with the words
‘objects which exist together in the landscape exist in interrelation’. More generally, the notion of
a system has a long history, as Bennett and Chorley (1978, pp. 11–14) point out: teleological
traditions, for example, postulate the world as ‘a vast system of signs through which God teaches
man how to behave’ (p. 12), whereas functionalism links observed phenomena together as
‘instances of repeatable and predictable regularities’ of form.
However, the field of modern systems analysis as applied to geography in the 1960s was a
derivation from a Cold War project of managing complex military systems. Developed first at the
American Air Force Research and Development (RAND) ‘think tank’ in Santa Monica, California,
systems analysis embodied postwar American scientific application across a spectrum of science,
engineering, economics, political science and sociology (Collins, 2002; Hughes, 2000). Its impacts
in the late 1950s and early 1960s on both military thinking (warfare strategies and nuclear weapons
systems) and public policy (the growth of centralised top-down decision-making and technocratic
‘expertise’) were profound. Its appeal lay in the bold claims it made to predict trends and outcomes
and the sense of rational order that it claimed to bring to bear on complex problems (at the same
time as moving them out of the arenas of political and public debate). The keystones of such study
of systems were connectivity and prediction. Although geographers made little or no contribution
to developments at RAND or to the status of general systems theory, geography would inevitably be
influenced. Thus, Harvey’s (1969a) Explanation in Geography adopts key aspects of the logic of systems
analysis. He points out that reality is infinitely complex in its links between variables, but systems
analysis provides a convenient abstraction of that complexity in a form which maintains the major
connections (p. 448).
A system comprises three components:

1 a set of elements;
2 a set of links (relationships) between those elements; and
3 a set of links between the system and its environment.
Human geography as spatial science 111

The last component may be absent, creating closed systems. These are extremely rare in reality
(because ‘everything is related to everything else’), but are frequently created for analytical purposes
either experimentally or, more usually in human geography, by imposing artificial boundaries in
order to isolate a system’s salient features. Thus, just as an internal combustion engine comprises a
set of linked elements which receives energy from, and returns spent fuel to, its environment, so a
set of settlements linked by communications networks forms a spatial system, with links to other
settlements outside the defined area of the system providing the contacts with the environment.
A system’s elements have volumetric quantities and material flows along the links; as the system
operates, the various quantities may change.
Systems terminology was widely adopted by human geographers in the 1960s, but much of
the early literature on systems analysis was programmatic rather than applied; it suggested how
the terminology might be applied, often reinterpreting old material (McDaniel and Eliot Hurst,
1968). Relatively few applications were reported, and more than a decade later much of the
literature assessed in a major review was written by other scientists (Bennett and Chorley, 1978).
Nevertheless, Harvey wrote that:

If we abandon the concept of the system we abandon one of the most powerful devices yet
invented for deriving satisfactory answers to questions that we pose regarding the complex
world that surrounds us. The question is not, therefore, whether or not we should use systems
analysis or systems concepts in geography, but rather one of examining how we can use such
concepts and such modes of analysis to our maximum advantage.
(1969a, p. 479)

In seeking answers to this question, two variants on the systems theme have been employed. The
first is systems analysis, which in turn triggered debate about information and the estimation of
order and disorder (under the term entropy); the second is general systems theory, which was an
attempt (no longer considered effective) to provide a more unified science than current disciplinary
boundaries allow.

Systems analysis
Several typologies have been suggested for studying geographical systems (Harvey, 1969a,
pp. 445–9). Chorley and Kennedy (1971) identified four types (Figure 4.2):

1 Morphological systems are statements of static relationships – of links between elements: they
may be maps showing places joined by roads, or equations describing the functional
relationships between variables. Much of the spatial analysis outlined earlier in this chapter
described such morphological systems.
2 Cascading systems contain links along which energy passes between elements: factories
are cascading systems, for example, with the output from one part forming the input
for another. Each element may be a system itself, producing a nesting hierarchy of cascad-
ing systems, as with Haggett’s (1965c) nodal regions and the input–output matrix
representation of an economy (Isard, 1960). Berry (1966) linked these two examples
of cascading systems in his interregional input–output study of the Indian economy.
Within each element, the material flowing through is manipulated in some way (the
industrial process in a factory, for example). The nature of the manipulative process may be
ignored entirely in the investigation, with focus on the inputs and outputs only;
such a representation of the element is termed a black box. White-box studies investigate
the transformation process, whereas grey-box analyses make a partial attempt at their
description.
112 Human geography as spatial science

A C
A A O
MORPHOLOGICAL PROCESS-RESPONSE
SYSTEM SYSTEM

5 C B c

B □ A
C
CASCADING A CONTROL
O
SYSTEM SYSTEM

B C

Figure 4.2  Types of system: A, B and C indicate system elements, I represents input, O represents output,
and in the control system A is a value

Source: Chorley and Kennedy, 1971, p. 4.

3 Process-response systems are characterised by studies of the effects of linked elements on each
other. Instead of focusing on form, as in the first two types, these are studies of processes, of
causal interrelationships. In systems terms these may involve, for example, the effects of one
variable, X, on another, Y; in the analysis of spatial systems they could involve the effect of
variable X in place a on variable Y in place b, as with the transmission of a disease from one
area of a country to another.
4 Control systems are special cases of process-response systems, having the additional
characteristic of one or more key elements (valves) which regulate the system’s operation and
may be used to control it.

Attention focused on process-response and control systems. Langton (1972), for example,
suggested that the former provide an excellent framework for studying change in human geography.
He identified two subtypes. Simple-action systems are unidirectional in their nature: a stimulus in
X produces a response in Y, which in turn may act as a stimulus to a further variable, Z. Such a causal
chain merely reformulates ‘the characteristic cause-and-effect relation with which traditional
science has dealt’ (Harvey, 1969a, p. 455); in another language it is a process law. The second
subtype comprises feedback systems. According to Chorley and Kennedy (1971, pp. 13–14),
‘Feedback is the property of a system or subsystem such that, when change is introduced via one
of the system variables, its transmission through the structure leads the effect of the change back to
the initial variable, to give a circularity of action’. Feedback may be either direct – A influences B,
which in turn influences A (Figure 4.3a) – or it may be indirect, with the impulse from A returning
to it via a chain of other variables (Figure 4.3b). With negative feedback the system is maintained
in a steady state by self-regulation processes termed homeostatic or morphostatic: ‘A classic example
is provided by the process of competition in space which leads to a progressive reduction in excess
profits until the spatial system is in equilibrium’ (Harvey, 1969a, p. 460). But with positive feedback
the system is characterised as morphogenetic, changing its characteristics as the effect of B on C
leads to further changes in B, via D (Figure 4.3d).
The concept of feedback, with the associated notions of homeostasis and morphogenesis,
provides ‘the nuclei of the systems theory of change’ (Langton, 1972, p. 145). In many spatial
systems, feedback may be uncontrolled; others may include a regulator, such as a planning policy
Human geography as spatial science 113

A D
DIRECT
A B A B C
FEEDBACK
POSITIVE
B FEEDBACK D
C
LOOPED
FEEDBACK
A B

C E
A B C A B C
NEGATIVE NO
FEEDBACK FEEDBACK
D D

Figure 4.3  Various types of feedback relationships in systems

Source: Chorley and Kennedy, 1971, p. 14.

(Bennett and Chorley, 1978). There were few geographical studies of such feedback processes,
however. For homeostatic systems, Langton cited investigations of central place dynamics in which
the pattern of service centres is adjusted as the population distribution changes, to reproduce the
previous balance between supply and demand factors (Badcock, 1970). Morphogenetic systems are
illustrated by Pred’s (1965b) model of the process of urban growth, in which expansion in a sector
generates further growth there, as in Myrdal’s (1957) more general theory of cumulative causation.
Such systems modelling has been used to predict urban futures (Forrester, 1969). In most of these
studies the input from systems theory was relatively slight, however, leading Langton (1972,
pp. 159–60) to the paradoxical conclusions that:

First, there is little correlation between the extent of the penetration of the ter­minology of
systems theory and the rigorous application of its concepts. The empty use of terminology, which
is typified by the use of the term feedback as an explanatory device rather than as a description
of a fundamental research problem, must be counter-productive in a situation in which the
terms themselves may be given many subtle different shades of meaning. . . . Second, some-
what paradoxically, many of the concepts of systems theory are already used in geography
without the attendant jargon and without apparently drawing direct inspiration from the litera-
ture of systems theory.

One of the most substantial attempts to apply systems theory to a problem in human geography
was Bennett’s (1975) study of the dynamics of location and growth in north-west England. Having
represented the system – its elements, links and feedback relationships – he estimated the influence
of various external (i.e. national) events on the regional system’s parameters, isolated the effects of
a government policy on the system’s structure, and forecast the region’s future spatiotemporal
morphology. He developed the forecasting aspects of this methodology in later papers (Bennett,
1978a, 1979), suggested how an optimal distribution of government grants could be achieved
Bennett, 1981a), and outlined the likely spatial variation in the impact of a new tax (the ‘poll tax’:
Bennett, 1989a; see also Hepple, 1989).
114 Human geography as spatial science

One area of investigation which firmly adopted the systems approach covers the intersection
of human and physical geography. The ecosystem is a process-response system involving energy
flows through biological environments, most of which include, or are affected by, people. It is also
a control system whose living components regulate the energy flows: ‘they further represent
a major point at which human control systems must intersect with the natural world’ (Chorley
and Kennedy, 1971, p. 330). Most naturally occurring ecosystems are homeostatic for much of the
time (see Chapman, 1977, Chapter 7), but human ‘interference’ often transforms them into
morphogenetic systems, with potentially catastrophic effects (Johnston, 1989).
Stoddart (1965, 1967b) argued that the ecosystem should be employed as a basic geographical
principle, as did other programmatic statements (e.g. Clarkson, 1970), including two based on the
associated concept of community (Morgan and Moss, 1965; Moss and Morgan, 1967). But
Langton’s conclusion about relatively little substantive research in human geography based on
systems’ thinking remained valid (see Grossman, 1977). Similar attempts, but involving less con-
sideration of the biotic environment, were made in allied disciplines, and were occasionally
imported into the geographical literature. Sociologists’ human ecosystem models (e.g. Duncan,
1959; Duncan and Schnore, 1959) were used as frameworks for investigating migration (Urlich-
Cloher, 1972) and urbanisation (Urlich-Cloher, 1975), for example, and the operational research
techniques of economists, with their important feedback mechanisms, stimulated work in trans-
port geography (e.g. Sinclair and Kissling, 1971).
The most comprehensive early attempt to forge a systems approach to geographical study was
Bennett and Chorley’s book (1978), written to provide ‘a unified multi-disciplinary approach to
the interfacing of “man” with “nature”’ (p. 21), with three major aims:

First, it is desired to explore the capacity of the systems approach to provide an inter-disciplinary
focus on environmental structures and techniques. Secondly, we wish to examine the manner
in which a systems approach aids in developing the interfacing of social and economic theory,
on the one hand, with physical and biological theory, on the other. A third aim is to explore the
implications of this interfacing in relation to the response of man to his current environmental
dilemmas. . . . It is hoped to show that the systems approach provides a powerful vehicle for the
statement of environmental situations of ever-growing temporal and spatial magnitude, and for
reducing the areas of uncertainty in our increasingly complex decision-making arenas.

This task involved elucidating not only the ‘hard systems’ of physical and biological sciences but
also the ‘soft systems’ characteristic of the social sciences. The latter cover a large and fertile literature
concerned with, first, the cognitive systems describing people as thinking beings and their decision-
making systems (as individuals and in groups) and, second, the socioeconomic systems made up
of very many of these interacting individuals and groups. They then attempt to interface the two
types, because:

in large-scale man-environment systems the symbiosis of man as part of the environment of the
system he wishes to control introduces all the indeterminacies of socio-economic control
objectives. . . . In particular, we need to ask what are the political and social implications of
control, and for whom and by whom is control intended?
(p. 539)

Their essay ends with a discussion of the substantial problems involved in such interfacing, many
of which are firmly tackled in the text.
Use of systems analysis in human geography assumes (usually implicitly) that valid analogies
can be drawn between human societies on one hand and both natural phenomena-complexes and
machines on the other. Individual system elements have predetermined roles, and can only act and
Human geography as spatial science 115

change in set ways, depending on the system’s structure and its interrelationships with the
environment. As a descriptive device, this analogy allows the structure and operation of society and
its components to be portrayed and analysed, providing a source of ideas from which hypotheses
can be generated (see Coffey, 1981). And once a system has been defined and modelled, systems
analysis can predict the likely nature of the elements and links following certain environmental
changes (such as the introduction of new elements and/or links, as in the classic Lowry model used
to predict the impact of new land-use configurations on traffic flows: Batty, 1978).
The potential fertility of this analogy was examined in Wilson’s (1981a) discussion of methods
for analysing environmental systems. He defined environment as ‘natural, man-nature, and
manufactured “systems of interest”’ (p. xi), in all of which ‘the main concern is with complicated
systems whose components exhibit high degrees of interdependence. The behaviour of the “whole”
system is then usually something very much more than the sum of the parts’ (p. 3). He argued that
moorland ecosystems, water resource systems and cities (his three initial examples) can all be
studied in the same way and set out available methods for that; a further book (Wilson, 1981b)
presented the mathematics for studying systems in which the rates and directions of change
suddenly alter, and he returned to the topic in a later summary volume (Wilson, 2000). Huggett
(1980) similarly argued that systems analysis has wide applications in both human and physical
geography, plus the interface where people and environment interact (see also Huggett and  Thomas,
1980). Once a system has been successfully modelled, it can be manipulated using control theory:
‘a dynamic optimization technique . . . [that] permits optimal allocation over long time horizons
. . . [and] shifts emphasis from mere model construction to model use’ (Chorley and Bennett,
1981, p. 219). Such a combination of models describing systems with a theory of system control
has a wide range of potential applications, according to Chorley and Bennett, in such fields as
pollution control, catchment management, inter-area resource allocation and urban planning. It
suggests a commonality of interest, focused on methods, between applied physical and applied
human geography.

Systems theory, information and entropy


A system has been defined here so far as a series of linked elements interacting to form an operational
whole. This was challenged by Chapman who opened his book with:

I do not think that the concept of a system will have any great operational consequences in
geography for a long time yet. It represents an ideal that the real world does not fully approach.
On the other hand, in conceptual terms I think the concept is extremely important and useful,
and that it has a great and immediate role to play for those who are about to plan the strategy of
their research. As a framework for analysis, it has no current peers.
(1977, p. 6)

For Chapman, a system comprises a series of elements which can take alternative states, and his
definition – following Rothstein (1958) – is:

A system is a set of objects where each object is associated with a set of feasible alternative
states: and where the actual state of any object selected from this set is dependent in part or
completely upon its membership of the system. An object that has no alternative states is not a
functioning part but a static cog.
(p. 80)

An example is a number of farms, each comprising a series of fields: every farmer has to decide
how to use those fields. Each decision will in part reflect the farm’s general operations and the uses
116 Human geography as spatial science

to which all other fields are put; in part, too, it will be a function of the external market and the
decisions made by other farmers regarding use of their own fields. Thus, there is a large number of
possible states for the system of fields – different configurations of land uses. According to Chapman,
systems analysis should involve investigating those configurations and placing the observed pattern
within the context of the alternatives:

to theorize merely about what does exist is not very useful. If we restrict ourselves to that alone,
all explanation will be merely historical accidental. At all stages it is most important to include
consideration of what else could have been. The definition of organization in a system even
explicitly requires the assessment of what else could have been.
(pp. 120–1)

Taylor and Gudgin (1976) argued similarly in a different context: instead of simply asking ‘is
there a bias [towards one political party] in the electoral districting of a borough?’, they ask ‘what
is the likelihood of a bias occurring, given the system constraints?’ (the number of different ways
that the districts could be constructed). This allowed them to then set the study of electoral
districting, the aggregation of spatial units into constituencies and its consequences, on a strong
statistical footing (Gudgin and Taylor, 1979; Johnston et al., 2001; Johnston, 2012).
Such analyses focus on one configuration of the system as a sample from a set of possible
configurations, and among their key concepts is entropy. In the second law of thermodynamics an
increase in system entropy involves an increase in uncertainty, as with the introduction of a layer of
hot water to a body of cold water. Initially, the two are separate, and one can be completely certain
about the location of the hot molecules, for example. But with no external influence the two slowly
mix, until all are at the same temperature. As the mixing proceeds, so the entropy increases.
Social scientists have drawn their usage of entropy from two separate, though linked,
definitions. Thermodynamic entropy relates to the most probable configuration of the elements
within the system constraints, as just illustrated. In information theory, entropy refers to the
distribution of the elements across a set of possible states, and is an index of element dispersion.
One can be completely certain about a distribution, in terms of predicting where one element will
be, if all elements are in the same state; conversely, one will be most uncertain when elements are
equally distributed through all possible states, so that prediction of the location of any one element
is most difficult. (See Webber, 1977, and  Thomas, 1982, on the relationship between entropy and
uncertainty.)
In its simplest form, the information-theory measure of entropy is another descriptive index,
but it can be developed in a variety of ways. Chapman (1977) illustrates three uses:

1 as a series of indices of variations in population distributions;


2 as an index of redundancy in a landscape, where redundancy is defined as relating to a regular
sequence so that it is possible to predict the land use at place ‘a’ from knowledge of the land
uses at neighbouring places; and
3 as a series of measures of reactions to situations in states of uncertainty.

In general terms, these continue the tradition of Stewart and Warntz’s macrogeography
(p. 68, this book): the aim is to describe a pattern rather than to explain it, although the nature of
the constraints used to derive the entropy measures provides an input to explanatory modes of
analysis (Webber, 1977).
The use of entropy as developed in statistical mechanics was introduced to the geographical
literature by Wilson’s (1970) extensions to the gravity model. His initial example was a flow matrix.
The number of trips originating in each of a series of residential areas is known, as is the number
ending in each of a series of workplace areas, but the entries in the cells of the matrix – which
Human geography as spatial science 117

people move from which residential area to which workplace area (the flow pattern) – are
unknown. What is the most likely flow pattern? Even with only a few areas and relatively
small numbers of commuters, the number of possibilities is very large. Wilson defines three
system states:

1 The macro-state comprises the number of commuters at each origin and the number of jobs
at each destination.
2 The meso-state consists of a particular flow pattern: five people may go from zone A to zone
X, for example, and three from the same origin to zone Y, but it is not known which five are
in the first category and which three in the second.
3 Finally, a micro-state is a particular example of a flow pattern – one of the many possible
configurations of eight people moving from zone A, five to X and three to Y. Entropy-
maximising procedures find that meso-state associated with the largest number of micro-
states; the most probable distribution is that with the greatest number of micro-states giving
rise to it. (For illustrations, see Johnston and Pattie, 2000, 2003.)

The most likely (maximum likelihood) distribution corresponds to the position where we are
most uncertain about the micro-state of the system, as this has the largest possible number of such
states and we have no grounds for choosing between them. This approach, too, follows the
macrogeography tradition. It is not an attempt at explanation and Wilson sees his work illustrating:

the application of the concept of entropy in urban and regional modelling; that is, in hypothesis
development, or theory building. [‘Model’ and ‘hypothesis’ are used synonymously, and a theory
is a well-tested hypothesis.] . . . the entropy-maximizing procedure enables us to handle
extremely complex situations in a consistent way.
(pp. 10–11)

In reviewing Wilson’s presentation, Gould (1972, p. 689) termed it ‘the most difficult I have
ever read in geography’ but continued, ‘he has planted a number of those rare and deep concepts
whose understanding provides a fresh and sharply different view of the world’.
The hypothesis that the entries in the flow matrix conform to the most likely distribution can
be tested against ‘real’ data. If it is falsified, either entirely or in part, it can be refined by building
in more constraints.Wilson does this with intra-urban transport models, for example, by introducing
travel-cost constraints, different types of commuters (class, age, etc.), different types of jobs, and so
on. The aim is to describe the most likely system structure from a given amount of information,
which is incomplete. He subsequently developed both the theory of his modelling and the
substantive applications (see Wilson, 1981a). A general text (Wilson, 1974) introduced a whole
family of models that can be used to represent, and then forecast, the various components of a
complex spatial system such as an urban region. Some of these models were expanded (e.g. Rees
and Wilson, 1977, on demographic accounts) and applied, with varying success, to the West
Yorkshire region (Wilson et al., 1977).
Wilson’s work was applied and developed by others (see Batty, 1976, 1978, for example),
though rarely in other contexts. Michael J. Webber (1977) extended Wilson’s argument that the
purpose of entropy-maximising models is to draw conclusions from a dataset that are ‘natural’ in
that they are functions of that dataset alone and contain no interpreter bias. For him, they provide
a convenient way of organising thinking about a complex world, and he identifies an ‘entropy-
maximizing paradigm’ (p. 262). At Leeds, Wilson’s work on the entropy-maximising approach was
extended into the field of micro-simulation (Ballas et al., 2002; Birkin and Clarke, 1988, 1989;
Clarke and Holm, 1988; Clarke, 1996; Williamson et al., 1998) which produces statistically reliable
estimates of micro-level characteristics of a population from macro-data. Given the number of
118 Human geography as spatial science

people in each age group in each of a number of small areas, for example, and, separately, the
number with cancer and the cross-tabulation of age by cancer for a larger area comprising those
small areas, it lists the individuals in each area in each age group who are estimated to have cancer;
as with entropy-maximising, these are the maximum-likelihood estimates given the constraints
(the number of people in an age group with cancer in all of the small areas must equal the sum for
the larger area).
One of the few examples of the application of entropy-maximising models to other research
contexts is in electoral geography. It may be, for example, that information on the number of votes
for each party in each district at each of two elections suggests that the number of voters who
changed their choice between the elections varied across districts, but no district-by-district data
are available to see if this is the case. Johnston (1985b) adapted Wilson’s method to address this
issue using national survey data on party-switching as a constraint to enable estimates of the volume
and direction of switching in each district. Tests using available data have shown that the estimates
are generally very accurate representations of the actual patterns (Johnston and Pattie, 2000, 2003),
and the method has been employed in a large number of applications to demonstrate that there are
significant spatial variations in various form of electoral behaviour (Johnston and Pattie, 2001).
They also linked it to other attempts to tackle one of the major statistical issues in quantitative social
science – the solution of the ecological inference problem. This relates to how individual
relationships and behaviour can be inferred from aggregate data, such as differences between ethnic
groups in their turnout at elections and spatial variations in those differences, when there are no
data on turnout by ethnic group only on the ethnic composition and turnout rates of different areas
(King, 1997; Johnston and Pattie, 2001).
In emphasising aggregate patterns, this work is macrogeographic; according to Webber (1977,
p. 265), ‘The entropy-maximizing paradigm asserts . . . that, though the study of individual behavior
may be of interest, it is not necessary for the study of aggregate social relations.’ The patterns
predicted by the models are functions of the constraints (the information provided at the meso-
state), so that knowledge of them means that ‘the entropy-maximizing paradigm is capable of
yielding meaningful answers to short-run operational problems’ (p. 266) of immense value for
immediate planning purposes. But:

in the longer run, much of the economic system is variable: the constraints and the spatial form
of the urban region may change . . . the research task facing entropists is (1) to identify the
constraints which operate upon urban systems, which is partly an economic problem; (2) to
deduce some facets of the economic relations among the individuals within the system from the
use of the formalism; and (3) to construct a theory which explains the origins of the constraints.
Only when the third task has been attempted may the paradigm be adequately judged.
(p. 266)

The entropy-maximising model acts not only as a ‘black-box’ forecasting device (see p. 111, this
book), therefore, but also as a hypothesis: if a system’s operation is to be understood, the axioms
– the constraints – must themselves be explained. Given the nature of the constraints (in Wilson’s
initial example, why people live where they do, why people work where they do, and why they
spend a certain amount of time, money and energy on transport), the task is a major one: entropy-
maximising models aim to clarify it and indicate the most fruitful avenues for investigation.

Dynamic processes
The study of systems allows dynamic processes to be incorporated within geographical analyses,
instead of focusing on static patterns that are the outcomes of such processes. Thus, much of the
mathematical development reviewed has been concerned with such processes, to advance
Human geography as spatial science 119

understanding of change and the ability to forecast it. (On the use of the term ‘process’ in this
context, see the critique by Hay and Johnston, 1983.) Dynamical systems theory and analysis were
the focus of a major research programme conducted at the University of Leeds by Alan Wilson and
his associates from the mid-1970s, for example, during which a number of major advances were
made; in particular, attention was directed away from relatively straightforward linear modelling to
complex representations in which change is presented as discontinuous and not necessarily
unidirectional – often termed chaotic (see Wilson, 1981b).
Many geographical analyses of dynamical systems have focused on static spatial patterns or
structures, representing these as equilibrium or steady-state situations within the ongoing dynamic
processes. Change is then handled, as Clarke and Wilson (1985, p. 429) describe it, ‘by forecasting
(in some other theory or model) the independent variables associated with a system and then
calculating the new equilibrium or steady state’. (There are parallels here with Darby’s approach to
historical geography, linking cross-sections through narratives of change, see p. 96, this book.)
Their applications of dynamical systems analysis suggest that this approach is not tenable, however,
because in complex systems ‘There are too many possibilities of transition to different kinds of
equilibrium or non-equilibrium states’ (Clarke and Wilson, 1985, p. 431), which casts doubts on
the validity of the traditional approach to forecasting and hence the contribution of geographical
modelling to planning. The nature of that contribution must be rethought, therefore, because
conditional forecasting is of little value – ‘there are simply too many possible futures for this to be
useful’ (p. 446). The new contributions, they argue, could involve the following:

First, it may often be possible to recognize the ‘nearness’ of some instability or structural shift
to an undesirable state. Policy can then be focused on conservation. Secondly, it may be possible
to see how to bring about a shift to a new desired state by changing policy in order to move a
parameter through some critical value. Thirdly, both the ideas of dynamical analysis and the
capabilities of modern computer technology lend themselves to the construction of planning
systems focused on information retrieval . . . and monitoring, so that at least planners, and
policy makers are in a position to respond more rapidly when difficulties are identified.
(p. 446)

Geographers thereby come more to terms with the inherent complexity, and hence unpredict-
ability, of the world.

The theory of systems and general systems theory


Like regional science and the impact of Walter Isard, the development of General Systems Theory
(GST) was very much tied up with the work of one person – Ludwig von Bertalanffy (1950). He
focused on isomorphisms, the common features among the systems studied in different disciplines:
GST’s ‘subject matter is the formulation and derivation of those principles which are common for
systems in general’ (Walmsley, 1972, p. 23). The goal was to write meta-theories with rules that
apply in a variety of contexts; application was usually by analogy from one discipline to another (as
in Chappell and Webber’s, 1970, use of an electrical analogue of spatial diffusion processes and in
work on artificial intelligence using computer modelling: Couclelis, 1986a). GST was presented as
offering geographers an organising framework, an empirical exercise using inductive procedures to
fashion general theories out of the findings of particular disciplines (Coffey, 1981).
Although it was claimed that there have been no advances in either the theoretical base or the
empirical application of GST (Greer-Wootten, 1972), some advances were made using models of
one system as metaphors for understanding another. Woldenberg and Berry (1967) drew analogies
between the hierarchical organisation of rivers and central-place systems, for example; Berry
(1964b) argued that cities are open systems in a steady state, as exemplified by the stability of their
120 Human geography as spatial science

behaviour-describing equations; several authors (e.g. Ray et al., 1974) applied the concept of
allometry – that the growth rate of a component of an organism is proportional to the growth
of the whole; and Haggett (1965c, p. 22; 1990) was attracted to D’Arcy Thompson’s 1917 work
On Growth and Form, which ‘illustrates how many subjects find common ground in the study
of morphology; there is inspiration still to be found in his treatment of crystal structures or
honeycomb formations’ (see also Werritty, 2010).
Some analysts were attracted to the concept of fractals (Goodchild and Mark, 1987, p. 265). If a
line is measured at two scales, the second larger than the first, then we might expect its length to
increase as a ratio of the two scales. In many areas of geography, however, this is unlikely to be the case:
as the scale of a map increases (i.e. the representative fraction falls and more detail is shown) the
length of a line – such as a stretch of coast – will probably increase by more than the ratio of the scales,
because extra detail is added. Fractals are the geometrical objects that operate in this manner; even
though the two lines may be generated by the same process (i.e. they are technically self-similar so
that, for example, any part has the characteristic features of the whole), at different scales more detail
can be shown. The concept was extensively used by Batty and Longley (1994) in analyses of urban
form – both the shapes of entire built-up areas and those of their component parts; identification of
fractal regularities allowed them to simulate urban growth and change (see also Batty, 2007).
According to its proponents, GST’s advantages for human geography lie in its interdisciplinary
approach, its high level of generalisation and its concept of the steady state of an open system
(Greer-Wootten, 1972; Walmsley, 1972), but they also contended that geography’s strong empirical
tradition means that it has more to contribute than to take from GST. One critic, however, claimed
that ‘General systems theory seems to be an irrelevant distraction’ (Chisholm, 1967, p. 51).
Chisholm summarised the case for GST as follows:

1 there is a need to study systems rather than isolated phenomena;


2 there is a need to identify the basic principles governing systems;
3 there is value in arguing from analogies with other subject matter; and
4 there is a need for general principles to cover various systems.

He argued that something as grand as a meta-theory is unnecessary in order to convince people of


the need to understand what they study, of the value of interdisciplinary contact, and of the potential
fertility of arguing by analogy. His case was generally accepted, and references to GST soon
disappeared from the discipline’s literature.
Yet although a considerable number of programmatic statements were written about the
benefits of adopting a system approach in human geography, relatively few applications were
reported outside a small number of topical areas: the study of land use and transport patterns, as in
the many analyses by Wilson and his co-workers already discussed; the study of input–output
matrices (for examples, see Isard, 1975); and the study of population changes. With the last of
these, for example, Robert Woods (1982) promoted a more theoretical approach to population
geography than had previously characterised the subdiscipline, with an emphasis on systems, and
with Rees he edited a pioneering collection of essays launching an approach termed ‘spatial
demography’ (Woods and Rees, 1986). Many of the essays in the latter treated the three main
components of a population system – birth, death and migration – in a multiregional spatial
systems framework, which addressed the issue:

Given that the characteristics of the population vary in interesting ways across space and that
their time paths of development may be very different . . . how do we represent the processes of
demographic change in formal models which will make the predictions about the future path of
development possible?
(Rees, 1986, p. 97)
Human geography as spatial science 121

The nature of the proposed accounting systems for interregional population changes was set
out in detail in Rees and Wilson (1977).
A further area in which systems thinking was suggested concerns the interrelation-
ships between society and nature, including ecology. There were some attempts to integrate the
two through input–output and related models (as in Bennett and Chorley, 1978) and a number
of authors presented flow diagrams of human–nature interrelationships that portrayed them as
systems (as in Blaikie, 1985; Cooke and Reeves, 1976; Goudie, 1986a; Huggett, 1980; and Wilson,
1981a). In general, however, the concept of a system has been applied much more by physical than
by human geographers. A small group of the latter has continued to work on the formal
representation of spatial systems. Wilson (2000, p. vii) claimed some thirty years after his first
essays into the area that such modelling of urban and regional systems remained underdeveloped,
yet had enormous potential for policy-making and planning; for him, geography’s ‘classical
theorists’ remained von Thünen, Weber, Palander, Hoover, Hotelling, Christaller and Lösch, Burgess,
Hoyt, Chauncy Harris and Ullman, plus the original formulators of the gravity model.

Spatial separatism?
Opposition to arguments for human geography as a spatial science developed largely as counters to
claims for its separate status within the social sciences, with distance as the key variable. Crowe
(1970), for example, portrayed using the spatial variable in nomothetic studies as naive spatial
determinism.
The most sustained argument against geography as a spatial science – what he called the
‘spatial separatist’ theme – came in a series of papers by Sack, a former associate of Lukermann at
the University of Minnesota (see p. 82, this book). Reality has three dimensions – space, time and
matter – and geography, according to the spatial separatist view, is the science of the first. Sack
contended that space, time and matter cannot be separated analytically in an empirical science,
however, and that geometry is not an acceptable language for such a science (Sack, 1972). Geometry
is a branch of pure mathematics that is not concerned with empirical facts; its laws are static, with
no reference to time, and they are not derivable from any dynamic or process laws.
Geographic facts have geometric properties (e.g. locations) but if, as Schaefer (1953) proposed,
geographical laws are just concerned with the geometries of facts, they will provide only incomplete
explanations for them. To illustrate this contention, Sack used an analogy of chopping wood. If the
answer to the question ‘Why are you chopping wood?’ is ‘because the force of the axe on impact
splits the wood’, then it is a static, geometric law; but if the answer is ‘to provide fuel to produce
heat’, then it is an instance of a process law, which incorporates the geometric law. In this analogy,
a process law is equated with the intention behind an action. The static laws of geometry are
sufficient to explain and predict spatial patterns, so that if geography aimed only to analyse points,
lines and shapes on maps it could be an independent science using geometry as its language. But
‘We do not accept the description of the changes of its shape as an explanation of the growth of a
city’ (p. 72), so that ‘Geometry alone, then, cannot answer geographic questions’ (p. 72), leading
to the conclusion that (p. 77):

To explain requires laws and laws (if they are valid) explain events. Since the definition
of an event implies the delimitation of some geometric properties (all events occur in space),
the explanation of any event is in principle an explanation of some geometric properties of
events.
  Thus geography will be closely allied with geometry in its emphasis on the spatial aspects of
events (the instances of laws), but geometry alone is insufficient as a basis for explanation and
prediction since no processes are involved in the derivation of geometries.
122 Human geography as spatial science

Bunge’s (1973a) response claimed that spatial prediction was quite possible with reference to
the geometry alone, as instanced by central place theory and Thünian analysis of land use patterns.
Such geometries provide ‘classic beauty’, and ‘purging geometry from geography reduces our trade
to no apparent gain’ (p. 568). Sack (1973a) replied that the static laws espoused by Bunge are only
special cases of dynamic laws having antecedent and consequent conditions, and that:

Although the laws of geometry are unequivocally static, purely spatial, non-deducible from
dynamic laws, and explain and predict physical geometric properties of events, they do not
answer the questions about the geometric properties of events that geographers raise and they
do not make statements about process.
(p. 569)

Sack did not argue, as Bunge supposed, that geometry should be purged from geography,
only that space should not be considered independently from time and matter. He further
contended that:

for a concept of physical space to conform to the rules of concept formation and be useful in a
science of geography every instance of the geometric or spatial terms must be connected or
related to one or more instances of non-geometric terms (to be called substance terms).
(1973b, p. 17)

Thus, physical distance is not a concept in itself; it is necessary to know the terrain that a road
crosses, for example, in order to assess the significance of its length in a gravity model – geometry
alone is not enough. Since there is no such thing as empty physical space, there are no frictions of
distance per se. There are frictions which demand work in crossing a substance, but the substance
itself and the context in which it is being crossed create the frictions (such as transport costs), not
simply the distance: ‘There are frictions and there are distances, but there is no friction of distance’
(Sack, 1973b, p. 22). Geography, according to Sack, is concerned to explain events and so requires
substantive laws; such laws may contain geometric terms, such as the frictions of crossing a
substance, but these terms alone are insufficient to provide explanations.
The spatial separatist approach proposes an independent position for geography within
the social sciences using geometry as its language, but Sack (1974b, p. 446) contended that ‘The
spatial position’s aim of prying apart a subject matter from the systematic sciences by arguing for
spatial questions and spatial laws does not seem viable’. Instead, two types of law relevant to
geographical work must be identified (Sack, 1974a):

1 Congruent substance laws are independent of location: statements of ‘if A, then B’ are universals
which require no spatial referent.
2 Overlapping substance laws, on the other hand, involve spatial terms: ‘if A, then B at C’ contains
a specific reference to location.

Both are relevant and necessary in answering geographical questions, so no case can be made for a
necessary ‘spatialness’ to human geography’s substance laws.
Extending his argument, Sack (1981, pp. 3–4) contended that ‘Space is an essential framework
of all modes of thought’ but ‘geographic space is seen and evaluated in different ways at different
times and in different cultures’. His book illustrated this by examining several approaches to the
study of space: that of the social scientist concerned with objective meanings of space; that of
the social scientist concerned with subjective meanings; the practical view of people who live
in and learn about space (he used children as his example); the mythical and magical views of
space; and the societal conceptions within which organisations and institutions structure and use
Human geography as spatial science 123

space. Only the first of these is the concern of ‘spatial separatists’, whose approach takes space out
of its relational context, with the consequence that ‘Ignoring spatial relations or conceiving them
non-relationally will hinder the discovery and confirmation of social science generalizations’
(p. 85).
J. A. May (1970, p. 188) also argued against Schaefer’s claim that geography is the study of
spatial relations:

If we extend Schaefer’s argument to include time, and assign the study of temporal sequences
or relations to the historian, then the only conclusion respecting this matter that can be drawn
is that economic, social, political, and other relations must be non-spatial and non-temporal.
Hence economics, sociology, political science, etc. are non-spatial, non-temporal sciences. But
this is absurd . . . insofar as economics qualifies as a science possessing empirical warranty,
then its generalizations must apply to given spatio-temporal situations.

If all sciences have a spatial content, what defines a separate discipline of geography? May lists five
possibilities:

1 Geography is a ‘super-science’ of spatial relations, ‘a generalizing science of spatial relations,


interactions and distributions’ (p. 194) drawing on the findings of other sciences. This would
leave the latter truncated and their studies unfinished. Such an approach had already proved
unsuccessful; ‘the issue of the conception of geography as a generalizing or law-finding science
that somehow stands above the social sciences and history is not even appropriately debatable’
(p. 195).
2 Geography is a lower-level science of spatial relations, applying in empirical contexts
the laws of higher-level, generally more abstract sciences. (This may be a valid description of
much of the geography produced in the 1960s.) This again truncates the latter sciences
and raises the question: ‘What differentiates economic geography from economics, and vice
versa?’.
3 Geography is the study of geographical spatial relations. This implies that there are spatial
phenomena not studied in other social science disciplines and which can therefore be claimed
as geography’s; May could conceive of no objects which are purely geographical (or, in the
parallel argument, purely historical either).
4 Geography is the study of ‘things in reality’ spatially. Yet again, this abstracts from other
sciences; May admits that certain ‘bits and pieces’ are not studied elsewhere, but argues that
they do not offer a satisfactory empirical foundation for a separate discipline.
5 ‘Geography is not a generalizing or law-finding science of spatial relations’ (p. 203).

The first four indicate that, because of the analytical indissolubility of time, space and matter, all
social sciences are concerned with spatial relations, so that May, like Sack, argued that geography
cannot claim an independent status on the basis of the spatial variable and the geometrical aspects
of space alone. R. P. Moss (1970, p. 27) reached a similar conclusion:

geometrical relationships must be assigned economic, social, physical, or biological meaning


before they can in any sense become explanatory . . . though geometries may be important tools
in geographical study and research, they cannot be a source of theory since their analogy with
geographical phenomena is simply through particular logical structures, and not through
explanatory deduction . . . such an application implies that space, area, distance, etc., are
important in and of themselves, quite independently of any implications they may have in terms
of diffusion, of cost, of time, or of process. This is manifestly false.
(p. 27)
124 Human geography as spatial science

Derek Gregory (1978b, 1980) also criticised the extremely narrow, even superficial, view of
spatial processes identified in many spatial scientists’ work. Their claims are instrumentalist,
involving theories which cannot be validated conclusively but can only be evaluated pragmatically
against the real world. He argued that Bennett (1974), for example, accepted that his models
did not mirror actual processes but assumed that they did in order to allow policy formulation
(and therefore produced self-fulfilling prophecies – as Lukermann had argued: see p. 82, this
book); because they can postdict the world as it presently is, it is assumed that they explain it and
can be used to predict the future.
The arguments reviewed in this section were critical of much of the work undertaken by
geographers in the paradigm debate over which dominated the 1960s, impelled by the ‘Victorian
myth of the supremacy of the natural sciences’ (Gregory, 1978a, p. 21). The case for spatial analysis
continued to be argued, however. Gatrell (1983), for example, countered Sack’s critique of spatial
science – while accepting his case that the separation of space from substance is untenable. He did
not confine spatial analysis to a positivist philosophy, however, stating that:

My response to both structuralists and humanists is that, since they too deal with relations
(among individuals or social groups, or between man and his environment), they cannot avoid
the notion of space, since any relation defines a space. Moreover, because every relation has a
geometry associated with it . . . they cannot avoid the fact that geometry underlies much of what
they deal with. Structures . . . are intrinsically spatial, but not in any simple geographical sense.
(p. 5)

Gatrell’s definition of space is much broader than simply distance, therefore, and he promoted
spatial analysis not as a separate paradigm of geography, but as an arsenal of tools to be used in all
empirical research. Much of that research, he argued elsewhere (Gatrell, 1985, p. 191), involves
portraying objects arranged in space, investigating the role of distance as a constraint on human
spatial organisation and achieving efficiency in locational arrangements.

Behavioural geography
Although not apparently directly influenced by the arguments of Sack and others regarding
geography and geometry, by the end of the 1960s some critiques of ‘quantitative and theoretical
geography’ were being articulated on the grounds that testing of models of spatial organisation and
behaviour based on rational decision-making dominated by monetary criteria (and hence, in
geography, minimising transport costs) were not substantially aiding understanding. They were too
simplistic in their assumptions about how people make decisions and behave. Instead, there were
calls for more ‘realistic’ modelling based on observed rather than assumed decision-making
processes.
These proposed modifications to the spatial-science approach stimulated work that became
known as ‘behavioural geography’, whose birth was announced in a key collection of essays (Cox
and Golledge, 1969) that would be revisited twelve years later in a companion volume (Cox and
Golledge, 1981), and which was further synthesised in two editions of a major textbook (Golledge
and Stimson, 1987, 1997). Its essential ingredients, as set out by Golledge and Timmermans
(1988), were:

1 a search for models which were alternatives to those of normative location theory based on
economically and spatially rational beings;
2 a search to define environments other than objective physical reality as the milieux in which
human decision-making and action took place;
Human geography as spatial science 125

3 an emphasis on process rather than structural explanations of human activity and the physical
environment;
4 an interest in unpacking the spatial dimensions of psychological, social and other theories of
human decision-making and behaviour;
5 a change in emphasis from aggregate populations to the disaggregate scale of individuals and
small groups;
6 a need to develop new data sources other than the generalised mass-produced aggregate
statistics of government agencies which obscured and over-generalised decision-making
processes and consequent behaviour;
7 a search for methods other than those of traditional mathematics and inferential statistics that
could aid in uncovering latent structures in data, and which could handle datasets that were
less powerful than the traditionally used interval and ratio data; and
8 a desire to merge geographic research into the ever broadening stream of cross-disciplinary
investigation into theory-building and problem-solving.

Towards a behaviouristic spatial science


The main ground for disillusion with ‘spatial science’ was thus a growing realisation that many
of the models being propounded and tested provided poor descriptions of reality; progress towards
the development of geographical theory was painfully slow and its predictive powers consequently
weak. The large body of work based on central place theory, for example, was built on axioms
regarding human behaviour regarding choice between spatial alternatives, from which a settlement
pattern was deduced. But the deductions were often only weakly reflected in settlement morpho-
logies. The theory suggested how the world would look under certain circumstances of economic
rationality in decision-making on an isotropic plain; that those circumstances did not prevail sug-
gested that the world should be looked at in other ways in order to understand how people structure
spatial organisation. As Brookfield put it with regard to the models then popular:

We may thus feel that we have proceeded far enough in answering our questions when, by
examination of a sufficient number of cases, we can make assertions such as the following:
population density diminishes regularly away from metropolitan centres in all directions; crop
yields diminish beyond a certain walking distance from the centres of habitation; air-traffic
centres lying in the shadow of major centres do not command the traffic that their populations
would lead us to expect. . . . Such answers, which represent the mean result of large numbers of
observations, whether statistically controlled or otherwise, are valuable in themselves, and
sufficient for many purposes. But each is also an observation demanding explanations which
may seem self-evident, or which may in fact be very elusive. Furthermore, there will be
exceptions to each generalization, and in many cases, there are also limits to the range of
territory over which they hold true. Both the exceptions and the limits demand explanation.
(1964, p. 285)

The concern was, therefore, not with the basic goal of establishing generalisations and theories, but
rather the route being taken to that goal. Better models than those of ‘rational economic man’ were
needed, and their search took a more inductive route than previously followed. Rather than base
hypotheses on assumptions about behaviour, models were to be constructed that replicated observed
behaviour.

Rationality in land-use decisions


Some of the earliest attempts by geographers to explore behaviour inductively, as a prelude to later
modelling, were investigations of human responses to floods and other environmental hazards
126 Human geography as spatial science

initiated at the University of Chicago during the late 1950s and early 1960s. Their director was
Gilbert White, whose own thesis on human adjustment to floods was published in 1945, and who
has been described as ‘the outstanding geographer in the man–land [sic] tradition, in the study
of natural resources and hazards, and the study of the human environment’ (Kates and Burton,
1986b, p. xi). (White is one of the most honoured of geographers, having been awarded both the
Public Welfare Medal of the National Academy of Sciences, its highest award, in 2000 and the
National Medal of Science in 2001: Turner, 2002, p. 68; these aren’t mentioned in White’s 2002
autobiographical essay.) Water resources were his main focus, in which ‘he found himself a leader
in the newly developing geography of perception, the world inside people’s minds’ (p. xi; Kates and
Burton, 1986a, provides a collection of his writings and of valedictory essays; see also Hinshaw,
2006; Macdonald et al., 2012).
Gilbert White’s associates developed a behaviourist approach for studying reactions to hazards
based on Herbert Simon’s (1957) theories of decision-making. Roder (1961), for example,
categorised Topeka residents according to their attitudes to the probability of future floods there,
concluding that:

Flood danger is only one of the variables affecting the choices of the flood-plain dweller, and
many considerations operate to discourage a resident from leaving the flood plain, even when he
is aware of the exact hazard of remaining.
(p. 83)

Such behaviour did not fit easily into notions of profit-maximising decision-making. Alternative
theories were needed.
A major exponent of this behaviouristic approach was Kates (1962, p. 1), whose study of
flood-plain management began: ‘The way men [sic] view the risks and opportunities of their
uncertain environments plays a significant role in their decisions as to resource management’. Kates
developed a schema for studying such decision-making based on four assumptions:

1 People are rational when making decisions. Such an assumption may be either normative/
prescriptive – describing how people should behave – or descriptive of actual behaviour.
The latter seemed most fruitful, both for understanding past decisions and for predicting
those yet to be made. Kates suggested adoption of Simon’s (1957) concept of bounded
rationality. Decisions are made on a rational basis, but in relation to the environment as it is
perceived by the decision-maker, which may be quite different from either ‘objective reality’
or the world as seen by the researcher. Rational decision-making is constrained, therefore, and
is not necessarily the same as the maximum rationality assumed in the neoclassical normative
models discussed earlier; people make decisions in the context of the world as they observe
and interpret it, which may differ from others’ perceptions (including those of geographers
studying them).
2 People make choices. Many decisions are either trivial or habitual and accorded little or no
thought immediately before they are made (Kahneman, 2012). Some major decisions
regarding environmental use may also be habitual, but such behaviour usually develops only
after a series of conscious choices has been made, which may generate a stereotyped response
to future similar situations.
3 Choices are made on the basis of knowledge, which is usually only partial. Only very rarely can
decision-makers bring together all the information relevant to their task, and they are
frequently unable to assimilate and use all that is available.
4 Information is evaluated according to predetermined criteria. In habitual choice the dominant
criterion is what was done before, but in conscious choice the information must be weighed
according to certain rules (individually determined, though usually in a social context). Some
Human geography as spatial science 127

normative theory prescribes maximising criteria (of profits, for example); descriptive theory
may use Simon’s notion of satisficing behaviour, involving decision-makers who seek a
satisfactory outcome only (a given level of profit, perhaps, as in Rawstron’s, 1958, industrial
location theory: see Smith, 1981).

Models based on such behavioural axioms are likely to differ very substantially from those
which assume not only rationality but also complete information, perfect decision-making ability
and common goals. As Kates (1962, p. 16) describes his model, ‘men [sic] bounded by inherent
computational disabilities, products of their time and place, seek to wrest from their environments
those elements that might make a more satisfactory life for themselves and their fellows’. As a
consequence:

Thus, a descriptive theory of choice must deal with the well informed and the poorly informed
and the choices that men make under certainty, risk or uncertainty . . . such a theory must deal
with the eventuality that not only do the conditions of knowledge vary, but the personal perception
of the same information differs.
(p. 19)

People behave rationally, but within constraints, many imposed by their context – the local cultures
in which they have been socialised to make decisions.
The results of decision-making that do not match the predictions from the theories employed
by normatively inclined spatial scientists do not imply irrational behaviour, therefore. Most
decisions are made rationally on the basis of, probably non-random, selections of information,
are intended to satisfy a goal which does not imply making a perfect decision, and are based on
criteria which vary somewhat from individual to individual. Having learned a satisfactory solution
to a given class of problems, decision-makers apply it every time such a problem occurs, unless
changed circumstances require a re-evaluation.
Kates wanted to understand why people chose to live in areas that are prone to flooding. Their
information was based on their knowledge and experience, and they varied in the certainty of their
perceptions regarding further floods. In justifying their decisions, most were boundedly rational;
they made conscious choices to satisfy certain objectives. Similar findings were reported by others of
White’s co-workers and had impacts on public policy formulation internationally (White, 1973,
2002), covering a wide range of environmental hazards such as floods, water management and
desertification (Burton et al., 1978). Their initial impact on the wider geographical enterprise was
not great, however, especially in the early years of their work, perhaps because they were operating
close to the boundaries between human and physical geography. Later work in other fields brought
Simon’s ideas more forcefully before geographical audiences, however. These articulate with the
question of the boundaries of human and physical geography – a theme we return to in Chapter 10.

The decision process in a spatial context


In the 1960s human geographers were introduced to the behaviourist approach by Julian Wolpert’s
(1964) paper, based on his Wisconsin Ph.D. thesis with field data from Sweden. The normative
theory then espoused by many geographers assumed a rational economic decision-maker who:

is free from the multiplicity of goals and imperfect knowledge which introduce complexity into
our own decision behavior. Economic Man has a single profit-maximizing goal, omniscient
powers of perception, reasoning, and computation, and is blessed with perfect predictive abilities
. . . the outcome of his actions can be known with perfect surety.
(p. 537)
128 Human geography as spatial science

In the study of spatial patterns, however, ‘Allowance must be made for man’s finite abilities to
perceive and store information, to compute optimal solutions, and to predict the outcome and
future events, even if profit were his only goal’ (p. 537). Farmers face an uncertain environment –
both physical and economic – when making the decisions that in aggregate result in a land-use
map. Wolpert suggested that differences between these decisions and those that would be made by
‘economic man’ reflect aspects of the farmers’ economic and social environments.
Comparing the observed labour productivity of farms in an area of Sweden with what could
have been achieved under optimising decision-making, Wolpert decided that the farmers were
probably satisficers, although such a conclusion is difficult to verify without detailed knowledge of
aspiration levels. How they acted was undoubtedly contingent upon their available information,
and he argued that spatial variations in the levels of potential productivity achieved were the con-
sequences of parallel spatial variations in knowledge. Only conspicuous alternatives are considered,
it was suggested, and the result is rational behaviour, adapted to an uncertain environment. Gould
(1963, 1965) approached a similar subject – land-use decisions in Tanganyika – using a different
approach based on the mathematical theory of games. (See also Chapman, 1982, who uses games
to illustrate decision-making in uncertain situations.)
Wolpert (1965) continued his theme regarding the role of information with studies modelling
the decision-making behind observed aggregate patterns of migration. He contended that the
gravity model is inadequate to represent such flow patterns; indeed, ‘Plots of migration distances
defy the persistence of the most tenacious of curve fitters’ (p. 159; see also Taylor, 1971). Rational
individuals make sequential decisions: first, whether to move, and second, where to, doing both on
the basis of place utilities – their evaluations of the degree to which each potential location,
including that currently occupied, meets defined needs. The information on which these utilities
are computed is invariably far from complete; indeed, for many places people have none. Each
individual has an action space – ‘the set of place utilities which the individual perceives and to
which he responds’ (Wolpert, 1965, p. 163) – whose contents may deviate considerably from that
portion of the ‘real world’ which it purports to represent. Once the first decision – to migrate – has
been made, then the action space may be changed as the would-be mover searches for potential
satisfactory destinations and, if necessary, extends the space if no suitable solution to the search can
be found (see Brown and Moore, 1970).
Wolpert’s papers heralded the development of behavioural geography (Cox and Golledge, 1969,
pp. 1–3), an approach ‘united by a concern for the building of geographic theory based on postulates
regarding human behaviour . . . upon social and psychological mechanisms which have explicit
spatial correlates and/or spatial structural implications’. Early work focused on topics related to
decision-making in spatial contexts, much of it involving researchers associated with the Ohio State
University. Golledge (1969, 1970), for example, looked at models of learning about space and of
habitual behaviour therein, and with Brown investigated methods of spatial search (Golledge and
Brown, 1967). Others researched the information flows on which decisions are based, indicating the
influence of local context on behaviour (Cox, 1969), and Brown and Moore (1970) extended
Wolpert’s place utility and action space concepts for the study of intra-urban migration.
The fundamental aim of behavioural geography, according to a review by Golledge et al. (1972,
p. 59), is to derive alternative theories to those based on ‘economic man’, ‘more concerned with
understanding why certain activities take place rather than what patterns they produce in space’. This
involves ‘the researcher using the real world from a perspective of those individuals whose decisions
affect locational or distributional patterns, and . . . trying to derive sets of empirically and theoretically
sound statements about individual, small group, or mass behaviors’. Individuals are active decision-
makers, not passive reactors to institutionally created stimuli (Cox and Golledge, 1981).
In evaluating such behaviouristic endeavours, Golledge et al. (1972) indicated the seminal
influence of Hägerstrand’s (1968) use of the concept of a mean information field (analogous to the
action space of a place’s residents) to model migration flows and the adoption of innovations.
Human geography as spatial science 129

Further developments included a series of pioneering papers by Wolpert and his associates
on political decision-making. Regarding the distribution of certain artefacts in the landscape,
Wolpert (1970, p. 220) pointed out that the location of, for example, a public facility in an urban
area is frequently the product of policy compromise:

Sometimes the location finally chosen for a new development, or the site chosen for a relocation
of an existing facility, comes out to be the site around which the least protest can be generated
by those displaced. Rather than being an optimal, a rational, or even a satisfactory locational
decision produced by the resolution of conflicting judgements, the decision is perhaps merely
the expression of rejection by elements powerful enough to enforce their decision that another
location must not be used. . . . These artefacts are rarely ‘the most efficient solutions’, and
frequently not even satisfactory neither for those responsible for their creation nor for their
users.

(This argument avoids considering any definition of optimal, in either economic or political
terms.) Such decisions involve what Wolpert terms ‘maladaptive behaviour’. Kates and others had
suggested that decisions are adaptively rational, within the constraints of uncertainty, utility
and problem-solving ability. Coping strategies under the mutual exchange of threats between
interested parties can involve decision-making which does not involve the careful and methodical
investigation of alternatives until a satisfactory solution is found, however. Instead, decisions are the
consequences of conflict between groups with different attitudes and motivations, and are not the
result of joint application of criteria on whose relevance there is a consensus.

This formulation lays the framework for the interpretation of locational decisions which appear
to be more the product of pressurised responses than the end result of a dispassionate and
considered selection of alternatives posited by the classical normative approaches or even the
Simon scheme of bounded rationality.
(Wolpert, 1970, p. 224)

The approach was applied in a variety of contexts, such as the routes for intra-urban freeways and
the siting of community mental-health facilities (Wolpert et al., 1975). Many of the outcomes of
such decision-making processes reflected the uneven distribution of power among the various
groups of participants.

Mental maps
One concept enthusiastically adopted by a number of workers was that of a mental map of the
environment, which guides a decision-maker’s deliberations. The term was not new to the
geographical literature, having been used in Wooldridge‘s (1956) descriptions of the perceived
environments within which farmers make land-use decisions. Gould (1973) revived it in 1966, in
a seminal, widely circulated discussion paper, which included his guiding belief that:

If we grant that spatial behavior is our concern, then the mental images that men hold of the
space around them may provide a key to some of the structures, patterns and processes of Man’s
work on the face of the earth.
(p. 182)

Increasingly, he argued, location decisions involve perceived environmental quality, so it is


necessary to know how people evaluate environments and whether their views are shared by their
contemporaries. To investigate such questions, Gould asked respondents in various countries to
130 Human geography as spatial science

rank-order locations according to their preferences for them as places in which to live, and these
rankings were analysed to identify their common elements – the group mental maps (Gould and
White, 1974, 1986). Such maps, he argued, are useful not only in the analysis of spatial behaviour
but also in planning social investments, such as offering differential salaries to attract people to less
desirable areas (Gould and Ola, 1970).
Those who followed Gould’s lead investigated a range of methods for identifying and analysing
spatial preferences (Pocock and Hudson, 1978). Their results made little impact on theoretical
development, however, and Downs (1970, p. 67) wrote that:

Even the most fervent proponent of the current view (that human spatial behaviour patterns can
partially be explained by a study of per­ception) would admit that the resultant investigations have
not yet made a significant contribution to the development of geographic theory.

Apart from Gould’s rank-ordering procedures, Downs identified two other major approaches to the
study of environmental images. The structural approach enquires into the nature of the spatial
information stored in people’s minds and which they use in their everyday lives – Kevin Lynch’s
(1960) book was a model for such work: his five-element categorisation of urban environments
based on map-drawing exercises comprised paths, boundaries, districts, nodes and landmarks as
the main components of the urban scene identified by users. The evaluative approach addresses the
question: ‘What factors do people consider important about their environment, and how, having
estimated the relative importance of these factors, do they employ them in their decision-making
activities?’ (Downs, 1970, p. 80).
With this latter approach geographers moved into the wider field of cognitive mapping –
‘a construct which encompasses those cognitive processes which enable people to acquire, code,
store, recall and manipulate information about the nature of their spatial environment’ (Downs and
Stea, 1973, p. xiv). Although medical technologies (based on brain scanning) would only be
applied decades later, some of the pioneers of behavioural geography worked alongside both
psychologists, who were becoming increasingly interested in the individual’s relationship to a
wider area than the proximate environment and the development of relevant non-experimental
research techniques, and designers concerned with creating more ‘liveable’ environments. The
journal Environment and Behavior was launched in 1969 to cater for this interdisciplinary market, but
despite some interest (e.g.  Tuan, 1975a; Downs and Stea, 1977; Pocock and Hudson, 1978;
Porteous, 1977), the general field has not made a major impact within human geography. Gold
(1992) argued that although a small number of scholars have continued working in this area, the
challenges from other types of work (see Chapters 5–7 below) meant not only that it failed to
develop into a large component of the discipline, but also that it was marginalised, as both passé
and tainted with the generally perceived problems of positivism. Gold quotes Cloke et al. (1991) as
presenting cognitive-behavioural geography as forming ‘something of a “bridge” leading from the
“peopleless” landscapes of spatial science through to the “peopled” landscapes of humanistic
geography’ (Gold, 1992, p. 242). The impression he gives is of a small specialism ‘retaining a
precarious autonomy on the fringes of human geography’ (p. 246).
The concept of ‘mental map’ and the associated process of ‘cognitive mapping’ – which ‘seems
to imply the evocation of visual images which possess the kinds of structural properties that we are
familiar with in “real” cartographic maps’ (Boyle and Robinson, 1979, p. 60) – became the centre
of considerable debate both among behavioural geographers and between them and outside critics.
Gould’s initial work, and that which it stimulated, was criticised as the study of space preferences
only (Golledge, 1981a; see also Golledge, 1980, 1981b; Guelke, 1981a; Robinson, 1982). But, as
Downs and Meyer (1978, p. 60) made clear, ‘perceptual geography’ – ‘the belief that human
behaviour is, in large part, a function of the perceived world’ – extends much further than the
elicitation and mapping of space preferences.
Human geography as spatial science 131

The basic arguments of behavioural geography are that:

1 people have environmental images;


2 those images can be identified accurately (i.e. quantitatively) by researchers (as in landscape
evaluation: Penning-Rowsell, 1981); and
3 ‘there is a strong relationship between environmental images and actual behaviour’ (Saarinen,
1979, p. 465).

The nature of those images – whether they are maps in the generally understood sense of that word
and whether they can be apprehended by researchers – remained a problem; the concept of a
‘mental map’ may be a red herring but, to behavioural geographers, the argument on which it is
based is not. (For an early review of research into cognitive mapping, see Golledge and Rushton,
1984.) Similarly, the concepts of cognitive mapping were increasingly used in work on the history
of cartography (on which, see Lewis, 1998).

Time-geography
One area of work sometimes identified as behavioural, but which extends into the humanistic and
realist philosophies discussed in later chapters, was developed by Hägerstrand from the late 1960s
on and introduced to a wider audience by Pred (1973, 1977a; Persson and Ellegård, 2011; Sui,
2012). As interpreted by Carlstein et al. (1978), time and space are resources that constrain activity.
Any behaviour requiring movement involves individuals tracing a path simultaneously through
space and time, as depicted in Figure 4.4, where movements along the horizontal axis indicate
spatial traverses and those along the vertical signify the passage of time. All journeys, or lifelines,
involve movement along both and are displayed by lines that are neither vertical nor horizontal;
vertical lines indicate remaining in one place; horizontal lines are not possible for people, though
they are (or virtually so) for the transmission of messages (see Adams, 1995).
Movement in space and time is constrained in three ways, according to Hägerstrand:

1 capability constraints include the biological need for about eight hours sleep in every twenty-
four, and movement across space is constrained by the available means of transport;

time

II

a space

Figure 4.4  The time–space prism. In this simple example, a person cannot leave place a until time I and
must return there by time II; the prism between those two times indicates the maximum available spatial
range of travel
132 Human geography as spatial science

2 coupling constraints require certain individuals and groups to be in particular places at stated
times (teachers and pupils in schools, for example) and thus limit the range of mobility
during ‘free time’; and
3 authority constraints may preclude individuals from being in stated places at defined times.

Together, these three define the time–space prism (Figure 4.4) which contains all the possible
lifelines available to an individual who starts at a particular location and has to return there by a
given time.
Pred (1977a, p. 207) claimed that time-geography ‘has the potential for shedding new light
on some of the very different kinds of questions customarily posed by “old-fashioned” regional
and historical geographers, as well as “modern” human geographers’ because:

It is . . . a great challenge . . . to cease taking distance itself so seriously . . . to accept that space
and time are universally and inseparably wed to one another; to realize that questions pertaining
to human organisation of the earth’s surface, human ecology, and landscape evolution cannot
divorce the finitudes of space and time . . . it is a challenge to turn to the ‘choreography’ of
individual and collective existence – to reject the excesses of inter- and intradisciplinary
specialization for a concern with collateral processes.
(p. 218)

Thus, time-geography was in part a critique of spatial analysis as currently practised by human
geographers. For Hägerstrand it was much more, however, because he was addressing problems
concerned with the quality-of-life implications of packing people together in space and time; for
example, we are enabled to

see existing together what we otherwise have chosen to see apart. Neighbour meets neighbour
in some sort of association. My concern now will be with how their presence together has come
about, how they go along together and what is going to happen ahead in time.
(Hägerstrand, 1984, p. 375)

To explore what Pred (1977a, p. 213) calls the ‘principle of togetherness’, Hägerstrand
employed three concepts:

1 Paths (or lifelines in the earlier terminology) are ‘successions of situations’ (Hägerstrand,
1982, p. 323) traced by individuals. To study paths alone is just to map outcomes (in the same
way that geographers map migrations or shopping trips); investigation of the path alone may
reveal very little about the purpose and meaning behind the events that it incorporates, because
it tells nothing about the ‘living body subject, endowed with memories, feelings, knowledge,
imagination and goals – in other words capabilities too rich for any conceivable kind of
symbolic representation but decisive for the direction of paths’ (p. 324).
2 Projects, goals and strategies for project fulfilment are the activities which generate paths,
whose intersections produce situations, particular moments in the flow of history in particular
places.
3 Dioramas. Geographical study of paths and projects has traditionally involved the concept of
landscape, devised to represent ‘the momentary thereness and relative location of all
continuants’ (p. 325). Hägerstrand claimed that this concept insufficiently incorporates ‘the
human body subjects, the keepers of memories, feelings, thoughts and intentions and initiators
of projects’ (p. 320) and preferred the concept of diorama, normally used to denote static
museum displays which depict people and animals in their usual environments. The concept
implied to Hägerstrand that ‘All sorts of entities are in touch with each other in a mixture
Human geography as spatial science 133

produced by history, whether visible or not . . . [we] appreciate how situations evolve as an
aggregate outcome quite apart from the specific intentions actors might have had when they
conceived and launched projects out of their different positions’ (p. 320).

Hägerstrand illustrated his concepts with a description of his childhood home, demonstrating
the importance of coupling, authority and capability constraints on the flow of daily life and the
dioramas (particular situations) that resulted; Pred (1979) applied the concepts to his academic
career. The study of paths alone is insufficient if time-geography is adequately to portray the ‘real
life of real people’ (Hägerstrand, 1982, p. 338), however; thus autobiographical material (as in
Buttimer, 1983; Billinge et al., 1984) provides an important source on projects and dioramas
because ‘Only one’s own experience is able to provide the kind of intimate detail which can bring
the study of project and situation into any real depth. He is after all an expert on his own networks
of meanings’ (Hägerstrand, 1982, p. 338).
Most interpretations and applications of Hägerstrand’s initial work focused on the study of
paths, and were set in the positivist mould of other behavioural geography enterprises. Indeed, this
aspect of time-geography was the only one presented in an introductory review by Thrift (1977),
who emphasised that a ‘“physicalist” approach is the backbone’ (p. 4). With it, for example, Parkes
and Thrift (1980) sought ‘to place time firmly in the minds of human geographers’ (p. xi) in an
approach they termed ‘chronogeographical’, arguing that ‘Together, territories, societies and times
are the principal components of urban and social geography’ (p. 34); this focus on the meaning
and construction of time in historical contexts was very substantially extended by Glennie and
Thrift (1996).
The concept of diorama, and the ‘togetherness’ of a situation that it denotes, were absent from
these early presentations, apart from passing references such as Thrift’s (1977, p. 7), quoting
Hägerstrand (1975), that ‘every situation is inevitably rooted in past situations’. Projects were also
mentioned, as in Thrift’s (1977, p. 7) statement that ‘All human beings have goals. To attain these
they must have projects, series of tasks which act as a vehicle for goal attainment and which, when
added up, form a project’, but it was implicit that those projects can be treated in the same sort of
aggregate data analysis and policy prescription mould that characterise most behavioural geography
(see Palm and Pred, 1978). Van Paassen (1981) argued that Hägerstrand’s work is essentially
humanistic, however, aiming ‘to provide insight into what is specifically human in man’s nature and
. . . [to] elucidate the specific human situation’ (p. 18), a case accepted by Hägerstrand (1982) in
his reference to human intentions (Pred, 2005; see also Thrift, 2005).
The concept of diorama later led authors to associate Hägerstrand’s work not so much with the
humanistic approaches outlined in the next chapter, but rather with the realist proposals discussed
in Chapter 6. The social theorist Giddens (1984), for example, drew heavily on Hägerstrand in his
arguments for a structurationist approach (see p. 221, this book). (Note, however, Gregson’s, 1986,
critique of Giddens’s attempts to incorporate time-geography into structuration theory, but also
Gregory’s, 1985a, p. 329, contention that time-geography ‘must draw on substantive theories of
structuration for its explications of contingency and necessity’.) In all these applications, however,
authority constraints and their associations with bounded spaces have been largely ignored, with
continuous time–space the dominant concern.
Most criticisms of time-geography focused on the physicalist description of paths. Thus, Baker
argued that:

While space and time may usefully be considered as resources whose competitive allocation gives
rise to patterns of use which may be observed empirically and modelled theoretically, the nature
of that human struggle to control and structure time and space – the process underlying the form
– should be of paramount concern rather than descriptions of temporal or spatial organisation.
(1979, p. 563)
134 Human geography as spatial science

As with other aspects of spatial science, description of outcomes, however sophisticated,


cannot elucidate the processes involved in their production. (Processes here are defined as
mechanisms, the products of human agency, and not just sequences: see Boots and Getis, 1978;
Haining, 1981; Hay and Johnston, 1983.) Thrift and Pred responded to Baker by denying his
physicalist interpretation; to them:

time-geography is much more than that. It is a discipline-transcending and still evolving


perspective on the everyday workings of society and the biographies of individuals. It is a highly
flexible and growing language, a way of thinking about the world at large as well as the events
and experiences, or content, of one’s own life.
(1981, p. 277)

They argued that ‘time-geographers’ are necessarily concerned with underlying processes, with the
ideological uses of time and space as devices to channel individual paths, and with the crucial role
of human agency in the production of particular situations. They tied time-geography into Giddens’s
ideas on structuration and also with developing Marxist humanism, concluding that:

Some see the graphs used in time-geography as just neat pieces of art but others, in turn, are
able to internalize the perspective represented by the graphs and use the path and project
language as a way of thinking about themselves and the world. This will we believe be the lasting
legacy of time-geography.
(p. 284)

Baker’s (1981, p. 440) response was largely positive, accepting that time-geography could be of
value in a reorientation of geographical work: ‘we should be examining the social organisation of
space and time, not the spatial and temporal organisation of society for this is to put the cart before
the horse’. Gregory (1985a) was more cautious, however, arguing that Hägerstrand too readily
focused on paths rather than on the people whose projects fashion those paths, thereby failing to
explore the meanings that are hidden beneath the tasks that produce the biographies. (Elsewhere,
Gregory, 1994, implied that the fault is more with those applying Hägerstrand’s ideas than with
Hägerstrand himself; others – e.g. Ellegård and Svedin, 2012 – have illustrated the importance of
Hägerstrand’s concepts to the study of certain types of behaviour, as in transport geography.)
Hägerstrand’s papers were written before the ‘information technology revolution’ which
enabled the almost instantaneous transmission of information to multiple sites around the globe
and promised virtual reality, whereby people in one place could operate as if in another. This led
Paul Adams (1995) to promote a reconsideration of what he termed ‘personal boundaries in space-
time’, using Janelle’s (1973) concept of ‘personal extensibility’, which he defines as ‘the ability of
a person (or group) to overcome the friction of distance through transportation or communication’
(P. Adams, 1995, p. 267). As that ability increases and ‘distant connections become easier to
maintain’ (p. 268), so interaction patterns alter, to the extent that ‘Some believe that time-space and
cost-space convergence have reached the point that one’s location is of little or no significance for
an increasing variety of interactions.’ Extensibility promotes the transcendence of place, breaking
down the crucial role of spatially bounded locales (see p. 213, this book) as interaction containers.
Thus, people are both point-entities and extensible persons. They comprise:

A) a body rooted in a particular place at any given time, bounded in knowledge gathering by the
range of unaided sensory perception and, in action, by the range of the unaided voice and grasp;
and B) any number of fluctuating, dendritic, extensions which actively engage with social and
natural phenomena at varying distances. This dynamic entity depends on media.
(p. 269)
Human geography as spatial science 135

Acceptance of this argument requires a reworking of the importance of the presence/absence


distinction in much analysis of human behaviour, and a new form of social geography (heralded,
Adams argues, by Melvin M. Webber in 1964). It implies the need to distinguish between the
geography of the body from that of the person: the former is grounded in space–time, but
technology removes that constraint for the latter, with many implications for the exercise of power
and responsibility.

Methods in behavioural geography


Whereas early theory- and model-builders of the spatial-science school of human geographers
derived much of their stimulus from neoclassical economics, in some cases via regional science, the
alliance for behavioural geography was mainly with other social sciences, notably psychology and
sociology. The behaviouristic approach is largely inductive, aiming to build general statements out
of observations of ongoing processes. The areas studied were very much determined by the work
in the spatial-science school, however. As Brookfield’s statement quoted earlier suggests (p. 125,
this book), the spatial-scientists’ models and theories, such as central place theory, raised many of
the queries which the behaviourists followed up, stimulated by observations of the theories’ failings
when matched against the ‘real world’. In terms of the accepted route to scientific explanation (see
Figure 3.1), therefore, behavioural geography involved moving outside the accepted cyclic
procedure to input new sets of observations on which superior theories might be based. In doing
this, it did not move far from the spatial-science ethos, and many of the methods were those used
in that work.
Somewhat away from this general orientation of behavioural work, Pred (1967, 1969)
presented an ambitious alternative to theory-building based on ‘economic men’ in a two-volume
work Behavior and Location. His critique of location theory was based on three groups of objections
concerned with:

1 logical inconsistency – it is impossible for competing decision-makers to arrive at optimal


location decisions simultaneously;
2. motives – maximising versus satisficing behaviour; and
3. capacity – human ability to collect, assimilate, manipulate and use all possible information.

To Pred (1967, p. 17):

Bunge’s theoretical geography is easily distinguished from geographical location theory because
its optimal final goals are disassociated from the interpretation of real-world economic
phenomena . . . and because these same goals can only yield a body of theory that for all intents
and purposes is totally abehavioral and static rather than dynamic.

Location and land-use decisions are made with imperfect knowledge by fallible individuals and as
a consequence there is bound to be disorder in the ensuing spatial patterns. (For another critique,
see Barnes, 1988.)
As an alternative, Pred proposed a behavioural matrix (Figure 4.5), whose axes are quantity
and quality of available information and ability to use that information; completely informed
rational decision-makers occupy the bottom right-hand corner. Because of the nature and
importance of information flows, decision-makers’ positions on the first axis partly depend on
their spatial locations; positions on the second reflect aspiration levels, experience and the norms
of any groups to which the individuals belong (many of which are spatially bounded). Different
people in the same matrix position could vary in their decisions, therefore, if they acted on different
information and in the pursuit of different goals, even if their stores of knowledge and ability to
136 Human geography as spatial science

Figure 4.5  The behavioural matrix

Source: Pred, 1967, p. 25.

use them were volumetrically commensurate. Similarly, people occupying different positions could
make the same decision, based on different information and/or different ways of using it.
Individuals do not stay at the same position in the matrix; as they learn and react, so their
positions change. Pred’s (1969) second volume introduced a dynamic element, by shifting
individuals through the matrix; as they make decisions, they change the environment in which they
and others operate. As people learn, they may both acquire more and better information, and
become more skilled in its use; they shift towards the bottom right-hand corner of the matrix,
some of them in advance of others who benefit from the decision-leaders’ experience. The
unsuccessful are gradually eliminated, so that a concentration of ‘good’ decision-makers close to
the optimum position evolves, although new entrants to the matrix will probably not be located
there. Changes in the external environment (such as market prices for farmers or the closure of
some outlets for shoppers) generate parametric shocks, however, which result in decision-makers
becoming less informed and less certain; as a consequence, they are shifted back towards the upper
left-hand corner and another learning cycle begins. As long as parametric shocks occur relatively
frequently, then optimal location patterns will never emerge, except perhaps by chance; the
environment will have changed before all people reach the bottom right-hand corner of the matrix.
Pred (1969) presented the behavioural matrix as a ‘gross first approximation’ (p. 91), arguing
that any theory is better than none (p. 139), even if the model itself is literally untestable (p. 141;
see also Pred and Kibel, 1970). Harvey (1969b) treated it to a scathing review, however, calling the
two dimensions vaguely defined, ambiguous, unoperational and an oversimplification of the
complex nature of the factors influencing behaviour. Indeed, Harvey (1969c) was generally
sceptical about the potential of any behavioural location theory, a view shared by Olsson (1969)
who pointed out the difficulties of studying processes and demonstrated that much behavioural
geography involved only inferring processes from aggregated data on individual behaviour.
Others argued that such inference could be very strong, however. Rushton (1969), for example,
accepted that any one pattern of behaviour – what he termed behaviour in space – was largely a
function of the spatial structure within which it occurred (the choice of shopping centre to
patronise, for example), but general rules of spatial behaviour could be deduced from examining
the types of preferences displayed within particular patterns: ‘To say that these preferences do not
exist independently of the environment where the decision is made is to argue that environments
could exist about which the person would be unable to reach a decision’ (p. 393). Thus a
Human geography as spatial science 137

distance-decay pattern reflects the details of the environment in which it is observed, and its
production involves decision-making based on certain rules, which Rushton claimed his analytical
procedure could isolate. Its validity was queried, however (Pirie, 1976), and, like Pred’s behavioural
matrix, it did not attract many disciples. (Rushton’s arguments suggest activity in a ‘taken-for-
granted world’: see p. 185, this book.) Few others took up the explicit notion of the behavioural
matrix, but many of the ideas that it was founded on were explicit in other studies, such as those
of industrial geographers who studied the spread of ‘best practice’ methods.
Harvey (1969c) suggested two alternatives to behavioural location theory – further develop-
ment of normative theory and the construction of a stochastic location theory; he claimed that
both offered more immediate pay-offs for understanding spatial patterns than behavioural theory,
because of the latter’s conceptual and measurement problems. A stochastic approach was also
favoured by Leslie Curry (1967), who argued that large-scale patterns are the outcomes of small-
scale indeterminacy; individual choices may be random within certain constraints, but when very
many of them are aggregated they may display considerable order. Similarly, Webber (1972)
attempted to model locational decision-making processes in states of uncertainty using normative
approaches, concluding that ‘uncertainty increases agglomeration economies’ (p. 279), thereby
leading to greater concentration of economic activities and people into cities than predicted by
models based on ‘economic men’ (see also H. Richardson, 1973; Johnston, 1976a; Scott, 1988).
Game theory is a mathematical procedure developed to handle decision-making in uncertainty that
has received little attention from human geographers (Gould, 1963); the most ambitious attempt
to use it, which had very little impact, is in Isard et al. (1969).
For some critics, therefore, micro-analysis at the level of the individual is one or more of
impossible, unnecessary or misleading; macro-analysis, and the morphological laws that it produces,
provides sufficient insight to the behaviour that generates aggregate patterns. Both are needed
according to Mary Watson (1978), however; macro-analysis provides an initial overview, posing
questions which can only be answered by behavioural study. (See also Andrew Sayer, 1984, 1992a,
on extensive and intensive research; p. 220, this book.) The behavioural approach did not stimulate
a major revolution away from the spatial-science focus within human geography, therefore, but
rather generated an extension to it – which over time became increasingly the norm as the
assumptions underlying the original models were rejected as unrealistic. Whereas those normative
approaches started with simplifying assumptions about human behaviour and deduced what spatial
patterns follow from the axioms, behaviourists employed inductive procedures to identify the rules
of behaviour, using these to predict (and therefore ‘explain’) spatial patterns (Gale and Golledge,
1982). Their approach involved a sequence of interrelated investigations. An individual is faced
with a decision, with either a direct spatial input or spatial consequences. To make it, criteria are
established and information is collected to be evaluated against the criteria. That may lead to a
decision; alternatively, no satisfactory outcome could be identified so the individual may then alter
the criteria, collect more information or both. (This pragmatic approach to problem-solving is
similar to the procedures of the scientific method outlined in Figure 3.1.)
Whereas much of the initial work done in the spatial-science mould could be conducted using
published data sources (such as censuses) or relatively small field-collection exercises, the
behavioural approach generally requires specific data collection from the individual decision-
makers. The need for social surveys of various kinds furthered the growing links between
geographers and sociologists, psychologists and, to a lesser extent, political scientists, and led to an
expansion in the data-handling procedures necessary for the training of geographers. One of the
problems in their use is that many of the topics studied in human geography involve very large
numbers of individual decisions – as in migrations, journeys to work and to shop, voting decisions,
and so on. Very large sample surveys may be necessary to produce valid generalisations about such
behaviour, especially across a range of places, but resource limitations have meant concentration on
both small selections and only limited segments of the full behavioural sequence.
138 Human geography as spatial science

The behavioural sequence has also been applied in branches of human geography that deal
with topics involving relatively few decision-makers. In the study of diffusion, for example,
Larry Brown (1975) attempted to divert attention away from overall patterns of spatial spread and
the reasons for adoption (or not) to the decision-making which brings certain innovations to
places; most of these innovations involve selling products, which he terms ‘consumer innovations’
(see also Brown, 1981). Similarly, a number of industrial geographers have moved away from
investigations of aggregate patterns, which could be compared to those predicted by application of
neoclassical economic analysis (D. Smith, 1971), to the study of decision-making behaviour within
firms (e.g. Hamilton, 1974; Carr, 1983; Hayter and Watts, 1983; Schoenberger, 1993). Not all of
this work involved large datasets whose analysis called for sophisticated quantitative analysis, but
the overall approach was similar – seeking to establish general patterns of behaviour as revealed by
available data, as in Dicken’s (2003) classic work on globalisation.
The analytical procedures employed within behavioural geography became increasingly
sophisticated during the 1980s, paralleling developments in statistical procedures for analysing
categorical data. Most of the research involved analysing behaviour within the framework of the
spatial-science approach and its general positivist orientation. The goal was to explain, using
mathematical modelling and statistical analysis, variations in aspects of behaviour (choice of travel
mode for the journey to work, for example) in terms of variations in a number of independent
variables (such as the characteristics of the decision-makers and the milieux in which their decisions
were made: see Kitchin, 1996). Data for such studies are usually categorical in form, involving
classifications (which travel mode was used, for example, or the gender of the person concerned)
rather than variables measured on interval or ratio scales. Neil Wrigley (1985) provided a major
overview of the relevant statistical procedures for analysing such data; Richard Davies and Andrew
Pickles (1985) explored the important issue of inferring secular trends from cross-sectional data,
while others promoted the analysis of longitudinal data comprising repeated interviews with the
same individuals (Dale, 1993). Methods for quantifying attitudes and other aspects of human
characteristics and behaviour have been explored, involving both increasingly sophisticated survey
instruments for investigating how people cognise and learn about their spatial environments
(Golledge and Timmermans, 1990; Timmermans et al., 2001) and technical procedures for
representing those cognitions quantitatively (see Aitken et al., 1989).
Many of the choice models underpinning work in behavioural geography are based on theories
of utility maximisation. This approach was heralded by Cadwallader (1975), exemplified in fuller
detail by Neil Wrigley and Paul Longley (1984), and became the basis for a burgeoning literature
(as displayed in great detail in Golledge and Timmermans, 1988, and reviewed in Timmermans and
Golledge, 1990; Timmermans et al., 2001). Such theories propose that decision-makers select from
within the choice sets presented to (and/or perceived by) them, according to the utility which they
allocate to each of the alternatives evaluated; as Timmermans and Golledge (1990, p. 312) express
it, all ‘are based on (variants of) a conceptual model that explicitly relates choice behaviour to the
environment through consideration of perceptions, preference formation and decision-making’
(utility being a measure of preference). A full analysis of discrete choices thus involves knowing:

1 the available choice set;


2 the elements of the choice set considered by each individual;
3 the criteria on which each member of the choice set was evaluated by individual decision-
makers; and
4 the relative importance they attached to each criterion.

James Bird (1989), following Desbarats (1983), illustrated this (Figure 4.6). The process starts
with a listing of all possible opportunities. Some are discarded to form an ‘objective choice set’;
evaluation of its elements results in some being discarded as unacceptable, producing an ‘effective
all seemingly possible and appropriat!
- spatial behavioural opportunities

because of institutional external supply of housing, mainly


discard and accessibility constraints employment, shopping and = external
(partially due to choice of location] recreational opportunities constraints

objective choice set

because of information and social opportunities not known to


constraints incl. those self-imposed individual because of less _ internal
discard
and evaluation of and tendency to knowledge or poor - constraints

conform to social norms information networks

effective choice set

because of individual evaluation, via


psychological characteristics in context of
discard
perceived societal values and attitudes and
potential obstacles

target choice set

because of situational constraints;


residual possible others (incl. social ‘gatekeepers'] may prevent
discard external constraints
spatial behaviour actualisation (high income and influence
can circumvent)

- actual Note: discard is seen by the individual as enforced by external


^behaviour constraints or is a decision based on an amalgam of personal
factors - internal constraints

Figure 4.6  Choice sets in the spatial decision-making process

Source: Bird, 1989, p. 145, after Desbarats.


Human geography as spatial science 143

further investigation, and identify some of the relationships that might assist in developing
explanations for the observed patterns (Hepple, 2008). Such explanations need not, in the strict
positivist mould, imply general laws of cause and effect; they may be simply accounts of a particular
situation which can be assessed against theoretical models of the behaviour patterns involved and
generate ideas to be tested in new situations. In mass societies, behavioural geography provides
insights to mass behaviour. Further, some of the methods developed for studying behaviour have
been adapted for particular purposes, such as wayfinding by visually impaired individuals, and
applied in a number of contexts (Golledge, 1993; Golledge’s work – he was himself visually
impaired – was strongly critiqued for its interpretations of disablement; see Imrie, 1996; Gleeson,
1996; and Golledge, 1996).
The continued vitality of the group of specialists working on cognitive-behavioural topics was
illustrated by Golledge and Stimson’s (1987) text on Analytical Behavioural Geography and its 1997
successor Spatial Behavior: A geographic perspective. They introduced the approach (Golledge and Stimson,
1987, p. 1), and its origins in the 1960s, as a recognition that:

in order to exist in and to comprehend any given environment, people had to learn to organise
critical subsets of information from the mass of experiences open to them. They sense, store,
record, organise and use bits of information for the ultimate purpose of coping with the everyday
task of living. In doing this, they create knowledge structures based on information selected
from the mass of ‘to whom it may concern’ messages emanating from the world in which we live.
Different elements from these various environments are given different meanings and have
different values attached to them. It was the explicit recognition of the relationship between
cognition, environment and behaviour that initially helped to develop behavioural research in
geography.

They illustrated how the work developed, and structured approaches through a diagram which
places individual decision-makers at the interface between environment and behaviour, learning
and acting within the environment and changing it as they act (Figure 4.7). The organisation of
their book, covering both the methods used by behavioural geographers and their substantive
achievements in various topical areas, provides a clear view of a vital subdiscipline, as does the size

Environmental Structure

Interface

Perception
Attitudes Learning
Coqnition

Spatial Behaviour

Figure 4.7  The society–environment interface

Source: Golledge and Stimson, 1987, p. 11.


Human geography as spatial science 141

(a) the importance of logical and mathematical thinking; (b) the need for public verifiability of
results; (c) the search for generalization; (d) the emphasis on analytic languages for researching
and expressing knowledge structures; and (e) the importance of hypotheses testing and the
importance of selecting the most appropriate bases for generalization or theorizing.

The goal is to develop quantitatively verified theory (Macmillan, 1989b).


This continued emphasis on key elements of the positivist philosophy links to a second, much
less substantial, area of work. Pipkin (1981) noted that much effort had been expended on
identifying behaviour patterns but little on exploring the underpinning mental constructs.
Understanding why people behave as they do has not been advanced very far, therefore; as Greenberg
(1984, p. 193) expressed it, ‘For the most part, the intention of behavioural-perceptual geographers
has not been to explain the spatial organisation of society, but to illuminate the spatial behavior of
individuals.’
Artificial Intelligence (AI) was presented as offering much to the study of cognitive processes
(T. R. Smith, 1984), using computer-modelling procedures to represent the decision-making
processes and thereby gaining insights (by analogy) to the nature of the human brain. Couclelis
(1986a, p. 2) indicates that this involves the ‘human computer’ metaphor according to which,
‘cognitive functions such as problem-solving, pattern-recognition, decision-making, learning and
natural language understanding are investigated by means of computer programs that purport to
replicate the corresponding mental processes’. The ability to replicate processes by predicting their
outcomes (as in Smith et al., 1984) cannot be equated with understanding them, however. Couclelis
(1986a, p. 111) concluded a detailed discussion of AI’s utility in the study of human behaviour by
noting that ‘reliable predictions can be made about intentional systems even by theories which . . .
are totally vacuous psychologically’. Whether one wants to know how or why people behave is
crucial; AI can reproduce the former it is claimed, but can it assist in the latter? Nystuen (1984,
p. 358) doubted even the former claim, however, arguing that he could:

see little potential in AI methods available today in addressing problems considered important in
the spatial decision-making literature, such as the decision to migrate. . . . These processes would
require elaborate models of spatial cognition and tradeoff behavior whereas even the simplest
model of a child’s wayfinding is complex and contains major unresolved methodological problems.

If the claim were sustained, however, it would only provide a constructed explanation (see the
discussion of Lukermann’s arguments on p. 82, this book), but:

I am struck by the fact that careful empirical analysis by biologists describing the anatomy and
behavior of bats did not lead to the discovery of how bats navigated in the dark. The explanation
was beyond imagination until a purely human system (radar, followed by sonar) was invented
and by analogy applied to the behavior and anatomy of the bat. Then all the things fell into place.
(Nystuen, 1984, p. 359)

In other words, if you can reproduce a process then you may well gain some appreciation of it or,
as Nystuen put it:

If a constructed computer program can repeatedly resolve an issue under varying spatial
conditions in a way that is considered useful to geographers, then one might say that we
understand the issue. This is a sufficient claim: the problem has been solved by whatever logic
or capacities the program has at hand. There is no need to claim that this is necessarily the way
human spatial decision-making works.
(p. 359)
142 Human geography as spatial science

Others reject such an instrumentalist argument, however (e.g. Gregory, 1980: see the discussion
of automated geography, p. 160, this book.) Openshaw (1995), on the other hand, argued for the
power of AI software for understanding and simulating human behaviour (see also Openshaw and
Openshaw, 1997).
Thrift argued that by the end of the 1970s:

The halcyon days of behavioural geography are long gone. With them have passed the days when
behavioural geographers made inflated claims for the explanatory power of their subject area.
But the subject area still has its place in human geography.
(1981, p. 359)

He recognised two criticisms of behavioural work: those which perceived it presenting the
individual decision-maker as little more than an automaton responding to stimuli in a programmed
way; and those which claimed that it ignored the characteristics of society as a whole which are
greater than the sum of its individual parts. He argued that behavioural geography might be
presented as ‘half-blind’: ‘But to say that behavioural geography is therefore half-blind is not to say
that it can see nothing at all. Its explanations may be limited. That does not mean that they are
therefore non-existent’ (p. 359).
While a substantial volume of work continued during the 1980s (summarised in reviews such
as Golledge and Rushton, 1984; Golledge and Timmermans, 1990; Timmermans and Golledge,
1990; Timmermans et al., 2001), it could also be claimed that behavioural geography by then had
become (or at least was perceived by most in the discipline) a specialist interest. It was increasingly
isolated within human geography (Gold, 1992), because of both the theoretical position and
analytical sophistication achieved by its leading practitioners and what Cloke et al. (1991, p. 67) call
its ‘partial treatment of people’ (which they contrast with their ‘complete neglect in spatial science’).
Many human geographers have accepted the need to collect and analyse individual data through
questionnaires and similar methods, to portray how people learn about, represent and behave in
space. Others have rejected that approach entirely, because it cannot provide telling insights into
individuals – thus, according to Cloke et al., making it ‘somewhat limiting’, ‘dehumanising’, ‘pallid’
and ‘horribly reductionist’. Behavioural geography became one of many components of an
increasingly diverse discipline: it made a considerable general impact upon geographical practice in
its early years and has since been advanced by a small group of specialists somewhat apart from the
mainstream (as discussed in Gold, 1992).
Against those claims are arguments – closely aligned to Golledge’s distinction between
‘positivist law-seeking’ and ‘analytical research’ – which see the methods and approaches developed
within behavioural geography as necessary components of understanding central areas of
geography’s research agenda (Johnston, 2000a). Many millions of people migrate every year; many
millions vote in national elections; very many millions commute daily, and so forth. Although full
understanding of these events requires appreciation of why individuals acted as they did, that is
virtually impossible because of the scale of the task. General patterns of behaviour can only be
uncovered through combinations of:

1 analyses of the aggregate situation – the number of migrations between given origins and
destinations, for example;
2 analyses of general relationships within such situations – the proportion of migrants in
different age and educational groups, for example; and
3 analyses of the reasons for individual decisions.

The first two can only be achieved through work – usually quantitative – on large datasets, which
indicate the size and nature of the issue, give an overall picture of general patterns that call for
Human geography as spatial science 143

further investigation, and identify some of the relationships that might assist in developing
explanations for the observed patterns (Hepple, 2008). Such explanations need not, in the strict
positivist mould, imply general laws of cause and effect; they may be simply accounts of a particular
situation which can be assessed against theoretical models of the behaviour patterns involved and
generate ideas to be tested in new situations. In mass societies, behavioural geography provides
insights to mass behaviour. Further, some of the methods developed for studying behaviour have
been adapted for particular purposes, such as wayfinding by visually impaired individuals, and
applied in a number of contexts (Golledge, 1993; Golledge’s work – he was himself visually
impaired – was strongly critiqued for its interpretations of disablement; see Imrie, 1996; Gleeson,
1996; and Golledge, 1996).
The continued vitality of the group of specialists working on cognitive-behavioural topics was
illustrated by Golledge and Stimson’s (1987) text on Analytical Behavioural Geography and its 1997
successor Spatial Behavior: A geographic perspective. They introduced the approach (Golledge and Stimson,
1987, p. 1), and its origins in the 1960s, as a recognition that:

in order to exist in and to comprehend any given environment, people had to learn to organise
critical subsets of information from the mass of experiences open to them. They sense, store,
record, organise and use bits of information for the ultimate purpose of coping with the everyday
task of living. In doing this, they create knowledge structures based on information selected
from the mass of ‘to whom it may concern’ messages emanating from the world in which we live.
Different elements from these various environments are given different meanings and have
different values attached to them. It was the explicit recognition of the relationship between
cognition, environment and behaviour that initially helped to develop behavioural research in
geography.

They illustrated how the work developed, and structured approaches through a diagram which
places individual decision-makers at the interface between environment and behaviour, learning
and acting within the environment and changing it as they act (Figure 4.7). The organisation of
their book, covering both the methods used by behavioural geographers and their substantive
achievements in various topical areas, provides a clear view of a vital subdiscipline, as does the size

Figure 4.7  The society–environment interface

Source: Golledge and Stimson, 1987, p. 11.


144 Human geography as spatial science

of their bibliography, along with the large number of other pieces listed in the review papers on
which parts of this chapter have drawn.
A much-revised second edition extended the coverage of material that illustrated not only the
continued volume of geographic work but also the strong links that were being forged with
psychology. Behavioural geography was defined as:

characterized by a concern both for scientific rigor or experimental realism and for
phenomenological and anthropomorphic understanding of human-environment systems and
relationships.
(Golledge and Stimson, 1997, p. 29, original italics)

Its concerns covered ‘philosophical’ topics such as experimental design; data collection procedures;
the search for validity and reliability; the selection of appropriate analytical methods; the choice of
a ‘modern, analytical, epistemological basis’; innovative models of behaviour and environments;
recognition of socially constraining dimensions; and differing viewpoints based on ‘bottom-up’ or
‘top-down’ approaches. Six main subject areas were identified – cognitive mapping and spatial
behaviour; attitudes, utility, choice, preference, search and learning; consumer behaviour; location
decision-making; wayfinding, mode choice and travel behaviour; and mobility and migration – on
the grounds that these ‘lend themselves more to the process of measurement, model building,
abstraction, generalization, and theory building than do other areas of human geography’ (p. 30).
The result – as stressed by Golledge (2002, p. 126) – was ‘an extra explanatory dimension to more
traditional geographic research’ examining cognitive processes in a wide range of settings. The use
of new tools of functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) to measure cognitive responses
within sections of the brain and their relationships to spatial reasoning occasioned by use of maps
has also offered fresh directions. Work in this field has indicated how maps are different from other
geometric objects, so that:

even with a relatively simple map, the map influence [as they are orientated and perceived] is
significant enough to elicit distinctly different brain activation. We do not offer this study as one
of methodology, although we recognize that fMRI is far outside the methodological norm in
geography. Instead, we offer this study as one that empirically supports the underlying premise
in many definitions and discussions of maps – that they are tools designed for a specific use that
distinguishes them from other types of graphics.
(Lobben et al., 2014, p. 110)

Yet one of the intriguing aspects of work in behavioural geography is that those who wrote
about it, such as Golledge and Stimson (1997), tended to restrict it to the study of certain types of
behaviour. The substantive chapters of their book deal with choice of transport mode, choice
of shopping centre to patronise, migration, residential mobility within cities and the problems of
specific groups within the population. Other forms of decision-making, such as those related to the
location of production and service facilities, were apparently outside the remit of behavioural
geographers. And yet a great amount of work was done on such decision-making processes and
their outcomes, which involves collecting data from the individuals making the location decisions
at a great range of scales from the global, through the national and regional to the local – albeit in
many cases within theoretical frameworks that have few links to the models that stimulated much
of human geography’s urban and quantitative revolution. The theoretical frameworks within which
such authors deal (as with Dicken’s, 2003, work on globalisation, and Schoenberger’s, 1997, work
on corporate behaviour) came from political economy and concepts of explanation that are
discussed in the next chapter. (The journal Regional Studies carries a great deal of this work.) But many
of the data collection methods are behavioural, even if there is little complex statistical analysis, and
Human geography as spatial science 145

the goals are, as in so much else discussed in this chapter, to identify and account for general
patterns of behaviour in space. According to Scott (2000, p. 24), this separation was because
behavioural geography ‘became more or less the preserve of a few highly specialized researchers
who turned increasingly to experimental psychology for their inspiration’. Indeed, as long ago as
1976, Cullen (1976, p. 400) had argued that although behavioural geography should have a great
deal to offer for those interested in macro-patterns, it was failing to do so, and was instead an
‘intellectual backwater’, ‘every bit as mechanistic as the neoclassical economic geography it was
supposed to replace’ (Scott, 2000, p. 24). As with so much in contemporary geography, it is difficult
to draw boundaries between different sections of the subject.

Spatial (or geo-)statistics


The application of various approaches to ‘geography as spatial science’ over the last half-century
has involved much attention being given to quantitative data analysis. Initially, most of the
researchers involved followed Garrison (1956a) in accepting that statistical procedures developed
for other fields of enquiry could be adopted for geographical investigations without difficulty.
Some suggested necessary modifications – as in spatial sampling (Berry and Baker, 1968) – but,
despite Robinson’s (1956; see p. 67, this book) early work, it was generally assumed that no
technical problems prevented the application of standard procedures to spatial datasets. A number
of textbooks appeared, especially in the late 1960s, which made little reference to any peculiarities
of geographical data; they differed from the texts produced by other social scientists only in the
nature of their examples. And even in the 1980s, few contributors to a book on Recent Developments
in Spatial Data Analysis (Bahrenberg et al., 1984) discussed spatial data per se; most of their work
referred to the use of standard statistical procedures in geographical applications. (This was also
the case in a major review of quantitative geography in the UK: Neil Wrigley and Robert Bennett,
1981, and an earlier special issue of The Statistician – Peter Taylor and John Goddard, 1974 – in
which geographers introduced statisticians to their quantitative applications, with only one paper
– David Unwin and Les Hepple, 1974 – dealing with what Taylor and Goddard, p. 151, refer to
as ‘the peculiar nature of geographical data, particularly the lack of spatial independence’.)
Others simply adapted standard procedures to geographical problems, as with Chorley and
Haggett’s (1965a) application of polynomial regression to the analysis of spatial patterns – what
they termed ‘trend surface analysis’.
Indeed, relatively few texts have focused on techniques for spatial (or map) analysis, although
some general texts on statistical analysis for geographers (such as Taylor, 1977) have included such
material. David Unwin (1981), for example, dealt with point, line, area and surface patterns, along
with map comparison, providing a clear emphasis on spatial statistical analysis (see also O’Sullivan
and Unwin, 2003); Peter Lewis (1977) covered point and line patterns for a more advanced
audience; Graham Upton (a statistician) combined with Bernard Fingleton (a geographer) in an
advanced two-volume treatment of aspects of spatial data analysis (Upton and Fingleton, 1985,
1989); Gatrell, also in collaboration with a statistician, published a text with worked examples on
a CD-ROM (Bailey and Gatrell, 1995); and Fotheringham et al. (2000) brought out a book as ‘a
statement on the vitality of modern quantitative geography . . . where the [recent] emphasis has
been on the development of techniques explicitly for spatial data analysis’ (pp. xi–xii, original
italics). Similarly, relatively few followed the paths set out in two editions of a book on mathematical
models (Wilson and Kirkby, 1975; Wilson and Bennett, 1985). To some extent, spatial statistical
analysis – as against statistical analysis in geography – was a minority activity.
In this context, there has been infiltration of human geography by technical developments
elsewhere. One such was work on classification (a procedure common to the life sciences) and its
links to regionalisation. Berry used these widely in his ideas on regional analysis (Berry, 1964a: see
146 Human geography as spatial science

p. 88, this book) in studies of, for example, urban residential areas (or factorial ecology: Berry,
1971) and others have deployed variants on them for the task of defining electoral areas such
as parliamentary constituencies and congressional districts (Johnston, 2003d): methods of
classification have been substantially advanced in recent years using high-speed computers for
the large dataset manipulations involved in the analysis of remotely sensed imagery (Mather, 1999;
Tso and Mather, 2001). Elsewhere, Wrigley (1973) pointed out the problems involved in the use
of percentage and proportional data in linear regression and related methods and in a series of
publications (Wrigley, 1976, 1985) introduced the use of logit and other forms of categorical data
modelling. These are now widely used in work with such data – for example, voting studies in
which the values are binary (either yes, the individual voted for a given party, or no, he/she did
not: Pattie and Johnston, 2000; see also Lloyd et al., 2012).
Kelvyn Jones (1991) introduced methods for exploring varying relationships from work in
education. It may be hypothesised, for example, that a student’s performance reflects not only her/
his innate ability but also home background, school type, the quality of teaching provided, and so
forth. Thus, for example, a student from a supportive home background may perform better in a set
of tests than one with the same innate ability but from a less supportive background, but the better
the teaching provided to the two, the smaller the gap between their performance. This suggests an
interaction effect between the independent variables – when operating together they have a greater
impact than when operating separately. Such interaction effects can be modelled within standard
general linear models (e.g. Andrew Russell, 1997) but Jones has demonstrated that multi-level
models developed by educational researchers are more efficient ways of estimating those interactions
in complex datasets and has applied them to a range of geographical problems such as differing
voting patterns across regions (Jones et al., 1992) and disease patterns (Jones and Duncan, 1996,
1998); they also have the advantage that they explicitly take into account and correct for the
influence of any spatial autocorrelation (see below) that may be inherent in data, such as those
collected using cluster sampling which have autocorrelation effects in-built.
Various aspects of spatial interaction have continued to be a focus of formal modelling work,
as in major studies of the spatial diffusion of diseases (much of it summarised in Haggett, 2000).
Bennett and Haining (1985; Bennett et al.,1985) placed such work at the forefront of methodological
developments in the discipline. Much of it was summarised by Wilson and Bennett’s (1985) volume
on Mathematical Methods in Human Geography and Planning in a Handbook of Applicable Mathematics series.
Others sought to ensure proper use of the standard statistical procedures (e.g. Jones, 1984;
Wrigley, 1984), with the use of statistical significance tests forming the basis of further debate
(Summerfield, 1983; Hay, 1985b). Better ways of testing hypotheses were also expounded, not
only with regard to the use of categorical (or nominal) data (e.g. Fingleton, 1984; Wrigley, 1984),
but also in terms of pattern analysis (Upton and Fingleton, 1985) and representing relationships
through structural models (e.g. Cadwallader, 1986). Much of this work has been criticised for its
reliance on methods that impose structures on data rather than ‘letting the data speak for themselves’
(Gould, 1981a); the mathematics of q-analysis was proposed to meet the latter criterion (Gould,
1980; Beaumont and Gatrell, 1982; Gatrell, 1983; see also the essays edited by Macgill, 1983) but
was not taken up. More interest was shown in exploratory data analysis – the inductive interrogation
of datasets unconstrained by prior hypotheses and assumptions such as those underpinning the
general linear model (Cox and Jones, 1981; Wrigley, 1983). By assuming less, it was argued, you
may discover more.
Increasingly, however, the assumption that all geographers needed was an appreciation of
standard procedures was considered invalid. Instead, it was contended that geographical data of
various forms required specific procedures because of their particular nature. Geographers thus
became involved – in some cases in collaboration with statisticians – in the development of those
procedures, as illustrated in the next subsections. Interestingly, some of the earliest work on
these issues was done by non-geographers (e.g. Duncan et al., 1961). There have been substantial
Human geography as spatial science 147

advances in the development and adaptation of sophisticated modelling and analytical techniques:
some, however, thought these advances, although ‘scholarship of the highest order’, may reflect
‘a misdirection of effort’ (King, 1979b, p. 157) because they had not illuminated spatial organisation
as much as they might. New techniques continue to be advanced, assisted by massive technological
advances in data handling. A ‘paradigm’ in the sense of a community with a clear world view was
established within geography in the 1950s and 1960s, and has remained strong and vibrant within
the discipline ever since. Its nature has changed considerably since then, with the formal models of
spatial structures being largely forgotten and replaced by new approaches. The methods applied
have changed too, with greater technological power and sophistication.

Spatial autocorrelation
During the late 1960s a group of researchers at the University of Bristol began to question the
widespread assumption about the relevance of standard statistical procedures for analyses of
spatial data. Statisticians had for long recognised difficulties in applying the general linear model
– notably, in its regression and correlation form – to the time-series data used in economic
analysis and forecasting because of what was termed autocorrelation. One of the model’s
assumptions is that all observations are conditionally independent of each other; the magnitude
of one reading on a variable should in no way influence that of any other. Such autocorrelation
clearly exists in most time series; the value of the retail price index at one date, for example,
strongly influences its value at nearby later dates, and is itself influenced by preceding values.
(An early example of this being brought to geographers’ attention was in the discussion in
Chisholm et al., 1971, p. 465.) Because of such interdependence between adjacent observations,
conventional regression methods could not be used; autocorrelation leads to inefficient regression
coefficients because of underestimated standard errors and casts doubt on the validity of any
forecasts using those models, as well as overestimating the goodness-of-fit measure (usually the
correlation coefficient). The estimated impact of the independent variable on the dependent was
reliable, but because the standard error of that estimate was overstated with autocorrelated data
the strength of the relationship appears statistically less significant than would have been the case
without autocorrelation.
The Bristol group (led by Peter Haggett, Andrew Cliff and Keith Ord, who is a statistician)
argued not only that this autocorrelation problem applied to spatial datasets too, but also that it was
much less tractable than with temporal series. Time proceeds in one direction only, but space is
two-dimensional, and the independence requirement can be violated in all directions around a
single point, and not necessarily to the same extent. Spatial autocorrelation can therefore involve all
neighbours influencing all others with regard to the values of a particular variable, as recognised by
some statisticians (e.g. Geary, 1954) and hinted at by geographers such as Dacey (1968), whose
work stimulated the Bristol investigations. (Andrew Cliff worked as a graduate student with
Dacey at Northwestern University in the early 1960s.) Considerable effort was expended on this
problem over a number of years (Cliff and Ord, 1973, 1981), covering a wide range of spatial
applications, including the well-known gravity model (Curry, 1972; Johnston, 1976b; Sheppard,
1979; Fotheringham, 1981; Tiefelsdorf, 2003).
The spatial autocorrelation problem severely constrains the application of conventional
statistical procedures in geographical analyses if the statistical significance of regression estimates is
a focus of attention. Several people thus argued that application of regression methods, and others
based on the general linear model such as principal components and factor analyses, was invalid
with spatial datasets (Haining, 1980, p. 24). As Harvey put it:

The choice of the product-moment correlation coefficient for regionalization problems appears
singularly inappropriate, since one of the technical requirements of this statistic is independence
148 Human geography as spatial science

in the observations. Since the aim of such regionalization is to produce contiguous regions which
are internally relatively homogeneous, it seems almost certain that this condition of independence
in the observations will be violated.
(1969a, p. 347)

Gould (1970a) noted that spatial autocorrelation reflects the order that geographers were seeking
to establish with their laws and theories, and it was somewhat paradoxical that its presence
prevented its identification through accepted technical procedures. As Tobler (1970, p. 236)
expressed it more prosaically, the ‘first law of geography’ is that ‘everything is related to everything
else, but near things are more related than distant things’ – in other words, spatial autocorrelation
is the core of geography.
On realising the force of the case, however, some accepted that conventional statistical
procedures could not be applied in their work (e.g. Berry, 1973a) and the Bristol group omitted
them from their rewrite of Haggett’s major text (Haggett et al., 1977). The second part of the
book – ‘Locational models’ – was much expanded and rewritten. In the first edition (Haggett,
1965c), the chapter on ‘Testing’ included a section on ‘Testing via statistical methods’ which
included standard linear regression analysis. The comparable chapter in the second edition omitted
that material, however, on the grounds not only that:

Since the first edition of this book appeared, the use of conventional statistical methods and
tests of significance . . . has become commonplace in human geography. It is not the purpose of
this chapter to outline the procedures for carrying out such analyses.
(Haggett et al., 1977, p. 329)

but also that:

the aim of this chapter is to examine those properties of geographical data which make their
analysis using statistical methods of the sort cited more difficult than might at first appear.

For them, the lesson to be learned from appreciation of the problems of spatial dependence and
autocorrelation in geographical data was that ‘If geographers continue to apply the usual forms of
many of the basic statistical models to spatially autocorrelated data, then a very severe risk is run
of reaching misleading conclusions’ (Haggett et al., 1977, p. 336). Others have carried the argument
forward, developing methods – termed spatial econometrics by Anselin (1988: Anselin studied
regional science with Isard – see p. 24, this book) – for modelling with spatially interdependent
datasets. (Such software is now generally available through the World Wide Web: Anselin, 2012;
Anselin and Rey, 2012.)
Many continued to apply the methods, however, either in ignorance of the autocorrelation case
or on the grounds that the biased-coefficients problem refers only to the use of the general linear
model in forecasting and prediction (and not in any situation that involves statistical significance
testing), and does not affect use of the procedures for either description (see Johnston, 1978b) or
certain types of ecological analysis (Johnston, 1982a, 1984b).

Spatial forecasting
One of the Bristol group’s substantive interests was in spatial forecasting, involving the development
of procedures for estimating how trends – in the spread of a disease, for example, and of prices and
unemployment – would proceed through time and over space (Haggett, 1973; Cliff et al., 1975).
They organised a major symposium on this (Chisholm et al., 1971) and stimulated a considerable
volume of work, much of it technical, on the problems of identifying and forecasting
Human geography as spatial science 149

spatio-temporal trends (e.g. Bennett, 1978b). Hägerstrand’s work on diffusion patterns provided
the foundation for much of this research, which focused on the patterns of spread rather than on
their generating processes, and spawned a literature on technical aspects of forecasting (e.g. Bennett,
1979) and deducing ‘spatial processes’ from mapped patterns (Haining, 1981, 1990). Haggett
(1994, p. 6) continued to maintain that ‘prediction plays an essential part in the building of models
of geographical systems’, although he increasingly illustrated this with reference only to
epidemiology. (Haggett was initially introduced to ideas about diffusion and spatial spread by
reading the English translation of Lösch when he was a postgraduate in Cambridge in 1954. He was
in particular stimulated by some of the ideas in Lösch’s footnotes – e.g. note 139 on p. 195, and
note 38 on p. 415 which was concerned with functional regions – as well as by the figure on p. 496
which showed spatiotemporal trends in the spread of depression in Iowa, 1929–1931. Although
Haggett was inspired by these ideas in the mid-19590s it was only in the later 1960s, after he
moved to the University of Bristol and obtained one of the first-ever grants to geographers from the
SSRC that he began a programme of research into spatiotemporal trends first in economic
activity and then, after he had attended a World Health Organization seminar in Geneva, diseases.)
Gregory (1994, p. 59) argues that Haggett’s ‘main concerns have always been descriptive-
predictive’, and that he has little interest in ‘theoretical questions’ and explanation. Haggett himself
agreed with this in a published interview (Browning, 1982, p. 54); in response to a statement that
‘It seems to me that you are naturally inclined towards models but not necessarily theory’
he replied, ‘Yes . . . I think that the broader theories of the subject are not something I can cope
with easily.’
Hay’s (1978) review of this work challenged what he saw as its fundamental assumption that
phenomena behave coherently in both time and space. He questioned the assumed stability of
interplace interrelationships over time in analyses such as Ron Martin and J. E. Oeppen’s (1975)
work on market-price variations, and argued instead for consideration of the value of catastrophe
theory, wherein small changes in the control variable(s) can stimulate major changes in the
dependent variable being studied (such major changes are the catastrophes). If catastrophes occur,
then the linear extrapolations typical of the Bristol group’s work have clear limitations as forecasting
procedures. There were relatively few geographical applications of this relatively new area of
mathematics, however (Wilson, 1976a, 1981b), which received more attention among physical
geographers (Thornes, 1989a, 1989b).

The modifiable areal unit problem and ecological inference


A further problem characteristic of much geographical data is what became termed the modifiable
areal unit problem (MAUP). There are many ways in which a large area can be subdivided into
smaller units for data collection, reporting and analysis, and geographers showed that different
divisions of the same area could result in different analytical outcomes; the relationship between
old age and long-term illness may differ in its strength (and even direction) depending on which
particular set of areas was used in the analysis. The importance of this issue became apparent in
studies of electoral redistricting (Gudgin and Taylor, 1979), as in the reapportionment exercises
undertaken after every decennial census in the USA when the goal is to produce Congressional
(and other) districts as equal in their populations as possible. Each state is allocated a number of
districts. Maps of proposed districts – subdivisions of the state – are created using population data
for much smaller areas than the districts, so that each district is an amalgamation of many of those
small areas, which should be contiguous. Analysts using computers could identify a very large
number of possible ways of producing a set of districts in any state, each of which would have its
own electoral impact; it could be possible, for example, for a state that has been allocated twelve
districts to have a majority of its seats won by either the Democratic or the Republican Party,
depending on how the map is drawn. The implications of the MAUP, therefore, are that one’s
150 Human geography as spatial science

findings apply only to the particular map configuration used; they may not be more generally
applicable. Different maps may result in different geographical conclusions. (The original examples
of this were given by Morrill’s (1973, 1981) work on redistricting in Washington state, and
Openshaw and Taylor’s (1979) on the impact of different redistrictings in Iowa. Rossiter and
Johnston, 1981, extended Gudgin and Taylor’s 1979 classic work on the statistical underpinnings
of the geography of redistricting to develop a computer program which identifies all of the possible
outcomes; see also Cirincione et al., 2000.)
The MAUP issue was first noted by Gehlke and Biehl (1934) and further generalised by Yule and
Kendall (1950). Gehlke and Biehl had data on numbers of juvenile delinquents and median house-
hold incomes in the 252 census tracts in the Cleveland metropolitan area; the correlation between
those two variables was –0.502. But as the tracts were aggregated into larger units (of approximately
similar size), so the correlation increased; with 175 units, it was –0.580; with 125, –0.662; with 100,
–0.667; and with just 25 it was –0.763. Using data on wheat and potato yields in English counties,
Yule and Kendall (1950) found even greater variation according to the number of units: using all
48 English counties, the correlation was only 0.22; with 24 groups of counties, 0.30; with 12, 0.58;
with 6, 0.76; and with just 3 counties, 0.99. In these studies, just one example of each aggregation
(e.g. into six groups of English counties) was employed, but in almost all cases there are many
different ways in which n units can be aggregated into k regions, where k is smaller than n. Each
regionalisation might produce a different correlation coefficient, as demonstrated by Openshaw and
Taylor (1979). They had data on the percentage of the population aged over 60 and the percentage of
the votes cast in the 1968 presidential election obtained by the Republican candidate for Iowa’s
99 counties. The correlation between these two was 0.346. With 30 zones (i.e. aggregations of con-
tiguous counties), the average correlation was 0.33, but with a standard deviation 0.11; as the number
of zones decreased, the standard deviation increased. And even this figure concealed the extent of the
variation: with 30 zones, for example, it was possible to get a correlation of 0.98 between the two
variables at one extreme, and of –0.73 at the other. In effect, as Openshaw (1984a) later demon-
strated, it is virtually possible to produce a regionalisation of the 99 Iowa counties to produce any
desired OLS relationship between the two variables – both the correlation and the slope coefficient.
Openshaw (1984a, 1984b) showed how different spatial aggregations of the same dataset
(counties into regions, perhaps, or census enumeration districts into social areas) can produce very
different correlations between two variables as a result of the interaction of two influences – scale
and aggregation; indeed, his simulations suggest that with many datasets any correlation between
+1.0 and –1.0 might be obtained, so that the particular aggregation employed needs careful
justification (see Wrigley, 1995). Openshaw and Taylor (1981) explored three responses to such
findings:

1 it is an insoluble problem, and so can only be ignored;


2 it is a problem that can be assumed away, with the results obtained from the particular available
dataset being accepted as ‘the real ones’; or
3 it is a very powerful analytical device for exploring various aspects of geography and spatial
variations, since alternative regionalisations can be produced – this allows the creation of
frequency distributions with which one regionalisation can be compared (as with the example
from Cirincione et al., 2000, cited earlier), and of optimal regionalisations for particular purposes.

Most geographers and other spatial analysts have at least implicitly adopted the first of these (and
perhaps even the second) – in part because they lack the available data which would allow the third
response to be adopted. (Flowerdew, 2011, concludes that in most cases MAUP makes little or no
difference to the statistical results using English census data.)
Associated with this work on ecological inference and the MAUP has been the development
of inductive procedures for classification and regionalisation, using AI (Openshaw and Openshaw,
Human geography as spatial science 151

1997). For example, a region-building exercise may begin with a ‘representative sample’ of the n
building blocks being selected as the k ‘cores’ for the regions and then a genetic algorithm
allocates the remaining (n–k) building blocks to those cores through a ‘learning process’ until
homogeneous regions are created. The algorithm is rerun a large number of times, and the
‘best’ available regionalisation then selected on a predetermined criterion. Such procedures are
often termed ‘unsupervised’ because the cores are randomly selected. An alternative – ‘supervised’
– procedure involves creating ‘ideal type’ cores as the nodes for the regions, rather than using
samples of the building blocks; there must therefore be a predetermined number of regions. The
cores have a given ‘population mix’, which may be derived either a priori or empirically, from that
or another dataset. Having created those cores, the building blocks are then regionalised
using neural net methods, with the nature of the cores changing during the learning process
(for an example, see Mitchell et al., 1998). Openshaw et al. (1995) used such a procedure to classify
Britain’s residential areas. Using census data (85 variables), 145,716 census enumeration districts
(EDs, population average c.500), were the building blocks for a clustering into 60 types, themselves
aggregated into 17 super-clusters.
These analytical advances have been used to develop regionalisations for practical
applications, as in the design of reporting (or output) areas for censuses. Early work on functional
regions around cities using flow data (notably for commuting) was used to define metropolitan
regions in the USA and travel-to-work areas in the UK (e.g. Berry et al., 1969; Coombes et al.,
1982). At smaller scales, in the UK census from 1951 to 1991, for example, the smallest data-
reporting units were the EDs – small areas used for the administration of the census collection
and tabulation procedures. They were defined for administrative convenience only, and bore no
necessary relationship to the underlying geography they were portraying. Many users – private
and public sector as well as academic researchers – argued the desirability of these being defined
so that they were relatively homogeneous on defined characteristics, within prescribed
constraints, notably relating to their size (e.g. population or household minima or maxima).
Using data for even smaller areas than EDs (postcode sectors), Martin et al. (2001) used one of
Openshaw’s classification algorithms (AZP: Openshaw and Rao, 1995) to produce a set of Output
Areas (OAs) after the census data had been collected, which met certain criteria – a target
population (i.e. average population) with given population minima and homogeneity on
specified other variables (such as housing tenure) plus a shape constraint. The result was a
geography for publishing data from the 2001 UK census with reporting units that were much
more homogeneous than heretofore (Martin et al., 2001); the same procedure was used again in
2011 (Cockings et al., 2011).
The classifications of areas according to their population characteristics using large public and
private datasets has not only stimulated much geographical analysis – of the geography of family
names, for example (Longley et al., 2007), and what they indicate about migration patterns – but
also the development of geodemographics in a wide range of marketing and other applications
(Harris et al., 2005). Classifying small areas according to their residents’ characteristics allows not
only firms but also other organisations, such as political parties, to target likely ‘customers’ for their
products on the assumption that similar people, living in similar areas, have similar tastes – an
assumption they can test using data collected on individual buying-habits by stores. The conduct of
such classifications has been the focus of much debate, especially with regard to the concept of
residential segregation, especially that of ethnic groups (e.g. Poulsen et al., 2011).

Ecological fallacies and inference


Linked to this work on the MAUP was an increasing appreciation of the problem of ecological
inference. Much statistical work involves the analysis of data about population aggregates taken
from censuses, such as the relationships between a population’s age and its health status, from
152 Human geography as spatial science

which inferences about individual behaviour are then drawn; if there is a positive relationship
between the average age of an area’s population and the proportion of its members suffering
long-term illnesses, it may be inferred that older people are more likely to suffer in that way.
But, as classic works in sociology and statistics had shown (and as reviewed in Gary King, 1997),
such an inference may be unsustainable when data on individuals are available. (The classic study
of this – by William S. Robinson (1950) – had a major influence, although geographers –
Subramanian et al. (2008) – have shown using more sophisticated data analyses that his example
was flawed.)
The response to that case was twofold: care in the interpretation of what became known as
‘ecological correlations’ (i.e. analyses based on aggregate data, such as those derived from
censuses for administrative areas, but interpreted as showing a relationship at the individual
level); and attempts to resolve the problem. Regarding the former, given the available data for
tackling many spatial problems, geographers had little alternative but to continue making
such inferences – all the while being aware of both the nature of various inferential problems
involved (Alker, 1969), and the extra issues raised by Openshaw’s work on the MAUP.
Only in the late 1990s was a procedure developed which its author claimed resolved
the ecological inference problem, providing a method of accurately estimating individual
behaviour from aggregate data (King, 1997). Its relevance to geographical work was assessed a
few years later (Sui et al., 2000), and a few applications have been undertaken. At the same time,
other ways of solving the problem have been advanced, such as the entropy-maximising and
micro-simulation approaches already discussed (Johnston and Pattie, 2001). In all of these, the
goal is to derive valid statements about individual behaviour from aggregate data, as an input to
analyses of possible causal relationships.

Point pattern analysis


The analysis of point patterns was one of the earliest focuses of quantitative interest among
geographers, in large part because central place theory and similar models suggested regular
patterns for punctiform data: nearest neighbour analysis was adapted from ecology for their analysis
(e.g. Dacey, 1962; King, 1962). As such, models attracted diminishing attention, however, so point
pattern analysis declined in its importance in human geography. It was revived and much extended,
however, in a series of publications by Openshaw.
In studies of the nuclear industry, for example, he evaluated the potential impact of bombing
different targets and of selecting different locations for nuclear power stations and hazardous
waste disposal by analysing the distribution of population relative to selected points (Openshaw
et al., 1983; Openshaw, 1986; Openshaw et al., 1989). The latter work linked with his later studies
of the clustering of rare events round certain points – such as particular cancers linked to possible
radiation sources – inductively suggesting cause-and-effect relationships; if significant clusters
are identified, this provides strong circumstantial evidence that there is a local cause of the
disease, worthy of closer investigation. He began this work by building a Geographical
Analysis Machine (GAM), which inductively sought all possible clusters in a point pattern, such
as one for cases of childhood leukaemia (Openshaw et al., 1988). This involved using massive
computing power to identify those clusters – groups of points which were unlikely to occur by
chance.
Critiques of Openshaw’s approach focused on details rather than the core argument – that
inductive searches for patterns can stimulate hypothesis development. With spatial autocorrelation,
however, and the problems of underestimated error terms, the significance of clusters may be
overemphasised, leading to developments of tests which allow for that autocorrelation – as in
Markov Chain Monte Carlo methods (Ward and Gleditsch, 2002; alternative approaches are set out
in Elliott et al., 1996; Elliot et al., 2001; and Wakefield et al., 2001).
Human geography as spatial science 153

Local statistics
As stressed repeatedly in this book, one of the basic tenets of geographical work is that places
differ. If that is the case, then the nature of statistical relationships may vary across space – as
suggested by varying gravity model exponents and the application of multi-level models in
geographical research. Furthermore, following from that observation, if the nature of a relationship
varies across space, why is that the case: what other variables are related to such variation? To answer
such questions, geographers have been involved in the development of what are known as local
statistics, as applied to point patterns, univariate and multivariate relationships, and flow patterns
(Fotheringham, 1997; Unwin, 1996). The issue was raised early by Leslie King:

There are no general laws in social science that are consistent over time and independent of the
context in which they are imbedded. The search for law-like generalization of cause and effect
relationship is an illusion. Any particular patterning of events will not remain stable for very
long, and generalization about them cannot provide a firm theoretical basis for intervention.
(1976, p. 304)

John Paul Jones and Robert Hanham (1995) suggested that the reference to context means that
relationships vary over space as well as time (and thereby linked their work on local statistics to the
realist critique of positivism discussed on p. 219, this book).
A substantial component of the literature on certain types of local statistics has been reviewed
by Fotheringham et al. (2002, p. 241, original italics), whose book ‘is based on the premise that
relationships between variables at different points in space might not be constant over space’. Because
of that, an analysis which does not allow for such spatial variation commits what is known as
Simpson’s paradox, which is the ‘reversal of results when groups of data are analysed separately and
then combined’ (Fotheringham et al. 2002, p. 7). In the former case, as they illustrate, spatial
disaggregation may show two negative relationships between a pair of variables, but when they are
aggregated into a single dataset the relationship is positive.
A number of procedures have been explored to test for the existence of this paradox and,
where necessary, identify the separate relationships between different sets of observations within a
population. One (as discussed on p. 146, this book) is multi-level modelling, which takes a linear
relationship between two variables and enquires whether its parameters (the intercept and slope
coefficients) vary according to subsets of the population, which might be spatially defined: ‘Is the
relationship between economic deprivation and the propensity to vote for left-wing political
parties the same across all regions of a country?’, for example (Jones et al., 1992). Another,
developed by geographers – the Spatial Expansion Method (Jones and Casetti, 1992) – related the
parameters of a regression equation to other variables. Most of the applications were aspatial –
they simply tested for differences between subsets of the population, however defined; it was
possible to produce a spatial model so that, for example, the strength of a relationship (between
distance from the CBD and population density, say) varied by sector of the city. This is a rather
limited approach, however, and, as with multi-level modelling, operates with predetermined
subsets of the population rather than inductively, searching for variations in relationships – as with
Openshaw’s searches for clusters of points. (Jones and Bullen, 1994, report on a comparison of the
two methods.)
To extend the search process, Fotheringham et al. (2002) developed a technique which they
term Geographically Weighted Regression (GWR). It tests whether there is spatial variation in the
strength, intensity and direction of a relationship inductively through analysing separate subsets of
the population of data points, defined by their proximity to a randomly selected core at different
scales. This GWR procedure is similar to Openshaw’s GAM just discussed, and Openshaw (1998)
himself produced a similar Geographical Explanations Machine to undertake similar inductive
explorations (and was extended to other statistical procedures – e.g. Harris et al., 2011). With such
154 Human geography as spatial science

methods it is possible to explore whether relationships – such as that between school performance
and the characteristics of its catchment area – vary spatially.
One aspect of the study of local statistics is related to the issue of spatial autocorrelation
(see p. 147, this book). For example, one of the standard spatial autocorrelation statistics may
indicate spatial clustering of a variable across a map of areas for which a variable has been measured,
but not whether this involves a single core of high values for the relevant variable or a series of local
clusters, or ‘hot spots’. Geographers, such as Anselin (1995) and Getis (Ord and Getis, 1995), have
developed measures which can identify such clusters – such as a G* measure which identifies the
degree of clustering of similar values around each area and bearing correlograms indicate whether
trends in a variable are stronger in some directions than others; wombling methods identify
whether certain boundaries (e.g. between two adjacent areas) act as barriers to such a trend,
blocking their development. (For examples of an application of these methods, see O’Loughlin,
2002; Johnston et al., 2009. More generally, Nelson, 2012, reviews recent developments in spatial
statistics.)

Spatial modelling
By the 1980s, spatial analysis would no longer occupy the central place within the discipline’s
literature, as was the case in the 1960s and 1970s. But it remained a foundation of much
geographical analysis and has continued to be significant. Indeed early in the 2000s, according to
Golledge:

Today we have all the components deemed necessary to define and justify the existence of a
scientific discipline – a huge array of empirically-verified factual data, spatial theories and
models, innovative methods of spatial analysis, unique modes of representation, and practical
usefulness for decision-making and policy formulation.
(2002, p. 12)

According to Wilson (1989a, p. 29), modelling within human geography had led to ‘dramatic
advances’ and has ‘a substantial contribution to make in the long term’ (Clarke and Wilson, 1989,
p. 30). Wilson (1989a, p. 30) accepted the limitations of the approach – models ‘have relatively
little to offer in relation to individual behaviour directly’, but are important tools which can ‘help
to handle complexity in a variety of situations’. His review focused on work (much of it his own)
which sought to extend the ‘classics’ of location theory (von Thünen et al.; see also Clarke and
Wilson, 1985; Wilson, 2000), and which he considers has provided, through its mathematical
sophistication, substantial advances in understanding. (Wilson (1989a, p. 41) claimed that the use
of mathematics to model complexity distanced his work from positivism; statistics are needed to
calibrate and test models, but ‘a purely statistical approach to theory and model-building is limited
in scope and is also more directly connected to positivism’.)
The modellers’ achievements were similarly lauded by Macmillan (1989a, 1989b), who
equates their activity with ‘quantitative theory construction’; to him theories are empirically
testable statements of ‘universal empirical propositions, law-like generalizations’ (1989a, p. 93), so
that modelling involves the development of theories which contain ‘quantifiable propositions’ that
can be tested. It has already ‘helped geography to achieve widespread and significant advances’
(1989b, p. 292), and the feelings within the modelling community are of ‘frustrated optimism
rather than pessimism’ (p. 291).
The sort of modelling undertaken – and still promoted by – Alan Wilson (e.g. Wilson, 2011;
Dearden and Wilson, 2011; Pagliara and Wilson, 2010) is now a minority interest within
‘quantitative geography’. Much less attention is now played to geometry and spatial order than in
the early years of the ‘quantitative revolution’, and although distance remains a key concept in some
Human geography as spatial science 155

work – notably of flow patterns, such as migrations and the spread of diseases – it is no longer the
key variable in a large number of analyses; geography is no longer perceived and portrayed as very
largely, ‘a discipline in distance’. Nevertheless, some important work in this area continues, as in
Batty’s (2013) book on The New Science of Cities, in which he revisits some of the ‘traditional’ concerns
of urban geography as a spatial science arguing that ‘to understand place we must understand flows,
and to understand flows we must understand networks’ (p. 1). His modelling leads him to conclude
that ‘there is an intrinsic order to the number, size and shape of the various attributes of networks
and thus, in turn, of spaces and places that depend on them’ (p. 2).
Instead, much more attention is paid to local context, to the links between people and their
environs – physical, built and, especially, social – as influences on behaviour. In effect, space has
been downplayed, and place has become a much bigger leitmotif in much spatial analysis
(as argued in Johnston et al., 2014a, 2014b). As Kelvyn Jones (2010, p. 203) expresses it, the goal
of such work is to identify and then to understand regularities in behaviour, not to seek potential
laws, as some geographers argued for in the 1950s–1960s, but rather to identify ‘potentially causal
generative processes that operate in particular historical, local, or institutional contexts to produce
particular patterns of outcomes’. The development of methods for such analyses continues (e.g.
Fotheringham and Rogerson, 2009; Fischer and Getis, 2009; the contents of these books illustrates
that such analyses are undertaken in a wide range of disciplines and not just geography).
A considerable amount of the criticism of ‘quantitative geography’ (discussed in detail in later
chapters: see Cloke et al., 1991; Cloke, 2004; Cresswell, 2013) is based on an appreciation of that
work as concentrating on the search for geometric order and laws, subordinating the individuality
of subjects to mechanistic cause-and-effect, stimulus-response models (hence its omission from
textbooks introducing contemporary human geography: Cloke et al., 1999, 2005). Much of the
work undertaken in the last three decades is not of that nature, however. Some of the concepts
studied by geographers are necessarily aggregate in nature – unemployment levels, indicators of
health – and are necessarily studied as such; many public policies, including those aimed at
ameliorating if not removing inequalities and injustices, are similarly aimed at population
aggregates, including populations characterised by where they live, rather than at individuals.
Understanding contemporary society calls for analysis of those aggregates, searching for order. The
underlying philosophy, as Jones (2010) argues, is critical realism (see p. 219, this book); the goal
is neither generalisable laws nor simply to interpret and appreciate the lived experience of social
actors but rather to accept that there are truths, knowledge of which is ‘more than just some
undetermined socially constructed language system’ (p. 203). That knowledge – the observed
‘truths’ comprising patterns and relationships – lies in the empirical world which the analyst seeks
to describe in a rigorous and replicable way, accepting that the structures, mechanisms and
tendencies that stimulate the production of those patterns and relationships cannot be ‘discovered’
in analyses of the empirical world; they have to be determined separately, providing convincing –
‘theoretical’ – accounts for the worlds that we live in, and frequently want to change.

Geocomputation
By the late 1980s, technological developments had emerged that would significantly deepen and
broaden the capacities to tabulate and visualise geographical data. In turn, their adoption soon
led to lively and heated debates about the merits of a geography configured around these
technologies.
Very few of the statistical and mathematical developments discussed could have occurred
without rapid cumulative changes in technology which have allowed massive volumes of required
computation to be undertaken increasingly easily and quickly, at decreasing relative prices (Rhind,
1989; Longley et al., 2001, pp. 445–6). As the technology advanced in the last years of the twentieth
century many different ‘geofutures’ could be visualised (Clarke, 1998; Armstrong, 2000).
156 Human geography as spatial science

Computers became generally available for research in universities in the 1960s, and
geographers were soon using them. The first paper on the potential application of computers
in cartography appeared in 1959 (Tobler, 1959). There was much initial collaboration in
writing, developing and operating programs, as illustrated by an early catalogue (Tarrant, 1968),
with texts on computer use by and for geographers (Dawson and Unwin, 1976; Unwin
and Dawson, 1985). There were two major areas of use from the outset – multivariate statistical
analyses and computer mapping (Hägerstrand, 1967; Haggett, 1969). With the former, most
geographers increasingly relied on packages developed for wide use – such as SPSS, MICROTAB
and MINITAB – although developments in specialised fields of spatial analysis (such as spatial
autocorrelation) required custom-built programs. For most human geographers, programming
was no longer a required skill by the 1980s since many of their requirements could be met by
standard packages or others developed for geographical/spatial analysis (Anselin, 1988; Anselin
et al. , 2004; Anselin and Rey, 2010).
This increasing reliance on large computers led to the creation of an approach termed
geocomputation, which incorporates such topics as data visualisation and transformation,
representing and modelling spatial interactions, and generalisation regarding spatial processes
(Longley, 1998). Furthermore, according to Macmillan (1989c, p. 257), such was the computing
power available by the late twentieth century that it allowed more than just a step change in the
geographer’s ability to manipulate information to answer traditional questions:

Technical advances have been so advanced that the problems we can think about have changed.
Moreover, there has been a transformation in the kinds of thoughts we can have [by analogy with
computing power expansion and mathematics]. As it became possible to find solutions to
mathematical problems computationally, so it became possible to think about new classes of
problems that could be solved.

Geocomputation is but one part of a wider area of technical development, which has been
termed geoinformatics and incorporates not only geocomputation but also geodesy, cartography,
photogrammetry, global positioning systems, remote sensing, geostatistics and geographical
information systems (Curran, 2001b). Since then this has been supplemented by the combination
of geographically referenced data with the mobile internet, producing a geoweb.
A number of these – notably remote sensing – received considerable attention within physical
geography (Cooke and Harris, 1970). The analysis of remotely sensed images – initially from
planes, increasingly from satellites – assumed considerable importance because the images provided
immediate, regular and frequent information on parts of the world which were difficult to access
physically, allowing not only detailed mapping but also estimations of environmental conditions
(such as biomass volume, soil wetness and river sediment loads) and assessment of changes,
especially short term. Furthermore, such images are the only sources which provide data at the
global scale, increasingly important for modelling environmental changes. They have attracted
relatively little use in human geography, however, except in work on land use and defining
boundaries of different types of built-up area (Longley and Mesev, 2000; Longley, 2002; Mesev,
2003).
Openshaw (1994, 1995) has argued that the computational power available could transform
the practice of human geography, provided that (1994, p. 504) ‘you are neither blinded by past
prejudices about science, not scared of the words computational human geography, nor too hyped
up by an overenthusiasm for AI or infected by the neural net virus’ (on which, see Fischer and
Gopal, 1993). His approach was empiricist and inductive, calling for ‘greater intelligence by first
becoming less sophisticated in our analysing and modelling technology and then more than
compensating by computational intensity’ (p. 503). He rejected (1995, p. 161) ‘a qualitative,
linguistically defined understanding of how a whole system works in vague and general terms’ and
Human geography as spatial science 157

promoted ‘a detailed and precise computer model of one small part of it’, using fuzzy set logic as
‘a new scientific paradigm for doing geography’ (Openshaw, 1996). He called for a HPC (high
performance computing) culture within geography focusing on HSM (human system modelling),
and the University of Leeds established a Centre for Geographical Computation to advance this
work (as illustrated in Openshaw and Rao, 1995); the book by Openshaw and Openshaw (1997)
illustrates some of the potential uses of AI within this strategy.
Whereas massive computing power has enabled major advances in modelling and data
analysis, it also stimulated improvements in basic analytical procedures. In particular, the
development of visualisation methodologies, such as the ability to graph relationships on computer
screens and to explore maps (Unwin, 1994), aided exploratory data analyses, such as enquiring
whether there is a linear relationship between two variables (something that was often assumed
because of the time-consuming procedures involved in graphical procedures: Jones and Almond,
1992; Jones and Wrigley, 1995), as well as allowing spatial exploratory data analyses (Anselin,
1998). Thus, computing power has enabled not only massive advances in spatial analysis but also
improvements in standard applications. These include mapping. By the mid-1990s, the availability
of computer software mapping packages made much pen-and-ink cartography obsolescent, and
allows exploratory maps to be drawn and rapidly displayed on screen. As Dorling and Fairbairn
(1997, p. 4) expressed it, ‘the craft skills required to undertake map-making are diminishing in
importance’; map-making has moved from the field and the drawing board to the laboratory and
the keyboard (Rhind, 2003) – atlases are relatively straightforward to produce, given the plethora
of data and readily available software, and are frequently deployed as descriptive devices (e.g.
Dorling et al., 2010).
One of the contemporary biggest challenges to spatial data analysis is that posed by what are
generally known as ‘big data’ – large, often geocoded, datasets, many of them collated by commercial
firms from a variety of sources and ‘mined’ to provide inputs to a wide range of (including
locational) decision-making processes. The manipulation and analysis of these data – characterised
by Kitchin (2013, p. 262) as ‘high volume, velocity, variety, exhaustivity, resolution and indexicality,
relationality and flexibility’ – present not only computational issues but also ethical and interpretative
(as set out in Graham and Shelton, 2013; Wyly, 2014); traditional spatial analytic procedures based
on frequentist models with statistical significance testing are no longer relevant for such datasets,
for example (Brunsdon, 2014).

Geographical Information Systems to Geographical


Information Science
The arrival of GIS
Spatial data capture, storage, integration, display and analysis have been advanced since the early
1980s by the development of Geographical Information Systems (GIS: Curran, 1984; Green et al.,
1985; Chrisman et al., 1989; Foresman, 1998; Longley, Goodchild et al., 2005; Chrisman, 2006;
Steinitz, 2014), which brought together rapid advances in computer cartography and data collection
in dedicated machines (comprising both hardware and customised software) for the analysis of the
three main types of spatial data: those referring to points (such as mapped locations), areas (such
as towns and fields) and lines (transport routes, for example). Increasingly, data produced by a wide
variety of agencies are geocoded (i.e. given unique spatial references which facilitate spatial
analysis), and technological advances are leading to the introduction of computers with which it is
possible to gather, store, display and analyse spatial data. Different geocoded datasets (i.e. different
maps) can be integrated within a GIS, which performs the technically demanding tasks of
transforming different coordinate systems to a common structure and interpolates unknown values
from various point and line three-dimensional data (Longley et al., 2011, is an example of the many
158 Human geography as spatial science

textbooks in this area). GIS are, according to Longley (2000, p. 157), ‘fundamentally a facilitating
and applications-led technology, which transparently assesses the importance of space, and as such
should be central to our geographical understanding of the world’. Advances in GIS, as he notes
(Longley, 2004), have been such in recent years as to blur the distinction between iconic and
symbolic modelling; whereas initially GIS stored maps in their iconic form, increasingly they are
able to store symbolic (e.g. formulaic) representations of environments and their process systems,
in four dimensions.
Development of this technology in the UK was heralded and promoted by a major project
initiated to mark the 900th anniversary of the 1086 Domesday Book census. A GIS to provide a
modern equivalent was developed and marketed as a teaching aid for schools and other educational
institutions (Goddard and Armstrong, 1986). Its massive data base could be used to display a wide
range of maps (including the Ordnance Survey 1:50,000 series for the whole of Great Britain) and
pictures, and could also be analysed interactively (Openshaw et al., 1986); the technology on which
it was based is now obsolete. Other major stimuli included early work on computer cartography at
the Experimental Cartography Unit in London, the Department of Geography at Durham and
Edinburgh universities, and the Laboratory for Computer Graphics and Spatial Analysis in the
Graduate School of Design at Harvard University (for histories of GIS, see Foresman, 1998; Mark
et al., 1996; Chrisman, 2006).
GIS allow many problems to be addressed that previously could not be afforded in terms of the
time and resources necessary for data collection, analysis and display: as such, they are the basis for
much applied research work (see p. 338, this book). The UK’s Economic and Social Research Council
established a network of Regional Research Laboratories to explore their potential as research tools
in the late 1980s, most of them located in university departments of geography which offered
postgraduate degree courses in GIS (the October 1988 issue of the ESRC Newsletter, was devoted to
the topic ‘Working with geographical information systems’) and the USA’s National Science
Foundation invested US$5.5 million in a National Center for Geographic Information and Analysis,
based at three sites (see the announcements in the Association of American Geographers’ Newsletter
for August 1987 and October 1988, and Fotheringham and MacKinnon, 1989); a key individual in
winning funding for the latter was Ron Abler, then responsible for geography in the NSF and later
Executive Director of the Association of American Geographers (see p. 86, this book; Mao, 2014; and
Skupin, 2014; Abler’s successor at the AAG, Doug Richardson, also had a background in GIS, having
established a successful firm, GeoResearch). Their use was promoted in teaching (Maguire, 1989;
Fisher, 1989a); an Association for Geographic Information was established in the UK, following a
major report by a House of Lords Select Committee for which a geographer (Rhind) acted as
scientific advisor (Rhind, 1986; Rhind and Mounsey, 1989); several specialist journals were launched
(such as the International Journal of Geographical Information Systems; in 1997 Systems was replaced by
Science); a bibliography of over 1,000 items was published in early 1990 (Bracken et al., 1990); and
a major encyclopaedic survey was published in the following year (Maguire et al., 1991; a second,
much revised and rewritten edition, appeared eight years later; Longley et al., 1999a; for a review of
work in urban geography alone, see Sui, 1994). This movement also saw a large number of textbooks
published to cater for teaching GIS, alongside specialist technical volumes, and others made explicit
the role of GIS in spatial data analysis (O’Sullivan and Unwin, 2003).
In his 1989 presidential address to the Canadian Association of Geographers, Roger Tomlinson
(see also Tomlinson, 2007), a pioneer in the development of GIS from the 1960s on, referred to
their growing use in the following terms:

Geographers have a crucial role to play in integrating a wide variety of technologies into new
forms of ‘earth description’ which will act as a foundation for geographical methodology and
open the way to richer forms of spatial analysis and geographical understanding.
(1989, p. 298)
Human geography as spatial science 159

Spatial problems will multiply and become more complex in the future, and geographers’
ability to handle and analyse large bodies of data in the search for solutions using GIS should
demonstrate the strength of their ‘integrating science’, as part of a ‘data are good ethic’ (p. 292).
Whereas many of those involved in the development of GIS have largely focused on the resolution
of the technical issues involved with integrating data bases and their statistical manipulation,
and cautioned against over-optimism regarding their potential (see Goodchild, 1995b), some of its
promoters have made grand claims, as illustrated by Stan Openshaw’s (1991) reaction to Peter
Taylor’s (1990b) separation of geographical information systems from ‘geographical knowledge
systems’ (see the discussion, p. 156, this book). At its core, however, the use of GIS was charac-
terised, according to one of its leading practitioners, Michael Goodchild, as using ‘geographic
location as a common key to link data’ (Schuurman, 1999, p. 10); the more that is done using
such data, the more central ‘geography’ becomes to a wide range of practices. GIS technology
has enabled many of the advances in spatial analysis discussed. To appreciate the importance of
place – locale, spatial context – as an influence on behaviour, means have been developed using
address files to link individual data (most of them derived from surveys) with information on their
local area (much of it derived from censuses); indeed, in some studies ‘bespoke neighbourhoods’
around each survey respondent’s home have been designed, at a variety of scales, to provide the
best available approximations of each person’s local context (Johnston et al., 2005a; Johnston
et al., 2005b; Boyle et al., 2004; Östh et al., 2015). In other studies, such as the UK Millennium
Birth Cohort Study, the samples have been deliberately spatially structured to enable analyses of the
influence of local geography (such as areas with high levels of child poverty and concentrations of
ethnic minorities: Hansen, 2010). Such designs allow for efficiency in data collection; initially,
because of the potential impact of the clustering on statistical parameters (the problem of spatial
autocorrelation), they were seen to create a ‘nuisance’ for quantitative analyses, but appreciation
of the important role of local context means that such datasets are particularly valuable for explor-
ing the importance of place as a behavioural influence (Jones, 1997), although such procedures
have their limitations, as illustrated by what Kwan (2012) terms the ‘uncertain geographic
context problem’.
The use of GIS has not only expanded exponentially in research over recent decades – across a
wide range of the spatial sciences (as illustrated in NRC, 2011) – but has become the basis for
major commercial developments in the private and public sectors of most countries, along with the
associated use of Geographical Positional Systems (GPS) in many of those applications. As such, it
has been promoted by geographers and for geography in many contexts (as in Cutter et al., 2003),
and as a major element of a geographical education providing graduates with much-demanded
specialist skills is a wide range of employment situations.

Critical responses and debate


GIS soon became the subject of critical debate (see Curry, 1994, and several of the essays in Pickles,
1995a). Pickles (1995b, p. 2), for example, argues that GIS are much more than ‘merely more
efficient counting machines’ providing more accurate descriptions and visual images; their
‘virtual representations will produce illusions that will be so powerful it will not be possible to tell
what is real and what is not real’ (p. 10; see the discussion at p. 82, this book, on Lukermann’s
arguments regarding models). For others, their use, whether in sophisticated marketing procedures
(i.e. geodemographics: see Batey and Brown, 1995; Birkin, 1995; for a critique, see Goss, 1995) or
military applications (N. Smith, 1992), raised moral and ethical issues (none of which are specific
to GIS but apply to any application of ‘knowledge’). To Michael Curry (1995), GIS involve ethical
inconsistencies which are necessarily built into systems and can be used to advance surveillance
(whether by the state or by other bodies) very substantially. (These issues are discussed in Pickles,
1995a; Longley et al., 1999a; on the wider issue of representation, see Cosgrove, 2001.)
160 Human geography as spatial science

In responding to some of these critiques, Daniel Sui (1994) categorised them into those
which stress one or more of the following:

1 ontological inadequacy – GIS present a limited, Cartesian representation of reality, ignoring


social and cultural representations;
2 epistemological insufficiency – GIS are deeply rooted in positivist modes of thinking;
3 methodological insufficiency – GIS applications lack coherent theory and are biased by their
use of secondary data; and
4 ethical inconsistency – the values embedded in GIS are ignored, along with any recognition of
subjective differences in representations of reality.

He claimed that the critiques have ‘at best, been refuted by the GIS community or, at worst, have
been totally dismissed as anti-progress and anti-science nuisances’ (Sui, 1994, p. 268). Examples
are presented of GIS researchers who have addressed each of the four issues, showing that:

the GIS community has realized that the implementation of GIS should go beyond mere technical
decisions justified by matters of efficiency and give the ethical use of this information a serious
consideration. . . . GIS, if not a fertile ground for common search, at least has initiated a search
for common ground.
(p. 271)

(The last sentence draws on the title of Golledge et al.’s, 1988, collection.) Nevertheless, he con-
cluded by noting that ‘so far, GIS enthusiasts and GIS opponents have been mutually hostile or at
least dismissive of each other’s views’ (Sui, 1994, p. 272) and suggested that closer cooperation is
needed in which ‘GIS enthusiasts must avoid the imperialistic claim that science is the only
guarantor of objective truth. Postmodernists (see Chapter 7, this book) must relinquish the playful
cynicism in their critiques on the scientific chauvinism of GIS’. Schuurman (2000) argued that
such cooperation was now developing. She suggests that critiques published during the 1990s
drew responses from GIS specialists, which led to the establishment of an NCGIA initiative on
the social impacts of GIS. Nevertheless, she feared that the lack of a common vocabulary could
reduce the impact of any cooperation, with the critics using approaches based in the sociology of
science that have little in common with the scientific and technological languages employed in GIS.
For Goodchild, many of the critiques – which focused on GIS use in a range of non-academic
contexts – had considerable validity. To him, a ‘GIS is a machine that is capable of a wide range
of operations and these in turn are compatible with a wide range of philosophical positions’
(Schuurman, 1999, p. 5); it can be used both to identify unique features in a dataset and to search
for ‘the general processes that operate on those unique conditions’ (p. 6).
The advances in computer technology, including GIS, have had very substantial impacts on the
practice of cartography and other forms of graphic information display. Only a small number of
geographers are involved in research on cartographic methods (see MacEachren, 1995), but their
work on visualisation has allowed major advances in the computerised presentation of large and
complex datasets (see Dorling, 1995). Dobson (1983a) argued that dealing with these massive
datasets will require the development of automated geography, an ‘integrated systems approach to
geographic problem solving in which the problem is defined, the appropriate methods are chosen,
and the tools are selected from a broad repertoire of automated and manual techniques’ (p. 136).
This would be highly dependent on computer hardware and software developments (sufficient of
which were already available, though see Cowen, 1983) and would facilitate participation in public
policy research on a large scale. Most commentators on Dobson’s paper (in the August 1983 issue
of The Professional Geographer) argued that automated geography was a misnomer, since the main
benefits of the hardware and software that he described related to the scale and speed of data
Human geography as spatial science 161

manipulation only. They preferred less emotive terms such as ‘computer-assisted geography’ or
‘computer-assisted geographic systems’, and some, like Poiker (1983), argued that the case was no
more than one for another set of tools, just as the case for quantification turned out to be decades
earlier: ‘our tool seems to attract an inappropriate number of prophets’ (p. 349). Dobson (1983b)
disagreed, however, arguing that ‘what I am talking about is not a system or collection of systems.
It is a discipline which uses human and electronic cybernetic systems to further understanding of
physical and social systems’ (p. 351), with some decisions (e.g. with regard to how data are
displayed) taken by the computers, not by people. Thus, computers should be programmed so that
they incorporate ‘the character of our discipline’, presenting the results of geographical analysis
without the detailed intervention of geographers (see Couclelis, 1986b; Fisher, 1989b; Haines-
Young, 1989).
Dobson’s arguments were revisited a decade later. He claimed that:

GIS has become a sine qua non for geographic analysis and research in government, business and
academia. This advance has been hailed widely as a technological revolution, but I proposed a
more exciting prospect beyond technology. The strength of GIS innovation and diffusion suggests
that science and society are in the beginning stage of a technological, scientific and intellectual
revolution as profound as earlier revolutions brought on by the printing press or the computer.
(1993, p. 431)

Nevertheless, he expressed concerns over the amount of geographical research done using GIS,
other than in mapping and survey (p. 432), suggesting that ‘the GIS community is still searching
for a greater sense of purpose’ (p. 433), and claiming that ‘the current state of GIS is woefully
deficient when compared to our predecessors’ ultimate goal of representing landscapes as three-
dimensional geographic units with interactions of multiple phenomena in space and time, with
order’ (p. 434). He ended with a call for geographers to become more involved in what was clearly,
to him, an unfulfilled revolution:

The technological revolution, understandably, may be led by private companies and government
laboratories, and technical leadership may come from many fields. But academic geographers
are essential to the scientific and intellectual revolutions. Geographers are needed as
consummate leaders in conceptual design and in geographic analysis employing GIS.
(p. 438)

Others agreed, while noting that hardware and software developments, although substantial,
were still far from those needed for completing Dobson’s revolution (Armstrong, 1993; Cromley,
1993). But whereas some were optimistic about the growing use of computers in all aspects of
geography (and not just those involving numerical applications: Monmonier, 1993), others were
pessimistic. Marble and Peuquet (1993, p. 446), for example, argued that since 1983 ‘the impact of
the computer upon geographic research appears to have been even less than our most pessimistic
estimates’, in part because of ‘a substantial turning away from those activities that GIS can do best’
(p. 447). Goodchild (1993, p. 445) appeared to agree: ‘Whether or not GIS and automated
geography have anything to offer to geographic research, we cannot escape the fact that GIS has had
a significant impact on many kinds of human activity.’ This was reflected in the subtitle of
Sheppard’s (1993) contribution – ‘What kind of geography for what kind of society?’ – and in
Pickles’s (1993) rehearsal of arguments regarding the impact of technology on geographical and
other practices (see p. 159, this book).
The technical advances have not been associated with parallel developments in substantive
geographic theories it is argued, therefore, in large part because (as discussed in later chapters)
spatial analysis has been somewhat marginalised within the discipline. In some of the continuing
162 Human geography as spatial science

work, the ‘traditional’ models associated with the developments of the 1950s/1960s have provided
the basic underpinning, focusing on optimum distributions of points and lines, and on flows
between those points along the lines. Wilson (1984b) argued that mathematical development
enables us to build new models by combining old problems (for example, von Thünen’s and
Weber’s) with new methods, claiming that comprehensive models can now be built combining
macro-population backcloth, macro-economic backcloth, spatial interaction, the location of
population activities, the location of economic activities, and the development of economic
infrastructure into representations of spatial pattern or settlement structure.Two papers ‘demonstrate
the ability of models of spatial interaction and structure to reproduce the results of classical
industrial location theory’ (Birkin and Wilson, 1986, p. 305) and they are the foundation for the
applied work undertaken at Leeds (Birkin et al., 1995: see p. 351), but relatively few workers now
concentrated on such modelling. Even more prefer non-positivistic approaches, leaving the
substantial GIS community somewhat isolated within geography as a whole – notwithstanding calls
to overcome such divides (Elwood, 2006; Kwan, 2004; Kwan and Schwanen, 2009a, 2009b;
Schwanen and Kwan, 2009; Zolnik, 2009), through hybrid, critical or participatory GIS. One of the
proponents of deconstructing the divides via a ‘critical GIS’ argued that by the mid-2000s there had
been ‘three distinct waves’ (Schuurman, 2006, p. 727) of critiques of GIS:

The first wave, between 1990 and 1994, was characterized by the ferocity of the criticism that
human geographers reaped on technical geography and spatial analysis . . . the tone of the
papers was frequently scolding and paternalistic . . .
  The second wave of critiques took place between 1995 and 1998. By 1995, more than forty
papers had been published by human geographers worried about the implications of a pervasive
GIS. . . . Concern was expressed that GIS best served large corporations and public agencies
rather than the disenfranchised. . . . Moreover, critics were skeptical about a technology that
they deemed a relic of the quantitative revolution . . .

For Schuurman, a third wave of critique followed at the end of the 1990s, but this saw the birth
of ‘critical GIS’, which moved from antagonistic attacks on GIS ‘to a means of positively affecting
a technology that was being widely adopted in other disciplines and in the commercial sphere’.
Yet, during the same decade, Obermeyer (1994) had claimed that GIS now meets all the criteria
for identification as a separate profession. At the same time, too, arguments were being advanced
that the last term in GIS should be changed to Science.

GISci
Goodchild (1992, p. 31) made the case for GIS to be renamed as Geographical Information Science,
arguing that while ‘spatial data handling may describe what we do’ and that many of the advances in
GIS have been technology-driven, there were two questions that suggested the change of name. The
first concerned GIS as science, addressing a particular set of scientific questions that are generic
rather than restricted to particular applications; the second concerned GIS for science, with wide
applications across many sciences. Regarding the first set, he argued that because geographical (or
spatial) data have unique properties, then this leads to a set of generic issues that such a science
would cover: these relate to data collection, measurement and capture, spatial statistics, data model-
ling and theories of spatial data, algorithms for representing data, data display, and analytical tools.
In each, he claims, there are ‘clearly challenging scientific questions [in which] . . . the spatial context
appears to be distinctive’ (p. 40). Addressing such key questions is the core of his nascent geographic
information science (GISci), which focuses on technological solutions to the many issues relating to
spatial data handling, whose relevance is widespread across other sciences and in myriad public and
private sector applications. (On GISci as a science, see Sui, 2004a; Reitsma, 2013.)
Human geography as spatial science 163

Several years later, Goodchild reaffirmed the value of the term, noting that:

I wanted to respond [in the 1992 paper] to comments that seemed to marginalize GIS as ‘a mere
tool’. . . . The history of science provides ample evidence that there is nothing ‘mere’ about many
scientific tools. The microscope and telescope both produced an outpouring of new science
and new ways of thinking about the world. By comparison, however, the effects of the digital
computer have been immeasurably greater . . . I wanted to suggest that when a researcher in
the GIS community used the acronym they were probbaly referring to something more than
software . . .
(1995a, p. 1)

Fifteen years later, he reviewed the first two decades of GISci (Goodchild, 2010), identifying
not only major research achievements which had generated widely adopted, user-friendly, data-
handling and associated scientific breakthroughs, but also institutional accomplishments:
GIScientists, like Waldo Tobler and David Rhind, had been elected to national science academies,
for example, and – perhaps like regional science before it but a much greater size – a growing
professionalisation of the field reflected in its conferences and journals (he identified sixteen
of the latter). Five issues for the next decade were then discussed: ‘knowing where everything is,
all the time’; the role of the citizen in what is sometimes known as ‘participatory GIS’ or neogeo-
graphy (Turner, 2006; Leszczynski, 2014); the use of GIS in dynamic, ‘real time’, data collection,
analysis and modelling; introducing third (time) and higher dimensions to what is largely a
two-dimensional enterprise; and GIS education, leading to the conclusion that:

the domain addressed by GIScience is well-defined and persistent. There is no danger that
GIScience will be absorbed into one of its intersecting disciplines: geography, computer science,
or information science. On the other hand a greater interaction with a broader domain of spatial
information science seems both logical and desirable.
(p. 16)

(The latter point is also central to the NRC, 2011, report.)


GIS has certainly transformed a substantial proportion of geographic research in recent decades
(in physical as well as human geography, as illustrated by papers in the relevant specialised journals,
and the birth of new ones in the 1990s such as Annals of GIS, Transactions in GIS, and the International
Journal of Geographical Information Science, which celebrated its 25th anniversary in 2011, with a free
access virtual issue containing 25 ‘classic’ papers that shaped the field: www.tandf.co.uk/journals/
pdf/freeaccess/TGIS25th.pdf). The sheer weight of publications led to those analysing their content
to describe a ‘paradigm of GIScience’ (Parr and Lu, 2010). In addition, GIS has become widely used
commercially and by public agencies for the storage, display and analysis of myriad types of spatial
data. As such, skills with GIS are seen as important for future generations of graduates, and geogra-
phers have argued that GIS should form a central component of degree programmes, providing
graduates with ‘transferable skills’ that they can apply in a range of careers. Indeed, GIS has been
presented by some as a ‘saviour’ for the discipline, providing it with a raison d’être within the edu-
cational structure and a component of the discipline which should enable it to attract students. In
surveys of graduate employment and academic job opportunities in the mid-1990s, for example,
the Association of American Geographers found that more programmes were preparing graduates
for careers in GIS and remote sensing than any other specialism, that GIS was the modal employ-
ment category for new graduates, and that GIS specialists were in most demand for posts in USA
geography departments – with many more to be hired over the next decade than were expected to
retire, resulting in a rebalancing of the profession. (The reports are reproduced in NAS-NRC, 1997;
see also p. 87, this book.)
164 Human geography as spatial science

In reporting on a ‘renaissance’ in geography during the 1990s, the NAS-NRC (1997) volume
Rediscovering Geography paid particular attention to spatial analysis and GIS as indicative of the discipline’s
relevance to contemporary social problems. GIS, geographic visualisation and spatial statistics get
much of the coverage in the chapter on ‘Geography’s techniques’– indeed, that chapter makes no
reference to the methodologies deployed in other areas of geography (such as those discussed in
the next chapters). The case for promoting geography in this way is clarified in the chapter’s
conclusion:

Current trends in geography’s techniques suggest a future in which researchers, students,


business people and public policy makers will explore a world of shared spatial data from their
desktops. . . . The users of the future will also bring different world views and theoretical
perspectives to these tools. They will challenge the adequacy of current techniques for analysing
and understanding geographic phenomena, posing challenges that must be taken up by
developers when designing next-generation tools and theories.
(p. 69)

Similarly, chapters on ‘Geography’s contributions to scientific understanding’ and ‘Geography’s


contributions to decision making’ focus substantially on spatial analysis and GIS applications,
including a ‘national spatial data infrastructure’. Not surprisingly, therefore, when it comes to the
report’s recommendations for ‘Strengthening geography’s foundations’ with regard to research and
teaching priorities, the section on ‘Geographic competency among college and university students’
calls for:

efforts to ensure that . . . [they] have access to geography courses and perspectives that go
beyond a concern with ‘where things are‘ to provide a basic conceptual and analytic grounding in
the spatial and environmental dimensions of human and physical processes.
(pp. 150–1)

Furthermore:

The discipline of geography is in a period of transition from a past where most geographic infor-
mation was transmitted in the form of paper maps to a future in which most geographic
information will be transmitted through digital information systems. . . . Geographers need to
learn about these spatial information sources and understand how to use them appropriately in
their work. Academic geographers also need to consider how new technologies and data sources
will create new opportunities for collaborations with the private sector.
  If geography is to meet the challenges of rapid technological change, steps must be taken to
familiarize students with new technologies for data analysis and display. . . . Technology now
plays a pre-eminent role in a wide range of geographic research. . . . Continued advances of this
sort will require a substantial coterie of geographers who understand new technologies and can
use them effectively.
(p. 160)

As far as the report is concerned, the future of American geography lies very much with spatial
analysis and its enabling technologies, such as GIS. Certainly, GIS was then rapidly expanding as a
technology, enabling not only the relatively easy resolution of previous difficulties regarding the
integration of spatially coded datasets, but also both a wide range of commercial/public sector
applications and the ability to pose questions previously unconsidered. For Longley et al. (1999b,
p. 1) GIS is a ‘generic term denoting the use of computers to create and depict digital representations
of the Earth’s surface’, thereby enabling a wide range of geographical questions to be addressed. By
Human geography as spatial science 165

1997 it was being taught in over 1,500 universities and there were some 500,000 regular users in
an industry worth US$12 billion annually. GIS has its own learned societies and literature, and a
number of major annual conferences, but the adjective in its title is more than symbolic: geography
is the academic discipline most closely connected with developments in the application and
teaching of GIS, if not in the enabling hardware developments, with potentials that extend well
beyond the narrowly technical (Gilbert, 1995).
Since then, GIS applications have multiplied, as reflected in the NRC (2011) report on
Understanding the Changing Planet, which has a chapter on ‘How might we better observe, analyze and
visualize a changing world’ which discusses those developments and the future potential of GIS
and GISci with the development of what it terms a cyberinfrastructure. The analysis of such data
‘requires a set of highly distinct and specialized techniques collectively known as spatial
data analysis. The assumptions, data structures, and techniques of spatial data analysis are very
different from those of standard statistical analysis and require specially designed software packages
commonly known as GIS’ (pp. 162–3); training in those specialised techniques is thus central to its
programme for the expansion of ‘geographical science’.
GIS has led to a reappraisal of the prior moves to quantification, spatial science and speculation
on laws in geography. This includes some of the themes that animated behavioural geography, in
the form of cognitive models of geographic space (Mark et al., 1999) as well as fundamental
questions about geographical representation and spatial analysis (Miller and Wentz, 2003). They
have included re-evaluation of  Tobler’s (1970) proposal for a first law of geography (see p. 148,
this book, and Miller, 2004). Sui (2004b, p. 269) notes that this, which he calls ‘TFL’ for short, had
‘remained buried in the literature without much notice throughout the 1970s and 1980s’, until
GIS in the 1990s ‘gradually brought new popularity to TFL both within and outside geography.’
Although others have questioned its veracity, universality and meaning (Barnes, 2004b; J. M. Smith,
2004), for Harvey Miller:

To a large degree, TFL distinguishes geography from other fields of inquiry. Using TFL as a core
principal, spatial analysis and geographic information science continue to develop sophisticated
techniques for extracting explanatory and predictive power . . .
(2004, p. 288)

GIS has also proved a vehicle for reintroducing maps to geography, albeit in a very different
form from previous situations (Kain and Delano-Smith, 2003; Rhind, 2003). In the 1950s, the map
was still being promoted as the foundational geographical tool (James, 1954, p. 9; Robinson,
1954). Fifty years later, editors were bemoaning their absence from many geographical papers
(Martin, 1998; J. Wheeler, 1998; see also Johnston, 2004b). Dorling (1998), however, argued that
mapping is becoming much more common beyond the discipline, in a wide range of contexts:

Maps have become a very common currency. People in western societies now consult maps so
often that they often do not remember using them. These images have become commonplace,
from bus maps to maps of offices, to maps in newspapers, in books, and on the news. They are so
common that we often fail to question their authority, fail to ask why they are drawn as they are.
(p. 279)

Many of those maps are used to change the way in which people think about the world
(as happened in the Second World War when new projections were used to demonstrate America’s
proximity to Europe with regard to potential aerial attack: Schulten, 2001). ‘Not all maps simplify,
subvert, collude or conceal’ (Dorling, 1998, p. 287), but their use as a means of informing and
educating should remain a focus of geographers’ concerns, albeit sometimes in new media
(Crampton, 2009). For Sui, GIS could therefore be the basis for a:
166 Human geography as spatial science

third culture [that] stresses the cross-fertilization of creative ideas from the arts and sciences
via state-of-the-art technology. The recent history of GIS and cartography should be viewed in
the context of the third culture, which has the potential to fuse traditional branches of knowledge
in truly creative ways . . . whether geography is going to become a more vibrant discipline
depends on to what extent we can revive geographic imaginations in this computer age via
GIScience to address issues of great societal concern.
(2004a, p. 63)

As we chart in Chapter 9, claims about the ways that GIS could bridge social concern, theory, maps
and technology have continued in the decade since.

Conclusions
As stressed in the previous chapter, much of the force of the developments in human geography
during the 1950s and 1960s concerned methodology and the approach to traditional geographical
questions. In addition, however, attempts were made to inaugurate and press a particular
geographical point of view, with two main themes. The first – the spatial-science viewpoint – was
fairly widely and rapidly accepted, and many geographers placed spatial variables at the centre of
their research efforts; as will be indicated in Chapter 5, their work came under increasing attack
from the late 1960s. The second – the systems approach – has received much less detailed
attention, despite frequent approving gestures, except in studies of environmental and
demographic systems. Compared with the spatial-science view, which could be rapidly assimilated
within the developing statistical methodology, the systems approach was technically much more
demanding, and perhaps for that reason attracted fewer active researchers (though see Coffey’s,
1981, defence).
Although there were some antecedents, human geography as spatial science was largely
inaugurated in North America in the 1950s. By the end of the 1960s it was providing much of the
material for many of the journals published throughout the English-speaking world (Wheeler,
2002a). Much research was positivist in its tone, if not its detail, seeking not only to describe
patterns of spatial organisation but also to account for (explain) these as consequences of the
influence of distance on human behaviour. A great deal of it used quantitative methods and it
contributed to bodies of theory about spatial organisation in general or certain aspects of it in
particular. It has influenced other academic disciplines (even though, as Laponce, 1980, expressed
it, geography had less impact on the other social sciences than vice versa) and the planning
profession.
Since the 1970s, positivist spatial science has been under considerable attack among
anglophone human geographers. This attack had little initial effect on the volume of work done in
this paradigm, as illustrated by a major review of Quantitative Geography by workers in the UK (Wrigley
and Bennett, 1981); this work has been stimulated and aided by advances in data-handling
technology and display. The approach was also fostered outside the Anglo-American realm,
especially in Western Europe where the reaction to quantification was initially stronger than in the
UK and North America (see Bennett, 1981b). Many of the models and theories that acted as the
foundations to the pioneering work,such as central place theory, are now largely consigned to
disciplinary history, as stimuli to work that eventually proved relatively unproductive but generated
interest in a wider range of issues that remain central to a geographical agenda, along with the
methods needed to address that agenda.
Work in the spatial-science mould continues to thrive, however (though Kevin Cox, 2014, has
expressed surprise at the degree to which it has been marginalised within geography). The field of
GIS, for example, has spawned its own suite of outlets and professional societies, much like remote
Human geography as spatial science 167

sensing before it. This is part of the specialisation and fragmentation that came to characterise
human geography (Johnston, 1996b, 2004b) and, given the large volume of work done in other
parts of the discipline, means that much of what is being reported can readily go unnoticed by
other geographers. For a while it appeared for many that quantitative analyses had been marginalised
within geography, while supporters of geocomputation and GIS had promoted their saleable
expertise:

It is clear that geographers specializing in geographical information systems will survive


only by combining considerable technical expertise with a taste and talent for the
Realpolitik of grants, contracts, committees, administrators, and entrepreneurs. A canny
awareness of commercial and political realities will be as necessary as any particular intellectual
qualities.
(N. J. Cox, 1989, p. 207)

For Nicholas Cox, this carried the danger that ‘preoccupation with data will omit imagination
and creativity’ (p. 208) but, as the later chapter in this book on applied geography shows, many see
it as a major way to protect the discipline in a context where utility and saleability are the crucial
indicators of the worth of its work. This great volume of commercial and applied work suggests that
there has been a mode of ‘progress’ within the positivist approach. But there has also been a series
of debates about its merits and latterly more engagements between GISci and wider theoretical
concerns. For some authors, spatial analysis retained – or should retain – a central position within
geography. Casetti (1999, p. 339), for example, identified three modes of enquiry – literary,
academic and mathematical. His preference was clearly for the last of these, arguing that ‘In
geography in general, and in human geography in particular, the mathematical mode of inquiry is
progressing much too slowly . . . [to have the required] positive influence on . . . the evolution of
the social SCIENCE called geography’ (original capitals). Like others involved with the quantitative
revolution (e.g. Getis, 1993), he feared that the spatial analytic viewpoint was being marginalised
within geography. It had ‘saved geography from extinction as a serious university discipline, by
attracting and training good students, by writing articles and books that developed theory and
method, by gaining a foothold in science at large, and by applying these methods and theories to
contemporary social problems’ (Morrill, 1993, p. 442), but these gains were at risk as geography
becomes increasingly ‘anti-science’ (p. 446). As stressed by Johnston et al. (2014a), however, there
has been a major change of emphasis within contemporary spatial analysis, with studies of place
becoming dominant and those of space declining in their volume.
Much of the remainder of this book is concerned with alternative approaches to human
geography from those outlined in this chapter; many were initially based on critiques of ‘positivist
spatial science’, and some have attracted large numbers of adherents. They have certainly involved
critiques of the idea of human geography as science – at least in the terms that the later came to be
understood by geographers in the 1960s – if not always being ‘anti-science’.
Yet if the paradigm model of revolutions and normal science discussed in Chapter 1 is
relevant to human geography, then as a consequence – given the later developments discussed in
the following chapters – interest in the approaches set out here should have waned in the 1970s
and 1980s, if not disappeared totally. In relative terms there has undoubtedly been some decline,
as the alternative world views on offer (discussed later in this book) have attracted substantial
attention. But a substantial amount of work is still being done which is firmly based within the
world views that came to the fore in geography in the 1960s, and there continue to be substantial
advances in the methods and applications of spatial analysis. This was illustrated in O’Kelly’s
(1999) listing of some of the most influential papers in Geographical Analysis over its first 30 years
of publication. Thirteen years later, Nelson reviewed trends in spatial statistics, identifying new
opportunities in the
168 Human geography as spatial science

better integration of GIS and spatial analysis, the development of methods for large spatial data
sets, overcoming the limitations of local statistics, improving how spatial sciences are
communicated, and retaining the home of spatial analysis within geography.
(2012, p. 87)

Some of its adherents have sought to accommodate the critiques, while others have counter-
attacked and argued for the validity and vitality of their point of view. There have been significant
calls too for hybrid approaches that transcend these divides. There is a general consensus among the
counter-attackers that modelling, with associated quantitative analysis, is a viable approach to
human geography, though there is considerable variability in emphasis as to the way forwards.
Moreover, as computers moved from being tools that could be marshalled for geographical analysis
to becoming part of the everyday socio-technical worlds that human geography reckons with, so
new questions about the relationships between geocodes, technology, society and space have arisen
(Kitchin and Dodge, 2011; Pickles, 2004). Latterly, these include the geospatial web or geoweb,
where cloud computing, internet and georeferenced data and mobile devices are interacting in
ways that shift subjectivities and social relations (Elwood, 2010; Elwood and Leszcynski, 2011;
Yang et al, 2011). Haklay et al. (2008, p. 2011) thus described how, in everyday life, ‘New techniques
are being used and new terms have been invented and entered the lexicon such as: mash-ups,
crowdsourcing, neogeography and geostack.’ We will return to these evolving forms of applied
geography in Chapter 9.
Meanwhile, in the decades while those technologies and subjectivities were in formation,
other approaches to geographical study have been introduced and debated, many of which have few
links with those introduced here; in many cases, the subject matter addressed does not call for the
forms of analysis discussed in this chapter.They are discussed in the following chapters, exemplifying
the rich variety in geographical scholarship which emerged, in various ways, from the ‘revolutions’
inaugurated in the decades after the Second World War.
Chapter 5

Humanistic geography

An impartial spectator at the time would likely have bet on the eventual victor of the positivists,
who were young, coordinated, and zealous; but a change in the zeitgeist was about to favor
humanistic geography for close to 20 years.
(Jonathan M. Smith, 2009, p. 241)

Abstraction and fragmentation in human geography are related facets of a broader cultural
condition, and as such they should not be confused with a law of nature.
(David Ley, 1989, p. 244)

Maps can be misleading because they don’t – and can’t – convincingly represent the
seamier side of life. Consider United States Geological Survey Topographic Sheets.
Looking through them, one might well conclude that all is well with America. What can be
amiss when forests are green, rivers and lakes are blue, and settlements are either a
eye-catching yellow or a healthy pink, depending on the scale? Conveying rot and degradation
cartographically is difficult, perhaps impossible, because maps use conventional signs,
which exhibit pattern, and pattern is by its nature aesthetic, whether it represents tulips or
sewage pits.
(Yi-FuTuan, 2002a, p. 129)

In 1985, I sat in a course called humanistic geography. It was a second year course at University
College London taught by Peter Jackson and Jacquie Burgess. It was a revelation to me. It
made me decide I wanted to be a geographer. Here we learned about Tuan and Relph and
Buttimer. We also learned to go out into London and talk to people, to record our impressions,
to be creative – to practice a form of ethnography.
(Tim Cresswell, 2010, p. 169)

Although the behavioural geography that was considered in Chapter 4 had involved a reorientation
of the work undertaken within the spatial-science approach, it maintained the generally positivist
framework and overall commitments to scientific methods. Alongside it from the early 1970s,
however, though with roots extending much further back, emerged a fundamental critique of the
entire positivist approach. Much of this also argued for a focus on the individual as decision-maker,
but denied the goal of explanation and prediction that was inherent to the behavioural approach;
its goal was fuller appreciation and understanding of human values, meanings and interpretations.
It rebuffed the idea of human geography as a science in favour of it as a discipline aligned with the
arts and humanities.
Critics were vocal in their opposition to what had been promoted as the ‘new [scientific]
geography’ (as illustrated in Cosgrove’s 1989a, 1989b, cogent presentations of that case). Indeed,
J. M. Smith notes how:
170 Humanistic geography

the harbingers of a new mode of inquiry . . . spatial scientists assertively promoted a new ‘posi-
tivist’ geography, and in so doing frightened a large number of regional, historical, and cultural
geographers, as well as some old style economic geographers, into self-conscious awareness of
their identity as methodological humanists.
(2009, p. 241)

Be it out of fear, or mere bemusement, that opposition to spatial science was clarified by Entrikin’s
definition of what became known as humanistic geography as:

a reaction against what they believe to be an overly objective, narrow, mechanistic and
deterministic view of [the human being] presented in much of the contemporary research in the
human sciences. Humanist geographers argue that their approach deserves the appellation
‘humanistic’ in that they study the aspects of [people] which are most distinctively ‘human’:
meaning, values, goals and purposes.
(1976, p. 616)

A few years later, Meinig (1983) advocated ‘geography as an art’, reviewing themes such
as ‘geography and literature’, ‘geography and the humanities’ and the ‘geographer as a creator
of literature’. Meinig was keen to link human geography more closely to the humanities
and arts, rather than see it as a science. He mobilised a range of past currents in geography
in this task:

one can pick out a few bold threads and trace connections . . . but essentially it is a new literature,
for while we have long had a ‘human geography’ we have never before had an explicitly
‘humanistic geography’ with such a self-conscious drive to connect with that special body of
knowledge, reflection, and substance about human experience and human expression, about
what it means to be a human being on this earth.
(p. 315)

Reviewing the variety of similar calls for humanistic geography of the 1970s and 1980s,
Cloke et al. (1991, p. 69) also noted the way that they emerged from a critique of spatial science:

It almost goes without saying that the geographers referenced here were unhappy about the
tendency of spatial science to treat people as little more than dots on a map, statistics on a graph
or numbers in an equation, since the impression being conveyed was of human beings ‘whizzing’
around in space – travelling from place X to place Y; shopping in centre X rather than in centre Y;
selling produce in market X rather than at market Y – in a fashion little different from the
‘behaviour’ of stones on a slope, particles in a river or atoms in a gas. Indeed, it was complained
that such exercises . . . effectively converted human beings into ‘dehumanised’ entities drained
of the very ‘stuff’ (the meanings, values and so on) that made humans into humans as opposed
to other things living or non-living.

Seventeen years later, one of those authors similarly characterised humanistic geography
as:

driven by a belief that spatial science failed to take seriously the lived experiences, decisions and
struggles of human beings as human beings (not as dots on maps, numbers in tables or flow-
lines in diagrams). To some degree, such a worry emerged within spatial science, occasioning a
behavioural move . . . inquiring into the bases of people’s environmental perception, cognition
and decision-making . . . For other scholars, however, there could be no truck with spatial
Humanistic geography 171

science because its very philosophical and methodological precepts disqualified it from
embracing humanity in its profounder, meaningful and even spiritual dimensions.
(Philo, 2008, pp. xxix–xx)

The nature of those criticisms, the alternatives advanced and the developing practices of humanistic
geography are the subject of this chapter.

Humanistic geography’s antecedents in cultural


and historical geography
As indicated in earlier chapters, relatively few cultural and historical geographers were attracted
by the so-called quantitative and theoretical revolutions. There was some application of statistical
procedures to make work in these fields appear more contemporary or ‘modern’, but few substantive
changes were adopted by adherents working within the traditional approaches (despite the efforts
of the ad hoc committees established to chart ways forward for the ‘new geography’: see p. 85, this
book). By the 1970s, however, some historical and cultural geographers had taken the initiative
and were proposing alternative philosophies to positivism which were humanistic in their
orientation: according to Hugill and Foote (1994, p. 12), prior to the Second World War ‘cultural
geography was more advanced in its theories than was the rest of human geography’, but the
challenge of the ‘revolutions’ outlined in the previous two chapters meant that ‘Cultural geography
ceased to be the most theoretically informed of the subdisciplines and embarked on a long search
for theory that is still underway’ (p. 14).
The beginnings of these changes can be traced to two papers, one of which had more impact
on the geographical discipline at large. In the first, John K. Wright (1947, p. 12) introduced the
term ‘geosophy’, defined as the study of geographical knowledge:

it covers the geographical ideas, both true and false, of all manners of people – not only
geographers, but farmers and fishermen, business executives and poets, novelists and
painters, Bedouins and Hottentots – and for this reason it necessarily has to do with subjective
conceptions.
(p. 12)

Wright conceded that study of such subjective ideas could not employ the strict scientific
principles of physical geography, but claimed that it provided indispensable background and
perspective to geographical work:

geographical knowledge of one kind or another is universal among men, and is in no sense a
monopoly of geographers . . . such knowledge is acquired in the first instance through
observations of many kinds. . . . Its acquisition, in turn, is conditioned by the complex ­interplay of
cultural and psychological factors . . . nearly every important activity in which man engages,
from hoeing in a field or writing a book or conducting a business to spreading a gospel or waging
a war, is to some extent affected by the geographical knowledge at his disposal.
(pp. 13–14)

These words could well have heralded an earlier start to behavioural geography than that chronicled
above, but the lack of reference to them in later published works suggests that they had little impact
until taken up by Wright’s colleague at the American Geographical Society, David Lowenthal (1961,
p. 259), in a widely cited paper ‘concerned with all geographic thought, scientific and other: how
it is acquired, transmitted, altered and integrated into conceptual systems’. Lowenthal argued in a
172 Humanistic geography

wide-ranging survey that the world of each individual’s experience is intensely parochial and
covers but a small fraction of the total available. There are consensus views about many aspects of
the world, but individuals will often mistakenly assume that their view is the consensus. We all live
in personal worlds, which are ‘both more and less inclusive than the common realm’ (p. 248). Our
perceptions of these worlds are personal too; they are not fantasies, being firmly rooted in reality,
but because ‘we elect to see certain aspects of the world and to avoid others’ (p. 251) behaviour
based on such perceptions must have its unique elements. Different cultures have their own shared
stereotypes, however, which are often reflected in language, and attempts are made to create
environments fitting into these stereotypes:

The surface of the earth is shaped for each person by refraction through cultural and personal
lenses of custom and fancy. We are all artists and landscape architects, creating order and
organizing space, time, and causality in accordance with our apperceptions and predilections.
(p. 260)

His ideas were implemented in papers concerned with the interpretation of landscapes as reflections
of societal norms and tastes (e.g. Lowenthal, 1968; Lowenthal and Prince, 1965), thereby belatedly
bringing Wright’s ideas before a wider, and perhaps more readily appreciative, audience.
The second of the original papers was by a British geographer, although it was published in
India (Kirk, 1951; it is reprinted in Boal and Livingstone, 1989; see also Johnston, 1993c); the
main arguments were reiterated in a later article (Kirk, 1963). Kirk stressed that the environment is
not simply a ‘thing’ but rather a whole with ‘shape, cohesiveness and meaning added to it by the
act of human perception’ (Kirk, 1963, p. 365); once this meaning has been ascribed, it tends to
be passed to later generations. Thus, he recognised two, separate but not independent, environ-
ments: a phenomenal environment, which is the totality of the earth’s surface, and a behavioural
environment, which is the perceived and interpreted portion of the phenomenal environment:
‘Facts which exist in the Phenomenal Environment but do not enter the Behavioural Environment
of a society have no relevance to rational, spatial behaviour and consequently do not enter into
problems of the Geographical Environment’ (p. 367). Since much geography is concerned with
decision-making and its consequences, appreciation of the behavioural environment should be
central to its study. Indeed, according to Ley (1977a), one cannot proceed without such awareness
of what is in the behavioural environment; even an apparently neutral statement such as ‘Pittsburgh
is a steel town’ is, he argued, a value-laden view of a geographer-outsider, which may not accord
with the perceptions of the resident-insiders, so that:

Too often there is the danger that our geography reflects our own concerns, and not the meanings
of the people and places we write of. . . . The geographical fact is as thoroughly a social product
as the landscape to which it is attached.
(Ley, 1977a, p. 12)

Disciplines, as indicated in Chapter 1, usually comprise a number of ‘invisible colleges’, groups


of scholars working on the same topic who refer to each other’s publications. Wright, Lowenthal
and Kirk were not members of any substantial ‘college’ during the early 1960s, and so had little
impact on the first phase of behavioural work identified in the previous chapter. None of the three
is in Pred’s (1967, 1969) reviews of the field, for example, nor referred to by Wolpert’s (1964,
1965, 1967, 1970) work through the decade. Golledge et al. (1972, p. 75) make only a passing
reference to Lowenthal’s work in their overview of behavioural approaches in geography:

Pursued by insightful researchers, the analysis of literary and other artistic data of past and
present can have strong explanatory power. The subjective element in these attempts to assess
Humanistic geography 173

the impact of spatial perception is acknowledged, but its presence in many other studies is more
subtle and potentially damaging.

Kirk (1978, p. 388) referred to his influence on non-geographers who adopted the concept
of the behavioural environment, however, and Spate (1989, p. xix) later described Kirk’s initial
paper as ‘the Catalytic Crystal in the Saturated Solution’, a trigger for the ‘crystallization’ of a
humanistic geography (for a detailed exegesis of Kirk’s work, see J. Campbell, 1989).The behavioural
work of the mid-1960s was in the positivist mould; that of Wright, Lowenthal and Kirk just
discussed was not, however, and so they were largely ignored by the former, who were in the
ascendancy.
Several cultural and historical geographers did take up the concept of the behavioural or
perceived environments though. One of the leaders was Brookfield, a British geographer with field
experience, by the mid-1960s, of South Africa, Mauritius, New Guinea, and several Pacific Islands.
In reviewing work by cultural geographers on these societies, he noted:

A difference of approach is apparent between those who have an overtly chorographic purpose,
who scarcely ever seek explanations in matters such as human behaviour, attitudes and beliefs,
social organization, and the characteristics and interrelationships of human groups, and those
whose inquiries are not primarily chorographic, and who are more inclined to undertake a
search for processes as a means of reaching explanation.
(Brookfield, 1964, p. 283)

Social organisation provides the key to many explanations, he argued, so that:

when an individual human geographer is sitting down in one small corner of a foreign land, and
seeks to interpret the geography of that small corner, then it is difficult for him to do so without
trying to comprehend the perception of environment among the inhabitants.
(p. 287)

Geographers had largely failed to delve into such details of social organisation, however,
because of the broad areal scale at which they tended to work, their concern with distributions
rather than with processes, and their avoidance of what he terms ‘micro-geography’. Enquiry in
human geography should involve three stages:

1 general statements about areal patterns and interrelationships;


2 detailed local inquiries which follow up the questions about processes raised by these general
statements; and
3 organisation of the general and local material to produce explanatory generalisations.

Brookfield argued for more microgeographical studies at the second of these stages, to provide the
foundation for the development of comparative methods with which generalisations could be
forged. Brookfield’s (1969, p. 53) later literature survey showed that ‘decision-makers operating on
an environment base their decisions on the environment as they perceive it, not as it is. The action
resulting from decision, on the other hand, is played out in a real environment.’ Referring to the
‘modern’ behavioural work, as well as studies by cultural geographers, he pointed out the great
problems involved in isolating the perceived environment – something which is ‘complex, monistic,
distorted and discontinuous, unstable and full of unwoven irrelevancies’ (p. 74) – and of building
it into an analytical methodology. Further data are needed, too, on such topics as work organisation,
time allocation, and budget allocation, on the meaning of consumption and of distance – all
necessary tasks for the full understanding of people-environment systems.
174 Humanistic geography

The concept of the perceived environment has a considerable pedigree in historical–


geographical scholarship, though without the scientistic terminology adopted by behavioural
geographers. A key example was Glacken’s (1956, 1967) survey of societal attitudes to
environments. Historical geographers, Prince (1971a) suggested, must study a trilogy of
worlds:

1 the real world, as recorded in the landscape;


2 the abstract world, as depicted by general models of spatial order in the past; and
3 the perceived world: ‘Past worlds, seen through the eyes of contemporaries, perceived
according to their culturally acquired preferences and prejudices, shaped in the images of their
assumed worlds.’
(p. 4)

Using all three, it may be possible to explain landscape changes, which cannot be done by assuming
processes from investigations of continua of data over time (see also Moodie and Lehr, 1976). Thus,
‘it [is] the province of the intellect to observe the facts, to reduce them to order and to discover
relationships among them, but it [is] the imagination which [gives] them meaning through the
exercise of judgement and insight’ (Prince, 1961–2, p. 21). Reconstruction of past environments is
extremely difficult, however, for it involves seeing the written record through the cultural lens of
the writer:

A study of past behavioural environments provides a key to understanding past actions,


explaining why changes were made in the landscape. We must understand man and his cultures
before we can understand landscapes; we must understand what limits of physical and mental
strain his body will bear; we must learn what choices his culture makes available to him and
what sanctions his fellows impose upon him to deter him from transgressing and to encourage
him to conform.
(Prince, 1971a, p. 44)

Perhaps the enormity of such a task explains why most successful reconstructions concerned
the relatively recent past, such as the perceptions which guided the settlement of the American
West (e.g. Lewis, 1966), although Wright (1925) essayed a similar task for Europe at the time
of the Crusades. Not all perceived worlds refer to either past or present; some landscapes have
been fashioned out of Utopian views of the future (Porter and Lukermann, 1975; Powell, 1971).
In general – however, and whether of past, present or future, geosophy was not a popular field
of study, despite some intriguing essays (Lowenthal and Bowden, 1975). But directly or indirectly,
it led to arguments for alternative approaches in human geography to those of the positivists
and spatial scientists, or the behavioural geographers and those arguments form the material for
the rest of this chapter.

Alternatives to spatial science


From the early 1970s on, some cultural and historical geographers attacked the positivism
of spatial-science. To replace it, a variety of humanistic approaches was proposed, focusing
on decision-makers and their perceived worlds, and denying the existence of a straight-
forward objective world which can be studied by positivist methods. The intent was to reorient
human geography towards a more humanistic stance, to resurrect its synthetic character,
and to re-emphasise the importance of studying unique events rather than the spuriously
general.
Humanistic geography 175

Critics and defenders of positivism


The various humanistic approaches have much in common, but they can be separated into
different proposals in the present context. The first discussed here is associated with two scholars
– Richard Colebrook (Cole) Harris and Leonard Guelke – who were together at the University of
Toronto at the end of the 1960s; both are historical geographers.
The basic theme of Harris’s (1971) initial paper was that geography is a synthetic discipline,
concerned with particular assemblages of phenomena and not with the science of spatial relations
(see Cosgrove, 1996). Thus:

When the history of North American geography in the 1950s and 1960s is written, a paradox with
which it will have to deal is how, with little argued, logical justification, so many geographers
came to see their subject as a science of spatial relations.
(p. 157)

With May and Sack (p. 121, this book), Harris saw the spatial perspective producing a dismember-
ment of geography, as specialists communicate more with their contemporaries in other disci-
plines than with other geographers, and develop theories that are descriptions of how the world
might operate under certain conditions, rather than of how it actually works:

The difficulty in conceiving of geographical theory comes down to this. The development of
theory is necessarily an exercise in abstraction and simplification in which the complexities
of particular situations are eliminated to the point at which common characteristics
become apparent. But if geography is thought to have a particular subject matter, it is certainly
not individual phenomena or categories of phenomena which other fields do not study. Rather it
is a whole complex of phenomena, many or all of which may be studied individually by other
fields but which are not studied elsewhere in their complex interactions.
(p. 162)

The clear parallel is with history, for ‘Few historians would attempt to develop a general theory
of revolutions. In so doing they would lose grasp of the type of insight that characterizes good
historical synthesis’ (p. 163). The goal of both history and geography is synthesis, therefore. In
developing syntheses, positivist methods may be applicable: historians may be law-consumers,
applying the generalisations of other social scientists to particular events, and geographers could
operate likewise. Alternatively, both historians and geographers could apply the idealist method,
arguing that all activity is based on personal theories. Thus, Harris (1978, p. 126) – who gained his
Ph.D. at the University of Wisconsin where he was supervised by Andrew Clark (see p. 62, this
book), and was also clearly influenced by Hartshorne, wrote of a ‘historical mind’:

Such a mind is contextual, not law-finding. Sometimes it is thought of as law-applying but,


characteristically, the historical mind is dubious that there are overarching laws to explain the
general patterns of human life.

It is open and eclectic, Clark argued, uses no formal research procedures, sees things in context, is
sensitive to motives and values, excludes little and is wary of sweeping generalisations. Its goal is
understanding, not planning, and this should be the case with the ‘geographical mind’ too. To
understand an event is to appreciate why it took place, which is the humanistic goal; to explain an
event is to predict it, as an instance of a general law or suite of such laws, and that is the positivist
goal. (Interestingly, few others have addressed this issue of a ‘geographical mind’. Two have been
attracted to a parallel concept of ‘geographical imagination’. To Harvey (1990; see also Harvey,
2005a) the geographical imagination focuses on ‘the historical geography of social conceptions of
176 Humanistic geography

space and time’, with the goal of stimulating critical reflection on the spatial and temporal
components of alternative societies to capitalist; to Gregory (1994, p. 11) it involves the roles of
space and time, plus nature, in everyday life, just as Mills’s (1959) sociological imagination involves
the dialogue of biography and history.)
Developing his theme of the parallel between history and geography, Harris (1971, p. 167)
identified four points of agreement concerning the nature of history:

1 its primary concern is with the particular;


2 explanation may take into account the thoughts of relevant individuals;
3 explanation may make use of general laws; and
4 ‘Explanation in history relies heavily on the reflective judgement of individual historians.’

From these, he concluded that ‘If geography aims to describe and explain not so much particular
events or peoples, as particular parts of the surface of the earth, then these points of agreement
about history also apply to geography’ (p. 167). The landscape results from actions; behind those
actions lie thoughts; study of thoughts allows understanding of landscape. Thus, synthesis is
crucial, since

the idea of synthesis itself becomes more important as it becomes obvious that our larger
problems transcend narrow subject-matter fields . . . integration . . . in a larger understanding
is still achieved, however aided by statistical methods and computers, by the judgement of wise
men who have cultivated the habit of seeing things together.
(p. 170)

Geographers are presumably to be those wise individuals. This was not an original claim for,
according to Buttimer the basis of Paul Vidal de la Blache’s work was that:

The task which no other discipline with the possible exception of history claims is to examine
how diverse phenomena and forces interweave and connect with the finite horizons of particular
settings. Temporality and spatiality are universal features of life so historical and geographical
study belong together.
(1978a, p. 73)

Positivist work seeks the same end, interweaving parts of a whole, but its parts are instances of
general laws, not unique events.
Many of Harris’s arguments were extended by his Toronto graduate student, Leonard Guelke,
whose first paper was a strong criticism of the ‘narrowly conceived scientific approach’ (Guelke,
1971, p. 38) to geography using the positivist method. He argued against geography as a law-
seeking activity by asking the proponents of the positivist approach to indicate how their laws
would meet the basic standards of scientific acceptability, particularly with regard to prediction.
Whereas they might be able to produce generalisations concerning the phenomena which they
actually studied, he felt it very unlikely that they could generate laws applicable to all examples of
the relevant phenomena. Statistical regularities are not laws and

Until the new geographers have shown that the laws that might conceivably be discovered in
geography will be more than generalizations, which describe common but non-essential
connections between phenomena, their claims must be treated cautiously . . . there is little
cause for optimism, especially as the statistical methods widely employed by geographers
cannot be considered appropriate law-finding procedures.
(p. 42)
Humanistic geography 177

With regard to the idea of geography as a law-applying science, Guelke argued that laws of human
behaviour are virtually impossible to conceive in anything but the most generalised form because
so much behaviour is culturally specific; an a priori statement of the determining conditions for
their operation is thus not feasible so that ‘Human geographers cannot consider themselves to be
law-applying scientists . . . because they have no laws to apply’ (p. 45).
Turning to the use of theories and models in geography, Guelke pointed out that for them to
serve a valid purpose in the pursuit of understanding, criteria must be specified which indicate how
such devices are testable against reality (see also Newman (1973) on the vague use of the term
‘hypothesis’). Such criteria have not been, and cannot be, stated, Guelke claimed; for example,
studies purporting to test central place theory seemed to operate on the rule that ‘one counts
one’s hits but not one’s misses’ (p. 48; see also Guelke, 1978, p. 50). Too often, failure to reproduce
reality was explained by claims that the test environment was not entirely suitable, and ad hoc
hypotheses were frequently adduced to account for observed disparities. Models and theories may
have heuristic value for human geographers, clarifying certain aspects, therefore, but they can have
no explanatory power. Guelke concluded that:

The new geography . . . has not yet produced any scientific laws and . . . appears unlikely to
produce them in the future. . . . The theories and models . . . are not amenable to empirical
testing. . . . The new geographers insisted on . . . logical and internally consistent theories and
models. Yet, none of their theoretical constructs were ever complex enough to describe the real
world accurately. They had achieved internal consistency while losing their grip on reality.
(1971, pp. 50–1)

His offered alternative to that discredited procedure was an ‘idealist’ approach mentioned by Harris,
which is ‘a method by which one can rethink the thoughts of those whose actions he seeks to
explain’ (Guelke, 1974, p. 193). Understanding these should not be constrained by a single
geographical theory. Instead, theory comprises ‘any system of ideas that man has invented, imposed,
or elicited from the raw data of sensation that make connections between the phenomena of the
external world’ (p. 194). Many such theories are part of the individual’s society and culture; they
include its religions, myths and traditions. Using them, ‘the explanation of an action is complete
when the agent’s goal and theoretical understanding of his situation have been discovered . . . One
must discover what he believed, not why he believed it’ (p. 197). Thus, human geographers do not
need to develop theories, since the relevant theories, which led to the action being studied, already
exist (or existed) in the minds of the actors involved. The analyst’s task is to isolate those theories
(a task of considerable difficulty, according to Curry (1982a), because people cannot always identify
the reasons for their actions). Some of them may be unique to particular individuals, but
most are shared in large part by (sometimes great) numbers of actors; they represent the order
which people themselves have stamped on the world and do not require further theories in order
to be understood.
Guelke’s argument was challenged by John E. Chappell (1975), who pointed out that focusing
on the individual actor alone omitted any reference to the environmental constraints and influences
on that person’s actions (see also Gregory, 1978a). Guelke (1976) accepted the existence of such
constraints and influences, but claimed that their investigation lay outside the geographer’s domain.
Study of environmental causes would, he felt, lead into physiology and psychology, and deflect
attention from ‘the most critical dimension of human behaviour, namely the thought behind it’
(p. 169). Chappell (1976) responded that ‘to go so far as to say that there is no possible respectable
theory to explain man’s rational theories and the actions which flow from them’ (p. 170) is to be
myopic: ‘paradigms not only explain facts but they guide the research of whole disciplines’
(p. 171). To him, Guelke’s contention that the ultimate causes of actions lie outside the scope of
human geography places geographers in an inferior position in the academic division of labour.
178 Humanistic geography

In a further essay, Guelke (1975) further sought to counter arguments for the approaches and
techniques of positivism. With reference to historical geography, he argued that:

It is obvious that quantitative techniques will often be useful. . . . [but] Statistical methods put in
harness with positivist philosophy are a dangerous combination. . . . Historical geographers
need to rethink not their techniques but their philosophy. . . . This can best be achieved by moving
from problem-solving contemporary applied geography towards the idealist approach widely
adopted by historians.
(p. 138)

Stan Gregory (1976) agreed with the first part of this statement, but not with the proposed solution.
Like Chappell, he saw the need to investigate individual action within its constraining structures
(see Curry, 1982a).
Positivist approaches in human geography were defended by Hay (1979a), who both
responded to the criticisms and raised points of contention with the proposed alternative. He
argued that Guelke’s case is ill-founded and rests on misconceptions of the nature of positivism,
such as:

1 that all theory must be both normative and based on conceptions of optimal decision-
making;
2 that to be scientific is always to be nomological (that is relating to basic laws); and
3 that prediction is the same as prophecy (rather than simply testing, from the known to the
unknown).

He also claimed that Guelke presented an anti-positivist argument by using a positivist test and
failed to realise the value of ad hoc hypotheses in the improvement of theory (the basis of Lakatos’s
concept of a research programme): Guelke should not, according to Hay, ask ‘Does this theory
explain Y?’ but rather ‘Does this theory contribute to an understanding of Y?’ – again, a pragmatic
approach to knowledge (Does it work?). To Guelke however:

The assumption that thought lies behind human action is not related to the numbers involved. . . .
If thousands of people drive motor cars to their places of work the idealist assumes that each of
these journeys is a considered action involving thought. In such situations the investigator will
not be able to look at each case individually, but he will seek to isolate the general factors
involved in typical circumstances . . . [for which he] might well make use of statistical procedures
. . . the value of statistical analysis will largely depend on its successful integration in the general
interpretation or explanatory thesis being developed.
(1978, p. 55)

These debates continued over the next decade (Curry, 1982b; Downs, 1979; Guelke, 1981b;
Mabogunje, 1977; Mercer and Powell, 1972; Pickles, 1986; Rushton 1979; Saarinen, 1979). As part
of them, Guelke (1982) restated his position that geography is an ideographic discipline seeking to
understand the ‘complexity of human activity on the land’ (p. 52), drawing the boundaries such
that ‘The geographer is not concerned with explaining fluctuations in wheat prices or the level of
interest rates, but he is concerned with the impact that these factors might have on, say, farming in
western Canada’ (p. 53). In seeking to understand the reasons for any action, he accepted that stated
reasons may not always help and that a ‘historical reconstruction of thought’ is necessary to explicate
the learned response which is ‘part of an individual’s cultural heritage’ (p. 54). Guelke remained
committed to this cause, and over a decade later wrote in a review of Derek Gregory’s (1994)
discussion of European colonisation in Geographical Imaginations that:
Humanistic geography 179

The geostrategic thinking of both the colonists and the colonized needs to be reconstructed in a
way that provides a convincing explanation of how one group subdued others and how colonization
itself was sustained within ideologies of white supremacy. This task involves explorations of how
people saw themselves in societies and in relation to the earth, and of the contrasts that existed
between different systems of knowledge and territorial control and exploitation as they actually
articulated themselves in specific geographical circumstances.
(Guelke, 1995, p. 185)

Phenomenology and related approaches


Phenomenology attracted considerable attention from those developing humanistic geography.
Declaring that ‘Humanistic geography is concerned with geographical experience – what the
spatiality of the earth/world means to those whose lives are part of it – in contrast to those who
study geography as externalized, objective data’, Backhaus (2009, p. 137) also notes how
‘phenomenology offers a methodology that can open up the full spectrum of spatial inscriptions of
human life, the fundamental concern of human geographers’.
Talk of a methodology might not have attracted all humanistic geographers, but to some this
was exactly the kind of ‘philosophically articulated alternative to objectivist science’ that could
provide an alternative framework ‘offering methodologies congenial and adaptable to their
geographical concern for the experiential dimension’ (Backhaus, 2009, p. 138). The first direct
advocate for a phenomenological approach was Relph (1970), who was also associated with
the Department of Geography at the University of Toronto. Despite a variety of specific inter-
pretations, he noted that phenomenology’s basic aim is to present an alternative methodology to
the hypothesis-testing and theory-building of positivism, an alternative grounded in people’s lived
world of experience. Phenomenologists argue that there is no straightforwardly objective world
independent of human existence – ‘all knowledge proceeds from the world of experience and
cannot be independent of that world’ (p. 193). Thus, according to Entrikin (1976, p. 617),
‘phenomenologists describe, rather than explain, in that explanation is viewed as [an observer’s]
construction and hence antithetical to the phenomenologist’s attempt to “get back” to the meaning
of the data of consciousness’. Seamon (1984, p. 4) too defined phenomenology as a ‘descriptive
science’.
The phenomenological environment’s contents are unique to every individual, for each of its
elements is the result of an act of intentionality – it is given meaning by the individual, without
which it does not exist but through which it influences behaviour. Phenomenology is the study of
how such meanings are defined. It involves researchers identifying how individuals structure the
environment in an entirely subjective way; the researchers are presuppositionless, using no per-
sonal ideas in seeking to understand their subjects’ ideas. Subjectivity becomes the focus of study.
Phenomenologists may be satisfied with such empathetic understanding, but some seek to go
further, however, and identify essences – elements in individual consciousness which control the
allocation of meanings (Johnston, 1983a; Pickles, 1988, p. 252, distinguishes between ‘transitional
essences’ and ‘invariant and universal structures (understood carefully)’). Phenomenology then
studies human appraisals. It works at the individual level, but may search for the common (imprinted
not agreed) elements among those appraisals.
Relph’s paper was followed by one from another geographer briefly associated with the
University of Toronto (preceded by doctoral training in Berkeley and a period in Arizona, and
latterly based in the American Midwest – Minnesota, then Wisconsin-Madison – Tuan, 1999).
Geography for Yi-Fu Tuan (1971) is a mirror, revealing the essence of human existence and human
striving: to know the world is to know oneself, just as careful analysis of a house reveals much about
both the designer and the occupant. The study of landscapes is the study of the essences in the
societies which mould them, in just the same way that the study of literature and art reveals much
180 Humanistic geography

of human life. Such geographical study has its foundations in the humanities, rather than the social
or physical sciences. Tuan (1974a, 1975b) illustrated it in a number of essays giving, for example,
insights into such topics as the sense of place

Humanistic geography achieves an understanding of the human world by studying people’s


relations with nature, their geographical behavior as well as their feelings and ideas in regard to
space and place. . . . Scientific approaches to the study of man tend to minimize the role of
human awareness and knowledge. Humanistic geography, by contrast, specifically tries to
understand how geographical activities and phenomena reveal the quality of human awareness.
(Tuan, 1976, pp. 266–7)

Tuan exemplified this with five themes: the nature of geographical knowledge and its role in
human survival; the role of territory in human behaviour and the creation of place identities;
the interrelationships between crowding and privacy, as mediated by culture; the role of knowledge
as an influence on livelihood; and the influence of religion on human activity. Such concerns are
best developed in historical and in regional geography; their value to human welfare is that they
clarify the nature of the experience (see also Appleton, 1975, 1994). Indeed, Tuan (1978, p. 204)
claimed that ‘The model for the regional geographers of humanist leaning is . . . the Victorian
novelist who strives to achieve a synthesis of the subjective and the objective’, and quoted the first
two pages of E. M. Forster’s A Passage to India as a paradigm example. (Alternative examples – from a
geographer, but published after Tuan wrote – are Mead, 1993, 2002.)
Tuan’s corpus of work has not usually involved philosophical explorations, and he rarely claims
allegiance to any particular approach. Rather, he has been involved in a variety of explorations of
the interrelationships between people and environments:

my point of departure is a simple one, namely, that the quality of human experience in an
environment (physical and human) is given by people’s capacity – mediated through culture – to
feel, think and act . . . I have explored the nature of human attachment to place, the component
of fear in attitudes to nature and landscape, and the development of subjective world views and
self-consciousness in progressively segmented spaces.
(Tuan, 1984, p. ix)

Thus, for example, he shows that fear is both a representation of the environment and an influence
on the creation of environments (Tuan, 1979), that the creation of residential segregation reflects
the retreat of individuals from wholes to segmented parts (Tuan, 1982), and that the construction
of gardens reflects a desire to dominate the environment (Tuan, 1984). Such works are implicitly
phenomenological in that they suggest the existence of general essences, or behavioural stimuli, but
the term is not in the index to any of his books. Indeed, as Gregory argues:

One of the most persistent motifs in Tuan’s writings is an appeal to common sense and common
experience: to a ‘we’ whose inclusive address presumes a shared human condition to which
‘we’ have access without theoretical mediation. His humanistic geography is, in essence, a
moral-aesthetic discourse; it is contemplative, at once reflective and speculative, and yet –
despite the model of the ideal conversation – at best studiously indifferent to the wider
conversations that might be made possible through the theoretical.
(1994, pp. 79–80)

These explorations by Tuan have covered a wide range of topics within what Gregory (1994,
p. 385) terms ‘ways of being-in-the-world’. Tuan, whose first work (including his Ph.D.) was in
geomorphology, grounds his work in his desire to answer his wonderings, since childhood,
Humanistic geography 181

regarding ‘the meaning of existence: I want to know what we are doing here, what we want out of
life’ (Tuan, 1999, p. 94) – what he terms ‘the big woozy questions’ and which he related to his own
individuality – ‘my apartness from others’ – which aroused in him both pride and anguish, and
which resulted in him being comfortable in the open environments of deserts but dreading
rainforests. The title of his autobiographical chapter on his research interests is ‘Salvation by
geography’, because the discipline has ‘directed my attention to the world, and I have found there,
for all the inanities and horrors, much that is good and beautiful’ (p. 115). His books and other
essays illustrate those discoveries from the point of view of (p. 10): ‘a maverick in the discipline
to the degree that, unlike most other geographers, my landscapes are “inscapes”, as much
psychological conditions as material arrangements’. They are thus individual and particular, but
assist others in illuminating their own ‘inscapes’.
Tuan’s ‘inscapes’ mean that he focuses more on place than space, from that binary pair of major
geographical concepts (as in Tuan, 1977), thus to some extent seeking to correct the bias towards
space that characterised ‘geography as spatial science, and seeks to present them as complementary
perspectives’. (For Taylor (1999, p. 10) Tuan’s ‘generally undervalued’ 1977 book, which provides
‘explicit treatment of what are arguably geography’s two core concepts by unarguably one of the
discipline’s leading thinkers’, has ‘featured only marginally in the stories told of geography’s recent
past’; it was reprinted in 2001.) In a volume dedicated to Tuan and produced to mark his retirement,
however, Adams et al. (2001) focus on place, something with texture, with a shape and feel which
‘provides a glimpse into the processes, structures, spaces and histories that went into its making’
(p. xiii), suggesting a weaving of the terms text and context, and which is conveyed through
conversations (or communication acts: p. xiv). For them, Textures of Place involves highlighting:

the geographic tradition of trying to understand the meanings and processes of place – their
material and symbolic qualities – as well as the range of peoples and social relations that
continuously define and create social and spatial contexts.
(p. xiv)

In this mould, knowing the world involves knowing oneself – a goal that they associate
with Tuan’s (1974b) writings on topophilia. But for Tuan it is more than just ‘knowing oneself’. For
him:

Geography is indispensable to survival. All animals, including American students who


consistently fail their geography tests, must be competent applied geographers. How else do
they get around, find food and mate, avoid dangerous places? History, in striking contrast, is an
esoteric field of knowledge, and for that reason it plays only a small, indeed negligible role in the
common tasks of life. It is not too far-fetched to call animals geographers, but it is to call them
historians. With animals and probably most human beings, knowledge of the past is folded into
present time and space – into geography, where the challenges of living lie.
(Tuan, 2002a, p. 123; see also Tuan, 2002b)

Among other advocates for phenomenology, Mercer and Powell (1972, p. 28) argued that the
use of positivism in geography ‘left the subject with too many technicians and a dearth of scholars’;
they claimed that land-use patterns can never be understood ‘by the elementary dictates of geometry
and cash register’ (p. 42) and the world can only be comprehended through people’s intentions and
attitudes towards it. In a lengthy discussion of phenomenology and its development in other
disciplines, notably sociology, they pointed to ‘a very real danger of the research worker assuming
that concepts which are cognitively organized in his own mind “exist” and are equally clearly
organized in the minds of his respondents’ (p. 26). They argued instead for research methods
involving empathy between researcher and researched, which for geographers means ‘that we make
182 Humanistic geography

every effort to view problems and situations not from our own perspective, but from the actor’s
frame of reference’ (p. 48) – a position they term ‘disciplined naiveté’.
Buttimer (1974) made a similar case for geographers studying the values which permeate all
aspects of living and thinking. The order, precision and theory produced by positivists are dearly
bought – ‘we often lose in adequacy to deal with the values and meanings of the everyday world’
(p. 3) – and behavioural geography similarly fails to break away from the mechanistic, natural
scientific view of humans as preconditioned responders to stimuli. Ley (1981) also identified the
positivist elements in behavioural geography and the suggestions of operand conditioning: people
are assumed to react in predetermined ways to particular stimuli, and so can be manipulated
accordingly. On the other hand, ‘An existentially aware geographer is . . . less interested
in establishing intellectual control over man through preconceived analytical methods than he
is in encountering people and situations in an open, inter-subjective manner’ (Buttimer, 1974,
p. 24). Such activity results in ‘a meditation on life’, with geographers providing more com-
prehensive mirrors than their colleagues from more specialised disciplines can achieve, thereby
clarifying the structural dynamics of life. Prediction would be impossible, apart from ‘the most
routinized aspects of experience’ (p. 29), but the deeper appreciation achieved would allow much
more vital social action and planning than is possible using spatial science and behavioural
approaches.
Buttimer (1976) also directed geographers’ attention to the concept of  ‘lifeworld’, an amalgam
of the worlds of facts and affairs with those of values in personal experience – ‘the pre-reflective,
taken-for-granted dimensions of experience, the unquestioned meanings, and routinized
determinants of behavior’ (p. 281). Positivism should be rejected for analysing the lifeworld
because it separates the observer from the object of study and thus constrains appreciation of the
human experience. Phenomenology, on the other hand, provides a path to understanding, on
which informed planning can be built:

It helps elucidate how . . . meanings in past experience can influence and shape the present . . .
extremely important as preamble not only to scientific procedure, but also as a door to existential
awareness. It could elicit a clearer grasp of value issues surrounding one’s normal way of life,
and an appreciation of the kinds of education and socialization which might be appropriate for
persons whose lives may weave through several milieux.
(p. 289)

The result is an understanding of actions as those involved understand them, rather than in the
terms of abstract, outsider-imposed models and theories. Having achieved that understanding,
human geographers can transmit it, thereby helping the subjects of their investigation to understand
themselves better and realise their potential. In this way, the applied geographer acts as a provocateur,
stimulating human development but not forcing it (Buttimer, 1979).
Berry backed this phenomenological orientation, calling for

a view of the world from the vantage of process metageography. By metageography is meant that
part of geographic speculation dealing with the principles lying behind perceptions of reality,
and transcending them, including such concepts as essence, cause and identity.
(1973a, p. 9)

But not all accepted that phenomenology can entirely replace the positivist approach. Walmsley
(1974), for example, accepted the merits of Buttimer’s case because so many human decisions are
based on ‘experiential’ rather than ‘factual’ concepts, but argued that the scale of geographical
enquiry and its long tradition of certain types of empirical work required maintaining the positivist
orientation. That the perceived world is not necessarily the same as the real world must be realised,
Humanistic geography 183

but ‘logical consistency and empirical truth will remain central to geographical enquiry provided
the importance of values is recognized’ (p. 106).
Gregory (1978a) criticised both positivism and phenomenology. Those favouring the former
were condemned for making ‘social science an activity performed on rather than in society, one
which portrays society but which is at the same time estranged from it’ (p. 51) and for supporting
a procedure which, because it so often assumes ceteris paribus in testing its models, can never be sure
why these fail to replicate reality (p. 66). He recognised the need for humanistic approaches, but
argued that these would not be sufficient to provide a satisfactory foundation, because they
ignore the ‘constraints on social action which are so much part of the taken-for-granted life-world
of the actors’ (Gregory, 1978b, p. 166): ‘A geography of the life-world must therefore determine
the connections between social typifications of meaning and space-time rhythms of action and
uncover the structures of intentionality which lie beneath them’ (Gregory, 1978a, p. 139). But ‘A
major deficiency . . . is [the] restricted conception of social structure: in particular, it ignores the
material imperatives and consequences of social actions and the external constraints which
are imposed on and flow from them’. Phenomenology must be incorporated with broader
investigations of those imperatives and constraints; such incorporation produces a critical stance,
whose nature is discussed in Chapter 6.
Whereas a key feature of the positivist/spatial-science approach was a great numerical
superiority of practitioners over preachers, the phenomenological movement was initially
characterised by the converse – much preaching but relatively little practice (Relph, 1981a, pointed
to the absence of substantive applications of the phenomenological approach in geography, though
see Jackson and Smith, 1984, p. 44):

There is an essential difference between the contemplative intentions of this transcendental


philosophy and the practical concerns of a social science, so that it is scarcely surprising that . . .
geographers’ . . . efforts have been directed towards the destruction of positivism as a philosophy
rather than the construction of a phenomenologically sound geography.
(Gregory, 1978a, pp. 125–6)

Tuan’s interpretative essays exemplify its use, and Relph, who ‘would much prefer to
see substantive applications rather than discussions of the possible uses of phenomenology’
(1977, p. 178), published his thesis on Place and Placelessness in which – implicitly, he says –
phenomenological methods are used ‘to elucidate the diversity and intensity of our experiences
of place’ (Relph, 1976, p. i). His essential themes are the sense of place and identity in the
human make-up and the destruction of this through the growing placelessness of modern
design (see also Porteous, 1988). Other work generally quoted as phenomenological includes
pieces on European settlement of the New World. Joe Powell (1972), for example, has written
on images of Australia; his major work on the settlement of Victoria’s western plains (Powell,
1970) examined the conflict between official and popular environmental appraisals, the dialogue
between these, and the learning process which resulted in the final settlement pattern (see also
Powell, 1977, where he presents the study of eiconics, or image-making, in the context of
colonisation processes). Billinge queried whether such works are really phenomenological,
however:

the idea has spread that since certain branches of our discipline are less susceptible to
quantitative reduction (and, so the argument continues, by false extension, to scientific analysis),
we can justify our partially formulated hypotheses, exploit the atypicality of our data, cease
worrying about the validity of our reconstruction and within some weakly articulated framework
label the whole exercise phenomenological.
(1977, p. 64)
184 Humanistic geography

But for Billinge, ‘phenomenological we have by no means become’ (p. 67) since geographers have
paid little attention to consciousness.
Geographers’ attempts to adopt a phenomenological approach were also trenchantly criticised
by Pickles (1985), not because he opposed them in principle but rather because he believed that
those undertaken were misconceived. He accepted that, if for no other reason than its attack on
positivism, ‘It cannot be denied that the founding and guiding intuitions of a phenomenological
approach in geography as it exists at the moment are in the main sound and well intentioned’
(p. 68), but argued that work such as Buttimer’s and Relph’s ‘is ungrounded method, unfounded
claims, and the actual imposition of unexamined propositions’ (p. 71). His criticisms led him to
contend that ‘we now need to move from what passes for phenomenology in the geographical
literature, towards what is actually the case in phenomenology itself’ (p. 89). Quoting substantially
from Husserl’s and Heidegger’s original works, he argued that phenomenology is not concerned to
explicate subjective meanings as an end in itself, but rather ‘to be the science of science through
explicating the science of beginnings’ (p. 97). Its goal is to identify the essences that underpin
individual meanings:

The essential relation between an individual object and its essence – such that to each object
there corresponds its essential structure, and to each essential structure there corresponds a
series of possible individuals as its factual instances – necessarily leads to a corresponding
relationship between sciences of fact and sciences of essence.
(p. 111)

The subjectivity of the lived world is to be explored for the insights that it can provide on those
essential structures, the underpinnings of knowledge itself.
According to this interpretation, phenomenology has much in common with certain forms of
structuralism in its basic concern with neither empirical appearances nor actual decision-making
but rather with the deep structures of consciousness (see p. 207; Johnston, 1986c; Pickles, 1988,
p. 252, implies this too).Thus, it does not fit easily into the humanistic concerns of most geographers
who have espoused phenomenology, which Pickles identifies as the search for those essences that
give rise to the necessity for geography, as the empirical science concerned with particular facets of
behaviour. (Each empirical science should be grounded in such an essence.) Thus:

we seek an ontological, existential understanding of the universal structures characteristic of


man’s spatiality as the precondition for any understanding of places and spaces as such. That is,
we seek to clarify the original experiences on the basis of which geography can articulate and
develop its regional ontology if geography as a human science, concerned with man’s spatiality,
is to be possible at all.
(p. 155)

Spatiality is that essence, he claims, best represented by the German noun Raum and verb raumen,
‘which means to clear away, to free from wilderness or to bring forth into an openness. Raumen is
thus a clearing away or release of places, a making room for the settling and dwelling of man and
things’ (p. 167). In this context, space and place are closely related concepts (see also Gould,
1981b).
Phenomenology is closely associated with existentialism, and some geographers have
experienced difficulty in separating the two (Entrikin, 1976). Whereas phenomenology assumes
the primacy of essence – the allocation of meanings results from the existence of consciousness –
for existentialists the basic dictum is ‘being before essence – or man makes himself’. The process
of defining oneself (creating an essence) involves creating an environment. Thus, Samuels (1978,
p. 31) argued that environments can be read as biographies – ‘for every landscape or every existential
Humanistic geography 185

geography there is someone who can be held accountable’. Generalisation may be possible from
analysing such landscapes. Appleton (1975), for example, suggested that landscapes reflect two
primal needs – prospect (the need to search for the means of survival), and refuge (the need to hide
from threatening others) – although individuals and groups may satisfy these in particular ways
(as he illustrates from his autobiography: Appleton, 1994). Lowenthal (1975; see also Lowenthal,
1985) argued that individuals rewrite their biographies, and those of their ancestors, by their
choices of what to preserve in the landscape.
All of this suggests that humanistic geography is concerned either with the study of individuals
and their construction of, plus behaviour in, phenomenal environments (as in Rowles, 1978) or
with the analysis of landscapes as repositories of human meaning. As such, it is separate from the
subject matter of much human geography, notably behavioural geography and its investigation of
everyday activity within environments. But the phenomenological perspective has been adapted to
the latter type of work also, in the application of Schutz’s writings on the ‘taken-for-granted’ world
(Ley, 1977b). Much everyday behaviour is unconsidered in that it involves no original encounters
with new situations. The behaviour is habitual, because all of the stimuli encountered can be
processed as examples of particular types (on which, see Kahneman, 2012). Those types are not
externally defined for the individual, but are personally created. The phenomenology of the taken-
for-granted world is the study of those individually defined typifications – of the unconsidered
‘world of social reality’ rather than ‘a fictional non-existing world constructed by the scientific
observer’ (Ley, 1980, p. 10, quoting Schutz; see also Michael Curry’s, 1982a, p. 38, discussion of
‘the ordinary, everyday actions of individuals’ which create for the geographer ‘a complex world of
complex places and actions’ in which the role of the individual decision-maker ‘can be determined
only on an individual basis, case by case’). Interaction within communities may lead to shared
typifications, which quantitative methods may be used to identify descriptively.
Humanistic geography is based on a profound critique of positivist work, which it claims
makes major unwarranted assumptions about the nature of decision-making, and seeks inductive
laws of human behaviour that can be scientifically verified (Ley and Samuels, 1978; Powell, 1980b).
Its counter-argument promotes understanding of the individual as a ‘living, acting, thinking’ being.
To some, however, it is foremost a form of criticism – Entrikin argued that:

humanist geography does not offer a viable alternative to, nor a presuppositionless basis for,
scientific geography as it is claimed by some of its proponents. Rather the humanist approach is
best understood as a form of criticism. As criticism the humanist approach helps to counter the
overly objective and abstractive tendencies of some scientific geographers.
(1976, p. 616)

For others, however, the human condition can only be discerned through humanistic
endeavour, for attitudes, impressions and subjective relations to places (the ‘sense of place’) cannot
be revealed by positivist research. As Pickles (1986, p. 42) put it, ‘The value of humanism has been
its resilience in consistently raising questions which do not fit within other frameworks . . .
humanism has been the voice of man against reason, against science’. In similar terms, for Buttimer
(1979, p. 30), unless tempered by humanistic impulses, geography risks being managerial,
manipulating individuals and their environments rather than seeking to advance the process of
‘human becoming’. Relph (1981b, pp. 139–41) coined the term ‘geographism’ to describe ‘the
view that people should behave rationally in geographical, two-dimensional space . . . that cities
and industries and transportation routes should be arranged in the most efficient way’ which, when
used as a basis for planning, ‘will diminish the distinctiveness and individuality of . . . communities
and places. Geographism involves the imposition of generalizations onto specific landscapes; it
breeds uniformity and placelessness.’ Both Buttimer and Relph argued that planning should
emphasise subjectivity and individuality. Scientists, engineers and planners may seek to improve
186 Humanistic geography

well-being, but in so doing they make people rootless and deny them individuality. Planning must
be allied with environmental humility, by which ‘places and communities would increasingly
become the responsibility of those who live and work in them instead of being objects of
professional disinterest’ (Relph, 1981b, p. 201). In this context, humanistic geography is not only
a reaction against the dehumanising treatment of people in spatial science and behavioural
geography, but also an argument against an applied geography which imposes that treatment on the
landscape, and for a form of anarchism in which individuals are encouraged to realise what they
are and how they can control both themselves and their environments (see also Pickles, 1986,
p. 47). Seamon (1984) also argued that phenomenological work could be ‘a learning tool which
can help us to discover more about ourselves, others, and the world in which we live’ (p. 21), and
which may then have practical value in environmental design.

The practice of humanistic geography


Much of the practice of humanistic geography has been concerned with exploring and explicating
the subjectivity of human action and its base in meanings (both individual and shared), with
relatively little concern for the claims of phenomenological, existentialist, and other philosophies.
(Curry, 1996, p. 16, for example, claims that although the earliest figures involved in the break from
positivism all referred to phenomenology, ‘it seems fair to say that none took it very seriously’.)
To the extent that such work is explicitly influenced by philosophical and methodological writings,
the (albeit usually implicit) stimulus is more often the pragmatism (and symbolic interactionism)
developed by the Chicago school of sociologists in the 1920s and 1930s (and largely overlooked by
human geographers who paid much more attention to the relatively small amount of spatial analysis
undertaken by that school, as typified by the Burgess model of the internal structure of cities:
Johnston, 1971). Pragmatism portrays life as a continuous process of experience, experiment and
evaluation through which beliefs are continually reconstructed; such reconstruction is a social
process, whereby individuals learn and behave in the context of the beliefs of those with whom
they interact (hence the term ‘interactionism’: see Jackson and Smith, 1984, Chapter 4; both
S. Smith, 1988, and Jackson, 1988, illustrate this in their own research).
Understanding social life within this broad framework involves participatory field work
(as detailed in Evans, 1988), the methodology of which, according to Susan Smith (1984, p. 353),
is ‘a hallmark of much geographic humanism’. This, she continues:

requires a commitment to fieldwork, with the aim of securing data lodged in the meanings
ascribed to the world by active social subjects. The strength of this strategy derives from the
unique insight it offers into ‘lay’ or ‘folk’ perceptions and behaviors. True to the pragmatic
maxim, the method allows the truth of a social reality to be established in terms of its
consequences for those experiencing it.
(pp. 356–7)

How local societies work is thereby explicated, which was the goal of the ethnographic work of the
Chicago school (Jackson, 1984, 1985). Ley’s (1974) detailed portrayal of a Philadelphia community
illustrates this, as does his general textbook on urban social geography (Ley, 1983).
Field studies, involving interaction with residents over long or short terms, provide a rich
source of information about how people structure their lives. Although mindful of how ideas about
the field and fieldwork are mediated through technologies, academic structures and theoretical
reframing, it is not hard to detect influences from humanistic geography (and those earlier sources
on which it sought inspiration, such as Sauer and Vidal de la Blache) in the introduction to a special
issue of The Geographical Review on ‘Doing fieldwork’:
Humanistic geography 187

We learn about ourselves in the field: we learn about places from doing fieldwork there. Whatever
our degree of theoretical engagement, it is what we know about a part of the world – or all of it
– that is our first fact. And there fieldwork commences.
(DeLyser and Starrs, 2001, p. vii)

Humanistic geography was long sensitive to the range of texts that could become
sources, along with other repositories of meanings; Pocock (1983) described humanistic strategies
ranging ‘from library search, to the observational, to the experiential’ (p. 356). The landscape, the
creation of those who live/have lived in it, is an important text, and Lowenthal (1985) provides a
perspective on its study. He portrays it not as a mirror of the past but rather as an insight to the
present:

Traditions and revivals dominate architecture and the arts; schoolchildren delve into local
history and grandparental recollections; historical romances and tales of olden days deluge
all the media. The past thus conjured up is, to be sure, largely an artifact of the present.
However faithfully we preserve, however authentically we restore, however deeply we immerse
ourselves in bygone times, life back then was based on ways of being and believing
incommensurable with our own. The past’s difference is, indeed, one of its claims: no one would
yearn for it if it merely replicated the present. But we cannot help but view and celebrate it
through present-day lenses.
(p. xvi)

The present landscape is a conglomerate of relics from many different periods in most cases, and
by preserving only parts of it we bias our representation of the past:

Every act of recognition alters survivals from the past. Simply to appreciate or protect a relic, let
alone to embellish or imitate it, affects its form or our impressions. Just as selective recall
skews memory and subjectivity shapes historical insight, so manipulating antiquities refashions
their appearance and meaning. Interaction with a heritage continually alters its nature and
context, whether by choice or by chance.
(p. 263)

Thus, when use of the landscape as a text involves reading the outcome of a long sequence of
selective retentions of earlier forms, so that we learn about what parts of their history people
wanted to build into their own presents and futures, ‘We must concede the ancients their place . . .
But their place is not simply back there, in a separate and foreign country; it is assimilated in
ourselves, and resurrected into an ever-changing present’ (p. 412). The past does not exist
independently of those who seek to interpret it (as Taylor, 1988, makes clear in a very different
context); the landscape may tell us more about the past which people wanted to preserve than
about the past as it was experienced. (It also tells us much about the people who describe it, as
Porteous, 1986, illustrates in his discussion of body imagery as a metaphor for landscape
description.) Study of the current processes of landscape-creation illustrates this process, as with
the creation of various types of ‘living museum’ and the promotion of places as ‘cities of spectacle’
(as in Crang, 1994; Jacobs, 1994a).
An increasingly-used text for the explication of meanings as humanistic geography evolved
was literature – or ‘creative literature’ in Paul White’s (1985) term; Porteous (1985) refers to
‘imaginative literature’, with which geographers have been highly selective:

Plays are not considered, poetry is but occasionally used, the novel reigns supreme. The
advantages of the novel lie in its length (meaty), its prose form (understandable), its involvement
188 Humanistic geography

with the human condition (relevant), and its tendency to contain passages, purple or otherwise,
which deal directly with landscapes and places in the form of description (geographical).
(p. 117)

He argued that when using novels as texts, geographers have concentrated on nineteenth-century,
rural contexts (as in Darby’s, 1948, paper on Hardy’s Wessex). To correct this, he proposed a two-
variable categorisation of situations according to whether the subject is an insider or an outsider,
and whether the place being described is ‘home’ or ‘away’. The ‘home-insider’ provides material on
sense of place, whereas the much less frequently reported ‘away-outsider’ refers to those
experiencing alienation in a placeless world. (White’s, 1985, use of novels to describe migrants’
situations fits readily into this category.) ‘Home-outsiders’ are people who fail to develop insider
relationships with their milieux, whereas ‘away-insiders’ are travellers reporting their experiences
(as in ‘road, tramp, and down-and-out novels’; Porteous, 1985, p. 119). Such distinctions are
reflected in a collection of essays about literature and migration (King et al., 1995), which
distinguishes between migrants’ autobiographical accounts and general fiction about migration
(Duffy, 1995). These are used to explore the renegotiation of identity that accompanies migration
experiences (White, 1995), but as texts they are subjected to less critical scrutiny than that
undertaken by deconstructionists (p. 259, this book). Similarly, science fiction and related literature
gives insights to imaginative geographies of the future: it ‘maps out possible future spatialities of
the postmodern condition, and provides cognitive spaces which are being used by individuals and
institutions in conceiving and making future society’ (Kitchin and Kneale, 2001, p. 32). And
reviewing the trajectory of ‘literary geography’, Angharad Saunders (2010, p. 436) argued that ‘it
was possible to identify a literary geographic tradition which stretched back to the early twentieth
century and encompassed work of various theoretical and critical hues’.
Much humanistic geography has been written to describe and appreciate the variety of the
human condition, as it is experienced. (Eyles’s, 1989, essay, in a volume designed to ‘introduce
some of the most exciting challenges of the contemporary subject to a wider audience’, considers
place and landscape without reference to philosophy.) It has been relatively unconcerned with
philosophical issues, such as the origins of meanings in human consciousness, and has focused
almost entirely on the empirical worlds of experience, even if these have to be interpreted from
secondary sources. However, J. Wreford Watson (1983), himself a prize-winning poet, claimed that
literature is not a secondary source but ‘primary source material for the whole world of images’
(p. 397) that illustrates the ‘soul’ of a place. Its relevance, according to Pocock (1983), is that:

it attempts to unravel the nature of being-in-the-world, as it explores the existential significance


of place as an integral part of human existence. In short, it is a geographical contribution to the
most fundamental of questions, ‘what is man?’
(p. 357)

Meinig (1983) expresses this more vigorously:

By limiting ourselves to describing and measuring and analyzing certain aspects of the world as
it seems geographers have denied themselves the possibility of probing very deeply into what it
all means. Being unable to convey what it means we cannot help shape it toward what it might
become.
(p. 325)

Explicating what it means involves practising geography as art – placing the discipline firmly in the
humanities as well as the sciences and the social sciences – as illustrated by Meinig (2002) in a
biographical essay.
Humanistic geography 189

One problem for such work, brought home to geographers in a series of iconoclastic essays
(Olsson, 1978, 1979, 1980, 1982, 2007; see also Pred, 1988; Abrahamsson and Gren, 2012), is
that the medium of the text is constraining as well as enabling. Olsson (1982) focuses on language
as the most frequently used medium, with the constraints that word definitions and usages put on
their application, hence the modes of thought that they support. Thus:

any social scientist is handicapped by the methodological praxis which requires him to be more
stupid than he actually is. Thus, in the interests of discipline, verification and communication he
relies mainly on the two senses of sight and hearing: what counts is what can be counted: what can
be counted is what can be pointed to; what can be pointed to is what can be unequivocally named.
Accumulation of knowledge about the nameable is consequently the point of the scientist’s game.
(p. 227)

Ambiguity, therefore, is translated into certainty; describing a phenomenon in words allocates it to


a category and can oversimplify its complexity. Hence, our ability to think is made possible by the
richness of language, yet also constrained by the categorisations that it imposes; the former aids our
understanding but the latter can hinder it (as critical theorists and poststructuralists have explored:
see Chapter 7).
Geographers’ involvement in humanistic work involves more than interpretation of texts,
however, since they themselves create new texts in transmitting their appreciations to others,
usually in writing but also through maps, lectures and other media. This involves what is some-
times referred to as a double hermeneutic. Initially developed for the exegesis of biblical
texts, hermeneutics was extended by Dilthey (Rose 1980, 1981) to embrace all studies
which involve scrutinising an author’s intentions when evaluating a text. This involves what
Dilthey termed Verstehen (interpretative understanding), which not only enables students of a text
to appreciate its author but also to increase their own self-awareness:

Understanding a text from a historical period remote from our own . . . or from a culture very
different from our own is . . . essentially a creative process in which the observer, through
penetrating an alien mode of existence, enriches his own self-knowledge through acquiring
knowledge of others.
(Giddens, 1976, p. 17)

Thus, an applied humanistic geography promotes both self-awareness and awareness of others.
A double hermeneutic is involved because it is not only ‘the job of human geographers to interpret
such texts as a spectator in order to make certain statements about actors operating within the
texts’, but also ‘to communicate the meanings of such phenomena as he should deem important
back to the actors involved’ (Rose, 1981, p. 124) as well as to others who wish to understand those
meanings. Thus, the reader of a research paper by a humanistic geographer is only interrogating
those meanings through their interpretation by an intermediary – the humanistic geographer.
The latter’s selection of those items ‘deemed important’ means that different geographers may
transmit different interpretations of the same text, in the same way as two biographers might
interpret a novelist’s texts differently and two artists may differ in their portrayal of the same
landscape. (On hermeneutics in geography, see Livingstone, 2002, who has also written on ‘the
geography of reading’ (Livingstone, 2005) as part of his general argument regarding the situatedness
of knowledge production and reproduction: Livingstone, 2003b.)

Humanistic and ‘old’ and ‘new’ cultural geography


Detailed debates about philosophy and methodology in geography have engaged only a minority
of the discipline’s practitioners, so far as the empiricist/positivist approaches are concerned,
190 Humanistic geography

whereas a majority have conducted their own empirical inquiries informed by those debates
but only marginally connected to them. To a considerable extent this has been the case
with humanistic geography too, with Hugill and Foote (1994, p. 18) contending that whereas
humanistic geographers turned to such philosophies and methodologies as ‘ethnomethodology,
existentialism, idealism, phenomenology, symbolic interactionism, and transactionalism . . .
[although] successful applications of each of these can be found in the geographical literature . . .
none captured the imaginations of more than a handful of geographers at a time’.
A small number of writers have been concerned with philosophical underpinnings and the
relative merits of different humanistic approaches, but more have accepted the general tenor of the
argument, described by Boal and Livingstone as:

We can give up the need to find direct empirical connections between terms and objects in the
world; we can view knowledge not as presenting the world in some correct way, but as just
helping us to get along in it, or to change it. Truth, to repeat, has nothing to do with accurately
representing, or, as Rorty has it, mirroring reality; it is just, according to [Courtice Rose, 1987],
‘what we are well advised, given our present beliefs, to assert’. The purpose of geography, then,
is not to tell us about how the world ‘really’ is: it tells us nothing about regions or landscapes or
economic structures or human agency, because these are mere linguistic fictions; it is just the
search for the right vocabulary, the right jargon, the best discourse in which to pursue the kinds
of account which help us, in the most basic sense, decide what to do.
(1989, pp. 7–8)

Doing that, according to Pickles (1986, p. 29), involves ‘archaeology’, uncovering the layers of
human behaviour to identify the experience that underpins it, which involves the explication
of texts – the ‘written records, cultural artefacts, urban landscapes or whatever’ (Boal and
Livingstone, 1989, p. 15) – which are the repositories of human meanings, and whose interpretation
is the goal of humanistic geography.
Some of the work undertaken within this humanistic framework, and without the explicit
philosophical underpinnings, goes under the rubric of a form of cultural geography, which has a
long and distinguished background, notably in the USA, based on the work of Carl Sauer. Others
found some inspiration in Vidal de Blache’s commitment to regional description and exploration of
the spirit of place, or work on landscape work in prior German geography (see the essays in Ley
and Samuels, 1978). In other words, the reaction to spatial science may have been shared, but the
literatures mobilised to enable humanistic geography were quite diverse. The story is further
complicated by the later talk, from British geographers in the 1980s, of a ‘new cultural geography’
that would be informed not only by humanistic geography, but also by some of the radical and
critical currents that are the focus of the next chapter. Cosgrove and Jackson (1987) note this hybrid
origin, going on to declare that:

If we were to define this ‘new’ cultural geography it would be contemporary as well as historical
(but always contextual and theoretically informed); social as well as spatial (but not confined
exclusively to narrowly-defined landscape issues); urban as well as rural; and interested in the
contingent nature of culture, in dominant ideologies and in forms of resistance to them. It would,
moreover, assert the centrality of culture in human affairs. Culture is not a residual category, the
surface variation left unaccounted for by more powerful economic analyses; it is the very medium
through which social change is experienced, contested and constituted.
(p. 95)

The suggestion of a break between an ‘old’ and a ‘new’ cultural geography was denied in the
review in Geography in America; Rowntree et al. (1989, p. 215) argued that ‘Although traditional cultural
Humanistic geography 191

geography has preferred topics with historical depth, there is increasing interest and emphasis on
the study of everyday life and landscapes.’ They recognised that trends originating in the UK, as
promoted by Cosgrove and Jackson (1987), differed substantially from the more traditional
concerns (as represented in the chapter on cultural ecology in the same volume: Butzer, 1989; see
also Turner, 1989). ‘Whether the British trajectory becomes an integral part of North American
cultural geography remains to be seen’; quoting Kofman (1988), they suggested that ‘the “new”
cultural geography is more talked about than done’ (p. 209). Hugill and Foote (1994, p. 18),
however, saw the introduction of humanistic approaches (as exemplified by Ley and Samuels’s,
1978, anthology) as ‘an attempt to define a “new” cultural geography’ in an ‘attempted coup’
which failed. Furthermore, they also portrayed a conflict between traditional cultural geography as
practised in North America and promoted in the UK:

a large number of [American cultural] geographers had continued to cultivate the traditional
themes of the Berkeley school. . . . These geographers felt little need to accept humanistic
geography and resented its new agenda. Humanistic research had little to say about traditional
concerns. The unfortunate mismatch between American cultural geography and British
social geography compounded problems of assimilation. The contributions of British social
geography to recent advances in humanistic cultural geography have been increasing . . . but the
overlap is slight.

James Duncan (1994) refers to this debate as:

a civil war [that] has been going on in cultural geography since the early 1980s. This struggle has
largely, though not exclusively, had an intergenerational character, younger cultural geographers
trained in the late 1970s and 1980s assailing the positions of an older generation trained in the
1950s and 1960s.
(p. 95)

The main issue, he argued, was theory:

The younger generation launched its attacks using an arsenal of theory-seeking weapons
provided by suppliers in the humanities and social sciences. Some direct hits were scored on the
lightly camouflaged theories of the older generation, but such hits proved indecisive in the war
for a number of reasons. Many of the older generation were unaware that they had any theories
in their camp: others insisted that these were relic theories long since abandoned. Still others
claimed that the theoretical targets had in fact been surreptitiously inserted into their camp by
the younger generation to discredit them. At any rate, they argued that no meaningful losses had
been sustained.

Others (e.g. M. Price and Lewis, 1993a) argued that the older generation was far from homogeneous
in its views, however, and that ‘traditional cultural geography’ was being misrepresented by those
advancing an alternative position.
Cosgrove and Jackson (1987) pointed not only to the continued vitality of cultural geography
as the interpretation of past and present landscapes and other texts – for which they appropriated
the term ‘iconography’ (as in Cosgrove and Daniels, 1988; see also Powell, 1977, to whom they do
not refer) – but also to growing contacts with contemporary social geography. (Soon after they
wrote, the Social Geography Study Group of the IBG was renamed the Social and Cultural Geography
Study Group.) The field of contemporary cultural studies offered ‘alternative ways of theorising
culture without specific reference to the landscape concept’ (p. 98), they claimed, with its emphasis
on contemporary subcultures and their political struggles rather than ‘the elitist and antiquarian
192 Humanistic geography

predilections of traditional cultural studies’. This is illustrated in a special issue of Society and Space
(Gregory and Ley, 1988), and in Jackson’s (1989) text Maps of Meaning, which begins with a definition
of culture that characterises a ‘new’ cultural geography:

This book employs a more expansive definition of culture than that commonly adopted in cultural
geography. It looks at the cultures of socially marginal groups as well as the dominant, national
culture of the elite. It is interested in popular culture as well as in vernacular or folk styles: in
contemporary landscapes as well as relict features of the past.
(p. ix)

The work of Sauer and the Berkeley school (p. 53 and p. 97, this book) is criticised for being
relatively narrow; culture is instead linked by Jackson to the contested concept of ideology, and
his substantive chapters cover popular culture, gender and sexuality, racism and language (see
Chapter 7). An agenda for future work suggests an even wider coverage, into aspects of social rela-
tions that impinge upon the economic organisation of society and thus link cultural geography
more firmly with aspects of radical geography (as discussed, in Chapter 6). Work in this mould
would presumably further the challenge to the content of traditional cultural geography as
‘innocent’ (Rowntree et al., 1989, p. 214).
Subsequently, the concept of culture has itself been examined. The definition adopted by
Duncan and others, in contrast to the ‘superorganicism’ of the Berkeley school and its followers, is
described as ‘socially constructed, actively maintained by social actors, and supple in its engagement
with other “spheres” of human life and activity’ (Mitchell, 1995, p. 102). For those who adopt this
position, culture exists as, according to Cosgrove and Jackson (1987, p. 95), ‘the very medium
through which change is experienced, contested and constituted’. To Don Mitchell (1995) this
means that:

Culture, therefore, can be specified as something which both differentiates the world and
provides a concept for understanding that differentiation. Culture itself is a sphere of human life
every bit as important as, yet somehow different from, politics, economy and social relations. It
is an important ontological category which must be theorized and understood if we hope to
understand human differentiation, behaviour, experience and contest.
(p. 103)

Against this, he argues that ‘there is no such (ontological) thing as culture. Rather there is only a
very powerful idea of culture, an idea that has developed under specific historical conditions and
was later broadened as a means of explaining material differences’. As with the superorganic
conception, he contended, the concept of culture promoted by the ‘new cultural geography’
involves reification and its adherents have reached ‘something of a dead end’ (p. 104): ‘While
important empirical work exploring the social creation of many aspects of life continues, none of
this work has been able adequately to explain what culture is. Cultural geography has remained
incapable of theorizing its object.’
Attempts to define culture, according to Mitchell, involve an infinite regress, using terms
which themselves are neither internally coherent nor inclusive (see the discussion on metaphors on
p. 258, this book). The regress is ended by claims that cultures exist and the term is used as part of
a strategy to define and control:

the naming and representation of cultures create partial, yet globalizing, truths. By localizing social
interaction into discrete cultures . . . contentious activities are abstracted into the partial truth
contained in the idea of culture: namely that there are true and deep differences between people.
(p. 109)
Humanistic geography 193

This strategy is crucial in many aspects of life, such as geopolitics (see p. 264, this book)
and the promotion of consumerism; indeed, as the essays in Roger Lee and Jane Wills (1997)
illustrate (see also Thrift and Olds, 1996; Wheeler, 2002b), it is increasingly difficult to separate the
cultural from the economic. For Don Mitchell (1995), therefore:

like ‘race’, ‘culture’ is a social imposition on an unruly world. What does exist, and very
importantly, is the historical development of the idea of culture as a means of ordering and
defining the world. . . . Culture is an idea that integrates by dividing . . .
(p. 112)

As such, many cultural geographers were deeply involved in developments during the 1990s,
characterised in Chapter 7 as ‘the cultural turn’.
We return to these issues in Chapter 7. For now, it is sufficient to note that whereas traditional
cultural geographers paid little explicit attention to methodological concerns, those linked to the
more recent developments addressed a range of issues involved in the collection of ‘data’, through
the interrogation of both texts and people’s lived experiences. In this respect, Ian Cook and Mike
Crang (1995) equated (a renewed) cultural geography with humanistic geography in terms of the
methods adopted. There is a sense that one of the preconditions for such renewal, however, was the
legacy of human-orientated research in geography which came to the fore in humanistic geography’s
critique of positivism and spatial science. ‘Doing humanistic, or cultural, geography’ involves a
variety of methods often characterised as ethnographic and contrasted to the positivist approach
(Cook and Crang, 1995, p. 4) as ‘reading, doing and writing . . . thoroughly mixed up’ during the
course of a piece of research rather than the ‘conventional read-then-do-then-write sequence’ of
other approaches.
Cook and Crang noted that one author has identified forty-three different ways of conducting
ethnographic research (Tesch, 1990), but focus on just four:

1 participant observation, in which the researcher(s) lives in and/or works among a selected
community in order to appreciate its values and ways of life, and then interprets that culture
to a wider audience – the process involves researchers and community developing mutual
(or intersubjective) understandings;
2 interviewing, which involves conversations between researcher(s) and researched, which can
vary in the degree to which they are structured with predetermined questions by the
interviewer;
3 focus groups, whereby researchers initiate information-collection by bringing together groups
who interact as they discuss the issues raised by the researcher (and perhaps others which lead
from them), thereby treating people as members of interacting communities that influence
their behaviour rather than as isolated individuals; and
4 filmed approaches, wherein visual material obtained from the research subjects indicate
meanings and values which are not readily expressed in words (Rose, 2001).

Preparing for each of these approaches is a major task, as is the follow-up construction
of the information obtained. A number of ethical issues is involved and the continued relation-
ship between researcher(s) and the researched is of considerable importance. Although
Cook and Crang’s (1995) essay was expanded and brought out as a book (Crang and Cook,
2007) by a commercial publisher, it is interesting to note that it originally appeared in a series
that began in 1975, published by the quantitative methods group of the Institute of
British Geographers (the series is archived at: http://qmrg.org.uk/catmog/). A series that was
originally dedicated to the methods required by spatial science ended up publishing what became
a key text on qualitative methods (and, along the way, also published a review on humanism;
194 Humanistic geography

Pickles, 1986). Perhaps such methods might seem closer to humanistic geography than to the
abstractions of spatial science. Yet as Cloke et al. (1991, p. 92) put it, ‘doing ethnography’ lacks
neither rigour nor academic merit; it is not, as some imply, a ‘soft option’ compared to the ‘hard’
spatial science:

rather, it is to engage very honestly with both the enchantment and the problems associated with
researchers trying to gain an insight into the worlds of other peoples in other places, and it is
also to insist that this insight emerges not by supposing (as might a philosophically inclined
phenomenologist or existentialist) that these peoples are basically the same as us but by letting
them and their version of humanity simply be different.

Conclusions
A common thread links the material discussed in this chapter and the behavioural work that formed
part of the preceding chapter; both are concerned with positive (the way things are) rather than
normative (the way they should be) investigations, with attempts to uncover how humans behave
in the world rather than with contrasts between actual patterns of behaviour in space and those
predicted from normative theories. Both were also part of a more general trend towards a human
focus within the social sciences, which reflects reorientations in the external environment. From
the late-1960s on, there was a significant disillusion with science and technology, especially in
comparison to the 1950s and early years of the 1960s. Accordingly, there was a shift in emphasis
from study of the aggregate to the individual, an increase in the relative volume of research
conducted at the micro-scale, and growing unease about the role of social scientists in planning
mechanisms. Both behavioural geography and especially the various humanistic approaches
reflected these trends.
The two approaches remained distinctive. Behavioural geography treated people as
responders to stimuli and investigated how different individuals respond to particular
stimuli (and also how the same individual responds to the same stimulus in different situations);
by isolating the correlates of those varying responses it builds models that can account for,
and potentially predict, the probable impact of certain stimuli. The end product is input to
processes aimed either at providing environments to which people respond in a preferred way or
at changing behaviour by changing the stimuli. The other set of approaches – humanistic
geography – treated the person as an individual constantly interacting with the environment
and with a range of communities, thereby continually changing both self and milieu. It
sought to understand that interaction by studying it, as it is represented by the individual and
not as an example of some scientifically defined model of behaviour. And then by transmitting
that understanding, it sought both to reveal people to themselves, enabling them to develop
the interactions in self-fulfilling ways, and to promote their appreciation by others.
A chapter entitled ‘A brief history of geographic thought’, published in 2002, subtitled
its account of this period ‘Humanistic thought and poetic geographies’ (Hubbard et al., 2002,
p. 37), noting how these had ‘fuelled a geography in which qualitative methodologies
were regarded as superior in the production of meaningful knowledge . . . seen as viable ways
of teasing out the emotional, aesthetic and symbolic ties that bound people and place’ (p. 41).
For David Smith (1988a, p. 266), humanistic work involved a ‘new movement’, and the chapters
in the book that he edited with Eyles:

have provided persuasive accounts of ways of interpreting the geographical world which are
capable of challenging if not displacing prevailing orthodoxy or at least of providing a convincing
alternative. The positivist and empiricist paradigm fixated by mathematical process modelling
Humanistic geography 195

with a promise of policy relevance . . . is already yielding to approaches more sensitive to actual
human achievement.

For him, the struggle between paradigms seemed set to continue, with humanistic interpretative
work being rich in empirical example as well as strong in philosophical criticism. According
to Gregory (1994, p. 78), however, too many humanistic geographers had been reluctant to ‘engage
more directly with theoretical concerns’. As the following chapters illustrate, setting human
behaviour in a sharpened theoretical (and hence, for many, a geographical and political) context
became a prime focus of much geographical work from the 1970s on. Entrikin and Tepple
(2006, p. 32) could remark that these later trends saw humanistic geography as ‘relatively
atheoretical and apolitical’, and that humanism in geography might now be thought of ‘as a very
specific moment in the history of the discipline, a moment that has now passed’ but which offered
a ‘voice against the narrowing of the field and an alternative vision of humans as complex intentional
agents’ (p. 36). Warf (2012) similarly argues that:

Humanistic thought made great contributions to the discipline, helping to revive cultural
geography and forcing researchers to take seriously the complex question of human
consciousness. It jettisoned the myth of objective research and made explicit discussion of
values and biases an integral part of the process.
(p. 236)

The meaning of those ‘values’ and the recognition of ‘biases’ would soon expand and lead
many to go beyond humanistic approaches, as the next three chapters detail. Indeed, another
recent review (Seamon and Sowers, 2009) notes that is not really possible to tell the story of how
existential and phenomenological geographical work have evolved since the 1970s without looking
into how they informed, were interpreted by and have to some extent been supplanted by
subsequent trends (including the advent of radical geography, and those critical and poststructura-
list impulses that form the basis of the subsequent chapters of this book). For Entrikin and
Tepple (2006, p. 36), however, the enduring legacy of humanistic geography was both to inform
concepts and to sharpen cultural critique, enabling subsequent reworkings of human geography, as
well as to inject a heightened sensitivity to morality, emotions and ethics (see too Cloke, 2002;
Valentine, 2005):

The recent interest in ethics has been evident in articles, books, special sections of journals,
and relatively new journals such as Ethics, Place and Environment and Philosophy and
Geography. It is within this emerging subfield that the humanist’s concerns with the auto-
nomous intentional agent and humans as the creators and interpreters of meaning are most
evident.

Such openings to morality and ethics and fundamental human beliefs also led to both renewed
disciplinary engagement with religion (A. Cooper, 1992; Kong, 1990; Park, 1994) and ‘new age’
beliefs (Holloway, 2000). Mapping religion had been part of traditional cultural geography, but it
is only after the critics of a detached/objective geography outside emotions, ‘beliefs’ and feelings
was trail-blazed by humanistic geography that advocacy of an explicitly ‘Christian contribution’
appeared in mainstream journals (M. Clark, 1991).
It is now more than two decades since Paul Rodaway (1994, p. 6) detected ‘a revival of interest
in humanistic issues and some cross-fertilisation between humanistic and postmodern thinking in
geography.’ A more recent set of essays on GeoHumanities charts more recent engagements between
geography and the humanities (including ‘Humanities GIS’, ‘Geocrativity’, ‘Geohistories’ and
‘Geopoetics’) but notes how ‘The seeds of a distinct geohumanities were planted during the 1970s,
196 Humanistic geography

when human geography was buffeted by a flood of fresh ideas from the social sciences and
the humanities’ (Dear, 2011, p. 311). In the decades since humanistic geography was proposed
as a reaction to positivism and quantification, geographers have repeatedly drawn on its
creative impulses. However, subsequent activism and turbulent political debates subsequently gave
these impulses a new character for many geographers who would advocate more radical paths
beyond spatial science.
Chapter 6

Radical geography

How and why should we bring about a revolution in geographic thought? The quantitative
revolution has run its course . . . to tell us less and less about anything of great relevance. . . .
In short, our paradigm is not coping well. It is ripe for overthrow.
(David Harvey, 1973, pp. 128–9)

Everyone who studies Marx, it is said, feels compelled to write a book about the experience.
(David Harvey, 1982, p. 1)

[D]uring the ‘summer of love’ (1967) geography was perhaps the least sexy subject, certainly
in the English-speaking world. The influence of the intellectually conservative Richard
Hartshorne . . . still weighed heavily on US geography even as a new generation of positivists
in Britain and the US were installing themselves as the next new thing. It is difficult to conceive
of a discipline more uncool than geography in 1967. And yet, the influence of the anti-war
movement in the US, the feminist and environmental movements, the Prague Spring of 1968,
the anti-imperialist movement, radicals discovering socialism and Marx – all of these wider
social eruptions in the late 1960s and early 1970s completely transformed the discipline. They
had a greater effect on geography than on any other social science in the Anglophone world.
(Neil Smith, 2001, p. 6)

[I]t is precisely because patterns of spatial organization continue to have such strategic
significance to capital, states, and social forces at all scales that such concerted political
strategies are being mobilized to reshape them. The politics of space thus remain as
contradictory and contentious as ever, and their consequences for everyday life remain to be
fought out in diverse territorial arenas and at a variety of spatial scales.
(Neil Brenner and Stuart Elden, 2009, p. 33)

Antipode [subtitled A Radical Journal of Geography] will reassert itself as not just another
academic journal. We want it to be a radical intellectual and political space, and a project that
represents both a way of seeing the world and a shared commitment to changing that world by
‘being the change we wish to see’.
(Paul Chatterton et al. [The Antipode Editorial Collective], 2011, p. 189)

Since the late 1960s, a group of interrelated politicised approaches has developed within human
geography, which is nevertheless hard to classify under an all-embracing single, descriptive
adjective. The term initially favoured was ‘radical’ (see Smith 1971; Peet, 1977, 1985b; Peake and
Sheppard, 2014), but this became less popular in the 1980s as that term was being applied to the
political movements associated with the ‘new right’, ‘Thatcherism’ and ‘Reaganomics’. Blunt and
Wills (2000, p. xi) used the term ‘dissident geographies’ for their textbook ‘about radical ideas
198 Radical geography

and practices, their geographical origins and manifestations and their implications for geo-
graphical thought’. Since then, the more common term has been ‘critical geography’, although this
includes a considerably wider range of work and influences than those of prior radical geographies
(see Best, 2009, and Castree, 1999, for more on this relationship). Subsequently, much of the spirit
of earlier radical geography has been incorporated into such ‘critical’, postmodern, postcolonial,
poststructuralist and feminist geographies. Anarchism has also had some influence via a radical
rediscovery and celebration of the works of Kropotkin and Reclus, both late nineteenth-century
Russian and French anarchist geographers (see the summary in Blunt and Wills, 2000; the ‘notes
towards autonomous geographies’ by Pickerill and Chatterton, 2006; and a reappraisal and
repositioning of anarchist geography by Springer, 2013, 2014). Since the 1990s, a variety of
‘activist’ and ‘participatory’ geographies ‘concerned with action, reflection and empowerment
(of oneself and others) in order to challenge oppressive power relations’ (Routledge, 2009, p. 7)
have re-energised radical stances while also reshaping the meanings of applied geography.
In the late 1960s and 1970s, however, radicalism was more clearly associated with the adoption
of a Marxist (or Marxian: on the difference, see Harvey, 1973) approach. Thus in Gibson’s (1991,
p. 75) words:

It appears that the stature of human geography within the social sciences has changed
dramatically over the last 20 years. From its location as a field of study uneasily straddling
the earth sciences–social sciences divide and whose contribution to debates central to the
study of society were rather defensively limited to spatial impacts and effects, geography
has become ‘flavour of the month’, especially within left social science discourse. This shift
has partly been produced by others ‘discovering’ geography – Giddens and Foucault, for
example. But more importantly, I would say, it has been produced by changes within the
discipline itself, particularly those wrought by the marrying of aspects of marxist and
geographic theory and the incredible burst of vitality and productivity to which this gave rise.
The work of geographers such as Harvey, Soja, Massey and Sayer is now almost as well known
outside the discipline as within. Many of us have been surprised, and I suppose rather chuffed,
by the way in which human geography has become more broadly validated. But even more
surprising over this period has been the acceptance into ‘mainstream geography’ of significant
elements of marxist theory.

For Cumbers (2009, p. 461), moreover, ‘The adoption of marxism as a theoretical perspective and
a political project in the 1970s was the single most important development in the evolution of a
critical human geography.’
It was certainly entangled with debates about the relevance and applications of human
geography (to the poor or to radical politics, for example), so that it is useful to read this chapter
in tandem with Chapter 9 which focuses on applied geography. For a few years – mostly during the
1980s – radical approaches also became entangled with debates about the merits of an approach to
research known as ‘philosophical realism’ or more often ‘critical realism’ and about the potential
for human geography of ‘structuration theory’ which had been developed by the sociologist
Anthony Giddens. Embodying these, Cloke et al.’s (1991) text contained an entire chapter on realist
approaches in human geography and another on structuration theory. A few years later, in Peet’s
(1998) text, these approaches were relegated to a wider chapter on ‘Structuration, realism and
locality studies’. In more recent textbooks, both realism and structuration crop up, but neither is
given prominence. There are 10 references to structuration theory and 16 references to realism in
the textbook by Kevin Cox (2014) and 10 for each in Cresswell’s (2013). Nayak and Jeffrey’s text
(2011) has brief reference to structuration theory as part of a section on challenges to humanistic
geography on the part of scholars ‘who felt it privileged human free will over societal structures’
(p. 65), but none to realism.
Radical geography 199

It is notable that at the end of the 1980s, Walker (1989a, p. 135) went as far as to claim that
‘While not every realist is a Marxist as regards theory of society . . . every Marxist must be a realist.’
However, not all (indeed not most) of those geographers influenced by Marxism would agree with
Walker. Lawson and Staeheli (1991) defend critical realism from those who see it as an ‘arcane sect’.
For others, however, such as Yeung (1997, p. 52), realism was also a wider philosophy that offered
a path through questions of ‘what is the relationship between philosophy, ontology, epistemology,
theory and method in the social sciences?’. Certainly for some human geographers, realism seemed
to offer a way to specify ‘the difference that space makes’ (S. Duncan, 1989a; A. Sayer, 1985a,
1985b). We will return to the uses made of realism and structuration theory by geographers later
in this chapter. But we should note here that the type of questions posed by Yeung (1997) continued
to produce a wide range of different answers among geographers. These have been further enlivened
by the breadth of debate in radical and critical geography. Geographers’ adoptions of Marxism and
the influence of other radical currents, such as feminism, anti-racism/critical race theory and
postcolonialism, have produced an enduring and heterodox radical presence in geography.

Geography from the left


In his evaluation of radical contributions to American geography, Walker (1989b) wrote of
‘Geography from the left’, which involved ‘bringing the analytic framework and progressive social
agenda of Marxism and allied schools of thought into most of the traditional subject areas of the
discipline’ (p. 619). The goal of achieving a ‘more explicitly spatialized theory of capitalist societies’
involved some scholars developing Marxist theory more fully, whereas others concentrated on
methods and welcomed ‘the clarifications that realism, critical theory, and structuration theory
might add to the understanding of social processes and how to grasp them’ (p. 620); others focused
on ‘middle level’ theories of such topics as local labour markets. Walker argued that:

Left geographers can be proud of their achievements in a discipline that is not always noted
for its explanatory depth or overriding concern with human oppression and liberation. The left
can claim a good deal of credit for broadening the intellectual respectability of the geographic
enterprise.
(p. 620)

His review clearly illustrates the breadth of enquiry undertaken by ‘the left’ in geography over the
preceding couple of decades. Also embodying these contributions, but no longer favouring the
adjective ‘radical’, Peet and Thrift (1989) selected the term ‘political economy’:

to encompass a whole range of perspectives which sometimes differ from one another and yet
share common concerns and similar viewpoints. The term does not imply geography as a type of
economics. Rather economy is understood in its broad sense as social economy, or way of life,
founded in production. . . . Clearly, this definition is influenced by Marxism. . . . But the political-
economy approach in geography is not, and never was, confined to Marxism. . . . So while
political economy refers to a broad spectrum of ideas, these notions have focus and order:
political-economic geographers practise their discipline as part of a general, critical theory
emphasizing the social production of existence.
(p. 3)

This group of approaches began, however, as ‘radical geography’ in the 1960s, largely as a
reaction to the crises of capitalism made clear in increased concern about the persistence of deep
pockets of poverty within the supposedly affluent Western societies, the domestic and international
200 Radical geography

response to the American war in Vietnam, the American Civil Rights movement (beginning with a
call for an improved status for African-Americans, but later encompassing other ‘racial’, ‘ethnic’ and
‘cultural’ minorities), the nascent Green (ecological and conservation) movement, and the wider
rise of a ‘counter-culture’ (perhaps epitomised by the ‘hippies’ of the late 1960s and early 1970s)
who questioned the ‘mainstream’ way of life. Critical work on imperialism and war (especially the
American-led war in Vietnam) soon featured in radical geography (Blaut, 1970; Folke, 1973;
Lacoste, 1973), along with a pioneering paper about the geography of anti-war demonstrations in
the USA (Akatiff, 1974; for more on this aspect of the making of radical geography, see Power and
Sidaway, 2004; Mathewson and Wisner, 2005; Bowd and Clayton, 2013; Peake and Sheppard,
2014). These mobilisations were accompanied by the ‘sexual revolution’: changing social mores
and a sense of increased sexual freedom in Western societies – although it would be a few years
more before these mores were further questioned by the women’s and gay liberation move-
ments (see Chapter 8). The late 1960s and 1970s also saw a period of creative reinterpretation of
Marx(ism) in the aftermath of the Stalinist orthodoxy which prevailed in preceding decades. This
was both an intellectual movement, led by scholars in Western universities, and a practical politics
of revolution and social change, especially in those parts of the Third World (such as Cuba and
Vietnam) where national liberation and revolutionary movements gained or sought power. In
short, left-wing and revolutionary causes enjoyed a renaissance and were characterised by
experimentation and fresh ideas. Geography connected with these new left and counter-cultures
which in America was institutionalised by the creation of several short-lived bodies such as the
Union of Socialist Geographers (USG) and the Socially and Ecologically Responsible Geographers
(SERGE).
Looking back to this moment, which dates from the late 1960s, Harvey (1999) notes how:

Marx seemed to speak to those of us (always a minority of course) who were seeking a theo-
retical basis to understand the chaos and political disruptions surrounding us at the time (the
imperialist war in Vietnam, the strikes and urban unrest, the civil rights movement, the student
movements of 1968 that shook the world from Paris to Mexico City, the Czech ‘spring’ and its
subsequent repression by the Soviets, the war in the Middle East – just to name a few of the
signal events that made it seem as if the world as we knew it was falling apart).
(p. xi)

The Spanish geographer Horacio Capel (1981, pp. 426–7; our translation) thus notes how, in
American geography of the late 1960s: ‘That which just a few years before [quantitative geography]
had been received as the truly scientific method, seemed now clearly unsatisfactory or a mystification.’
Capel designates 1969 as a significant moment in the emergence of radical geography:

Firstly, the 1969 annual meeting of the Association of American Geographers at Ann Arbor saw
a critical mass of radical papers and manifestos. Secondly, in 1969 commenced the publication
of a journal which, in its very title already expressed its aspiration to situate itself in the antipodes
of geography as it was then practised: Antipode. A Radical Journal of Geography.

Capel also notes that, at the same time, William Bunge initiated his so-called ‘geographical
expeditions’ to ‘marginal urban areas’ (see p. 237 and p. 322, this book) and other geographers
increasingly participated in political and citizens’ movements. Finally, Capel notes that while the
actual numbers of radical geographers were never large, radical geography constituted ‘an
extraordinarily active movement that has extended its critique to very diverse fields of academic
geography and forced it to encounter authentically radical alternative trajectories’ (p. 427).
That William Bunge and David Harvey who had both been associated with spatial-science just
a few years before were now lending their intellect and authority to radical geography helped to
Radical geography 201

foster the latter. But, radical geography’s agendas were also being shaped by a new generation, many
of them postgraduate students, who established Antipode as a radical forum for publication in 1969.
Subsequently, as the revolutionary pressures of the late 1960s became a distant memory, the ideas
and critical insights of radical geography percolated into and then – to a significant extent – became
part of the intellectual mainstream of anglophone human geography. In the process it had become
‘more sober and less combative’ (Peet and Thrift, 1989, p. 7). There were a number of reasons for
this. In the first place, Marxism was subjected to renewed criticism. Second, the recession and
restructurings of the 1980s (which included cuts in academic budgets) led to a more sober
and cautious intellectual atmosphere than the heady days of the late 1960s when everything
seemed possible – and Antipode itself was transferred from an in-house publication at Clark
University’s Graduate School of Geography to a commercial publisher, with ownership vested in an
editorial trust (Peake and Sheppard, 2014). At the same time, greater awareness of the problems of
state socialist economies and a wider sense that the tide of history had tipped against statist and
socialist projects made the prospects of revolutionary or radical change more precarious. Finally,
radical geography became more narrowly professional, and some of the ‘radical, anti-establishment
Young Turks’ joined the establishment (see Barnes, 1996, p. 49). Nevertheless, Peet and Thrift
conclude that ‘The [radically inspired] political-economy approach . . . has survived counterattack,
critique, and economic and professional hard times, and has matured into a leading and, for many,
the leading school of contemporary geographic thought’ (p. 7).

Radical trajectories
Peet (1977) has claimed that the early ‘radical’ work by geographers in the late 1960s was mostly
liberal in its interpretations and aspirations:

Radicals investigated only the surface aspects of these questions – that is, how social problems
were manifested in space. For this, either we found the conventional methodology adequate
enough or we proposed only that existing methods of research must be modified to some extent
if they are to serve the analytic and reconstructive policies of . . . radical applications (Wisner,
1970, p. 1) . . . we were fitting into an established market . . . we were amenable to established
ways of thinking . . . we were useful in providing background ideas for the formulation of
pragmatic public policy directions, and so could not, and were not, engaging in radical analysis
and practice.
(p. 245).

Ideas of mapping welfare (Smith, 1975) and later a fully-fledged ‘welfare geography’ (described in
more detail in Chapter 9) were broadly in this reformist spirit, part of what Roger Lee and Chris
Philo (2009, p. 225) describe as ‘an emerging sense that human geographers should be investigating
the geographies of inequality, and perhaps the clearest index was a number of papers appearing in
Antipode . . . during its earliest years’. Initially, therefore, the purpose of much writing in the emerging
radical framework was to demonstrate the shortcomings and lacunae of positivist-inspired (and
related behavioural) research. Gray (1975), for example, presented a critique of studies of the
operations of housing markets which mapped people’s residential moves and inferred that these
were the outcomes of choice and the expressions of preferences. He argued that such research:

1 assumes that people are free to choose in which homes (including where) they live, when
most are constrained to particular types of dwellings in certain parts of urban areas only;
2 accepts that residential patterns are the consequence of a large number of residents’ decisions
rather than those of a few developers and institutional managers; and
202 Radical geography

3 implies that the study of consumers provides the key to understanding the structure of urban
areas.

People are not free to choose, however: ‘Instead, many groups are constricted and con-
strained from choice and pushed into particular housing situations because of their position in the
housing market, and by the individuals and institutions . . . controlling the operation
of particular housing systems’ (p. 230). Research in line with Gray’s critique focused on the
controllers of access to housing, individuals who became known as ‘urban managers’.
According to Pahl’s (1969) influential paper, urban residential patterns are the consequence
of two basic sets of constraints: the spatial constraints on access to resources and facilities,
which are usually expressed in terms of time/cost distance; and the social constraints – the
bureaucratic rules and procedures operated by gatekeepers – that govern access and reflect
the distribution of power in society. Study of the latter focused on the key managerial groups,
such as building societies and their lending policies (Boddy, 1976; Dingemans, 1979), the
managers of local government housing stock (Gray, 1976; Taylor, 1979), the local authority
officials who influence the redevelopment of private housing (Duncan, 1974a, 1975), and
the real-estate agents who structure access to housing submarkets (Palm, 1979). Subsequently,
therefore, urban geography became a key entry point of radical ideas into the discipline.
This was given further impetus by the evolution of radical perspectives in the neighbouring
field of urban sociology and the inauguration of the multidisciplinary International Journal of
Urban and Regional Research which was founded under the auspices of the International Sociological
Association (ISA) research committee on the sociology of regional and urban development
in 1977.
The reception of Pahl’s work is a case in point (he was trained as a geographer, with a Ph.D.
from the LSE, but then worked in a sociology department). In the 1970s, Pahl was widely read and
cited among radical geographers (especially in the UK and Europe). Pahl himself continued to
revise his ideas, pointing out that planners, for example, are merely ‘the bailiffs and estate managers
of capitalism, with very little power’ (1975, p. 7; see also Pahl, 1979) so that focusing on them and
other gatekeepers tends to:

view the situation through the eyes of disadvantaged local populations and to attribute more
control and responsibility to the local official than, say, local employers or the national
government . . . such ‘a criticism of local managers of the Caretaking Establishment’ and ‘of
the vested interest and archaic methods of the middle dogs’ may lead to an uncritical
accommodation to the national elite and society’s master institutions.
(pp. 267–8)

Whereas the managerial approach focused on the agents who interpret and activate the real
mechanisms, producing patterns of residential segregation, Harvey paid much more attention to
the mechanisms themselves (though with reference to particular outcomes: Harvey, 1974e).
Residential separation is one means of reproducing class differences in a capitalist society. It is
produced by those who manage finance capital, interpreting the basic mechanisms of the capitalist
mode of production (i.e. the need to generate profits), and it results in a series of spatially separated
housing submarkets within which individual households may express their preferences, producing
micro-scale migration patterns:

But there is a scale of action at which the individual loses control of the social conditions of
existence . . . [sensing] their own helplessness in the face of forces that do not appear amenable,
under given institutions, even to collective political mechanisms of control.
(Harvey, 1975a, p. 368)
Radical geography 203

In the American context the promotion of suburbanisation was a major means of stimulating
consumption (of housing, automobiles, consumer durables, etc.) at a time of dangerous latent
overproduction (Harvey, 1975b, 1978; Walker, 1981a; for the particular outcomes, see Johnston,
1984c). Thus, urban geographers who accepted the Marxist argument saw their basic task as
integrating discussions of the mechanisms that drive capitalist (and other) societies, the inter-
pretations of those mechanisms by key agents (the managers and gatekeepers), and the empirical
outcomes and experiences. They focused on how and why society operates, not on generalisations
regarding the empirical outcomes (as in Bassett and Short, 1980; Badcock, 1984; Johnston, 1980a).
However, the study of urban residential patterns is just one element of the wider study of urbani-
sation, which Scott (1985) – in ways that echoed Harvey’s developing work on the urbanisation of
capital – related to the complex nature of capitalism:

the mechanisms of production, the interlinkages of firms, and the formation of local labor
markets . . . combine to create a process in which the profit-seeking (cost-reducing) proclivities
of producers lead directly to the dense spatial massing of units of capital and, as a corollary, of
labor.
(p. 481)

The influence of the initial move to radical urban geography has thus been long and
enduring. Subsequent work has explored how cities are both labour markets and places for the
reproduction of labour, involving what Castells (1977) and others term ‘collective consumption’ of
commodities produced by the state rather than purchased in the market place (see also Pinch,
1985, 1997), although the shift to ‘privatise’ these has itself become a domain of critical analysis,
amid other regulatory shifts (see p. 211, this book). The issue of gentrification, whereby some
formerly working-class inner-city neighbourhoods become areas of middle-class and elite housing
also became a subject of investigation, following a key paper (N. Smith, 1979b) that designated
gentrification as a ‘back to the city movement by capital, not people’ (p. 538); for a review of the
debates that this initiated, see Lees (2000, 2012) and Lees et al. (2010). More than three decades on,
the role of capital flows through urban real estate, especially in American cities (so-called ‘subprime
loans’, designated as ‘predatory lending’ by radicals) in the making of the financial crisis became a
focus, especially via capital’s articulations with race and class (Harvey, 2011; Wyly et al., 2008; Wyly
et al., 2009). Here, however, we are getting ahead of the story of the formation of radical geography
in the late 1960s and early 1970s.
The move from liberal interpretation to radical and Marxist critique was also illustrated in
Peet’s (1971) paper on poverty in the USA, in which, like Morrill and Wohlenberg (see p. 322, this
book), he argued for a series of growth centres in the poverty areas to stimulate economic
development and job creation, and also by the tenor of the articles in early issues of the radicals’
journal, Antipode. Morrill (1969), for example, argued:

against the ‘New Left’ premise that a revolution is the only route to progress . . . the dreams of
revolution are naive . . . the ‘New Left’ vastly exaggerates potential support . . . a ‘revolutionary
program’ is hopelessly dated and simplistic . . . the ‘New Left’ underestimates the capacity of
our society for change. . . . All revolutions seem to have been betrayed by incompetents who
preferred exercising power to executing reform.
(pp. 7–8)

Again, he argued (Morrill, 1970b) that:

A simple Marxist-type change in the ownership of business from private to a government (or
union) bureaucracy would in all probability decrease production, and would not necessarily bring
204 Radical geography

any improvement in basic conditions. The key is to retain the institution of private property while
instituting social control over its exchange and circumscribing its power over people.
(p. 8)

The case for a Marxist approach was first presented formally by Folke (1972) in a critique of
Harvey’s (1972) paper on ghetto formation and counter-revolutionary theory. Folke represented
geography and the other social sciences as:

highly sophisticated, technique-orientated, but largely descriptive disciplines with little relevance
for the solution of acute and seemingly chronic societal problems . . . theory has reflected the
values and interests of the ruling class.
(p. 13)

Liberal cases like Morrill’s were dismissed as unlikely to succeed. Morrill’s two papers in Antipode
argued for change to be brought about by political consensus, producing a capitalist–socialist
convergence. But this is the social democrat method practised in Sweden (and then also influential
in other left-of-centre parties, such as the French socialists, German Social Democrats and the
British Labour Party) where, according to Folke (1972):

it has been shown over and over again that the idea of equal influence for employers and employees
is an illusion. After half a century of social-democratic rule injustices and inequalities still
prevail. . . . No small group of experts can accomplish anything . . . when it runs counter to the
interests of the dominant social forces. These are not interested in equality or justice, but in profit.
(p. 15)

Radical change requires mass mobilisation and so, to Folke, Harvey’s call for a new paradigm
within geography was insufficient. What was needed was a new paradigm for a unified social
science, containing geography, which deals with problems in all their complexity and provides
not only theory but also the basis for action: ‘Revolutionary theory without revolutionary practice
is not only useless, it is inconceivable . . . practice is the ultimate criterion of truth’ (p. 7; see
also Eliot Hurst, 1980, 1985).
The major contribution to the case for a Marxist-inspired theoretical development within
geography was subsequently made by David Harvey, initially in his collection of essays Social Justice
and the City (Harvey, 1973). The book is presented as autobiographical, illustrating the evolution of
Harvey’s views towards an acceptance of Marx’s analysis:

as a guide to enquiry . . . I do not turn to it out of some a priori sense of its inherent superiority
(although I find myself naturally in tune with its general presupposition of and commitment to
change), but because I can find no other way of accomplishing what I set out to do or of
understanding what has to be understood.
(Folke, 1972, p. 17)

The first part of the book, entitled ‘Liberal formulations’, comprises essays which analyse
problems of inequality within societies in terms of income-allocating mechanisms; the role of
accessibility and location in those mechanisms is stressed. This leads into an attempt at defining
territorial social justice, which separates the processes allocating incomes from those which
produce them. Only in the second part of the book – ‘Socialist formulations’ – is it:

finally recognized that the definition of income (which is what distributive justice is concerned with)
is itself defined by production. . . . The collapse of the distinction between production and
Radical geography 205

distribution, between efficiency and social justice, is a part of that general collapse of all dualisms
of this sort accomplished through accepting Marx’s approach and technique of analysis.
(p. 15)

Harvey (2000, pp. 77–8) subsequently noted how he had become disillusioned with the
evident limits to the socialism of the British Labour party in the late 1960s (the government of
Harold Wilson). However, it was his move to the USA (from the University of Bristol to Johns
Hopkins University, Baltimore) at the end of the 1960s that sharpened his political commitment.
Thus, when he wrote Explanation in Geography (Harvey, 1969a) in 1968 (which, as Chapter 4 charts,
was a key text setting out the prospects for a positivist and quantitative geography):

my politics at that time were closer to a Fabian progressivism, which is why I was taken with the
ideas of planning, efficiency and rationality. . . . So in my mind, there was no real conflict between
a rational scientific approach to geographical issues, and an efficient application of planning to
political issues. But I was so absorbed in writing the book that I didn’t notice how much was
collapsing around me. I turned in my magnum opus to the publishers in May 1968, only to find
myself acutely embarrassed by the change of political temperature at large. By then, I was
thoroughly disillusioned with Harold Wilson’s socialism. Just at that moment, I got a job in the
US, arriving in Baltimore a year after much of the city had burnt down in the wake of the
assassination of Martin Luther King. In the States, the anti-war movement and the civil rights
movement were really fired up; and there was I, having written this neutral tome that seemed
somehow or other just not to fit. I realized I had to rethink a lot of things I had taken for granted
in the sixties.
(Harvey, 2000, p. 78)

That political stance did not disappear; when he returned to the UK in 1987 to take up a senior
post, ‘I was forcefully reminded of what I had long ago rebelled against. The smugness of much of
Oxford repelled me, and I could not understand how the left in Britain, within geography and
without, was taking such wishy-washy positions in relation to Thatcherism’ (Harvey, 2002, p. 179).
The transition in Harvey’s approach is marked by his paper on ghetto formation (Harvey,
1972). He begins with a critique of Kuhn’s model of scientific development (p. 15, this book),
asking how anomalies to the current paradigm arise and how they are translated into crises. The
problem with Kuhn’s analysis, he claims, is the assumption that science is independent of its
enveloping material conditions, when in fact it is very much geared to its containing and
constraining society. Recognition of this point is important for geographers because:

the driving force behind paradigm formulation in the social sciences is the desire to manipulate
and control human activity in the interest of man. Immediately the question arises as to who is
going to control whom, in whose interest is the controlling going to be exercised, and if control is
going to be exercised in the interest of all, who is going to take it upon himself to define that
public interest?
(Harvey, 1973, p. 125)

To Harvey, Marxist theory provides ‘the key to understanding capitalist production from the
position of those not in control of the means of production . . . an enormous threat to the power
structure of the capitalist world’ (p. 127). It not only enhances an understanding of the origins of
the present system, with its many-faceted inequalities, but also propounds alternative practices
which would avoid such inequalities: ‘we become active participants in the social process. The
intellectual task is to identify real choices as they are immanent in an existing situation and to devise
ways of validating or invalidating these choices through action’ (p. 149). In such a context,
206 Radical geography

geography can no longer be merely an academic discipline, isolated in its ‘ivory towers’. Its
practitioners must become politically aware and active, involved in the creation of a just society
which involves not only reform but rather replacement of the present one. The remainder of
Harvey’s (1973) book does not make this commitment clear, however; it contains one essay on land
use and land-value theory, investigating the difficult concept of rent, and another on the nature of
urbanism, presenting a Marxist interpretation of the process of urbanisation. His later (1984)
historical materialist manifesto is a very clear statement of that goal, however, and his (1982;
second edition, 1999) The Limits to Capital is presented as a venture to extend Marx’s theory, excavating
the centrality of the production of space and geographically uneven development to the reproduction
of capitalist society, in a similar spirit to Neil Smith’s (1994a) equally ambitious excavations of the
essential, but highly complex, relations between capitalist (re)production and Uneven Development.
(Interestingly, Harvey (2002, p. 176) claimed that it was ‘far easier to bring Marxism into geography
than to take geographical perspectives back into Marxism’.)
Harvey’s work continued to develop these themes during the 1980s, 1990s and 2000s. Two
further volumes of essays extended his analyses of urbanisation under capitalism (Harvey, 1985a,
1985c; see also Harvey, 1996b, and for a critical overview the essays in Gregory and Castree, 2006,
including Harvey’s own response) followed by an interpretation of the socioeconomic and
geographical backdrop to ‘postmodern’ forms of culture (1989a). Other essays addressed issues of
geopolitics (Harvey, 1985b) and relationships with nature (Harvey, 1994). He then returned to
issues of justice (Harvey, 1993a, 1996a) and the imperative for and possibility of alternatives to
capitalist urbanisation and ‘globalization’ (Harvey, 2000), while at the same time defending his
approach against a variety of critiques. Throughout, he has advanced the case for Marxism (as a
creative and open-ended historical dialectical materialism), as a holistic approach that necessarily
puts material issues at the core of its analysis (Harvey, 1989b). Over the years, Harvey’s understanding
of this materiality has broadened (Harvey, 2000, thus has an extended consideration of ‘the body’
as a site of accumulation) but remained always resolute and ambitious in the face, as Harvey (2000,
pp. 87–8) would see it, of ‘The ubiquity and volatility of money as the impalpable ground of
contemporary existence.’
Peet had also moved from a liberal to a Marxist position, replacing his earlier paper on poverty
(Peet, 1971) by a marxist interpretation (Peet, 1975a) based on the assumption that inequality is
inherent in the capitalist mode of production. This led to a ‘metatheory dealing with the great forces
which shape millions of lives’ (p. 567) within which ‘Environmental, or geographic, theory deals
with the mechanisms which perpetuate inequality from the point of view of the individual. It deals
with the complex of forces, both stimuli and frictions, which immediately shape the course of a
person’s life’ (pp. 567–8). Environmental resources act as constraints because they define the
milieux within which individuals are socialised and are presented with opportunities for
participation within the capitalist system (see also Soja, 1980). Redistribution of income through
liberal mechanisms, based on taxation policies, will not solve the problems of poverty, therefore;
according to Peet, alternative environmental designs, with removal of central bureaucracies and
their replacement by anarchistic models of community control are needed and geographers should
work towards their creation. (Harvey (1973, p. 93) disagreed with the latter, pointing out that
unless resources are equalised among communities and territories, community control will only
result in ‘the poor controlling their own poverty while the rich grow more affluent from the fruits
of their riches’. See, however, Harvey, 2000.)
Later on, responding to the post-9/11 wars led by the USA, Harvey (2003) examined the new
forms of imperialism as well as associated forms of neoliberalism and enclosure. For Harvey,
neoliberalism, as the ideology and practice of commodification and privatisation, needs to be
studied as a geographical project of remaking state and society in the image of capital, restoring the
privilege of the ruling class (producing an expanded super-rich but eroding working-class
solidarity). This has:
Radical geography 207

entailed much ‘creative destruction’, not only of prior institutional frameworks and powers
(even challenging traditional forms of state sovereignty) but also of divisions of labour, social
relations, welfare provisions, technological mixes, ways of life and thought, reproductive
activities, attachments to the land and habits of the heart.
(Harvey, 2005b, p. 3)

Harvey and other geographers influenced by Marxism’s commitment to expose the


dynamics of the capitalist system (such as Massey’s, 1984a, Spatial Divisions of Labour and sub-
sequent research on the geography of work, such as Herod, 2001, as well as other material
reviewed elsewhere in this chapter), thus both developed a Marxist (or Marxian) geography and a
geographical approach to reading Marx’s Capital that insisted that these capitalist dynamics
were necessarily spatial. Capitalism sought ‘a spatial fix’ – it made and remade space (through
mobilising labour and the means of production, including technology), relentlessly pursuing
profit, endlessly looking to accumulate.
To Eliot Hurst (1980), however, embracing Marxism would always be insufficient. In a
subsequent essay he argued that by circumscribing their discipline, geographers were severely
constraining what they could contribute towards understanding the world: their discipline was
presented as a technical practice only, which ‘is merely descriptive of self-selected phenomena and
is scientifically bankrupt’ (Eliot Hurst, 1985, p. 62). He examined eight separate definitions of
geography, all of which were guilty of what he termed spatial fetishism (after Anderson, 1973),
whereby space is accorded a separate and substantial reality with its own distinctive powers, and he
followed David Slater (1977) in arguing that geography cannot be incorporated within Marxism
but has to be transcended and superseded by it; to become Marxist, geographers as a professional
group must commit suicide. He concluded that ‘geography is irrelevant to contemporary society on
two basic grounds’ (Eliot Hurst, 1985, p. 85):

1 in terms of substantial content, it has developed ‘certain types of ideography, method/


technique-strong, but lacking theory in a strict sense’ to provide the sort of material which
underpins contemporary capitalism; and
2 in philosophical terms it occupies ‘an untheorized point of entry to knowledge’ because its
dominant ‘categories of concern, such as space, spatial differentiation, spatial interaction and
uneven development, are mere fetishisms and unscientific’.

Radical reconfiguration is needed in order to promote full understanding of capitalist society, not
just of geography but the entire body of ‘bourgeois social science’.

Structuralist Marxisms, regulation theory,


localities and regions
Structuralisms
The reinvigorated Marxism which influenced radical geographers has sometimes been presented as
a variant of the philosophy of structuralism (of which there are many different forms: cf. Johnston,
1983a; Peet, 1998), but which are most indebted to the French Marxist Louis Althusser who
published a number of influential reinterpretations of Marx in the 1960s and early 1970s.
Structuralism is certainly not the only strand of Marxist geography, for Sheppard and Barnes (1990)
have also set out the possibilities of an ‘analytical Marxism’ in geography and David Harvey charted
his own course to an historical geographical materialism. On Harvey, Castree (1996) therefore
argues that:
208 Radical geography

what is distinctive about Harvey’s Marxism . . . is how little indebted it is to other readings of
Marx: reading Capital has for him long been preferred to Reading Capital (Althusser and Balibar
1970). . . . This is quite unusual among Anglophone Marxian theorists: few appropriate Marx in
an ‘unreconstructed’ way and far more read him through interpretations provided by earlier
heirs of Marx’s legacy. . . . This is why Harvey . . . sees both Althusserian and analytical Marxism
– perhaps the two leading Marxist paradigms of the last two decades – as radical reworkings of
Marx. . . . Harvey, by contrast, very much regards his own work as a more or less direct, ‘faithful’
continuation and extension of Marx’s own practices and ideas: in short, as a peculiarly classical
version of Marxism bought forward from the last fin de siècle to our own.
(p. 344)

Meanwhile, analytical Marxism seeks to evaluate Marx’s work and insights using tools
available from contemporary social sciences. Influential within radical branches of economics, for
geography it has amounted to:

the use of analytical methods . . . to construct a wide-ranging model of the capitalist space
economy incorporating commodity production, natural resources, the built environment, class
formation, technical change and industrial organization.
(Sheppard and Barnes, 1990, pp. 1–2)

Describing some of the inspiration to this project, Sheppard and Barnes (1990, p. 1) also note
how:

As a model for the kind of account we wish to present, we pay homage to David Harvey’s (1982)
Limits to Capital, from which we drew many insights and ideas. Yet our argument is different in
style from his, and indeed from many others whose ideas we share. For at the core of this book
is the belief that a clear account of the political economic approach is obtained by interrogating
our subject matter with an analytical (mathematical) logic.

Nevertheless, structuralism merits further consideration here, in part because of its indirect impacts
as an influence on the regulationist approaches that we will also consider.
Perhaps where structuralism had the most direct impact within anglophone geography was in
reactions to the work of the Catalan theorist, Manuel Castells (whose original work was mostly
written in French). Peet (1989) notes how:

structural[ist] work on cities and urban planning (Preticeille 1976; Pickvance 1976) began to
appear in English in the middle 1970s. . . . Most importantly, a translation of Manuel Castells’s
(1977) structuralist work on cities, The Urban Question, had a profound effect, especially on
urban geography.
(p. 112)

Peet, however, goes on to note how:

The move towards structuralism, never complete in geographical thought, represented a


search for greater theoretical coherence and rigor. It is also the most misrepresented and
underappreciated period in social and geographical thought.
(p. 112)

Structural Marxism was also an influence in Doreen Massey’s (1984a) account of Spatial
Divisions of Labour: Social structures and the geography of production. This soon proved to be an influential book
Radical geography 209

(see p. 212, this book), although its debt to structural Marxism was only explicitly specified in the
second (1995) edition. Structural Marxism also came to influence a generation of work on the
unevenness, contradictions and limits of capitalist development in the Third World (for example,
Blaut, 1975; Cannon, 1975; Slater, 1973, 1977), even if its influence on development geography
was soon being criticised for its perceived ‘economism’. Thus, Corbridge (1986, p. 64) claimed
that ‘Althusserians have not escaped the sins of economic determinism. . . . In their curiously
changless theories, capitalism is endowed with an endless and ageless capacity to secure its own
perpetuation.’
In response, Michael Watts (1988) stressed the continued relevance and richness of Marxist
perspectives on geographies of (uneven) development. Althusser’s work can thus be read as creating
radically new formulations of Marxism, especially his development of the concepts of ‘over-
determination’ and ‘condensation’. In this he adapted terms from psychoanalysis (‘condensation’ is
used in Freud’s interpretations of dreams) to refer to the way that elements of a complex whole are
expressed in each of its parts and vice versa. The potential application of these to human geography
was not quickly realised, however. Moreover, the sense that structural Marxism has often been mis-
represented or caricatured as unduly rigid and mechanistic is also a point of critique for Castree
(1994, 1995a), who reminds us of both the continued diversity of Marxist writings, their consid-
erable nuances and differences, and the range of works in geography that they lend themselves to.
Moreover, as Peet shows, the impacts of structuralism within and beyond Marxist-influenced geo-
graphy have been complex. Perhaps the most significant influence has been a rather indirect one,
via the way that structuralist ideas shaped regulation theory, which in turn became an influential
strand of geographical work in the 1990s. We will consider this strand in a moment.
First, however, it should be noted that structuralism more widely has had a long-standing
concern with the dynamics and rules of systems of meaning and power. In particular, structuralism
proceeds through examining the relations and functions of the smallest constituent elements of
such systems in relation to each other (see p. 111, this book). The emphasis is on this relation, on
the relationship of parts to the whole. The work of Ferdinand de Saussure, undertaken just prior to
the First World War in the field of linguistics, has been a prototype and inspiration. Setting the
agenda for wider structuralist analysis, Saussure’s study was centred less on speech itself, but rather
on the fundamental rules and conventions enabling language to operate. Structuralism has since
found further application in the fields of linguistics and textual analysis, as well as anthropology
and wider studies of culture, prior to coming into fruitful interactions with Marxism in the form
of Althussers’s work. The fact that Marx’s method contained a parallel commitment to study the
dynamic relations between the whole and parts of the capitalist system enabled this encounter.
Marxism adopts a dialectical approach to its subject matter, since this represents how societies
develop. It involves the resolution of opposites, usually represented by the trilogy of:

thesis

synthesis anthesis

in which each synthesis becomes the next thesis; thus, there is no permanent resolution, each
synthesis containing within itself the seeds of its own destruction. Dialectic processes operate at a
variety of spatial and temporal resolutions (Castree, 1996; Harvey, 1996b; Ollman, 1993). Indeed,
Castree (1996) reminds us that:
210 Radical geography

Just as Marxism has developed into a complex discursive tradition [and we might add complex
political practice too] – that is, a variegated set of distinct but related intellectual positions and
practices whose particularity and specific genealogies must be respected – dialectics too has
assumed manifold forms and accumulated multiple meanings within [and we might add beyond]
this Marxist tradition. Strictly speaking, then, the language of ‘Marxism’ and ‘dialectics’, in the
singular, must be abandoned for a more discriminating attention to Marxisms and dialectics, in
the plural.
(p. 344)

A key structuralist theme is that of relations between levels of analysis:

1 the level of appearances, or the superstructure;


2 the level of processes, or the infrastructure; and
3 the level of imperatives, or the deep structure.

Most forms of structuralism have no deterministic relationship between these levels. A process can
result in a considerable number of outcomes, depending on a variety of enabling and constraining
factors, most of them within the superstructure. To illustrate this, the French social anthropologist
Claude Lévi-Strauss used the analogy of the cam-shaft driving a machine for cutting the outlines of
jigsaw puzzles (Figure 6.1). The machine is constrained to certain movements only, but the order
in which they come is random, which means that it can produce a large number of unique puzzles.
Study of one of these puzzles alone could not reveal the nature of the machine; only study of the
machine could do that. Structuralism is the study of the machines but, unlike the analogy, these are
not available for investigation. Structuralist researchers must develop a theory of the machine and
test whether the contents of the superstructure are consistent with that theory; the contents of the
superstructure cannot be predicted, however, because, to continue the cam-shaft analogy, the
particular operation of the machine cannot be foreseen.

SPATIAL PATTERNS Empirical Level


Levi-Strauss’s
(empiricist conception of
’jig-saw puzzle’ OF spatial structure1
50CIAL EXCHANGE

Levi-Strauss’s systems of constraints


’cam-shaft’

Socio-structural level
(collectivist conception of
spatial structure)

ςρΔτίΔΐ STRurrniRF

Levi-Strauss’s
models of intelligibility
‘mathematical formula’

Neuro-structural level
(formalist conception of
spatial structure)

SPATIAL SCHEMA

Figure 6.1  A geographical interpretation of Lévi-Strauss’s cam-shaft for structuralism


Radical geography 211

In some forms of structuralism, such as Lévi-Strauss’s social anthropology (E. R. Leach, 1974),
it is further argued that the processes operating in the infrastructure reflect imperatives located in
the deep structure. Theoretical study of the patterns in the superstructure should reveal the nature
of the deep structure, therefore (in somewhat similar fashion to the identification of essences in
phenomenology: p. 179, this book). Thus, according to Lévi-Strauss, all incest taboos are variants
of a basic taboo which is imprinted in everybody’s conscience. That basic form occurs in different
ways in separate societies and cultures, but careful comparison of all taboos should reveal their
common elements, and thus that aspect of human neural structure.
Few geographers have taken structuralism this far, although it might be claimed that the
imperatives of deep structures have often appealed to geographers as a domain of analysis (see
Golledge, 1981a; Sack, 1983; Sibley, 1998). Moreover, there are those who pointed to the
consequences – in their view, problematic ones – of Marxist geography (in the form of David
Harvey’s work) replicating this appeal to structure at the perceived expense of agency and
contingency (Jones, 1999). We return to this theme later in this chapter.

Regulation theory
One way in which structuralism has found productive expression has been via geographers’
adoption of regulation theory. This studies the procedures and practices whereby capitalism is
reproduced (‘regulated’) – the sets of checks and balances that keep the system going, albeit from
one period of crisis to another. It thus draws on a nuanced understanding of both ideology and
power – drawing on the rediscovery and translation of the (pre-Second World War) works of the
Italian Marxist Antonio Gramsci (more recently re-presented to geographers by Joel Wainwright,
2010, and Ekers et al., 2013), as well as the concepts of multiple determination (so-called
overdetermination) which shape the balances between ‘state’, ‘society’, production, consumption,
and social and technological forces which are seen to propel and embody socio-spatial
transformations (this owes much to Louis Althusser; see Lipietz, 1993). This is much more than a
formal interest in government rules and regulations; what is understood by regulation in the
common sense of the word. Instead, as Peck and Tickell (1995, p. 16) note:

Although by no means a completed theoretical project, it has nevertheless matured to the


extent that proponents now work from a well-established set of conceptual foundations. The
theory holds that capitalist development proceeds through a succession of historically specific
phases of stability and crisis, sustained growth and intense restructuring. Emphasis is placed on
the role of state forms, social mores, laws and habits; the so-called mode of social regulation
(MSR) in underwriting sustained phases of growth. These phases, in which the schema of
reproduction (the complex of production, consumption, and distribution systems) is broadly in
synchronisation are termed regimes of accumulation.
(p. 16)

Though regulation theory first developed in France outside geography (see Boyer and Saillard,
1995; Macleod, 1997), ‘Anglo-American’ human geographers and allied social scientists have since
added greatly to it through careful attention to the relationships between reconfigurations in
systems of production, different geographical scales and their roles in regulatory reconfigurations
(e.g. Amin, 1994; Amin and Robins, 1990; Clark, 1992; Dunford, 1990; Gertler, 1992; Goodwin
et al., 1993; Tickell and Peck, 1992), including reconfigured rural geographies (Cloke and Goodwin,
1992). In turn, this has reinvigorated geographical literature on the intersection and production of
different scales of social and political life (Herod and Wright, 2002, review these debates). Related
notions of the ‘geographies of governance’ have noted how they are today less clearly organised
along state lines (and national boundaries – hence, such work has consequences for political
212 Radical geography

geography) within the context of rescalings (e.g. Brenner, 2004; Brenner et al., 2003; G. Clark,
1992; Herod et al., 1998; Herod and Wright, 2002) and the shifting regulation and scales of state
policy (see the reviews by MacLeod and Holden, 2009; Painter, 2000; Peck, 2000).
At the same time as regulation theory offered fruitful pathways to renew radical geography’s
concern with the structural dynamics of capitalism, other work had returned to the points and
relations of production (though not just industrial production), charting labour geographies (see
the review in Wills, 2002) and changing geographies of class relations (e.g. Herod, 2001; Peck,
1996), including those of universities in which academic geographers and many relatively low-
paid support and technical staff work (Roberts, 2000). (For an extended discussion of changes
within economic geography over the second half of the twentieth century, see Scott, 2000.)

Spatial divisions of labour and localities


The localities research programme originated in part from Massey’s (1984a) work on the changing
geography of economic activity in the UK. (A measure of the significance of her book on Spatial
Divisions of Labour is the collection of ten commentaries by Australian-based authors in Environment and
Planning A: Fahey et al., 1989.) Her central argument was that understanding changing locational
patterns of industries requires appreciation of the links between economic and social change. Local
social structures vary in how the labour process is organised, and from comparing two case study
regions she concluded that:

although both . . . are now being drawn into a similar place in an emerging wider division of
labour, their roles in previous spatial divisions of labour have been very different; they have
different histories. They bring with them different class structures and social characteristics,
and, as a result, the changes which they undergo . . . are also different.
(p. 194)

Thus, changing industrial geography is linked to a changing social geography as new ‘layers of
investment’ (and disinvestment) are superimposed on those of earlier eras (see also J. Anderson
et al., 1983).
Those processes generate uneven development; a regional mosaic of unique areas reflecting
the interpretations of local contexts by the actors involved in creating the UK’s changing geographies
of production. Massey (1984b) generalised this in her essay ‘Geography matters’, in terms of each
of its three traditional concerns – space, environment and place. Regarding space, for example, she
argued that ‘aspects of “the spatial” are important in the construction, functioning, reproduction
and change of societies as a whole and of elements of society. Distance and separation are regularly
used by companies to establish degrees of monopoly control’ (p. 5). Regarding the environment,
she argued that conceptions of the ‘natural’, and thus interpretations of local environmental
potentials, are socially produced, and could vary among areas as a reflection of their separate social
systems, whereas with regard to place she contended that general processes can have particular
outcomes in unique areas – hence her introduction of the concept of the ‘global sense of place’
(Featherstone and Painter, 2013). Thus, the study of geography involves unravelling the unique and
the general: ‘the fact of uneven development and of interdependent systems of dominance and
subordination between regions on the one hand, and the specificity of place on the other’ (p. 9) is
thus a central concern for the discipline.
Massey illustrated her general contention by a number of case studies in Spatial Divisions of Labour
and provided others in an essay on women in the labour force (McDowell and Massey, 1984; see
also Damaris Rose, 1987). Her work was also instrumental in the establishment of a major research
programme (financed by the UK’s Economic and Social Research Council), into the Changing
Urban and Regional System (CURS); this was introduced by its coordinator (Cooke, 1986) and
Radical geography 213

summarised in a volume that reported on the programme’s seven case studies (Cooke, 1989a).
The substantive focus was the spatially varying processes of economic restructuring taking place in
the UK during the 1980s. Thus,

The overall objectives of the programme were to explore the impact of economic restructuring
at national and local levels, and to assess the role of central and local government policies in
enabling or constraining localities, through their various social and political organizations, to
deal with processes of restructuring.
(Cooke, 1989a, p. ix)

In addition:

an important dimension of the research involved seeking to establish the conceptual ­status of
the idea of ‘locality’ by taking account of a wide range of social scientific theory and research.

The concept of locality was chosen after both the traditional terms ‘community’ and ‘locale’
were rejected:

There is a gap in the social science literature when it comes to a concept dealing with the sphere
of social activity that is focused upon place, that is not only reactive or inward-looking with
regard to place, and that is not limited in its scope by a primary stress on stability and continuity.
(Cooke, 1989a, p. 10)

Locale was rejected because its spatial scope is vague; it suggests a passive rather than an
active context for action and lacks any specific social meaning. (Giddens, 1984, defined a locale as
a ‘setting for interaction’, which implies a spatial component but no more; a virtual site could be
described as a locale with that definition.) A locality, on the other hand, is ‘the space within which
the larger part of most citizens’ daily working and consuming lives is lived’ (Cooke, 1989a, p. 12)
and in which their citizenship rights are defined. Citizenship, according to recent debates, involves
individuals having obligations to their community (via the state) as well as entitlements from it – or
duties as well as rights (Smith, 1989; see also Bennett, 1989b). The contest over rights and duties
is fought out in places, at a variety of scales; their nature involves ‘the construction of an identity
complete with a package of known rights and obligations related, which posits residence in a
definable place or (commonly quite sizeable) territory as the basis for the nurturing and preservation
of this identity’ (Painter and Philo, 1995, p. 111). We become what we are because of where we are
and the categories used in the structuring of civil society there (and we are implicated in those local
struggles over our rights, obligations and identities).
At the end of his summary volume on the localities project, Philip Cooke argued that the seven
case studies sustained his earlier contention regarding the crucial role of localities in the restructuring
process and in the creation and recreation of uneven development; they illustrate

the argument that the relationship between the different scales is not simply a one-way street
with localities the mere recipients of fortune or fate from above. Rather localities are actively
involved in their own transformation, though not necessarily as masters of their own destiny.
Localities are not simply places or even communities: they are the sum of social energy and
agency resulting from the clustering of diverse individuals, groups and social interests in space.
They are not passive or residual but, in varying ways and degrees, centres of collective
consciousness. They are bases for intervention in the internal workings of not only individual and
collective daily lives but also events on a broader canvas as affecting local interests.
( Cooke, 1989a, p. 296)
214 Radical geography

This conclusion, and the path towards it, however, became the subject of considerable debate, much
of it unfavourable on conceptual grounds because what is necessarily local, and what is contingently
so, has not been defined (Cox and Mair, 1989).
One of the initial critiques was Neil Smith’s (1987b) argument that the CURS programme as
formulated was likely to be submerged in a morass of statistical information; it contained within
itself the potential for producing no more than those earlier empiricist studies, ‘which deliberately
examined individual places for their own sake, and [did] not attempt to draw out theoretical or
historical conclusions’ (p. 62; see also Jonas, 1988). He was also concerned about the vagueness of
the spatial scale in defining localities, but welcomed the attempt to blend theoretical analysis with
local understanding. (As discussed in the next chapter, the nature of scale, as a social construction,
has been extensively explored by geographers: see Cox, 2014, chapter 5, for example.) Philip
Cooke (1987) refuted the charge of empiricism, arguing that the objective of the CURS initiative
was ‘theorised interrogation’ (p. 75) of available data. His general position was supported by Urry,
who initially argued that ‘there are some significant locality-specific processes’ (Urry, 1986,
p. 239), which he followed with a list of ten different ways in which social scientists have addressed
them (Urry, 1987; see also Urry, 1985).
Cochrane (1987, p. 355) wondered whether CURS was ‘just a cover for structural Marxism
with a human face, or . . . the cover for a return to empiricism with a theoretically sophisticated
face’, and concluded that the programme contained the danger that as a guide to political action it
might suggest that local struggle could suffice (what he termed ‘micro-structuralism’) rather than
the realisation that parts cannot readily be isolated from wholes. Gregson (1987a) was perhaps even
less sanguine, arguing that the theoretical rationale for the seven case studies was far from clear,
thus making the likelihood of falling into the empiricist trap high; without a properly articulated
theoretical core ‘CURS simply replicates the mistakes of previous local studies; with such a core it
could be so much more’ (p. 370). Beauregard (1988) claimed that the programme lacked any clear
directions for practice, for using the radical theory to achieve social change.
Simon Duncan’s (1989b) full critique accepted that the concept refers to something important
– spatial variability and specificity – but he concluded that ‘the locality concept is misleading and
unsupported’ (p. 247; he concluded elsewhere – Duncan and Savage, 1989, pp. 202–4 – that it is
‘confused, unsatisfactory, and largely redundant . . . a mystification’). He accepted that ‘space makes
a difference’ in three ways:

1 social processes are constituted in places, which may differ because of previous ‘layers of
investment’ (to use Massey’s term);
2 actions take place locally and so can vary spatially; and
3 spatially varying actions can create spatially varying contexts.

But the concept of locality implies ‘social autonomy and spatial determinism’ (p. 247), both of
which he rejects. He is not convinced that local differences are very important in creating uneven
development, relative to more general processes: ‘Locality is . . . only important if and when locality
effects are part of the causal group explaining any event. And locality may well not be important’,
which implies a verdict of ‘not proven’ (p. 248).
Philip Cooke’s (1989b) response to these critiques (and to the Duncan and Savage paper in
particular) was trenchant:

Local social processes are clearly an abiding feature of contemporary social life. Duncan and
Savage’s injunction to ignore them and settle on the structural level, supra-local, supra-national
or whatever, in order to describe spatial variation in terms which deny agency to the social
groups comprising localities, is both dated and redundant.
(p. 272)
Radical geography 215

And he concluded that: ‘“Locality” can be seen to be a fascinating, complex concept of considerable
value to geographical theory and empirical research.’
Griffiths and Johnston (1991) outlined a clearer framework for studying how localities differ,
using three components of local economic, social and political structures drawn from their study
of responses to the 1984–5 National Union of Mineworkers’ strike in the UK. Johnston (1991) later
applied this framework to a range of studies of uneven development at a number of scales, including
the southern USA.
The debate over ‘localities’ was part of a much wider range of work which addressed the role
of place in the creation of social scientific understanding. Agnew and Duncan (1989), for example,
opened their introduction to The Power of Place with the statement that the book is:

an attempt to make the case for the intellectual importance of geographical place in the practice
of social science and history . . . [through] bringing together what can be called the geographical
and sociological ‘imaginations’.
(p. 1)

Agnew (1989) analysed why place had been devalued in ‘orthodox social science’ in recent decades,
focusing on the confusion of place with community (itself a term with many definitions: Colin Bell
and Howard Newby, 1976). The orthodox treatment identifies a decline in community with
‘modernization’ and its replacement by a ‘placeless’ society, a transition seen as ‘natural, lawful, and
universal’ (Agnew, 1989, p. 16), with nationalism growing as a ‘place-transcending ideology’.
Similarly, the alternative view derived from Marxism devalued place with its emphasis on ‘freeing
people from places’ (p. 22; Entrikin, 1989, provides a parallel, elegant argument). The goal of The
Power of Place is to correct those tendencies, and, through both theoretical argument and empirical
illustration, ‘argue against the prevalent tendency in history and social science to overvalue the
sociological imagination at the expense of the geographical’ (Agnew, 1989, p. 7; see also Agnew,
1990). He adduced five reasons for a place perspective (Agnew, 1987a):

1 it allows abstract categories – such as class – to be analysed in the context of everyday


situations;
2 it avoids the search for ‘universal’ laws;
3 it allows a focus on structure–agency interrelations;
4 it shows that societies in different places change at different rates and along different trajectories,
thereby removing any tendency to identify ‘historical stages’ to which all should conform; and
5 it illustrates the operation of cultural agents acting outside economic determinism.

A ‘new regional geography’?


The debate over locality research became part of a wider literature on the importance of studying
the specific characteristics of places. The numerous works using an implicit contextual approach
include Agnew’s (1984, 1987a) argument that voting behaviour is strongly influenced by the
electorate’s local context (see also Johnston, 1986d; Johnston and Pattie, 2006) and a detailed
analysis of variations between local states in their provision of public housing (Dickens et al., 1985).
Some translated this general concern into a plea for a revived, but restructured, regional geography.
Massey (1984b, p. 10), for example, ended such a plea with the argument that it is:

necessary to reassert the existence, the explicability, and the significance, of the particular.
What we [must do] . . . is take up again the challenge of the old regional geography, reject the
answers it gave while recognizing the importance of the problem it set.
(p. 10)
216 Radical geography

This echoes Gregory’s (1978a) contention that:

Ever since regional geography was declared to be dead . . . geographers, to their credit, have kept
trying to revive it in one form or another . . . This is a vital task . . . we need to know about the consti-
tution of regional social formations, of regional articulations and regional structures . . . [producing]
a doubly human geography: human in the sense that it recognizes that its concepts are specifically
human constructions, rooted in specific social formations, and capable of – demanding of – continual
examination and criticism; and human in the sense that it restores human beings to their own worlds
and enables them to take part in the collective transformation of their own human geographies.
(pp. 171–2)

This call was not immediately taken up, although Fleming (1973), Steel (1982) and Hart (1982a)
all called for a revival of traditional regional geography, which to Hart meant ‘producing good
regional geography – evocative descriptions that facilitate an understanding and an appreciation of
places, areas and regions’ (p. 2; as an example of such work – what might best be termed regional
landscape history – see Haggett, 2012). Some have followed Gregory’s lead (see also Gregory,
1985b), however, and argued – as do Roger Lee (1984, 1985) and Johnston (1984d, 1985c,
1985d) – for a reconstituted regional geography which recognises (Lee, 1985) that:

1 social processes operate in historically and geographically specific circumstances, so their


understanding requires a sensitivity to geographical variations (regional mosaics);
2 society is not a fixed phenomenon but something that is constantly being recreated by human
actions. Since those actions occur in historically and geographically specific contexts, then
societal recreation is similarly historically and geographically variable;
3 those local transformations occur in the context of wider social relationships; and
4 the regions that emerge are not fixed divisions of territory but changing social constructions.

A major goal of geography should be to uncover the nature of those regions, as illustrated by some
of the essays in Johnston et al. (1990).
The emphasis on change in these arguments implies the absence of a distinct niche for
historical geography within the discipline’s overall programme. The claim that a major route to
understanding the present lies in study of the past is not new, but adoption of approaches based on
structuration and contextual theory clarifies the importance of an historical perspective. Not
surprisingly, therefore, historical geographers have made major contributions to the debates (see
Baker and Gregory, 1984), drawing on such sources as the writings of the French Annales school of
history (Baker, 1984; Pred, 1984c, draws on Braudel, for example). Thus, interpretations of the
long-term evolution of a society (e.g. Dunford and Perrons, 1983) and its regional components
(Langton, 1984), of basic transformations in a region, whether industrial (e.g. Gregory, 1982a) or
agricultural (Pred, 1985, 1986), and of the constitution of particular places (as in Harvey’s, 1985c
detailed analysis of nineteenth-century Paris as an example of how consciousness is created in a
particular context) all illustrate how changes take place as the result of general tendencies being
played out in specific milieux by particular human agents. (Not all historical geographers agreed,
however: see Meinig, 1978, especially p. 1215, and Dodgshon, 1998.)
The differences between the ‘new’ and the ‘traditional’ approaches to regional geography are
clarified by Pudup (1988, p. 374), who characterised the latter as empiricist:

Theoretically neutral observations are the basis for areal description. A reconstructed regional
geography has founda­tions that rest in a clarified status of regions as objects of study – put
simply, why geographers bother to study regions in the first place.
(p. 379)
Radical geography 217

The answers to that ‘Why?’ question are provided in works such as Pred’s (1984c) on southern
Sweden and Gregory’s (1982a) on West Yorkshire: regions are (not necessarily formally bounded)
territorial entities, produced, reproduced and transformed through human agency; regions are the
places in which people learn a culture, and contribute to its continuation (what Thrift, 1983,
after Giddens, calls ‘settings for interaction’). The nature of those processes is appreciated through
a theorized approach, with the appreciation being provided through a narrative that draws on a
defined vocabulary and permits ‘theory to speak through subsequent empirical accounts’ (Pudup,
1988, p. 383; see also Sayer, 1989a, 1989b). What those empirical accounts should focus on is still
debated, and the need for a subdiscipline called regional geography has been contested. Warf
(1988, p. 57) contended that with the replacement of traditional regional geography by positivism,
‘a geography of “regions without theories” quickly became a geography of “theories without
regions” ’, but Johnston (1990a, p. 139) argued that whereas ‘we do not need regional geography
. . . we do need regions in geography’.
Pudup’s characterisation of the ‘new’ regional geography was extended by Anne Gilbert
(1988), who identified three separate concerns with regional specificity in recent writings:

1 a concern with regions as local responses to capitalist processes, which she identified as
probably the most prominent among English-speaking writers, who set the study of local
variations within a political economy (usually Marxist) framework;
2 a concern with the region as a focus of identification (or ‘sense of place’), which is especially
strong among French writers concerned with the analysis of culture. To them, appropriation
of a place (or region) is part of the creation and recreation of cultural identity; and
3 a concern with the region as a medium for social interaction, playing ‘a basic role in the
production and reproduction of social relations’ (p. 212). The work on ‘localities’ fits within
this concern.

All three represent a break from ‘traditional’ regional geography, Gilbert claimed, through their
recognition that the persistence of regional diversity in the face of the homogenising tendencies
within capitalism provides regional geography with a practical significance, in the mobilisation of
resistance to those tendencies (see also Peet, 1989). The ‘new’ work depends on structuralist theory
(as illustrated in Agnew’s, 1987b, book on the USA within the capitalist world economy); on the
recognition that regional processes rely on dialectical rather than naturalistic theories; and on
the importance of human agency in the creation, recreation and transformation of regions. Together,
these suggest a mode of study committed to understanding and achieving social change, which
provides the challenge of making ‘geography a science useful for society’ (Gilbert, 1988, p. 223).
Subsequently, as already noted, regulationist work has also informed accounts of regions and
regional configurations of governance and accumulation (e.g. MacLeod, 1998; MacLeod and
Goodwin, 1999), as well as making what Kevin Ward (2001, p. 130) terms ‘a substantial contribution
to the study of urban politics’. Both strands of work, on regions and on urban localities, have been
informed by (and blended with) social, cultural and political geographies, and wider social and
political theory (e.g. Murphy, 1991; Paasi, 1991; Thrift, 1990, 1991, 1993, 1994). Thus, according
to MacLeod and Jones (2001):

geographers were encouraged to embrace elements of social theory, sociology, anthropology, and
political economy in order to transcend the purported limitations of an earlier regional geography,
not least its emphasis on the natural environment as the key factor in establishing the regional
shape of society . . . for the new regional geographers, amid a range of rapid economic and political
restructuring, regions were being presented as arenas through which to view the movements and
dramas of individuals and groups in a whole series of economic, political and cultural contexts.
(p. 671)
218 Radical geography

Noting how regional autonomy and devolution movements in many countries (especially in
the European Union) had fostered much discussion of regions and regionalism since the 1970s,
MacKinnon (2009, p. 233) also charts geographers’ reworking of ‘their regionalist heritage’
drawing on the insights of political economy and subsequent strands of thought (including those
considered in Chapter 7) ‘has fostered a new concern with “the relational region” which reimagines
regions as open and discontinuous spaces, defined by the wider social relations in which they are
situated’. MacKinnon (2009, p. 233) cites work on southeast England (Allen et al., 1998):
the emblematic growth region of neoliberal Britain in the 1980s and 1990s, defined by its close con-
nections to the global economy through the City of London in particular. Within the South East, areas
of economic decline and deprivation exist, complicating and confounding the overarching image of
growth and prosperity, while the boundaries of the region can be seen as open and porous (see
Figure 6.2).

Global financial markets Tokyo

International labour markets

Branch outlets (foreign banks)

Decentralisation of branch offices

Miles 50
0 Kilometres 80

New York

Europe

Figure 6.2  International financial links of South East England

Source: Allen et al. (1998) Rethinking the Region, p. 49, reprinted in MacKinnon (2009, p. 233).
Radical geography 219

The relationships between territorial, place bound and relational, networked conceptions of regions
continue to offer fruitful grounds for investigation (Jonas, 2012).

Critical realism and structuration theory


Marxism has long been interested in exploring different levels of analysis and relations; between
economy and culture, for example, or between production and reproduction as well as between
different scales and places – classically the contrast between the ‘country and the city’, but also
between ‘core’ and ‘periphery’, and the spatial and temporal dynamics of growth and decline.
While Marxism has a materialist base, arguing that the basic underpinning of society comprises a
set of economic processes and behaviours, these may only be reproduced through social, cultural
and political processes, and in turn those also become aspects of what Marxists characterise as the
means and forces of production. Debates about the relations between these and their ‘relative
autonomy’ have long characterised Marxist thought. Later – in the 1990s and since – regulation
theory has promised geographers a path through these.
In the 1980s, however, human geographers also explored two approaches which claimed to
offer advances in the way that structure and agency (and the role of space) could be conceptualised.
The first of these, the philosophy of realism, is based on the separation of three domains (Bhaskar,
1978):

1 the domain of the empirical is concerned solely with experiences, with the world as it is
perceived;
2 the domain of the actual is concerned with events as well as experiences, accepting that an
event (a particular item of human behaviour, for example) may be interpreted in different
ways by individuals (by the actor, perhaps, and by another person experiencing it); and
3 the domain of the real is concerned with structures that cannot be apprehended directly, but
which contain the mechanisms that lead to the events and their empirical perception.

Realists argue that all science incorporates these three domains, but the natural and the social
sciences differ in the type of mechanism with which they deal. In particular, natural science deals
with ‘closed systems’ in which the same interrelationships can be observed on innumerable
occasions, allowing the development of universal laws based on replicable results. Social science
rarely if ever deals with such closed systems, however, both because of the difficulties of abstracting
independent parts from the whole (most attempts to do this produce what Sayer, 1985a, terms
‘chaotic conceptions’) and because major components of the system – people – learn from their
experiences, so that experiments can never be replicated.
The goal of realism, like that of positivism, is to explain events, to discover their causes by
‘finding out what produces change, what makes things happen, what allows or forces change’
(Sayer, 1985a, p. 163). It differs from positivism because it contends that ‘what causes something
to happen has nothing to do with the matter of the number of times it has happened or been
observed to happen and hence with whether it causes a regularity’ (p. 162). Indeed, ‘regularities’
(i.e. laws and lawlike generalisations) are very unlikely to occur in the social sciences. Andrew Sayer
(1984, 1992a) argues that two conditions are necessary if regularities are to occur:

1 the mechanisms must be invariant; and


2 the relationships between the mechanisms and the conditions in which they occur must be
constant.

If both hold, then scientists will be studying closed systems, with identical conditions leading to
identical events (either naturally or in laboratory conditions). If one or both is absent, however, the
220 Radical geography

object of study is an open system, and regularities will then not occur. The social sciences study
open systems:

we can interpret the same material conditions and statements in different ways and hence learn
new ways of responding, so that effectively we become different kinds of people. Human actions
characteristically modify the configuration of systems, thereby violating the . . . [first] condition
. . . while our capacity for learning and self-change violates the . . . [second] condition.
(Sayer, 1992a, p. 123)

The mechanisms underpinning the operations of human societies are interpreted in different ways,
therefore, with the outcomes of those interpretations creating new sets of conditions within which
future interpretations will be constrained. The mechanisms are abstract concepts which are
actualised in contingently related conditions, as for example with:

the law of value, which concerns mechanisms which are possessed necessarily by capital by
virtue of its structure (as consisting of competing and independently directed capitals, each
producing for profit and being reliant on the production of surplus value, etc.), produces effects
which are mediated by such things as the particular kinds of technology available, the relative
power of capital and labour and state intervention. (p. 140). [.] Now no theory of society could be
expected to know the nature and form of these contingencies in advance, purely on the basis of
theoretical claims.
(p. 142)

A major issue for those adopting a realist approach concerned the role of space is: does it, as
raised by the title of Sayer’s (1985b) essay, ‘make a difference’? In realist terms that question can be
pitched at the level of either the necessary or the contingent – is space important in theoretical
work, or only in concrete realisations of the outcome of general processes? Regarding the former,
he noted that ‘Abstract social theory need only consider space insofar as necessary properties of
objects are involved, and this does not amount to very much’ (p. 54). All matter has a spatial
location, so all events occur in space but, while recognising this, abstract theory need say very little
about actual spatial forms. ‘Hence, while it is important for abstract theory to be aware of the
existence of space, the claims that can be made about it are inevitably rather indifferent ones’ and
refer to concrete realisations only. He concludes that to claim that space is contingent in its operation
does not mean that it is unimportant: ‘The difference that space makes in concrete situations can
never be ignored, and therefore in that sense “geography matters” ’ (p. 109).
The study of causation in a realist context involves what Sayer and Morgan (1985) term
intensive research programmes, whose questions take the form ‘What did the agents actually do?’;
answering them involves examining causal processes in a particular case or group of cases. The
answers cannot be generalised beyond those cases, in contrast to those produced in extensive
research programmes, commonly adopted in empiricist/positivist human geography, which are
‘mainly concerned with discovering some of the common properties and general patterns in a
population as a whole’ (p. 150). It is evident that realism enabled and inspired some rich empirical
research in human geography. It is not hard to discern why many were attracted to the mixture of
critical potential and rigour that it claimed to offer. Reviewing this, Pratt (2009, p. 381) notes how:

Critical realism has had a significant impact in the discipline of geography, and in particular it
offered a resolution of the disenchantment with positivism, especially – although not exclusively
– within human geography, heralding an approach that, it is claimed, avoids the perceived
shortcomings of subjectivism (as in the humanistic or phenomenological geography . . . ).
(p. 381)
Radical geography 221

A second path, which some geographers advocated in the 1980s as an overall framework to
research and as a means to explore the constitutive role of space in social life, was structuration – a
theoretical approach first developed by Giddens (1984) to account for the ways in which
people learn about and transform social structures. This is a place-bound (and time-bound)
process; one’s context (including one’s language: see p. 376–7, this book) and a major influence on
one’s individual development. For exegeses and applications by geographers, see Moos and Dear
(1986); Dear and Moos (1986); Phipps (2001).
Structuration, as an example of a contextual approach, clarifies the falseness of any distinction
between social relations and spatial structures; as Gregory and Urry (1985, p. 3) express it, ‘spatial
structure is now seen not merely as an arena in which social life unfolds, but rather as a medium
through which social relations are produced and reproduced’. Together they produce the process
of spatiality (or socio-spatial dialectic), used by Soja (1980, 1985) to characterise the
conjoint social production of space and the spatial construction of society. Giddens and
others identify much common ground between his conception of structuration and Hägerstrand’s
of time geography (though see Gregson, 1986, 1987b). Pred used the two in a number of essays
to illustrate their relevance to understanding both the unfolding of his own career (Pred, 1979,
1984a) and the development of particular places (Pred, 1984b, 1984c). Thus:

The meanings of interpretations I have imposed upon the past, the there and then in Berkeley
and Sweden, are a result of the knowledge, attitudes and values I hold now, the ever fading here
and now in Berkeley. Yet, the knowledge, attitudes and values I hold here and now are rooted in
my past path, my past participation in projects and the institutional and societal context which
generated those projects.
(Pred, 1984a, p. 101)

Also, ‘Biographies are formed through the becoming of places, and places become through the
formation of biographies’ (Pred, 1984b, p. 258).
In the end, relatively few geographers adopted structuration as a research methodology,
although, as we have noted, it did appear promising. Derek Gregory (1994, p. 113) judged that ‘its
philosophical and theoretical rigor dovetailed with the sensibilities that had been put in place by
spatial science, by a number of post-positivist geographies, and by the development of historico-
geographical materialism’. Hence, Cloke et al.’s (1991) text contained an entire chapter on
structuration theory, juxtaposed to the one on realism, and Phipps (2001) subsequently explored
structuration theory’s empirical applications. All adopted the basic argument – derived from
Marx – that people make and remake themselves in the places that they make and remake.

The production of ‘nature’


The holistic conception of relations and dynamics in Marxist thought has also lent itself to work on
one of the oldest of concerns in geography – human–environment relations. Marxist work on
uneven development thus includes work on the relationships between society and nature. Liberal
concerns over environmental issues had increased substantially during the late 1960s and early
1970s. Harvey (1974d) introduced a Marxist perspective to this issue, arguing that contemporary
statements on resource–population ratios are ideologically based, an argument sustained through
examination of the works of Malthus (Mayhew, 2014), Marx and Ricardo. Resources are not defined
outside the context of societal appraisals of nature, and those appraisals reflect the current mode of
production. Thus, predictions such as those of the Limits to Growth study (p. 328, this book) represent
a status quo theoretical perspective (p. 316, this book), whereas employment of other perspectives
may lead to different conclusions:
222 Radical geography

let us consider a simple sentence: ‘Overpopulation arises because of the scarcity of resources
available for meeting the subsistence needs of the mass of the population.’ If we substitute our
definitions [of subsistence, resources and scarcity] into this sentence we get: There are too many
people in the world because the particular ends we have in view (together with the form of social
organisation we have) and the materials available in nature, that we have the will and the way to
use, are not sufficient to provide us with those things to which we are accustomed.
(Harvey, 1974d, p. 272)

With the first version of the sentence, the policy option seems clear – population reduction.
The second allows Harvey to identify three possibilities, however: (1) changing both the desired
end and the social organization; (2) changing technical and cultural appraisals of nature; and
(3) changing views about the capitalist system and its scarcity basis. The Ehrlich–Commoner
arguments regarding the origins of current environmental problems accept the first version of the
sentence, however, and Harvey claimed that they have been grasped by the elite of the capitalist
world to provide an underpinning for a popular ideology (the need for birth control). Similarly,
Keith Buchanan (1973) argued that the arguments for birth control in the Third World are part of
the ‘white north’s’ imperialist policy of ensuring its continued access to the resources of the
international periphery (even to the extent of stimulating environmental destruction and famine:
Bradley, 1986; Blaikie, 1986), and Johnston et al. (1987) have explored the geography of what
Buchanan (1973, p. 9), along with other peace scientists, terms structural poverty: ‘The poverty
which is regarded as symptomatic of reckless population growth is rather a structural poverty
caused by the irresponsible squandering of world resources by a small handful of nations’.
Under capitalism, the environment (or nature) is treated as a commodity, to be bought,
exploited and sold. Neil Smith (1984) points out that nature is presented in capitalism’s ideology
as external to society, as the ‘antithesis of human productivity . . . the realm of use-values rather than
exchange values’ (p. 32). But a ‘second nature’ is produced by capitalism:

In its uncontrolled drive for universality, capitalism creates new barriers to its own future, it
creates a society of needed resources, impoverishes the quality of those resources not
yet devoured, breeds new diseases, develops a nuclear technology that threatens the future
of all humanity, pollutes the entire environment that we must consume in order to reproduce,
and in the daily work process it threatens the very existence of those who produce the vital
social wealth.
(p. 59)

Nature, like spatial organization and reorganization, becomes a product of the continuing processes
of capitalist accumulation (Fitzsimmons, 1989); as an abstract concept it is of no value to society
and it is of interest only as a sphere of human activity (Pepper, 1984, 1996). This representation of
nature as a social construction is not new: Zimmerman’s (1972) classic work on natural resources
defined a resource as only existing when it was perceived as such, and Glacken’s (1967) classic
survey shows how cultural conceptions of nature have varied over centuries. In his adaptation,
however, David Pepper (1984) separates the ‘historicity of nature’ (how the concept of nature in a
particular time and place is related to the human activities there) from the ‘naturalness of history’
(the relationship between natural conditions and human activity – a relationship crudely expressed
in theories of environmental determinism, p. 43, this book). Part of the creation of a society involves
its historicity of nature:

Labour is the means whereby man converts nature into forms useful to him. In the main nature
does not offer ready-made subsistence to man, neither does man take direct possession of
nature’s resources. He has to transform them. This process of transformation is a social one – it
Radical geography 223

is done with other people who are organized in a particular way. . . . Thus through shaping
nature, men shape their own society and their relations with their fellows.
(p. 162)

Thus, just as the creation of social relations (the means of exploiting surplus value from labour by
capital) is part of the making of a society, so too is the creation of society–nature interrelations; and
just as those social relations contain within them the seeds of crisis for capital accumulation
(the class conflict) so too do society–nature interrelations (environmental problems). Johnston
(1989, 1996d) has carried this argument forward in an account of society–nature relationships
under various modes of production and of the role of the state in their regulation (see also Taylor,
1994); the essays in Blaikie and Brookfield (1987) illustrate the general theme.
Harvey’s (1974d) early Marxist work on ideology, social and economic life, and their complex
interrelationships with nature, has since been extended by others into a holistic conception of the
social mediation of nature and the inevitability and necessity of (geographically) uneven
development under capitalism (e.g. Braun and Castree, 1998; Castree, 1995b, 2003; Castree and
Braun, 2001; Peet and Watts, 1996; Smith, 1984) and the possibility of ‘liberation ecologies’ (Peet
and Watts, 2004) and political ecology’s wider connections with geopolitics, power and domination
(Peet et al., 2011). Recognising the wealth of work on ‘nature’, Andrew Jones’s (2009, p. 474)
review of the trajectory of Marxist geography notes that while it also influenced development
geography (Peet, 1991), political geography (Taylor, 1982) and urban geography (Smith, 1996):

The fourth and final strand of a revised Marxian human geography that has generated an
identifiable literature can be loosely described as a revised eco-Marxist human geography. . . .
Much of this thought has drawn on a burgeoning eco-Marxist literature beyond human geography,
although it has also developed the Marxian perspectives on the production of nature developed
by Neil Smith and others in the 1980s. More recent contributions represent a form of revised
Marxist geography insofar as they have increasingly sought to engage with postmodern
epistemological arguments concerning society/nature and new forms of politics. Such eco-
Marxist human geography has been concerned, for example, with debates about environmental
political movements, the rights of indigenous groups in the developing world, and environmental
values.

In turn, similar relationships between nature, production, ideology and power were also
problematised in Marxist-influenced work on ‘landscapes’. Stephen Daniels (1989) thus stressed
how conceptions of landscape were rooted in reactions to Western capitalist society (see the review
by Cosgrove, 2003). Building on this, but in a more direct line to Marx, Don Mitchell (2003,
p. 238) notes that ‘the landscape can be understood to be a product of human labor, of people
going to work on the land to make some thing out of it’. Thus:

To understand landscape, and to understand the ‘culture’ within which it exists, requires an
examination of human practices – of forms of labor. Through labor the landscape is both made and
made known. And in the process of working on and in landscape so too are people changed, whether
that change is understood at the level of culture . . . or at the level of the individual human body . . .
(p. 239)

Radicals in debate
The ‘radical camp’ was never a united body of scholars. Although Marxism remained a focus, it was
attacked by others, themselves associated with ‘radical’ stances. In 1986, for example, Peter Saunders
224 Radical geography

and Peter Williams equated the recent literature in urban studies with an unchallenged ‘taken for
granted orthodoxy . . . [that] thrives on an unspoken and largely unexamined political and
theoretical consensus’ (p. 393). They claimed that this has opposition to positivism as its linchpin,
and arguments within it occupy ‘a very narrow spectrum embracing left Weberianism and the
different varieties of Marxism, but excluding almost everything else’. They concluded that, as a
consequence, urban studies currently:

makes little pretence of being ‘value-free’ or ‘ethically neutral’ and . . . is sheltered from the
possibility of empirical disconfirmation. This in turn means that approaches (such as the
philosophy of the so-called ‘New Right’) which cannot be subsumed under the orthodoxy can be
dismissed almost a priori. Such work is rarely read, still less seriously considered on its own
terms. Rather a pejorative label is attached to it (for example, ‘Thatcherism’, ‘Reaganism’, or
‘authoritarian populism’) which enables us to pigeonhole it within our existing conceptual
apparatus . . . without ever having to engage with its intellectual content. In this way alternative
ideas are dismissed but never discussed, explained away but never critically evaluated.
(pp. 393–4)

Elements of both Marxism and realism were then criticised, with the latter being characterised as a
‘justification for subordinating history to theory’ (p. 394) and the source of ‘causes which
can only be identified theoretically and which are guaranteed immunity from falsification even
where there is no manifest evidence for their existence’ (p. 395); works which are explicitly
anti-positivist are therefore castigated for not being subjected to positivist and critical rationalist
procedures.
According to this critique, theories of structures have primacy in realist and Marxist approaches
and as such are outdated; some major changes (such a changing gender relations and reconfigurations
of culture, ‘race’ and identity) in British society over the last century are ignored, it is claimed – ‘we
still employ an essentially outdated class theory in our analyses’ (p. 397) – and these approaches are
also criticised as:

having done little or nothing to change the essential features of capitalism. As social change
takes place under our noses, so we risk a situation where our methods and theories ensure that
we pay it little heed. The orthodoxy is safeguarded and reproduced as the society changes.

One of the strongest continuing adherents to a Marxist position, and a major focus of the
Saunders–Williams critique, is Harvey, who characterised the goal of ‘my academic concerns these
last two decades . . . [as] to unravel the role of urbanisation in social change, in particular under
conditions of capi­talist social relations and accumulation’ (Harvey, 1989b, p. 3). He responded to
Saunders and Williams by noting ‘a marked strategic withdrawal from Marxian theory within the
field of urban analysis and a broadening reluctance to make explicit use of Marx’s conceptual
apparatus in articulating arguments’ (Harvey, 1987, p. 367), and launched an attack against those
he identified as abandoning the ‘tough rigour of dialectical theorizing and historical materialist
analysis’, because:

The case for retiring Marx’s Capital to the shelves of some antiquarian bookstore . . . is not yet
there. Indeed, in many respects the time has never been more appropriate for the application of
Marx’s conceptual apparatus to understanding processes of capitalist development and
transformation. Furthermore, I believe the claim of Marxian analysis to provide the surest guide
to the construction of radical theory and radicalizing practices still stands.

His critics had caved in too readily to right-wing pressures, he argued.


Radical geography 225

Harvey (1987, p. 368) agreed with Saunders and Williams that realism and the concept-
ualisation of agency and structure ‘are nothing more than weak disguises, soft versions of a
traditional left orthodoxy ranging from left Weberianism to “different varieties of Marxism”’. But
he disagreed with their identified way forward. He claimed that three ‘myths’ have pervaded the
critique of Marxist scholarship. The first is economism, as illustrated by James Duncan and David
Ley’s critique (1982). The second is the claim that ‘The abstractions of Marxian theory cannot
explain the specificities of history and the particularities of geography’ (p. 370), to which he took
great exception. Harvey believes that ‘it is in principle possible to apply theoretical laws to under-
stand individual instances, unique events’ (p. 371), particularly since Marx’s most interesting
lawlike statements were about capitalist processes, not events. He illustrated this with the chapter in
Capital on ‘The working day’, arguing that such a detailed empirical description of how humans
respond to their conditions on a daily basis allow ‘categories like money, profit, daily wage, labour
time, the working day, and ultimately value and surplus value [to] arise through an examination of
historical materials’ (p. 372), thereby illustrating how theory is both derived from and developed
through the unravelling of particular situations.
Harvey saw the second myth being advanced from ‘within the ranks of the left itself’ (p. 373);
Massey and Sayer’s ‘very deep and serious concerns for the particularities of places, events and
processes’ were noted. Sayer’s realist approach was presented as involving a combination of
‘wide-ranging contingency with an understanding of general processes’, however:

The problem with this superficially attractive method is that there is nothing within it, apart from
the judgement of individual researchers, as to what constitutes a special instance to which special
processes inhere or as to what contingencies (out of a potentially infinite number) ought to be
taken seriously. There is nothing, in short, to guard against the collapse of scientific understandings
into a mass of contingencies exhibiting relations and processes special to each unique event.
(Harvey, 1987, p. 373)

This, Harvey feared, is a path to ‘simple empiricism’ (p. 374), which he believed Saunders and
Williams (1986) were also promoting; he characterised their agenda as ‘nothing short of an
abrogation of scientific responsibility and a caving in of political will’. Against that, Harvey insisted
on ‘the viability of the Marxist project’, with its focus on ‘universalising statements and abstractions’
(p. 375) and its ability to guide political practice.
Finally, the third myth (the ‘never-never land of nontotalising discourses into which
Marxists cannot enter because they insist on talking about totalities’, p. 374) was presented as an
attack on ‘totalizing discourses’, meta-theories and meta-narratives. While rejecting the notion that
Marxism is ‘inherently totalizing’, Harvey nevertheless argued that ‘nothing appears more totalizing
to me than the penetration of capitalist social relations and the commodity calculus into every niche
and cranny of contemporary life’. If social theory can look only at the parts, then the whole can
never be apprehended and challenged (part of Harvey’s argument against postmodernism: see
Chapter 7). To Harvey (1987):

every single local study I read . . . points to how locality is caught up in universal processes of
financial flows, international divisions of labour, and the operations of global financial markets.
Claims to the contrary are dangerous, for they involve avoiding confrontations with ‘the realities
of political economy and the circumstances of global power’.
(p. 375)

As Harvey (2002, pp. 184–5) later recorded, he rarely responded to critiques – ‘because it had
always seemed to me that the general stance of opposition to capitalism was best served by making
creative contributions rather than engaging in destructive slanging matches’. But he ‘had been
226 Radical geography

somewhat taken by surprise’ by the feminist critiques (see Chapter 8) of The Condition of Postmodernity
(Harvey, 1989a: cf. Deutsch, 1991; Massey, 1991) and felt he had little option but to reply; this was
published in Antipode (Harvey, 1992) – ‘Nobody took much notice’.
Harvey’s stance was supported by Neil Smith (1987c), who defended Marxism as providing
both a broad analytical framework and a ‘quintessentially political discourse’; he found that the
‘realist project . . . has become the theoretical justification for the belief that there can be no general
theory at all concerning questions of geographical space, and that any attempt to devise such a
theory is fundamentally misconceived’ (p. 379). Others, however, were less supportive; Ball (1987,
p. 393), for example, took issue with Harvey’s:

total dismissal of anyone who does not repeatedly declare their Marxist label, who does not
believe that everything Marx said is unambiguous and correct, and who fails directly to apply the
most abstract propositions of Marxist theory to the empirical situations they are investigating.

Sayer (1987, p. 395) also resented Harvey’s impugning of motives, and responded to both Saunders
and Williams, and Harvey that ‘even if it means breaking off from what I had hoped and still hope
for is a broad but common project, the search for a social science with an emancipatory potential’.
Sayer agreed very much with Harvey that empirical research enables a clarification of theoretical
understanding, it being ‘partly responsible for making me revise my abstract ideas about the nature
of capital, competition, class and the division of labour’ (1987, p. 397; see also Sayer, 1995, 2013).
He also defended realism against the charges of both reductionism and theoreticism (exemplified
by Saunders and Williams) on one hand, and of empiricism (Harvey) on the other.
Saunders and Williams (1987, pp. 427–8) began their response with the following
categorisation:

Harvey eschews fraternization with the enemy, and he adopts a quasi-religious, almost messianic
tone in delivering his epistle. He tells us . . . of his unswerving belief that Marxism provides the
surest guide to radical salvation . . . Harvey’s statement provides a good example of precisely that
tendency in contemporary urban studies which we suggested could stifle fresh initiatives and
hamper intellectual debate. If you believe, as Harvey apparently does, that the eternal verities have
largely been established by Marx’s Capital, then you have effectively closed off the possibility of
open debate, and even more the possibility of learning from others who disagree.

Gould (1988) similarly criticised Marxist writers in general and Harvey in particular for
what he termed their ‘claim to exclusiveness’. Saunders and Williams then attacked Harvey for
sustaining a ‘totalizing’ form of theory, which embraces the whole of society and thus has a
privileged starting-point (or set of initial assumptions) which is not open to empirical refutation/
confirmation:

It is difficult to see how you can get to the whole by studying the parts and building up from
there. . . . Totalising discourses are thus always unalterably committed to a priori assumptions
– Marx’s theories of exploitation, class struggle, and historical evolution came, not from studying
people in Manchester, but from ideas about society ‘as a whole’, and these ideas were then
mapped onto existing empirical observations.
(Saunders and Williams, 1987, pp. 428–9)

Thus, Harvey’s Marxism is not susceptible to effective falsification; nor, they assert, despite
Sayer’s arguments, is realism. Both are presented as ‘closed’ approaches, and although Saunders
and Williams share the same goal as Harvey and Sayer, they believe that ‘you will not develop
an emancipatory social science before social science itself is opened up’ (p. 430). Hence the debate,
Radical geography 227

which the editor argued was necessary because capitalist society is changing; the nature of politics
is altering and ‘social theory has to take account of these cumulative changes’ (Dear, 1987, p. 363).

Liberals, radicals and post-marxists in debate


Alongside debates within the ‘radical’ approach there have been others which, in the published
contributions at least, have been much more heated than that generated by the ‘quantitative
revolution’. They developed in more depth and detail through the 1970s and 1980s, using forums,
such as the journal Area, which were not available 20 years earlier, when publication outlets for
‘views and opinions’ were few. Whereas the behaviourists caused little real concern within the
discipline, and their views were soon co-opted within the corpus of acceptable approaches,
the radicals had much more impact, because they attacked not only the basis of most prior geo-
graphical work but also, in the clear interdisciplinarity of their approach, both the bureaucratic
structure of the discipline and the existence of geography itself (Johnston, 1978a); some, such as
Eliot Hurst (1980, 1985), argued explicitly for the abolition of geography as a separate discipline
(see also Taylor, 1996). A clear early example of the liberal–radical polarisation was a debate on the
geography of crime initiated by Peet (1975b), who argued that in attempting to make their work
relevant geographers avoided asking ‘relevant to whom?’ (on which, see Harvey, 1974c); the poli-
tical consequences of their work were ignored. The studies of crime reviewed (e.g. Harries, 1974)
referred only to the surface manifestations of a social problem and could not provide solutions,
only ways of ameliorating the problems: ‘So it is that “useful” geography comes to be of use only
in preserving the existing order of things by diverting attention away from the deepest causes of
social problems and towards the details of effect’ (Peet, 1975b, p. 277). Furthermore, geographers
study only the crimes for which statistics are collected, thereby accepting the definition of crime by
the elite; their maps, which are useful to police patrols, can therefore be employed to help maintain
the status quo of power relations within society. The implicit position of the geographers involved
is one of protecting the ‘monopoly-capitalist state’.
Harries (1975) responded by attacking the simplistic nature of Peet’s arguments, claiming that
geographers would have no influence at all if they argued merely that crime is a consequence of
monopoly capitalism. He contended that it is best to work within the system, to make the
administration of justice more humane and equitable, to protect the potential victims of crime and
to provide employment opportunities for graduate geographers. Approaches based on crime control
are likely to be more influential than polemics relating its cause to the mode of production: as Yuk
Lee (1975, p. 285) also pointed out, Peet ‘failed to provide us with any clues as to how he or other
radical geographers would study crime’ (p. 285).
Peet (1976) responded to Yuk Lee’s challenge, outlining a radical theory which would
‘contribute directly, through persuasion, to the movement for social revolution’ (p. 97). Capitalism
harnesses human competitive emotions and generates inequalities in material and power rewards.
Aggression is an acceptable part of being competitive and is often released on the lower classes,
who are encouraged to consume but are provided with insufficient purchasing power. As the
contradictions of this paradox increase, so does the pressure to turn to crime. Thus, crime occurs
where the lower classes live, and at their spatial interface with the middle class. Harries (1976)
replied that being a radical was a luxury few academics could afford, because working at a publicly
financed university demanded a pragmatic rather than a revolutionary approach. To him, Peet’s
theory is overly economic and deterministic; it fails to account for cultural elements, such as the
disproportionate criminal involvement of blacks, the subculture of violence in the southern USA
and other areas, and the fact that all economic systems produce minorities disadvantaged in terms
of what they want and what they can get by socially legitimate means. He could offer no alternative
theory, however: ‘I do not carry in my head a theory of crime causation, and I am quite incapable
of synthesizing and attaching value judgements to existing theoretical formulations within a couple
228 Radical geography

of pages of typescript’ (p. 102). He encouraged Peet to come off the fence, and to get involved in
the production of change within the present system. Laurence Wolf (1976), on the other hand,
claimed that by concentrating on the traditional concerns of Marxism, Peet was not radical enough.
Two geographers who were involved in a considerable, often virulent, debate in the 1970s
were Brian Berry and David Harvey. Berry (1972a) initiated the exchanges with comments on
Harvey’s (1972) paper on revolutionary theory and the ghetto. He wondered whether Harvey’s
rational arguments on the need for a revolution would be accepted, ‘because of “commitment”, the
opposition will quietly drift into corners, the world will welcome the new Messiah, and social
change will somehow, magically, transpire’ (p. 32). The power to achieve change, he contended,
needs more than logical argument – ‘nothing less than cudgels has been effective’ (p. 32) – and
Harvey’s belief in logical rationalism will be to no avail. He also argued that Harvey was wrong
about the ghetto, for liberal policies were succeeding and the inequalities between blacks and
whites were being reduced (Berry, 1974a). Harvey (1974a) responded that scarcity must continue
in a capitalist economy, which will leave some people – probably those in the inner city – relatively
disadvantaged. (One of the consequences of recent neoliberal economic policies and the ‘rolling
back of the welfare state’ has been the rapid increase of inequality within most countries of the
‘developed world’ over the last three decades, as illustrated in several atlases and other geographical
works: Glasmeier, 2005; Dorling, 2010.)
Berry’s (1974b) review of Social Justice and the City (Harvey, 1973) criticised Harvey’s dependence
on economic explanations. Based on Daniel Bell’s (1973) characterisation of post-industrial society,
Berry (1974b) claimed that the economic function is now subordinate to the political:

the autonomy of the economic order (and the power of the men who run it) is coming to an end,
and new and varied, but different, control systems are emerging. In sum, the control of society is
no longer primarily economic but political.
(p. 144)

Harvey (1974b) responded that Marxism could not be considered as passé while the selling of
labour power and the collusion between the economically and the politically powerful continue,
and that the state has to be considered within a marxist framework too (Harvey, 1976; which he
brought up-to-date in his writings on neoliberalism and imperialism – e.g. Harvey, 2005b, 2005c
– and capitalism’s current crises, Harvey, 2014). Berry (1974b) retorted:

I believe that change can be produced within ‘the system’. Harvey believes that it will come from
sources external to that system, and then only if enough noise is produced at the wailing wall. . . .
The choice, after all, is not that hard: between pragmatic pursuit of what is attainable and
revolutionary romanticism, between realism and the heady perfumes of flower power.
(p. 148)

Harvey’s (1975c) response came in a review of Berry’s (1973b) The Human Consequences of
Urbanization – a study of urbanisation processes at various times and places, and of the planning
responses they stimulated – which concluded that the book is ‘all fanfare and no substance’ (p. 99),
revealing that Anglo-American urban theory is ‘substantively bankrupt’ and that ‘it is scholarship of
the Brian Berry sort which typically produces such messes’ (p. 99):

It is doubtful if it makes any sense even to consider urbanisation as something isolated from
processes of capital formation, foreign and domestic trade, international money flows, and the
like, for in a fundamental sense urbanisation is economic growth and capital accumulation – and
the latter processes are clearly global in their compass.
(p. 102)
Radical geography 229

To Harvey, Berry has nothing to say of any substance, but he recognised that Berry ‘is influential and
important . . . his influence is potentially devastating’ (p. 103 – whether he meant this influence as
within geography only, or beyond it too, is not clear). Berry’s only response at the time was a
general comment on the Union of Socialist Geographers (Halvorson and Stave, 1978):

there’s no more amusing thing than goading a series of malcontents and kooks and freaks and
dropouts and so on, which is after all what that group mainly consists of. There are very few
scholars in the group.
(p. 233)

Nearly thirty years later, Berry (2002c, p. 443) revisited that debate, claiming that Harvey’s
‘approach was that of the armchair intellectual contrarian . . . [he] came to exemplify the tenured
radical who lives comfortably on the rewards provided by the society that is the objective of his
disdain’. Harvey (2002, p. 173), on the other hand, recorded that ‘I had a relatively secure position
in the field. I could use my intellectual resources and powers to a political end and was fiercely
determined . . . to do so to the hilt, much as I had as an undergraduate when confronted by
aristocratic privilege’ at Cambridge.
Apart from these very polarised exchanges, several others indicated that whereas some ‘liberals’
were prepared to consider the radical case seriously, others tended to avoid the issues. Michael
Chisholm, for example (1975a, p. 175), claimed that:

while I am fully sympathetic to the view that the ‘scientific’ paradigm is not adequate to all our
needs, and must be supplemented by other approaches, I am not persuaded that it should be
replaced. . . . Harvey wants us to embrace the marxist method of ‘dialectic’. This ‘method’
passes my understanding; so far as it has a value, it seems to be as a metaphysical belief system
and not – as its protagonists proclaim – a mode of rational argument.
(p. 175)

More frequently, reviewers accepted that the radical view added to their appreciation, but
argued that it was not, for them at least, tenable in its entirety. Thus, Morrill (1974) wrote of Social
Justice and the City that ‘I am pulled most of the way by this revolutionary analysis but I cannot make
the final leap that our task is no longer to find truth, but to create and accept a particular truth’
(p. 477). Leslie King (1976) also sought a middle course:

An economic and urban geography that will be concerned explicitly with social change and
policy. . . . Such a middle course will not find favour with the ideologues, who will see it either as
another obfuscation favouring only ‘status quo’ and ‘counter-revolutionary’ theory, or as a
distraction from the immediate task of building elegant quantitative-theoretic structures, but
some paths are being cut through the thicket of competing epistemologies, rambling lines of
empirical analysis, and gnarled branches of applied studies that now cover the middle ground.
(pp. 294–5)

He accepted that much quantitative-cum-theoretical geography had sought mathematical elegance


as an end in itself; he believed that social science must feed into social policy and generate social
change; and he accepted the ‘intellectual power’ of Marxist analysis but believed that prescriptions
based on it are acceptable only if the ideological framework is also. His conclusion suggested the
need for more quantification, which was operationally useful rather than mathematically elegant
(see also Bennett, 1985a, 1985b), and later noted that ‘space . . . should be seen as an element in
the political process, an object of competition and conflict between interest groups and different
classes’ (King and Clark, 1978, p. 12). Finally, David Smith (1977, p. 368) concluded that:
230 Radical geography

Marx may have been able to dissect the operation of a capitalist economy with particular clarity,
and see the essential unity of economy, polity and society that we so often miss today. But Marx
does not hold the key to every modern problem in complex, pluralistic society.

The debates continued, with many geographers unable/unwilling to accept both the Marxist
analysis of society and the Marxist programme for action. In part, this reflected a partial reading of
Marxism – in particular, a concentration on strict structural interpretations which neither allow for
the activities of knowing individuals nor accept or acknowledge the considerable heterogeneity of
Marxism. Ley (1980, p. 12), for example, saw in Marxism not only ‘some hidden transcendental
phenomenon . . . directing the course of human society’, which commits an epistemological error
by denying or at least suppressing the subjective, but also a theoretical error that devalues the power
of human action to redirect the course of events, and a moral error, which makes humans into
puppets and threatens basic freedoms of speech, assembly and worship. Muir (1978) attacked
interpretations of Marxism and similarly implied that it threatens individual freedom of the
academic ‘to pick and choose from among the . . . literature’ (p. 325). Respondents pointed to the
lack of such ‘intellectual orthodoxy’ and ‘sterilized geography’ (Manion and Whitelegg, 1979;
Duncan, 1979), but Muir (1979, p. 127) remained convinced of the threat implicit in ‘the
commands from such little men as Marx, Lenin, Trotsky, Stalin and Mao concerning the primacy of
activism, the obligations of party membership and the necessity to subordinate individual
judgement to the will of the party’. He claimed that radical geography is contributing to
understanding, but to call it Marxist is to give it a certain programmatic base. Walmsley and Sorensen
(1980), on the other hand, presented Marxism as just irrelevant, deflecting attention from
‘reformism and relevance’.
James Duncan and David Ley (1982) published an extensive critique of marxism in geography,
containing four major themes.

1 Marxist analysis is a form of holism, in which the whole – variously termed capital, the
economic structure, economic processes, etc. – is given a life of its own: an abstraction is
assumed to exist. This reification (see also Gould, 1988) offended their belief in individuals as
conscious, free agents (see J. Duncan, 1980, on holism in cultural geography, and Agnew and
Duncan, 1981) – although they did not proclaim an idealist alternative and accepted that
‘individual action cannot be fully explained without reference to the contexts under which
individuals act’ (p. 32).
2 Individuals are represented as agents of the whole – the means of implementing its goals – not
as free decision-makers in their own right.
3 The materialist infrastructure of Marxism is a form of economism – it presents economic
processes as the ultimate cause of all behaviour, which excludes many other influences.
4 ‘The attempt to cast explanation continually and everywhere in terms of economic imperatives,
[leads] . . . to a crisis in empirical exposition’ (p. 47).

The last comprises what is essentially a positivist critique: ‘the form of the explanations is both
tautological and empirically untestable. The result is a mystification in explanation of how real
processes operate’ (p. 55). They concluded that structural Marxism in human geography presents a
passive view of the individual, offering explanations in terms of abstract wholes which are
obfuscatory and not verifiable. Later work by James Duncan (1985) showed that he was attracted
to the structuration approach, however, which allows for human agency operating within structural
constraints, as indeed do most interpretations of Marxism.
Others who criticised structural Marxism disagreed with its treatment of the individual, and
wanted more convincing models of the interrelationships between infrastructure and superstructure
in the process of societal change. Gregory (1981) presented four such models (Figure 6.3):
Radical geography 231

A REIFICATION typified in social theory by Emile Durkheim and by some neo-Marxist formulations

SOCIETY Society is a reality sui generis


which is external to and constraining
upon human agency
INDIVIDUAL

B VOLUNTARISM typified in social theory by Max Weber

SOCIETY Society is constituted by intentional


action

INDIVIDUAL

C DIALECTICAL typified in social theory by Peter Berger


REPRODUCTION

SOCIETY SOCIETY Society forms the individuals who


create society in a continuous dialectic:
society is an externalization of man, and
INDIVIDUAL INDIVIDUAL man a conscious appropriation of society

D STRUCTURATION typified in social theory by Jiirgen Habermas and Anthony Giddens

SOCIETY SOCIETY Society systems are both the medium


and the outcome of the practices that
constitute them: the two are recursively
INDIVIDUAL INDIVIDUAL
separated and recombined

Figure 6.3  Models of the relationships between society and individual

Source: Gregory, 1981, p. 11.

1. reification, in which the individual’s actions are determined by the whole, as in a structural
Marxism that limits human agency;
2. voluntarism, in which society has no separate identity but is constructed from the actions of
free individuals;
3. dialectical reproduction, in which the whole creates the individuals, whose actions then
influence the whole, which in turn creates the next generation of individuals; and
4. structuration, which starts with individuals rather than with the whole and portrays them in a
continuous dialectic with society from then on.

These different approaches are based on a variety of conceptions of the nature of the human agent
(see Barnes, 1988; Claval, 1983; Harrison and Livingston, 1982; and van der Laan and Piersma,
1982). Gregory opted for the fourth, because it integrated humanist and materialist (or structuralist)
perspectives, in a way that critiques such as Duncan and Ley’s did not (see also Thrift, 1983). Such
an integration would recognise the materialist base to society (the infrastructure) while accepting
the important role of human agency in the superstructure; humanistic geography should not
compete with a scientific approach, but should acknowledge ‘the recurrent and recursive relations
between the individual and society as being fundamentally implicated in the production and
reproduction of both social life and social structure’ (p. 15).
Alongside debates on the relevance of Marxist ideas, other geographers were defending
quantitative spatial science against critiques such as Gregory’s (1978a, 1980). Bennett (1981c,
p. 24), for example, argued that much of the critique of quantitative geography as ‘positivism’
had been misplaced and accepted uncritically the representation of science as positivism given
232 Radical geography

by Harvey in 1969. This has had a pernicious and destructive effect on the subject in three
main ways, he claimed: first, it has suggested that scientific and empirical enquiry is largely
socially worthless; second, it has often rejected the links between physical and human geography;
and third, it has often rejected the existence of geography as a discipline at all. (Elsewhere, he
characterised the critique as ‘at best a mis-representative irrelevance, and at worst a fatuous
distraction’: Bennett and Wrigley, 1981, p. 10.) Quantification need not be allied with positivism,
according to Bennett, who identified three messages from Harvey’s Explanation in Geography: geography
is primarily inductive; geography is an objective science; and geography seeks universal laws.
But ‘each is only a partial representation of the literature and ideas it seeks to describe’ (Bennett,
1981c, p. 13). Radical and quantitative approaches must be integrated ‘by empirical analyses,
from the integration of environmental, social, political, and economic aspects with space,
historical stimuli, and specific modes of thought and their spatial-political manifestations . . .
by the re-establishment of the geographical subject matter’ (p. 24). A separate discipline of
geography (human plus physical), in which quantitative geography – ‘never . . . truly positive’
(Bennett and Wrigley, 1981, p. 10) – occupies a central place, would answer ‘the fundamental
questions of social norms, social distribution, policy impacts and humanistic concerns which
the critics rightly emphasize’ (p. 10). Many ‘radicals’ would categorise this as a status quo approach
(p. 316, this book).
In a later provocative essay, Bennett (1989b) argued that much ‘radical geography’ was out of
touch with what he termed the ‘spirit of the times’. He claimed that the welfare state, with its
emphasis on rights, had led geographers to concentrate not only on inequalities but also to adopt a
welfarist view that ‘morally they should be overcome or at least ameliorated’ (p. 279). This leads to
the argument that all differences imply relative deprivation and automatic entitlements to state
action which would remedy them. But the newly dominant social theories (associated in the UK
with ‘Thatcherism’) stress not ‘the negative aspects of capitalism’s capacity to create new wants and
hence new “relative deprivation” but rather the liberating potential of markets’. According to his
argument, geographers should reorient their work to focus on the proper role of the state in such
a society, identifying when it should interfere with market forces to ensure basic human rights,
rather than promoting a welfare-corporate state that must eventually fail (see Johnston, 1992,
1993d).
Thrall (1985) reported on a conference on ‘scientific geography’ which reached the consensus
that ‘Research in the unified areas of theory and modelling, data measurement and simulation,
estimation and verification is central to the discipline of geography’ (p. 254); such a perspective,
he contended, should be used to promote the image of geography among the sciences and
the ‘acceptance of scientific approaches within geography’. His equation of science with
mathematics, statistics and computer literacy was challenged by Driver and Philo (1986), who
argued that ‘science is more than a matter of technique’ (p. 161) and that a clearly technocratic
approach ‘effectively marginalizes all other modes of interpretation and explanation’ (p. 162).
Thrall’s (1986) response identified three major geographical traditions: humanistic, scientific and
pure theoretical. Scientific geography, he claimed, is a ‘philosophy of research . . . clearly distinct
from the earlier quantitative geography movement’ (p. 162); he advocated research involving
hypothesis-testing leading to theory creation and verification, rather than either the empiricism of
regional geographies or the sterile output of pure theoretical research.
This presentation of geography as an applied, quantitative discipline faced continuing
criticism. David Smith (1984), for example, concluded an autobiographical essay with the statement
that:

Who else but geographers would dignify their puerile pursuit of statistics, models and paradigms
as a ‘revolution’ as though it mattered to anyone but themselves? . . . And who else would want
to read such trivia? How can we take it all so seriously, when it contributes so little to the
Radical geography 233

improvement of the human condition? Most geography is inconsequential claptrap, and never
more so than during the ‘quantitative revolution’.
(p. 132)

Mercer (1984, p. 194) argued in the same vein, though noting that:

the last few years have witnessed a small – though perhaps temporary – retreat from the
more lunatic excesses of flat earth quantitative geography towards a growing recognition
that reality is not in fact beautifully ordered but that it is characterized much more by contradic-
tions, tension and disharmony. The daunting . . . task for the critical geographer – whether
‘Marxist’ or humanist – [includes] . . . the fight against the hegemony of naive, blinkered,
technocratic thinking.

He wanted to unmask ‘technocratic geography’ and divert attention away from topics such as
‘Where are the regions of healthcare need based on access to hospitals?’ to more fundamental
questions like ‘What leads to ill health?’. His basic theme was that selection of a particular research
style, with the connotations of how its output may be used, involves an (albeit possibly unconscious)
ideological choice: different conceptions of science are based on different views of both its utility and
the social order within which that utility is to be employed. David Seamon (1984) was more
forthright:

the humanistic, experiential and phenomenological thrusts swelling in the human and natural
sciences today have much relation to the human rights movement proceeding in larger society.
The manipulative, explanatory, predictive style of positivist science closely parallels the
masculine, centralized, materialist power structures that not only subjugate minorities and even
entire national populations but also manipulate and exploit the natural environment, bringing on
ecological damage and collapse.
(p. 217; see too Chapter 8, this book)

Other geographers, however, sought to integrate elements of the positivist, humanistic and
structuralist approaches to human geography (e.g. Christensen, 1982; for a fuller review, see
Johnston, 1986c). Some earlier attempts at fusion or dialogue have been short-lived, such as an
essay on the links between catastrophe theory and the discontinuities central to Marxist economic
theory (Day and Tivers, 1979, pp. 54–8; Alexander, 1979, pp. 228–30). Hay (1979a,) argued for an
empirical, analytical geography that is:

at the same time a nomological geography which seeks, for example, to understand the workings
of urban rent theory as positivistically observed, a hermeneutic geography which seeks to
identify the meaning of the urban rent system for those who are participants (active or passive)
within it, and a critical geography which points to the extent to which present urban rent systems
are themselves transformations of the capitalist system, but which admits that some of its
features may indeed be ‘invariant regularities’.
(p. 22)

On a parallel track, Livingstone and Harrison (1981, p. 370) had presented a case for ‘a
humanistic geography which is, at the same time, critical, in questioning rather than bracketing our
presuppositions, hermeneutic, in interpreting the meanings behind action, and empirical, in
examining the subjectively interpreted objective world’.
Thirty years later, Wyly (2009) called for a ‘strategic positivism’, challenging what he sees
as ‘an assumption that there was something inherent and essential in the links between positivist
234 Radical geography

epistemology, mathematical/statistical/quantitative methodology, and elite conservative politics’


(p. 314). He argues that a ‘blurred collective memory’ about how positivism came to be criticised
and avowedly rejected by many radical geographers has emerged. Presumably this has been
enabled by textbooks recounting (as Geography and Geographers has) the ways that ‘prominent figures’
(Wyly, p. 314, mentions ‘struggles between Berry and Harvey and other prominent figures’)
argued out the case in the 1970s ‘in vivid memorable terms’. He argues that this is not helpful,
since it obscures the ways that corporations and states had adopted some of the conceptual
categories and language that critical social sciences thought was their own, and misses the fact
that many geographers associated with positivism and the quantitative revolution also had critical
political orientations. Moreover, he celebrates strands of positivism and quantitative method that
combine ‘analytical rigor, scholarly accountability, and progressive strategic relevance’ (p. 316).
Many of the critics of positivism had argued that such attempts at integration were not feasible,
however, because the approaches are incompatible: Gregory (1978a, p. 169) terms it ‘inchoate
eclecticism’. (See also Gregory, 1982b; Eyles and Lee, 1982; Hudson, 1983. Positivist and
structuralist approaches sit unhappily together in Rhind and Hudson, 1981.) The biggest problem
was held to be with positivism – not quantification (Walker, 1981b; though see Sayer, 1984, 1992a,
and the response in Johnston, 1986a, 1993e) – because of its nomological orientation and belief
that human geographers can discover ‘invariant regularities’.
Some of the debates were not directly concerned with different philosophies of geography, but
rather with their utility. As a consequence of the demands on education and research from
governments of the ‘New Right’, considerable pressure to advance the study and practice of applied
geography built up. (Taylor, 1985a sets such pressures in historical context, themes returned to in
Chapter 9.) Some, such as Bennett (1985a) and Openshaw (1989), saw geographers’ technical
competence being applied to situations in the public and private sectors without any necessary
reference to philosophical issues; applied geographers are thus technicians (as in Gatrell, 1985),
who implicitly accept the context within which their skills are used. The philosophical issues
remain important to others, however; Golledge et al. (1982) countered Hart’s (1982a, p. 5) case for
regional geography that ‘We cannot allow ourselves to be intimidated by those who flaunt the
banner of science’ with:

We equally cannot allow ourselves to be intimidated by those who flaunt the banner of anti-
science, those who would reject all that is scientific about the discipline, and those who would
urge a return to the descriptive morass from which we have recently emerged.
(p. 558)

Most arguments for applied geography (again, see Chapter 9 for more details) implied that it
should be based in empiricist/positivist philosophies, however; the counter-arguments that
humanistic science can be applied to improve self- and mutual awareness and that realistic science
can be applied to advance social transformation were rarely presented (Johnston, 1986a).
Others believed that an eclectic pluralism is possible (see the discussion in Johnston, 1986c);
some conducted empiricist work (often in the behavioural geography mould) unconcerned with
any philosophical ramifications of that practice (see Flowerdew, 1986), however, whereas others
generally accepted the realist case and situated their activities within that context. And years later,
others argued that radical (or its later variant, critical) geography need not be shy of statistics (Wyly,
2009, 2011). Marxism certainly influenced many geographers (and the work of radical geographers,
such as Harvey and Massey, made impacts in other disciplines). Gould (1985a), for example,
contended that:

There is no question in my mind that the appearance of Marxist concern in geography, and its
concomitant shaping of the lens through which the world is seen, have greatly enriched our
Radical geography 235

methodological approach. There is an insistence that the things at the surface are not always
what they seem, and that it is crucial to dig down underneath the superficial appearances to get
at the deep structures. I think this is quite right.
(p. 671)

However, he criticised Marxists for their claims to truth, their condescending attitudes to ‘non-
believers’, their over-concentration on economic forces, and the ‘messianic claims that seem to lead
so readily and so often to the sacrifice of human beings today for some promise tomorrow’
(p. 300). Nearly two decades on, one of a set of papers re-evaluating David Harvey’s (1982)
landmark The Limits to Capital, notes how:

It is written by someone with an acutely sensitive historical-geographical imagination, but


barely contains any conventional history or geography. It is relentless in its precision and
chiselled in its logic, but eschews a mathematical vocabulary that is the embodiment of precision
and logic. It is a political-theoretical tract in favour of the working class, but they barely appear
in its pages.
(Barnes, 2004d, p. 412)

For another geographer: ‘Reading Harvey, he says, is an exercise in being convinced and then
engaging in the hard task of working out why you shouldn’t be so convinced’ (Gregory, 2006,
p. 24, quoting Don Mitchell). Meanwhile, while Harvey and the contributions of other Marxist
geographers continued to be reassessed, and as the initial political moment that gave birth to radical
geography faded into history, the wider global geographies of power and production had been
shifting, accompanying many other global political and social transformations.

What’s left
Just as wider political pressure for radical transformations around the world provided the initial
backdrop to the emergence of radical geography at the end of the 1960s, so the relative eclipse of
socialism in the Third World and its collapse in what was hitherto the Second World of the Soviet
Union and Eastern Europe produced new contexts. The political events of the late 1980s and early
1990s in Eastern Europe thus demanded critical reflection. As Sayer (1995) notes:

For the Right they were a vindication: communism was defeated, capitalism had won. . . .
Strangely, it was assumed by many that it also meant that Marxism was defeated, as if Western
Marxists ought to have recanted as soon as the statues of Lenin and Marx started being toppled.
This ignored the fact that the vast majority of Marx’s work and most Western Marxism is
concerned with capitalism and that most Western Marxists were overwhelmingly critical of the
state socialist regimes.
(p. 13)

This, Sayer argued, diverted attention to capitalism’s continued failings and to the failure
of what he termed radical political economy to suggest viable alternatives. Hence, his
detailed analysis of work in that genre, which he located within ‘Marxism’s lack of a
sufficiently materialist understanding of the social division of labour and its associated division
and dispersion of knowledge in advanced economies’ (p. 12). Instead of attacking this
problem, researchers (in the context of the ‘cultural turn’ – see the next chapter) have switched
their attention away from issues of power, domination and subordination linked to class and
capital (p. 13):
236 Radical geography

This seems an entirely reasonable response, as analysis of these matters was long overdue. The
uncharitable explanation is that faced with the challenge of the New Right and the weakening of
Marxism, radicals shifted their attention to new concerns which did not require them to make
any painful concessions to the Right. Socialism as an alternative political system was increasingly
difficult to articulate and defend, but in any case there were other important issues to turn to
which provided a convenient escape. While understandable, this escapist response is surely less
defensible. In my view, both of these explanations of the shift from economy to culture –
charitable and uncharitable – are right. Although post-Marxism has been generally a progressive
development in terms of broadening radical interests it has neglected political-­economic theory.
There is therefore much unfinished business.
(p. 13)

Sayer’s approach to that unfinished business concentrates on the complexity of the social
division of labour within contemporary capitalism (see also Sayer and Walker, 1992). Social
divisions occur between enterprises involved in the creation of a vast range of products and services,
whereas technical divisions (on which Marx and his followers concentrated) occur within
enterprises, and are concerned with their ownership and structure, and the nature of labour
contracts (see Rose and Pevalin, 2003). Individual enterprises can be planned in terms of how
much will be produced and marketed, by how many people, and at what cost.Whole conglomerations
of enterprises – Sayer follows Hayek in terming them ‘catallaxies’ – cannot be so planned because
of their internal variety and complexity, however; their activities must be coordinated in other
ways, which at present means the market economy celebrated by the New Right’s identification of
the ‘end of history’ (Fukuyama, 1992; Peet, 1993; Johnston, 1994d). But the inequalities that
follow pose major challenges (Sayer, 1995):

Political economy . . . has to address issues of division of knowledge and catallaxy,
horizontal control, coordination, allocation and economizing, which generally elude
democratic control . . . To ignore these issues is simply to duck the most serious problems of
political economy.
(p. 210)

So that:

Radical political economy cannot continue to follow Marxism in standing apart from the
debates of normative political theory, nor can it embrace a postmodernist celebration of
fragmentation and rejection of the search for a better social framework. It is now more clear
than ever that struggles which are directed against domination and oppression but which lack
any normative direction in terms of alternative frameworks are unlikely to be successful. Though
it has recently suffered from neglect we need a radical political economy more than ever before.
(p. 252)

The events of 1989 and the early 1990s in the former Soviet Union and its client regimes in
Eastern Europe (and their variants in the Third World) thus posed both difficulties and an opportu-
nity for geographers of a Marxist persuasion, as many of their opponents argued that the collapse
of the communist states indicated the fallibility of Marxist political programmes. (Neil Smith,
1991, p. 406, noted that ‘it has become a common argument in left circles that the crumbling of
Communist Party control throughout Eastern Europe and the Soviet Union provides definite proof
that planning and state control of the economy don’t work and can’t work’.) Folke and Sayer
(1991) argued that to claim that ‘they [the ex-communist states] weren’t really socialist’ anyhow is
an unsatisfactory response, although they recognise that the events mean that ‘genuine socialist
Radical geography 237

visions and utopian dreams will have a hard time in Eastern Europe in the coming years’ (p. 248);
new blueprints of how to manage complex societies in the interests of all are needed (see Sayer,
1995), and they must recognise, as Neil Smith (1991, p. 416) argued, that ‘1989 teaches us
the profound depth of human resistance to all forms of economic, social and political
repression’: successful revolutions must be broadly based and sustained. Sayer (1992b, p. 217)
responded that:

The problems that the left now faces are not just a consequence of the rise of the right, or of
mistakes made in the 1920s; they are also a result of the vacuum on the left concerning socialist
alternatives which are feasible as well as desirable. I think we would do better to confront that
fatal weakness.

Subsequent work in a political economy tradition has charted the contradictions and unevenness of
the capitalist transition in post-communist societies (Pickles and Smith, 1998). Such works claim
the continued relevance of Marxist and allied political economy approaches in an avowedly post-
Marxist world. Notable too was an online and activist ‘People’s Geography Project’:

The major goal of the People’s Geography Project is to popularize and make even more relevant
and useful to ordinary people the important, critical ways of understanding the complex
geographies of everyday life that geographers have and continue to develop. Our contention is
that such knowledge is an important tool not just in learning to cope with constantly developing
and transforming relations of power that are deeply geographical, but in learning how to actively
transform those relations in the name of social and economic justice.
(www.peoplesgeographyproject.org/ last accessed 1 May 2015)

Mitchell (2009, 116) describes people’s geography as having ‘many roots’. These include
similar work in history, Bunge’s (1971, and Bunge and Bordessa, 1975) earlier commitment to
radical ‘geographical expeditions’ that would map and document injustice, poverty, racism and
exclusion in American cities (on Bunge’s project, see Merrifield, 1995, and a more recent set of
commentaries in Progress in Human Geography, pp. 35, 712–20). On another scale, the role of ‘global
cities’ that are the ‘control centres’ of the international (or ‘globalizing’) corporate economy
(Beaverstock et al., 2000; Knox and Taylor, 1995; Derudder et al., 2012) has become a significant
theme of contemporary research (see the online Globalization and World Cities Study Group and
Network at www.lboro.ac.uk/gawc/), whose origins can partly be traced to radical geography’s
attention to power and inequality and its understanding of urbanisation and uneven development
as integral to capitalist dynamics.
Others brought Marxist influences to bear within a critique of the globally hegemonic ideas
and practices of ‘neoliberalism’ (see the special issue of Antipode – volume 34, 2002, especially Peck
and Tickell, 2002), including David Harvey (as noted at p. 206, this book). Thus, Jane Wills (2002)
felt able to claim that:

Political-economic geographers are seeking to develop new theory and analysis to understand
capitalism and political change. Encouragingly, I detect a move back to the big picture, to
unpacking capitalism, while also developing a more sophisticated theorization of political
agency, which incorporates economy and culture, class and identity. . . . There is a huge canvas
on which a new generation of geographers could get to work and it is critically important that
new students are attracted into political-economic research within the discipline. Indeed this
may happen through an initial engagement with cultural and social geography as much as
through economic or political geography.
(96–7)
238 Radical geography

And while, as Wills points out, Marxism also continued as an important influence in reconstituted
cultural geography (see the debates covered in Chapters 5 and 7), on the part of others there was
continued caution and sober reassessment about the limits to Marxism (e.g. Jones, 1999;
Storper, 2001) and/or the value of supplementing it with other approaches and qualifications.
Debates in Antipode about the future of radical geography have periodically reviewed its status and
roles, as well as reconsidering the commitment of geographers to progressive social change, and
the policies and politics that might be most productive in such a project, and the role of ‘theory’
therein (see Hague, 2002; Castree, 2002; Castree et al., 2010; Larner, 2011). For example, Marvin
Waterstone (2002, p. 666) claimed that: ‘What we have is, once again, a radical critique from the
margins of a truly staid discipline that moves along mostly untouched by what happens in the pages
of this journal.’ To which Jane Wills and Jamie Peck (2002, p. 669) responded that ‘the fact that
radical geography can no longer be dismissed as a fringe concern represents a remarkable victory
for the project, even if in the process it has taken on some ‘mainstream’ connotations’.
A few years later, Neil Smith (2005a), in exchanges with Amin and Thrift (2005), forcefully
argued that radical geography had been tamed, co-opted and was increasingly disciplined by the
forces of audit, and the dominant neoliberal agenda of universities and government (especially in
the UK, where he compared radical geography’s fate to the right-ward course of the Labour
Party under Tony Blair’s leadership). Amin and Thrift had argued that the Left was in a healthy
state, with its continuing political orientation, belief that there must be better ways of organising
the world, its critique of power structures and its internal reflexivity, but they doubted that
Marxism’s privileged position underpinning those values could be maintained; they welcomed the
proliferation of alternative theoretical positions as foundations for charting ways forward: ‘it is time
that the Left in geography came to accept this vibrant pluralism, instead of insisting that certain
perspectives necessarily hold a privileged insight into the ways of the world’ (p. 238; see also Amin
and Thrift, 2013).
Arguably, however, periodic conferences of the International Critical Geography Group
(established in 1997, see Desbiens and Smith, 1999; Bachmann and Belina, 2012) as well as new
journals (such as www.acme-journal.org) published online and/or collectively owned (www.
hugeog.com) still embody something of the original radical spirit. Equally, campaigns about the
RGS receiving sponsorship from a multinational oil company with a controversial reputation
regarding environmental and human rights issues in its zones of extraction (Chatterton and Maxey,
2009; Gilbert, 1999, 2009) and calls to boycott (by not publishing in or reviewing articles
submitted to) the journals owned by a large commercial academic publisher who also arranged
events where sales of lethal military equipment are promoted (Chatterton and Featherstone, 2007)
are inspired by radical geography. Attention also to the geography of a fresh generation of protest
(on issues such as anti-globalisation or more mundane ones like the commodification of public
services, including education: see Sparke, 2013) rework radical – or as it has more often been
termed today – critical geography. Throughout virtually all human geography, the scale and force of
the radical contribution and legacy means that it has proved hard to ignore. Meanwhile, Antipode
(Chatterton et al., 2011) itself finessed its radical vision, setting out new and long-standing areas of
interest (geographies of poverty, marginality and power; urban transformations in the Global South;
food, agriculture and environment; counter-imperialism; capitalism and neo-populisms).
It may long have been the case that, as Peter Taylor (2003) states:

Soon after its emergence, radical geography, whether of Peet, of Harvey, of Blaut, or of Bunge,
became explicitly Marxist in nature . . . to be a radical scholar no longer inevitably means taking
a Marxist, ‘neo’ or otherwise, approach to understanding social change. In the contemporary
academy there is an array of schools of thought that aspire ‘to turn the world upside down’.
(pp. 55–6)
Radical geography 239

However, it is a measure of the ongoing presence of radical geography and of Marxism


within it that avowedly ‘post-Marxist’ geographers such as Richard Smith and Marcus Doel
(2001, p. 137) allowed that ‘it is clear that many postmodernists and poststructuralists have
extended or reacted to Marxism in a number of useful and interesting ways which do not necessarily
mean the jettisoning of a radical left-wing politics’. Such possibilities are also among the subjects
of our next chapters here.

Conclusions
This chapter has illustrated the depth and breadth of discussions that occupied much of the 1970s
and 1980s. They continued in attenuated forms in the 1990s and offer continuing sources of
inspiration. Peet (1998, p. 294) feels that ‘A discipline can support only a few true radicals; the rest
have functional utility, oblique though this often may seem.’
Yet in the turbulent decades since the late 1960s, a growing proportion of geographers wished
to be involved in reshaping societies, either through ameliorative correction of current problems
and trends or by designing desirable spatial organisations (Berry, 1973b); some saw this as necessary
if human geography was to retain its institutional position. Their motives ranged from ‘pure
altruism’ to ‘devoted self-seeking’; their methods varied from those who accept the present mode
of production and see humanitarian goals as achievable within its constraints, to those who
subscribed to the phenomenological view (Buttimer, 1974) that:

the social scientist’s role is neither to choose or decide for people, nor even to formulate the
alternatives for choice but rather, through the models of his discipline, to enlarge their horizons
of consciousness to the point where both the articulation of alternatives and the choice of
direction could be theirs, to those who believed that a revolution is necessary to remove the
causes of society’s myriad problems and replace them by an equitable social structure.
(p. 29)

Perhaps paradoxically, many ‘revolutionaries’ in the above classification were not ‘activists’ in
the sense of being deeply involved in contemporary issues. The ‘liberals’ advanced the strongest
arguments for geographical contributions to the solution of societal problems, particularly those
which involve public sector intervention (e.g. Bennett, 1983), and pressed for academic engagement
in policy-making; many of the ‘radicals’, on the other hand, argued that their longer-term goals
were best served through educational programmes (e.g. Huckle, 1985), although some were
involved in policy-making activities for institutions (such as local governments) that promoted
alternative (socialist) strategies, especially in the support for employment initiatives (e.g. Duncan
and Goodwin, 1985; see, however, Harvey, 1995 and Massey, 2001, on the tensions this can create).
The two groups were members of the same discipline and practised in the same academic
environments, yet their goals and methods seemed incommensurate. As Chapter 9 illustrates, key
issues around which these arguments pivoted concerned the applications, relevance and prospective
impacts of human geography.
At this point, however, we should note that perhaps the key to the influence of radical
geography is that Marxist work was able to set many of human geography’s leading intellectual
agendas. Thus, Neil Smith (2001) comments that:

Within ‘establishment geography’, the dramatic rise of Marxism in the early 1970s was first
ignored, later despised, and eventually resented, even if it was eventually if begrudgingly
accommodated. Yet there was little that establishment geographers, who completely controlled
the discipline in North America, Britain, and Australia, could do to prevent it. Responses to
Marxist work in this period invariably lacked the intellectual sophistication that Marxist theory
240 Radical geography

brought, and criticisms often came across as shallow and contradictory. . . . A medical metaphor
captures the situation. The allergy of English-speaking geography (as a discipline) to social
theory throughout most of the twentieth century now meant that the discipline had no immune
system against Marxism. Marxism in the 1970s and 1980s . . . offered powerful insights
concerning the political questions of the day, and offered a breathtaking global vista of of the
geographies of exploitation, oppression and injustice – and their causes. . . . Just as important,
it provided the most sophisticated social theory that many geographers had come in contact
with, and its opponents had few if any social theoretical resources for counteracting its influence.
Unlike anthropology or sociology where various major figures had been socialists, geography as
a discipline lacked all immunity against Marxism. Intellectually if not institutionally, the old
guard was defeated almost before the struggle began.
(p. 9)

Yet by the 1980s, anglophone geography as a whole was still characterised by a plurality of
approaches (Gould and Olsson, 1982), which can perhaps be classified into three intertwined
philosophical strands (or sets of strands), each with a distinctive epistemology, or theory of
knowledge.

1 First was the stress on science and putative break with the geography inherited from before the
Second World War. This was associated with positivism and quantification, a belief in the
objectivity of scientific description (empiricism) and analysis of the world, its goal of formu-
lating laws about that world, and its assumption that explanation (causal laws) can be derived
by studying the outcomes of the laws; the laws of spatial organisation and behaviour can be
revealed by analysing spatial patterns. At least some of those who promoted the empiricist
foundation to this philosophy denied that it necessarily leads to the full positivist commit-
ment. They also disagreed over how to use scientific procedures for the evaluation of hypo-
theses, however, as in the critical rationalism usually associated with Popper (Hay, 1985a;
Marshall, 1985; Bird, 1989). Others later stressed the need to study perceptions and cognition;
the move to behavioural geography that seemed to offer a way forward. Going beyond this,
however:
2 Second were the humanistic philosophies based on a belief that people live in subjective
worlds that need to be interpreted and cannot be modelled in any straightforward way.
Their actions cannot be explained (predicted) as examples of general laws of behaviour,
but only understood, or appreciated, through methodologies that appreciate their
subjectivity.
3 Finally, there were various radical moves (often allied with variants of Marxism) which argued
that explanations for observed patterns cannot be discovered through analysis of the patterns
themselves, but only by the development of theories of the underlying processes that generate
the conditions within which human agents can create those patterns. Foremost within this
group was Marxism, which argues that the processes are themselves changing – and can be
altered by concerted political action – so that no eternal laws of spatial organisation are
possible; at least not outside an understanding of the social dynamics of particular societies
and modes of production. When he advocated ‘a revolution in geographical thought’, David
Harvey (1973) had argued that:

the most fruitful strategy at this juncture is to explore that area of understanding in which certain
aspects of positivism, materialism and phenomenology overlap to provide adequate
interpretations of the social reality in which we find ourselves. This overlap is most clearly
explored in Marxist thought.
(p. 129)
Radical geography 241

However, the trajectory of Marxism through geography has been complex, and contained detours
such as realism and structuration theory (see Cox, 2013). Moreover, these trajectories
(as in the case of structuralist Marxisms’ indirect influence, via the work of Massey and in regulation
theory) have not always been clear to all who contributed to or contested a variety of Marxist
geographies. Weaving across the entire path was also a nascent feminist critique (the focus of
Chapter 8) and reworking of the human–environment tradition in geography via Marxist literatures
on ecology, landscapes and nature.
All this plurality provided a focus of debate, and even a source of confusion, among human
geographers. For some, it presented a polarisation that can only be solved when one approach
(paradigm) is proved triumphant. Others accepted that this cannot be done, since there are no
common criteria for comparing the approaches. For some, the plurality offered potential for
developing a newer, more robust human geography (e.g. Wilson, 1989b), though the nature of
that development remained unclear to many. (The summaries of the statements made by six
geographers – Peter Hall, Peter Jackson, Doreen Massey, Brian Robson, Nigel Thrift and Alan Wilson
(1987) – to a review by the UK Economic and Social Research Council on Horizons and
Opportunities in Social Science clearly illustrated the pluralism.) However complex and uncertain
this may have looked to many, geography had undoubtedly been transformed, and although it was
still a relatively small discipline (especially in the USA), its relative status among the social sciences
was greatly enhanced. As both Peet (1998) and Cox (2014) argued, spatial science initiated three
major changes in human geography – the importance of explicitly addressing and developing
theory; the need for methodological rigour; and the crucial role of space in human affairs. But it
addressed the wrong type of theory, used inappropriate methods and had a limited conception of
space. The ‘radical (and other) revolutions’ that followed accepted those foundational needs and
built new analytical structures accordingly.
Looking back and celebrating this, Don Mitchell (2009) notes how:

If the so-called quantitative revolution had shaken geography’s old guard but nonetheless
seemed to be aligned with the political status quo (it was largely a technocratic development),
then radical geography hoped to upend both the discipline and the world of which it was
part. Radical geography was thus enthused with experimentation . . . it sought to be directly
relevant in ordinary and oppressed people’s lives in ways that academic knowledge production
rarely has.
(p. 117)

As this chapter indicates, how far radical geography succeeded in those aims remains a
subject of debate. Moreover, the world in which geographers work and which they study, and the
political and philosophical influences upon them, continued to change. Without any definitive
resolution of the debates outlined in this chapter, by the 1990s, geographers were being presented
with further intellectual and practical challenges. Writing in 2006, Castree could note how: ‘Those
Leftists who passed through bachelors programmes and graduate school from the early nineties
were inculcated into ways of thinking which, in the main, defined themselves as post- or non-
Marxist’ (2006b, p. 248). Thus, further developments outside the discipline influenced it by the
mid-/late 1980s, and within a decade these were the source of further significant reorientations in
what many human geographers did and why. They are the focus of the next two chapters.
Chapter 7

Postmodernism, poststructuralism
and postcolonialism

The impact of postmodernism in the field of geography has been particularly intense and far-
reaching, perhaps more so than in any other social science   . . .   postmodern and related
poststructuralist critiques of traditional modes of interpreting and explaining geographical
phenomena have influenced scholarly research and teaching in nearly all branches of the
discipline.
(Edward Soja, 2001a, p. 11860)

We begin by outlining the essence of postmodern ideas. This is no easy task.


(Phil Hubbard et al., 2002, p. 73)

[W]e will only unlock the power of poststructuralist geography to the extent that we embrace
nothing but relations and co-relations, their folding and unfolding.
(Marcus Doel, 1999. p. 147)

In certain moments, in certain milieus, particular cities generate a number of issues that
incite attention. The work produced by the Los Angeles School of postmodern urbanism
(hereafter LA School or LA scholars) is a diary of one such occasion . . . [describing] the onset
of what has been called the ‘postmodern condition’ – that is, a changing perception and
experience of space and time and an intensified, sometimes celebratory, consciousness
of the ‘new’.
(Barbara Hooper, 2009, p. 293)

Perhaps the best – and last – bit of advice that can be given to readers of this book is to not
accept anyone else’s definition of postmodern geographical praxis.
(Edward Soja, 2001b, p. 294)

Posts- and turns


According to Claudio Minca (2009):

any attempt at defining the state of the art of postmodern geography is doomed to fail; if only for
the very fact that the introduction of postmodernism to geography – as to other fields of enquiry
– has implied the breaking down of any paradigmatic logic and scepticism toward any linear
reconstruction of the history of the discipline.
(p. 363)
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 243

Minca dedicated an earlier collection on Postmodern Geography: Theory and praxis ‘to all those who have
had the courage to try to free themselves of the strangleholds of modernity . . . this book can
represent a sign that you are not alone’ (Minca, 2001, p. xiii). Like others who propose new
approaches (though postmodernists would scarcely see themselves as part of a new ‘paradigm’),
individual postmodern geographers may have faced isolation or resistance at first. Avowedly
poststructuralist geography, that soon followed postmodernism, often met ‘scornful derision
at one end [of the scale of reactions] to bemused indifference at the other’ (Dixon and Jones, 1996,
p. 767). But their collective presence in the discipline soon made them familiar to many geographers
and a significant presence in classrooms, texts and journals. Thus, David Clarke (2006, p. 107)
reflects on the way:

The term postmodern burst unceremoniously onto the geographical scene in the mid to late
1980s. . . . Against the sober promises of realism to rethink science for human geography and
the wise counsel structuration theory offered in attempting to resolve the long-standing family
feud between structuralists and humanists . . . the reckless, dizzying antics of postmodernists
seemed to throw reason itself into doubt . . .
(p. 107)

He also claims that:

The very first thing to say about the post-modern wor(l)d is that it’s inherently confusing.
(And postmodernists are wont to perform cheap tricks like that, so we now no longer know
if we’re talking about words or worlds, and are left feeling thoroughly disorientated regarding
their relationship – which we once took for granted as a straightforward matter of representation.)
(p. 107)

It might therefore be rather unpostmodern of us to give our readers the clear structure of this
chapter in advance. We also might rearrange things, like Soja’s (1989) text on Postmodern Geographies
which begins on page one with a combined Preface and Postscript – ‘to shake up the normal flow
of the linear text to allow other, more “lateral” connections to be made’. Alternatively, like Michael
Dear and Steven Flusty’s (2002, p. xiii) The Spaces of Postmodernity, we might ‘forego a “Conclusion”
for an “Inconclusion”, refusing even to contemplate a closure that, like so many previous
(anti)climaxes, would function only to suppress different ways of knowing’. But like many
geographers, a structured and linear narrative might be what you have come to expect from
diagrams, texts, tables, maps and published papers in the discipline, so allow us some pointers here.
This chapter is concerned with a number of influences and transformations which informed
human geography in the 1980s and 1990s, and that led to considerable reworking of human
geography in the twenty-first century. These include postmodernism, poststructuralism and
what was termed a ‘cultural turn’. The latter saw a reinvigoration not only of cultural geography, but
also a bringing to bear of cultural themes on a wider range of human geographies (including
economic geography: such as in Lee and Wills, 1997; Thrift and Olds, 1996). Feminist geography
also had a substantial and growing impact since the 1980s; we will consider this in the next
chapter. Here, however, we also consider the impact of postcolonialism, in particular a reconsider-
ation of geography’s complicity in colonialism and tentative moves to decolonise geography.
The former – geography’s colonial history – is something that radical geographers and positivists
had both sought, in different ways, to put behind them. Positivists had advocated a new scientific
geography which would have little or nothing to do with geography’s prior trajectory of regional
description and narration of difference (geography as an inventory of regions and their peoples).
For their part, radicals had often proclaimed their anti-imperialism. Postcolonialism builds on this
sense of critique.
244 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

Beyond the discipline, the 1980s and 1990s saw extensive changes in the economic, social/
technological and political contexts within which academic geography was set and in the practices
employed in other social science and humanities disciplines.The former comprised the globalisation
and flexible accumulation trends within capitalism, and associated shifts in the means and spaces of
production/consumption (including digitisation and the birth of the internet) described earlier,
along with major changes in the nature and role of the state apparatus (and the eclipse of
communism – at least that form of it which had been known through most of the twentieth
century), which had profound effects on the funding and expectations of research in higher
education. The latter involved attempts to come to terms intellectually with those changes in the
context of widespread disillusion with current academic practices. On both sides of the North
Atlantic and in the other anglophone contexts that are the focus of this book, the private and public
sector structures in place since the 1940s were being partly dismantled and replaced by others in
which ‘markets’ (and models from business) played a greater role. In the private sector, for example,
many of the large manufacturing industries were very significantly ‘downsized’, often moving to
cheaper sites of production in what was called the ‘Third World’, and their replacements were often
in service industries, usually offering less job security and fewer fringe benefits, and with weaker
trade union organisation. In the public sphere, social democratic and ‘left’ political parties appeared
to have lost some of their core support and had to reinvent themselves (in the UK case, the Labour
Party branded itself ‘New Labour’ and in so doing accepted many of the ‘market’ shifts that
Conservative governments had instigated in the 1980s and early 1990s). Change was rapid and was
everywhere; understanding why it was happening and what was replacing it provided human
geographers with major challenges (as suggested by the essays in Johnston, 1993f.), but the
changes were also affecting the institutions in which they worked, often increasing pressures
associated with such rapid changes, combined with increased audit and so-called ‘efficiency’ gains
(see Chapters 1 and 10). At the same time, however, many of the demographic and social changes
and pressures of the 1960s were also working through the system, with attendant generational
shifts and a sense of new possibilities. The radical geography which began then had also come of
age and continued to be a point of departure and reference – it had opened up new ways of
thinking and new engagements for human geography – and would be re-evaluated by new
generations of geographers. Hence, in Neil Smith’s (2001) words:

The rapid deepening of Marxist research in that decade [of the 1980s] was therefore matched by
an even more rapid broadening as Marxist work explored and eventually fused with all kinds of
social theory.
(p. 10)

For Hubbard et al. (2002), however:

much contemporary critical human geography (though not all) is fundamentally different from
the more homogeneous radical geography practised in the late 1960s and 1970s. . . . As such,
structural and materialist accounts have been complemented (and in many instances replaced)
by positions more sensitive to human agency and questions of culture.
(p. 63)

Cultural turns?
Although it might also partly be summarised by reference to the growth of qualitative methods
(Crang, 2002), a more frequent way of summarising new trends in human geography during the
later part of the 1980s and the 1990s has been to adopt the label of ‘cultural turn’. Chris Philo, who
had earlier (1991) identified a nascent cultural turn in human geography, had the following to say
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 245

of that earlier moment (and of the 1991 collection of essays New Words, New Worlds: Reconceptualising
social and cultural geography which he had compiled and which contributed to the sense of new
departures):

the main achievement was arguably to heighten our senses of how all things cultural might be
raised to a much more prominent position in studies throughout the corpus of human geography
(and not just in one or two neatly parceled-off subdisciplines). It was to take much more seriously
than hitherto all manner of things that might be construed as constituting the cultural ‘stuff’ of
human life, not just phenomena routinely designated as cultural . . . but also the complete
panorama of meaning systems both collective (e.g. religions and nationalisms) and more
individual (built up in personal psychic economies). . . . This was to anticipate the amazingly rich
arc of the cultural turn within human geography as it has now arisen: a turn which obviously had
great ramifications for both social and cultural geography, but one too which has undoubtedly
sent shockwaves throughout the length and breadth of human geography, leading to debates
(more or less explicit, more or less heated) about the merits of a cultural turn within (say)
economic geography, political geography, population geography, environmental geography and
elsewhere.
(Philo, 2000, p. 28)

For Philo, the cultural turn had been many years in the making. Thus, what he terms the
‘valuable maneuvers’ (p. 32) and ‘twin routes out of spatial science after c.1970 signposted by,
respectively, radical/Marxist geography (with its focus on social structure) and behavioural/
humanistic geography (with its focus on human agency)’ (p. 31) together:

paved the way for the cultural turn of more recent vintage . . . the wider horizons of late 1980s
human geography which gave birth to the cultural turn included a variety of developments which
extended, and in many cases recast, the Marxist and humanistic revolutions of the previous
decade. . . . The reworkings of Marxist geography – the spatializing of Marxist concepts; the
restructuring, spatial divisions of labour and locality studies debates; the advent of regulation
and regime theories; the critical realist encounter; the agitations around post-Marxism . . . have
all created a receptiveness to the ways in which . . . cultural processes become implicated in
political-economic spaces . . . [and] the reworkings of humanistic geography – the reappraisal of
the landscape tradition; the growing attention to intersubjective meaning systems; the
fragmenting of the singular figure of ‘Man’ in recognizing the sheer diversity of peoples occupying
this planet; the new mapping of the human subject(s); the alertness to the psycho-dynamics of
gender and sexuality – have all fostered a sensitivity to the many dimensions of immaterial
culture which enter into the making of virtually all human spaces imaginable.

Nayak and Jeffrey (2011, p. 115) point out that ‘the cultural turn was never a solitary exercise
. . . geography was only one of a number of social science disciplines that was influenced by this
movement’. Instead, they describe a ‘coming together of different strands and activities’
encompassing literary criticism, a reinvigorated cultural studies and ‘new insights on power and
subjectivity’. In human geography however, Barnett (2009) argued that the cultural turn signified
three related trends:

1 the emergence of a ‘new’ cultural geography;


2 an increased attention to culture in a variety of subfields, including economic and historical
geography;
3 a claim that culture had become more central in wider social, political and economic processes
(as in ‘cultural industries’ or ‘cultural clashes’).
246 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

Moreover, for Barnett:

Theoretically, the cultural turn has promoted a greater degree of pluralism in human geography,
drawing on concepts from other disciplines and focusing attention on multiple dimensions of
difference . . . the cultural turn has underwritten a commitment to investigate the contingent
and constructed qualities of phenomena.
(p. 134)

The notion of a ‘new’ cultural geography (as in the first trend identified by Barnett, 2009)
suggests a link with the subdiscipline of cultural geography, in particular a contrast with how it was
traditionally practised – what was widely known as the Berkeley school, associated with the work
of Carl Sauer (see p. 49, this book). Marie Price and Martin Lewis (1993a) thus suggested that
beyond the use of the adjective ‘cultural’, the ‘old’ and the ‘new’ ‘share precious little’ (p. 2). They
argued that the ‘new cultural geographers’ (they cited Cosgrove, Duncan and Jackson as ‘standard
bearers’) had ‘reinvented’ the nature of ‘old’ cultural geography, in order to criticise it, with the
Berkeley school as ‘its currently most misinterpreted form’ (p. 3). In return, Cosgrove (1993)
accused them of inventing a conspiracy, claimed that he had not wholeheartedly embraced the term
‘new cultural geography’, and welcomed the growing accommodation between the ‘theory-
free’ Berkeley school and the theoretically grounded approaches. Jackson (1993b) was also
accommodating, while pointing to a wide range of other traditions. More stridently, James Duncan
(1993b, p. 518) responded that ‘I cannot accept that it is possible to employ the term culture in
one’s work and yet employ no theory of culture’, to which Price and Lewis (1993b) responded by
restressing their case that Duncan (1980) misrepresented the Berkeley canon, both in its orientation
and in its implicit acceptance of ‘the tiresome superorganic debate’ (Price and Lewis, 1993b, p.
521). Since those exchanges, debates about the dynamics and merits (or otherwise) of the cultural
turn(s) continued (notably in Don Mitchell’s, 1995, work as detailed in Chapter 5; see too, Barnett
1998a, 1998b, 2004, and Sayer, 2000). In Nayak and Jeffrey’s (2011, p. 117) view, a key to the
consolidation of the cultural turn was a ‘new generation . . . [of] PhD students who had
broken away from Sauerian traditions to explore how culture is linked to power, ideology and
the broader field of representation’. In what follows, we return to aspects of these debates and the
paths they opened.
Meanwhile, the cultural turn runs through most themes that follow, but these are not contained
by it (or them, for, as Cook et al., 2000, p. xii, pointed out, ‘there has been less a cultural turn than
a series of cultural insights, turns, multiple circuits’). So this chapter will be somewhat more
disjointed than its predecessors, as we work through a series of interwoven, postmodern,
poststructuralist and postcolonial strands of contemporary human geography.

Postmodernism

Whose definition?
Postmodernism became increasingly popular in the social sciences and humanities in the 1980s
and early 1990s attracting considerable attention from geographers. Its rise, according to Soja
(1989), represented an attack on the predominance of historicism in modern thought, with its
emphasis on biography (both individual and collective) and time and the consequent neglect of
spatiality and geography. He defined historicism as:

an overdeveloped historical contextualization of social life and social theory that actively
submerges and peripheralizes the geographical or spatial imagination . . . [and which produces]
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 247

an implicit subordination of space to time that obscures geographical interpretations of the


changeability of the social world.
(p. 15)

Because of this, he claimed that geographers had failed to attain their ‘rightful position’ within the
social sciences for much of the twentieth century. A ‘superficially similar historical rhythm’ (p. 33)
was assumed to occur across all places, rather than a realisation – as stressed in the localities project
and new regional geography projects discussed earlier (p. 215, this book) – that social processes are
differently constituted in different places, so that the historical flow is not the same everywhere; not
surprisingly, some sought to link the localities project to postmodernism (see Cooke, 1990). Thus,
for example, postmodern novels have either a non-linear or an apparently chaotic structure when
they try to represent different things happening simultaneously in different places, and postmodern
architecture does not rely on the kinds of clear functional structure that characterised most modern
architecture (Knox, 1987).
This problem of synchronicity has long been recognised by geographers (as well as poets,
novelists and film-makers), as Massey (1992) observed with reference to Darby’s (1962) paper on
‘The problem of geographic description’. Darby pointed out that:

A series of geographical facts is much more difficult to present than a sequence of historical
facts. Events follow one another in time in an inherently dramatic fashion that makes juxtaposition
in time easier to convey through the written word than juxtaposition in space. Geographical
description is inevitably more difficult to achieve than is historical narrative.
(p. 2)

But histories have geographies, and relating concurrent changes over both time and space
simultaneously provides particular problems, especially since all mapped distributions are simply
static snapshots of continuing processes (Blaut, 1962). In a sense then, in his concern for the
combinations of place and space Soja was returning to an old theme in the geographical tradition.
He did so, however, in the context not of a rural or isolated region but of what he described
(adopting a slogan from the Los Angeles Times) as:

the place where ‘it all comes together’ . . . the sprawling urban region defined by the sixty mile
(100 kilometer) circle around the centre of the City of Los Angeles a prototopos, a paradigmatic
place; or, pushing inventiveness still further, a mesocosm, an ordered world in which the micro
and the macro, the idiographic and the nomothetic, the concrete and the abstract, can be seen
simultaneously in an articulated and interactive combination.
(p. 191)

So Soja writes a ‘free-wheeling essay on Los Angeles . . . a decidedly postmodern landscape, a search
for revealing “other spaces” and hidden geographical texts’ (p. 2). He captures the putative
postmodernism of these spaces by drawing upon the Argentinean writer Jorge Luis Borges. Thus,
Soja (p. 2) quotes from Borges’s short story (originally published in Spanish in 1945) of:

‘The Aleph’ – the only place on earth where all places are, a limitless space of simultaneity and
paradox, impossible to describe in less than extraordinary language. Borges’ observations
crystallize some of the dilemmas confronting the interpretation of postmodern geographies:
Then I saw the Aleph. . . . And here begins my despair as a writer. All language is a set of symbols
whose use among its speakers assumes a shared past. How, then, can I translate into words the
limitless Aleph, which my floundering mind can scarcely encompass? . . . Really what I want to do
is impossible, for any listing of an endless series is doomed to be infinitesimal. In that single
248 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

gigantic instant I saw millions of acts both delightful and awful; not one of them amazed me more
than the fact that all of them occupied the same point in space, without overlapping or transparency.
What my eyes beheld was simultaneous, but what I shall write down will be successive, because
language is successive. Nonetheless, I will try to recollect what I can.

While for Soja it is found in Los Angeles, whose ‘spatiality and historicity are archetypes of
vividness, simultaneity, and interconnection’ (p. 248), postmodernism has been attributed a wide
range of explicit and implicit meanings, and its core is hard to identify; Cloke et al. (1991, p. 19)
write of it as ‘infuriatingly difficult to define’.
According to Michael Dear (1994a, p. 3):

Postmodernity is everywhere, from literature, design and philosophy, to MTV [Music Television],
ice cream and underwear. This seeming ubiquity only aggravates the problem in grasping its
meaning. Postmodern discourse seems capable of instant adaptation in response to context and
choice of interlocutors.
(p.3)

Nevertheless, he believes ‘we can cut to the heart of the matter by identifying three principal
constructs in postmodernism: style, epoch and method’, with the first having provided the source
of the initial explosion of interest.

1 Postmodernism as style originated in literature and literary criticism, and spread to other
artistic fields such as design, film, art, photography and architecture; the general trend involved
the promotion of difference and the lack of conformity to overriding structural imperatives.
Dear found trends within architecture especially revealing:

the search for the new was associated with a revolt against the formalism and austerity of the
modern style epitomised by the unadorned office tower. . . . The burgeoning postmodern
architecture was disturbingly divorced from any broad philosophical underpinnings, taking
the form of an apparently-random cannibalizing of existing architectural archetypes, and
combining them into an ironic collage of (or pastiche) of previous styles.

2 Postmodernism as epoch portrays current developments within society as a major radical


break with the past – hence use of the term ‘postmodernity’ to contrast it with the modernity
of the previous epoch. These ‘new times’ are characterised by difference, so that study of the
postmodern epoch involves grappling with the fundamental problem of theorising
contemporaneity, i.e. the task of making sense out of an infinity of concurrent social realities.
Any landscape is simultaneously composed of obsolete, current and emergent artefacts; but
how do we begin to codify and understand this variety?
3 Postmodernism as method is, according to Dear, likely to be the most enduring of the three
main trends. It eschews the notions of universal truths and meta-theories which can account
for ‘the Meaning of Everything’. No portrayal can claim dominance over another; separate
theories are incommensurable and so their evaluation is always relative and contingent: ‘even
the attempt to reconcile or resolve the tensions among competing theories should a priori be
resisted’.

Epoch, style and method are undoubtedly tangled up and can be differentiated in a variety
of ways. Such tangles are what led Cloke et al. (1991) to propose a twofold approach to
postmodernism – as an approach or method and as object of analysis – while Demeritt (cited in
Hoggart et al., 2002, p. 3) located three strands of postmodernism:
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 249

1 a concern for new and non-universalist models of human subjectivity and rationality (e.g. Pile
1991, 1993; Sibley, 2000) that emphasise complexity and diversity;
2 an epistemological project critiquing concepts of truth and claims of universal knowledge;
and
3 an emphasis on ‘the radical phenomenological and social constructivist implications of
postmodernism in suggesting that our knowledge of nature, and, in some sense, the nature of
reality itself (and of nature), are culturally relative’ (see Demeritt, 1998).

Either way, postmodernism’s emphasis on ‘heterogeneity, particularity and uniqueness’ (Gregory,


1989a, p. 70) undoubtedly attracted some human geographers to it. Human geographers under the
sway of modernism had emphasised order in their promotion of spatial science, when their
empirical observations could really only identify disorder, which suggested the absence of generally
applicable theories and universal truths (Barnes, 1996). Postmodernism gave them a philosophical
hanger, recognising (Gregory, 1989a):

[that] there is more disorder in the world than appears at first sight is not discovered until that
order is looked for . . . we need, in part, to go back to the question of areal differentiation: but
armed with a new theoretical sensitivity towards the world in which we live and to ways in which
we represent it.
(pp. 91–2)

With regard to theory, Michael Dear (1988) observed that postmodernism suggests that
geographers should be wary of aspirations to ‘grand theory’ (p. 272). Yet recognition that all
knowledge is not only time–space specific but also expressed in language which reflects what such
specificity (see below) meant, to him, that geography can ‘claim its place alongside history as
one of two key disciplines concerned with the time–space reconstruction of human knowledge’
(p. 272).
Understanding the attractions of this postmodern stance to geographers requires prior
appreciation of why modernist spatial science came to be so influential. According to Gregory
(1989b), throughout much of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries geographical practice has
been influenced by particular aspects of, first, anthropology, then sociology, and finally economics.
Two features dominated the adopted modernist paradigm:

1 Its firm base in naturalism, which was likely to have ‘special significance in a discipline like
ours, where human geography is yoked to physical geography’ (p. 352) and the consequent
reliance on the aims and procedures of the natural sciences as relevant to the study of humans
and their societies.
2 A totalising conception of space, which involves the search for a ‘systematic order whose
internal logic imposes a fundamental coherence on the chaos of our immediate impressions’
– hence, the dominance of spatial science within that project.

Postmodernism presented a substantial critique to the approaches that dominated much of


geography in the period from the 1950s through the 1980s, with their emphases on order and
‘grand theory’. As Cloke et al. (1991, p. 200) noted:

human geographers will increasingly come to recognise the gravity of the challenge that
postmodernism as attitude poses to the most conventional theorisations of the human world,
and will begin to appreciate that a sensitivity to the geography of this world – to its fragmentation
across multiple spaces, places, environments and landscapes – is itself very much bound up
with (and an impetus for) a postmodern suspicion of modernist ‘grand theories’ and
250 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

‘metanarratives’. . . . These manoeuvres will doubtless cause much unease and controversy,
however, given that they cast doubt on the stability of the foundations from which most human
geography had proceeded over the last thirty years or so.

Soja’s (1989) book represented mostly an engagement with what it identified as postmoder-
nism as a place (or assembly of places). As already noted, the Los Angeles metropolitan area is, he
argued, difficult to represent in a narrative because its many images seem ‘to stretch laterally instead
of unfolding sequentially’ (p. 222), and because ‘it too seems limitless and constantly in motion,
never still enough to encompass, [it seems] too filled with “other spaces” to be informatively
described’. All he says he can offer is ‘a succession of fragmentary glimpses’ into a ‘particularly
restless geographical landscape’ (p. 223) – what he terms an ‘interjacent medley’ (p. 247). Its
environment is too multilayered, created by too many authors to be identified: there are too many
‘discordant symbols drawing out the underlying themes’.
Soja’s work was subjected to an engaged critique by Gregory (1990; see also Gregory, 1994,
chapter 4). He argued that modernist theories of the capitalist city also stressed ‘geographically
uneven development via simultaneous tendencies towards homogenization, fragmentation and
hierachization’ (Soja, 1989, p. 50). He accepted that the Los Angeles landscape contains ‘an eco-
nomic order, an instrumental nodal structure, an essentially exploitative spatial division of labor’,
but claimed that these cannot be summarised into a ‘totalising description’; all that can be offered
is a ‘series of fragmentary glimpses’ (p. 246). And yet, Gregory stressed, Soja advised those wishing
to explore the metropolis that ‘it must be reduced to a more familiar and localized geometry to be
seen’ (Soja, 1989, p. 224) and its emphases are (Gregory, 1994):

Towers and freeways, sites and districts, zones and areas, enclaves and pockets, gradients and
wedges: a landscape without figures . . . Soja’s essay becomes a morphology of landscape that,
like Sauer’s original, is rarely disturbed by the human form . . . Soja’s essay [is] so astonishingly
univocal. We never hear the multiple voices of those who live in Los Angeles – other than Soja
himself– and who presumably learn rather different things from it.
(pp. 300–1)

To Gregory, Soja excluded much of the difference which is supposedly at the heart of a
postmodern approach; he ignored the various social struggles that underpin the making and
remaking of the Los Angeles landscape, plus the distinctive urban cultures of ordinary people’s
everyday lives. Thus, whereas Gregory applauded Soja’s thesis that ‘it is impossible to recover
human geographies from a contemplation of their abstract geometries’ (p. 304), nevertheless he
concluded that Soja ‘renders the landscape of Los Angeles as a still life’. Soja had demonstrated that
‘postmodernism can have an insistently critical edge’ (Gregory, 1990, p. 312), but there is a
clear hermeneutic problem in his work: ‘his master-narrative is sometimes so authoritarian that it
drowns out the voices of other people engaged in making their own human geographies’. Indeed,
according to Nancy Duncan (1996, p. 443) Soja’s ‘goal of reconstructing geography along
postmodernist lines . . . belies the fact that Soja is not really postmodernist!’.
Dear’s work has also attracted considerable criticism, notably a paper on ‘Postmodern
urbanism’ (Dear and Flusty, 1998), which also uses the case of Los Angeles – and the work of a ‘Los
Angeles School’ of urbanists (which they contrast with the ‘Chicago School’ of the 1920s–1940s)
– to argue that a new form of urbanism is emerging. They contrasted five features of ‘modern’
townscapes (those analysed by the Chicago school) – mega-structural bigness; straight-space;
rational order and flexibility; hardness and opacity; discontinuous serial vision – with five charac-
teristics of their postmodern successors: quaintspace (or cuteness); textured façades; stylishness;
reconnection with the local; and pedestrian–automobile split. They then identify ten features
of ‘Southern Californian urbanisms’ which are synthesised into a ‘theory’ of protopostmodern
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 251

urbanism: globalisation and restructuring are generating both political–economic polarisation


and cultures of heteropolis (i.e. increased cultural variety stimulated by immigration). Together
these are leading to the development of interdictory spaces – or segregation – and a greater variety
of spatial forms, such as edge cities and fortified enclaves, as well as a new politics of nature. The
result is that:

Conventional city form, Chicago-style, is sacrificed in favor of a noncontiguous collage of


parcelized, consumption-oriented landscapes devoid of conventional centers yet wired into
electronic propinquity and nominally unified by the mythologies of the disinformation
superhighway. Los Angeles may be a mature form of this postmodern metropolis; Las Vegas
comes to mind as a youthful example.
(p. 67)

Nijman (2000, p. 135) offered Miami as an alternative ‘paradigmatic city’ illustrating the
‘fundamental traits and trends’ of the emerging urban system.
Critiques of Dear and Flusty included arguments that they had not identified a clear modern–
postmodern break: ‘The theory of postmodern urbanism is a mixture of the old and the new, of
breaks and continuities. It is indebted to and rooted in modernism, just as Los Angeles is less of the
sheer novelty than its devotees proclaim’ (Beauregard, 1999, p. 398). Jackson (1999) contended
that the contrast with the Chicago school was poorly drawn, given the lack of ethnographic studies
of life in these paradigmatic cities (on which, see Amin and Thrift, 2002). Sui (1999) went further,
arguing that postmodernism was likely to lead geographers into a new ‘Dark Age of intellectual
inquiry’ because of its ‘assumed or implied ontological relativism, epistemological nihilism, and
methodological neologism’ (p. 408; see also Symanski, 1994). Dear and Flusty’s (1999) response
not only defended their position against Beauregard and Jackson’s criticisms but also argued –
contra Sui – that postmodernism will not go away (p. 415): ‘To encompass the full richness of
urban life requires much more work and that we invent new ways of writing, because conventional
academic writing is singularly ill-equipped for this task.’
More generally, Michael Dear (1994b, p. 299) has argued that postmodernism has encountered
such hostility from those geographers (as it has within other disciplines too) who

perceived their intellectual authority being threatened; [plus] incomprehension on the part of
those who (for whatever reason) failed to negotiate its arcane jargon; and the indifference of a
majority who ignored what was presumably perceived as the latest fad . . . [yet] despite the
combined armies of antipathy and inertia, postmodernism has flourished.

In some cases, it seems, the debate has been conducted in highly personal terms (Dear, 2001).
To others, it is just a reflection of changes in not only theoretical positions but also substantive
concerns (see, for example, Peach’s, 2002 comparisons of the ‘old’ and the ‘new’ cultural
geography). For Nicholls (2011) the ‘LA School’ had not only been an exponent of ‘postmodern’
urbanism, but had integrated Marxist and poststructuralist theories (another ‘post’ trend in human
geography) to create a distinctive analytical framework. Whatever the language and concerns,
however, by the end of the twentieth century, new textbooks (in the classic Kuhnian sense) came to
see postmodernism as an integral part of ‘new theories, new geographies’ (Hubbard et al., 2002).

Time–space compression and landscapes of postmodernity


Other geographical work considering postmodernism and putatively postmodern landscapes
explored a diversity of postmodernisms, refusing to draw clear boundaries around who or what is
or is not ‘postmodern’ (Amin and Thrift, 2002; Dear 2000; Dear and Flusty, 2002). Leaving aside
252 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

who and what is and is not ‘really’ modern or postmodern (for it should be clear that these
terms are contested and defined with reference to each other), the most influential geographical
treatment of postmodernism turned out to be a wide-ranging critique of it launched by
Harvey (1989a) in The Condition of Postmodernity (on which, see Harvey, 2002). This soon became an
academic bestseller: Neil Smith (2001, p. 10) notes that it ‘went on to sell almost 100,000 copies
in various languages, was widely influential throughout the social sciences and humanities, and
was voted one of the best 100 books of the second half of the twentieth century by the
New Statesman/New Society’.
Harvey drew on his prior Marxist work (see Chapter 6) on the dynamics of capitalism to argue
that the epoch and phenomenon of postmodernism was less a break with the modernism that had
supposedly gone before and instead might be interpreted as a variant on a old theme. Harvey’s basic
thesis on postmodernism is clearly expressed in his brief summary page, entitled ‘The argument’,
which is reproduced here in full:

There has been a sea-change in cultural as well as in political-economic practices since around
1972.
  This sea-change is bound up with the emergence of new dominant ways in which we experience
space and time.
  While simultaneity in the shifting dimensions of time and space is no proof of necessary or
causal connection, strong a priori grounds can be adduced for the proposition that there is some
kind of necessary relation between the rise of postmodernist cultural forms, the emergence of
more flexible modes of capital accumulation, and a new round of ‘time–space compression’ in
the organization of capitalism.
  But these changes, when set against the basic rules of capitalistic accumulation, appear more
as shifts in surface appearance rather than as signs of the emergence of some entirely new
postcapitalist or even postindustrial society.
(p. vii)

The observed changes, especially but not only in modes of economic organisation and
much facilitated by technological changes (notably, but not only, in information technology), are
the outcomes of the processes of continual restructuring by which capitalism seeks to overcome
crisis tendencies (on which see Harvey, 1982; Harvey and Scott, 1989; their term for this
restructuring was ‘flexible accumulation’) and within which cultural forms are produced and
reproduced (as set out in Harvey, 1985c). For Harvey, geography matters in understanding the
arrival of a postmodern epoch, style or landscape. Indeed, the key is the way that capitalism and its
attendant means of production and circulation have compressed space and time in pursuit of ‘spatial
fixes’ to the ever-present capitalist tendency to crisis and over-accumulation (and hence declining
profits). Thus, next to a figure indicating a sense of a shrinking world (see Figure 7.1), Harvey
(1989a) notes:

In what follows I shall make frequent use of the concept of ‘time–space compression’.
I mean to signal by that term processes that so revolutionize the objective qualities of space
and time that we are forced to alter, sometimes in quite radical ways, how we represent the
world to ourselves. I use the word ‘compression’ because a strong case can be made
that the history of capitalism has been characterized by speed-up in the pace of life, while so
overcoming spatial barriers that the world sometimes seems to collapse inwards upon us. . . .
The experience of time-space compression is challenging, exciting, stressful, and sometimes
deeply troubling, capable of sparking, therefore, a diversity of social, cultural and political
responses.
(p. 240)
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 253

1500-18AD

Best average speed of horse-drawn coaches


and sailing ships 10mph
1850-1930

Steam Locomotives average 65mph


Steam ships average 36mph

1950s

Propeller aircraft
300-400mph

1960s

Jet passenger aircraft


600-700mph

Figure 7.1  The shrinking map of the world through innovations in transport that ‘annihilate space
through time’
Source: Harvey, 1989a, p. 241.

Harvey’s assessment of postmodernism identified some positive elements:

in its concern for difference, for the difficulties of communication, for the complexity and nuances
of interests, cultures, places and the like, it exercises a positive influence. The meta-languages,
meta-theories, and meta-narratives of modernism . . . did tend to gloss over important
differences, and failed to pay attention to important disjunctions and details.
(pp. 113–15)
254 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

But he also rejected what he identified as the negative elements, with postmodernism presented
as ‘a wilful and rather chaotic movement to overcome all the supposed ills of modernism’.
Postmodernism, to him, reflected:

a particular kind of crisis within . . . [modernism], one that emphasizes the fragmentary, the
ephemeral, and the chaotic side . . . (that side which Marx so admirably dissects as integral to the
capitalist mode of production) while expressing a deep scepticism as to any particular prescriptions
as to how the eternal and immutable should be conceived of, represented, and expressed.
(p. 116)

And so it gets the balance wrong, because its adherents are unwilling to grapple with the need for
a theory which promotes appreciation of the nature of capitalism and its manifest contradictions,
especially, for geographers, those relating to time–space compression through changed transport
and other technologies and the political strategies which promote the fortunes of people in different
places. The shifts identified in the first sentence of his summary require a dynamic theory of
historical materialism, within which he identified four main agenda items:

1 The treatment of difference and ‘otherness’ (see p. 273, this book) within the dialectics of
social change, thereby ‘recuperating such aspects of social organisation as race, gender, religion,
within the overall frame of historical materialist enquiry (with its emphasis on the power of
money and capital circulation) and class politics (with its emphasis upon the unity of the
emancipatory struggle)’.
2 Recognition of the importance of cultural practices, including the production of images and
discourses, on the reproduction of the social order.
3 Recognition of the importance of space and time in the geopolitics of capitalism, now that
‘Historical materialism is finally beginning to take its geography seriously.’
4 Acceptance that historical–geographical materialism is an open-ended and dialectical mode of
enquiry rather than a closed and fixed body of understandings. Meta-theory is not a statement
of total truth but an attempt to come to terms with the historical and geographical truths that
characterise capitalism in general as well as in its present phase.
(p. 355)

Harvey, in turn, was critiqued. Deutsch (1991) criticised his ‘totalizing vision’ of society, with
aspects of difference merely appended to Marxist theory, and Massey (1991) similarly pointed out
that the book fails to consider the possibility of a feminist interpretation (also see Chapter 8, this
book) of postmodernism (and of the images that Harvey uses to illustrate modernism and
postmodernism in The Condition of Postmodernity). Massey points out that ‘gender is a determining
factor in cultural production’ (p. 51), but Harvey promotes a form of Marxism within which
gender differences can be subsumed. Likewise, Michael Dear (1991b) claimed that Harvey ‘seems
incapable of tolerating difference’ (p. 536) so that ‘The catalogue of different voices that are
consequently denied relevance in Harvey’s discourse is long and depressing’ and his goal appears to
be to ‘dissolve differences’ (p. 537).
Much of the postmodern literature is ignored, Dear argued: ‘Harvey is a much better political
economist than he is cultural critic’. He summarised Harvey’s position as follows:

1 all aspects of social processes can be encompassed within historical materialism; so that
2 no alternatives need be addressed;
3 the shift to flexible accumulation accounts for recent social, economic and political changes;
and
4 there is no need for any other theory beyond historical materialism.
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 255

He then concluded that ‘Perhaps it is time that Harvey tried to transform his Marxism, rather than
obliging the world to fit into it’. Harvey recognises difference, but refuses to incorporate it to his
thinking.
In response, Harvey (1992) noted that he was influenced by some feminist writers, and that
incorporation of their insights would have strengthened his book; the work of Young (1990) in
particular had considerably shaped his later work on justice (Harvey, 1993a). He accepted the role
of situation and position in the production of knowledge (see p. 272, this book) but found some
of their applications in feminist work ‘rather more vulgar’ because their focus on individual
biographies is not dialectically placed in an evolving mode of production and because of their
denial of the veracity of other accounts. Thus, his book was written from a particular (privileged,
white male) position and:

emphasized the commonality of our condition as users of commodities and money and as partici-
pants in labor markets and the circulation processes of capital. But emphasizing commonality
does not deny difference. Properly done, it can enhance the understanding of differences at the
same time as it provides a critical basis from which to evaluate the work of those who purport to
write critical theory outside the confines of what capitalism as a social system is all about.
(p. 304)

In this context, he found the critiques ‘unnecessarily personalized, hurtful and sometimes
abusive’ (p. 308), part of a strategy of creating a feminist position which he claims shows that ‘they
exhibit not the slightest hint of concern to grapple with the deeper problematic’ involved with
dissolving gender differences. He wants debate to focus on these and finishes by pointing to a major
paradox regarding truth and generalization in all postmodern writing:

postmodernists . . . cannot criticise The Condition as wrong, misguided, or fundamentally


misconceived without deploying truth terms of their own which presuppose they have an
ultimate line on a truth they theoretically claim cannot exist. I am reminded here of William
Blake’s great aphorism: ‘to generalise is to be an idiot; to particularise is to achieve the greatest
distinction of merit’, which sounds great . . . until it is recognized as a generalization and thereby
self-condemned as idiotic.
(p. 322)

Elsewhere, Dear (1991a, p. 549) criticised both Harvey and Soja, claiming that each rejects the
pluralism and celebration of difference that characterises postmodernism:

By insisting on their totalizing and reductionist visions, Soja and Harvey squander the insights
from different voices and alternative subjectivities. Difference is relegated to the status of an
obstacle hindering ‘our’ view of a coherent theoretical and political praxis.

Trevor Barnes (1996), too, concluded that Harvey’s commitment to what he terms the
Enlightenment project – ‘a belief in rational progress, the individual subject, a monolithic order,
and universal truth’ (p. 3) – runs counter to prevailing trends:

Although [Harvey] wants to recognize that truths are socially constructed at a given moment in
time and space, he also wants to claim that his theory is a valid and accurate representation of
the capitalist world.

Michael Dear’s evaluation of postmodernism’s promise for human geography was unequivocally
positive (1994a):
256 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

Simply stated, we live in an era of postmodern consciousness; there is no choice in this matter,
unless we are prepared to declare in favor of ignorance or the status quo. I believe that a
revolution of sorts is occurring in geographical thinking.
(p. 9)

He supported this last claim by arguing that in the decade since 1984 we had witnessed: (a) a truly
unprecedented increase in quality scholarship devoted to the relationship between space and
society; (b) reassertion of the significance and role of space in social theory and social process;
(c) an effective reintegration of human geography with mainstream social science and philosophy;
(d) the establishment of theory and philosophy as the sine qua non for the discipline’s identity and
survival; (e) a new appreciation of diversity and difference, and a consequent diversification of
theoretical and empirical interests; and (f) a self-conscious questioning of the relationship between
geographical knowledge and social action. He further claimed that a large number of publications
that appeared in 1989 or later ‘reveal a significant postmodern consciousness’ (p. 7) in seven areas:

1 cultural landscapes and ‘place-making’;


2 the economic landscapes of flexible accumulation and post-Fordism;
3 philosophical and theoretical disputes about space and language;
4 problems of representation in geographical writing and image-making;
5 the politics of postmodernity and difference;
6 the construction of the individual; and
7 a realisation of the importance of nature and the environmental question.

This leads him to an optimistic conclusion, provided that geographers are prepared to grapple with
the postmodern challenge:

Postmodernism places the construction of meaning at the core of geography’s problematic. The
key issue here is authority; and postmodernism has served notice on all those who seek to
assert or preserve their authority in the academic or everyday world. And yet I understand that
geographers, like everyone else, cling tenaciously to their beliefs. Knowledge is, after all, power,
and we are all loathe to relinquish the basis for our claims to legitimacy.
(p. 9)

Thus:

To ignore the postmodern challenge is to risk disengaging geography once more from the
mainstream. To accept it is to encourage new ways of seeing, to relish participating at the cutting
edge of social and philosophical inquiry, to convince our peers of the significance of space in
contemporary social thought and social process, and to help forge a new politics for the twenty-
first century.

Many human geographers remained concerned as to how these could be achieved, as Dear
(1995) recognised in responding to an evaluation of developments since his 1988 paper. Elspeth
Graham (1995, p. 175) accepted that in evaluating Dear’s (1994b) claim that postmodernism has
flourished:

If judged by the volume of literature which mentions postmodernism then this is certainly true.
Postmodernism has become the lingua franca of intellectual discourse (Ley, 1993). As yet,
however, few are fluent and communication easily breaks down, inevitably producing a
disturbingly disorganised discussion (a concern also of Warf, 1993).
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 257

Such debates continued (see Minca, 2001) and became tangled up with others; about
consumption and its roles in the (post)modern economy and society (e.g. Gregson et al., 2002;
Glennie and Thrift, 1992; Gregson, 1995; May, 1996a; Thrift and Olds, 1996), for example, and
concerning the merits, possibilities (or otherwise), pitfalls and problematics of poststructuralism
and postcolonialism. But there is possibility here, too, in the startling recognition that all
geographical (and other) interpretations:

are local and contingent, and that any conclusions represent no more than a temporary
hegemony of a favoured belief. Such studied relativism makes it a condition of knowing and
practice that we make explicit the conditions and criteria under which knowing is to occur and
decisions to be deliberated.
(Dear, 1995, pp. 179–80)

Such a notion of knowing one’s position has been problematised in poststructuralist (and many
feminist, see Chapter 8) conceptions of the individual a complex and sometimes contradictory or
divided subject. It is to such reconceptualisations that we now turn.

Poststructuralism: power, representation


and performance
Poststructuralism’s geography
We have already noted how for some geographers the fragmented city of Los Angeles becomes a
place to investigate postmodernity. What has come to be known as ‘poststructuralism’ also has its
own geography. It is hard to say where postmodernism and poststructuralism divide – for some, the
latter is viewed as variant of the former. And while Richard Smith (2003, p. 71) warns us that ‘the
term was not widely used in France’ and that the label poststructuralism ‘obliterates the differences
between quite different authors’, Peet (1998), however, begins his account of ‘Poststructuralism,
postmodernism and postmodern geographies’ across the Atlantic, in a city that has at times been
presented as an archetype of modernity:

Poststructuralism and postmodernism in their theoretical guises are very much the direct
products of events in France. In May 1968, a Parisian alliance of student agitators and working-
class militants rose in spontaneous revolutionary upheaval. It seemed for a short while that the
dreams of radical modernism were about to be realized in their ultimately radical, social-
anarchistic form (worker self-management, participatory democracy . . . ). But the eventual,
eternal return of bourgeois rational normalcy to Paris began a period of contemplative reaction
on the left. This turned against structuralism and Marxism immediately, hence a series of
poststructural and post-Marxist ideas. But thinkers began also to react once more against
the aspirations of modernism as a whole, hence the postmodern aspect to poststructural
philosophy.
(194–5)

A key concern of ‘poststructuralist’ work has been the issue of struggles over representation:
the complex of linguistic, cultural and symbolic processes which poststructuralists argue is
intimately tied up with (express and constitute) power. Although humanistic geography (see
Chapter 5) and some of the debates about regional geography did raise issues about how language
(and other modes of geographic description) embody, enable and constrain power, poststructuralism
made these a more central concern:
258 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

Pieces of the world . . . do not come with their own labels, and thus representing ‘out there’ to an
audience must involve more than just lining up pieces of language in the right order. Instead it is
humans that decide how to represent things, and not the things themselves.
(Barnes and Duncan, 1992, p. 2)

Thus, writing is integral to the complex and contested social construction of knowledge and
meaning. If the written word is not a straightforward mirror of the world it seeks to represent, but
is itself understood as a complex social creation, several consequences follow (Gregory and Walford,
1989).

1 Severing the assumed mirror link between ‘reality’ and ‘text’ means that reality cannot be
apprehended outside the language used to describe it: the world is always narrated. The texts
that we produce draw on other texts, which are the sources of the images that we are trying to
convey, such as the metaphors that we use to describe the ‘unknown’ (Barnes, 1996). This is
termed intertextuality: meanings are created in a continual transition process from text to text
(Barnes and Duncan, 1992, p. 3):

new worlds are made out of old texts, and old worlds are the basis of new texts. In this world
of one text careening off another, we cannot appeal to any epistemological bedrocks in
privileging one text over another. For what is true is made inside texts, not outside them.

2 Writing reveals as much about the writers, and their position, as it does about what is being
written about. We write, Barnes and Duncan argue, from our own ‘local’ setting; thus the worlds
we represent are inevitably stamped with our own particular set of interests. To understand
critically our own representations, and also those of others, we must therefore know the kinds
of contexts bearing upon an author that makes an account come out the way that it does.
3 All writing involves the use of literary apparatus, such as metaphors and other rhetorical
devices, whose use we must appreciate since they are central to the construction and circulation
of meanings.

These are illustrated by Barnes and Duncan, and in the essays in their edited volume, with reference
to landscape descriptions. Landscapes, following Cosgrove and Daniels (1988, p. 1), may be
‘represented in a variety of materials and on many surfaces – in paint on canvas, in writing on
paper, in earth, stone, water, and vegetation on the ground. A landscape park is more palpable but
no more real, nor less imaginary, than a landscape painting or poem.’ Thus the ‘texts’ to be
appreciated may be produced through the medium of words, drawings, paintings or other media,
or may be inscribed in the landscape itself.
Trevor Barnes and James Duncan (1992) identified three major concepts as central to the
study of representation: text, discourse and metaphor. Text embraces a wide range of cultural
products (p. 263, this book) that involve the author rewriting what has been ‘read’ in a hermeneutic
exercise (p. 189, this book) and is open to a range of interpretations:

the meaning of a text is unstable, dependent upon the wide range of interpretations brought to
bear upon it by various different readers. Similarly, social productions and institutions also
address a wide range of possible interpreters. But those interpreters are not free to make of the
text what they like, but are subject to discursive practices of specific textual communities. Thus
both how we produce a text and how we interpret one depends upon our textual community – on
the language (even the particular form of a language) that we use, reflecting our individual
compositional and contextual positions.
(p. 6)
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 259

Discourses are the larger structures from within which texts are constructed and within which
others are read. They comprise (p. 8):

frameworks that embrace particular combinations of narratives, concepts, ideologies and


signifying practices, each relevant to a particular realm of social action. Between discourses
words may have different connotations, causing people who ostensibly speak the same language
to talk past one another, often without realizing it.

The relationship between a component of the text, such as a word (the signifier), and that to which
it refers (the signified) is a complex social construction, undertaken within the specific textual
community. Thus:

discourses are practices of signification, thereby providing a framework for understanding the
world. As such, discourses are both enabling as well as constraining: they determine answers to
questions, as well as the questions that can be asked. More generally, a discourse constitutes
the limits within which ideas and practices are considered to be natural. . . . These limits are by
no means fixed, however. This is because discourses are not unified, but are subject to
negotiation, challenge and transformation.
(p. 8)

Metaphors are major devices for representing meanings. The world is apprehended and known
through study, which requires a language, or some other form of textual representation, for the
transmission of meanings. Metaphors are extremely valuable, since they provide a means of
describing the unknown using the vocabulary of the known; the unfamiliar is illuminated by
comparing it to the familiar. In much science, for example, the use of metaphor steers the study of
the unknown, providing a framework for its investigation – as was the case with applications of the
gravity model in spatial science (described in Chapter 6 of this book; Barnes, 1996). Understanding
a discourse therefore involves appreciating its metaphors.
If metaphors dominate textual discourse, however, they also ensure instability in the ongoing
transmission of meanings, or the reproduction of knowledge. As Trevor Barnes (1996) argued,
drawing on the work of Derrida:

the meaning of words and concepts (signifiers) can never be directly tied to particular
things (signified). For meaning is derived from a signifier’s position with respect to all
other signifiers in the system [i.e. a metaphor can only be understood in the context in which
it was developed]. According to Harland (1987, p. 135), ‘In Derrida’s conception, one signifier
points away to another signifier, which in turn points away to another signifier, which in
turn points away to another signifier, and so on ad infinitum’. There is no anchor of some
final presence or some ultimate origin point of meaning. Meaning, rather, is always
produced through displacement and deferral, shaped as much by what is absent as by what is
present.
(p. 166)

If meaning can only be conveyed through ‘an orchestration of signifiers’ (metaphors),


therefore, then we are led ‘to deny identification of an unimpeachable presence. For, if there is no
ultimate signified and only a shifting system of signifiers . . . there can only ever be the flux of
meaning and no constant presence’ (Barnes, 1996, p. 166).
Hubbard et al. (2002) similarly registered the developing impacts of Derrida in geography
and how ‘deconstruction’ (which also refuses to recognise any clear distinction between the
metaphorical and the literal) opens up the meanings of geography:
260 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

For Derrida, when we describe something as having a certain characteristic (‘x’), we inevitably
recognize that it lacks another characteristic (i.e. is not ‘y’) and we are able to speak the
difference between these (so that one becomes deemed as lacking in relation to the other: ‘x’ >
‘y’) . . . language is a play of signifiers that cannot articulate absolute difference, only lack or
excess. The implication of Derrida’s thinking is that the meaning of texts can never be [definitively]
pinned down; language is seen to defer, rather than yield, truth and meaning.
(p. 87)

They illustrated this through looking up the word ‘geography’ in the Oxford English Dictionary. They
note that it contains three definitions (referring to places, area and arrangement). In turn, they look
up the words (such as climate) that crop up in one of these definitions, only to find that each also
has several meanings:

Tracking through the dictionary highlights how meaning is always intertextually deferred, always
reliant on words that are themselves reliant on others and so on. Only when located in discourse
and grounded in context do words take on meanings.
(Hubbard et al., 2002, p. 88)

In turn, however, the limits to such contexts are hard to specify. In other words, any geo-
graphical categories that construct boundaries are susceptible to deconstruction, whereby the
boundary is shown to be to profoundly arbitrary and to rest on excluding what is held to belong
(usually difference and diversity) only on the ‘other’ side of the boundary.
Metaphor is not the only device used in geographical writing, however. According to Jonathan
Smith (1996), geographers use four different modes in their story-telling: Romance –
as in biographical narratives of individual and group struggle, especially where it leads to radical
change; Tragedy – as in representations of deterministic systems, many of which involve
prognostications of doom; Comedy – which represents harmony and reconciled conflict; and Irony
– in which the detached observer occupies a superior position. These represent release, resignation,
reconciliation and removal respectively, and in them the author employs one or more tropes, or
figures of speech:

1 Metaphor involves the use of comparisons to introduce concepts, describing ‘the remote in
terms of the immediate, the exotic in terms of the domestic, the abstract in terms of the
concrete, and the complex in terms of the simple’ (p. 12).
2 Metonymy uses technical terms to provide (accurate) descriptions for specialised
audiences.
3 Synecdoche promotes understanding through synthesising the general and the particular to
impart meanings.
4 Irony suggests that representation and understanding are futile, and that general apprehensions
can never be produced.

James Duncan and David Ley (1993, pp. 2–3) identified four major modes of representation
within human geography:

1 Description of observations obtained through fieldwork, which dominated cultural geography


until relatively recently; its underpinning assumption was that ‘trained observation transcribed
into clear prose and unencumbered by abstract theorising produces an accurate understanding
of the world’.
2 Mimesis, whereby the world is reflected in media other than words, as with the mathematical
modelling of spatial science that had little impact upon cultural geography.
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 261

3 Postmodernism, which ‘distrusts and interrogates all meta-narratives including those of the
researcher’ and, as indicated earlier, rejects the search for ‘universal truths’.
4 Hermeneutic interpretation, which acknowledges the role of the interpreter and therefore
rules out mimesis – ‘reality’ cannot be faithfully reproduced.

Yet, however many discrete styles are identified and whatever way they are classified, the
rhetorical styles produced by geographers reflect both the general approach to their subject matter
and the audiences they consider themselves to be writing for – for example, irony is characteristic
of many postmodernists; metonymy (and perhaps tragedy) of many analysts of spatial systems; and
metaphor and romance of the educator seeking to open eyes to the world. Above all, language is
crucial in the construction and transmission of meanings, for, as Barnes (1996) explained:

we can never have direct access to things in and of themselves. This is because in order to
understand those terms, they must already be expressed in language. But if they are part of
language, then their meaningfulness only becomes about through a play of difference among
signifiers, which . . . exclude any fundamental signifieds or presences.
(p. 167)

Appreciation of those meanings involves understanding the metaphors employed (as Olsson,
1980, did when exploring the gravity model metaphor which underpinned his early spatial
science). This involves appreciating the translation process, represented by Olsson (1992, p. 86, and
1991) as distortion, and therefore an exercise in the use of power (see the sympathetic review by
Philo, 1994). Doel (1993), for example, uses irony in his characterisation of the futility of much
geographical writing’s failure to represent the world the author claims to portray, whereas Pred
(1989, 1990) explored a variety of linguistic repertoires (‘words, variable meanings, pronunciation,
grammar, sign-tactical arrangements, rules of interpretation and expressive bodily gestures at one’s
command’ (1990, p. 33)) to show how their production and reproduction are inherent to local
struggles. Further, like Olsson, he has employed various writing strategies in order to ‘subvert the
taken-for-granted (and thereby ideology-riddled and power-laden) nature of the academic printed
word’ (Pred, 1990). This:

seeks to make the taken-for-granted format of representation appear strange and yet
comprehensible, that seeks to make the reader understand and mentally see what she otherwise
might not understand or mentally see, that seeks, somehow, to push through the filter of
preconceptions and interpretative predispositions deeply inset in the reader’s social, biographical
and disciplinary past. Thus, I occasionally resort to chameleon like (mis)spellings, hyphenations
and word-couplings that are de- or re-signed either so as to trigger previously unmade
associations, or so as to convey the ambiguity, the shifting subtleties, the multiplicity of meanings
characteristic of on-the-ground practices and social relations in any place.
(p. 48)

Thus, as Trevor Barnes and Derek Gregory (1997) note, attention to the poetics of geographical
writing is also attention to their politics:

It might seem odd that we foreground ‘poetics’. Some geographers read and write poetry during
their off-hours, and occasionally use it in their books and articles, but there is nothing
conventionally poetic about most contemporary geographical writing. Some critics would say
that post-positivist geographers are among the least poetic of all: that their prose is all too often
stilted, leaden, inflated, and opaque. . . . By poetics we have in mind the interpretation provided
by the anthropologist and cultural critic James Clifford. . . . For Clifford, all ethnographic
262 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

accounts – and, we would argue, geographical ones too – are rhetorical constructions, textual
artefacts that seek to persuade us of their claims through an amalgam of ‘academic’ and
‘literary’ genres. But such accounts are not just texts; they also reach out to wider contexts of
power and resistance, institutional constraint and innovation. . . . Words, as poets and
contributors to this volume know very well, are extraordinarily powerful. We need to use them
with care, with sensitivity, and above all with a critical passion: a poetics of inquiry is thus also a
politics of inquiry.
(pp. 3–4)

Deconstructing maps and critical geopolitics


Of course, geography is not only writing – words-(and sometimes numbers and formulae)-in-
order-on-a-page. Geography also involves mapping. Although it may be particularly evident in the
case of propaganda maps (see Monmonier, 1996; Pickles, 1992), all maps (and Geographical
Information Systems, see Curry, 1998; Pickles, 1995a; Flowerdew, 1998, among the other debates
prompted by the arrival of GIS that were considered in Chapter 4) are interpretations, a point that
was stressed in a series of papers by a cartographic historian, Brian Harley. His starting-point was
that (Harley, 1989):

we still accept uncritically the broad consensus, with relatively few dissenting voices, of what
cartographers tell us maps are supposed to be. In particular, we often tend to work from the
premise that mappers engage in an unquestionably ‘scientific’ or ‘objective’ form of knowledge
creation. Of course, cartographers believe that they have to say this to remain credible but
historians do not have that obligation. It is better for us to begin from the premise that cartography
is seldom what cartographers say it is.
(p. 1)

Cartographers’ ‘scientistic rhetoric’ was becoming more strident with the development of
computer-assisted map-making, he claimed, but he used deconstruction procedures ‘to break
the assumed link between reality and representation which has dominated cartographic thinking’
(p. 2); by ‘reading between the lines’ of maps, he sought to identify their ‘silences and contradictions’,
their metaphors and rhetorical flourishes.
Cartographers have traditionally tended to accept that the objects they wish to represent on
their maps are ‘real and objective’ pregivens. Their goal is to display these accurately, hence their
search for ever greater scientific precision; they can come closer to an exact mirror in their
representation and can reject maps (especially old ones) that fail to conform to their canons of
conforming to the rules. But, Harley argued, the production of maps is governed by cultural as well
as scientific rules. Thus, for example, most societies are ethnocentric in producing maps which have
their territories at the centre of their world, thereby helping to promote geopolitical world views.
In selecting what to show, and what prominence to give it, cartographers frequently employ a
‘hierarchicalization of space’:

it is taken for granted in a society that the place of the king is more important than the place
of a lesser baron, that a castle is more important than a peasant’s house, that the town of an
archbishop is more important than that of a minor prelate, or that the estate of a landed
gentleman is more worthy of emphasis than that of a plain farmer. Cartography deploys its
vocabulary accordingly so that it embodies a systematic social inequality. The distinctions of
class and power are engineered, reified and legitimated in the map by means of cartographic
signs.
(p. 7)
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 263

Thus, partial representations are undertaken ‘behind a mask of a seemingly neutral science’, yet the
‘rules of society will surface. They have ensured that maps are at least as much an image of the social
order as they are a measurement of the phenomenal world of objects.’
If we accept maps as cultural texts, Harley contends, we can interrogate them and come to
learn of their functions within the society for whom they were created. Map-making involves a
series of steps, he argues – selection, omission, simplification, classification, the creation of
hierarchies, and ‘symbolization’ – all of which are rhetorical devices. Cartographic rhetoric is
involved in the production of all maps, and is implicated in the exercise of power:

Power is exerted on cartography. Behind most cartographers there is a patron; in innumerable


instances the makers of cartographic texts were responding to external needs. Monarchs,
ministers, state institutions, the Church, have all initiated programs of mapping for their own
ends. In modern Western society maps quickly became crucial to the maintenance of state
power – to its boundaries, to its commerce, to its internal administration, to control of
populations, and to its military strength.

Thus, mapping became a state business, and the publication of maps became subject to laws
regarding state security.
The map becomes ‘juridical territory’; it facilitates surveillance and control. Maps are still used
to control our lives in innumerable ways. A mapless society would now be politically unimaginable.
All this is power with the help of maps. It is an external power, often centralised and exercised
bureaucratically, imposed from above and manifests in particular acts or phases of deliberate policy.
As a consequence, cartography and cartographers are not just one element in a power structure
(p. 13): ‘Cartographers manufacture power: they create a spatial panopticon. It is a power embedded
in the map text.’ Their power is not exercised over people directly, but rather over the knowledge
made available to them; ‘maps, by articulating the world in mass-produced and stereotyped images,
express an embedded social vision’ (p. 14; Harley, 1992, exemplified this in his essay on the role of
maps in the Columbian encounter with the ‘new world’; see also Schulten, 2001).
Deconstructing maps serves three functions:

1 It challenges the myth that technological improvements ‘always produce better delineations of
reality’.
2 It allows appreciation of the role of maps in the historical processes of creating a socially
constructed order to the world.
3 It promotes the understanding of other texts as the meaning of maps is discovered.
(Harley, 1989, p. 15)

Harley later extended this argument, asserting that ‘As a discourse created and received by
human agents, maps represent the world through a veil of ideology, are fraught with internal
tensions, provide classic examples of power-knowledge, and are always caught up in wider political
contexts’ (Harley, 1990, p. 1). This is illustrated by a range of examples including, for example,
cartographic complicity in racial stereotyping through place-name labelling, and the exclusion of
‘places to avoid’ (such as the shanty towns that are absent from the maps of most South American
cities). Cartographers’ interests, he claimed, are dominated by mechanical issues related to
‘efficiencies’ associated with new technologies, so that the ethical issues of what is and is not
depicted go largely unconsidered.
Harley concluded his 1990 paper by noting that ‘The challenge to and continual crisis of
representation is universal and not peculiar to cartography’ (p. 18). Earlier, he had referred to GIS
as extending the crisis of representation to the crisis of the machine. GIS are new ways of presenting
the world, new texts to be deconstructed to illustrate meanings and power relationships. This
264 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

argument has been taken up by Pickles (1995a, p. 3), who identified as a central characteristic of
all GIS that they involve ‘the production of electronic spatial representations’ of data. Those media
not only facilitate data capture, entry and reproduction and speed up operations on the data but also
allow ‘new forms of representation’.
Thus, like maps and other texts, the use of GIS relies on signs and representations (signifiers
and signified) which call for deconstruction: ‘We are . . . entering a potential new phase of ways of
worldmaking for which we desperately need new ways of wordmaking’ (Pickles, 1995a, p. 5)
because GIS are much more than counting machines with greatly increased efficiency; they are
enabling new ways of representing the world, and hence new ‘realities’, and their use by the
technically skilled involves new power relationships.
For David Gilbert (1996), wider developments of ‘hypermedia’ (within which GIS could be
situated) would allow exactly the sorts of explorations of textual and other media that postmodernists
and others promote:

In a computer hypertext the reader can use a mouse to point and click on a word, and be instantly
taken to related ideas elsewhere in the text. The freedom created for the reader to jump from
place to place, to compare, contrast, or simply juxtapose different elements radically changes
the nature of writing (or ‘authoring’ . . . ) and of reading . . . the hypertext form marks a move
away from a modernist concern for ‘objects, positions, order and stability’ towards a postmodern
emphasis on ‘processes, relations, chaos, and instability’.
(p. 7)

Images (still and moving), diagrams, sounds and other media can be incorporated, allowing a
‘polyphonic’ (Crang, 1992) approach to geographical writing and study similar to the postmodern
novel: the ‘reader’ becomes an ‘active co-author’. For Pickles (2004), the entire world is ‘geo-
coded’, so the boundaries between maps, meanings and the world have become hard to discern.
Building on this (and noting the importance of Harley’s work and the debates about GIS), Kitchin
and Dodge (2007) insist that maps emerge through practices. In other words:

Rather than cartography being narrowly understood as the scientific pursuit of how best to
represent the spaces of the world (focused on issues such as form and accuracy), cartography
becomes understood as the pursuit of representational solutions (not necessarily pictorial) to
solve relational, spatial problems.
(p. 343)

The powers and limits of maps, and of what Pickles terms a ‘critique of cartographic reason’ also
form one of the themes in Olsson (2007). Like other works by Olsson (see p. 189, this book) this
book defies easy summary. According to one sympathetic reviewer: ‘the writing exudes a captivating
playfulness and pleasure . . . the productive questioning of geometric propositions, not their fixing
and binding of terms’ (Pickles, 2007, pp. 396 and 397).
Others have also set out the consequences and possibilities of deconstructive approaches in
geography, in particular through more careful engagement with the works of the French philosopher
Jacques Derrida (Barnett, 1999; see also p. 259, this book) and such approaches (in fertile
combination with Foucault’s work and the legacies of radical geography) have also enabled a critical
reengagement with geopolitical discourses (Dodds and Atkinson, 2000; Ó Tuathail, 1996; Dalby
and Ó Tuathail, 1998) that examines the imagination, narration and scripting of global and strategic
spaces. As was noted in Chapter 2, a ‘political trend’ associated with the birth of geopolitics was
among the six foundational strands of human geography described by Freeman (1961). Geopolitics
rapidly acquired its own trajectory: ‘an enigmatic, shadowy, contested and sometimes shameful
category’ (Atkinson and Dodds, 2000, p. 1). One response however, inspired by poststructuralism,
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 265

has been to interrogate such traditions through a ‘critical geopolitics’ (initiated by Taylor’s, 1990c,
pioneering book). Thus, according to Ó Tuathail and Dalby (1998):

Critical geopolitics bears witness to the irredeemable plurality of space and the multiplicity of
possible constructions of space. Thus . . . it pays particular attention to the boundary-drawing
practices and performances that characterize the everyday life of states. In contrast to
conventional geography and geopolitics, both the material borders at the edge of the state and
the conceptual borders designating this as a boundary between a secure inside and an anarchic
outside are objects of investigation. Critical geopolitics is not about the ‘the outside’ of the state
but about the very construction of boundaries of ‘inside’ and ‘outside’, ‘here’ and ‘there’, the
‘domestic’ and the ‘foreign’.
(p. 3)

Such work has examined both elite (government and state) and popular (e.g. media or cinematic)
geopolitical narratives and the connections between them (Dittmer, 2010; Sharp, 2000).
A similar critical sense of the taken-for-granted spaces of (geo)politics and cartography
informed Martin Lewis and Karen Wigen’s (1997) critique of conventional notions of continents
(Europe distinct from Asia, for example, or the notion of Australia as a continent apart from Asia
and the Pacific); the ‘common-sense’ and naturalised view of the world, which they show to be
historically contingent, rather than eternal and fixed. And while some have wondered if any
rendition of geopolitics (‘critical’ or otherwise) is compatible with a cosmopolitan, multicultural
society (Heffernan, 2000), Ó Tuathail (writing under both the anglicised and Irish spellings of his
name) responded that: ‘“critical geopolitics”: a project that involves commitments, subjectivities
and positions which can be described . . . as a positional geo-politics which “one cannot not
want”’(Toal/Ó Tuathail, 2000, p. 386).

Poststructuralist geographies
While ‘critical geopolitics’ has offered a rich vein of ideas and poststructuralist departures and
others have revisited complex and wider entanglements of power (see the survey by Allen, 2003),
Doel’s (1999) Poststructuralist Geographies: The diabolical art of spatial science retraced human geography’s
trajectory through an avowedly poststructuralist lens:

Letting space take place: that is the ambition of geography . . . geography is simply an inclination
towards the event of spacing. This is not spacing in the paranoiac sense of dissociating one
position from another, of forcing distanciated identities onto space – a tendency that I have
dubbed ‘pointillism’. Rather than a poststructuralism that could get taken up by geography and
geographers, I want to demonstrate that poststructuralism is always already spatial: that it
attends from the off to the ‘difference that space makes’.
(p. 10)

Doel makes clear that his explorations of poststructuralism and geography are operating in the
spaces opened by Marxist geography (he thus engages creatively with Harvey’s work), yet the result
is not reducible to a reworking (or even a post-) Marxist geography. For example, he posits a
‘Deleuzian’ notion of origami rather than socio-spatial dialectics:

the world can be (un)folded in countless ways, with innumerable folds over folds, and folds
within folds, but such a disfiguration never permits one (or more) of those folds to become
redundant, nor for one (or more) of them to seize power as a master-fold. Every fold plays its
part in lending consistency to the thing that is folded and since every fold participates in the
266 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

lending of consistency to ‘something = x’ without ever belonging to it . . . folds cannot be


distinguished in terms of the essential and the inessential, the necessary and the contingent, or
the structural and the ornamental. Every fold plays its part: every fold spays ‘it’ apart. The event
of origami is in the (un)folding, just as the gift is in the wrapping: not as content, but as process.
(p. 18)

The book is subsequently divided into three sections: (a) the space of poststructuralism: a review
of the spatiality of selected writings by Baudrilliard, Deleuze, Foucault, Irigaray and Lyotard; (b) a
schizoanalysis of the geographical tradition – exploring spatial science and the drawing of lines;
and (c) a move to a ‘Poststructuralist geography’. Doel, however, explains that:

Accordingly what I want to achieve in this book is neither a secure identity for poststructuralist
geography, which one or two readers may attest to being the ‘Real Thing’, nor a justification for
reducing the geographical idiom in all of its heterogeneity to the theoretical practices of figures
such as Deleuze, Derrida, Lyotard, Irigary, Baudrillard and Olsson. I hope that my actual aim is
much more modest. I want to participate in generating a different way of feeling about events,
about the world, about others, and about theoretical practice.
(p. 18)

Doel’s book, and similar works by him and his collaborators elsewhere (Doel and Clarke, 1999),
elicited a variety of reactions from hostility to fascination and bemusement. Thus, Peet (1998,
p. 241) labelled it an ‘Amoral geography’: ‘an extreme form of the postmodern position in the
discipline of geography, which does manage to lose virtually all connection with any project of
emancipatory politics’.
Responding to an earlier paper (Clarke and Doel, 1995), in this case on ‘transpolitical
geography’, however, Philo (1994) begins with an observation that:

It goes without saying that papers by David Clarke and Marcus Doel are tricky to read, and that
many readers – whether they would call themselves political geographers, cultural geographers,
urban geographers or whatever – are wary about the effort required to see if anything valuable
can be recovered from them. Questions immediately arise as to whether readers can fully
understand the papers, whether they are indeed supposed to be able to, whether the onus is
deliberately being shifted from the author(s) to the reader(s), and about whether the latter can
ever achieve more than one creative ‘misreading’ after another.
(p. 525)

Philo concludes with a mixture of reservations and possibility:

I . . . would want to be less cavalier than Clarke and Doel in consigning large portions of existing
political geography to the dustbin of outdated or untenable geographical inquiries, but I
nonetheless have sympathy for a paper which is so consistently unnerving and unswerving in its
commitment to finding the ‘holes’ in an established geography . . .
(p. 531)

Philo (1992) had earlier sought to explore the geographies in the influential works of the French
(poststructuralist) thinker Michel Foucault (cf. Matless, 1992). Philo presents this as: ‘Not a matter
of “creating yet another intellectual base to defend” . . . but of stirring another voice into the
richness of recent “geographical” debates . . .’ (p. 138).
Foucault is interpreted as suspicious and subversive of supposed historical (and geographical)
certainties. Foucault’s heterodox notions of order and power (the former as highly contingent to
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 267

different times, societies and places and the latter as diffuse; not something which is simply held,
so much as enacted and exercised) provide us with:

a blueprint for . . . a postmodern geography in which details and difference, fragmentation and
chaos, substance and heterogeneity, humility and respectfulness feature at every turn, and an
account of social life which necessarily brings with it a sustained concern for the geography of
things rather than a recall for the formal geometries of spatial science.
(p. 159)

Moreover:

Foucault’s geography emerges directly from his own suspicion of the certainties (the order,
coherence, truth, reason) supposed by most historians and social scientists to lie at the heart of
social life, and as such I think that it can be adjudged a ‘truly’ postmodern human geography in
a manner that, say, Edward Soja’s postmodern geographies cannot. We might not like this
Foucauldian version of a postmodern human geography, but I think that there is much we can
learn from it, even if we then chose to retain our faith in a more obviously modernist conceptual,
practical, and political geographical project.
(p. 137)

Twenty years later, Philo (2012, p. 496) noted how ‘There are [now] many works in anglophone
human geography deriving nourishment from Foucault conceptually, methodologically and
substantively, including one compendium of essays.’ He argued that the appearance of new material
(both French transcripts of some of Foucault’s lectures and new material in translation) and cross-
fertilisations with some of the more recent currents of anglophone human geography signalled how:

Foucault not only has many of the answers, he still has many of the as-yet little-asked questions.
To me, academic geography is not yet ready to move beyond Foucault; or, if we do move, then he
needs to come along with us as a peculiarly interesting travelling companion. If we recognise
that Foucault is still publishing new work, more so than many scholars still alive, then this
assertion acquires even more force.
(p. 496)

Foucault and other francophone philosophical-historical thinkers (such as Deleuze and


Guattari) were interpreted in another book-length text on Post-structuralist Geography. In this, Murdoch
(2006) reviewed the impacts and implications of poststructuralist theory for human geography,
claiming that:

In the wake of post-structuralism’s incursion, geographers arguably investigate a broader range


of socio-spatial phenomena than was the case previously and do so using innovative research
methods. . . . Writing styles have also changed, with less attention now paid to the scientific
rigour and rather more emphasis placed on the aesthetic and inventive character of geographical
discourses and texts . . .
(p. 1)

Although Murdoch considered both Foucault’s approach to power and variety of


‘relational’ approaches to space, place and nature (building on Massey, 2005), his book also
contained a chapter on ‘Spaces of heterogeneous association’ dedicated to new ways of under-
standing networks (as ‘actor-networks’, comprising complex assemblages of human and non-
human components) and referred to limits of what geographers can know with reference to an
268 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

emerging ‘non-representational theory’. Both of these have developed as significant strands of


poststructuralist influence enlivening human geography.

Actor-network theory (ANT), affect and


non-representational theories (NRTs)
Actor-network theory was first developed in (very broadly poststructuralist inspired) work on the
histories and applications of science and technology (see Law and Hassard, 1999, for a summary).
According to Murdoch (1998) it was:

a useful way of thinking about how spatial relations come to be wrapped up into complex
networks. Moreover, the theory is also believed to provide a means of navigating those dualisms,
such as nature/society, action/structure and local/global, that have afflicted so much
geographical work.
(p. 357)

The study of networks has long engaged human geographers – as in spatial science and spatial
analysis (see Chapter 4). ‘Relational’ spaces had also been explored earlier in humanistic and radical
geographies (Chapters 5 and 6). Actor-network theory (ANT) however, interprets ‘actors’
(or actants as they are termed) as complex assemblages of humans and artefacts:

What ANT [Actor-Network Theory] adds to the more commonplace understandings of relational
spaces is a concern with networks. While the term network is commonly utilised in social
science to describe technological relations, economic forms, political structures and social
processes, ANT uses the term in a way which is quite distinct from such applications. Or rather,
it might be argued that ANT bundles all these network applications together for it concerns itself
with the heterogeneity of networks; that is, ANT seeks to a analyse how social and material
processes (subjects, objects and relations) become seamlessly entwined within complex sets of
association.
(Murdoch, 1998, p. 359)

ANT was soon adopted by geographers interested in cyberspaces and more mundane
technologies (Bingham, 1996; Hinchliffe, 1996). ANT also proved a fruitful means to explore
human-nature interactions (Whatmore, 1999, 2002). Indeed, for Thrift (2000):

all the usual boundaries from which and with which western knowledge is constituted – between
humans and things, NATURE and CULTURE, tradition and MODERNITY, inside and outside –
must be put aside. These divides have made it impossible to see the world for what it really is: a
collection of heterogeneous activities which are constantly in formation.
(p. 5)

Whatmore (2002) draws on ANT to investigate ‘hybrid geographies’, whereby humans are caught
in networks with animals/nature and technologies. In a subsequent symposuim about this work,
Whatmore (2005) notes that her aim was:

To experiment with ways of writing more-than-human geographies that were as imaginative as


they were materialist, at odds with the analytical terms set by a rivalry between political economy
and cultural studies that prevailed during my formative years as a geographer.
(p. 843)
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 269

Such oppositions – like others such as nature/human – have long haunted human geography. For
this reason the ‘more-than-human’ geographies in Whatmore’s work are celebrated by some
readers. Philo (2005, p. 826), for example, celebrates how in Whatmore’s analysis: ‘everything just
gets so entangled, so translated into everything else – the delicate networks of nature and culture,
economics and politics, text and context, discourse, documents and devices’.
ANT was subsequently used in an increasing range of work, from scholarship on the planning
of Sydney’s urban fringe (Ruming, 2009), to the study of waste in Hungary (Gille, 2010), or the
reconceptualisation of landscape (Allen, 2011). Reviewing the expansion of ANT-approaches,
Bosco (2006) claimed that:

as exemplified by the number of books, articles and conference presentations, the


conceptualization of networks provided by ANT has surpassed other more traditional ideas and
theories about networks that have been around in geography for more than four decades . . .
(p. 140)

While Bosco judges that ‘ANT is an excellent framework to describe the complex and mutable
composition of networks of heterogeneous actors’ (p. 143), it is not always seen in these terms.
For one veteran Marxist geographer, earlier radicals (he cites Jim Blaut as an example: see
Mathewson and Wisner, 2005, and Harvey, 2005) ‘said more about space than a thousand
actor network theorists ever could . . . ANT has to be the biggest fraud ever visited on social
theory’ (Peet, 2005, p. 166). ANT did rapidily become influential, however (see the review by
Jóhannesson and Bærenholdt, 2009). Moreover, it has influenced other recent geographical
departures, especially those using terms such as affect, performativity and non-representational
theory (NRT).
Hence, soon after ANT became influential, other strands of broadly poststructuralist work in
human geography emerged. One questioned the validity of notions of (nested or interacting) scales
that had emerged from Marxist geography since the 1970s (see Chapter 6), urging geographers
instead to attend to consider how they might develop a ‘Human geography without scale’ (Marston
et al., 2005). They argue that the literature on scale has been characterised by binaries (place–space,
local–global) and by presuppositions that one side of the binary has more causal force than the
other. As a consequence, certain processes/scales are relegated to the status of a mere ‘local’ case
study:

This is why, we believe, localities researchers more often looked ‘up’ to ‘broader restructurings‘
than ‘sideways’ to those proximate or even distant localities from which those events arguably
emerged . . . thereby eviscerating agency at one end of the hierarchy in favour of such terms as
‘global capitalism’ . . . ‘larger scale forces‘ . . . while reserving for lower rungs examples meant
to illustrate . . . these processes in terms of local outcomes and actions. . . . What is ignored in
these associations is the everydayness of even the most privileged social actors who, though
favourably anointed by class, race and gender, and while typically more efficacious in spatial
reach, are no less situated than the workers they seek to command.
(p. 421)

Poststructuralists also renewed debates about the difficulties, potentials and pitfalls of
geographical representation and contexts (old themes, but given new twists by poststructuralism,
in the 1980s and 1990s, as already noted). In revisiting these, Richard Smith (2003) drew
on Baudrillard, Paul Harrison (2002) on Wittgenstein, and John Wylie (2005) on Merleau-
Ponty; all stressed the (drawing/framing of) limits to (geographical) explanation/representation
of practices. Summing up such departures, Dewsbury et al. (2002) provided the following
indications:
270 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

in the performances that make us, the world comes about. This is about giving space to the event
of the world, to make primary its emergent nature, and to the active role we too play in actualizing
that which happens – we are thinking here ephemerally felt; the desire that lights up a room, the
turning you didn’t take (but which still haunts you), the anxiety of completing the next task. . . .
These are not arcane concerns; they speak directly to our practices as social scientists, to the
way our techniques are attentive to aspects of the world’s unfolding. We are thinking of an
expanded socio-logic, of mobilising other sources of expression (literature, art, performance),
and above all of rearticulating what counts.
(p. 439)

Thrift and Dewsbury (2000) illustrated this via a musical score for a jazz performance
(Figure 7.2), drawing attention to the ‘dots’ in the diagram: ‘those concentrations, those moments
of intensity, events if you like – that allow dead geographies to come alive as they are performed . . .
through the full range of senses – an art of evocation’ (p. 427).
In related terms, work on ‘affect’ raised both the social-spatial relations of emotion – and
spaces of human thoughts/actions embodied via expressions, movement and visceral feelings
(Anderson, 2006; Anderson and Harrison, 2006; Mohammad and Sidaway, 2012; Pile, 2010; Thien,
2005). This work evolved against the backdrop of what Kingsbury and Pile (2014, p. 6) describe as
a growing ‘breadth, depth and maturity of psychoanalytically inspired approaches to geography’.
In McCormack’s (2003, p. 488) terms, affect means ‘the ways in which the world is emergent from
a range of spatial processes whose power is not dependent upon their crossing a threshold of

GRAPH-1-

Cage’s score for Fontana Mix [1958]. The grid Laid over the dots and serpentine lines guides the performer.

Figure 7.2  Cage’s score for Fontanta Mix (1958)

Source: reprinted in Thrift and Dewsbury, 2000, p. 427.


Fonatana Mix by John Cage
© Copyright by Henmar Press, Inc., New York
Reproduced by kind permission of Peters Edition Limited, London.
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 271

contemplative cognition’. In other words, human geography must attend to social forces, human
feelings, actions and movements that are not always explicitly thought through. Considering affect’s
interface with American geopolitics after ‘9/11’, Ó Tuathail (2003) describes how:

the United States is not the only place where the politics of affect loom large and the desire for
revenge and symbolic empowerment abound. Across the globe, from Casablanca to Chechnya,
Bali, Riyadh, and Tel Aviv, suicide bombers are blowing their bodies apart to become temporarily
potent heroic martyrs, unleashing the affect within as deadly violence all around.
(pp. 868–9)

To some extent, these literatures (ANT, perfomativity, affect) have coalesced around ‘non-
representational theories’ (Thrift, 2008), yielding another abbreviated term: NRT. While Barnett
(2008, p. 186) notes how NRT draws on ‘work on the phenomenology of everyday urban life’,
hence suggesting that there might be links with the phenomenological approaches developed more
than twenty years before (related to humanistic geography, see Chapter 5), NRT arguably owes
more to the work of French ‘poststructuralist’ authors Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari (whose
work has also entered geography through other routes, see Bonta, 2007) and a diverse range of
work on performance and philosophy. However, the introductory chapter to a collection-taking
stock of NRT and geography explains that:

non-representational styles of thinking can by no means be characterised as anti-representation


per se. Rather what pass for representations are apprehended as performative presentations,
not reflections of some a priori order waiting to be unveiled, decoded, or revealed.
(Anderson and Harrison, 2010, p. 19)

One widely cited account of the rise of NRT approaches prefers the term ‘more than represent-
ational’ (Lorimer, 2005), signifying all that exceeds and cannot be straightforwardly captured in
geographical representations. However, a more recent ‘interested sceptic’ claims to:

identify the heart of NRT through its insistence on the following: on the practical and processural
fluidity of things (rather than the finished and fixed); on the production of meaning in action
(rather than through pre-established systems and structures) . . . the possibilities of things
emerging surprisingly (rather than being predetermined); on a wide definition of Life as humans/
with/plus (rather than humanistic) . . .
(Cresswell, 2012, p. 97)

Nayak and Jeffrey (2011, p. 291) claim that NRT ‘is still something of a cult pursuit rather than
mainstream practice’ while acknowledging how ‘the fullness of experience can never be reduced to
mere words and sparse representational codes’ (p. 301). They interpret the onset of NRT in
geography as, in part, a reaction to the focus on contests over meaning/representation that was
central to the cultural turn as it developed in the 1980s and 1990s. In their view, much NRT is
thereby ‘consciously written against the representational modes familiar in earlier [work]’ (p. 302).
Situating NRT, however, Nayak and Jeffrey ‘suggest that this work might do better to place itself
within, rather than against, the “cultural turn” ’ (p. 302). For Barnett (2008), the recent growth of
work on emotions, affect and NRT might be overstating the emotional/unconscious in an ironic
reversal of earlier models in human geography that privileged the conscious and rational, whereas
for Tolia-Kelly (2006) much of the consideration of affect in human geography is marked by
ethnocentrism, mistaking white/Western experiences of these as universal and hence valid for
everyone. Such critical reflection on ‘race’, eurocentricity and imperialism (past and present), have
been advanced by postcolonial geographies.
272 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

Postcolonialism: decolonising human geography?


As Chapter 2 charted, geography has long had a close relationship to colonialism and racism. Jane
Jacobs (2001, p. 11838) describes ‘a special relationship . . . between geography and the making of
empires . . . surveying, mapping and description were the frontier technologies’, and Mayhew
(2011b, p. 36) notes ‘a genesis drenched in blood’ for the ‘set of willed appropriations we label
“geography”’. Some radical geographers had drawn attention to this legacy in the late 1960s–
1970s (see Chapter 6), part of the initial demands for a new, more critical geography. Since then,
calls to ‘decolonise’ geography have multiplied.
These demands yielded more explicit awareness of the class, ‘racial’ and gendered backdrop
to geographical work (also linked to the impacts of feminism, which will be considered in
Chapter 8); an enhanced and politicised sense of the ‘positionality’ of the author. Thus, according
to Jackson (1993a):

Contemporary society is characterized by multiple forms of exploitation and oppression, which


suggests that our politics should also be increasingly positional. . . . Those of us who wish to
change the discipline and have ambitions to change the world should start from modest
beginnings, recognizing our own positionality with respect to the fundamental inequalities of
gender, ‘race’ and class. For if those dimensions are a source of power to us, they are as surely
a source of oppression to those around us. If our geographical imagination is to develop in ways
that are genuinely and constructively oppositional, we should begin by changing ourselves.
(pp. 210–11)

Gregory (1994, p. ix) claims that he recognised this need when he moved from the University of
Cambridge to the University of British Columbia (Vancouver, Canada) while writing Geographical
Imaginations. He had to come to terms with what he calls his own ‘situatedness’, clarified to him by
three features of his new home:

1 Canada had a double colonial legacy, linked to both England and France, plus close ties to the
USA.
2 Canada is an ‘avowedly multicultural society’ and many of his students had cultural roots
different from his own.
3 The University of British Columbia was taking issues of gender and sexuality much more
seriously than he had been accustomed to.

As a consequence, he abandoned his first draft of the text and began again, although Guelke (1995)
argued that:

in the text there is scarcely a hint of Canadian culture or intellectual life. This work could have
been written anywhere but Canada . . . Gregory has a desk in Canada, but he has ignored its
artists and intellectuals as thoroughly as any British colonial official might have kept his focus
on London in the heart of Africa. Canada for Gregory is an invisible country and its peoples have
evidently produced little of importance for him.
(p. 185)

However, Gregory claims to have been awakened to issues of positionality in North America, such
as colonial status and equal rights, which altered his stance on the issues and literature that he
addressed without requiring a particular ‘Canadian position’.
For Gregory, a major source for geographers’ appreciation of their own positionality and hence
partial representation of the world (in every sense of the term partial) has been the writing of
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 273

Edward Said, especially his classic Orientalism (Said, 1978), which argued that ‘Westerners’ created
an ‘imaginative geography’ of the Orient as part of the imperialist project. Orientals were presented
by ‘Westerners’ as ‘others’, with different (implicitly if not explicitly inferior) cultures that
contrasted with themselves (for examples and elaborations, see Kasbarian, 1996, and Taylor, 1993).
The Orient did not exist as a straightforward pre-given object. It was imagined by the British
and French in the nineteenth century (an activity promoted by the various geographical societies
which transmitted this view of the Oriental ‘other’ to home audiences: see M. Bell et al., 1995), for
example, in part to promote its colonial dispossession and exploitation (Gregory, 1994, p. 171):
‘Orientalism was an active process of othering, the exhibiting of “the” Oriental in a profoundly
worldly set of texts which, in a quite fundamental sense, made colonization and dispossession
possible’ (see also Gregory, 1995b).
The ‘othering’ of the Orient (and the wider non-West) also provided its residents with a
position from which they could later challenge the imperial and colonial hegemonies, not only
politically but also culturally and intellectually. This includes, for example, the field of ‘subaltern
studies’ whose goal is to enable the voice and recognise the experience of hitherto marginalised
colonial subjects, thereby challenging the intellectual hegemony of ‘Western’ narratives. That
‘Western’ hegemony is based on partial views of the rest of the world, often promoted for political
and other reasons (see Sharp, 1993). Emancipation and exchange requires that such partiality be
countered. Gregory (1994) argued that:

To assume that we are entitled to speak only of what we know by virtue of our own experience is
not only to reinstate an empiricism: it is to institutionalize parochialism. Many of us have not
been very good at listening to others and learning from them, but the present challenge is surely
to find ways of comprehending those other worlds – including our relations with them and our
responsibilities toward them – without being invasive, colonizing and violent. If we are to free
ourselves from universalizing our own parochialisms, we need to learn how to reach beyond
particularities, to speak to the larger questions without diminishing the significance of the
places and the people to which they are accountable.
(p. 205)

Thus, the call for postcolonial perspectives in geography that:

highlight the importance of representing people and places across different cultures, traditions
and contexts but also point to the difficulties of such endeavours. At the same time, postcolonial
critiques stress the need to destablise what might be taken for granted and assumed in our own
cultures, traditions and contexts. So for example, postcolonial studies challenge the production
of knowledges that are exclusively western and ethnocentric by not only focusing on the world
beyond ‘the West’ but also by destabilising what is understood and taken for granted about ‘the
West’.
(Blunt and Wills, 2000, p. 168)

Others, such as Daniel Clayton (2001, 2002, 2011), Jonathan Crush (1994), Eric Pawson
(1999), Jennifer Robinson (2003a, 2003b), Sarah Radcliffe (2005) and James D. Sidaway (2000a)
similarly characterised the possibilities and difficulties of a postcolonial geography, from a variety
of subdisciplinary vantage points. For example, Crush (1994) also specifies what the aims of a
postcolonial geography might be:

the unveiling of geographical complicity in colonial dominion over space; the character
of geographical representation in colonial discourse, the de-linking of local geographical
enterprise from metropolitan theory and its totalizing systems of representation; and the
274 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

recovery of those hidden spaces occupied, and invested with their own meaning, by the colonial
underclass.
(pp. 336–7)

Blunt and McEwan (2002, p. 3) detect a possibility for geography here, in so far as ‘an emphasis on
the spatiality of postcolonial thought can help us move beyond the impasse of thinking [about
postcolonialism] primarily in temporal terms’. While geography has traditionally been associated
with Western knowledge and colonialism, they stress ‘the diversity of postcolonial perspectives in
analyzing space, power, identity and resistance’ (p. 6). Moreover:

Although postcolonialism might not have had much impact on the power imbalances
between North and South, the diverse body of approaches identified as postcolonial are a
significant advancement and offer a great deal to the possibilities of a meaningfully decolonized
geography.

Daniel Clayton (2001, pp. 749–50) suggested the following departures for ‘postcolonial-
geographical lines of enquiry that (variously and among other things)’:

1 seek to document and theorise multiple, contradictory and fragmented spaces of identity;
2 work with postcolonial theory in grounded ways;
3 be attuned to the discordant postcolonial politics of places studied;
4 acknowledge that all studies of colonialism are ‘situated knowledges’ that stem from and feed
into particular sites of study, learning and memory;
5 work at a variety of scales and seek to build ‘middle range’ narratives;
6 treat colonial contact as a two-way and contradictory process;
7 take archives and the past seriously, but use them to question or transform understandings of
the present; and
8 have an anti-colonial effect.

However, for Clayton, this list:

does not amount to some sort of postcolonial template for geography. Rather, we have here the
rudiments of a postcolonial-geographical way of thinking, and one that I think needs to be
explored and debated in much greater depth, not least because there is considerable
disagreement about the appropriate aims and methods of postcolonial studies and the status of
colonialism as a spatial problematic.
(p. 750)

Jazeel (2014, p. 101) wants ‘a postcolonial geographical research imagination to more effectively,
and far less imperially, engage radical alterity’. Offering five pathways for postcolonial geography,
Sidaway et al. (2014) suggest:

1 Narrating the planetary: instead of references to the global, with assumptions of universality,
they focus on ‘grounded genealogies of the uneven co-production of categories, sites and
landscapes’ (p. 6).
2 Acknowledging other postcolonialisms: they suggest the value of work in postcolonial
theology for example, as well the importance of postcolonial scholarship from outside the
Anglo-American mainstreams and in other languages.
3 Planetary indigeneity: calling for further thoughtful engagement with categories, movements
and epistemologies associated with indigenous peoples.
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 275

4 Seeing like an empire: examining the presence and reproduction of imperial ways of thought
and action not only in the West but also with reference to other powers, such as China’s
narratives about its place in the world system.
5 Problematising translations: asking how the translation of geographical terms and categories
invariably involve intersections ‘on imperial ground’ (p. 16).

The arrival of an undergraduate textbook on Geographies of Postcolonialism (Sharp, 2009) might


signify that postcolonial issues had already become part of anglophone human geography’s
mainstream (Sharp examines Western representations of the ‘Other’ and how these shaped European
self-images, the continuing legacies of colonialism and postcolonial theory). But for Joel Wainwright
(2013), the critical moves required to decolonise geography have scarcely begun, and risk being
outmanouevred by renewed links between applied geographical technologies (such as GIS, remote
sensing and surveillance of geodata) and the American military. Moreover, writing from two
territories (Canada and Ireland) that were once parts of the British Empire, Gilmartin and Berg
(2007, p. 120) argued that ‘much of what passes for postcolonial theory in British geography
reinforces new forms of colonial epistemologies and colonial hierarchies, while destabilising their
older forms’. In particular, they complain that not only do geographers in imperial ‘core’ countries
continue to dominate theory production in human geography (including postcolonial theory) at
the expense of those in the formerly colonised ‘peripheries’, but that:

postcolonial geography is dominated by critiques of the discursive construction of historical


colonialism, rather than focusing on the aftermath or continuation of colonialism. This effective
hijacking of the postcolonial within geography means that it loses theoretical force, becomes one
of a long list of ‘posts’ that often alienate geographers who might like to, or already do, engage
with the challenges posed by postcolonialism to the ways in which we construct knowledge.
(p. 123)

In developing this argument, they draw on Derek Gregory’s (2004) book on The Colonial Present. In
this Gregory returns to Said’s (1978) account of Orientalism, since ‘Orientalism is abroad again,
revivified and hideously emboldened’ (p. 18). He argues that this ‘revivification’ became most
evident via the ‘war on terror’ after 9/11, culminating in Western occupations of Afghanistan and
Iraq as well as the ongoing colonisation of Palestine through Israeli settlement. However, according
to Gregory:

– for us to cease turning on the treadmill of the colonial present – it will be necessary to explore
other spatializations and other topologies, and to turn our imaginative geographies into
geographical imaginations that can enlarge and enhance our sense of the world and enable us
to situate ourselves within it with care, concern, and humility.
(p. 262)

‘Race’, racisms and ethnocentrism


Jacobs and Jackson (1996) argued that postcolonialism demands sustained argument with
geographies of ‘race’ and racism. This raises both the complicity of the discipline in the racist
categorisations of colonialism (and all the attendant debates about environmental determinism
considered in Chapter 2) as well as the contemporary whiteness of the discipline (see Bonnett,
1997; McGuiness, 1999) and therefore, in Peake and Kobayashi’s (2002, p. 50) terms: ‘the various
(and often hidden) racist practices and discourses that permeate the epistemological foundations of
geography and the institutional structures and practises that shape our work and environment’. For
them, an anti-racist geography embraces:
276 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

1 research on the geographies of racism;


2 extending anti-racist principles throughout the ‘institutional practices’ of the discipline,
particularly in the classroom;
3 increasing the participation and presence of non-white geographers in the discipline; and
4 linking all of these to activism beyond (but building on insights offered by) the discipline,
academic life and the university.

For these geographers (and others contributing to a 2002, special issue of The Professional
Geographer on ‘Race, racism and geography’) the key would be a less white discipline as well
as a discipline that is more self-critically aware of its historic whiteness (and anti-racist in practice:
Kobayashi and Peake, 2000; Nayak and Jeffrey, 2011, pp. 192–8; Mahtani, 2006; Sanders, 2006).
Echoing the ways that the increased presence, power and visibility of women in the discipline since
the 1970s has played a role in the making of feminist geographies (see Chapter 8), Pulido (2002)
argues that:

We need sufficient scholars to generate an intellectual synergy around race. A similar process
can be seen in feminist geography. Only after women gained access to academia did the study of
gender flourish. Men could have taken the lead, but they did not. Because patriarchy was a
problem for female geographers, they studied it seriously.
(pp. 45–6)

She insisted, therefore, that while white geographers have produced incisive and critical work on
race and that there is no inherent reason why ‘scholars of color are more likely to have more
penetrating insights and analyses’ (p. 45), ‘more people of color could create a “critical mass”,
which currently does not exist’. Thus, a call to change the culture of a discipline that institutionally
‘is nearly as white an enterprise as country and Western music, professional golf, or the supreme
court of the United States’ (Delaney, 2002, p. 12).
And whiteness itself should be seen as a marker of difference, rather than the often taken-for-
granted norm against which supposed minorities (in global terms, arguably majorities) are defined.
Thus, Bonnett and Nayak (2003) argued that:

it is only by understanding such normative terms as ‘white’ and ‘western’– the ones against
which others are defined as exotic – that wider systems of racial privilege can be bought into
view. By making it clear that categories such as whiteness are also the products of racialization,
that they too have a history and a geography and, hence, are changeable, we can help transform
the critique of race and ethnicity from a ‘subfield’ into an essential theme running throughout a
rigorous geographical education.
(p. 309)

Similarly, the ethnocentrism of geography curricula in British schools (Winter, 1997) had attracted
fresh attention – and historical scrutiny (Ploszajska, 1999). More pertinent to much of the other
material being considered in this chapter, however, have been critiques of the ethnographic
assumptions of much of the research on affect, which tend to assume they are universally valid,
across space and time. Challenging this leads Tolia-Kelly (2006, p. 216) to demand ‘distinctly
anti-racist theorizations of emotional economies of  “love” and “hate”’ along with others examining
the ‘racialization’ of affect (Crang and Tolia-Kelly, 2010; Nayak, 2010; Saldanha, 2010; Swanton,
2010).
Almost a decade on from the special issue of The Professional Geographer on ‘Race, racism and
geography’ that had foregrounded the issues, two critical reflexive papers returned directly to the
problematics of race and power in the discipline. In one of these papers, Patricia Price (2010,
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 277

p. 166) asks: ‘what does it mean to be anti-racist if there is no outside to racialized geographies?
How does one go about really doing anti-racist work in a wholly racialized world?’ For Price, it is
both troubling and easy to document ‘the remarkably persistent whiteness of geography’s
practitioners’ (p. 156) such that the growing popularity of work on whiteness in the discipline
might have become ‘a comfort zone rather than a space of truly critical engagement with racism’
that ‘may in fact not simply reflect but also unwittingly act to reinforce white dominance in
geography’.
Also reiterating the point about whiteness of geography (writing from a location in western
Canada), Berg (2012, p. 509) remarks how often white geographers ‘fail to recognize (let alone
contest) the actually existing forms of white supremacy that operate in contemporary colonial
settler and imperial societies in places like Europe, North and South America and Australasia’. For
Berg, this is about more than white hegemony; it is part and parcel of white supremacy. Those white
folk in these societies who disavow racism or seek to disaffiliate themselves from racism also need
to recognise that they are ‘benefitting in very real material ways from ongoing white supremacy’
and that ‘All geographers are invited into white supremacy . . . but not under the same conditions
nor with the same penalties for refusal to enter’ (p. 515).
However, charting the shifts from mapping ‘race’ and ethnic segregation towards geo-
graphies of the social construction of such categories, Claire Dwyer and Caroline Bressey
(2008, p. 7) described how moves ‘to engage more critically with categories of identity and
place testify to the depth and dynamism of current work on geographies of race and racism’.
Meanwhile, ‘ideas about “race(s)” (and their relationship to territorially bounded nations)
remain among the most powerful sources of human identity and division within the con-
temporary world’, in the terms of Jackson and Penrose (1993, p. 1) written early on in
the growth of such work. But although they are often taken for granted, they are social
constructions, ‘the product of specific historical and geographical forces, rather than biologically
given ideas whose meaning is dictated by nature’. Thus, those who speak from a ‘racial’ or
national position are doing so within categories defined by imperial and colonial histories
and geographies – in many cases (notably with regard to racism) from positions of
(often unacknowledged) privilege or, in Berg’s (2012, p. 8) view, ‘from ongoing white
supremacy’. It is still frequently the case that ‘resistance is often couched in terms which do not
challenge such dominant modes of representation’ (Penrose and Jackson, 1993, p. 203). Only
when the social construction of identity is recognised does a politics of identity emerge, whereby
individuals and groups ‘attach significance to certain dimensions and contest the relevance of
other designations’.
The politics of identity, like all politics, is a struggle for power and, as Penrose and Jackson
(1993) argued, ‘takes place within a hegemonic system of social relations’:

at any given place and time positions of hegemony are being employed to exercise and
preserve power [which] . . . includes the capacity to set the parameters for negotiation within any
given society. It also gives the freedom to define ‘difference’ and to enforce this vision through
hegemonic institutions of government, law and education. In a system where ‘sameness’ and
conformity are rewarded, the power to define ‘difference’ becomes the power to disadvantage
and disempower.
(p. 207)

These and other complex geographies of power, domination and resistance (Pile and Keith, 1997),
or ‘entanglements of power’ as one collection (Sharp et al., 2000) termed them, became rich
domains of geographical enquiry since the 1980s. Moreover, the practice of geography, the circu-
lation of its texts and journals, and the structure and sociology of the academic discipline came to
be interpreted:
278 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

as much a product of specific social, cultural and geographical constructions as the taken-for-
granted geographies they [geographers] wish to contest and transform and this affects their
analyses (and their disagreements with each other). Such geographies are always constructed
within relations of power in which some spaces (and ways of understanding them) are effaced by
dominant and hegemonic geographies.
(Berg, 2003, p. 308)

Related concerns, of course, were also evident in the debates initiated by radical geography, as
Chapter 6 documented. And we will return to them in Chapters 8, 9 and 10.

Conclusions
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism and the cultural turn intersected human
geography in complex and intertwined ways and have been subject to a wide variety of definitions,
understandings and interpretations. However, Dixon and Jones (2005) noted how, during the
1990s:

work that labelled itself as ‘post-structuralist’ or ‘post-modern’, as well as a host of concepts


and methods under the heading of ‘social theory’ and ‘literary theory’, were increasingly deployed
as a means of critiquing the ontological presumptions and claims to scientific rigour of what
were then considered to be the dominant ‘paradigms’ within the discipline, namely spatial
science, critical realist/Marxist, and humanist geographies.
(p. 243)

Some geographers voiced concern over what these would mean for the identity and social relevance
of the discipline or drew attention to the degree of fashionability associated with geography’s
‘cultural turn’ (Barnett and Low, 1996; Barnett, 1998a, 1998b; Castree, 1999; Mohan, 1994), and
others condemned the ‘excesses’ of the cultural turn (and associated encounters) for its neglect of
urgent social questions about inequality and social justice or for its lack of application (e.g. Sayer,
2000) and its ‘disciplinary idealism’ (Peet, 1996b). While personally sympathetic to many of its
departures, McDowell (2000) also noted that there was a considerable unease and angry reaction
from some regarding the ‘cultural turn’. Thus, Hamnett (2003) was concerned:

that the rise of a ‘post-modern’ human geography, with its stress on textuality and texts,
deconstruction, critique, ‘reading’ and interpretation, has led human geography into a theoretical
playground where its practitioners stimulate or entertain themselves and a handful of readers, but
have in the process become increasingly detached from contemporary social issues and concerns.
The risk is that much of human geography will cease to be taken seriously in the world beyond the
narrow confines of academe. It will be seen simply as a corner of the post-modern theoretical
playground, possibly entertaining to study for a while, but something which can be safely ignored
while the grownups get on with the business of changing the world, often for the worse.
(p. 1)

Others, notably Don Mitchell (1995), criticised what they see as the reification of culture in
geography’s putative cultural turn: ‘Like “race”, “culture” in itself possesses no explanatory
value. . . . Our goal, therefore, should be one of figuring out how the idea of culture becomes
socially solidified as a thing, ream, attribute or domain’ (p. 113).
Some others might sympathise with Mikesell’s (1999, p. 441) claim that ‘Most of what has
been written by self-styled radical, new, or social-cum-cultural geographers is superficial or worse’;
similar sentiments are voiced by Gould (1999). Yet many welcomed and took pride in a human
Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism 279

geography which is more engaged with (and in some ways contributing to) wider social theory.
Gregory (1994, p. 4) thus claimed that:

Many of those working in other humanities and social sciences have also become interested in
questions of place, space and landscape. . . . Their studies have multiple origins, but they treat
the production of social space, of human spatiality, in new and immensely productive ways.

Gregory went on to state – reflecting a human geography more deeply informed by and situated
within a wider social theory, revealing both a sense of optimism and of limits about what human
geography has achieved – that:

The production of space is not an incidental by-product of social life but a moment intrinsic to its
conduct and constitution, and for geography to make a difference – politically and intellectually
– it must be attentive to difference.
(p. 414)

In complementary terms, Amin and Thrift (2000) argued that economic geography was
currently ‘narrowly specialised’ (p. 4) and drew on only a thin range of work within the
contemporary discipline of economics – what they saw as its ‘certain type of rigour; its emphasis
on well-defined models of limited domains’ (p. 5). Geographers should look beyond those
traditional areas of economic scholarship to the ‘new areas of economic study that are currently
both flourishing and provided a genuine ground for the kind of contributions we can make’ (p. 8).
This stimulated a number of responses, several of which – like Ron Martin and Peter Sunley’s
(2001) – warned against ‘throwing out the baby with the bathwater’ by abandoning contacts with
‘traditional’ economic geography: one of the headings in their response – ‘Beware of vague theory
and thin empirics’ – was repeated by others in a variety of guises. Rodríguez-Pose (2001) warned
of the possibility of ‘killing economic geography’ with a ‘cultural turn overdose’, for example, and
Plummer and Sheppard (2001) asked ‘Must emancipatory economic geography be qualitative?’.
Elsewhere, Plummer (2001, p. 761) argued that increasingly geographers’ ‘visions of the economic
landscape are being constructed on the basis of, at best, vaguely formulated and strictly imposed
theoretical constructs’ which are only evaluated by either ‘casual empiricism or self-selected case
studies’ – leading him to align himself with Markusen’s (1999) query – ‘How do I know it when
I see it?’.
We have perhaps not been able to do proper justice in this chapter to all aspects of the
developments of the last few decades, for we are also mindful of Chris Philo’s (2000) point that:

It is important, I feel, to resist the impression of sitting in some kind of satellite circling human
geography’s cultural turn, claiming the ‘scopic power’ to see clearly all that is taking place but
which others closer by cannot themselves comprehend.
(p. 27)

Nearly a decade later, Philo (2009, p. 466) criticised the ‘conflation’ of the cultural turn,
postmodernism and poststructuralism in textbooks. For example, of the sixth (2004) edition of
Geography and Geographers’ attempt to negotiate these in a single chapter (as in this seventh edition),
Philo argues that:

It would surely be preferable not to run together these theoretical stances, but rather to inspect
them carefully, critically, but sympathetically on their own (really quite different and distinct)
terms, and even more importantly they should not be homogenized as somehow constitutive,
indicative, or derivative of a more overarching cultural turn. To do so risks losing conceptual
280 Postmodernism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism

precision, and thereby evacuating the cultural turn of whatever focus, specificity, and coherence
can be detected . . .
(p. 446)

However, part of the cultural turn (and perhaps postmodernism and poststructuralism)
was the reconfiguration of many subdisciplinary boundaries (epitomised in the scope and
heterodoxy of edited ‘companions’ to and handbooks for economic, cultural and political
geography; Anderson et al., 2003; Agnew et al., 2003; Sheppard and Barnes, 2000) as well as some
inter- and transdisciplinary trends. Hubbard et al. (2004, p. 61–2) provided a useful précis of these
intricate turns – and their limits:

the importance of culture has been seized upon widely across the discipline, with social,
political and economic geographers seeking to undertake culturally sensitive analyses [they cite
Lee and Wills, 1997, as an example of such engagements by economic geographers for instance]
. . . while the combination of the ‘cultural turn’ in geography and a wider ‘spatial turn’ across the
social sciences and humanities might create the semblance of a more fluid, post-disciplinary
landscape, disciplinary boundaries do continue to exist as administrative units within institutions
and within the popular (academic) imagination.

Similar thoughts led Mike Crang and Nigel Thrift (2000) to reflect that:

Within the discipline there has been a burgeoning interest in social thought that has both
extended and pluralized the influences drawn upon by geographers. Beyond the discipline social
thought appeared to be increasingly smitten with a geographical idiom of margins, spaces and
borders. However, this spatial turn was not a cause for disciplinary triumphalism that others
were turning to geography since much of it seemed resolutely ignorant of geography and
geographers as a discipline. Indeed, it seemed at various times to show both deliberate ignorance
of geography while – lest anyone might become chauvinistic or proprietary over the claims of the
discipline – also displaying how limited much geographical thought had been.
(p. xi)

Indeed, their book illustrated the wide range of philosophical and social-theoretical sources on
which geographers and others came to draw in their considerations of space. They identified six
‘spaces’ within this corpus of work: spaces of language; spaces of the self and other; metonymic
spaces; agitated spaces; spaces of experience; and spaces of writing. Furthermore, ‘exotic new
hybrids continue to be produced’ (pp. 24–5), and the interactions among geographers, social
scientists and scholars in the humanities over issues of space and spatiality are likely to increase (see
Merriman et al., 2012), even though many contemporary treatments by the last group are undertaken
in apparent ignorance of geographical interest in such topics (as in Miller and Hashmi, 2001).
Some have since claimed that poststructuralism has been distinctive in demanding:

rigorous interrogation of those core concepts – such as objectivity and subjectivity, center and
margin, materialism and idealism, truth and fiction – that underpin much of modern-day
academia, including the majority of geographic thought and practice.
(Woodward et al., 2009, p. 396)

Yet these more recent developments within human geography share something with those charted
earlier in this book. They were all based on dissatisfaction with what has been, and is being, done
in the name of the discipline, and a wish to change it, at least by adding new perspectives if not by
also expunging some of their predecessors.
Chapter 8

Feminist geography

Geography, could you be my world?


  . . .
  By looking within and without, upside down and inside out,
  Come alive geography, come alive!
(Clare Madge, 1997, pp. 32–3)

In 1984, when feminist geography was just getting going, and when the field was characterised
by a relatively small number of individuals, the WGSG [Women and Geography Study Group,
established in 1980 within the professional Institute of British Geographers] produced the text
Geography and Gender. Aimed at first year undergraduates, this ground-breaking book was
also important for the collective way in which it was written. Rather than being written by one
or two named individuals, the book was written by several people working and writing together,
as ‘a collective’, and has as its ‘author’ the WGSG. Taking their cue from wider feminist
politics, the feminist geographers who wrote Geography and Gender wished both to challenge
the accepted conventions of academic writing (conventions which celebrate and reward the
individual, apparently working in glorious isolation) and to acknowledge the genuinely
collaborative and supportive ways in which feminist geography was emerging in Britain.
(Gillian Rose et al., 1997, pp. 1–2)

To the pioneers of the 1970s, a journal devoted to feminist geography must have seemed a
distant dream. Although the women’s liberation movement motivated many to take action in
the streets, few dared to move that action into the halls of the academy. Yet feminist voices
persisted and slowly gained momentum. And from these modest yet courageous beginnings,
feminist geography has now permeated most, if not all, corners of the discipline and has
become a force that cannot be ignored in accounts of contemporary geographical knowledge.
Our hope is that Gender, Place and Culture – a journal devoted to feminist geography – will
serve to celebrate and consolidate that presence.
(Liz Bondi and Mona Domosh, 1994, p. 3)

Presumably every history of geography textbook written today and each seminar taught on this
subject must contend with the history of feminist geographies, of which the founding of the
journal Gender, Place and Culture comprises a significant event.
(Mona Domosh and Liz Bondi, 2014, p. 1068)

Since the 1970s, overlapping the flowering of humanistic geography, the growth of radical
geography and subsequent postcolonial/modern/structuralist geographies, the issue of gender
has been increasingly foregrounded. Much of this has been led by critical encounters between
geography and feminism; raising issues about the ways that space, place and landscape are
282 Feminist geography

experienced differently by men and women and exploring the power relations related to these
variations. Sexuality and space also become foci of investigation and debate. Thus, human
geographers began to study how and where people experience themselves as sexual beings, in
particular their relationship to categories (such as ‘lesbian’ or ‘heterosexual’) commonly attributed
to different expressions of sexuality. The advent of geographical research on gender and sexuality
reflects wider social changes accompanying the women’s movement in new waves of feminism, the
birth of the ‘women’s’ and subsequently ‘gay’ liberation movements and changing social and
sexual mores in Western society. The increased participation of women in the paid labour force
(albeit often receiving lower salaries than men, notwithstanding equal opportunities legislation
that makes formal discrimination illegal) also produced new gendered divisions of labour. The
sociospatial roles of men and women shifted. These, and the attendant struggles, also shaped what
human geographers researched as the gender division of labour in the discipline itself provided
considerable initial impetus (and has remained a key issue) for feminist geography.
Although for many years and in most places at least half of geography undergraduate students
have been women, more of the research publication and much of the teaching (both human and
physical geography) have tended to be done by men. This is still true in a number of university
geography departments. Long taken for granted, this male dominance (and the wider ‘masculinity’
of geographical scholarship) became a theme of extensive debate and focus of demands for
progressive transformation since the 1970s. For example, in the UK of the early 1980s – a period
when many of the changes associated with the radical and humanistic critiques of positivism made
for a lively human geography – only 25 per cent of graduate students in geography (the data were
for both physical and human geography) were women (Johnston and Brack, 1983). Johnston and
Brack went on to quantify some other facts and trends relating to the relative status of women in
the discipline:

of the 1106 [UK-based] academic geographers identified in this survey, only 126 (11.4 per cent)
were female. Furthermore, the percentage of females obtaining posts has declined. In the 1930s,
16.8 per cent of geographers obtaining their first posts (plus those in post in 1933) were female.
In the 1940s, the figure was 30.4 per cent, but it fell from then on, to 11.6 per cent in the 1950s,
8.5 per cent in the 1960s and 7.9 per cent in the 1970s. . . . Of the 142 geographers who have held
readerships [between 1933 and 1983] only 6.3 per cent were females (the chances of a male
becoming reader were 1 in 7.4, whereas for a female they were 1 in 14). Of the 142 who have
occupied chairs, only 6 (4.3 per cent) have been women.
(p. 110)

Even in those few departments where larger numbers of women entered postgraduate training
and research in geography, they frequently found limited prospects for employment as academic
geographers. Monk (1998), claims that Clark University in Massachusetts – where in the 1920s
Ellen Churchill Semple (see p. 44, this book) spent the later part of her influential career – was an
‘original hearthland’ of women geographers from the 1920s to the 1970s), but nevertheless:
Even though Clark was ‘welcoming’, when the women graduated they found restricted opportuni-
ties. Occupational segregation was quite evident. Realistically, women geographers, even those
with doctorates, could aspire to positions in teacher education institutions, the few women’s col-
leges, high schools, or outside academia. . . . University positions were almost exclusively open to
men.
(p. 28)

In many departments there remains a numerical prevalence of men, particularly in more senior
positions. Introducing a focus section of The Professional Geographer on ‘Women in geography in the
21st century’, Karen Falconer Al-Hindi (2000, p. 701) notes how:
Feminist geography 283

Many women geographers are the only one, or perhaps one of two, in their geography depart-
ments. Some are even the first woman ever hired by their department. I have long felt indebted
to the two women geographers who preceded me at my institution. Although neither was here
more than a couple of years, each had a significant impact on the department and helped make
it a place where I could remain and achieve tenure. While I cannot repay my debt to these women
directly, I can – as can each of us – through strategic participation in the structures of the
academy help to make it more welcoming (and someday perhaps even equally open) to the wide
variety of women and men who are geographers.
(p. 710)

Feminist geography has become a rich field. In addition to frequent papers in all the main
disciplinary journals and the prominent, specialist, journal Gender Space and Culture, there are many
collections and texts. For example, a 1990s text on Methods and Techniques in Human Geography (Robinson,
1998) contains a chapter on ‘Feminist geographies’ among others on ‘multivariate analysis’,
‘generalised linear models’ and ‘categorical data analysis’. Other collections such as A Feminist Glossary
of Human Geography (McDowell and Sharp, 1999), Space, Gender and Knowledge: Feminist readings (McDowell
and Sharp, 1997), Full Circles: Geographies of women over the life course (Katz and Monk, 1993), Thresholds in
Feminist geography (Jones et al., 1997), and A Companion to Feminist Geography (Nelson and Seager, 2005)
bear witness to the wealth of feminist work in geography. One of the more recent of these
collections, Feminisms in Geography: Rethinking space, place and knowledges (Moss and Falconer Al-Hindi,
2008), was keen to stress the range and diversity of scholarship in feminist geography, while noting
that ‘Along its path to the present, one of feminist geography’s arcs has been an active political
commitment, a praxis’ (p. 4). Specialist feminist geography research groups and organisations also
exist in many countries and at the international level (Morin, 2009). Most new textbooks (such as
the ones referenced in the Preface here) have chapters on feminist geography and all the companions
and encyclopedias that we also mention there contain extensive references to the field. At the same
time, references to ‘man and the environment’ that were taken for granted as somehow including
the half of humanity who are female are much less frequent. Papers now seldom say ‘he’ when
referring to an unnamed geographer, but usually write ‘he or she’ or sometimes ‘s/he’. Many
journals require submitted papers to be written in non-sexist language. It was not always so.

The other half


The first paper raising the issue of the relative status of women in the discipline appeared in 1973
(Zelinksky 1973a) – and was penned by a man – although around this time the first papers on
feminist geography appeared in Antipode (Burnett, 1973; Hayford, 1974). Subsequent papers tended
to focus on the facts and consequences of the exclusion and isolation both of women geographers
and of the distinctive geographies of women (for example, differing experiences and uses of urban,
paid work and ‘home’ spaces). The titles of subsequent papers that used terms such as ‘sex
discrimination in geography’ (Berman, 1974), ‘the other half’, ‘geographical study of women’
(Tivers, 1978), and ‘on not excluding half of the human in human geography’ (Monk and Hanson,
1982) reveal the concern to produce a more inclusive human geography. Looking back at this
formative period, Bowlby and Tivers (2009, p. 59) recognise the earlier presence of some women
as geography academics, many of whom ‘found important roles within the geographical community,
and did not question the male bias of its subject content’. In the 1970s, however, a new generation
of women entered geography who had been influenced by a fresh wave of feminism that reflected
wider political demands and social shifts since the 1960s. Bowlby and Tivers (2009) argue, however:

that the development of early feminist geography was not the heroic creation of a few pioneers.
Rather, in many places during the 1970s, women and some men in geography began to explore
284 Feminist geography

the geographies of women, and in time, this lead to the examination of a range of explanations
for the subordination of women and to the development of more sophisticated feminist
geographies.
(p. 63)

Looking back and celebrating the ‘amplification in the range of questions asked – and change
in the nature of some of the questions asked’ by geographers, Susan Hanson (2004, p. 719),
pointed out that:

Certain questions simply were not on geography’s agenda until women began raising them.
Examples are:

• the geography of everyday life;


• the links between unpaid work of caring and work in the paid labor force;
• the impacts of international monetary policy on the lives of women and children;
• the relationship of international migration to child care, domestic work, and the sex trade; and
• women’s role in changing the face of the earth.

Changes in who ‘we’ are has not just enlarged the range of questions asked; it has also helped
to expand the approaches we use in collecting and analyzing data and to alter the nature of the
theories that guide our views of the world.

Early feminist analyses in human geography stressed that the different experiences that
structure women’s views of the world are created in contexts that have a clear power gradient
between the oppressors (men) and the oppressed (women): the collective experiences of men and
women are distinctive and unequal. Thus, the feminist project is necessarily a political one, seeking
to remove the power gradient through emancipatory and other processes. Just as Marx argued that
his project involved the emancipation of the working classes, providing them with the means
to control their own destinies, so the feminist project is the basis for ‘identity politics’ –‘an
emancipatory politics of opposition . . . resisting and challenging the fraudulent claims of dominant
groups’ (Bondi, 1993, pp. 86–7). This calls for ‘consciousness raising’ and transformation, out of
which identities can be constructed and reconstructed (in places) as bases for action. While it came
late to geography, feminism has a long history as an intellectual and political movement and there
are diverse strands of feminist thought and politics. Nayak and Jeffrey (2011) hence preface
the chapter on ‘Feminist geographies’ in their textbook on Geographical Thought with an account of the
longer intellectual (and political) contexts in which feminism emerged. These comprise a series of
‘waves’: the first was a late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century struggle for basic rights of
citizenship – to vote; the second a wider struggle for equality and against stereotypes and
discrimination in the 1960s and 1970s; and the third, more recent wave, focused on diversity,
identity and difference. The impact on academic geography came in the latter part of this second
wave and into the transition to the third. According to Nayak and Jeffrey (2011):

Second wave feminism constituted both a political movement aimed at countering women’s
discrimination in a patriarchal society and an intellectual movement directed towards the gendered
ways in which knowledge is produced. This combination of political and intellectual objectives is
reflected in the emergence of a feminist geography as a distinct field of the discipline.
(p. 136)

By the 1980s, therefore, an engaged and diverse feminist geography had emerged and was
establishing itself as a vibrant domain of research and teaching. According to Linda McDowell
Feminist geography 285

(1986a, p. 151), such a feminist geography project ‘emphasizes questions of gender inequality
and the oppression of women in virtually all spheres of life’, and its goal includes uncovering and
countering such inequality and discrimination within the geographical profession itself (on which,
see that early essay by Zelinsky, 1973b, plus Zelinsky et al., 1982; Jackson et al., 1988; Johnson,
1989). That is part of a much larger task (McDowell, 1989):

to demonstrate that women do matter in geography, and to argue that the failure to take gender
differences into account impoverishes both geographical teaching and scholarship . . . [in
addition] it is not enough just to add women in as an additional category. Feminist geography, as
opposed to a geography or geographies of women, entails a new look at our discipline. It poses
several awkward questions about how we currently divide the subject matter into convenient
academic parcels and also challenges current practice in teaching and research.
(p. 137)

However, McDowell (1993b) also noted how:

As in feminist scholarship more generally, that part of our discipline subsumed under the
heading ‘feminist geography’ has become such a diverse and pluralistic enterprise that it is
increasingly inaccurate to define feminism as a single perspective.
(p. 305)

Refining this a few years later, McDowell (1999) identified ‘the specific aim’ of feminist geography as:

to investigate, make visible and challenge relations between gender divisions and spatial
divisions, to uncover their mutual constitution and problematise their apparent naturalness.
Thus the purpose is to examine the extent to which women and men experience spaces and
places differently and to show how these differences themselves are part of the social
construction of gender as well as that of place.
(p. 91)

Citing her work too, Nayak and Jeffrey (2011) note how:

One of the initial tasks for feminist geographers seems, at first sight, relatively straightforward:
to make women, and issues relating to women, visible within the discipline . . . this was a critical
moment . . . staking a claim within a discipline that had either ignored women or constructed
them as the ‘other’.
(p. 137)

While these concerns remained important, others soon supplemented and sometimes displaced
them. Nayak and Jeffrey (2011, p. 145) judge that this was ‘under the philosophical turn of post-
modernism’. Certainly, postmodern feminism, along with other encounters, theoretical departures
and politics, has produced diversity in feminist geography.

Diverse strands
In the 1990s new encounters between feminism and geography soon led to broader critiques and
concerns. Documenting these for the fourth edition of The Dictionary of Human Geography, Geraldine
Pratt (2000, p. 261) thus noted how ‘Since the late 1980s, many feminist geographers have moved
away from an exclusive focus on gender and class systems. This new phase can be identified as
feminist geographies of difference.’ She identified three characteristics of this new phase:
286 Feminist geography

1 The contestation of gender categories of man and woman. Feminist geography has refused to
take such categories for granted, instead exploring the ways that humans learn to perform the
accustomed roles of being a man or a woman and how these vary across time and space. Such
concern has led feminist geography to be ‘increasingly attentive to the differences in the
construction of gender relations across races, ethnicities, ages, religions, sexualities [the
differing experiences and meanings of gay, lesbian bisexual and heterosexual roles for
example], and nationalities, and to exploitative relations among women who are positioned in
varying ways along these multiple axes of difference’ (p. 261). In other words, the commonality
of women’s position and experiences – something that was often taken for granted in earlier
renditions of feminist geography – is replaced with a more nuanced understanding of the
diversity of what it means to be a man or a woman in different places, among different classes
and ethnicities, and at different times.
2 The resort to a broader array of social and (reflecting ‘the cultural turn’) cultural theory. This
includes both poststructuralist thought and psychoanalysis, seeking a deeper appreciation of
how gender relations and identities (including sexuality) are formed and shaped. While this
has produced a flow of works (and some attention to feminist geography in wider feminist
studies), another consequence of these developments is that ‘theoretical differences
among feminist geographers are more obvious than in the past’ (p. 261). In other words, it is
perhaps no longer appropriate (if it ever was) to speak of a singular feminist geography.
Rather, feminist geographies have come to embody the wider debates and polemics across the
more or less Marxist, poststructuralist and postcolonial positions that earlier chapters have
examined. So, while feminist geography has often had to struggle to establish itself against
sexist and sometimes misogynist dismissal on the part of other geographers, ideological
differences among feminist geographers frequently surfaced (see Valentine, 1998; Johnson,
1994; McDowell, 1990; and Peake, 1994, on different ‘personal’ aspects of all this), indicating
continuing debate.
3 A move towards the concept of ‘situated (feminist) knowledges’. This has meant exploring the
basis of different geographical claims and the diversity of vantage points from which they are
made. While this shares much with a wider postmodernism and poststructuralism in geography
and social sciences, in feminist geographies, it has also led to a stress on what is a stake in
creating feminist alliances across differences of class and ‘race’ (Gibson-Graham, 1994; Jacobs,
1994b).

Pratt illustrated these (and prior) developments through tabulating three strands of feminist
geography that have evolved very broadly in sequence. She described the first phase as a concern
to bring the effects of gender inequality into geography – hence, ‘the geography of women’.
A second strand, influenced by Marxism, sought to theorise these inequalities in terms of their
relationships to the capitalist economy – hence, ‘socialist feminist geography’. Finally, there
had been a wider stress on construction of gendered differences, both of men and women,
straight, gay and bisexual, from different places, classes and ‘races’, hence ‘feminist geographies of
difference’. In the equivalent table published nine years later in a subsequent edition of The Dictionary
of Human Geography (see Figure 8.1) Pratt (2009, p. 247) added a fourth strand that ‘could be called
“transversal” feminist geography’ in which ‘Connections are being drawn in many directions’ and
‘The lessons from the debates about difference have been learnt’ around ‘an ethics of care without
erasing the differences’ (pp. 247–8).
The table in Pratt (2009) was entitled ‘Interwoven strands of feminist geography’. However,
these putative strands do not always divide clearly or neatly at all. For example, Gibson-Graham’s
influential work The End of Capitalism (As We Knew It): A feminist critique of political economy (1996, reissued
2006) was simultaneously Marxist, feminist and poststructuralist.Throughout the many connections
made by feminist geography, the original concern with the sociology of the discipline long endured
Feminist geography 287

GEOGRAPHY OF WOMEN
Topical focus Theoretical influences Geographical focus
Description of the effects of  elfare geography, liberal
W Constraints of distance and
gender inequality feminism spatial separation

SOCIALIST FEMINIST GEOGRAPHY


Topical focus Theoretical influences Geographical focus
Explanation of inequality, and Marxism, socialist feminism  patial separation,
S
relations between capitalism and sedimentation of gender
patriarchy relations in place

FEMINIST GEOGRAPHIES OF DIFFERENCE


Topical focus Theoretical influences Geographical focus
The construction of gendered  ultural, post-structural,
C Micro-geographies of the
heter(sexed) identities; differences post-colonial, psychoanalytic, body; mobile identities;
among women; gender and queer, critical race theories distance, separation and place;
constructions of nature; imaginative geographies;
hetropatriarchy and geopolitics colonialisms and post-
colonialisms; environment/nature
FEMINIST TRANSVERSAL GEOGRAPHIES
Topical focus Theoretical influences Geographical focus
Citizenship; migration; Theories of Global networks and circuits;
nationalism; transnationalism; transnationalism, multi-scalar and multi-site focus
ethnographies of the state; globalization and on connections, relations and
development; political ecology; transversal networks processes; constructions and
geopolitics; state violence; and circuitries; non- disruptions of scale; space of
relations between global North representational theory; exception; borders and border
and global South; material political ecology; Agamben; breakdowns; embodiment and
objects; progressive possibilities political economy; theories connectivity; dispossession
for mapping and GIS; affect and of affect
emotions

Figure 8.1  Interwoven strands of feminist geography

Source: Pratt, 2009b, p. 248.

(and the concern with the hitherto relatively marginal position of women within its power
structures). Blunt and Wills (2000) thus noted how:

While feminist geographies are diverse, they share several common themes. . . . One important
site of resistance is against sexism within the discipline, departments and other institutions of
geography. Resisting the status of detached and disembodied analyses, feminist geographies often
share a commitment to situating the production of knowledge in more embodied and contextualised
ways. Finally, just as feminist theory and politics transcend disciplinary boundaries, they also
transcend the subdisciplinary boundaries within geography, inspiring a wide range of connections
within and between economic, social, cultural, historical, political and urban fields of geographical
interest.
(p. 91)

Some of the early militancy of feminist geography may have been tempered by time, however.
Although her account is of the specific trajectory of feminist geography in Australia, Louise Johnson
(2012) describes how it arrived there in the 1980s, quickly:
288 Feminist geography

Producing critical evaluations of male-dominated geography departments, curriculum, and


journals, feminist geographers proceeded to stake claims in each of these spheres while also
substantially revising the content of geographical research. . . . However, as the new century
dawned, the agenda changed and the anger and urgency dissipated as the broader and university
contexts altered. It was a period of consolidation, as feminist insights and approaches were
focused on key subject areas – such as the home, identity and sexuality – and became more
mainstream.
(p. 345)

She wonders, however, if this work and presence of women in the academy might be ‘an indication
of success or of co-option?’
In the meantime, work on the geography of masculinity displayed how feminist ambitions
to study the gendering of space and the social construction of gender could not be confined to
the scrutiny of women or women’s experiences of patriarchy, since gender is no more solely an
attribute of women than ethnicity is of black people. Feminist geography (and allied work) has
therefore stimulated more attention to masculinity, both within geography as a discipline (the
starting point of much critique, as already noted) and within wider society. Geographies of
performing manhood thus came under scrutiny (e.g. McDowell, 2002; McDowell and Court, 1994;
Nayak, 2003; Peck and Tickell, 1996; Smith and Winchester, 1998; Jones, 1998; Jackson, 1991b) as
well as their relationship to nationalism and the geopolitical (Dalby, 1994; Hyndman, 2001;
Radcliffe, 1996; Radcliffe and Westwood, 1996; Sparke, 1994b) plus the ‘public’ or political sphere
of citizenship (e.g. Staeheli and Cope, 1994), together with work on the diversity of (or ‘new’)
femininities (Laurie et al., 1999). Surveying emerging research on geography and masculi-
nity, Berg and Longhurst (2003, p. 351) pointed to masculinity’s ‘temporal and geographical
contingency’. This contingency has since been illustrated by Hopkins and Noble (2009) and via
an edited collection assembled by Van Hoven and Hörschelmann (2005) on Spaces of Masculinities,
although a review of the latter pointed to the still ‘sometimes tentative state of the art of geographical
research on masculinities’ (Phillips, 2006, p. 552), and Blunt and Dowling (2006, p. 112) argued
that, ‘there is a paucity of research on masculinity and home’ (though see the review by Gorman-
Murray, 2008).

Reassessing histories of geography


The aspiration of feminist geographers is not simply to add a further fragment to the academic
discipline, with the potential for its ghettoisation, therefore, but rather to ensure that a feminist
perspective informs all work within human geography. Feminist geography, according to Johnson
(1989), involved recognising women’s common experience of, and resistance to, oppression by
men, and a commitment to end it ‘so that women can define and control themselves’ (p. 85).
Evaluation of geographical practice will demonstrate that it is ‘sexist, patriarchal and phallocentric’
and will open the way to emancipation, by providing a guide to political practice (Bowlby et al.,
1989). One of the fullest such evaluations was undertaken by Gillian Rose (1995). In a critique of
histories of the discipline, for example, she argued that:

The writing of certain kinds of pasts is legitimated by, and legitimates, only certain kinds of
presents. . . . Traditions are constructed: written, spoken, visualized, taught, lived. . . . Certain
people or kinds of people are included as relevant to the tradition under construction and others
are deemed as irrelevant.
(p. 414)
Feminist geography 289

This is a procedure which, she claimed, allowed Stoddart (1991) to dismiss the writings of Victorian
women travellers (Domosh, 1991a) as outside what he interpreted as the geographical tradition
and thereby irrelevant to any history he might write. Women have been written out of geography’s
history, and not only by Stoddart, so that:

even if we can no longer be certain exactly what geography was in the past, in virtually all
histories of geographical knowledges one apparently incontrovertible fact remains: geography,
whatever it was, was almost always done by men.
(Rose, 1995, p. 414)

Stoddart (1991) argued against the perceived need for a ‘feminist historiography’ of geography
expressed in Domosh’s (1991a) critique of the treatment of women in his On Geography (Stoddart,
1986). He argued that such an enterprise is unnecessary for an understanding of the work of the
small number of women who were influential on nineteenth-century geography: ‘No feminist
historiography is required to analyse their contributions: they looked after themselves, their careers
and their scholarship perfectly well without such assistance’ (p. 485), and to do other is to impose
‘the explanatory whims of an evanescent present on an increasingly distant past’ (p. 486). Domosh
(1991b) responded that women should not be ‘tacked on to the list of heroes’; their particular
viewpoints and experiences should be explored through a feminist approach.
Domosh (1991b) and Rose (1995) thus force us to question the delimitation of geographical
tradition – how it is that which is classified as geography became defined in such a way that its
tradition is so male dominated, a ‘patriarchy’. Citing this work and others leads McEwan (1998) to
comment how:

Stoddart’s delimitation of the discursive boundaries of geography produces a definition that is


both epistemologically narrow and contestable. As Blunt [1994] points out, institutions outside
the academy were [also] important in shaping views of women and their travels, and produced a
wider constituency for geographical knowledge. Rose’s suggestion that a strategy is required to
unsettle the traditional boundaries of geography is both radical and holds out the potential of
producing more inclusive histories of the discipline. The real problem, it seems, in (re)writing
histories of geography lies with the apparent need to position women (and subaltern groups) and
their ‘knowledges’ at various historical junctures within or beyond the ‘tradition’, or within an
alternative ‘tradition’. The fact remains that women travellers, for example, were not
geographers, nor did they define themselves as such.
(p. 373)

Out of these tangles, McEwan (1998) proposes that:

A particular problematic in writing feminist histories of geography has been the apparent
need to claim women travellers in a disciplinary sense, in order that they can be located in the
‘geographical tradition(s)’. A critical feminist approach need not concern itself with such myopic
considerations.
  [for]
  Despite a recognition of their exclusion from the traditions and practice of scientific geography,
however, the experiences of nineteenth-century women [travellers] are nonetheless of relevance
to the histories of geography and imperialism.
(p. 374)

She notes that women were both actively involved in imperialism – in a variety of roles – and
influenced imperial policies as well as making notable contributions (through travel writing) to
290 Feminist geography

imperial discourse. Thus, ‘Their status as writers, rather than their place in “heroic” histories of
geography, lends significance to the works of women travellers.’
Moreover, influenced by postcolonial arguments (see Chapter 7 here), McEwan argues that the
very notion of a Western patriarchal geographical tradition demands deconstruction, which would
show it to have drawn extensively (and often without admitting it) on many others (‘native’ and
women’s labour and knowledges, for example). The question of the role and relative significance of
women’s geographical work in anglophone geography has returned in subsequent debates.
Focusing on its more recent history (especially the period since 1945 that is also our main
concern here), Gillian Rose’s (1993a) major book-length contribution to the debate on the role of
women, masculinity and men within geography (entitled Feminism and Geography) involved the
argument that:

1 ‘the academic discipline of geography has historically been dominated by men’ (p. 1);
2 within the profession, women have often been patronised, sometimes harassed and frequently
marginalised;
3 feminism remains ‘outside the project’ of geography (p. 3);
4 ‘the domination of the discipline by men has serious consequences both for what counts as
legitimate geographical knowledge and who can produce such knowledge. [men] . . . have
insisted that geography holds a series of unstated assumptions about what men and women
do, and that the discipline concentrates on spaces, places and landscapes that it sees as men’s’
(p. 2). Moreover, ‘to think geography—to think within the parameters of the discipline in
order to create geographical knowledge acceptable to the discipline—is to occupy a masculine
subject position’ (p. 4).

This leads her to conclude that the social construction of the discipline of geography is such that it
is now necessarily ‘masculinist’ – it concerns itself primarily with the issues classically of interest to
men (p. 4; see also Pile, 1994). This is not presented as a straightforward conscious strategy, even if
at times it may have been such. Rather, geography has adopted a particular set of positions and
practices which attract both men and women who subscribe, often either subconsciously or by
default, to masculinist positions. Most of her book details the four points of her main argument –
via a series of careful and creative engagements with many of the aspects of and ‘paradigms’ within
human geography that have also concerned us here (hence Rose examines work on landscape, for
example, on spatial science as well as political economy, structuration, locality, and so on). The final
chapter sets out the basis for a feminist approach to geography via thinking about the complexity
and richness of what Gillian Rose terms ‘paradoxical space’, and considers alternatives on which
resistance to the masculinist hegemony can be based.
In part inspired by Rose’s critique, another book-length study (Maddrell, 2009) sought ‘To offer
a new perspective on the history of British geography by focusing on the geographical work of
women from 1850 to 1970’ (p. 1). In Complex Locations: Women’s geographical work in the UK 1850–1970,
Maddrell provides evidence that ‘Women incontrovertibly were “doers” of geography before 1970,
which leads on to ask two key questions: what were they doing? And why does so little of it feature
in our disciplinary histories?’ (p. 6). In answering these, she reconsiders the question of the place of
women travellers in the history of geographical thought, arguing that their work was often more
connected with ‘the interests of state’ (referring to the imperial state, and nineteenth-century British
geography’s close involvement with imperial exploration, discovery and survey) than has been
acknowledged. However, the evidence assembled in her book and argument is a broader one about
the institutionalisation of academic geography in the UK. Maddrell (2009, p. 186) points out that:

Women students played an important role in the demand for geography courses in the 1900s. It
is also significant that the first women lecturers in geography in higher education can be traced
Feminist geography 291

to the foundation of the first geography departments and first formal qualifications in geography.
This can be seen as representing something of a strategic alliance between women gaining
access to higher education (including teaching posts) and the needs of an emerging discipline
within the university sector.

The sheer numbers of women involved in the early history of British geography as a university
discipline have been underestimated and their contributions often marginalised. She argues that
histories of geography need to take more account of these figures, some significant authors in their
own right (especially figures such as Eva Taylor and Hilda Ormsby, who produced historical
and regional geographies: Crowther et al., 1967; Maddrell, 2006), but others of whom many were
university teachers, editors or research assistants whose published record was modest and so has
tended to be forgotten or who are underrepresented in subsequent disciplinary histories – even
those who have excavated geographers’ wartime roles (Balchin, 1987), when British women played
an important part in intelligence work among other key, but often behind-the-scenes roles
(Maddrell, 2008). According to Maddrell (2008, p. 142), such ‘ordinary stories’, ‘provide the warp
and weft of contextual history and there is no justification for these stories to be hidden histories
because they do not fit the heroic traditions found in some histories of geography’. More widely,
however, Maddrell (2009) argues that:

Gender as an analytical concept needs to be more fully incorporated into the historiography of
geography, but this should not depend only on women undertaking a gendered division of labour:
anyone engaging with the history of the discipline should be sensitive to constructions of
femininities and masculinities within geographical discourses and practices, as well as other
axes of difference. Such an approach can only enhance our appreciation of the intricacies of the
detailed tapestry – to use a feminine metaphor – of the history of geography and geographical
ideas.
(p. 339)

On reading Complex Locations, Norcup (2010) in Ward et al. (2010) declares:

Let the book be not only illuminative to the reader about the diversity of geographical endeavour,
but also a reminder to contemporary geographers of how the legacies of the subject being
made today – in an era of departmental closures and short-term contracts – might be written up
or written out in the future. It is about being careful and mindful of all those lives making the
subject.
(p. 396)

Sixteen years before, Gillian Rose (1993b) had pointed to the ways in which feminist work
continued to face marginalisation. She thus pointed out how ‘two recent books discussing – and
thus implicitly constituting – geography as an academic discipline’ either disregard or incorporate
feminist work:

The first of these, Livingstone’s (1992) account of The Geographical Tradition, is a roll call of great
men which completely ignores over a decade of work on gender issues; both the women who
write on gender, and their work, are simply erased as if they never happened. The second adopts
a different strategy towards feminist work; [Tim] Unwin’s (1992) The Place of Geography devotes
one paragraph to feminist work in the discipline, which has the effect of rendering feminism as
just one more, rather small, example of the rich diversity of, well, the geographical tradition: any
possibility that feminism might offer a fundamental critique of the discipline is thus lost.
(p. 531)
292 Feminist geography

Similarly, Mayer (1989) felt that the representation of women in basic human geography
textbooks was still characterised by ‘consensus and invisibility’. While subsequent books describing
the changing structure of human geography (Hubbard et al., 2002; Holloway and Hubbard, 2001;
Peet, 1998) do accord feminist critiques more attention, Cloke et al.’s (1991) earlier and influential
Approaching Human Geography: An introduction to contemporary theoretical debates does not. Instead, they self-
consciously note both the exclusion of geographical debates conducted in languages other than
English (a theme we return to in Chapter 10) and the limited attention that they pay to feminist
geography, ‘and to the very real difference feminist arguments are undoubtedly making to the
theory and practice of human geography more generally’ (p. x). They note that feminist arguments
are at least as influential in human geography – and in some ways more so – than the series of
debates (Marxist, humanist, postmodernist etc.) that their book concentrates on. However, they feel
that feminist geography ‘is itself influenced by and to some degree fragmented into Marxist,
humanist, structurationist, realist and postmodernist approaches’ (p. x–xi). Their wish is not to
‘ghettoise’ feminist geography through according it a separate chapter, on grounds both of its
importance throughout human geography (they say that ‘feminism in geography should surely be
seen as more than just “another” approach’, p. xi) and, because they feel that while men can
meaningfully discuss feminism in geography, ‘at present such discussion is most ably pursued by
women within the discipline who are developing new ways of theorising and practising a human
geography sensitised to gender issues’ (p. xi).
Rose (1993a, p. 3) claims that Cloke et al.’s (1991) position only ‘demonstrates and sustains’
the continued exclusion of feminism, by refusing to address its impact on geography, and thus
relates ‘to the very nature of hegemonic geographical knowledge itself’. Nearly a decade on, Cloke
et al.’s tactic was less sustainable and Peet’s (1998) book on Modern Geographical Thought culminated with
a chapter on feminist theory and the geography of gender. Peet notes the initial close association of
feminist geography with radical geography although, as he goes on to chart the range of debates
that has characterised feminist geography since the 1970s, he recognises that the latter soon
developed its own set of debates and sense of purpose and directions. Although Peet recognises that
by the 1980s there were differences ‘between feminist and masculinist radical geography’ (as well
as ‘between perspectives in feminist geography’: p. 271), he reminds us that while some radical
geography may have been as sexist in its language and assumptions as the mainstream, feminist and
radical arguments were ‘often made by the same people, simultaneously radical and feminist’
(p. 270). It is thus no accident that the earliest papers formulating what became feminist geography
appeared in Antipode: A Journal of Radical Geography that today, according to its guidelines for authors
(appearing on every inside back cover and online), ‘publishes papers which offer a radical (Marxist/
socialist/anarchist/anti-racist/feminist/queer/green) analysis of geographical issues and whose
intent is to engender the development of a new and better society’. There too, in past copies of
Antipode, much of the extensive debate about the relationship of capitalism to patriarchy and the
spaces through which this is mediated can be found.

From the geography of women to socialist feminisms


By the mid-1980s, a rich debate about the relationship between class and gender relations
had developed (see, for example, Foord and Gregson, 1986; Lauria and Knopp, 1985; and
the reviews of the debates in Rose, 1993a, and Peet, 1998). These debates embodied a range
of approaches and positions. Walby (1986) identified five approaches to the study of gender
inequality:

1 the demonstration that it is either theoretically insignificant or non-existent;


2 indications that it is derivative of capitalist relations, and has no independent status;
Feminist geography 293

3 suggestions that it results from an autonomous patriarchal system that is the primary form of
social inequality;
4 demonstrations that it results from patriarchal relations that are so intertwined with capitalist
social relations that they comprise a single system of capitalist patriarchy; and
5 arguments that it results from the interaction of autonomous systems of patriarchy and
capitalism.

Bowlby et al. (1989) showed that the second and fourth of these have been more commonly
adopted among geographers, thus focusing on ways in which patriarchy is structured by
capitalism’s imperatives. Foord and Gregson (1986) adopted the fifth strategy, however, arguing
that although patriarchy and capitalism are empirically linked, they are theoretically separate.
Just as capitalism can be presented as a particular example of a necessary condition (a mode
of production within which economic and social life is structured), with unique individual
instances at separate times and places, so, they argued, patriarchy can be represented as a particular
example of a general condition (gender relations) which also has its time- and space-specific
realisations.
Foord and Gregson (1986, p. 199) argued that the necessary interrelationships between
humans and nature call for a form of social organisation to ensure human survival and social
reproduction, so that ‘all social relations must involve gender, and gender . . . relations will be
embedded in all forms of social relations’. They could not conceive of a society lacking gender
relations, therefore, so that the latter are independent of any mode of production, let alone any
particular instance of it. Patriarchy is a particular form of gender relations, in which men dominate
the processes of species reproduction; empirical work focuses on the nature of that domination ‘in
particular periods and places’ (p. 206): ‘Just as other relations vary and combine differently over
time and space, so too must the practices of which comprise these relations’ hence the professed
importance of studying them within the context of the localities programme, as illustrated by
McDowell and Massey (1984; see also p. 213, this book). The assumption that politics and social
relations could be read-off the socioeconomic characteristics of the locality was, however,
problematised by Rose (1989), who takes into account the roles of unwaged women’s labour and
thus disturbs the assumption that a locality is reducible to the structure of its paid employment
alone (cf. Jackson’s, 1991, wider cultural critique of locality studies).
Similarly, because they regard gender and social relations as semi-autonomous spheres of
activity, Foord and Gregson contended that Marxist and feminist theories could not easily be inte-
grated. Against this view, McDowell (1986b) advanced a class analysis and rejected the notion of a
universal female experience. Biological reproduction is part of the process of capitalist reproduc-
tion, and ‘Patriarchal social relations are further strengthened by the political and ideological func-
tions of the state that has a vested interest in supporting the domination of individual women in
the exploited class by individual men in that class’ (p. 313). The contradiction underpinning the
need to create surplus value within capitalism is thus the source of women’s oppression, not any
necessary gender relations: ‘the social construction of male sexuality and the dominance of family
forms based on sexuality and kinship networks to class societies are historical resolutions of the
contradiction’ (p. 317). Subsequently, McDowell insisted on supplementing regulationist approaches
(see p. 21, this book) with an understanding of the importance of unwaged work (overwhelmingly
performed by women) in the home and the significance of gendered subjects in the (paid) work-
place. In terms of the overall relationships between gender, space and society, Gier and Walton
(1987) took a slightly different approach, disagreeing with Foord and Gregson’s contention that
gender relations are necessary to all social relations:

Evidence from anthropology and history as well as other disciplines indicates that gender has
not always been used to identify male and female sexual difference and its attendant physical
294 Feminist geography

and psychological archetypes . . . . [so that] the very identification of the concept is the product
of human consciousness and human society.
(pp. 56–7)

According to this view, significant gender differences need not always be present (see also Knopp
and Lauria, 1987). Gregson and Foord (1987, pp. 373–4) responded by defending their position
that mode of production and gender relations are ‘distinct and separate objects of analysis which
interlock as particular forms (capitalism and patriarchal gender relations) but not as conceptual
categories’, but were unprepared to admit that this was a preface to the creation of a universal
theory of women’s oppression.
Although some of the earlier work presented as feminist geography involved demonstrating
that women are subordinated and thereby have distinctive spatialities in contemporary societies
(e.g. Women and Geography Study Group, 1984; Little et al., 1988), wider issues were soon
introduced. Pratt and Hanson (1994), for example, moved from demonstrating differences between
men’s and women’s commuting patterns to analyses of how those patterns were exploited by
capital to reproduce segmented labour markets (see Hanson and Pratt, 1995). Indeed, the issue of
mobility and gendered differences in its range and mode continued, albeit redefined and expanded,
by incorporating broader social and cultural geographies of mobility (associated with the ‘cultural
turn’: Law, 1999), including work on the gendered geography of urban fear and danger, and its
consequences for women’s experience and use of space (Pain, 1991).
The variety of perspectives adopted in feminist geography as it broadened is illustrated in
McDowell’s (1993a, 1993b) review articles. During the 1980s and early 1990s feminist geography,
while addressing the discipline’s three main concepts of space, place and nature, shifted from
analyses of gender differences to concerns over the social creation of gendered beings in particular
places, which brings feminist geography (as distinct from feminist geography) closer to the wider
feminist project – ‘the study of the lives, experiences and behaviour of women’ (1993a, p. 161).
Three main themes are identified in the early work:

1 Spatial differences in women’s status – demonstrating ‘man’s inhumanity to women’ (p. 163)
– a largely empirical task that emphasised Western experience and was increasingly criticised
for its ethnocentrism.
2 Gender and place: women and the urban environment, which stressed that most women were
excluded from analyses of urban areas that focused on public rather than private activities, at
scales which were larger than the individual household, and so ignored the gender relations
that underpinned the home, childbirth and the unpaid labour involved in social reproduction
(pp. 165–6):

in common with the other social sciences, geography takes for granted the Enlightenment
distinction between the public and the private, and, implicitly, the gendered associations of
those spheres . . . [which involves the patriarchal assumptions that] women are the angels of
the hearth, to be confined to domesticity preferably in sylvan and suburban surroundings,
while men join the fray of public life in the bustling city centres, returning home for emotional
and sexual solace, and hot meals to fit them for their continuing labours.

3 Patriarchal power, which illustrated the ‘blindness’ of (urban and other) geographers to the
‘embodiment of conventional gender divisions’ (p. 167) in the built environment on both large
(the structuring of urban land-use patterns) and small (the design and layout of buildings) scales.

Thus, gender inequalities were added to the others identified by those involved in portraying
‘unfairly structured cities’ (e.g. Badcock, 1984) as major elements in the reproduction processes of
Feminist geography 295

‘patriarchal capitalism’. This ‘feminist empiricism’ (McDowell, 1993a, p. 174) paralleled concerns
of other geographers for social justice, and stimulated a ‘common focus on excluded or oppressed
groups – be they women, the working class or ethnic minorities – [that] united “radical”
geographers’. These concerns needed to be linked to wider theoretical considerations,
however. McDowell (like Sheppard, 1995) saw a bifurcation within human geography (McDowell,
1993a):

It is perhaps not too much of a caricature to argue that throughout the 1970s and early 1980s
human geography consisted of two phalanxes going off in sharply different directions. In the
early part of the period, the opposing forces consisted of those who held on to mathematically
modelled, rational choice, context-free notions facing the grand theoreticians of structuralism
whose forward march in a single direction admitted women only in the tail position. Despite their
relegation, it was in this camp that feminists found common interests, not least because of its
intellectual and political attraction . . . [nevertheless] Despite an enormous shift over the last
15 years or so within economic and urban geography from a structuralist Marxism influenced by
Althusser towards a geohistorical materialism alive to specificity, complexity and local struggles
. . . gender issues remained marginal to the concerns of ‘left’ geographers.
(p. 174)

Yet in 1989 Susan Christopherson was moved to publish a critical reflection on the ways in
which feminism and feminists still remained outside what she saw as the geographical project.
Feminist empiricism was a foundation for a challenge to the masculinist domination, even
epistemological foundations, of human geography (p. 175):

this diverse set of theoretical and empirical books and papers published throughout the 1980s
succeeded in placing gender divisions on the geographical agenda. It made women and men
visible as both academic authors and subjects, thus challenging the implicit masculinity of the
discipline. It also succeeded as geography, documenting some of the range of variation in
women’s social position and circumstances in different parts of the world and raising questions
about gender identity and place.

It also laid the groundwork for advance on other fields:

this work has enabled more complex theoretical questions about the extent of variety in the
spatial constitution of gender and the specific ways in which the characteristics of masculinity
and femininity vary between spaces, classes and ethnicities to begin to be raised. Thus by the
end of the decade the particular geographic interest in variety coincided with a more widespread
interest in the deconstructionism in social theory to enlarge the scope of the agenda for feminist
geography in the forthcoming years . . .

– in which it was joined by those interested in other sources of difference, such as sexual
orientation (see p. 300, this book) and race.
Notably, feminist work on the intersections of race, class and gender explored how these are
registered in the lives of migrant women workers (e.g. England and Stiell, 1997; Kofman
and England, 1997; Pratt, 1999; Radcliffe, 1990; Stiell and England, 1997), extending socialist-
feminist influenced works on geographies of social class, patriarchy, maternity and childcare
(e.g. Dyck, 1990; England, 1996; Gregson and Lowe, 1994) and the wider reworkings of gender,
class and space (Pratt and Hanson, 1988). In tandem, work on the geographies of children
(Holloway and Valentine, 2000) and on different forms and geographies of illness, impairment
and disability (Butler and Parr, 1999; Imrie, 2000), while not simply reducible to feminist
296 Feminist geography

geography, were certainly influenced by its concerns and methods, and are a measure of its
broad impacts.
Meanwhile, feminist geography itself registered a growing concern with ‘the body’
(e.g. Longhurst, 1995, 2000), both as a subject in space – produced through a variety of discourses
(think of the role of advertising and media representations): ‘in order to understand questions
around sexual specificity, the differences between bodies, women’s social subordination to men,
and the mutually constitutive relationships that exist between bodies and spaces’ (Longhurst, 1997,
p. 486) – and about how geography (in tandem with other Western social sciences) has assumed a
masculinist separation between mind and body:

Cartesian dualism underlines our thinking in a myriad of ways, not least in the divergence of the
social sciences from the natural sciences, and in a geography which is based on the separation
of people from their environments. Thus while geography is unusual in its spanning of the
natural and social sciences and in focusing on the interrelations between people and their
environments, it is still assumed that the two are distinct and one acts on the other. . . .
Geography, like all of the social sciences, has been built upon a particular conception of the
mind and body which sees them as separate, apart and acting on each other.
(Louise Johnson, 1989, cited in Longhurst, 1997, p. 492)

Thus, too, feminist work sought to transform approaches to the study of landscape by relating
it to the way that it is represented (‘appreciated’), in ways that are analogous to the heterosexual
male gaze directed towards the female body (Nash, 1996). And subsequent geographical work
on embodiment owes some of its inspiration to feminism. According to Dyck (2011, p. 357),
the body is framed by the interactions of biology, technology, environment and science with
‘categories of difference, such as those based on perceived ethnicity or gender, which frame
our understanding of appropriate bodily practices in particular places as well as notions of
belonging’. Moreover, concerns about the body as a contested site and for the Cartesian distinction
between mind and body have been challenged in postmodern and poststructuralist feminist
geographies.

Feminist geographies of difference


Although explorations of postmodernism and poststructuralism in geography have sometimes
proceeded without due attention to gendered and sexual differences, the postmodern impulse to
accommodate and give voice to difference has been seen as a possibility for feminist perspectives
and feminist geographies. Building on that foundation involved two other feminist perspectives
emerging alongside the ‘rationalist or empiricist feminism’ (McDowell, 1993b):

1 Anti-rational, or feminist standpoint theory celebrates gender differences and, rather than
present them as unfair or unjust, promotes them and has as its goal the elimination of the
traditional allocation of superiority to everything associated with masculinity. Knowledge is
socially created, in context, so that women’s experiences of, for example, menstruation, child-
birth and lactation lead to the construction of different self-identities from those involved in
masculine experience, which also vary between places, because of their separately constructed
gender relations. Such different standpoints provide a basis not only for understanding but also
for practice, hence the development of various forms of radical feminism, including
ecofeminism.
2 Postrational or postmodern feminism argues that treatment of women as a single category
involves linking together very different groups with separate experiences and needs. Many
feminists initially identified this as a threat to the project, but McDowell argues that the
Feminist geography 297

encounter with postmodernism stimulated a debate about ‘situated knowledge’ which has led
to the situation (McDowell, 1993b) whereby:

geographers sympathetic to the postmodern deconstructive project are . . . reluctant to


abandon gender as a difference that makes a difference, if no longer the difference. The
current aim within feminist geography is a move towards . . . ‘partial’ or ‘situated knowledges’
that recognize that the positionings of white British women in the academy, to take but one
example, are not the same as those of other women, women from different ethnic or class
backgrounds, and that this makes a difference to knowledge construction.
(p. 310)

For geographers, this emphasis on difference within the ‘oppressed’ group raises important
issues regarding the role of place in identity-creation. Knowledge is both local and gendered – and
also linked to other socially constructed categories. Feminists argue that ‘some differences are more
significant than others’ (McDowell, 1993b):

their work demands a theoretical analysis of differences, building up an understanding of the


mutual interrelations of gender. . . . of sexuality, household and family structures and the
political economy of domestic and workplace relations within and between places. It is a
feminism located in a theoretical understanding of differences between women, rejecting both
the transhistorical and cross-class search for the origins of patriarchy that concerned us at an
earlier moment . . . and notions of a cultural feminist essentialism that denies the structure of
power relations between women. It is a feminism that recognizes the existence of a material
world, or women living in different social formations, engaged in struggles in which their
interests may converge or diverge.
(p. 315)

This presents a major challenge to all geographers, who, as this and the preceding chapter have
illustrated, are having to come to terms with a wide range of situated knowledges. Bondi and
Domosh (1992, p. 210) have argued, however, that although postmodernism attacks universal truth
claims and so should sustain feminist arguments, its application has failed to do so because ‘there is
a major impulse within postmodernism that continues a tradition of masculine discourse in which
the stereotyping of women is intrinsic to its operation’. However, both these writers and other
feminist geographers have welcomed aspects of postmodernism. Thus, Nancy Duncan (1999),
writing on postmodernism/postmodernity in A Feminist Glossary of Human Geography (itself a marker
of the vitality of the field) notes how:

Many feminist geographers are attracted to postmodernism’s rejection of REASON as


being gendered, historical and ethnocentric rather than disembodied and neutral, as is
usually claimed. Others agree with postmodernism’s refusal of ESSENTIALISM and the
replacement of POSITIVIST and empiricist theories of representation and truth with a diversity of
viewpoints.
(p. 212, author’s capitals)

Similarly, the emergence of work in a psychoanalytic tradition in geography (see Chapter 7)


was enabled by feminist geography even if it is not necessarily confined to it. The subsequent
evolution of this work, which has intersected with both emotional geography and geographical
debates about ‘affect’ (Bondi, 2005; Curti et al., 2011; Dawney, 2011; Pile, 2010, 2011) have
complex relationships to feminism. But they would be hard to imagine without feminism’s
influence on the discipline. More recently, too, a geographical encounter between the
298 Feminist geography

non-representational theory (NRT) that was described in Chapter 7 (p. 271, this book) and
feminism has commenced. While Bondi (2005):

would suggest that feminist geographers find research informed by non-representational theory
too abstract, too little touched by how people make sense of their lives, and therefore too
‘inhuman’, ungrounded, distancing, detached and, ironically, disembodied. Conversely, those
informed by nonrepresentational theory find feminist work too reliant on cognitive ways of
knowing (including especially individual accounts of experience), and insufficiently ‘transhuman’.
(p. 438)

Colls (2012) similarly registered this uneasy relationship, in which feminist geography and NRT
have tended to regard each other as outside their remit. But she advocates:

positivity as a way of affirming what feminist geography is rather than what it is not in relation to
other ways of knowing and doing . . . of what feminist geographies of sexual difference could be
if, through a critical alignment of sexual difference theory and non-representational geographies,
we begin to question ‘how might non-representational geographies allow us to think feminist
geography differently and to think differently as feminist geographers?’.
(p. 442)

Therefore, while the relationships between feminist geography and the variety of ‘post’ (-modern,
-colonial and -structuralist) geographies that were mapped in Chapter 7 have some-
times been fraught, equally often there are creative combinations and exchanges. Another
useful way to begin to take stock of some these is to focus on feminist methodologies in human
geography.

Feminist methods?
According to Thien (2009, p. 74), feminist geographers ‘have incorporated both quantitative and
qualitative methods, with preferences which have shifted over time’. Thus, by the early 1990s, most
feminist work in geography employed qualitative methods. Subsequently, however, this has been
reappraised:

Quantitative methods are neither absent nor rejected in feminist methodologies. . . . As the
special issue of The Professional Geographer, ‘Should women count?’ [Mattingly and Falconer
Al-Hindi, 1995] exemplifies, quantitative methods are not, in and of themselves, antifeminist;
rather it has been the underlying politics and the epistemological positionings of such methods
within masculinist claims to objective truth which have resulted in feminist critiques.
(p. 75)

Feminist geography’s concern with embodiment encouraged qualitative methodologies


and renewed debates about geographical fieldwork (a debate that was usefully summarised
in Peet’s, 1998, chapter on ‘Feminist theory and the geography of gender’ in his Modern
Geographical Thought), including assumptions about gender and sexuality in geographical field-
work (Cupples, 2002). These related to debates about ‘positionality’ – the vantage points
(class, gendered, national and ‘racial’ formations) from which geographers write and teach (see
England, 1994; the debates between Sidaway, 1992, and Madge, 1993; and McDowell, 1992, and
Schoenberger, 1992, plus Herod, 1999, and other papers in that 1999 special issue of Geoforum).
While such debates were not confined specifically to feminist geography, they were appreciably
enhanced by feminist critiques (see Rose, 1997, for a critical review).
Feminist geography 299

Moves to revive ethnography (participant observation in which the researcher observes and
interacts closely with the society under study; see the articles in a special issue of The Professional
Geographer on critical feminist perspectives: Nast, 1994) as a method in human geography also partly
rested on feminist groundings (Jackson, 1985; Herbert, 2000). At times, there seemed no end to
the potential for feminist geographies to make a difference to the assumptions and norms of human
geography. Thus, quantitative geographies (Falconer Al-Hindi, 2001; Mattingly and Falconer
Al-Hindi, 1995; Rocheleau, 1995) as well as issues such as remote sensing and GIS methodologies
came under distinctively feminist scrutiny. Summarising a set of papers (published in Gender, Place and
Culture) on feminist geography and GIS, Hanson (2002) noted how:

denying one’s connections to, embeddedness in, and complicity with an intellectual tradition
facilitates classifying that tradition as ‘the other’; such denial legitimizes intellectual boundary
maintenance and dismissing the other tradition as irrelevant. Years ago, the idea that feminism
and quantification were incompatible had to be dispelled by feminist geographers carefully
demonstrating how quantitative approaches could support a feminist analysis. Similarly, this
collection of articles effectively refutes the notion that feminism and GIS have nothing to offer
each other.
(p. 301)

At the same time, Mei-Po Kwan (2002, p. 645) sought ‘to reimagine GIS as a method in
feminist geography and describe feminist visualisation as a possible critical practice in feminist
research’.
Feminist geography (again sometimes in affinity with postmodernism and poststructuralism)
also encouraged attention to ‘writing practices’ (Bondi, 1997) and the development of alternative
narrative styles, genres and methods (England, 1994; and see also the reading group engagement
in Bondi et al., 2002). Thus, Gregson and Rose (1997) noted how:

The pre-eminence of the dispassionate, distant and disembodied voice is something which has
been challenged repeatedly in human geography over the past 20 years or so, for example by
those who initiated the first critiques of positivism. Humanistic geographers, for example,
argued that such a writing voice simply could not evoke the creative and emotional senses of
place. . . . Marxist geographers suggested that the supposed neutrality of that voice
served merely to hide its lack of critique of capitalism; it was a voice whose apparent objectivity
masked a conservative and reactionary set of values. More recently, feminist geographers
have also criticized that voice as expressive of certain kinds of masculinities. Particularly in
the academy, where cool and calm rationality is the desired norm of both behavior and debate
(which is not to suggest that this is what actually happens!), to be masculine often means not
to be emotional or passionate, not to be explicit about your values, your background, your own
felt experiences.
(p. 23)

As represented in one of the epigraphs opening this chapter, therefore, the conventional process
of academic writing (which foregrounds the names and therefore authority of individual or
joint authors) was challenged by more collective modes held to be in the spirit of feminist politics.
Thus, two key textbooks of feminist geography were authored by a collective, the Women and
Geography Study Group of the IBG (WGSG, 1984, 1997). Yet Gregson and Rose (1997) detected a
tension for feminist geography here. On one hand, the possibility that to write in alternative,
embodied or personalised positions risks having feminist work which does this being dismissed by
the mainstream. But, on the other hand, the potential and power of a human geography that
explicitly draws on personal experiences and feelings is evident.
300 Feminist geography

Sexuality and space


The intersections of sexuality with gender and class and space started to be mapped in the in the
late 1970s. As the human body became an explicit domain of geographical analysis and influenced
by feminism, by the 1990s a plethora of works considered sexuality and spaces, including a
landmark edited book, Mapping Desire: Geographies of sexualities (Bell and Valentine, 1995). Reflecting
on the preceding decade of such works on sexuality and space, Hubbard (2000, p. 191) thought
that:

Although traditionally regarded as ‘squeamish’ about sexual matters [see too Symanski, 2002]
. . . recent research by geographers has begun to demonstrate that space is inevitably sexed in a
variety of complex ways, placing issues of sex and sexuality firmly on the geographical agenda.
As such, there is now a substantial body of critical geographic scholarship which has indicated
that space is fundamentally shaped by the dynamics of human sexuality, reflecting the ways in
which sex is represented, perceived and understood.

In similar terms, England (1999, p. 95) recorded that:

The 1990s have seen a rapid expansion of published research on sexualities and sexual identities.
Most major English language geography journals have published articles related to sexualities
(although there are notable holdouts). There is certainly no longer a shortage of materials that
can be used to teach the geographies of sexualities although there is a shortage of materials
looking explicitly at heterosexualities.

Where there may once have been ‘squeamishness’ there is now a wealth of material. Gavin Brown
et al. (2011, p. 295) note how:

A quarter of a century ago, early sexual geographers taunted their colleagues for their
‘squeamishness’ about the spatial aspects of sexuality. . . . Today many introductory human
geography textbooks include some reference to ‘gay space’ and the geographies of sexual
difference, and journal articles abound . . .
(p. 265)

Elsewhere, in the introduction to an edited collection, taking stock of Geographies of Sexualities, they
note how ‘the relatively young field of geographies of sexualities has blossomed over the past
decade or so’ (G. Brown et al., 2009, p. 1).
The first papers on sexuality and space appeared at the end of the 1970s and in the
early 1980s (Weightman, 1981). These, and much of the subsequent work on sexuality
and space, focused at first on the spaces and places associated with expressions and geo-
graphical consequences of lesbian and gay male sexuality. Such research and associated
manifestations of lesbian, gay and bisexuality within geography did not establish themselves
without resistance. Citing Carter’s (1977) objections, Michael Brown and Lawrence Knopp
(2003, p. 314) note that in the mid-1970s: ‘The simple act of arranging meetings of gay
and lesbian geographers at Association of American Geographers’ meetings precipitated
extraordinary nasty public (and published) denouncements from established and secure figures
in the discipline.’
Subsequent cases of harassment (Valentine, 1998) revealed continued discord among
geographers over the status and positioning of work on sexuality and those who have fostered it.
However, a critical mass of scholarship and degree of wider acknowledgement of sexuality and
space as a challenging field of study became evident by the mid-1990s. A mark of this was the
Feminist geography 301

publication of that influential collection on Mapping Desire: Geographies of sexuality (Bell and Valentine,
1995). In this and other work that accompanied or preceded it (e.g. Adler and Brenner, 1992;
Brown, 1995; Forest, 1995; Valentine, 1993a, 1993b), the parameters of work on sexuality and
space both work with the early concerns about gay and lesbian spaces (and their experiences in
mainstream ‘heterosexual space’) as well as complementing this with a wider sense of the
paradoxical spaces of sexuality (Bell et al., 1994) and bodies, sexuality and the sociospatial dynamics
of capitalism (Duncan, 1996a; Knopp, 1992). Much of the earlier work was on urban quarters or
zones associated with the gay and lesbian ‘scene’, including the role of gay men as agents in the
wider gentrification of urban neighbourhoods, supplementing established Marxist work on
gentrification (Knopp, 1990). Subsequently, work in rural geographies and on migration was
enriched by attention to the roles of sexualities. Summarising all this, Binnie and Valentine (1999)
conclude that:

geographies of sexualities have come a long way in the last decade. Progress in the study of lives
of dissident sexualities has been most striking, most notably in three key areas: urban geography,
rural lesbian and gay geographies, and the geography of sexual citizenship. In each of these
areas, there have been significant developments in both geographical understandings of lesbian,
gay and bisexual lives and signs that sexual dissidents are beginning to have an impact on the
heteronormative nature of the geographical knowledge.
(p. 182)

The latter proved to be an enduring challenge, to which we will return in a moment. However,
at this point we should add that Binnie and Valentine also noted the unevenness of geographical
work on sexuality (something which has also been evident in terms of the development and
impacts of feminism in geography). In terms of sexuality and space, they note two dimensions with
respect to this. First, ‘the ethnocentricity of the literature on sexuality and space remains largely
unchallenged’ (p. 183); in other words the sexualities and spaces studied had mostly tended to be
Western and white. Second, they note how some subdisciplines have been much more receptive
than have others:

Indeed, there are many areas within the discipline of geography where discussion of sexuality
has been notable for its absence, for example, transport geography and population geography.
The different philosophical approaches that dominate different subdisciplinary areas may
explain the uneven impact of work on dissident sexualities within geography. Geography remains
a highly contested enterprise. While social and cultural geography have been very receptive
towards contemporary developments in social theory (particularly with respect to the postmodern
emphasis on ‘difference’) and therefore towards dissident sexualities, many other fields of
geographical enquiry remain wedded to their positivist tradition. However this does not explain
why the hegemonic sexual identity, heterosexuality, has thus far received so little attention from
geographers.

They note partial exceptions, such as Philip Crang (1995) and McDowell (1995) – both, however,
perhaps better known as social-cultural and economic geographers respectively – amid a relative
lack of attention to ‘mainstream’ heterosexuality. Subsequently, a few geographers mapped
and theorised heterosexuality, notably Hubbard (2000). The whiteness and Western focus
of the first wave of work on sexuality and space remained an issue that concerned some
(Nast, 2002), although that work has increasingly been supplemented by case studies and
theorisations of sexuality and space based on the experiences of non-whites (early examples
include Peake, 1993; Mohammad, 1999; the papers introduced by Puar et al.; Haritaworn, 2009;
and Rouhani, 2007).
302 Feminist geography

Queering geography
Much as feminist geography concerned itself first with the status of women, before turning to
consider wider constructions of femininity and masculinity (and thus men), so the work attentive
to sexuality and space tended first to focus on the relative invisibility of the geographies associated
with male homosexuality, lesbianism and bisexuality in Western society (‘insignificant others’ to
mainstream human geography, according to David Bell, 1991) before turning either to examine
the construction and problems associated with such categories or to the wider geographies of
sexuality – ‘straight’, gay, or whatever. One aspect of this is ‘queer theory’ (representing a subversion
of a hitherto mostly pejorative term) which begins with, but then goes beyond, the issue of
sexuality. Thus, as Elder (1999), a South African-born, white male geographer who worked in the
USA and represented his sexuality as ‘gay’, noted:

I see queerness as a theoretical and personal insistence to study the relationships between
social boundaries (like ‘race’, gender, sexuality and class). Queerness is not only a device for
thinking through issues related to sexuality. It follows that for me the attraction to queer theory
is an obvious one; the language of geography as well as the queer geography that shapes my
daily life. The queer geography that I refer to is learning to perform on boundaries (coming out)
and realizing the consequences and effects of those performances . . . I am not only referring to
the sexual aspects of my identity: I am perceived by students to be too white to be ‘African’ and
too foreign to be “American”. As a condition, queerness captures a delightful sense of unbounded
chaos and uncertainty and it helps me to think about identity.
(p. 88)

For Kitchin and Lysaght (2003, p. 490): ‘Queer theory, a theoretical position founded on
poststructuralist ideas, posits that sexual identity is never fixed, but is always in the process of becom-
ing  . . .  it critiques the notion of being able to draw coherent boundaries around sexual identities.’
What role, then, possibly for a queer geography?

[—] an extension of queer theory suggests that, given . . . that all space is sexed, all space is
inherently queered and it is only ever temporarily fixed as heterosexual (or homosexual for that
matter). That is, the sexing of space is in a constant process of ‘becoming’, created through the
(re)production of (sexual) discourse and practice.
(p. 491)

In turn, however, for others too sexuality (be it ‘queer’ or not) is, like the gender relations of which
it forms a part, seen to be caught up with wider economic, social, cultural and political geographies.
For Hubbard (2000), this was:

beginning (belatedly) to clarify the importance of heterosexuality in maintaining and reproducing


geographical order, particularly in their attempts to elucidate the importance of domestic space
in maintaining the ‘family values’ which lie at the heart of heteronormality.
(p. 211)

Geography as a discipline has also been seen as embodying similar heteronormality, an often
taken-for-granted assumption that the spaces and lives we study and the outlook of the geographers
who do the studies are ‘straight’. This led Binnie (1997) to ask the following questions:

How have systems of (geographical) thought from positivist social science to poststructuralism
treated sexual dissidence? Are they inherently, essentially heterosexist? Are some systems of
Feminist geography 303

thought and theoretical frameworks more damaging or better at promoting the interests of an
antihomophobic ‘project’ than others?
(p. 223)

It does not take Binnie long to conclude that spatial science was problematic, by virtue
of its indirect association with a scientific discourse that assigned deviance to homosexuality
(‘the medicalization and pathologicalization of homosexuality’ in his words (p. 224)). Binnie
recognised more potential in postmodern, feminist and poststructuralist geographies. Yet he
remained wary of the ‘cultural turn’, declaring that:

I remain deeply suspicious of the ‘cultural turn’ in geography and social theory more generally,
as the post-modern emphasis on difference (although opening up a space for work on sexuality)
has also been guilty of skirting around the edges of sex and sexuality, preferring a more abstract
engagement with, for example, Lacanian psychoanalysis.
(p. 225)

Binnie also took issue with much feminist geography. For example, he was concerned that
otherwise ‘invaluable, insightful critique of the masculinism of the discipline [here he refers to
Rose, 1993a, 1995] . . . does have a tendency to rant about “men and their theories”’. The use of
the term ‘rant’ here resorts to a pejorative language that has often been applied by sexist men to
feminism and feminists. But perhaps it is indicative of how strongly Binnie perceived a relative
failure of some feminist geographers to recognise diversity among men and masculinities. For
Binnie, there seems to be a world of difference within what maleness and especially ‘male’ sexuality
means (queer, bi, straight, camp, sadomasochist, for example). He feels therefore that those feminist
geographies that, for example, posit landscape as a domain of sexualised masculine vision foreclose
other ways that men and women might look and be seen, amid ‘the celebration of queer pleasure,
sexual diversity, and exuberance’ (p. 227).
A few years later, Howell (2009) reappraised the geography of sexuality in the light of these
and other contributions, such as a book-length study of Closet Space (Brown, 2000) which had
blended poststructuralist, queer and other social theories to provide an account of the interactions
of hidden and ‘out’ gay male lives, sites and spaces. According to Howell (2009), therefore,
‘Geographers of sexuality’ have:

been directed by the career of queer theory to a strikingly expansive and engaging new
topography of sexuality. We recognize that all space is sexed, in that it encodes and endorses
societal norms of sexual behavior and identity, but also that, because of the unstable and
contradictory nature of these sexual categories, all space is actually or potentially queer.
(pp. 123–4)

It might be expected too that more will ask broader questions about a queer epistemology in
geography, like Michael Brown and Lawrence Knopp (2003, p. 313) who argue that:

Serious engagements with sexuality, then, necessitate a careful reconsideration of some


fundamental ontological, epistemological and methodological issues. These include the
relationship between nature, society and human agency; the nature of identity; problems
of naming and counting; of drawing inferences and conclusions; of the roles of qualitative
and quantitative methods in social science (how can we understand the social consequences
of sexualities without understanding them as lived experiences?); objectivity and subjectivity
(can sexualities ever be understood as strictly objective or subjective phenomena?);
and more.
304 Feminist geography

These issues have been heightened in the case of transgendered people, whose identity either
does not conform to the biological sex that they were assigned at birth, and/or who may experience
being bi-gendered, a-gendered or seek to actively transform their gender. As Browne et al. (2010,
p. 573) noted: ‘Gender geographies have focused on normatively gendered men and women,
neglecting the ways in which gender binaries can be contested and troubled.’ They list a few
exceptions (such as Doan, 2007, 2010) and more appear in the special section of Gender, Place and
Culture that their paper introduces, but judge that generally:

geographical enquiry has yet to explore the lives and experiences of people, including trans
people, that trouble and call into question these hegemonic, normative binaries. Such omissions
mean that assumptions predicated on a straightforward gender mapping onto biological sex
organs and gender roles and relations grounded in male/female and man/woman separations
are often uncritically reproduced. To date, geographical scholarship has not fully engaged with
the challenges posed by gender diversity particularly as it has been taken up in trans and queer
scholarship.
(p. 573)

The challenges raised by transgendered geographies that do not readily fit into a male/female
binary are distinctive. Others, however, had sometimes felt themselves to be excluded from ‘the
project’ (a reference to Christopherson’s, 1989, paper designating how feminist work was poised
to play a defining role in ‘the project’ of reconstituting human geography), as in the case of the
concerns and insights of disabled geographers (Chouinard and Grant, 1995), who complained
of ‘not being anywhere near the project’ (see too the paper by Butler and Bowlby, 1997, and
others in that special issue of Environment and Planning D: Society and Space on Geography and Disability).
Arguably this form of marginality continues. Notwithstanding a few pioneering works, Wilton and
Evans (2009) judge that:

disability – as a dimension of oppression and a subject for inquiry – does not have the status of
race, class, gender, and sexuality in the broader subfields of social, cultural, urban, economic,
or political geography. This is despite the fact that disabled persons constitute a significant – and
growing – minority of the population in Western countries and they continue to confront and
struggle against manifold barriers to full participation in, and access to, housing, paid
employment, political participation, public space, social lives, and cultural representation.
(p. 209)

Conclusions
Things have changed since the end of the 1980s, when Jackson (1989) remarked that:

gender and sexuality are still too rarely regarded as part of the central agenda of human
geography . . . regarded as peripheral, private, and personal issues, not suitable for academic
debate or public discussion. . . . What could possibly be geographical, critics imply, about such
intimate personal subjects as gender and sexuality?
(p. 104)

Feminist geography has undoubtedly made a difference. There have been, however, some significant
boundaries to this.
First, the challenge of feminist geographies working across different cultures and languages
has been hard to negotiate, an issue raised in Radcliffe (1994) and Staeheli and Nagar (2002).
Subsequently, Garcia-Ramon et al. (2006, p. 3), writing from Catalonia, Denmark and Greece,
Feminist geography 305

raised the question of anglophone hegemony in the journal that had become a key outlet for
feminist geography (Gender, Place and Culture). They reconsider, for example:

the very concept of gender, including the distinction between sex and gender. Many non-English
languages, our own among them, have only one word and are therefore linguistically unable to
act out the sex/gender distinction. . . . We would however argue that the lack of a distinction
should not necessarily be seen as a disadvantage. The sex/gender distinction is a historical
construct, developed for the specific political purpose of formulating a defence against sexism
and biologism. Even though it actually did the job, it is not a necessary condition for developing
the argument. Many non-English-speaking feminists have managed to develop non-essentialist
arguments without access to these particular terms. It would be possible to argue that they, in
that specific case, avoid thinking in the binary oppositions that Angloamerican poststructuralist
feminists so painfully struggle to deconstruct.
(p. 3)

Yet while one of the key insights of feminist geography has been to bring home (so to speak)
the social and cultural contingency of gender relations, it was challenging to negotiate the global
range of these (given different expectations and norms of gender roles – and of gendered spaces
– in different sites around the world), notwithstanding important feminist work on geographies
of globalisation (Nagar et al., 2002) or collections such as Falah and Nagel (2005) on Geographies of
Muslim Women. Subsequently, however, Louise Johnson (2009, p. 52) claims that feminist geography
had gone ‘well beyond the dualism of women and men to admit race, ethnicity, age, disability,
nationality, religion, and sexuality into their works’ to document ‘how multiple axes of difference
are realized in and through space’.
Second, the impact of feminism in human geography invariably developed unevenly; it took
longer for political geography to register feminist themes (see Drake and Horton, 1983; Hyndman,
2001; Kofman and Peake, 1990) than social and cultural, urban and economic geography, for
example. And other subdisciplines hardly seemed to notice it at all. Much human geography
continued as usual, outside (but a subject of criticism from) the influences of feminist traditions.
There were also resistances, tensions and ‘backlashes’. For example, a senior male geographer
complained that in feminist geography, especially work focused on language, he claimed to have
encountered ‘not just anger, which is perfectly understandable, but something close to hate’ (Gould,
1994). This was countered by Peake (1994, p. 205), who characterised Gould’s position as:

woe betide any feminist who adopts a mode of expression that offends his notions of clearness,
effectiveness, and beauty . . . this situation is fine only if we accept the male prerogative to
legislate language . . . a proprietary attitude that could be espoused only by someone who has
appointed himself as the arbiter of language. . . . He is refusing women the right to make
linguistic changes because, in his dominant subject position, he cannot admit to change, to the
recognition of difference.
(p. 197)

Gould (1999) responded that although:

the various genres of writing emerging out of an excitingly refurbished social and cultural
geography are frequently enlightening, thought-provoking, and intellectually satisfying, in that
they help us to see something in a different way, from a perspective or viewpoint we had not
taken before . . . some throw up (the image is deliberate) writing that is so totally biased, shrill
and predictable that it eventually becomes boring.
(p. 82)
306 Feminist geography

Writing in the early 1990s, Susan Hanson (1992, p. 569) noted that in geography, feminists
‘have been likened to invaders from outer space – alien, ugly, women warriors, come to destroy
the cozy tranquility and predictability of an established order of earthly life’. But she turned this
science fiction metaphor around, by claiming that feminism could expose certain claims
of the irrelevance of gender ‘as science fictions’. She advocated a creative ‘collision’ of feminism
and geography that would transform both. Geography would not be the same after feminism,
but also:

Geographers can transform feminism by pulling it down to earth, by grounding it, by showing
how gender is and continues to be shaped by real geographies. With appropriate infusions of the
geographical imagination, feminists can come to see the importance of the real geography
behind the geographic metaphors that have suffused feminist writing,
(p. 583)

By the start of the new century, feminist concerns and influences had become visible across
many areas of human geography. The relative success (partial victories?) of feminist geography in
transforming human geography had also served as inspiration for others seeking other transforma-
tions (as we documented in Chapter 7 with respect to the ‘whiteness’ of the discipline). Some of
the impetus to social geographies of childhood (Aitken, 2001; Holloway and Valentine, 2000), as
well as non-human/more-than-human geographies of other sentient life in relation to humans
(e.g. Philo and Wilbert, 2000; Whatmore, 2002; Wilbert, 2009) may also have been encouraged by
the example of how feminism broadened the range and understanding of what constitutes ‘human’
geography.
Strategic tensions remain, as between the idea that feminist geography should (or has) become
mainstream and its sense of being on the margins and therefore iconoclastic and more critical.
There are questions regarding the importance of differences between the genders vis-à-vis
acknowledging differences among women and the stability of the terms ‘male’ and ‘female’.
These questions were most recently rearticulated within the Women and Geography Study Group
(WGSG) of the RGS (with the Institute of British Geographers). The WGSG had been an important
vehicle for the development of feminist geography in the UK; sponsoring conference sessions
and meetings and commissioning textbooks – as noted in one of the opening quotes for this
chapter. However, following debates and a poll of its members, it adopted the title of Gender and
Feminist Geography Research Group in 2013. Writing in favour of the change, Brickell et al. (2013)
felt they:

have to ask could the title of the WGSG be read as essentialised and symbolically exclusive?
Would the WGSG lobby on behalf of men where they were excluded because of their gender?
Are we in danger of embodying that very exclusion? Are there other gender related concerns and
advocacy issues for feminist scholars that don’t come under the heading of ‘women’? For those
of us writing here, as feminists, it is important that the WGSG is seen to ‘practice what it
preaches’ in terms of gender inclusion and this includes the group’s – symbolic – name. Hence
we think the name should be changed to a more inclusive form.
(p. 11)

This did not proceed without controversy, however, with Browne et al. (2013) arguing that:

the proposed removal of ‘women’ from WGSG would be a detrimental step. It negates the
understanding that inequalities still exist between men and women (as well as the ways in which
those who transgress this category are policed).
(p. 7)
Feminist geography 307

The WGSG had always been open to men. Though very few men joined (and two who had joined
argued also that the name change was not needed (Hopkins and Jackson, 2013)), many more were
influenced by feminist geography in different ways, from those who found intellectual engagement
and inspiration to those (the majority?) who became more aware of (and hence ceased or
moderated) sexist language in their writing, teaching and at academic meetings.
The feminist movement within geography from the 1970s on was a major, unsettling challenge
to the discipline and its then male hegemony. By the power of its arguments against then current
disciplinary practices and silences – as well as the structuring of its academic communities – it
rapidly achieved major changes, though not, of course, without resistance. But its impact was much
wider than the unequal treatment of women, and later of sexual orientations. It awakened human
geographers to the importance of positionality (as illustrated in the discussions of postcolonialism
in the previous chapter), thereby widening the general appreciation of the important role of context
(including geographical context) in the structuration of societies in general and geography in
particular, especially its political implications.
Yet while differences may have become more evident than in the formative days of feminist
geography, it would be wrong to emphasise these at the expense of missing the broad changes that
feminist geography has wrought. Feminist geography also tests notions of straightforward
disciplinary progress and a neat sequence of paradigms in human geography. Did the scientific and
technical revolution of quantification constitute ‘progress’ on what went before from a feminist
vantage point? Feminist geography must operate within and negotiate wider academic structures
(those described in Chapter 1), but is also critical of disciplinary and academic norms and has
questioned the boundaries of geographic thought and asked who makes and remakes these. More
than four decades on from its arrival, feminist geography is integral to the networks, history
and structures of the discipline. Arguably, therefore, it remains the case that, as Gregson et al. (1997,
pp. 199–200) postulated:

to position feminist geography entirely on the margins of contemporary human geography is


misplaced. Rather for this collective [here WGSG, 1997], feminist geographies occupy the centre
and margins simultaneously: another example of paradoxical space.
Chapter 9

Applied geography and the


relevance debates

If the past fifty years have been spent in developing geographical methods of survey and
analysis, surely the time has now come to apply those methods towards the understanding and
interpretation of some of the features of the world today. Further the time has surely come
when those same methods of survey and analysis can be used in helping towards the solution
of some of the great world problems.
(L. Dudley Stamp, 1960, p. 10)

Geography is by its nature applied. Geographers’ systems of interest are of such direct concern
to people, businesses, government, other organisations, and NGOs that any understanding
achieved within the discipline is likely to be applicable.
(Robert Bennett and Alan Wilson, 2003, p. 463)

There was a time when American geographers . . . graced the covers of national news
magazines and engaged in policy at the highest levels of political decision making. Recall that
Woodrow Wilson’s preparations for the post-World War I peace efforts were headquartered at
the American Geographical Society, calling on the expertise of seven past and future presidents
of the Association of American Geographers . . .
(Billie Lee Turner II, 2005, p. 462)

The history of geography is one of a subject and an academic discipline with a strong applied value
– or relevance, as it is often termed. Indeed, the subject matter from which the discipline emerged
comprised useful knowledge – maps, information about environmental conditions, material on
trade potential etc. And as that information was collated, so it was put to wider uses in the service
of the state apparatus – to Mackinder, one of the discipline’s founders in the UK, geography was an
‘aid to statecraft’ (Parker, 1982; Kearns, 2009; Morin, 2011). As Bennett and Wilson (2003) point
out, applied geography was being promoted there very early in the twentieth century (Keltie,
1908), with another book having the same title appearing soon after the First World War (Stevens,
1921). Nevertheless, and despite much ‘applied work’ by individuals (both academic geographers
and those with geographical training working in other professions), notably though not only in
subdisciplines such as medical and health geography that remain avenues for applied work (Kwan,
2014; J. Mohan, 2000; Cliff and Haggett, 2003), more explicit concerns about geography’s
applicability and relevance did not take centre stage within academic debates until well after the
Second World War.
The period since the late 1960s has contained many testing years in the countries being
studied here. The underlying problem has been economic uncertainty. After two immediate postwar
decades of relatively high rates of economic growth and a sense of increasing prosperity, the
Applied geography and the relevance debates 309

American and British economies began to experience serious difficulties, along with many of their
neighbours. At times, each of the post-1970s decades appeared to offer a return to growth, only for
the booms to be punctuated – in some areas at least – by sudden reversals, notably in 2007–2008.
Further, it became increasingly clear that the prosperity was not being shared by all, even within
the richest countries let alone at a global scale. This was highlighted in the USA by the growing
tempo of the civil rights movement and in the UK by the turmoil in Northern Ireland, which began
as a civil rights movement (and violent state reactions to it), and a series of ‘inner-city riots’ which
were in part responses to racism and deprivation/discrimination. Student and youth protest
erupted in both countries (as well as elsewhere) during 1968, related both to protest against the
American war in Vietnam (that extended to Cambodia and Laos) and a wider upsurge in militancy,
plus increasing concern about human-induced degradation of the physical environment.
Discrimination against women was also brought to the forefront of attention (including the
geographical profession: Zelinsky, 1973b), whereas since the 1980s growing economic and
associated social and political inequalities, both within most Western countries as well as
internationally, attracted increasing attention (Glasmeier, 2005; Dorling et al., 2010).
Much of the protest of the late 1960s centred on particular issues and was relatively ephemeral.
For many of those involved, the aim was to win reforms within society, in the classical liberal/social
democrat manner, while leaving its major structure untouched. For some, however, disillusion
stimulated what Peet (1977) termed a ‘breaking-off’ from liberalism and a move to more radical
political stances:

The starting point was the liberal political social scientific paradigm, based on the belief that
societal problems can be solved, or at least significantly ameliorated, within the context of a
modified capitalism. A corollary of this belief is the advocacy of pragmatism – better to be
involved in partial solutions than in futile efforts at revolution. Radicalization in the political
arena involved, as its first step, rejecting the point of view that one more policy change, one more
“new face”, would make any difference.
(p. 242)

The substantive concerns of those termed ‘radicals’ from the late 1960s on were treated in
detail in Chapter 6. Although there are significant overlaps with that, the current chapter is
concerned with general issues of applied geography and its role within the discipline. As noted in
Chapter 1, the pressures for more applied work built up from the 1970s on in response to economic,
social and political conditions. In addition, government policies towards higher education,
especially in the UK, placed an increased emphasis on applied work, both in terms of providing
vocational and professional training for students in fields where employment prospects were good
and in the pressure to cover institutional costs through ‘earnings’ from research activity, whereas in
the USA there was an increasing emphasis on geographic education providing students with
technical skills (notably though not solely in GIS) to enhance their employment and career
potentials. Thus, the debate over applied geography concerned pragmatic issues of disciplinary
survival as well as concerns with regard to relevance.
Tracking the development of applied geography is not as easy as study of other aspects of the
discipline, because relatively little of its output is published in academic journals. This is partly
because of the nature of the research contracts and the associated funding for researchers. Some
contracts make publication in academic journals difficult, because of commercial sensitivity of the
research results, and even where this is not a particular problem the time pressures on those
involved – to complete one project and then go on to the next, if for no other reason than to secure
a continuing salary for the contract researchers – militate against preparation of academic papers
and mature reflection on the theoretical and other implications of particular (usually empirical)
research findings. As universities have been pressed to do more of this type of work, however, and
310 Applied geography and the relevance debates

as geographers have identified commercial niches for themselves, so the practice of applied
geography has somewhat disappeared from general view. Nevertheless, its nature and validity have
been debated, and that forms the focus of the present discussion.

Disenchantment and disillusion in academic geography


A forthcoming revolution in human geography, against the innate conservatism of behavioural
studies and spatial science, was foreseen by Kasperson (1971):

The shift in the objects of study in geography from supermarkets and highways to poverty and
racism has already begun, and we can expect it to continue, for the goals of geography are
changing. The new men [sic] see the objective of geography as the same as that for medicine – to
postpone death and reduce suffering.
(p.13)

Through the 1970s, an important aspect of debates about the application and relevance of geography
concerned the status of ‘radical geography’. This can be illustrated by one senior geographer’s
writings then. Wilbur Zelinsky was President of the Association of American Geographers (AAG) in
1973; his views may not be entirely typical, and are certainly more firmly stated than those of most
of his peers (but see Symanski, 2002, 2007), but they reflect both growing disillusion within
geographical circles with past achievements (see also Cooke and Robson, 1976) and a concern
about future directions. Zelinsky’s (1970, p. 499) first statement began:

This is a tract. . . . The reader is asked to consider what I have come to regard as the most timely
and momentous item on the agenda of the human geographer: the study of the implications of a
continuing growth in human numbers in the advanced countries, acceleration in their production
and consumption of commodities, the misapplication of old and new technologies, and of the
feasible responses to the resultant difficulties.
(p. 499)

He developed three basic arguments:

1 that people are inducing for themselves a state of acute frustration and a crisis of
survival;
2 that these conditions originate, and can only be solved, in the ‘advanced’ nations; and
3 that the current ‘growth syndrome’ has profound geographical implications.

Material accumulation can no longer be considered progress, he argued, because it is unsustainable;


effort is currently misallocated on a massive scale, and there is a major geographical task involved
in its sensible reallocation.
Zelinsky identified five typical academic reactions towards the problems of the ‘growth
syndrome’:

1 ignore them;
2 accept that major consequences will occur, but only eventually;
3 admit that problems exist, but argue that they are easily solved by the free market, perhaps
with state guidance;
4 claim that nothing can be done, but that in any case we will survive; and
5 realise the potential for immediate, unprecedented trouble.
Applied geography and the relevance debates 311

His own reaction clearly fell into the fifth type, but many others suggested that it was (and remains)
an overreaction, as illustrated by Beckerman’s (1995) critique of the ‘sustainable development’
thesis. Zelinsky identified three roles which geographers could play in facing up to perceived
oncoming disasters. The first – which involves a minimal political commitment and ‘should
not offend even the most rock-ribbed conservative scholar’ (p. 518) – is the geographer as
diagnostician, applying ‘the geographic stethoscope to a stressful demography’ (p. 519) and
mapping what he calls geodemographic load, environmental contamination, crowding and stress.
The second involves the geographer as prophet, projecting and forecasting likely futures. Finally,
there is the geographer as architect of utopia, educating with regard to problems and possible
solutions and providing support for the unknown leaders who have the political will to guide
society through the coming ‘Great Transition’.
Ending his ‘declaration of conscience’ on a pessimistic note, Zelinsky argued regarding
geographers:

how woefully deficient we are in terms of practitioners, in terms of both quantity and quality, how
we are still lacking in relevant techniques, but most of all that we are totally at sea in terms of
ideology, theory and proper institutional arrangements.
(p. 529)

Those criticisms were not confined to geographers, however; he applied them to scientists
en masse in his AAG presidential address (Zelinsky, 1975). Science, he contended, is the twentieth-
century religion, and has failed to avert the oncoming crisis (see also Harvey, 1973, 1989a, 1994).
Its disciplinary specialisms and separatism ‘fog perception of larger social realities’ (p. 128) while
‘fresher, keener insights, along with much better prose’ (p. 129) are produced by the brighter
contemporary journalists.
Zelinsky identified five crucial axioms as the foundations of science:

1 that the principle of causality is valid for studying all phenomena;


2 that all problems are soluble (see Johnston’s, 1990b, response to Pacione, 1990a, regarding the
difference between the solution and resolution of a problem);
3 that there is a final state of perfect knowledge;
4 that findings have universal validity; and
5 that total scientific objectivity is possible.

The social sciences have failed to live up to these, he claims, for several reasons: their immaturity;
their use as a refuge for mediocre personnel; the difficulty of their subject matter concerning
interpersonal relationships; their problems of observation and experimentation; and the political
and other problems involved in applying their proposed solutions. Furthermore, and the major
cause of their failure, the natural science model is irrelevant to the study of society:

If we are in pursuit of nothing more than information or knowledge, then there is some value in
copying the standard formula of a research paper in the so called hard sciences. . . . But if we are
in pursuit of something more difficult and precious than just knowledge, namely understanding,
then this simple didactic pattern has very limited value.
(p. 141)

The natural science approach adopted by positivist spatial-scientists helps to describe the
world, he claims, but not to understand it. Berry, on the other hand, argued to the contrary that all
other approaches are flawed: science, as he defines it, ‘is the basis for rational action’ (Berry, 2002d,
p. 502). If geographers practise it, then they may have substantial influence on ‘how environmental
312 Applied geography and the relevance debates

influences modify thought and behavior by modifying brain structure and functioning . . .
provided . . . we resist the linguistic excesses and the seductive but ultimately self-defeating
siren song of self-congratulatory postmodernism’ (Berry, 1999, p. 590). For him, following Edward
O. Wilson (1998), science is differentiated from pseudo-science on five criteria: the repeatability of
its findings by independent analysis; the economy of its explanations; its unambiguous statements;
its heuristic power for future work; and its consilience – its appreciation that ‘all living phenomena
are ultimately obedient to the laws of physics and chemistry . . . and that all biological phenomena
are products of evolution by natural selection’ (Berry, 1998, p. 95). Geography needs to meet all
these criteria if it is to contribute to constructing a better world. In a later piece (Berry, 2002e,
p. 1), he presents a ‘toolkit’ for detecting whether a claim is valid as a series of four questions – ‘Can
it be tested?’; ‘Is it supported by evidence?’; ‘Has it been confirmed?’; and ‘Is it logical?’ –
and wonders ‘how much of what we see published in our flagship journals meets the test of my
Cheshire cat’s smile, and of that which does not, how much is pseudo-science, anti-science, or pure
baloney’ (p. 2).
There were two major components to Zelinsky’s case: geographical research should be
relevant to the solution of major societal problems; and the positivist-based spatial-science
methodology may be inappropriate for such a task. Several were quick to point out that neither was
particularly new, especially the first. House (1973), for example, reviewed the tradition of
involvement in public policy by British geographers, and Stoddart (1975b, p. 190) identified the
late nineteenth-century views of Reclus and Kropotkin as ‘the origins of a socially relevant
geography’ – the latter was later rediscovered by the ‘radicals’ (Peet, 1977). Nor was the more
‘revolutionary’ approach of those who had ‘broken off’ from liberalism particularly novel: Santos
(1974) reminded English-speaking geographers of the Marxist-inspired works of Jean Dresch on
capital flows in Africa and Jean Tricart on class conflict and human ecology, both prior to the Second
World War (see Clout, 2014), for example, and Keith Buchanan’s presidential address to the
New Zealand Geographical Society on the need for studying ‘the absolute geographical primacy of
the state, especially in the non-Western world’ (Buchanan, 1962), produced an acid response from
Spate (1963; on that episode more widely and related debates within New Zealand geography, see
Moran, 2000).
Zelinsky’s views were echoed in another AAG presidential address, with Ginsburg (1973)
writing that:

Much so called theory in geography . . . is so abstracted from reality that we hardly recognize
reality when we see it. . . . The increasing demand for rigor to cast light on trivia has come to
plague all of the social sciences . . . the most important questions tend not to be asked because
they are the most difficult to answer.
(p. 2)

At about that time, the Association established a Standing Committee on Society and Public
Policy (Ginsburg, 1972), which White (1973, p. 103) hoped would ‘be alert to distinguishing the
fatuous problems and the activities that are pedestrian fire-fighting or flabby reform’. This statement
was made at a session on geography and public policy at the Association’s 1970 conference; a
similar theme was chosen for the 1974 conference of the Institute of British Geographers
(IBG). Not all geographers accepted White’s aim – using learned societies to influence public
policy – while not denying the value of geographic method in social engineering. Trewartha (1973)
stated that:

I must demur when he proposes that it should be a corporate responsibility of our professional
society to become an instrument for social change. . . . From the beginning, the unique purpose
of the Association of American Geographers has been to advance the cause of geography and
Applied geography and the relevance debates 313

geographers; it was never intended to be a social-action organization. . . . All kinds of research,


pure as well as applied, should be equally approved and supported by the AAG.
(p. 73)

Relevance to what and for whom?


Claims that geographical work should be more relevant to major societal problems raised queries
about the nature of that relevance, and it soon became apparent that there was no consensus on
what should be done, and why. The ensuing debate is illustrated by a number of contributions to
the British journal Area during the early 1970s.
Michael Chisholm (1971b) opened it, identifying differences between governments, with
their interests in cost-effective research and their primacy in evidence-based decision-making,
and academics, some of whom are concerned to protect their academic freedom and their right to
be the sole judges of what they study and publish. Traditionally, geographers had advised
governments in the roles of information gatherers and ‘masterful synthesisers’ and they had not
been involved in the final stages of policy-making; they had been delvers and dovetailers, but not
deciders. On the latter role, unfortunately:

The magic of quantification is apt to seem rather less exciting when the specifications of the
goods it can deliver are inspected at close quarters (p. 66). . . . The danger with empirical science
is the absence of guidance at the normative level as to which of various options one should take.
(pp. 67–8)

The challenge to human geography, according to Chisholm, was to define such norms. He
himself later worked for several UK governments: as a member of independent commissions
(the Local Government Boundary Commission in the 1970s and the Local Government Commission
in the 1990s) he was involved in advising governments on the best way to redraw important
components of England’s administrative map (Chisholm, 1975b, 1995) – although he has been
critical of many of the procedures with which he was involved, and was apparently not reappointed
to the Local Government Commission because of this (Chisholm, 2000; Chisholm and Leach,
2008). Eyles (1971) responded that the focus of relevant research should be ‘some of the social and
spatial inequities in society’ (p. 242), and the first challenge is to study the distribution of power
in society, thereby identifying the mechanisms for allocating scarce resources. Research could then
isolate the disadvantages of relative powerlessness and provide the basis for policy aimed at
redistributing resources.
British geographers were introduced to the ongoing debates in American geography in two
reports on the 1971 AAG conference. (This was not the first at which major social issues had been
raised. The 1969 meeting should have been in Chicago but was transferred to Ann Arbor as a protest
over police violence directed at anti-war protesters at the 1968 Democratic Party Convention in
Chicago. The radical journal Antipode was launched there in 1969, and those attending were
confronted by the problems of the inhabitants of Detroit’s black ghetto, small groups of whom
‘invaded’ several of the sessions to present their concerns at the academics’ ‘unworldliness’. Bunge
led an ‘unofficial’ field trip to Detroit which highlighted the massive racialised disparities across
Detroit’s suburbia.) By 1971, ‘many geographers were deeply frustrated by a sense of failure’ to deal
with major social issuegs (Prince, 1971b, p. 152), but although some members were taking notice
of ‘the sufferings of the outside world’ (p. 152) other scholars remained ‘locked in private debates,
preoccupied with trivia, mending and qualifying accepted ideas’ (p. 153).
David Smith’s (1971) report on that AAG conference suggested that American geography was
about to undergo another revolution, to counter a situation in which ‘geography is overpreoccupied
with the study of the production of goods and the exploitation of natural resources, while ignoring
314 Applied geography and the relevance debates

important conditions of human welfare and social justice’ (p. 154). This forthcoming revolution
would involve a fundamental re-evaluation of research, teaching activities and basic social
philosophies, and was represented at the conference by activities such as the foundation of SERGE
(the Socially and Ecologically Responsible Geographer) by Zelinsky and others and by a motion at
the Annual General Meeting condemning USA involvement in Vietnam. Smith (1971) was unsure
whether this revolution, with its emphasis on social as against economic concerns, would spread to
the UK, however:

The conditions which have helped to spawn radical geography in the United States include the
existence of large oppressed racial minorities, inequalities between rich and poor with respect
to social justice, a power structure and value system largely unresponsive to the needs of the
underprivileged, and an unpopular war which is sapping national economic and moral strength.
These conditions do not exist in Britain or exist in a less severe form, and the stimulus for social
activism in geography is thus considerably less than in America.
(pp. 156–7)

By the mid-1990s, however, he was writing of the need ‘to place social justice at the heart of human
geography’ (Smith, 1994a/b, p. 1). Dickenson and Clarke (1972) responded to his 1971 claim by
arguing that British geographers had long been concerned with ‘relevant’ issues, with particular
respect to the Third World.
Another commentary on AAG’s 1971 conference came from Berry (1972b), who felt that
what he had observed was just a new fad involving ‘new entrants to the field seeking their “turf”’.
He could identify no real commitment:

The majority of the new revolutionaries, it seems, are essentially white liberals – quick to lament
the supposed ills of society and to wear their bleeding hearts like emblems or old school ties –
and quicker to avoid the hard work that diagnosis and action demand. A smaller group of hard-
line Marxists keeps bubbling the potage of liberal laments. In neither group is there any profound
commitment to producing constructive change by democratic means. . . . If either of these will be the
‘new geography’ of the 1970s, count me out.
(pp. 77–8, original italics; see also Berry, 2002c)

To Berry, academic geographers should provide a knowledge base on which policy can be
built, which implies close involvement with the education of future generations of policy-makers
(on which, see Yeates, 2001). To Blowers (1972), however, ‘The issue is not how we can cooperate
with policy-makers, but whether and in what sense we should do so. It is a question of values’
(p. 291); he argued that the sorts of activities proposed by Berry would be strongly supportive of
the status quo, and unlikely to produce fundamental social reform.
David Smith’s (1973a, p. 1) response to Berry was that ‘bleeding hearts sometimes help to
draw attention to important issues, and Marxists can make valuable contributions in the search for
alternatives to existing institutions and policies’, and he pointed out that the current ‘fad’ was no
more pronounced than that of the quantifiers a decade earlier. The results of their ‘revolution’
offered little for the solution of social problems, however, and Smith doubted the value of the large
projects established by the AAG as part of its geography and public policy drive. (One of those
projects produced a major series of books on metropolitan America, though their applied relevance
was not clear (Adams, 1976).) Research should highlight particular problems, and teaching should
place emphases on ‘a man in harmony with nature rather than master of it, on social health rather
than economic health, on equity rather than efficiency, and on the quality of life rather than
the quantity of goods’ (p. 3). Michael Chisholm (1973) advocated caution in the corridors
of power, because geographers had done insufficient substantive research to back up a ‘hard sell’
Applied geography and the relevance debates 315

(a point made three decades earlier by Ackerman: see p. 76, this book); Eyles (1973, p. 155) argued
that ‘any entry to those corridors assumes that the structure underlying policy alternatives is
basically sound’; and Blowers (1974) wrote that in the corridors one can only influence, not decide,
and that for the latter task geographers must develop their political convictions and act accordingly.
(Blowers was active in English local government, where political parties dominate, for some
decades, focusing on environmental issues, on which he also published major academic works
(Blowers, 1984). On another geographer’s role as an active local politician, see Pawson, 2011.)
This debate on if, and how, geographers should contribute to the solution of societal problems
was a major issue at the 1974 IBG annual conference. Coppock’s (1974) presidential address
presented the challenges, opportunities and implications of geographical involvement in public
policy, an involvement which he felt the current generation of students welcomed. He argued that
policy-makers were largely ignorant of potential geographical contributions, while at the same
time geographers seemed unaware that ‘there is virtually no aspect of contemporary geography
which is not affected to some degree by public policy’ (p. 5). Coppock wanted to change this, to
have geographers identify the contributions that they could make, to encourage research relevant to
those contributions, and to enter a dialogue with those who advise on and implement public policy.
(At Edinburgh in the 1960s he had established a Tourism and Recreation Research Unit within the
Department of Geography which undertook consultancy work for both the public and private
sectors as well as providing the material for research publications (Coppock and Duffield, 1975;
Clout, 2002).)
Other conference contributors were neither as optimistic nor as committed as Coppock. Hare
(1974), himself an adviser to the Canadian government, reacted to cries that geographers were not
consulted enough with the reply ‘Thank goodness’; geography, as a discipline, is irrelevant to the
separate domain of public policy-making, although geographers, as individuals, because of
the breadth of their training, could offer much that was valuable, so his conclusion was ‘Geography
no, geographers yes’ (p. 26). His was a different response to mounting social concerns from Steel,
who told the British Geographical Association (Steel, 1974):

As geographers we often get hot under the collar over the number of theoretical economists who
are called on to advise the governments of developing countries. We comment on how much better
World Bank surveys of countries would be if they were prepared, at least in part, by geographers. . . .
We wonder why university departments of geography are not engaged on a consultancy basis more
often than they are, and we marvel that the Overseas Development Administration in London has
only a handful of geographers on its staff where, we feel, an army would be more appropriate.
(p. 200)

Hare (1977) subsequently argued that a major reason for a lack of geographical contributions to
public policy may be the poverty of their academic training; in recent years we have ‘swept geography
departments into the social-science divisions of faculties of arts and sciences where, from playing
second fiddle to geologists or literary critics, we learned to play second fiddle to economists and
sociologists’ (p. 263). Geographers would have to rebuild their discipline based on the centrality of
society–environment interactions, he argued, with a new brand of physical geography that leans
heavily on biological ideas and sources: ‘We must reassert the old, essential truth that geography is
the study of the earth as the habitat of man, and not some small sub-set of that gigantic theme’
(p. 266; see also Steel, 1982; Hart, 1982a). Hare’s views on the current irrelevance of geography to
public policy were supported by Peter Hall (1974, p. 49), who argued that:

geography, most clearly of all the social sciences, has neither an explicit nor an implicit
normative base . . . spatial efficiency . . . is rather a description of what men seek to do in
actuality . . . not . . . an objective to be achieved or objective function to be maximized.
316 Applied geography and the relevance debates

Policy-makers must seek their norms elsewhere; geographers, meanwhile, must develop a new
political geography which will aid them in understanding the crucial role of political decisions in
structuring spatial systems (Johnston, 1978c).
Two other papers given at the 1974 IBG conference argued against Coppock’s programme.
Bridget Leach (1974), for example, claimed that governments, as paymasters, already constrained
what geographers could do research on, and as a result geographers were being used; their only
alternative was political action. Harvey’s (1974c) contribution was entitled ‘What kind of geography
for what kind of public policy?’. Individuals wishing to become involved in policy-making were,
he argued, stimulated by motives such as personal ambition, disciplinary imperialism, social
necessity and moral obligation; at the level of the whole discipline, on the other hand, geography
had been co-opted, through the universities, by the growing corporate state, and geographers had
been given some illusion of power within a decision-making process designed to maintain the
status quo. He portrayed the corporate state as ‘proto-fascist’ (p. 23), a transitional step on the path
to the barbarism depicted in Orwell’s Nineteen Eighty-Four. The function of academics, he claimed, was
to counter such trends, to expunge the racism, ethnocentrism and condescending paternalism from
within their own discipline and to build a radical subject, thereby assisting all human beings ‘to
control and enhance the conditions of our own existence’ (p. 24).
Harvey (1973) had previously argued that the current mode of analysis in geography offered
little for the solution of pressing societal concerns:

There is an ecological problem, an urban problem, an international trade problem, and yet we
seem incapable of saying anything of depth or profundity about any of them. When we do say
anything, it appears trite and rather ludicrous. . . . It is the emerging objective social conditions
and our patent inability to cope with them which essentially explain the necessity for a revolution
in geographic thought.
(p. 129)

He recognised three types of theory:

1 Status quo, which represents reality accurately but only in terms of static patterns, and therefore
cannot make predictions which will lead to fundamental social change.
2 Counter-revolutionary, which also represents reality, but obfuscates the real issues because it
ignores (either deliberately or accidentally) the important causative factors and so can be used
to promote changes that will not bring about significant alterations to the operation of those
factors. It is ‘a perfect device for non-decision making, for it diverts attention from fundamental
issues to superficial or non-existent issues’ (p. 151).
3 Revolutionary, which is grounded in the reality it seeks to represent, and is formulated so as to
encompass the contradictions and conflicts which produce social change.

Harvey wished to write revolutionary theory, thereby overthrowing the current paradigm; his
blueprint for geography:

does not entail yet another empirical investigation. . . . In fact, mapping even more evidence of
man’s patent inhumanity to man is counter-revolutionary in the sense that it allows the bleeding-
heart liberal in us to pretend we are contributing to a solution when in fact we are not. This kind
of empiricism is irrelevant. There is already enough information. . . . Our task does not lie here.
Nor does it lie in what can only be termed ‘moral masturbation’ of the sort which accompanies
the masochistic assemblage of some huge dossier of the daily injustices. . . . This, too, is
counter-revolutionary for it merely serves to expiate guilt without our ever being forced to face
the fundamental issues, let alone do anything about them. Nor is it a solution to indulge in that
Applied geography and the relevance debates 317

emotional tourism which attracts us to live and work with the poor for a while. . . . These . . .
paths . . . merely serve to divert us from the essential task at hand.
  This immediate task is nothing more nor less than the self-conscious and aware construction
of a new paradigm for social geographic thought through a deep and profound critique of our
existing analytical constructs. This is what we are best equipped to do. We are academics, after
all, working with the tools of the academic trade . . . our task is to mobilize our power of thought,
which we can apply to the task of bringing about a humanizing social change.
(pp. 144–5)

To Harvey, then, relevant geography involves building new geographic theory on a Marxist base,
and its dissemination will achieve social reform through the education process. (This gradualist
view, promoting reform through education, is only implicit in Harvey’s work (Johnston, 1974,
p. 189). Harvey later discussed the problems of creating a new society, and outlined a scenario of
how that might come about, and with what effects (Harvey, 2000).) Blaut (1979) contended that
Marxist theory offered benefits because it can handle two crucial issues which positivist theory
cannot: increased injustice and heightened economic and social instability.
Harvey (1984) presented a forceful elaboration of his views in a paper subtitled ‘an historical
materialist manifesto’. Geography, he contended, not only records, analyses and stores information
about society but also ‘promotes conscious awareness of how such conditions are subject to
continuous transformation through human action’ (p. 1). The nature of the knowledge that it
produces and propagates reflects the social context of place and time, hence the role of geography
in the ‘Bourgeois era’ as an ‘active vehicle for the transmission of doctrines of racial, cultural, sexual,
or national superiority’ (p. 3). The positivist movement had sought to establish a universal science
of spatial relations, which was countered by both humanistic and Marxist critiques. Together the
latter suggested the development of a revitalised geography, but they lacked:

a clear context, a theoretical frame of reference, a language which can simultaneously capture
global processes restructuring social, economic and political life in the contemporary era and
the specifics of what is happening to individuals, groups, classes, and communities at particular
places at certain times.
(p. 6)

Historical materialism provides that framework, he argues (though see Eliot Hurst’s, 1985,
argument that if Harvey accepted his own (1972) contention that disciplinary boundaries are
counter-revolutionary, then it is hard to understand how he can later promote a disciplinary-based
manifesto).
Harvey argued that geographers cannot be neutral; their work must be of value to some special
interest group within society. For him, that group should not be ‘generals, politicians, and corporate
chiefs’ (p. 7) but the disenfranchised. A people’s geography ‘threaded into the fabric of daily life
with deep taproots into the well-springs of popular consciousness . . . must also open channels of
communication, undermine parochialist worldviews, and confront or subvert the power of the
dominant classes or the state. It must penetrate the barriers to common understanding by identifying
the material base to common interests’ (p. 7). It would not only reveal to the disenfranchised how
societies are structured and restructured so that ‘centers exploit peripheries, the first world
subjugates the third, and capitalist powers compete for domination of protected space (markets,
labor power, raw materials). People in one place exploit and struggle against those in another place’
(p. 9). It would also help them to:

Define a political project that sees the transition from capitalism to socialism in historico-
geographical terms . . . we must define, also, a radical guiding vision: one that explores the
318 Applied geography and the relevance debates

realms of freedom beyond material necessity, that opens the way to the creation of new forms of
society in which common people have the power to create their own geography and history in the
image of liberty and mutual respect of opposed interests. The only other course . . . is to sustain
a present geography founded on class oppression, state domination, unnecessary material
deprivation, war, and human denial.
(p. 10)

Harvey returned to this theme in 1989, in a retrospective volume reporting on a conference


held to mark the twentieth anniversary of the publication of Models in Geography (see p. 93, this book).
He set out a brief critique of the scientific approach adopted in the earlier book, claiming that the
type of modelling adopted could not be used to tackle what he identified as the major geographical
questions (such as the ‘evolutionary path of capitalism itself’ (Harvey, 1989b, p. 212); in this
context, he portrays ‘all geography as historical geography’). Indeed, ‘when put in the context of
these grander questions, the modelling effort appeared both puny and not particularly revealing’.
Many geographers retained that modelling approach, however, by fragmenting the discipline and
focusing on narrow questions. They had restricted the nature of the questions asked and as a
consequence:

we can now model spatial behaviour like journey-to-work, retail activity, the spread of measles
epidemics, the atmospheric dispersion of pollutants, and the like, with much greater security
and precision than once was the case. And I accept that this represents no mean achievement.
But what can we say about the sudden explosion of third world debt in the 1970s, the remarkable
push into new and seemingly quite different modes of flexible accumulation, the rise of geo-
political tensions, even the definition of key ecological problems? What more do we know
about major historical-geographical transitions (the rise of capitalism, world wars, socialist
revolutions and the like)? Furthermore, pursuit of knowledge by the positivist route did not
necessarily generate usable configurations of concepts and theories. There must be thousands
of hypotheses proven correct at some appropriate significance level in the geographical literature
by now, and I am left with the impression that in toto this adds up to little more than the proverbial
hill of beans.
(pp. 212–13)

Harvey found it hard to understand why Marxism had had such little influence on geography
until the 1970s, and noted that, when it did, ‘geographers who turned to Marx were swept up in
that, and many were so submerged in it that they entirely forgot their own disciplinary identity’
(p. 215). The submersion was necessary, but so was the identity; the production of knowledge is a
political project, and the history and future of the discipline have to be appreciated in that context.
Thus:

any project to ‘remodel’ contemporary geography must take the achievements of the
Marxist thrust thoroughly into account at the same time as it recognizes the limits of
positivism and the restricted domain of the modelling endeavours that derived therefrom.
This is not to rule all forms of mathematical representation, data analysis and experi-
mental design out of order, but to insist that those batteries of techniques and scientific
languages be deployed within a much more powerful framework of historical-materialist
analysis.

This, he accepts, must be ideological ‘because it is necessarily political and built upon
some conception of our collective agency in history’, as illustrated in his book on Rebel Cities
(Harvey, 2012).
Applied geography and the relevance debates 319

Liberal contributions
Liberalism is defined here as combining ‘a belief in democratic capitalism with a strong com-
mitment to executive and legislative action in order to alleviate social ills’ (Bullock, 1977,
p. 347). Associated in the USA with the left of the Democratic party, and in Australia, Canada,
New Zealand, the UK and parts of Europe with social/liberal democratic, socialist and Labour
parties, liberals are concerned that all members of society do not fall below certain minimum
levels of well-being (variously defined), and are prepared for state action within the capitalist
structure in order that this can be achieved. There are diverse strands within liberalism, some more
radical/left and others more centred on market liberalism and so connected with centre-right
politics and neoliberal policies. Within geography however, much of the early work conducted in
liberal ethos focused on description rather than theory-construction; Chisholm’s (1971a) investi-
gation of the potential of welfare economics as a basis for normative theory which does not involve
profit-maximisation goals was one of the few exceptions (see also Wilson, 1976b).
There is a long tradition of liberal contributions by ‘applied geographers’, both in their
research and associated activities, and in their teaching (see House, 1973; Hall, 1981b, 2003,
reviews UK geographers’ work in the fields of urban planning, for example, and Hudson, 2003,
similarly outlines their work on issues of regional development and planning). In the UK, applied
geography as information gathering and synthesising has a substantial record, starting with Stamp’s
Land Utilization Survey in the 1930s, and his subsequent involvement in the preparations for
postwar land-use planning (Stamp, 1946b, 1949). Other aspects of land-use planning were of
interest to geographers in the 1930s and 1940s, and were discussed several times at the RGS
(Freeman, 1980b); similar geographical involvement occurred in the USA (Kollmorgen, 1979).
During the Second World War geographers made many contributions as information synthesisers
and gatherers, the latter including the development of air-photo interpretation (on British
contributions, see Balchin, 1987, and Clout and Gosme, 2003; on USA activity, see several of the
essays in E. W. Miller, 1993).
After the Second World War, land-use and transport planning were established on a large scale,
and trained geographers provided a substantial proportion of its personnel. The relationship
between land-use planning (often termed town and country planning in the UK and spatial
planning elsewhere – terminology increasingly adopted in the UK too) and geography led Phelps
and Tewdwr-Jones (2008) to ponder if planning is geography’s disciplinary alter ego. Moreover:

Further similarities between the disciplines of geography and planning emerge when we
consider not only critical reflection over what each of the disciplines is, but also critical reflection
on the evolution of ideas in both. Again, it is worth rehearsing for a geographical readership the
degree of intellectual ferment that has characterised the planning discipline over the past four
decades and more. Broadly speaking, academic planning has undergone the same evolution of
ideas and thought as human geography with key texts embracing positivism, behavioural and
humanistic approaches, structuralism and post-modern approaches, as well as specific theories
associated with these approaches.
(p. 571)

In addition to planning, after 1945, many academic geographers became active in applied work
in other ways. Technical developments in cartography and data handling saw them involved in
redistricting for Congressional elections (Morrill, 1981), a wide range of mapping activities
(Rhind and Adams, 1980; Rhind later became the first academic to head the British national
mapping agency – the Ordnance Survey: Rhind, 2003), and developing regional bases for the
presentation of census statistics (Coombes et al., 1982; Berry et al., 1969), for example, while
developments in GIS during the 1980s and 1990s stimulated very substantial increases in mapping
320 Applied geography and the relevance debates

and enumeration (Charlton et al., 1995; Martin, 2002). Alongside this, various policies have been
evaluated, such as those aimed at changing the distribution of industrial activity, and much of the
entropy-maximising systems modelling (p. 118, this book) was intended to provide procedures for
planning the joint activities of land-use and transport planning (Wilson, 1974; Bennett and Wilson,
2003; on whether it did, see Batty, 1989). Elsewhere, Hägerstrand, who made many original and
highly influential contributions to the development of spatial analysis (p. 132, this book) was
deeply involved in a wide range of spatial planning projects in Sweden, in part through his
pioneering work in computer cartography (Öberg, 2005). Developments in what has been termed
‘participatory GIS’ (see too Chapters 4 and 6) have promoted open access to the hardware and
software, thereby overcoming the ‘expert-customer’ relationship (Elwood, 2006) and the associated
creation of ‘neogeography’ provides online access to map-making tools for non-professionals
(Goodchild, 2009; Rana and Joliveau, 2012; see also the New Mappings Collaboratory at the
University of Kentucky: http://newmaps.as.uky.edu/online-public-engagement), though
scepticism about neogeography as ‘an attempt to reduce geography to an exercise in instrumental
rationality’ (Leszczynski, 2014, p. 75) reiterates some of the prior debate about for whom and what
kinds of (applied) geography is being proposed (and enacted) for what kind of policies
In a different context, after the events of 9/11 in 2001, the Association of American
Geographers published a book illustrating its editors’ conception of geography’s role – especially in
its deployment of GIS and associated technologies – in tackling such terrorist activities and reducing
the probability of their recurrence (Cutter et al., 2003). This was substantially criticised in reviews
(several were published, for example, in the December 2004 issue of the Annals of the Association of
American Geographers). The editors defended their chosen perspective by claiming that ‘through our
discussions with hundreds of geographers, it was clear that geography had a great deal more to
offer on this issue than political commentary’ (Cutter et al., 2004, p. 1001), with their collection
reflecting a discipline ready to respond to major national events with material about ‘how to reduce
risks of terrorism in the country and the world at large’, thereby demonstrating ‘disciplinary
citizenship’ (p. 1002).
Most of the work presented as exemplifying applied geography used an empiricist and
(usually implicit) positivist framework. Geographers are perceived as having valuable skills in the
collection and ordering of data, as in land-use surveys, for example, and the presentation of such
data frequently assumed the existence, and desirability of maintaining, certain causal relation-
ships; planning agricultural land use, for example, often assumed a clear causal link between the
physical environment and agricultural productivity and that of industrial location assumed the
need for efficiency via the minimisation of total travel costs. (Interestingly, some critics pointed
out that the greatest use of such optimising models occurred not in the ‘capitalist West’ but rather
in the ‘socialist East’.) As positivist work on the allocation of land uses and traffic flows increased,
so the potential for geographic inputs to spatial planning was promoted. Most of this was
pragmatic application of technical skills, though there were also evaluations of policy impacts
(e.g. Hall et al., 1973) and attempts to develop decision-making theories in this context (Hall,
1981b, 1982, 1998).
Geographers’ empiricist role continued to be advanced in response to economic crises and the
perceived need for valid data. In the UK, for example, the government introduced a three-year
programme in 1983 to provide ‘new blood’ for university research activities; 792 lectureships were
available, in open competition between universities, with a further 146 in the fields of information
technology. Geography departments received 11.5 per cent of these posts (1.1 per cent of the total;
the staff of geography departments comprised 2 per cent of all university posts in 1982–3). David
Smith (1985) argued not only that geography lost out relatively in that contest (the ‘winners’ were
engineering, technology, and the physical and biological sciences), but also that within geography
the posts allocated were selectively focused on certain aspects of the discipline: five were for
research in remote sensing/digital mapping, for example, and three more were for various aspects
Applied geography and the relevance debates 321

of mathematical modelling (two in physical geography); only one reflected ‘place-specific’ issues,
a post in historical–cultural geography. Smith interprets this as follows:

The predominance of remote sensing (and associated digital mapping) reflects a view of
geography as a technologically sophisticated means of gathering and displaying information, in
the tradition of the geographer as map-maker linked to the contemporary preoccupation with
information technology . . . [that] appears to conflate the needs of the discipline with a conception
of the needs of society in which the emphasis is much more economic than social. It is hard to
see more than one or two of the posts contributing much to the solution of social problems. The
predominant impression is of an a-social view of the world, in which social relations, class
structure and political power seem strangely absent.
(p. 2)

Clayton (1985a) responded that this was unlikely to be the only example of more direct state
influence on the direction of academic research (see also his analysis of how geographers should
react to that: Clayton, 1985b). In 1986 the University Grants Committee produced its first rating of
the research record of every university department – on criteria that included externally earned
research income as well as publications, information on which was subjectively examined by
‘expert panels’ which graded every department; for the latest exercise (2014) 20 per cent of the
final grading was based on a series of ‘impact case studies’. (The Research Assessment Exercises –
RAEs – were replaced by the Research Excellence Framework – REF – for the 2014 exercise.) Using
the results of the first exercise, it began a selective allocation of funds to universities that reflected
those ratings (see D. M. Smith, 1986). Similar rating exercises were undertaken in 1989, 1992,
1996, 2001 and 2006, and 2014 (each used peer review and was more transparent than the first:
Thorne, 1993, though see Collini, 2012, and Sayer, 2015). Virtually all the research money
distributed to the universities by the funding councils (some £20 million annually in 2003 across
geography departments) is now allocated by a formula linked to those ratings, with most money
going to the largest departments whose research records and plans win the highest ratings (on the
funding implications, see Johnston, 1993a, 1995b; on the ethics of such a distribution, see Smith,
1995, 1996; Rhind, 1996; Curran, 1996; and Curran, 2000, 2001a modelled the distribution of
‘success’ in these exercises). In the early twenty-first century, this allocation procedure was made
even more selective, with only a minority of the country’s geography departments getting substantial
allocations because only work graded 3* or 4* (the highest two grades) qualified for funding, with
the implication that the remainder were largely being funded for their teaching activities only.
(Similar exercises were adopted by the Australian and New Zealand governments.)
Alongside those who argued for a greater commitment to applied geography in the empiricist/
positivist mould, and therefore for an implicit acceptance of a particular ideology (Johnston,
1981a), others challenged this as the best way to respond to pressing societal problems. They
argued for a reappraisal of how geographers could assist in understanding the genesis of those
problems rather than in the suggestion of solutions which rarely tackled the root causes. The major
contributions of the two groups are the subject of the next sections.

Mapping welfare
A range of quantitative research was published in the 1960s and 1970s under the general title of
factorial ecologies, applications of multivariate statistical procedures to large data matrices as a
means of representing spatial variations in population characteristics. These, according to David
Smith (1973b, p. 43), were over-reliant on certain types of census data and therefore provided
little information on social conditions. Earlier attempts had been made to structure analyses of such
data towards particular ends, as in the work of rural sociologists on farmers’ levels of living
322 Applied geography and the relevance debates

(Hagood, 1943) – a concept introduced to the geographical literature by G. Malcolm Lewis (1968)
and in John Thompson et al.’s (1962) investigation of variations in levels of economic health among
different parts of New York State.
Factorial ecology procedures were adapted to the task of portraying spatial variations in social
welfare in the 1970s, led by two workers. Knox (1975) promoted the mapping of social and spatial
variations in the quality of life as a fundamental objective for geography, to provide both an input
to planning procedures and a means of monitoring policies aimed at improving welfare. He divided
the concept of ‘level-of-living’ into three sets of variables – physical needs (nutrition, shelter and
health); cultural needs (education, leisure and recreation, and security); and higher needs (to be
purchased with surplus income) – and used statistical procedures to portray their spatial variations.
With the resultant maps, geographers must then decide whether they are playing a sufficient role
in awakening human awareness of the extent of the disparities or are ‘under an obligation to help
society improve the situation’ (p. 53).
Similar work by Smith (1973b) was set in the context of the American social indicators
movement and the growing belief there that GNP and national income ‘are not necessarily direct
measures of the quality of life in its broadest sense’ (p. 1). He initiated the collation and dissemination
of territorial social indicators in order to illustrate the extent of discrimination by place of residence
which occurs in the USA; multivariate statistical procedures generated the maps, on interstate,
intercity and intra-urban scales. (Cox, 1979 extended the treatment to the international scale.)
Smith’s (1979, p. 11) goal was to present ‘the basis for a better understanding of the origins of
inequality as a geographical condition and of the difficulties in the way of plans to promote greater
equality in human life chances’.
In Chisholm’s terms (p. 313, this book), the works by Cox, Knox and Smith represented the
geographer as delver and dovetailer, producing information on which more equitable social
planning could be based, but with little indication as to how. Other studies performed similar roles,
but also suggested spatial policies which could lead to improvements. Harries (1974), for example,
analysed spatial variations in crime rates and the administration of justice, and argued that predictive
models of criminal patterns could assist the organisation of police work (see also Haining, 2009);
Shannon and Dever (1974) and Joseph and Phillips (1984) investigated variations in the provision
of healthcare facilities and argued for spatial planning that would improve the services offered to
the sick (which is different from a geography of prophylaxis: Fuller, 1971); and Morrill and
Wohlenberg (1971) studied the geography of poverty in the USA, proposing both social policies
– higher minimum wages, guaranteed incomes, guaranteed jobs, and stronger anti-discrimination
laws – and spatial policies (such as an extensive programme of economic decentralisation to a
network of regional growth centres) that would alleviate this major social problem. More recently,
research in social geography has been undertaken with the twin goal of both uncovering and
accounting for geographies of ‘social problems’ and contributing towards their amelioration/
eradication (e.g. on alcoholism: Jayne et al., 2011; on children’s use of online resources: Holloway
and Valentine, 2000). An alternative, highly personal, programme of mapping variations in human
welfare was advanced by Bunge (1971), who prepared a ‘geobiography’ of his home area in
Detroit’s black ghetto. His deeply humanitarian concern for the future was interpreted as a need to
ensure a healthy existence for children; he proposed a ‘dictatorship of the children’ (Bunge, 1973b,
p. 329) with regions –‘may the world be full of happy regions’ (p. 331) – designed for them. This
requires a reduction in the worship of machines, which are inimical to children’s health (Bunge,
1973c), and a mapping of the sorts of variables never collected by external agencies and therefore
requiring the development of geographical expeditions within the world’s large cities. These maps
would include roach regions, parkless spaces, toyless regions and rat-bitten-children regions
(Bunge, 1973d), and some were prepared for both Detroit and Toronto (Bunge and Bordessa,
1975). This work was later described by Merrifield (1995, p. 57) as involving excursions ‘beyond
the cloisters of the academy’ and ‘a redefinition of the research problematic and intellectual
Applied geography and the relevance debates 323

commitment of the researcher away from a smug campus career to one incorporating a
dedicated community perspective’. The task of empathising with and situating oneself authenti-
cally within an impoverished community is difficult, and the researcher’s own biography is
likely to influence the process of learning about and becoming committed to such a community.
This raises the issues of voice that have increasingly concerned those studying various forms
of representation. By becoming involved, the geographer will become ‘a person of action, a
radical problem-raiser, [and] a responsible critical analyst participating with the oppressed’
(Merrifield, 1995), but:

there is always an immanent hazard that the voice heard in the supposed symbiosis between
academic geographer and folk geographer is skewed towards the overzealous – though well-
meaning – academic geographer. As the voice of the oppressed is muted, the expedition program
degenerates into a paternalism reminiscent of 19th century Western missionaries and settlement
houses.
(p. 63)

More mapping has been undertaken since the pioneering efforts – as in Seager’s atlases (Seager
and Olson, 1986; Seager et al., 1995; Seager and Enloe, 2011), but increasingly, in line with Harvey’s
critique of such descriptive analyses, efforts have been redirected towards an appreciation of the
underlying processes generating such geographies, not just describing ‘who gets what, where’ but
also analysing ‘who gets what, where . . . and how’ (Johnston, 1975). Indeed, the ease of producing
maps by computer has resulted in a large number being published at all scales, with many being
welcomed for the spatial insights they provide into the geographies of, for example, inequality
(e.g. Dorling et al., 2010; Dorling and Thomas, 2011), even though such volumes are much stronger
on description than analysis and explication, let alone policy prescriptions; they stimulate questions
but have no answers (in the ‘geographer as information gatherer’ mould identified by Chisholm,
1971b), and some are basically political polemic/rhetoric (compare Dorling, 2014, and Sayer,
2015).

Attempts at understanding
The mapping investigations just discussed were – and their successors largely still are – very largely
descriptive, and any prescriptions offered based on limited theoretical foundations. Attempts were
made to develop the necessary theoretical understanding, however. Kevin Cox (1973), for example,
looked at the urban crisis in the USA – the racial tensions and riots, municipal bankruptcies, and
the role of the government in the urban economy – presenting his analysis in terms of conflict over
access to sources of power (see also Adams, 1972, on the role of spatial constraints as a generating
influence on ethnic unrest in American cities in the late 1960s). This was intended as part of an
educational exercise, for:

It would be utopian to think that we can propose solutions on the basis of our analysis. The
locational problems and locational consequences of policies weave too intricate a web for that to
be possible. All we can hope to do is inform. To be aware of the problems and of their complexity
may induce some sensitivity in a citizenry which has shown as yet precious little tolerance for the
other point of view.
(K. Cox, 1973, p. xii)

Nevertheless, his final chapter, entitled ‘Policy implications’, discussed two imperatives towards
greater equity in the provision of public services – moral and efficiency (the latter applies to the
total level of welfare in society as well). The policies presented involved spatial reorganisation to
324 Applied geography and the relevance debates

achieve the desired equity (including metropolitan government integration), community control,
population redistribution and transport improvements. Massam’s (1976) review of geographical
contributions to social administration also focused on spatial reorganisation; he evaluated service
provision using the spatial variables of distance and accessibility, with major chapters on the size
and shape of administrative districts and on the efficient allocation of facilities within such districts
(see also Hodgart, 1978).
Cox’s work heralded an increased geographical interest in a much neglected field, the role of
the state in capitalist society (see also Cox et al., 1974; Dear and Clark, 1978; Johnston, 1982b; Cox,
1979). Political geography had traditionally been mostly concerned with the state at the macro-
scale only, dealing with (geo-)political regions, with national and intra-federal boundaries, and
with the operations of the international political system (e.g. Muir, 1975). The similarly
underdeveloped field of electoral geography had highlighted spatial variations in voting, but there
had been little work on either the geographical inputs to voting or the geographical consequences
of the translation of votes into political power (Gudgin and Taylor, 1979; Taylor, 1978, 1985b;
Taylor and Johnston, 1979). The state is involved in many aspects of economic and social geography,
however, as both Buchanan (1962) and Coppock (1974) had stressed, but few geographers had
investigated this involvement in any detail, or the electoral base on which it is founded (Brunn,
1974; Johnston, 1978c).
A framework for understanding spatial variations in well-being was presented by Coates et al.
(1977). They defined the components of well-being, whose variations were mapped at three scales
(international, intra-national and intra-urban), and argued that those variations reflected three sets
of causes: the spatial division of labour; accessibility to goods and facilities; and the political
manipulation of territories (see also Cox, 1979). Spatial policies aimed at the reduction of spatial
inequalities were evaluated, such as various forms of positive discrimination by areas, leading to the
conclusion that the division of labour is the primary determinant of levels of social well-being.
Creation of this division is a social and not a spatial process, though it has clear spatial consequences,
so that:

The root causes of spatial inequalities cannot be tackled by spatial policies alone, therefore.
Inequalities are products of social and economic structures, of which capitalism in its many guises
is the predominant example. Certainly inequalities can be alleviated by spatial policies . . . but
alleviation is not cure: whilst capitalism reigns, however, remedial social action may be the best
that is possible . . . the solution of inequalities must be sought in the restructuring of societies.
(pp. 256–7)

Smith (1977; see also Smith, 1979) essayed a more ambitious attempt at explaining such
spatial variations, arguing that ‘the well-being of society as a spatially variable condition should be
the focal point of geographical enquiry . . . if human beings are the object of our curiosity in
human geography, then the quality of their lives is of paramount interest’ (pp. 362–3). This was the
foundation of his case for ‘a restructuring of human geography around the theme of welfare . . . to
provide both positive knowledge and guidance in the normative realm of evaluation and policy
formulation’ (p. ix). His book proceeded from theory through measurement to application. The
theoretical section is an amalgam of normative welfare economics with Marxian perspectives on
the creation of value, plus the political conflict for power:

The analysis will inevitably reveal certain fundamental weaknesses of the contemporary
capitalist-competitive-materialistic society, but the temptation to offer a more radical critique of
existing structures has been resisted, in favour of an approach that builds on the discipline’s
established intellectual tradition.
(p. xi)
Applied geography and the relevance debates 325

He concluded that:

As geographers we have a special role – a truly creative and revolutionary one – that of helping
to reveal the spatial malfunctionings and injustices, and contributing to the design of a spatial
form of society in which people can be really free to fulfil themselves. This, surely, would be
progress in geography.
(p. 373)

Inequality, justice and ethics


David Smith’s (1994a) Geography and Social Justice took forward his concerns with inequality and
welfare, reflecting changing circumstances (p. xiii). He had been:

involved [in] a variety of engagements with geographical aspects of inequality and human
welfare. Reflecting the dominant mood of the times, explicit concern for social justice remained
muted, for the most part. But the theme was still there, and increasingly required reassertion as
social change on the world stage – east, west and south – began to resurrect some basic
questions concerning the distribution of benefits and burdens under alternative economic and
political arrangements.

Smith determined to explore those aspects of moral philosophy related to the issue of distributive
justice, to ‘see what can be made of this in the geographical context’. This involved a return to
normative thinking, ‘with how we conceive of what is right or wrong, better or worse, in human
affairs lived out in geographical space’. He concluded that ‘social justice should not be left to market
forces’ because ‘to commend observed market outcomes on the grounds that they are the results of
a just process is not credible’ (p. 279), and he argued instead for a foundation in egalitarianism
which, despite postmodern critiques, should embrace certain universal needs (see also p. 246, this
book). Harvey (1993a, 1993b, 1996a) also addressed issues of justice, focusing on the interplay
between universal conceptions and local circumstances.
Smith took this agenda forward in a series of essays on ‘moral geographies’, at a time when
ethical issues came to the fore in debates within UK geography, as illustrated by the controversies
related to Shell’s sponsorship of the RGS (see pp. 334, this book; similar issues had previously been
debated at American geography conferences (see p. 313) but much less so in the UK). He identified
this ‘contemporary geography and ethics movement’ (Smith, 1997a, p. 584) as involving a greater
interrogation of the literature of philosophy than previously, with particular reference to the role of
space and place therein – what he terms ‘the contextual thickening of moral concepts in the
particular (local) circumstances of differentiated human being’ (p. 587), an area that philosophers
tend to ignore. (See Miller and Hashmi, 2001, who don’t ignore it, but do ignore the work of
geographers.) The study of ethics thus required appreciation of the place(s) in which people were
morally socialised. Space too was important, as illustrated by essays on the spatial scope of care and
beneficence: is there a distance-decay effect to moral action (Smith, 1994b, 1998)? As with others
(e.g. Sayer and Storper, 1997), Smith also found stimuli for this turn to ethical and normative
concerns in the writings of environmentalists and feminists as well as philosophers (see also
Whatmore, 1997, and Lawson, 2007, on the ethics of care).
For Smith (1997b), an ‘ethical turn’ in geography was necessary because of the pressing need
for public debate on moral issues, ‘Otherwise, humankind risks losing any residual grip on the
meaning of the good life, any capacity to recognise and challenge evil’ (Smith, 2000, p. vii). For
him, concepts central to geographic enquiry – ‘landscape, location and place, locality, proximity
and distance, space and territory, development and nature’ (p. viii: these are the subject matter of
326 Applied geography and the relevance debates

his book’s main chapters) – are significant to debates about ‘questions of justice and the good life’.
Difference is highly significant in ethics, not so much difference at an individual level (relevant
though this is to fair treatment of all) but rather difference between groups, much of which is
rooted in places, hence the importance of geography in what Smith terms ‘geographically [or
context-]sensitive ethics’. He sees the choice between universal ethical principles, universally
applied, and local particularity, lacking any transcendent values, as a false dualism, with either:

it would be hard to see how anything resembling moral truth might be discovered, or created,
except universals so vacuous as to be impotent in the face of our sorry reality, or beliefs so
restricted in scope as to be part of the problem rather than part of the solution of human conflict.
(p. 202)

His final message advances:

the imperative of developing more caring relations with others, especially those most vulnerable,
whoever and wherever they are, within a more egalitarian and environmentally sustainable way of
life in which some of the traditional strengths of community can be realised and spatially extended.
(p. 208)

Cloke (2002) made a similar argument for ‘living ethically and acting politically’, though his search
for the geographies that might underpin and secure this is based on spiritual beliefs and his focus
is on the recognition of what he terms ‘ordered evil’.
Others joined Smith in his effort to develop a ‘moral (or ethical) imagination’ within geography
(Proctor, 1998a), which includes calls for reconsidering the human/nature binary division that
underpins so much of contemporary geography (Proctor, 1998b; Whatmore, 2002). Apart from
David Smith’s (2000) book, several other contributions addressed a broad range of issues in and
exemplars of geographically sensitive ethics (see Proctor and Smith, 1999, which included essays
on space, place, nature and knowledge; Bondi et al., 2002; Valentine, 2003). For Sack (1997, p. 1),
for example, the fact that as humans we are geographical beings, transforming the earth and then
ourselves being transformed by the altered environments that we inhabit, requires a moral focus to
our work; the nature and force of geographical agency calls for moral agency, for an ‘understanding
of the consequences of our actions on nature and culture, locally and globally’ (p. 2). The impact of
these arguments was almost immediate: in 1998 a journal on Ethics, Place and Environment was launched
to carry material that illustrated and advanced the case for a more theoretically developed and
explicit moral commitment within geography. (In 2010, it was merged with the formerly separate
journal Philosophy and Geography.)

Environmentalism
The late 1960s saw a rapid increase in concern about environmental problems; in the USA (Mikesell,
1974):

Towards the end of the 1960s the American public was overwhelmed with declarations of an
impending environmental crisis. . . . Since that time, crisis rhetoric and a yearning for simple
answers to complicated questions have given way to a more sophisticated and deliberate search
for environmental understanding. Ecology has been institutionalized.
(p. 1)

Two of the leaders of the public debate disagreed over the cause of the problems (O’Riordan, 1976,
pp. 65–80). Ehrlich argued for the primacy of population increase, and popularised the concept of
Applied geography and the relevance debates 327

zero population growth; Commoner claimed that technological advances and the consequent rapid
depletion of resources plus deposition of pollutants created the major problems. Both arguments
have clear geographical components, and it was stressed that geographers have a strong record of
activity in resource conservation: George Perkins Marsh had written on the topic in 1864
(Lowenthal, 1965, 2001) and the climatologist Warren Thornthwaite had been closely involved in
the 1930s’ soil conservation movement established as a consequence of the Dust Bowl phenomenon
(Mather and Sanderson, 1996). The interest in landscape modification was advanced by Sauer and
his followers, and reflected in the 1955 symposium Man’s Role in Changing the Face of the Earth.
Similar interest elsewhere was exemplified by Cumberland’s (1947) pioneering classic on soil
erosion in New Zealand. Nevertheless, Mikesell argued that ‘developments in geography have been
such that the several phases of national preoccupation with environmental problems have not
produced a general awareness of our interests and skills’ (p. 2). Similarly, Eden (2003, p. 213; see
also Castree, 2004) argued that because of ‘a detour to other topics even as other disciplines
discovered the environment as a topic of interest’, British geographers were not prominent in the
early years of this movement, leaving them ‘playing “catch-up” in the late twentieth century, as the
discipline sought to reoccupy the ground previously abandoned’. (Turner, 2002, on the other hand,
argued that human–environment interrelationships now form a viable core area of geographical
scholarship in the USA, hence his welcome for the creation of a Human Environmental Sciences
Section in a recent reorganisation of the National Academy of Sciences with which most of the
geographers who are members of the Academy are affiliated.)
As part of the AAG’s increased commitment to public affairs in the early 1970s, its Commission
on College Geography established a Panel on Environmental Education and sponsored a Task Force
on Environmental Quality. The latter reported (Lowenthal et al., 1973) that geographers would make
excellent leaders for the educational tasks in hand, because of:

1 the breadth of their training and their ability to handle and synthesise material from a range
of sources;
2 their acceptance of the complexity of causation;
3 the range of information which they are trained to tap;
4 their interest in distributions; and
5 their long tradition of study in this area (as illustrated by Lowenthal’s 1958, 2001, biographical
studies of George Perkins Marsh).

All had fostered expertise in work on environmental perception, on vegetation succession, and
on relationships between land use and soil erosion, which could be used as the bases for
environmental impact statements, the elaboration of environmental choices and international
research collaboration.
Two types of work characterised geographers’ activities on society–environment interrelation-
ships at this time. The first involved the traditional geographical concern with description and
analysis. Review volumes such as Perspectives on Environment (Manners and Mikesell, 1974) were
prepared, and a particular interest in problems of the physical environment of urban areas was
generated (Detwyler and Marcus, 1972; Berry and Horton, 1974; Berry (with others) 1974; a later,
British, addition was Douglas, 1983, 2013). The second type focused on issues of environmental
management (O’Riordan, 1971a, 1971b), with particular emphasis on its economic aspects and on
societal response to environmental hazards (Hewitt, 1983); as Kates (1972, p. 519) pointed out,
economics provided the theories and prescriptions of the 1960s (and later, see Judith Rees, 1985).
A topic of special interest was leisure, particularly the growing demand for recreational facilities,
and the impact of recreational and tourism activities on the environment (Patmore, 1970, 1983; see
the critique of much of that work in Owens, 1984); a separate journal on Tourism Geographies was
launched in 1999.
328 Applied geography and the relevance debates

Despite such activity, Mikesell concluded that geographical contributions to environmentalism


had not been great up to 1974. He commented regarding the prognostications of The Limits to Growth
(Meadows et al., 1972), for example, that, ‘the debate on this most relevant of all issues has attracted
remarkably little attention from geographers’ (Mikesell, 1974, p. 19, though see Eyre, 1978). He
concluded more generally that ‘one must add hastily that many of the environmental problems
exposed in recent years and also many of the social and philosophical issues debated during the
environmental crusade have not been given adequate attention by geographers’. This conclusion
was supported by analysis of the contents of recent geographical journals and O’Riordan’s (1976)
lengthy bibliography, and sustained by Goudie (1993) nearly two decades later. Billie Lee Turner
(2002) suggested that this had been rectified, however, with research on the human–environment
interface forming a major component of (American) geography. The volume of work published in
journals such as Applied Geography supports this conclusion (although not all of the papers published
are based on applied work per se), as does the rapid growth of work in subfields identified as cul-
tural ecology and political ecology (Robbins, 2004), for which the Journal of Political Ecology was
launched in 1994. (For evaluations of work in political ecology and its applications, see Blaikie
2008, 2012; Dwyer and Baird, 2014.)
A powerfully argued case not only for more work on the society–environment interface but
also for its centrality to the whole of geographical activity was presented by Stoddart (1987; see
also Stoddart, 2001), who contended that instead of celebrating the achievements of a century of
professional geography, many of his colleagues were ‘despondent, morose, disillusioned, almost
literally devoid of hope, not only about Geography as it is today but as it might be in the future’
(p. 328). This, he believed, was because so many of them ‘have either abandoned or failed ever to
recognize what I take to be our subject’s central intent and indeed self-evident role in the community
of knowledge’ (p. 329). For him, geography had become diffuse, lacking a central focus which
should be ‘Earth’s diversity, its resources, man’s survival on the planet’ (p. 331). This requires a
unified discipline, human and physical, in which ‘The task is to identify geographical problems,
issues of man and environment within regions – problems not of geomorphology or history or
economics or sociology, but geographical problems: and to use our skills to work to alleviate them,
perhaps to solve them.’ Focusing on ‘the big questions, about man, land, resources, human potential’
would involve geographers reclaiming ‘the high ground’ (p. 334; examples include Williams, 1989,
2003) and abandoning much that is currently done:

Quite frankly I have little patience with so-called geographers who ignore these challenges.
I cannot take seriously those who promote as topics worthy of research subjects like geographical
influences in the Canadian cinema, or the distribution of fast-food outlets in Tel Aviv. Nor have I
a great deal more time for what I can only call the chauvinist self-indulgence of our contemporary
obsession with the minutiae of our own affluent and urbanized society. . . . We cannot afford the
luxury of putting so much energy into peripheral things. Fiddle if you will, but at least be aware
that Rome is burning all the while.

James Bird (1989, p. 212) pointed out, however, that although Stoddart called for a geography
that is ‘real, united and committed . . . we are not told exactly what it is, though for Stoddart such
a geography obviously exists’.
Similar, though less strident, calls have been made by others (e.g. Douglas, 1986; Goudie,
1986b; see also Cosgrove and Daniels, 1989); in response, the relevance of much that Stoddart
would disregard in contemporary social science has been promoted as necessary to an appreciation
of society–environment relations (Blaikie, 1985; Blaikie and Brookfield, 1987; Johnston, 1989 –
the latter was written to counter the relative naiveté of much writing by physical geographers
regarding the potential role of the state in the resolution of environmental problems: Trudgill,
1990; Pitman, 2005; see also Johnston, 1996d, 2006). The nature of risk was closely scrutinised by
Applied geography and the relevance debates 329

Adams (1995), for example, as were varying perceptions of nature (Simmons, 1993) and political
approaches to environmental problems (Pepper, 1996); a successor to the 1954 Wenner-Gren
Symposium (The Earth as Transformed by Human Action: B. L. Turner et al., 1990) explored human
exploitation of the environment in considerable depth, as have others on specific issues such as
desertification (Granger, 1990; Middleton and Thomas, 1994, discuss the extent to which it was a
political construction).
Stoddart’s argument was clearly set in the cultural ecology mould. A similar case was made by
Kates (1987), who regretted the dominance of spatial science within geography and argued that
when environmental issues became important on the public and political agenda in the early 1970s:

No discipline was better situated than was geography to provide intellectual and scientific
leadership. The natural science for the environmental revolution should have been the science
of the human environment. Instead, intellectual leadership was split among biology, economics,
and engineering, each of which transferred onto the human environmental realm their own
theories of nature, of economy, or of technology, but none of these offered a truly integrated
view. . . . The theory of the human environment, then, was the theory of plant or animal
ecosystems, or of pervasive externalities, or of technological and managerial fixes.
(p. 526)

For geographers, a perceived inability to respond to the demand for environmental scientists
(producing ‘geographers who can sit astride the natural and social science boundary to provide
analysis, integration and leadership’) was an opportunity lost, a ‘road not taken’. But the Malthusian
dilemma remains (Mayhew, 2014), posing great questions for society to which geographers can
bring their special disciplinary advantages in the search for answers:

We possess more than passing knowledge of both the natural and social sciences. . . . We have
some useful tools for organizing data and information. . . . We possess a strong tradition of
empirical field research. . . . And perhaps most important we have and we teach a respect for
other peoples’ theories. Our answer, then, as to why geography . . . is that we are needed and
that we are useful. When they go forth, our students understand the nature of the great questions,
have more than a passing knowledge of natural and social science, have been in the field, have
collected and organized new data, and have placed these data into a theoretical perspective.
(Kates, 1987, p. 532)

To be sure that they will be called upon to perform in this way, he argued, geographers must put
their house in order and some university departments should rebuild centres of expertise in the
human–environment tradition. The University of Oxford established an Environmental Change
Centre alongside its School of Geography, for example, and several of its directors have had an
established international reputation in the study of the interactions between climatic change and
human activity (Parry and Duncan, 1995; Liverman, 2009). Other universities have similarly
created ‘environmental institutes’ within which geographers play important roles; in some
countries, such as Australia, geography has somewhat disappeared as a separate academic discipline,
instead only being present in universities as part of some institutional structure focused on
environmental science/studies (Holmes, 2002).
One of the major concepts to emerge from the increased concern over environmental
problems in the late 1980s was sustainable development, a considerably ambiguous term that is
generally taken to imply continual increases in material living standards without any diminution in
environmental capacity to meet the needs of future generations (Turner, 1993). This was a focal
concern of the 1992 Earth Summit at Rio de Janeiro, but the difficulties of implementing global
environmental policies have been frequently stressed (see the essays in Johnston et al., 1995, 2002),
330 Applied geography and the relevance debates

although others believe that the problems have been overstated and can readily be addressed, within
a satisfactory time scale, using instruments of economic policy that promote continued develop-
ment (Beckerman, 1995; see also Kates, 1995).
While these broader concerns were being aired, geographers were continuing to be active in
the tradition established by White (see p. 126, this book). In 1937, for example, his memorandum
to President Roosevelt helped to convince him, against Congressional advice, not to make the
Secretary of War responsible for flood control projects, thereby bypassing local and regional
planning bodies, and in 1965 he prepared a paper for the Bureau of the Budget on national policy
options for dealing with floods and similar hazards. The result was the National Flood Insurance
Program, after which White held annual seminars in Boulder to bring public-sector officials and
academics together to discuss disaster response and mitigation policies (Platt, 1986). In this, he and
the many others who have studied environmental policy and contributed to its implementation
have adopted what Feldman (1986) termed the citizen-scholar model:

The scholar chooses his or her research concerns on the basis of perceived social need but attempts
to conduct the inquiry free of influence from outside the inquiry itself. The scholar is committed to
social and political action as follow-up to the research, based on the findings and quality of the
inquiry. But political activity is, during the course of the scholarship, kept separate . . . [In addition]
the citizen-scholar teaches public affairs both within a curriculum and by example, letting her or his
own activities demonstrate good citizenship and good scholarship without being didactic.
(p. 189)

Earlier, White (1972, p. 322) had asked, ‘What shall it profit a profession if it fabricate a nifty
discipline about the world while that world and the human spirit are degraded?’, and in seeking to
avoid that problem he developed an approach which Wescoat (1992) compares to that of the
philosopher of pragmatism, John Dewey. It had four components:

1 recognition of the precariousness of existence;


2 a pragmatic conception of the nature of inquiry – problems arise and are tackled within
situations, for there are no absolute truths; hence
3 a tradition of learning from experience; and
4 a belief in public discourse and democracy.

All these fitted White’s deep involvement with the work of the Society of Friends. (For a fuller
discussion of his career, see White, 2002; Hinshaw, 2006.)
The breadth of study in ‘modern’ environmentalism was illustrated by O’Riordan’s (1981)
work, much of it set in the liberal humanitarian tradition already illustrated here and from which
he drew four conclusions:

1 modern environmentalism challenges many aspects of Western capitalism;


2 it points out paradoxes rather than clear solutions;
3 it involves a conviction that better modes of existence are possible; and
4 it is a politicising and reformist movement, based on a realisation of the need for action in the
face of impending scarcity and a lack of faith in the western democracies (pp. 300–1).

A new social, environmental order is required and O’Riordan identified three possibilities:
centralised, authoritarian and anarchist. He chose a middle-of-the-road, liberal option:

we must individually and collectively seize the opportunities of the present situation to end
the era of exploitation and enter a new age of humanitarian concern and cooperative endeavour
Applied geography and the relevance debates 331

with a driving desire to re-establish the old values of comfortable frugality and cheerful
sharing.
(p. 310)

Such a new era, involving a new political order based on a combination of local self-determination
and supra-nationalism, can be achieved through education, he claimed, so environmental education
will form a preparation for citizenship. Others were more doubtful: Pepper (1996, pp. 324–5), for
example, was sceptical about the liberal arguments that ‘a basic unselfishness and communalism
which is human nature would come to the fore in ecotopia’s unalienated society, as it has never
been allowed to do in industrial capitalism’ (arguments that he terms ‘simply hard to believe’) and
promoted instead the view ‘that by making humanist, egalitarian and socialist aspirations a
prerequisite for an ecological society, rather than something that is supposed automatically to
follow, we can avoid making ecological society a repressive dystopia’. Social change must precede
the resolution of environmental problems.
Some writers have argued that the revival of interest in environmental issues – mainly through
the study of resources and their management – provides a contemporary linking of human and
physical geography. Relatively little of the research and textbook writing indicates any integration
of the two, however (Johnston, 1983b, 1989), because the focus is almost invariably on the pro-
cesses studied in one of the subdisciplines only. (This is illustrated by most of the papers in the
journal Applied Geography, which focuses on such issues and by those in The Geographical Journal, which
the RGS decided would also concentrate on such topics from 2001 on; geographers also contribute
to specialist journals in this field such as Global Environmental Change – Human and Policy Dimensions.)
Physical geographers portray trends such as demographic growth, technological sophistication,
urbanisation and demands for resources as catalysts for environmental processes and changes, but
they take those trends for granted and seldom address what processes generate them. Similarly,
human geographers largely take the resources of the physical environment as given and do not
enquire about the physical and chemical laws underpinning their genesis (though see Hudson,
2012, on the transformation of those materials in changing industrial processes, and Gregson and
Crang, 2014, on the ecology of recycling). For human geographers their links with other social
scientists are very much stronger than those with environmental scientists (as illustrated from the
outset, for example, by the lack of references to the physical geography literature in O’Riordan,
1976, and Pepper, 1996); physical geographers, in turn, direct much of their scientific activity away
from geographical journals towards work by their peers in other disciplines such as geology (espe-
cially of the Holocene), glaciology and hydrology (Johnston, 2003a). Alongside more theoretical
work by human geographers stressing the social construction of nature and the false nature–society
dichotomy (Whatmore, 2002; Castree, 2005), however, recent years have seen growing collabora-
tion between human and physical geographers in work on environmental issues (e.g. Landström
et al., 2011; Pappenberger et al., 2015).
Geographers have also turned their attention to other ‘great questions’ within contemporary
society, such as nuclear weapons and nuclear power. They have criticised attitudes to civil defence
policies and likely deaths from nuclear blast and fall-out (Openshaw et al., 1983), for example, with
others setting that concern within a developing geographical contribution to peace studies (Pepper
and Jenkins, 1985), and they have addressed issues relating to the siting of nuclear power stations
(Openshaw, 1986) and the transport of nuclear waste. (Openshaw’s work on these topics involved
innovative prototypes of GIS technology and was used to identify clusters of cancers that by their
location appeared to be linked to the presence of nearby nuclear installations.) Arguments for
geographical contributions to other aspects of peace studies, such as international relations (van der
Wusten and O’Loughlin, 1986; Agnew, 2005, 2009; Flint, 2005), were advanced (Pepper and
Jenkins, 1983), none more forcibly than Gilbert White’s (1985, p. 14), which saw the human
family ‘tortured and driven by its newfound capacity to throw the whole set of processes out of
332 Applied geography and the relevance debates

kilter by more violent action’. The two editions of A World in Crisis? (Johnston and Taylor, 1986,
1989; see also the two volumes on Geographies of Global Change; Johnston et al., 1995, 2002) focused on
many of these issues, ranging from the macro-scale in the study of geopolitics to the investigation
of individual human rights. And at the beginning of the twenty-first century, the attacks on New
York’s World Trade Center and the Pentagon led American geographers – under the auspices of the
AAG – to address issues of geography’s role in the promotion of ‘homeland security’ (Cutter
et al., 2003; substantial critiques of this book and the approach it promoted were published in the
AAG’s flagship journal Annals, volume 94 (4), 2004).

Geographers and policy


Many of the studies referred to here have been concerned with identifying problems and suggesting
solutions. Underlying their varied approaches has been the basic thesis that geographers should be
much more involved in the creation and monitoring of policies. But what sort of policies, and what
sort of involvement?
Berry (1973b) categorised planning policies into four types:

1 Ameliorative problem-solving involves identifying problems and proposing immediate


solutions, as with the removal of a traffic bottleneck. Such solutions are likely to stimulate
further problems in the future, since it is only the proximate cause that is tackled (the features
of the bottleneck) rather than the real cause (the growth of traffic).
2 Allocative trend-modifying: planning towards the future involves identifying trends, evaluating
what is likely to be the best outcome of the several which they imply, and then allocating
resources to steer the system being planned towards that end.
3 Exploitative opportunity-seeking: planning with the future identifies trends and then seeks to
gain the maximum benefit from them, irrespective of the possible long-term consequences.
Compared with the previous category, this one has a dominantly short-term focus.
4 Normative goal-oriented planning for the future begins with a statement of goals, a vision of
the future, and then prepares a strategy which will ensure that they are achieved.

Relatively little policy-making is of the fourth type; most involves elements of the other three,
with general statements about goals but no clear strategy regarding a foreseeable future. Some
critics (like Harvey, 1973, 1974c) interpreted this as meaning that geographers who become
involved in policy-making and evaluation are likely to accept the dominant forces in society
uncritically, which leads to arguments that their claimed scientific objectivity and neutrality
are an (often unrealised) cloak for ideological political judgements about the nature of
society. Whatever their individual motives, such geographers are acting on behalf of interest groups
(private and public) whose sustenance depends on maintaining an unjust and unequal structure
to society.
Gordon Clark (1982, p. 43) accepted that ‘the academic community is not independent: there
are no objective standards between competing explanations and thus policy advice’. Nevertheless,
he agreed ‘with the principle of policy analysis and the involvement of academics in policy-making’
(p. 48). That involvement cannot be presented as neutral and objective, however, since all social
science ‘explanations’ are incomplete and compete with others to provide plausible accounts and
prescriptions. He suggested that academic contributions to policy analysis should be guided by four
propositions (pp. 55–9):

1 academics must acknowledge their own values and beliefs in presenting policy alternatives
and impact assessments;
Applied geography and the relevance debates 333

2 policy analysts must be advocates for particular causes rather than supposedly independent and
objective adjudicators of knowledge;
3 policy science should be critical of the status quo; and
4 sponsoring institutions must encourage advocate briefs and make those briefs accessible to the
public.

In accepting these, academics who become involved in policy analysis should be considered ‘part
of the political process’ (p. 57) whose role would be to ensure that ‘Choices would be brought
squarely into the open and be dependent upon the political, as opposed to expert, process’ (p. 59).
The present situation idolises experts, he claimed, and promotes a myth of social science as
objective, neutral knowledge, although most governments carefully choose those experts who fit
their own ideological presuppositions and whose advice is therefore very likely to be consistent
with the desired direction of ‘evidence-based policy’, rather than policy-based evidence (Johnston
et al., 2015); there are always elements that distrust ‘experts’, however, especially if it can be shown
that their research (as in climate change) is supported by commercial and other vested interests.
Clark argues that social scientists cannot be neutral experts, because their ‘values, interests and
normative views of the world’ mean that their presentations, although scholarly and rigorous, are
necessarily partial. Sayer (1981) made a similar case in a slightly different context, arguing that any
rigorous social scientific inquiry must be based on rationally defended value judgements; objectivity
does not require neutrality. (Clark, 1991, illustrates this from his experience as an expert witness in
court.)
In an essay on the role of urban geographers in applied work, Pacione (1990a) argued that
practitioners have paid insufficient attention to conceptual issues underlying what they do. He
derived the following ‘principles or guidelines’ to remedy those failings:

1 the notion of value-free research is an illusion;


2 towns, as examples of places, are meaningful entities on which to work;
3 a spatial perspective is of substantial value;
4 the main emphasis of applied urban geography is on problem-solving;
5 a realist position provides the context for such work (see p. 219, this book);
6 analysis must integrate various spatial scales;
7 a wide methodological tool-kit of quantitative and qualitative procedures must be employed;
and
8 geography must integrate the findings of many disciplines.

Johnston (1990b) responded by posing six questions to Pacione: What is a problem? Are problems
always soluble? What is science? What is a geographic perspective? Who solves? What sort of
society? He concluded that some of the principles/guidelines are trivial and/or irrelevant, some are
unsupported, and some are wrong, and that unless Pacione is prepared to address the fundamental
issues of what problems are and how they can be tackled, he is unlikely to help those who want
both an end to currently perceived problems and a society which would no longer produce such
problems. Furthermore, few problems are soluble in the true sense of that term, which points to
the need for resolution between opposing points of view, none of which have any straightforward
claim to absolute truth (as earlier argued by Wolpert, 1970). This point was made in another way
in debates between Palestinian and Israeli geographers over the geography of Israel/Palestine
(Waterman, 1985; Soffer and Minghi, 1986; Newman and Portugali, 1987; Falah, 1989; Waterman
and Kliot, 1990; Falah and Newman, 1995; Newman, 1996).
Undertaking research characterised as ‘relevant’ – pertinent to tackling societal problems –
raises major issues for the individuals concerned. Bruce Mitchell and Dianne Draper (1982, p. 2)
argued that ‘when functioning as an advocate or consultant, the geographer must consciously
334 Applied geography and the relevance debates

decide how to resolve a conflict which may arise regarding the promotion of one perspective versus
critical assessment and balanced judgement about all viewpoints’. There are also issues of ethics:
‘when functioning as a pure researcher, the geographer must balance a concern for obtaining
necessary information against a concern for respecting the dignity and integrity of those people or
things being studied’ (p. 3), which also applies to ‘relevant’ research. They claimed that geographers
have largely ignored these ethical issues, and their professional bodies, unlike those of other
disciplines, have promulgated no codes of conduct. Conflict is frequently likely between striving to
‘discover truth’ and respecting the rights of those being studied, however, and they advocated
individual, institutional and external controls; most research institutions now have ethics committees
seeking to ensure that those rights are respected, and journals require authors to declare both any
funding that has supported their research and whether they have any conflicts of interest.
An example of the problem was raised in 1996 within the newly merged RGS-IBG. The Shell
oil company was one of the RGS’s commercial sponsors prior to the merger, donating £40,000 per
annum towards the costs of its Expeditions Advisory Service; this was presented as an example of
the sort of commercial sponsorship for geographical work which academic geographers could
benefit from within the merged society. In late 1995, however, several members of the Ogoni
people in the Niger Delta region of Nigeria, including a well-known author Ken Saro-Wiwa, were
sentenced to death by a military tribunal (in a trial which Western observers claimed violated their
basic human rights) and subsequently executed, despite political pressure on the Nigerian
government, which culminated in its exclusion from the Commonwealth Heads of Government
conference held in New Zealand in November 1995. Their ‘crimes’ were related to protests over
Shell’s treatment of the Ogoniland environment, where it was involved in exploiting major oil and
gas fields. A number of academic geographers argued that Shell’s corporate patronage of the
RGS-IBG should be ended because of its environmental record there and its alleged complicity in
the trial of the Ogoni leaders. A motion to that effect was passed by a very substantial majority at
the Research Section (formerly the IBG) conference in January 1996 (an event that attracted
considerable media attention worldwide) and the RGS-IBG as a consequence set up a working party
to consider all aspects of corporate sponsorship, which proposed a code of practice and ethical
guidelines but had little apparent long-term impact (on the debate, see Gilbert, 1999; see also
Watts, 2000).
Most of the critiques of the arguments for greater involvement by geographers in policy
analysis are entirely sympathetic. They make a case for sensitive geographical involvement; others
question the grounds for such involvement and instead focus on the development of revolutionary
theory (see p. 316, this book). The former focus almost entirely on applied work in the tradition of
positivist, empirical science, in which the goal is perceived to be to improve well-being through
contributing to one or more of:

1 the preparation of public (i.e. state) policies;


2 the development of commercial (i.e. profit-making) strategies; and
3 the attack on environmental problems.

Virtually none of this work is concerned with the applied ‘arms’ of the two other types of science
identified in Chapter 1, leading to either greater self- and mutual awareness (see Chapter 5) or
emancipation (Chapter 6). To that extent, most applied geography in the English-speaking world
accepts, and seeks to serve, the ruling ideas – and so also the ‘(new) ruling class’ Harvey (2003).
The nature of applied geography has been restricted by some to work at the ‘society–
environment interface’. When launching the journal Applied Geography in 1981, for example, its
founding editor followed Stamp (1960, p. 10), who defined the discipline’s applied role as
addressing ‘some of the great world problems – the increasing pressure of population on space, the
development of underdeveloped areas, or the attempt to improve living conditions’. Two decades
Applied geography and the relevance debates 335

later, according to Briggs (1981, p. 2), ‘These problems remain. Indeed, they are growing;
environmental problems such as pollution, damage to wildlife, destruction of habitats, soil erosion
and resource depletion; the problems of human deprivation and inequality.’ He set out the
fundamental basis of applied geography as use of resources:

The exploitation of scarce resources represents a dominating theme to human existence. It is


from the pursuit of these resources and from the attempt to decide between alternative policies
of exploitation, that not only environmental damage, but also the greater part of political, social
and economic problems emerge; they can be seen as expressions of man’s inability to organize
himself and his world to his best, long-term advantage.

To overcome that inability, the applied geographer must be brave (p. 6): ‘He needs to commit
himself before he knows all the answers. He needs to be able to make public mistakes. But he must
also be prepared to learn from them.’
Much applied work undertaken by academic geographers has been commissioned by one or
more arms of the public sector and many (perhaps most) geographers who have applied their skills
in non-academic careers have probably entered the public sector too. Given the importance of the
welfare state in the first four post-Second World War decades, this has not been surprising.
Nevertheless, work has always been done for the private sector too – for example, geographers such
as Applebaum (1954) were involved in work for supermarket and similar companies in the USA
during the 1950s and geographers were central to the establishment of an Institute for Retail
Studies at the University of Stirling in the mid-1980s (Dawson et al., 2006; see also Wrigley, 2002).
Others, building on their expertise in spatial data handling, have moved into information
management, including some who work in prestigious university business schools.
The pressure on university academics to obtain more external financial support for research
activities since the 1980s stimulated much more work for the private sector (Breheny, 1989) – a
trend accentuated by the attempts to reduce the size of the public sector and to increase
competitiveness and efficiency in the provision of public goods (including, of course, higher
education). Some of this work has involved spatial analysis in its various forms – as by the GMap
company established at the School of Geography at the University of Leeds, which has applied and
extended Alan Wilson’s pioneering work on location-allocation models to a wide range of problems
in, for example, operations research for healthcare providers and the location of franchises for
major car firms (Birkin et al., 1990, 1996; Birkin et al., 1995; Birkin et al., 2002, 2010); the company
was later sold by the university into the private sector. Other work has used geographers’ skills in
spatial data handling (what Openshaw and others refer to as ‘adding value’ to geocoded data) in the
growing field of geodemographics, whereby marketing and other campaigns are spatially targetted
to people living in areas where demand for particular goods and services is most likely to be
generated (Batey and Brown, 1995; Birkin, 1995; Harris et al., 2005; Longley, 2012). More widely,
a number of UK university geography departments have followed the early lead from Edinburgh
(p. 315, this book) and Leeds, and established units involving their academic staff and others
appointed for their research skills, only to undertake applied work (much of it interdisciplinary) in
a wide range of fields; examples include the Flood Hazard Research Centre at the University of
Middlesex (Penning-Rowsell and Pardoe, 2012), the International Boundaries Research Unit at the
University of Durham (which publishes two series of books – the International Boundary Studies Series and
the World Boundaries Series – as well as regular briefings: www.dur.ac.uk/ibru/) and the Personal
Finance Research Centre at the University of Bristol (www.bristol.ac.uk/geography/research/pfrc/
about/).
In many cases, because of commercial sensitivity such work – especially its applied components
– is not fully reported in academic journals and thus the discipline as a whole may not be aware of
it. An example is Alice Coleman’s (1985) research on the effects of building design on behaviour,
336 Applied geography and the relevance debates

based on Oscar Newman’s (1972) concept of defensible space; alongside her academic publications
she had a considerable impact on contemporary debates about neighbourhood design and UK £50
million was invested in experiments to test her ideas (Jacobs and Lees, 2013). Where the goal is to
influence (usually public) policy in general rather than a specific project, publication in academic
journals alongside the private advice is more feasible, as in work on the operation of housing
markets (e.g. Smith, 2008, 2015; Smith et al., 2006) led to policy proposals (Parkinson et al., 2009;
Smith and Searle, 2010; Smith et al., 2008).
A geographer who perhaps made more contributions to applied geography was Peter Hall.
Initially a historical geographer, he published many detailed analyses of urbanisation and the
cultural context of urban growth, including his magnum opus Cities in Civilization (Hall, 1998). He also
researched the nature of the UK planning system in comparative context, including a major two-
volume critique of its impact (Hall et al., 1973). His research led him not only to make many
contributions to debates over future urban form and its planning – not only as critic and
commentator but also as consultant and adviser to several governments – but also to paint scenarios
of those futures, as in London 2001 (Hall, 1989). His was a humanistic approach, as indicated by
the title of one of his last books – Good Cities: Better lives (Hall, 2014: for a full appreciation of his
career and work, including his own apologia per vita sua, see Tewdwr-Jones et al., 2014).

Changing contexts and applied geography


The demands for greater involvement in what is generally termed applied geography have grown
in recent decades, largely as a response to changes in the societal contexts within which Anglo-
American human geographers work. This is not a surprising trend, according to Peter Taylor’s
(1985a) analysis of the history of geography. In periods of economic recession, cutbacks in public
funding for higher education and research can be expected, and to counter the loss of support
academic researchers are forced to seek financial backing elsewhere (including arms of the state
which contract for research); that backing is only likely to come if individuals within the discipline,
and even organisations representing it, can convince potential sponsors of the value (i.e. potential
‘profitability’) of investing in geography and geographers. From this observation, and following
Gräno (1981), Taylor (1985a, p. 100) identified two external influences on disciplinary
developments: ‘Within academia geographers had to be given an intellectual foundation to satisfy
intellectual peers, and outside in the wider world geography had to be justified as a useful activity
on which to spend public money.’ These produce ‘pure’ and ‘applied’ geography respectively. Both
are necessary to a discipline’s future, but the relative emphasis placed on each will vary over time
and space:

Outside pressures will be particularly acute in periods of economic recession when all public
expenditure has to prove its worth. All disciplines will tend to emphasize their problem-solving
capacity and we can expect applied geography to be in the ascendancy. . . . In contrast in a period
of expanding economies and social optimism outside pressures will diminish and academia can
be expected to be under less external pressure. Geographers will thus be able to contemplate
their discipline and feel much less guilty about this activity. We can expect bursts of pure
geography to occur in these periods.

Taylor identified cycles of pure and applied geography corresponding to cycles in economic
prosperity, and Hägerstrand (1977, p. 329) reached a similar conclusion: ‘When the world is stable
and/or unhampered liberalism prevails, then there is probably not much to do for geographers
except surviving in academic departments trying to keep up competence and train schoolteachers
in how wisely arranged the world is.’ (Applied geography is also an increasing focus in many
Applied geography and the relevance debates 337

degree curricula which focus on transferable skills – notably in GIS – that students can deploy in a
variety of occupations: Schlemper et al., 2014; Singleton and Spielman, 2014.)
The period since the late 1970s should demonstrate applied geography in the ascendancy,
according to Taylor’s analysis, an expectation generally supported by experience of those years.
Pressure to justify the discipline in terms of utility to economic goals was strong, and the search for
research contracts of all types became much more determined (so that learned journals and
newsletters began to list new grants and contracts won by geographers, and institutions such as the
IBG prepared documents to promote the discipline that emphasised its utilitarian aspects, including
one which graduates could show to potential employers). That pressure for applied geography
continued into the neoliberal environment of the 1980s and following decades, with academic
departments continually encouraged to canvass for research funds from outside sponsors (which
they were apparently very successful at: Johnston, 1995b). In the 2013 UK Research Excellence
Framework , one-fifth of the evaluation was based on assessments of the impact of their research
on outside users, with each department having to produce case studies showing how the work of
individual academics or groups have directly implicated either public policy or commercial
activities (Collini, 2012; Pain et al., 2011). Increasingly, too, many of them promote their
degree programmes to potential students in terms of the skills that they will learn which will
be of benefit to them in the labour market (with considerable emphasis in recent years on
GIS and related technologies, as discussed on p. 157, this book). Such non-partisan academic
advice based on research evidence informing public debate and legislation is now frequently
published by learned societies such as the British Academy (e.g. Hix et al., 2010; Balinski
et al., 2010).
The consequences of ‘The Impact Agenda’ for geography became the subject of heated debates,
led by academics based in the UK, where the Research Excellence Framework institutionalised
audits and claims about impact (Pain et al., 2011; Slater, 2012). As the introduction to a set of essays
on impact and human geography noted:

Academics across diverse disciplines within the UK are therefore grappling with the changing
expectations and pressures placed on research, its practices and relationships. The impact
agenda requires that impact must be directly traceable back to a piece of published research,
even though in reality that relationship may not be direct or linear.
(Rogers et al., 2014, p. 4)

More generally, geographers – allied with other social scientists – have increasingly ‘sold’ their
relevance to government and other potential ‘stakeholders’ – the UK Academy of Social Sciences, for
example, published a volume on Why the Social Sciences Matter (Michie and Cooper, 2015), a booklet
on The Business of People (Campaign for the Social Sciences, 2015), and a volume researching The Impact
of the Social Sciences (Bastow et al., 2014).

The place of applied geography


While in the UK the impact agenda has led to a further phase of discussion in the recent years, the
desirability of applied geography has long been debated . Some clearly accepted and argued for an
applied ethos, but their main concern was either with geography using its perceived particular
skills in what Harvey (1973; see p. 316, this book) termed the application of status quo theory
(as in Pacione, 1990a, 1990b) or with exploring how geographers could make a committed
contribution towards the achievement of change (Clark, 1982).
Bennett (1989b) based a case for a reorientation of what geographers do on a belief that there
has been a major shift in the ‘culture of the times’, away from ‘welfarism’ – a consensus ideology
aimed at ‘improving the quality of life and provision of needs through collective and governmental
338 Applied geography and the relevance debates

intervention’ (p. 273) – towards what he terms ‘post-welfarism’, which emphasises individual
rather than collective decision-making, and the role of markets rather than states:

the emergent ‘culture of the times’ has been happier to see the market as both the creator and
the provider of new wants. Rather than markets being seen as an inhumane and exploitative
system, socialism and even corporatist social democracy have come to be associated with the
odious and paternalistic treatment of individuals.
(p. 286)

This led him to criticise geographers who work with ‘social theory’ and accept the welfarist ethos,
as being necessarily of the ‘political left’, and he challenged their ‘core concept of relative deprivation
and its consequential focus on relative intervention’, which inevitably leads to a situation of ‘total
state intervention in everything’, Bennett argued that:

Where the Thatcher era has heralded consumer choice and economic change, social theory and
socialist politics have sought to defend the mode of production and to trap people in labour-
intensive work practices and unattractive jobs vulnerable to technological change. The spirit of
market freedom of individuals has heralded a consumer and service economy which has offered
the release from the least attractive toils and labours, and has seemed to offer the potential to
satisfy many of people’s most avaricious dreams.
(p. 286)

This market-oriented society poses an important challenge to geographers’ applied role. It was
embraced by a number of geographers, including some who work with GIS. Longley (1995,
p. 127), for example, argued that spatial analysis using GIS technology can enhance business
management systems, enabling users ‘to gain competitive advantage in sophisticated consumer-led
markets’. He criticised the ‘deskilling of geography and planning’ associated with arguments such
as Harvey’s (1989b) that quantitative research has produced little relevant output. Not only does
the development and teaching of GIS equip students with ‘a range of flexible skills for use in
continually restructuring labour markets’ (p. 129; see also NAS-NRC, 1997; NRC, 2011), but in
addition the range of applications:

provides clear testimony that quantitative spatial analysis is most certainly not preoccupied with
techniques that do not work to analyse problems that do not matter. Social science that does not
show interest in real world issues of popular concern is doomed to remain on the sidelines of
academic respectability and perceived social relevance, and reinvigorated spatial analysis is
central to the measurement and modelling of economic and social aspects of human behaviour.

Bennett portrayed the geographical research he criticised as focused on aiding government


intervention in economy and society, without questioning its validity. He believed such intervention
to be no longer viable and also rejected its underpinning critical stance, based on a critique of
capitalism. He identified the intellectual challenge for geographers to involve dismissing notions of
a welfare state founded on a social theory which emphasises rights and relative needs, because
policies based on such theory ‘cannot be proved to work. . . . Even social democracy offers no easy
solutions’ (p. 287). But markets do fail, so:

The two key questions for a post-welfarist society are: first how can support be improved by
practical policies that can be demonstrated to work and are reasonably cost-effective; and
second at what point does governmental action end. . . . Hence what is needed is a better
definition of what is ‘socially’ possible through collective action and what is not. Social theory and
Applied geography and the relevance debates 339

social democracy have, perhaps, promised too much and hence led to disillusionment in its own
promises.
(pp. 287–8)

Answering those questions is central to the role he cast for geographers: ‘The grand objective of
the discipline should be to contribute to the debate around these issues. But it must be a
contribution to practice.’ This implies a discipline in which practical concern with means is
more important than theoretical debate about ends. In a post-welfarist society:

The welfare state, and its associated public decision-making, no longer have the privileged
status that it can be justified by mere statements of belief in public or governmental goods:
public goods and the policy that provides them have to be demonstrated to be effective in meeting
social needs; policies have to work and be more effective than alternatives.
(pp. 288–9)

Bennett provided no detail regarding what such a post-welfarist geography would contain,
though he referred approvingly to Openshaw’s (1989) arguments (see p. 156, this book). He
offered two brief suggestions, however. The first is a criticism of Marxist and related work:

The key aspect . . . is a better understanding of the structure of economic incentives and rights,
rather than class. . . . We need to identify a new language not of class but of ‘rights’ or nature. By
which I mean choice conceptions of rights which promote autonomy, freedom, self-determination
and human development, and not ‘interest’ conceptions of rights which make people passive
beneficiaries of the services of others.
(p. 289)

The other is a recommendation that:

For the academic discipline of geography this means adaptation of its frameworks of teaching
and research. I would argue that one aspect of this requires more intensive training in analytical
methods including model-based approaches, information systems and elementary analytical
skills.

Thus, geographers are called upon to participate in a re-evaluation of the welfare state, focusing
attention on the limits to both individual choice and collective action, and to develop the analytical
skills which will advance policy appraisal and so contribute ‘useful knowledge to the research
process, to policy debate and to practice’ (p. 290). In his commentary at the end of the book in
which Bennett’s chapter appears, Macmillan (1989b, p. 306) comments that ‘the idea that the
welfarist tradition is in terminal decline seems highly debatable’, though developments in
subsequent decades indicated that many governments are reconsidering the nature of their welfare
provision in more market-oriented terms and the consequences of the post-2008 debt and fiscal
crises in many countries saw the implementation of widespread reconfiguration of and cuts in
welfare eligibility and expenditure, in the context of (contested) political rhetoric that austerity
policies are needed to counter the crises.
The 1990s and subsequent decades did not see a return to the ‘traditional’ welfare state,
therefore, but rather a continuation of the trends set by Thatcherism in the UK and Reaganism in
the USA. The hegemonic ideology is associated with ‘neo-liberalism’ (Brenner and Theodore,
2002a, p. 350), underpinned by a ‘belief that open, competitive and unregulated markets, liberated
from all forms of state interference, represent the optimal mechanism for economic development’.
As they pointed out, however, this belief is generally associated with new sets of policies of state
340 Applied geography and the relevance debates

interference in non-economic spheres – usually conceived as associated with promotion


of economic success (Brenner and Theodore, 2002b) – as illustrated by the rise of the ‘workfare
state’ (Peck, 2001; Painter, 2002) and increased levels of prison incarceration in the USA (Gilmore,
2002).

Continuing debates: grey, public and participatory


geographies
Geographers have undertaken a great deal of applied work over recent decades, in both public and
private sectors and across a wide range of subject matter. In addition to the activities of those
working within academia, many trained geographers are putting their expertise into practice, not
least in the deployment of GIS (Wright, 2012), in which geographers play central roles in the
training of students and practitioners and the development of software for a wide range of
applications. This latter activity is probably more visible in the USA, where the AAG has a large
applied geography specialty group and holds regular conferences as well as sessions at the
Association’s annual meetings; these occur alongside specialist GIS conferences such as GISRUK and
ESRI’s international user conferences.
Despite all of this, however, and in part reacting to contemporary changes in the discipline, a
number of geographers bemoan their discipline’s apparent relative failure to address major
contemporary issues within society – i.e. to be sufficiently applied and relevant, and therefore
influential. Peck (1999), for example, argued in an editorial entitled ‘Grey geography?’ that ‘human
geographers have on the whole been conspicuous by their absence from substantive policy debates’
(p. 131). Academic practice increasingly privileges research outputs in the form of journal papers
(which enhance career prospects and a department’s ratings) over ‘practical and policy-oriented
research’:

Policy research seems to have become the grey ‘other’ of academic research. While academic
research appeals, with its cerebral and ‘pure’ processes of library-based learning and thoughtful
contemplation, to the privileged scientific canon, policy research is often tainted by its association
with cash, clients, contracts and reports-in-cardboard-covers. An appropriate analogy here
might be with the distinction between manual and mental labour, where policy research is
associated with ‘getting one’s hands dirty’.

The division between ‘academic’ and ‘practical’ research is potentially damaging to geography, he
claims, with the latter being significantly neglected and undervalued. Such research need not be
constructive – using the term in the sense of sustaining the status quo distribution of wealth and
power, but it should be engaged and effective – ‘Active participation in the formal policy process,
and in the wider political domain in which this is embedded, is surely something that geographers
would dispense with at their peril’ (p. 133). He cautions, however, that some policy-research is
‘shallow and simple’ (p. 134), aimed at quick fixes, as compared with that which is ‘deep and
complex’; unfortunately, the former is more likely to have an immediate impact within policy
communities, so that geographers wishing to influence policy have to find ways of being influential
without compromising their (‘deep and complex’) academic strengths.
Massey (2000) expanded this argument. She noted that there had long been an antipathy
towards the social sciences within political and policy communities, especially towards the ‘soft’
social sciences (i.e. all but economics), but that the UK’s New Labour government (1997–2010)
sought to change that in its drive towards ‘evidence-led policy’. However, one of the problems with
such a stance is that the politicians and policy-makers remain those who pose the questions and call
for the evidence which, in Peck’s terms, may call for ‘shallow and simple’ responses. She argues that
Applied geography and the relevance debates 341

social scientists (including geographers) should be involved in both reformulating the questions
and raising others that are rarely, if ever, asked. To do that requires a ‘more in-depth and sustained
relationship with policymakers’ (p. 132) than has been the norm. Massey exemplified her case
regarding geographers’ lack of impact with regard to regional uneven development in the UK,
suggesting that public debates about this in 2000–1 were being conducted as if no research had
been done on the issue. A government adviser had said in her presence that academics were ‘a waste
of time’ and ‘never came up with anything of real use to those involved in “real politics”’ (Massey,
2001, p. 11). To some extent this confirmed her view that much of what we write as academics for
academics (and perhaps their students) has no wider impact, but it also implied that ‘the only way
to be politically or socially relevant was to come up with advice or answers on government policy’
(p. 12). There is a need for a much wider engagement, deploying geographic theories and evidence
to promote policy initiatives rather than accepting the agenda of others, but to do that geographers
needed to tackle the negative public image of their discipline as ‘boring, as being a joke subject, as
being all about capes and bays’. Geographers have to tackle their intellectual image if they are to be
heard and respected in the policy-making corridors. (See also the essays, including her own, in her
festschrift volume: Featherstone and Painter, 2013.)
A similar theme was developed by Leyshon (1995) and reiterated by Ron Martin (2001a;
Martin and Sunley, 2011; Wrigley, 2013), who were concerned that geographers were not making
a greater impact in debates about major contemporary issues, such as growing inequality (though
see Philo, 1995). To Ron Martin (2001a, p. 267), important but rarely asked questions include
‘What are we doing geography for?’ and ‘For whom are we doing it?’. In this context:

Part of our endeavour must surely be to expose and explain the inequalities and injustices that
our socio-economic and [sic] system produces and reproduces. And following from this, we have
an obligation, indeed a duty, to assess and debate policy responses to those inequalities and
injustices, with a view to exposing the limitations of existing approaches and helping to reshape
political and public opinion as to possible alternatives. In short, there is a key role for the
geographer as social critic, and a strong case for making geography a more activist endeavour.

However, it seems that we aren’t, so that there is a missing agenda with regard to geography and
public policy, and associated with this is a failure to meet what he sees as a ‘moral duty’. That duty
involves an agenda with three main items: exposing and explaining inequalities (as in Dorling,
2010); interrogating and evaluating existing policies and practices; and ‘seeking to exert a direct
influence on policy-making processes, at all scales, with the aim of producing more appropriate
and more effective forms of policy intervention’ (Martin, 2001b, p. 190). (The implication is that
this should be an organised collective response, but later (p. 194) he acknowledges that there is a
case that such policy activity should be a separate response by individual geographers operating
within their own academic and political agenda – a restatement of Hare’s earlier argument; p. 315,
this book). The main reason why we currently lack influence, Martin argues, is not because we
publicise our work insufficiently or that we lack confidence in arenas beyond our immediate
profession but, rather, because ‘much of what is done under the banner of human geography is
unlikely to be seen by policy-makers as being remotely germane to policy issues. The fundamental
problem is that there is no readily discernible policy research agenda in the discipline’ (p. 191).
A major cause for geography’s policy irrelevance, Ron Martin argued (2001b, p. 194), was ‘the
postmodern/textualist/discursive and cultural “turns” that have had such a pervasive impact across
the subject in the last few years’. These have enriched the discipline in a number of ways but
nevertheless resulted in its further retreat from policy research and modes of enquiry: ‘it is difficult
to envisage how the vague abstractions and epistemic and ontological relativism of much of human
geography research . . . can form the basis of a critical public policy analysis’ (p. 196). Hamnett
(2003) agreed, claiming that geographers are not addressing major issues of global and national
342 Applied geography and the relevance debates

significance to anything like the level they should. For him, too, ‘much recent cultural geography
. . . has been a retreat from substantive political engagement and social analysis in favour of
superficial academic radicalism’ (p. 2):

parts of geography are the new intellectual dilettanti: relevance has been replaced by irrelevance,
reality by representation and social criticism by theoretical critique. For some, contemporary
human geography has become an arena for theoretical play, little more. Regrettably, such frothy
theoretical constructions are likely to be viewed in the outside world as . . . nice to look at, nice
to taste but insubstantial and not to be taken seriously.
(p. 3)

Their prognoses differed, however. For Martin, human geography is suffering from a lack of
empirical and explanatory rigour, as well as an intellectual bias against policy issues and a lack of
political commitment. Insufficient numbers of geographers lack one or more of these. As he notes,
to many empirical rigour implies ‘positivistic, quantitative methods and formal (statistical and
mathematical) analysis, and what is widely regarded as a misplaced search for general principles’
(p. 197). It may, but it need not: rigour calls for a ‘sustained attempt to interrogate . . . evidence
critically, to contextualize it thoroughly, to test propositions or to assess its wider relevance’. For
Hamnett, on the other hand, ‘Quantitative techniques and aggregate social research have been
largely abandoned. . . . Analysis of large data sets has become totally passé, the object of suspicion
or even derision as “empiricist”’ (p. 2; but see Johnston et al., 2003; Johnston et al., 2014a, 2014b).
In responding to these critiques, several authors have presented partial defences of the
contemporary situation, while at the same time agreeing with the force of much that has been
written. Several, too, highlight the constraints on academic work in this area, given other career
pressures. Thus, for example, both Banks and MacKian (2000) and Pollard et al. (2000) argue that
Peck focused too narrowly on a particular genre of policy research – emphasising macro-economic
issues to the neglect of others in social, environmental and cultural policy realms on which much
is being done, especially at local scales: ‘geographers are not abandoning policy – it is simply that
we are approaching it from many more angles, guises and positions than Peck gives us credit for’
(Banks and MacKian, 2000, p. 253). Peck (2000) responded positively, while at the same time
stressing his preference for engaged policy research, ‘which gets behind the backs – and, if necessary,
under the feet or up the noses – of policy makers and elite actors’ (p. 255). This involves creating a
different image for geographers and their fundamental concerns; in contemporary society,
neoclassical economic thinking is generally accepted as ‘the commonsense of our age’ (p. 256),
whereas critical geographical thinking is not.
The response from Dorling and Shaw (2002) called for geographers to participate more in
debates beyond their academic discipline and spend less time on ‘internal discussions’. In order to
get their arguments across to such wider audiences, they claim, geographers need concrete (i.e.
empirical, quantitative) not abstract arguments, presented without any deployment of ‘elitist
jargon’; the former are more likely to be reported in the press and eventually to infiltrate the policy-
making arena. Geographers also need, according to their prescription, to interact more with other
social scientists. At present, they do not value policy-related work, and are not very good at it when
they try; they are also too inclined to jump on new bandwagons – and perhaps geography ‘is an
intellectual safety net, an academic refugee camp – a place where academics can work on whatever
they wish to work on and not be disturbed by the need to conform to the traditions of other
disciplines . . . a home for intellectual anarchists’ (p. 638). Nevertheless, on a positive note they also
conclude that:

Academic research does influence policy. . . . It also helps to form the values of both individuals
and institutions. Most current policies are informed in some way by findings which were derived
Applied geography and the relevance debates 343

from university-based research at some point in the past. Most individual views are now very
much informed by what children learn in schools from teachers, almost all of whom are to some
degree influenced by what they learned at university. Similarly, academics in universities may
perhaps have their greatest impact through their teaching rather than publication.
(pp. 637–8)

So, as long as enough geography is taught in universities, eventually it will trickle through the
educational system and influence later generations of policy-makers. Ron Martin (2002) largely
agreed with them, pointing to a malaise within geography – its ‘inferior standing and profile in the
wider academic, educational and public domains’ (p. 643; see also Martin Powell and George
Boyne, 2001, and the response by John Mohan, 2003). For Massey (2002), however, Dorling and
Shaw have a narrow conception of the ‘political’: one can become embedded in civil society in a
wide variety of ways and arenas, gaining influence indirectly as a consequence. A discussion of
British urban policy illustrates one such route (Amin et al., 2000), whereas Susan Smith’s (1986)
classic monograph on Crime, Space and Society also illustrates the wider applicability of geographic
research. Meanwhile, Bonnett (2003) called on university geographers to capitalise on public
interest in their subject matter and connect with this in critical and engaging ways. In a related
move, Kevin Ward (2006) joined those exploring what might be meant by ‘public geographies’ and
how these could be fostered. He claimed that these public geographies were about more than policy
per se, and ‘more about the public or publics’ (p. 496) with whom geographers might usefully and
productively engage:

Let’s acknowledge that both [policy and public geographies] are legitimate means of involving
geographers and geography in the lives of people, in a world in which geography structures
the very social relations that hold together the human (and the non-human world). And let
us also reflect on how the public engagement of today might become the policy reform of
tomorrow.
(p. 501)

This notion of public geography broadly coincided with the development of what are known
as participatory geographies, a form of action-orientated research (Pain, 2003) involving
engagement with, rather than just study of, individuals, groups and communities; the research itself
is collaborative and involves not just enhancing appreciation of situations but assisting the
collaborators in campaigning for change in their (usually local) circumstances (Kindon et al., 2007;
mrs kinpaisby, 2008). A Participatory Geographies Research Group was established within the
RGS–IBG in 2007, taking forward ideas and approaches first launched by Bunge in the late
1960s – which themselves were partly inspired by the anarchist writings of Kropotkin and Reclus
(Springer, 2012). Emancipatory in its aims, this work is largely local in its orientation, although
Harvey (2012) has linked grassroots movements with the larger goal of replacing capitalism, and
Mason et al. (2013) have suggested a broader agenda aimed at ‘seeking out the workings of power
and resulting injustices and thence striving to transform such actions’ (p. 255).
Other work that has a broadly emancipatory goal includes critical work in geopolitics, broadly
defined. Books like Gregory’s (2004) The Colonial Present, Harvey’s (2003) The New Imperialism and
Neil Smith’s (2005b) The Endgame of Globalization are all aimed at much wider audiences than their
academic peers, and have been reviewed in the non-academic media. Furthermore, their authors
have become public intellectuals (Castree, 2006a), not only through their writing but also their
public performances and commentaries on contemporary events (as illustrated by Gregory’s
website: http://geographicalimaginations.com/).
344 Applied geography and the relevance debates

Conclusions
Many of the arguments for applied geography have located it within the spatial-science approach
to the discipline; that which is applicable is that which is based on empiricism, as illustrated
in Pacione’s (1999) substantial overview of ‘useful knowledge’ in geography. But each of the
three types of science identified in Chapter 1 has its ‘applied arm’; hermeneutic sciences have
as their goal the development of self- and mutual understanding, a project shared with the
critical sciences, whose emancipatory aspirations seek similar understanding within the wider
context of appreciation of the economic, social, cultural and political contexts within which
individuals and groups are embedded. Whereas radical geography sought emancipation largely in
the context of class interests (e.g. Harvey, 2012), therefore, that imbued with the cultural turn
promoted a wide range of identity politics, within which class is only of the foundations
(May, 1996b), and which the gender and sexual politics that feminist and allied work in geography
brought to the fore within the discipline. Such emancipatory intentions may extend further, both
opening people’s eyes to the nature of the world and leading them towards alternative scenarios
but, as the collection of papers introduced by Michael Woods and Graham Gardiner (2011)
illustrates, applied policy research can create dilemmas for those whose roots are within the critical
geography, what they identify as the trade-offs between principles and pragmatism. Thus, Blunt and
Wills (2000, p. x) introduced their book on dissident geographies by classifying them as sharing ‘a
political commitment to overturning prevailing relations of power and oppression’. Their stance
was further illustrated by the title and subtitle of a book, and many of the essays therein, published
to mark the fortieth anniversary of the first edition of the journal Antipode (Castree et al., 2010). Only
a few scholars, however (e.g. Harvey, 2000), have laid out in detail what such an alternative
(applied) geography might look like (see Gibbons, 2001), or explored how it might be brought
about (though see Harvey, 2012). Yet the development of wider debates reconsidering the nature
and place of applied geography, the arrival of public geography and a renewal of moves to enact
participatory geographies indicate that Harvey’s (1974c) earlier arguments remain pertinent to
fresh generations of geographers, whereby the crucial questions to be asked about any work
claiming to be ‘relevant’ continue to be ‘relevant to whom?’ and ‘for what?’ Three decades later, a
survey and review of ‘The Complex Politics of Relevance in Geography’ indicated, however, that
these questions could be answered in a diversity of ways. Therefore:

relevance is not easily measured, and may not be directly observable. While this perspective may
be at odds with the performance – or productivity-based outcomes that increasingly dominate
evaluations of research, we argue that our approach recognizes the ineluctably political nature
of relevance and the diverse goals that we, as a community of scholars, promote.
(Staeheli and Mitchell, 2005, pp. 357–8)

Whereas the debates about the impact agenda in the UK shaped the way that relevance and
applied geography have been conceptualised in recent years, the fact that responses from UK-based
geographers include discussions of ‘creativity’ (Phillips, 2010) and ‘engaging’ (Wills, 2014) is
testimony to ongoing contest about what/who is geography for. These contests transcend national
frameworks, however, taking their place in a wider disciplinary nexus of anglophone geography
whose past, present and futures we reappraise in the next chapter.
Chapter 10

A changing discipline?

I was only fifteen when I chose geography as my field. Twelve years later, in 1957, I received my
doctoral degree. So ended my long period of formal training. Ever since, I have not only taught
and done research in geography but I have breathed and lived it. How was (is) that possible?
How can geography, a rather down-to-earth-subject, have such a hold on me, offer me
‘salvation’ when, from time to time, my personal life seemed to be the pits? I couldn’t have
answered properly as a teenager or even as a newly minted PhD. I can give a well-rounded
answer only late in life – in retrospect, for the meaning of geography has expanded over a
lifetime. It grew as I grew.
(Yi-Fu Tuan, 1999, p. 93)

[Geographers] appear to live in an intellectual world characterized by groups of people plowing


their own theoretical furrows, with little outright objection to others doing their own thing. . . .
There is very little engagement between geographers today and geography over 20 years ago.
(Tim Cresswell, 2013, pp. 196, 15)

I wondered if the institutional position of the discipline had strengthened with its recently
enhanced intellectual position, and what the geography of geography’s institutional presence
and strength was. For sure, anecdotal stories circulate regarding the opening or closure of a
geography department, a renaming, a split and so forth . . .
(Lily Kong, 2007, p. 13)

Shifts of major importance [in geographical practices] do occur, but they seldom encompass
the whole scientific community – old ideas and concepts remain with us to a large extent; new
discoveries may sometimes have the character or mutations – and usually they look more like
the rephrasing of old truths.
(Arild Holt-Jensen, 2009, p. 124)

The preceding chapters have outlined the major debates among anglophone human geographers
since 1945 regarding their discipline’s practices – what it studies, how and why. The temporal
(post-1945) and spatial (UK and anglophone North America, though with some English-language
material from elsewhere) foci have been placed in broader historical and geographical contexts. The
chapter titles themselves indicate that several very different approaches to the discipline have been
advocated; their contents suggest a large number of academics promoting new arrangements but
being resisted by defenders of the old order – to a greater or lesser extent. The purpose of this final
chapter is not to assess progress within those approaches (Lowe and Short, 1990), let alone to
establish whether they have contributed towards the attainment of ‘higher levels of intellectual,
social and physical well-being for [our] fellow men [and women]’ (Wise, 1977, p. 10); indeed,
according to some interpretations, progress in the Enlightenment sense of that term is not feasible
346 A changing discipline?

(T. Barnes, 1996; Johnston and Sidaway, 2015). For, as Bassett (1999, p. 28) sets out in detail, one’s
determination of whether there has been progress depends on how that concept is defined.
Geography may have made one or more of: institutional progress – becoming more firmly
established and influential within academia; empirical progress – in that it can better predict some
aspects of the ‘reality’ it studies; explanatory progress – being better able to explain through
concepts and theories that which it studies; conceptual progress – with its theories having wider
scope and greater internal consistency; progress in intersubjective understanding – we can now
appreciate better how we and others see the world; pragmatic progress – our understanding allows
better public policy; and emancipatory progress – we are freed from illusions about how the world
works. (Tambolo, 2015, focuses on just three theories of progress: two derive from Popper –
increased explanatory power and closer approximations to the truth; the other to Feyerabend –
a steady increase of competing alternatives.)
Over the period discussed in this book, progress along several, if not all, of those dimensions
may have been achieved. Assessing that is not the basic concern here, however. Rather, the evaluation
returns to the issues raised in Chapter 1, where several models of the development of scientific
disciplines were presented. No formal testing of those models is presented, for no methodology has
been outlined that would allow such a task. Instead, their general relevance is assessed against the
material outlined in the earlier chapters.

Human geographers and models of disciplinary progress


Along with members of almost every other scientific and social science discipline, human
geographers have been attracted to the ideas and language of Kuhn’s paradigm model (M. Harvey
and Holly, 1981):

the use of the word paradigm has become fashionable in geography as well as having become a
pivotal concept for courses in geographic thought on both sides of the Atlantic. Thomas Kuhn
has become as familiar to students of geography as Hartshorne or Humboldt.
(p. 11)

Kuhnian ideas were applied in the 1960s and 1970s with relatively little reference to the major
debates they had stimulated throughout Anglo-American academia, however. Most human
geographers relied, it seems, on the first (1962) edition of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, apparently
unaware either that ‘The loose use of “paradigm” in his book has made [it] amenable to a wide
variety of incompatible interpretations’ (Suppe, 1977a, p. 137) or that ‘Kuhn’s views have undergone
a sharply declining influence on contemporary philosophy of science’ (Suppe, 1977c, p. 647).
Furthermore, Kuhn (1977) substantially revised his ideas later (see also the exegesis of his work in
B. Barnes, 1982) and argued that it would be rare for a paradigm as he understood it (puzzle-
solving within a normal science framework) to appear in the human sciences because their goal is
‘new and deeper interpretations’ (Kuhn, 1991, p. 23). Geographers at that time displayed a general
tendency to adopt ideas from other disciplines rather uncritically. Agnew and Duncan (1981),
for example, argued that:

Recent reviews and programmatic statements concerning trends in Anglo-American human


geography leave the impression that little attention has been given by geographers to the
philosophical compatibility of borrowed ideas . . . that the political implications of different ideas
have largely been ignored . . . and that controversy on source disciplines or literatures has not
excited much interest.
(p. 42)
A changing discipline? 347

Their examples do not include the import of Kuhnian ideas into geography, but their conclusions
certainly hold in this case. (For a critical discussion of geographers’ importing Kuhnian ideas, see
Mair, 1986. It could have been used as one of the examples in Symanski and Agnew’s (1981, p. 2)
treatment of ‘order and skepticism in geography’, in which they argue that ‘geographers have given
too much attention to the search for order and not enough to skepticism’.)
Kuhnian concepts were first used in the geographical literature by Haggett and Chorley (1967),
as part of a normative argument for a revolution in geographical method – and, perhaps surprisingly,
in a book that they produced from a conference designed to introduce school-teachers to their
‘new geography’. Models in Geography was reprinted in three separate paperbacks and widely used as
an undergraduate text (Haggett, 2015). Nevertheless, the context of its production echoes
Goodson’s (1988) claim that geography is one of the few academic disciplines for which the
pressure for its establishment in universities came largely from school-teachers (on which, see
Chapter 2). Haggett and Chorley argued that the then dominant paradigm, as they defined it, could
not handle either the explosion of relevant data for geographical research or the increasing
fragmentation and compartmentalisation of the sciences. They proposed a new ‘model-based’
paradigm:

able to rise above this flood-tide of information and push out confidently and rapidly into new
data-territories. It must possess the scientific habit of seeking for relevant pattern and order in
information, and the related ability to rapidly discard irrelevant information.
(p. 38)

A similar situation some fifty years later has been suggested with the rise of ‘big data’ (Kitchin,
2013; Graham and Shelton, 2013).
That new paradigm had been launched more than a decade previously (see Chapter 3); Haggett
and Chorley’s goal was to spread the new ideas, and to win British converts to a new orientation of
work within geography. In the same book, Stoddart (1967b, p. 512) used the concept to promote
an ‘organic paradigm’ – as a ‘general conceptual model’. When that essay was reprinted in 1986, he
added as a footnote ‘that I would now take a less enthusiastic view of Kuhn’s analysis’ (Stoddart,
1986, p. 231).
Haggett and Chorley were attracted by the concept of scientific revolutions. A similar argument
was presented in a paper that appeared at almost the same time as Kuhn’s book. Burton (1963,
p. 113) introduced the term ‘quantitative and theoretical revolution’ and argued that:

An intellectual revolution is over when accepted ideas have been overthrown or have been
modified to include new ideas. An intellectual revolution is over when the revolutionary ideas
themselves become part of the conventional wisdom. When Ackerman, Hartshorne and Spate
are in substantial agreement about something, then we are talking about the conventional
wisdom. Hence, my belief that the quantitative revolution is over and has been for some time.
Further evidence may be found in the rate at which schools of geography in North America are
adding courses in quantitative methods to their requirements for graduate degrees.

Wayne Davies (1972b) also used Kuhnian terminology in the title of his book, The Conceptual Revolution
in Geography. He identified a change from contemplation of the unique to adoption of ‘the more
rational scientific methodology’ (p. 9) as a revolution; none of the contributions reprinted in his
collection refers to Kuhn, but their context is clearly influenced by Kuhnian ideas. A year later,
Harvey (1973) used the term, like Haggett and Chorley, in a normative sense in his search for a new
world view; the goal was to promote a revolution in geographical practice rather than – as Kuhn
portrayed it – describing a revolution emerging from the anomalies thrown up by failures in
normal-science puzzle-solving.
348 A changing discipline?

The authors cited so far used the paradigm concept at either the macro-scale of a world view
or the meso-scale of a disciplinary matrix (see p. 19, this book). Others employed it either as a
general descriptive tool (e.g. Buttimer, 1978b, 1981; Holt-Jensen, 1981, 1988; see also Asheim,
1990; paradigm had the largest number of entries in the index to Preston James and Geoffrey
Martin, 1981, and remained one of the most commonly cited terms in the next edition – Martin
and James, 1993 – but had just four index entries in the fourth, Martin, 2005), or as a framework
for summarising subdisciplinary changes (Herbert and Johnston, 1978). Kuhn’s micro-scale
concept of a paradigm as an exemplar has also been deployed: Taylor (1976), for example, identified
seven separate revolutions during the preceding decades and Webber (1977) proposed an entropy-
based paradigm (see p. 115, this book).
Milton Harvey and Brian Holly (1981, p. 31) identified five paradigms within geography
during the last century, associating each with an individual scholar: ‘we can tentatively assign
paradigmatic status to . . . Ratzel with the paradigm of determinism, Vidal with that of possibilism,
Sauer with the landscape paradigm, Hartshorne with the chronological paradigm and Schaefer with
the spatial organization paradigm’. They were focusing on ‘schools of thought’ associated with
particular scholars, some of which ran concurrently rather than consecutively. They claimed that a
single paradigm dominated the 1960s. Whether it was stimulated by Schaefer as they claim, despite
the views of Bunge (1979) and others, is open to question. Cox (1995, p. 306) claimed that
‘Schaefer arguably was rescued from intellectual oblivion only in order to provide some
philosophical justification for what was happening in human geography at that time’, though Getis
(1993) reported that Schaefer’s paper was widely read at the University of Washington in the late
1950s (see also Berry, 1993). Some of James Wheeler’s (2002a) data cast doubts on Harvey and
Holly’s claim regarding dominance. The 1970s were rather characterised by a ‘diversity of
viewpoints’ (Harvey and Holly, 1981, p. 37), within which spatial organisation remained important.
Zelinsky (1978, p. 8) called that decade one:

of confused calm, or rather of pluralistic stalemate, as geographers explore a multiplicity of


philosophical avenues and research strategies . . . without that single firm conviction as to
destination that guided most of us in the past.

The discipline was technically more capable, substantively more catholic, philosophically more
mature, internationally more merged, socially more relevant, and academically more linked to
other disciplines, he claimed, and these would probably lead to a continued plurality of approaches:
‘I happen to believe that, more than anything else, this philosophical coming of age, this rising
above the superficiality and tunnel vision that blemished so much geographical work earlier in this
century, justifies’ (p. 10) the title of his edited collection – Human Geography: Coming of age.
Although some were uncertain about the relevance of Kuhn’s concepts to changes in the 1970s
and 1980s, in comparison with the 1950s and 1960s, others were less equivocal. In his introduction
to a collection of essays on The Nature of Change in Geographical Ideas, Berry (1978a, pp. vii, ix) claimed
that ‘The changes in geographical ideas that we have discussed are distinctly Kuhnian.’  The other
contributors’ essays provided little supporting evidence for this claim, however, and Berry’s own
contribution suggested that pluralism and interparadigm conflict were much more common than
periods of normal science. Writing of geographical theories of social change, he noted (Berry,
1978b, pp. 19, 22, citing Mikesell):

a diversity arising from the mosaic quality of modern geography . . . [geographers] have . . .
moved from one paradigm to another, and in the last decade they have been extremely
dynamic. . . . With multiple ideas and multiple origins, modern geography could rightly be
characterized as a mosaic within a mosaic.
(Mikesell, 1969)
A changing discipline? 349

Gauthier and Taaffe (2003) used the term ‘revolutions’ to describe what they identified as
three major changes in American geography during the twentieth century according to six criteria:
type of change; pace of change; intensity of accompanying debate; operational characteristics
(or core concepts); impact of the change; and context for the change. Paradigms were also the core
organising framework of a discussion of changes in geomorphology (Orme, 2002).

Human geographers’ critiques of Kuhnian applications


Kuhnian concepts and terminology were widely used by human geographers for several decades,
therefore, although some treatments of disciplinary history entirely ignored this literature (Freeman,
1980a, 1980b) and others made little use of it. Buttimer (1993, p. 70) has a single, brief, reference
to Kuhn, for example (as does Cox, 2014). Livingstone (1992), after noting that ‘In the wake of
Kuhn’s treatise, a batch of historians working in various disciplines set out on a paradigm hunt,
looking for paradigms, paradigm shifts, and what not’ and that ‘Geographers were no exception’
(p. 14), concluded that some, like Berry, Harvey, and Haggett and Chorley, used the concept of a
paradigm as ‘little more than a flag for rallying the troops’ (p. 24) to a new cause. Gould (1994,
p. 196) argued that ‘They challenge, sometimes with deliberate overstatement, using polemic to
grab the ear of an established coterie, and rhetoric to persuade it of its folly.’ Berry (1993) claimed
that this was necessary; in the context of Hartshorne’s responses to Schaefer (p. 61, this book),
those promoting the new approach in the late 1950s were engaged in a debate with the ‘discipline’s
luminaries’:

Mainline geographers were suspicious, threatened, antagonistic; and we reciprocated. We felt we


had to fight and fight we did, earning reputations for brashness and abrasiveness. So be it: if we
had not been aggressive, geography would have rolled over us. Instead, we tried to roll geography.
(p. 438)

In that fight they sought support from the emerging field of regional science (see p. 83, this book),
and as a consequence of their victory, according to Morrill (1993):

I believe we saved geography from extinction as a serious university discipline, by attracting and
training good students, by writing articles and books that developed theory and method, by
gaining a foothold in science at large, and by applying these methods and theories to
contemporary social problems.
(p. 442)

Nevertheless, he still found geography’s position ‘weak, fragile and almost invisible . . . we survived
but did not succeed in the goal of propelling geography into the mainstream’ because ‘much of
geographic work . . . was not good enough’ and some of the best spatial scientists ‘defected’
(p. 443).
Livingstone’s (1992) attitude to discussions of Kuhn and the revolutionary fervour of some
spatial scientists was that:

The details of these (and other similar cases) need not be reviewed here. Suffice to say that their
revolutionary gung ho spirit of triumphalism was scarcely what Kuhn had in mind as he portrayed
the mega-level Gestalt-shifts in the history of science.
(p. 24)

While the reception of Kuhn’s work in the half-century since its publication has been complex and
part of a wider opening-up of the history of sciences (Gordon, 2012), many of the presentations
350 A changing discipline?

and uses of Kuhn, however, were superficial (see Graves, 1981), both cavalier and uncritical in
basing their descriptions on Kuhnian foundations. Mair (1986, p. 357) includes earlier editions
of this book in that category, claiming that it ‘rarely reaches beyond a superficial comparison of
the Kuhnian model and the recent history of human geography’. Nevertheless, he did recog-
nise that it, like other evaluations, concludes ‘either that Kuhn’s ideas are irrelevant to the
historiography of geography, or that they “fit” only when stretched almost beyond recognition’
(p. 345). Hubbard et al. (2002, p. 26) were also critical of the use of the paradigm concept in
geography and its treatment in earlier editions of this book (although we should clarify here that
the fifth edition of Geography and Geographers had also concluded that ‘Kuhn’s model does not fit the
experience of human geography since 1945 therefore’, p. 389). They note that:

In particular, the idea that geography has moved through unified (and generational) paradigms
glosses over the ideas and practices associated with those who did not conform to the dominant
or fashionable way of doing things. The consensus among geographers at any one time that
there is a best way of doing things has seldom been complete or stable, and to pretend that it has
been so is to obliterate the voices of many researchers. In relation to the recent history of Anglo-
American human geography, we therefore need to be mindful of the fact that it is often white,
English-speaking, middle-class, heterosexual, able-bodied male academics who seek to define
the Zeitgeist and identify which ideas are most useful to progress. The net result of this is that
dissenting voices – and alternative traditions within geography – are often marginalised or
obliterated in the pages of geographical history . . . you should be wary that most histories
of geography can serve to legitimate the careers of an academic elite while obliterating the views
of others regarded as insignificant.
(p. 26)

Livingstone (1992, p. 25) found that ‘it became plain that much of this writing [about the
applicability of the paradigm concept] amounted to misdirected effort’, but agreed with Mair that
‘even among [the] . . . critics the flavour of Kuhn’s work still lingers. The Kuhnian ghost, it seems,
is proving rather hard to exorcize from the history of geography.’ Nevertheless, he welcomed the
sociological approach to disciplinary history which the adaptation of Kuhn’s ideas heralded; it
countered the belief in ‘conceptual cumulation, disciplinary progress, and internal chronology’,
and encouraged contextual readings in its stead.
Other geographers have been very sceptical of the value of a Kuhnian interpretation, with two
claiming that it has ‘distorted even perverted the development of geography’ (Haines-Young and
Petch, 1978, p. 1). Just over a quarter of a century later, Kwan (2004) described ‘the influence of
Kuhn’s (1962) model of scientific revolutions’ as a problem:

Since Kuhn was taken to conceive of disciplinary change as a succession of perspectives,


each eclipsing the other, and to advocate a clean break with existing practices and the dominance
of a singular vision . . . difference and diversity in perspectives have no role in this inter-
pretation of his model . . . [which] tends to intensify antagonism within geography because it
suggests that the normal state of human geography involves one perspective being victorious
over another and that there is something wrong with the persistence of an incompatible
viewpoint. It is therefore important to recognize that the Kuhnian model (as we used it) is not
suitable for a discipline like geography, in which a variety of perspectives and methodologies
coexist at the same time.
(p. 759)

The concepts of revolutions and normal science have also been criticised as providing poor
descriptions of geography in recent decades in another textbook (Holt-Jensen, 1988, 2009).
A changing discipline? 351

Individual geographers may have experienced personal revolutions and rapid shifts from one
paradigm to another – at the meso- if not the macro-scale. (Harvey, 1973, 2002, indicates this for
himself; see also the essays in Billinge et al., 1984: the editors (p. 11) quote Cox, Gould, Olsson,
Scott and David Smith as additional examples.) Sheppard (1995, p. 287), employing citation data,
contrasted a drastic shift in the discipline’s ‘master weavers’ – the term is drawn from Bodman’s,
1991, 1992, depiction of the most-cited human geographers – from spatial science to social theory
during the 1980s and also argued that:

It is of interest to note that 8 of the 12 social theorists [all of the geographers discussed are
classified by him as either spatial scientists or social theorists], as well as a large number of
other influential individuals in the social-theory group, began their careers within the research
traditions of spatial analysis.

Among them, Sheppard identified three cohorts:

1 Those who wrote classic spatial analysis papers of the 1960s (he cites Bunge, Cox, Harvey,
Johnston, Olsson, Pred, Scott, Soja and M. J. Webber).
2 Those ‘whose early work was solidly within spatial analysis, and recognised as such, but for
whom this work did not represent a major period in research careers that shifted rapidly
from spatial analysis to Marxism and social theory’ (he lists Dear, Massey, Peet, P. Taylor and
Thrift).
3 Those whose careers began in the late 1970s with contributions to spatial analysis when it was
already under heavy criticism, ‘only to re-identify themselves prominently with the concerns
of social theory’ (the names given, and trajectories discussed, are Gordon Clark, John Paul
Jones – and himself!).

For Sheppard, therefore, there have been only two major competing world views – the spatial-
scientists’ versus the social theorists’; most of the debates discussed in this book can presumably
either be encapsulated within that macro-scale competition or involve controversy within a world
view (over disciplinary matrices and/or exemplars, but not basic orientation, which Barnes, 1996,
portrays as for or against the Enlightenment project with its belief in progress and universal truths).
Indeed, much of the debate, especially in the latter twentieth-century decades, was about methods,
specifically ‘quantitative vs. qualitative’ (with many textbooks focusing only on one of the pair:
Johnston, 2006).
To claim that such individual experiences can be amalgamated into disciplinary revolutions
strikes some observers as both inapt and inconsistent with the evidence (Bird, 1977, p. 105):
‘Perhaps so many revolutions in so short a time indicate in themselves either a continuously
rolling programme, or something basically wrong with the overturning metaphor’. Bird (1978,
p. 134) suggested that mono-paradigm dominance of a discipline is inconsistent with ‘the fact that
society itself is organised around more than one major principle’. The focus of Bird’s criticism is
not clear, however; it is much more convincing on the world-view scale than at that of the
disciplinary matrix, for example, and even less so at the scale of the exemplar.
Stoddart’s criticism was even more pointed; he initially saw some value in the paradigm model
(Stoddart, 1967b) but later argued (Stoddart, 1977) that:

the concept sheds no light on the processes of scientific change, and readily becomes caricature.
I suggest that as more is understood of the complexities of change in geography over the last
hundred years, and especially of the subtle interrelationships of geographers themselves, the
less appropriate the concept of the paradigm becomes.
(p. 1)
352 A changing discipline?

Stoddart (1977, p. 2) also argued that ‘There is scope for sociological enquiry into the extent to
which the concept has been used in recent years as a slogan in interactions between different age
groups, schools of thought, and centres of learning.’ In 1986 he reiterated that ‘the adoption of
Kuhn’s terminology, far from clarifying history, actively distorts it, largely by reducing the
participants to caricature figures’ (p. 13).
His analysis showed both the absence of consensus (normal science) and the slow pace of
change (which is more readily represented in Lakatos’s schema (p. 19, this book)). In his view the
paradigm concept became part of the ‘boosterism’ image with which geographers conducted
debates (Stoddart, 1981a):

the paradigm terminology has been used to illuminate either the establishment of views of
which a commentator approved, or to advocate the rejection of those he did not (p. 72) . . . the
concept of revolution bolsters the heroic self-image of those who see themselves as innovators
and who use the term paradigm in a polemical manner . . . those who propound the Kuhnian
interpretation have done so in ways which tend to make it self-fulfilling.
(p. 78)

Continuing the argument, Stoddart (1986) argued that it was such wish-fulfilment and strategic
use by those who:

propound Kuhnian interpretation . . . rather than its value as a framework for studying historical
change, that makes the paradigm idea of interest to the historian of science: as itself an object
of study, rather than as means of understanding the complexities of change.
(pp. 17–18)

Billinge et al. (1984, p. 6) claimed that Chorley and Haggett’s initial use of Kuhn’s terminology
was ‘In some measure . . . only gestural’ because although they clearly distinguished between
normal science and extraordinary research ‘the “anomalies” within the traditional paradigm which
were central to Kuhn’s thesis were never identified in any detail’. Chorley and Haggett were pressing
for a revolution in the nature of geography, but it was not a revolution generated by the failure of
the previous paradigm (using failure in a Kuhnian context). Billinge et al. pointed out that the term
‘paradigm’ was being used more for propaganda than for historiography – thereby potentially
gaining prestige by locating their would-be revolution alongside those in physics described by
Kuhn (Taylor, 1976). They accepted that the Kuhnian model should be rejected, but argued that
since Kuhn himself did not expect the model to fit the social sciences, such a conclusion is
hardly surprising. Nevertheless, they did identify insights in Kuhn’s work that may be of value in
the study of a social science like human geography, such as his concept of the paradigm as what
constitutes, or ‘gives form to’ (Billinge et al., 1984, p. 16) scientific activity by providing the ‘maps’
with which scientists are socialised into a discipline or subdiscipline. Science takes place
in ‘heterogeneous settings’ with their own ‘rules and resources’ (p. 17); it is a ‘localised’ activity
which occurs within (scientific) communities and hence its study is necessarily a study of
community sociology.
Mair (1986, p. 359) took the criticism further, contending that, with the single exception of
Billinge et al.:

geographers have entirely misinterpreted Kuhn’s contributions. They have been wrong on
Kuhn in the simple sense that the skeletal Kuhnian model is misrepre­sented as Kuhn’s major
contribution. More fundamentally, however, they have been wrong on Kuhn in misconceiving his
entire project.
A changing discipline? 353

For him, the main values of Kuhn’s work were:

1 the concept of the exemplar as an analogy to be used in the creative process;


2 the notion of incommensurability in the comparison on competing paradigms; and
3 the clear need to study the sociology of scientific communities.

Geertz (1983) also stressed the last of these points. For others, the important issue is the absence of
clear ‘revolutions’. Michael Chisholm (1975a), for example, concluded that:

by using prose as the medium of exposition and by concentrating on the essential underlying
ideas, it is manifest that continuity of thought dominates over the apparent discontinuity which
some have called the ‘quantitative revolution’.
(p. 89)

Later in the same book, however, he admitted that ‘in respect of analytical techniques geography has
indeed experienced a revolution. However, in terms of the subject-matter studied the position has
changed less rapidly’ (p. 173; there is a confusion of scales implicit here, between exemplars and
disciplinary matrices, if not world views) – and it was only later that the problems addressed by
geographers ‘caught up’ with their analytic ability to handle them (see also Gregory, 1978a, pp.
52–3; 1994, p. 55). Although they use the term ‘revolutions’, Gauthier and Taaffe (2003) are close
to Chisholm in their characterisation, writing of a:

continuity model with surges superimposed to represent the three ‘revolutions’. During the
surges the weaknesses of the previous paradigm are usually stressed and caricatured. . . .
Later, as the surge subsides, we begin hearing more about hapless conceptual babies being
thrown out with the bathwater of the old paradigm. The merits of some aspects of the previous
paradigm are discussed and recognized, and a certain amount of continuity sets in – perhaps
only leading to a wave of enthusiasm about a new paradigm.
(p. 523)

Despite such criticisms (which according to Livingstone, 1992, p. 25, ‘began to come
thick and fast’ once ‘the first flush of paradigm enthusiasm died down and a more measured
consideration of Kuhn’s relevance to geographical history was undertaken’), relatively little was
done until the 1980s and 1990s to suggest alternative sociologies based on other models of the
history of science, including some developed specifically to represent the situation in human
geography. Livingstone’s (1992) work (first noted in the Preface here), drew on contextual histories
of science. He notes how, ‘In the wake of Kuhn’s treatise, a batch of historians working in various
disciplines set out on a paradigm hunt, looking for paradigms, paradigm-shifts and what not.
Geographers were no exception’ (p. 14). He did not wish to repeat the exercise, while recognising
that:

Whatever the internal conceptual irresolutions within the corpus of Kuhn’s writings, and the
conceptual sloppiness of the manner in which it was imported into geographical history, there
can be no doubting the benefit that a broadly sociological rendering of both science and
geography has wrought.
(p. 25)

Reflecting wider debates on the history and sociology of knowledge since Kuhn, Livingstone
favoured a broader ‘approach to geography’s history that will do justice to the intellectual and social
354 A changing discipline?

context within which geographical knowledge was produced’ (p. 23). Livingstone then wants to
suggest:

that it might be helpful if we were to think of geography as a tradition that evolves like a species
over time. As I say, this is a risky analogy, for my colleagues are sure to sniff all the problems of
earlier organic analogies or to suspect some underlying evolutionary epistemology . . . I judge
the risk worth taking because I think the image helps us see that ideas in general, and
geographical ideas in particular, are historical entities that change, transform, evolve over time
in different cognitive and social environments. As I see it, geography is a tradition that, like a
species, has undergone historical transformation.
(p. 30)

But tradition was seen by some to be no less problematic than paradigm as a way of narrating
disciplinary history. Drawing on a set of critical reactions to Livingstone’s arguments (Driver, 1995;
Matless, 1995; Rose, 1995), Anne Godlewska (1999) argued that:

Taking a history of ideas approach to the concept of ‘tradition’ as does Livingstone – following a
particular line of descent – de-emphasizes the exclusions, the contestations, the lulls, the gaps,
and the collapses in the history of geography and understates the power of discursive formations
to limit and form research and practice. I welcome Gillian Rose’s contention that ‘tradition’
implies exclusion. I think that discursive formations do also and I agree that those exclusions,
whether gender-based or otherwise, should be a particular focus of attention.
(p. 315)

Godlewska’s (1999) critique of Livingstone appears in an endnote to a book-length study ‘about


the nature of French geography about two hundred years ago. It is not a disciplinary history’ (p. 1).
Inspired by Foucault, she seeks:

to get at changes that alter discursive patterns: change that alters the objects of the study of
particular discursive formations, the operations they may engage in, the apparent relevance and
importance of their concepts, and the theoretical options open to thinkers; change that alters the
boundaries of a given discursive field and the means by which it reinvents itself; and change that
overturns hierarchies in the intellectual division of labor and consequently the orientation of
research.
(p. 1)

Her focus on the development of geographic language – both textual and graphic (modes
of mapping and visualising spatial and natural relations) – has inspired others (Johnston
and Sidaway, 2015) considering the relationships between geographical concepts, and disciplinary
change.
A decade before Livingstone’s (1992) account of The Geographical Tradition, Wheeler (1982)
found Lakatos’s work attractive, arguing that several separate programme cores could be identified
in contemporary human geography (he cites areal differentiation, spatial science, cognitive-
behavioural approaches and marxist structuralism), in each of which the operation of positive
heuristics (see p. 19, this book) can be identified. These research programmes are in continuing
competition, whose nature will change over time (Wheeler, 1982):

Given the deficiencies in Kuhn’s scheme and the rather ill-defined nature of geography, it seems
unlikely that the future of the discipline will be characterized by sequences of revolutionary
change interspersed with efficient problem solving. Moreover expectations of revolutionary
A changing discipline? 355

progress appear to be unjustified. Instead it seems that a variety of approaches, which will
undoubtedly wax and wane in popularity, will continue to be employed.
(p. 4)

Giles Mohan (1994), drawing on the notion of a product cycle, suggested that a rapid turnover
of theories had recently occurred within geography as a consequence of pressures within the
academic profession. He identified ‘four “big” approaches over the preceding decade hailed as
capable of explaining social reality’ alone (p. 387; the four were critical realism, structuration,
postmodernism and postcolonialism). He associates this rapid turnover with the growing
‘commodification of knowledge’ and the competition for status within academia, so that:

these ideas were not paradigmatic and their diffusion into geography uneven. Likewise some of
these intellectuals [those promoting the ‘big’ approaches] have persisted with their theoretical
frameworks and have not continually experimented with new ones . . . [nevertheless] Many
academics fight for currency and exploit new markets in knowledge. This increased competition
has, in the spirit of flexible specialisation, resulted in the ‘niching’ of academic thought despite
the recent emphasis on trans-disciplinary pursuits.
(p. 387)

Some of the forces impelling these trends are general within academia, but one at least is specific
to geographers (see also Crampton and Elden, 2007):

As a trans-disciplinary subject geography has often lacked kudos in wider social theory. The
result is that geography has tended to borrow and incorporate any social theory that appears
spatial or contains spatial metaphors. The increased commodification of knowledge has served
to heighten this tendency. For example, we have had Giddens’ locales, Foucault’s disciplinary
spaces and Mohanty’s contested cartographies. It seems that few have time to actually apply any
of these potentially useful ideas before the next theoretical innovation superseded them.
(p. 389)

Disciplinary matrices and exemplars come and go at an alarming rate according to this view, with
geography equated to a supermarket in its concern for ‘turnover time’ and short shelf lives as its
practitioners seek status through the novelty of their approaches.

Geography and its environment


Some geographers have argued (in similar terms to ours here) that the major influence on their
discipline’s content and approaches comes from a combination of its wider environment,
particularly its economic, social and political milieux, and changes in other subjects. In general, it
is believed that geography is more likely to change because of developments in other disciplines
than vice versa. Stoddart (1981b, p. 1), for example, introduced a book of essays as demonstrating
‘that both the ideas and the structure of the subject have developed in response to complex social,
economic, ideological and intellectual stimuli’. Evidence for this was presented, as a second theme
of the essays, in the reciprocal relationship between geographers and their milieux: ‘throughout its
recent history geographers have been not only concerned with narrowly academic issues, but have
also been deeply involved with matters of social concern’. This conclusion had less purchase in
subsequent decades, however, with the growth of what became known as a ‘spatial turn’ in the
humanities and other social sciences (Warf and Arias, 2009; Morton, 2011; Porter, 2011) and an
increasing awareness of the importance of incorporating space in general, and distance in particular,
356 A changing discipline?

in economic analyses. (Many of those who ‘discovered’ geography did so very partially, however,
often either selecting those geographical writings and practices which fitted their predilections or
largely ignoring much contemporary geographical scholarship, as in Kaplan, 2012.)
Hubbard et al. (2002) argued that:

contemporary theoretical approaches to human geography need to be understood contextually,


in relation to at least three things . . . :

1 The history of geography – how geography has actually developed in terms of what geographers
have studied (and how).
2 The sociology of geography – how institutions, social networks, journals and educational
structures (particularly universities) have shaped the development of geography.
3 The psychology of geography – how individual geographers have adopted ways of thinking
about and interpreting the world, whether conformist or confrontational.
(pp. 25–6, original italics)

One of the most detailed deployments of the contextual approach is Livingstone’s (1992) The
Geographical Tradition, in which he refers to the history of geography as ‘situated messiness’ with the
absence of any ‘essential nature’ (p. 28). In the discussion of any particular theory within geography,
therefore, this means that:

it will never be wrong to ask of any theory: Why was it put forward? Whose interests did it advance
or retard? In what kind of milieu was it conceived and communicated? How adapted was it to its
cognitive and social environment?
(p. 29)

Livingstone’s chapters on geography in the late nineteenth century (‘A sternly practical pursuit;
geography, race and empire’), the first half of the twentieth (‘The regionalizing ritual: geography,
place and particularity’) and the 1950s–1960s (‘Statistics don’t bleed: quantification and its
detractors’) illustrate his theme that:

geography changes as society changes, and that the best way to understand the tradition to
which geographers belong is to get a handle on the different social and intellectual environments
within which geography has been practised.
(p. 347)

Within those environments, the character of geography was contested, though not
necessarily by all of its practitioners, reflecting the particularities of any one time and place:
‘Sometimes the conversations have admitted a range of geographers, from time to time only a
select group were equipped, or permitted, to take part’ (p. 358). But as we get closer to the
present, the latter condition became rarer, with fewer ‘partisan apologists . . . [striving] to
monopolize the conversation in order to serve their own sectarian interests’. Likewise, Gregory
(1994, p. x) writes that the concept of a ‘discipline’ such as geography implies ‘a set of sovereign
concepts . . . [and] a rigorous policing operation’ when in effect it involves individuals and
groups traversing ‘nomadic tracks . . . [and] new lines of fight’ as they explore alternative ways of
producing and reproducing knowledge – as fully illustrated in the various chapters of Geographical
Imaginations. Elsewhere, Livingstone has argued for the importance of studying both ‘life geographies’
(the career trajectories of individual geographers, including their spatial movements) and
‘intellectual spaces’ – the places in which ideas are crystallised and developed (Johnston, 2004e;
Livingstone, 2000a).
A changing discipline? 357

KNOWLEDGE ACTION SOCIAL STRUCTURE

culture behaviour society


science researcn scieniiTic
'WissenschaftJ praxis :ommunity
content qeo-
grapnical geo­
of geo­
research graphers
graphy

Figure 10.1  Geography’s context

Source: Gräno, 1981, p.19.

Many geographers who employ a contextual approach stress that any changes in a discipline’s
contents (revolutionary or not) are associated with significant events in its milieux. Thus, Berdoulay
(1981, p. 10) wrote of the role of the Zeitgeist (spirit of the age) influencing what geographers do.
Gräno (1981) took this much further (Figure 10.1); geographers are a subset within the community
of scientists, which is itself a subset of wider society, whose culture includes a scientific component
that strongly influences the content of geography. The community of geographers is an
‘institutionalizing social group’ (p. 26), providing the context within which individual geographers
are socialised and defining their disciplinary goals within the constraining and enabling
characteristics of the external structures. A major goal when geography was established as an
academic discipline was to create an identity, to ‘establish an object of study that could be regarded
as geography’s own and that differed from that of other disciplines’ (p. 30). This, he claimed, was
a‘passive education role’ (p. 32) disseminating knowledge of society–environment interrelationships,
but it was replaced in the 1970s when ‘geography began to contribute actively to a transformed and
replanned world. Applied geography was created and geography became a profession outside the
small world of the university’ (p. 32).
Geographers made and continue to remake geography: ‘It was the external goals of society that
brought the establishment of geography as an academic discipline. This took place without any
noticeable contribution from any other scientists’ (Gräno, 1981, p. 30; see, however, Stoddart,
1986). The initial period of institutionalisation involved geography operating largely as a pedagogic
subject, meeting the needs for training teachers whose activities would promote the interests of the
expanding ‘nation-states’ (Capel, 1981; Taylor, 1985a; Goodson, 1981, 1988; Fuller, 2000). Capel
(1981, p. 36) referred to the creation of geography as a discipline resulting from:

the presence of geography in primary and secondary education at the time when the European
countries began the rapid process of diffusion of elementary education; the necessity to train
geography teachers for primary and middle schools was the essential factor which led to the
institutionalization of geography in the university and the appearance of the scientific community
of geographers.
(p. 36)

(See also Freeman 1961, 1980a, and, for a more critical account, Rieser, 1973.)
As the context changed, however, so did geography for (Capel, 1981):

The established community employs strategies tending to reproduce and amplify itself. Never
will it opt for self-liquidation; the community will defend its survival, even if other communities
of scientists investigate similar problems with like methods, or if the logical incoherence of the
358 A changing discipline?

conceptions that they defend is revealed . . . Everything will be sacrificed for the reproduction
and growth of the community, including the coherence of the very conception of the discipline:
different conceptions can defend themselves in distinct moments or even simultaneously,
without putting into doubt the continuity of the science practised.
(p. 66)

The promotion of national interests, especially national commercial interests, by nineteenth-


century geographical societies provided the context for the creation of geography as an academic
discipline (see the essays in Bell et al., 1995, and also Morin, 2011), and subsequent changes in
economic, social and political structures and needs generated new demands, to which geographers
responded. (See, for example, Taylor’s, 1993, evaluation of different geographical perspectives on
‘the global’ during the twentieth century.)
Scott’s (1982) answer to the question ‘Why do geographers, regional scientists, urban
economists and others study the spatial patterning of social events?’ (p. 141) provides an example
of disciplinary reconstruction in the context of changed circumstances. Writing in North America
in 1982 (a decade later, the context was very different), he concentrated on the ways in which late
capitalism is organised, not through market relations, but rather involving bureaucratic intervention
by an all-embracing state. Because ‘the geography of late capitalist society is shot through with
problems and predicaments’ (p. 145), state action is required in the ‘more subtle forms of social,
cultural, and psychological management’ (p. 146) on which science thrives (Scott here uses
‘geography’ not in the professional but rather the vernacular sense: Johnston, 1986b.) By
participating in those managerial tasks, however, scientists contribute to the creation of
countervailing forces, with which they may also become involved:

the endemic crisis of economic production and growth in late capitalist society creates the need
for specific problematics and policy discourses out of which technical control may be
accomplished. But technical control creates an advanced set of social conditions in which a
countervailing set of human predicaments makes its appearance – alienation, the destruction of
affective human relations, the repoliticization of human and regional planning, and so on.
(p. 152)

Hence, the radical and humanistic responses to spatial science.


The link between the external environment and the practice of economic geography was
examined further in a later essay, which Scott (2000, p. 18) began by claiming that:

Over time, economic geography has behaved in a manner quite different from that which might be
expected of a rationally ordered discipline pursuing some pre-ordained epistemological mission.
Its historical course has been notably responsive to changes in external economic conditions, to
the unfolding of political events, and to the play of professional ambitions and rivalries. . . . These
imply that any answer to the question ‘what are the central problems of economic geography?’ is
likely to be historically contingent, even if the inertia of tradition and its institutionalization in a
system of higher education means that important continuities can be deciphered over time.
(p. 18)

In this context, ‘one of the few general principles that seems to be reasonably evident in this
connection is that the concrete questions and problems that society faces at any given historical
moment tend also, in one way or another, to become burning questions and problems for practising
social scientists’ (p. 19), though it is not clear whether this simply reflects social scientists
responding to the perceived world or rather social scientists being required to reorient their
concerns by external ‘paymasters’. (In other cases, however, changes in the external environment
A changing discipline? 359

and their appreciation stimulate scholars to reorient their intellectual interests, as in Derek Gregory’s,
2004, The Colonial Present, writing of which was stimulated by his response to the 2001 and 2003
American-led invasions of Afghanistan and Iraq, and the ongoing Israeli occupation of Palestine.)
Thus, economic geography can be characterised by a series of episodes – spatial analysis and
regional science; behavioural geography (a ‘brief interlude’); political economy; localities (another
‘brief interlude’); and a world of regions within globalisation (see also Clark et al. 2000). Scott
eschews Kuhnian terminology – neither paradigms nor revolutions are mentioned – in part because
none of his episodes or interludes has entirely ended:

I have tended to treat the main episodes in the postwar history of economic geography as
occurring in relatively discrete blocks of historical time. To be sure, each of these episodes can
be described in terms of a moment of emergence, a subsequent period of rapid efflorescence,
and a period of decline, where the latter period is often extended over a number of decades. As
a consequence, almost all of the episodes identified here continue to leave traces on the work of
practicing economic geographers today, just as adherents of this or that tendency whose heyday
is long past continue to produce and publish scholarly work right down to the present. The
intellectual landscape of economic geography at any given moment in time is therefore best
represented as a sort of intellectual palimpsest rather than as a unified front.
(pp. 32–3)

Scott does not assess the value of work published long after the episode’s heyday, however.
Further, he implies – in part by his criticism of Trevor Barnes’s (1996) work – that the response to
economic changes by economic geographers is largely determined by those changes, leaving
relatively little room for debate and decision-making (with just a few economic geographers left
practising an obsolescent craft long after others have moved on). For Barnes (2000), context is both
constraining and enabling:

The discipline arose because of a set of contextual factors, and as those factors changed so did
economic geography. Further, those factors . . . entered into economic geography’s very
constitution, shaping the questions it asked, the methods and tools it used, and the range of
answers it deemed acceptable. For sure, the discipline had its own geniuses, people who were
brilliant in thinking up new ideas, but their creativity was always . . . informed and tempered by
a wider context.
(p. 12)

Thus, for him, economic geographers ‘invented’ and ‘re-invented’ economic geography through
the accepted practices of the subdisciplinary community(ies), as exemplified by Peck and Tickell’s
(2012) revisiting of their theorization of neoliberalism twenty years earlier (Peck and Tickell,
1994; Tickell and Peck, 1992). Scott (2000, p. 34), too, accepts that changes in disciplinary practices
are invariably subject to ‘a welter of critique and counter-critique’ and may reflect ‘the changing
fortunes of different professional groups as those whose human capital is sunk in waning
problematics engage with those pressing forward with new approaches in the endless struggle to
come out on top in the stock-market of ideas’, but seems less prepared than Barnes to identify
particular individuals having a significant role in this struggle.
For Thrift (2000, p. 692), the cultural turn – Scott’s final episode – ‘saved economic geography
from what might otherwise have been a musty oblivion. By the 1980s, economic geography was
in a pretty moribund state, at risk of boring its audience to death.’ Subsequently, however, work in
economic geography – and other social science disciplines too – no longer took place on economists’
terms: the nature of the economic, and the assumptions and principles of the discipline which
studies it, is open to debate (see also Amin and Thrift, 2000).
360 A changing discipline?

There is no necessity for geography, however, no ‘specific necessities in scientific knowledge’


(Gräno, 1981, p. 65). Rather, according to Peter Taylor (1985a, p. 93):

Geography is a social institution. Like all such institutions its value to society varies over time
and place. The creation of any social institution is a result of a group of people who identify a
particular need and are able to find the resources to meet that need. As needs change the
institution has to adopt to survive.
(p. 93)

It may fail; the forms of scientific discourse created and practised may not command sponsorship
and resources, and may lose their positions within educational curricula and institutions. Scott (1982,
p. 151) argued strongly that success requires identification of clear social needs: ‘only discourses that
are posited upon existing problems of social life and practice, and upon existing political interests,
stand any likelihood of commanding a significant consensus of scholars and scientists’.
There is nothing deterministic in these arguments, for they depend on geographers identify-
ing what is and is not sustainable in a particular context and successfully promoting themselves as
able to meet the perceived needs. How they do this will reflect what Berdoulay (1981) calls
their individual ‘circles of affinity’: social networks extending outside their disciplinary base.
To appreciate those one must appreciate biographies, as Buttimer (1981) argued and several
volumes of autobiographical recollections illustrate (Buttimer, 1983; Billinge et al., 1984;
P. Moss, 2001; Gould and Pitts, 2002; L. King, 2008; see also the fuller presentations in Haggett,
1990, and Gould, 1999). Buttimer (1983, p. 3) defends such an approach because ‘each person’s
life echoes the drama of his or her times and milieu; in all, to varying degrees, the propensity to
submit or rebel. Through our own biographies we reach toward understanding, being and
becoming.’ Autobiography provides what she terms ‘choreographic awareness’, the ‘moral,
aesthetic, and emotional commitments which are related to lived experience and which underpin
a scholar’s eventual choice of epistemological presentation and style of practice’ (p. 12). It can
indicate aspects of disciplinary history that are absent from the written record of research papers
and student texts, isolating the influence of ‘pioneers of geographic thought whose inspiration
flowed through their teaching and field experiences, through their counselling and listening’
(Buttimer, 1981, p. 88; for critical approaches to autobiography, see Roche, 2011, and Shaw, 2013).
Biographies offer an alternative source, but there are few on geographers who have contributed
significantly to the contemporary period (Paterson, 1985); and the few biographical dictionaries
available (most of which, like the serial Geographers: Bibliographies, deal only with dead geographers and
so have little resonance to contemporary geography) are limited in their treatment of geographers’
intellectual contributions relative to their career paths (Larkin and Peters, 1993).

Geographers and their networks


The autobiographical theme was taken up explicitly by Pred (1979, 1984a), using the language of
time geography (p. 131, this book). For him (1979):

under contemporary circumstances, the ‘life content’ and the spatial and temporal attributes of an
individual’s life path are apt to be highly influenced by the sequence of independently existing
specialized roles – created by institutions and technology – that a person is able to occupy. . . . For
the academic whose writings are rooted complexly in the past, it is evident that the content of those
works would be different if the individual’s life path had been linked differently with a variety of
specific, independently existing limited-access roles of both an academic and a non-academic
character.
(p. 175)
A changing discipline? 361

Thus, he was able to trace the evolution of his academic interests from his interactions with people
who were with him in particular places at certain times – their ‘path convergences’ – as well as
items that he read and appreciated.
A particular feature of a scientist’s autobiography, however, is that the encounters which
influence career development and change need not be interpersonal. James Bird (1975, 1985) used
Popper’s concept of World Three (the world of recorded knowledge) to show how geographers can
be strongly influenced by reading both ancient and contemporary sources, so that our milieux are
not as bounded (in time and space) as are those of people who rely much more on interpersonal
transmission of information (see Johnston, 1984e, 2004a) – though, of course, we are reliant on
what materials are, or can be, made available to us locally, which is increasing very rapidly through
developments in information technology (Adams, 1995). As noted earlier with regard to actor-
network theory (p. 268, this book), non-human artefacts – notably though far from solely published
items – are crucial elements in the circulation of knowledge and as influences on individuals’
academic developments; those artefacts are not themselves immutable, however, since
(as Livingstone, 2005, and others have argued) interpretations of texts often vary according to the
context in which they are read. Technological developments have speeded up this circulation
process, with major impacts on changes in knowledge construction, although, as always, uneven
accessibility to relevant items can have a significant influence: items that are widely circulated are
more likely to be influential, as was the case with the mimeographed discussion papers circulated
by graduate students at the heart of the ‘quantitative revolution’ in Seattle in the 1950s (Johnston,
2004a). Nevertheless, whether such ‘knowledge communities’, many of which are located in a
particular place (Pinch, 1998), eventually significantly influence the direction that their discipline
takes depends on their relative power to change others’ research practices.
Geographers have extended their work on contextual influences on their discipline’s content
and direction by drawing on the ideas of sociologists of science regarding ‘situated, or local,
knowledge’. In presenting an ‘alternative history’ of economic geography, for example, Trevor
Barnes (1996, p. 105) argued that understanding geographers’ practices requires knowing
‘something about the local context and not overarching principles of rationality’. Thus:

Economic geographers will continue to do economic geography in the way that they have always
done, that is, by creatively drawing upon existing ideas and beliefs and responding – sometimes
with great originality and imagination, other times with less of each – to the concerns of their own
local context . . . this is all there is to practice. There is no foolproof method of directing inquiry.
(p. 124)

The nature of the ‘local’ is not addressed in depth, however, so that the interaction of
‘place as context’ with ‘World Three as context’ remains unexplored. (For Barnes himself, for
example, the key local context was the Department of Geography at the University of Minnesota in
the late 1970s where he was a graduate student, working with Fred Lukermann and Eric Sheppard
and alongside Michael Curry. A decade later, he was working in Vancouver and still writing with
Curry and Sheppard, who were in Los Angeles and Minneapolis respectively.) But Barnes’s
later work illustrates his theme through the examples of economic geography and locational
analysis: rather than linear sequences of individuals building on their predecessors’ work, he
emphasises the ‘halting, local, contingent factors that shaped it’ (Barnes, 2003a, p. 91). While there
may be progress in the technologies deployed – as with computing power and communications –
there is no ‘relentlessly progressive’ trajectory of thought but rather a series of ‘enormously bright,
imaginative, intellectually vibrant and creative’ individuals carving out their own histories ‘reflecting
the particular circumstances of their origins’. Like Livingstone (2000b), Barnes argues that all
knowledge is locally produced, geographically and historically bounded in its generation – though
as communication without travel becomes easier, one wonders for how long the local can be
362 A changing discipline?

defined in terms of places rather than as networks – the ‘locales’ (or settings for interaction) of
knowledge-production within geography may increasingly be a punctiform set of sites (themselves
far from permanent) among which there are frequent flows, rather than a relatively small, bounded
space such as the Department of Geography at the University of California, Berkeley, in the 1930s.
(Keighren’s, 2010, example of how the dissemination of the arguments in Semple’s 1911 classic
Influences of Geographical Environment was aided by both her lecture tours and visiting appointments at
various North American universities illustrates how those locales were linked in actor networks;
part of Keighren’s exploration was based on a survey of the book’s impact reported by John Wright,
1962, and their uncovering of how the book was interpreted and deployed further exemplifies the
argument for a ‘geography of reading’.)
The case for understanding the changing nature of geography contextually closely parallels
that promoted by structurationists for appreciating all human activity; the operation of human
agency must be analysed within the constraining and enabling conditions provided by its
environment. Thus, Johnston (1983c, p. 4) enlisted structuration theory as a framework for
analysing the changes in human geography that are the concern of this book, arguing that ‘the
content of a discipline at any one time and place reflects the response of the individuals involved to
external circumstances and influences, within the context of their intellectual socialization’.
Mikesell (1981) took a similar position, though without the language of structuration, describing
the history of geography in the USA as a sequence of ‘temporary enthusiasms or episodes’ (p. 9),
which he claimed were responses to contemporary stimuli. Hence, the popularity of urban studies
then, the relative decline in foreign-area studies for some years after the American retreat from
Vietnam and the impact of national concern about the physical environment in the 1970s. He also
suggested that physical milieux influenced the culture of individual geographers:

The first generation of American geographers grew up in a country that was still strongly
influenced by the mores of small towns. Most of the students now attracted to geography are
products not only of an urban but increasingly of a suburban environment . . . the geographical
profession has changed and is changing as a consequence of the suburban, middle-class origin
of most of its current membership.
(p. 12)

Philip Porter (1978) advanced similar arguments, identifying two types of American geography: a
midwest version that ‘was a characteristically optimistic, action-oriented, “can-do” kind’ (p. 17);
and a Californian geography, based on Sauer that was ‘historical, uncompromisingly academic,
speculative, suspicious of government, keenly interested in cultures other than the dominant Anglo
culture of the United States’ (p. 18).
This environmental influence thesis should not become environmental determinism,
however. Mikesell noted that urban geography flowered in the 1950s and 1960s not only in Chicago
but also in Iowa. But it stresses the importance of studying human geography and human
geographers in context; as Capel (1981) noted, the disciplinary community (or major elements
within it) will seek to maintain its identity by bending to perceived shifts in their milieux
(as clearly demonstrated for anthropologists by Patterson, 1986). Mikesell (1981, p. 13; see also
Johnston, 1996e) also argued, following Harvey (1973) and others, that reactions to environmental
shifts involve individual scholars seeking not only to defend and promote their chosen discipline
but also to defend and promote their own status and careers within it:

innovation will continue to be regarded as a virtue. Much of the development that has already
taken place in American geography is a consequence of the attempt of individual scholars to
stake a claim for themselves, to be or at least to seem to be different from their rivals. The fact
that most academics see virtue in innovation means that there is reward for innovation.
A changing discipline? 363

Mikesell did not discuss the scale of the innovation, however; does it have to involve developments
within the positive heuristic of a research programme, to use Lakatos’s terms, or does it require the
launch of a new research programme? Can one bring potentially greater rewards, and disasters,
than the other?
One little explored aspect of this sociological approach is that it focuses on the winners rather
than the losers, on those whose ideas have a major impact on at least parts of their discipline. Many
ideas are not taken up at the time they are initially published, but are later revived, whereas others
are never followed through because the published versions languish largely unread. Why some
individuals and their ideas are much more influential than others is an intriguing aspect of a
discipline’s history, as illustrated by the belated recognition of Hägerstrand’s seminal work
(Duncan, 1974b: Morrill, 1984, p. 62, notes that his visit to Seattle in 1959 ‘had an electrifying
impact’); the slight impact of Wreford Watson’s ideas regarding the social geography of
cities, which predated other now better known studies by several years but were almost ignored
(Robinson, 1991; Johnston, 1993b); the focus on only one aspect of Gottmann’s voluminous
writings (Johnston, 1996c); and the lack of influence that Dickinson’s pioneering work on
functional regions and urban areas had on 1950s–1960s urban geography (Johnston, 2000c,
2002a). In general, it seems that the most influential are those who are well-networked with other
influential scholars, especially those who have been trained in large graduate schools with a clear
agenda for the discipline. Morrill recognised this with regard to the developments he was involved
in during the 1950s and 1960s, at both the University of Washington (see p. 69, this book; also
Berry, 1993, on the depth of the resources available there, outwith as well as inside the geography
department) and Northwestern University (Morrill, 1993):

This happened when and where it did because at a few universities there was a fortunate
combination of an emphasis on interdisciplinary study, existing development of theory in these
related fields, notably regional economics and sociology, some students ready for change, and
some faculty ready to encourage them.
(p. 442)

Following this, leading proponents of the new approach were able to promote the discipline more
widely within the social sciences, thus achieving what Leslie King (1993, p. 545) refers to as ‘the
professionalization of geography as a social science’.
Context is not deterministic, of course: it provides opportunities. Thus, Hanson’s (1993)
reflections on graduate school at Northwestern University, while stressing the positive aspects of
the education provided (such as the concern for theory and explanation, the importance of space,
and the emphasis on standards of evidence), also noted that:

Coexisting with these considerable strengths, counterbalancing and – at the time – sometimes
overwhelming them, were blind spots and inflexibilities bred in revolutionary fervor and in earlier
bruising conflicts with the reigning paradigm. Our mentors exuded a certain intolerance, a certain
hubris, a certain arrogance, a certain certainty that there was only one way to the Truth, and they
knew it. There was a caricaturing and a trivializing of the idiographic/regional approach, much as
today critical social theorists caricature and demean spatial analysis and scientific geography.
(p. 553)

Hanson and some of her contemporaries were involved in the emergence of behavioural geography
as a counter to some of the ‘certainties’ being advanced by the ‘space cadets’ (her term for the
Seattle-trained spatial-scientists then on the staff at Northwestern, p. 534): ‘By dethroning economic
man and replacing him with a variety of decision makers, behavioral geography ignited the first
glimmer of the notion that each viewpoint is partial, incomplete and dependent on the subject’s
364 A changing discipline?

[i.e. the decision-maker’s] location.’ She was led, by her questioning of the assumptions which
underpinned the then popular theories, to the realization that (pp. 555–6) ‘people’s decision
making and behavior are not immune to context but are conditioned, inter alia, by time, place, class
and gender’, an argument which applies as much to geography itself as to that which it studies –
indeed, the recent growth of GIS reflects geographers (among others) capitalising on what they
have seen as a major opportunity for their discipline.
Although context is undoubtedly important at some stages of any scholar’s career – where they
are and who they interact with there, influencing what they studied and how, it need not always be
important. Some major contributions to the expansion of knowledge are made by ‘lone scholars’
who work almost entirely independently, as indicated by the citations to their research publications;
good examples of this are provided by recent biographical studies of both Michael Williams
(Clout, 2011b) and, especially, Robin Donkin (Baker, 2011).
A broader way of placing geographers in networks has been to develop insights from actor-
network theory (ANT) (Barnes, 2001a). Debate about the merits of ANT as an approach for
geography became the subject of disciplinary debate in the 1990s and have continued (see p. 268
in Chapter 7). When applied to the evolution of the discipline itself, ANT takes the notion of a
community of scholars linked together in networks, but takes it further by extending the nodes on
that network to inanimate objects as well – such as publications – many of which may be mobile
rather than fixed, and immutable rather than transient. A discipline, in this context, is thus an
interlocked network of entities, ‘material and non-material’, ‘social’ and ‘natural’ (Barnes, 2001a,
p. 528) and understanding its development involves studying how strong network links are
developed: the powerful entities (probably though not necessarily individuals) in those networks
are those that have greatest influence on disciplinary change, as Barnes (2001a, 2001b) illustrates
for two different periods in economic geography.

A structure for the discipline?


The structure of geography can be represented as a network of nodes and flows – very much like
Haggett’s representation of the spatial economy (Figure 4.1, p. 102). The nodes are individual
geographers and the flows are the ideas and research findings they share with others in formal
situations such as teaching and conference sessions, during informal conversations, and in their
publications. Some of those flows are situated – in classrooms, conference halls, and the informal
settings for conversations; others are widely available in many places, such as the libraries of
geography books and journals; an increasing proportion is even more generally available, to
anybody with access to electronic libraries. Individuals move between settings (in some cases while
remaining in the same physical place), and as they do so may be either or both influenced by others
or influential on them. They also refer to the flow of material, again hoping to be influenced by
what they access, and submit further material to the network, hoping to influence others indirectly
through what they write.
Within those networks, some individuals and some flow materials are more important than
others – i.e. the network nodes can be structured into a hierarchy of influence. In part, the degree
to which either an individual or a flow material is influential reflects settings. With regard to direct
interpersonal contact, for example, it is often suggested that dense concentrations of workers with
linked interests are more likely to stimulate important developments through interaction: there are
intellectual economies of scale and scope. This is the basis for the growth of major graduate schools,
and of focused research groups of staff in many university geography departments (perceived as
necessary in the UK to meet the criteria for the post-1980 Research Assessment Exercises); they
provide the critical mass whereby ideas are generated, refined and disseminated, both within the
school and outwards, as graduates get posts elsewhere and convey the message to new settings.
Examples of this can be found in the twentieth-century history of human geography, as with the
A changing discipline? 365

‘Berkeley school’ under Sauer (Spencer, 1979), the historical geographers trained by Darby
(Prince, 2000), the ‘Washington school’ under Garrison (see p. 69, this book), the ‘Chicago
school’ of urbanism (Yeates, 2001; Berry, 2002c), and its Los Angeles successor (Dear, 2002;
Dear and Dahmann, 2008; plus a number of more specialised groupings: see, e.g., Peach, 2003).
To some extent the influence may be serendipitous: a student may enrol in a department not
expecting to be supervised, or even influenced, by a particular staff member (or even other students)
there. Unanticipated conversations at a conference may have a similar impact, and so forth.
The degree to which individuals may influence each other’s mode of working is likely to vary,
however, even if other possible factors are held constant. Some individuals may not be appointed to
a large graduate school, for example, and so lack the access to a potential band of disciples.
Others are, but for some reason or another do not capitalise on that access; they may be
‘lone scholars’, difficult to work with, or studying topics that are currently relatively unpopular
or, as in the examples of Donkin and Michael Williams cited earlier, working independently
without any strong links to established networks (and, usually in such cases, without their own
graduate students following their example). Chance, charisma and a number of other factors can
result in some individuals having much more influence over the development of their discipline
than others do.
The same argument can be made about the impact of various publications: some are widely
read and influential; others may attract few readers and be largely ignored (whatever their potential
merits). To some extent this may also reflect the settings in which they are placed: a paper in a
relative obscure publication that has a small circulation will be relatively invisible and may pass
largely unnoticed, compared to one in a widely circulated and referred to journal. Similarly,
some publishers are better able to get books widely purchased and adopted as texts and some
publications are identified by reviewers and other commentators as important exemplars of parti-
cular types of work (Johnston, 2009a). But there is more to the distribution of influence than such
material conditions. There is little doubt that some authors are considered more innovative and
stimulating than others – especially, perhaps, those who challenge the conventional wisdoms and
whose writings cannot be categorised, in a general sense, as simply contributing to normal science
activity within the context of a given exemplar. They may move work on in a small way along
established paths, but not stimulate wider debates about means and ends. Thus, some authors’
writings are more likely to be read and referred to (i.e. through formal media – class reading lists
and book reviews – and informal media) than others’, as is suggested by the large variations in the
numbers of citations to particular authors and works. Given the pressure on time, and the great
explosion of publications in recent decades, selectivity is necessary: people choose to read that
which looks most relevant to their current concerns, whether that is a course that has to be taught
or a research project advanced. Their selectivity is based on a number of criteria, such as whether
the potential reader knows (of) the author and rates her/his work highly, or advice that a piece is
worth consulting, or just chance while browsing along a bookshelf (or through a bookseller’s
website), through the pages of a journal (including the book reviews) or, increasingly, by both
Internet searches and customised information sources delivered electronically.
What we have, then, in the continuing operation of an academic discipline is a massive network
of potential contacts only some of which are actualised. Knowing which have been, when and
where, is not easy to discover. Some clues are given in published material Media – many authors
acknowledge individuals who have helped them in their work, for example; references in a paper
indicate the sources considered worthy of mention (although not necessarily all those accessed);
and known biographical details (where a person was in graduate school, and when, for example)
are suggestive. Autobiographical and biographical essays may fill in gaps – though these are
relatively few – as also might obituaries and memoirs. But in most cases we have only circumstantial
evidence of who influenced whom, who read what and to what effect, and so forth, and such
evidence is the stuff of books like this. (The items we have referred to in this book indicate our own
366 A changing discipline?

selectivity in deciding what was of value to read and use in compiling our account.) Almost
certainly, detailed studies of disciplinary networks would find them divided up into subcommunities
– Geertz’s (1983) ‘intellectual peasant villages’.
All of these contacts – direct and indirect, positive and negative – are not only the basic
evidence for books like this, therefore; they are also the foundation of disciplinary change. Almost
all intellectual endeavour involves and results from interpersonal interaction of some form, usually
mediated by the written word (World Three in Popper’s terminology). What is of interest, however,
even if difficult to determine, is how those micro-level contact patterns have any significant impact
on the directions that a discipline takes at the macro-level. Or, in other words, do some individuals
and groups (or individual written pieces) have a disproportionate impact, so that if they had not
been on the networks the discipline might have taken other directions? There seems little doubt that
in the early days of geography as an academic discipline this was indeed the case: among the small
number of practitioners a few powerful professors, by virtue of a combination of and ability to
disseminate ideas, were highly influential on geography’s foundations (on which, see Lichtenberger,
1984). Since then, as the number of geographers has grown and the size of the network expanded
exponentially, influence has been much more widely dispersed. Nevertheless, it may well be that
certain paths would not have been followed – at least when and where they were, and with what
effect – if particular events had not occurred. Almost certainly geography would have taken a
quantitative turn at some stage in the 1960s, but would it have taken the particular form that it did
if, for example, Ullman, Hudson and Garrison had not taken up posts at the University of Washington
in the 1950s, if a group of talented graduate students had not clustered there at the same time
(some of them attracted there by Ullman’s presence rather than Garrison’s), if they had been unable
to spread their ideas through discussion papers (Johnston, 2004a), and so forth? And would this
book have taken its particular form – even been written at all! – if Chorley and Haggett had not
been influenced by Kuhn’s ideas in the mid-1960s (and a publisher had not perceived a potential
market for it)?
Such questions are, of course, ultimately unanswerable counterfactuals, although by posing
them it is possible to illuminate what did happen. They also illustrate the all-important contingency
of academic life. A discipline like human geography is not a disembodied phenomenon with a life
and trajectory of its own; it is shaped and continually reshaped by geographers reacting to
circumstances in particular milieux, the temporal and spatial situations in which they are placed
and place themselves. We can present the history of geography as a changing melange of ideas and
approaches, but that melange is a (far from planned) human creation; it is the sum of a large
number of biographies.

Human geography’s response to challenges


The impact of external circumstances on geographical practice has been illustrated repeatedly in
this book. The initial establishment of geography as a university discipline was associated with
arguments about its strategic (military and imperial) and educational (training geography teachers
who could then instruct children about the place of their nation) value. Yet doubts about the rigour
and value of the discipline (especially, but not only in the USA) have cropped up repeatedly,
sometimes resulting in the closure of departments. Such challenges arguably fostered some of the
disciplinary revolutions and debates that Geography and Geographers documents, as human geographers
sought to make their subject more rigorous, relevant or critical and/or to reorient it vis-à-vis other
social or physical sciences and humanities. Reflecting on the post-1945 challenges to geography in
the USA, Murphy (2007) argued that:

The shadow cast by Harvard’s [1948] decision to close its department worked against the
establishment of geography departments at smaller public institutions, private universities and
A changing discipline? 367

liberal-arts colleges, as the argument could be (and was) made that a great university did not
have to have geography. . . . The situation was exacerbated when three other leading universities
– the University of Pennsylvania, Stanford and Yale – followed Harvard’s lead and dropped their
geography departments in 1963, 1964 and 1967, respectively. Hence, when the higher education
juggernaut slowed in the mid-1970s, the academic discipline of geography was vulnerable.
(p. 124)

Murphy goes on to note how:

The situation deteriorated further in the 1980s when formerly prestigious departments were
closed at the University of Michigan (1982), Columbia University (1986), Northwestern University
(1986), and the University of Chicago (1987). As with the earlier closures at Harvard, Penn and
Yale, each of these programme losses could be seen as the result of the actions of unsympathetic
administrators or of internal problems (lack of attention to general undergraduate education,
feuds among faculty, etc.). But focusing on such explanations directs attention away from the
larger issue: many in the US academic elite had come to view geography as a dispensable
subject in institutions of higher learning.
(p. 124)

Hence, further challenges have been noticeable since the 1970s as a consequence of economic
recessions, cut-backs in higher education funding, and attacks on social-science research. In 1996
the House of Representatives voted to end funding for the social science divisions of the National
Science Foundation – although this was not enacted then, there have been several attempts since,
the latest in 2014, to restrict funding for social science research. A decade earlier the UK Secretary
of State for Education insisted on the term ‘social science’ being removed from the title of the Social
Science Research Council, and sought to make its successor – the Economic and Social Research
Council (ESRC) – more responsive to government and commercial agenda, and the policy prescrip-
tions of the ‘New Right’ designed to sustain what has been termed ‘flexible accumulation’ (Hudson,
1988) and ‘neoliberalism’ (Peck and Tickell, 2002) through ideas about a ‘free economy and a
strong [though restructured and pro-enterprise] state’ (Gamble, 1988; Johnston and Pattie, 1990).
These pressures have continued. Thus, since 2012, when inviting reviewers to comment on grant
applications, the ESRC asked not only about the project’s originality, theoretical and methodological
foundations, potential contributions to knowledge, and value for money, but also its ‘potential for
policy and practitioner impact’: had the applicants provided ‘a clear impact summary’?; had they
‘fully considered the potential of their research for policy and/or practitioner impact . . . [and] set
out [feasible] appropriate plans for achieving impact’?; and had they ‘identified appropriate
stakeholders . . . [and] how they will benefit from the research’?
Many reacted to this by promoting human geography as an ‘applied discipline’, offering
relevant skills for the attack on contemporary problems. In the December 1981 issue of the AAG
Newsletter an article entitled ‘A survival package for geography and other endangered disciplines’
indicated that ‘On 19 June, 1981, the Board of Regents of the University of Michigan decided, by
unanimous vote, to terminate the Department of Geography at the end of the 1981–82 academic
year’ (Kish and Ward, 1981, p. 8). Their experience of this decision led George Kish and Robert
Ward to suggest how other departments of geography could counter similar attacks. They
emphasised the teaching role, recognising the need to attract students in a competitive market and
present ‘our wares in a stimulating and excellent way’ involving ‘the virtues of applied geography.
As students become more conscious of careers, there may be a corresponding need to increase a
skill-oriented curriculum. This could demonstrate the relevancy of geography and enhance its
appeal to students’ (p. 14). Kish and Ward – ‘To appease some traditionalists’ – did not advocate
reorganising the entire corpus of geography ‘but only [an] attempt to broaden the appeal of
368 A changing discipline?

geography to the student population’. (See also Ford, 1982; Powell, 1981, and Wright and Koch,
2009; on a more recent closure, see Chan, 2011.) Their prescriptions were written at a time in
North America when, according to Haigh (1992, p. 185), geographers’ peers saw their discipline
as ‘small, marginal and perhaps immature’: the late 1970s had seen a net loss of 32 university
departments, including one-sixth of those in ‘private and denominationally funded institutions’.
Avoiding the discipline’s demise was presented as a crucial task (Wilbanks and Libbee, 1979), a
problem stimulated by the absence of geography in most American high schools and the very small
number of undergraduate students intending to take geography courses (Murphy, 2007). Despite
the vitality of geographical research, therefore, ‘Geographical education is still regarded as a
marginal activity by American schools and colleges’ (Haigh, 1992, p. 189); the discipline there was
not only ‘small, often beleaguered’ (Koelsch, 2002, p. 274) but:

it would be difficult to identify any other university study that in the course of the 20th century had
achieved full departmental independence and programmatic recognition at the doctoral and
research level in so many leading American universities, only to lose both by the end of that same
century. At the pre-college level . . . geography remains largely a minor component of social studies
or of global education, taught most often by teachers with little or no background in the discipline.

Koelsch puts this parlous state down to the ‘fracturing of any consensual view of what the discipline
and its practitioners should be about’, although Murphy (2007) judged that:

the closing of the departments at Columbia, Northwestern and Chicago [in th 1980s] appears to
signal the end of an era of decline. Geography has not experienced a single major programme
loss since that time. In a few places geography has been folded into a larger unit with some loss
of influence or standing, and a handful of mid-size programmes have closed at regional colleges
(e.g. West Georgia College). Nonetheless, the last 15 years have generally seen a steady
expansion of geography’s institutional base. New programmes have been founded, many existing
programmes have expanded, and student enrolment has generally risen (although not without a
temporary downturn in undergraduate enrolments in the late 1990s – perhaps due to the rapid
expansion of interdisciplinary environmental studies programmes).
(p. 125)

There was some rejoicing within the geographical discipline when, as Tomlinson (2009)
puts it, there was a ‘reintroduction of geography to Harvard’. But it was a narrowly conceived
reintroduction, involving a Center for Geographical Analysis which the university’s president
promoted because ‘Geographic information systems will let us change the nature of questions that
are asked in a wide diversity of sciences and humanities.’ The Center’s website presents itself as
administering infrastructure, collecting and disseminating spatial datasets and providing training
and consultation in the use of geospatial technologies.
Yet elsewhere, challenges to the position of the discipline persist. In Australia since the 1990s
almost all the separate university departments of geography have been merged into larger units,
thereby losing a separate identity for the discipline in some cases (Holmes, 2002). This was part of
a larger shift in Australian universities whose traditional medium for teaching and research:

the academic disciplines, was to some extent destabilised and displaced amid the mergers and
rapid growth, the rationalistation of degreees and programs, the sudden changes in mission and
decision structures, the explosive growth in international education. Unless they could gain
autonomous resources by selling themselves, individual disciplines began to lose purchase on
their own agendas.
(Marginson, 2004, p. 220)
A changing discipline? 369

In the UK, too, mergers and closures characterised the first years of the millennium with more
than one-tenth of the country’s geography departments ‘disappearing’ – as separate entities, if not
totally – causing concern among disciplinary leaders (Cooke, 2002), not least because the trends
appeared to be linked with a reduction in the number of secondary (high) school students taking
geography, which for more than a century was the foundation for successful university departments
(see p. 39, this book). More recently, Tim Hall et al. (2015) note that:

The number of autonomous, single subject Geography departments in the UK has fallen from 47
in 1995 to 30 in 2013. The sharpest decline, from 41 to 33, occurred between 2003 and 2005.
Correspondingly the numbers of multi-disciplinary departments of various kinds within which
Geography is located rose from 29 in 1995 to 47 in 2013.
(p. 58)

Especially in the USA, there was frequently a commitment to secure geography through
promotion of it as an applied discipline (part of the wider debates considered in Chapter 9)
in research as well as teaching. The announcement of a new editorial policy for The Professional
Geographer in the AAG Newsletter for April 1992 reported that (p. 1) ‘[The new editor] hopes to
emphasize work in applied geography and to include information on corporation activities, state
and local government projects, Federal government activities, activities by United Nations and
other international agencies, and research projects.’ The need for more applied work was widely
accepted among American human geographers as a necessary means for their discipline’s vitality.
Mikesell (1981) had suggested that:

geographers fortunate enough to have secure teaching positions will worry about what they
should do. The best response to this concern could be a decision to do what they have been
doing, but with a keener appreciation of context and a greater willingness to be influenced by
environment.
(p. 14)

The response took a variety of forms, with many arguing for a greater concentration on cartographic,
remote sensing and geographical information systems skills.
This response was illustrated by a group of papers published by the AAG in 1995. In 1993, the
National Academy of Sciences/National Research Council undertook its first major review of
geography for nearly three decades (see p. 87, this book). It established a committee of 16 charged
with ‘Rediscovering geography: new relevance for the new century’ and given five objectives
(Wilbanks, 1995):

1 identify critical issues and constraints for the discipline of geography;


2 clarify priorities for teaching and research;
3 link developments in geography as a science with national needs for geography education;
4 increase the appreciation of geography within the scientific community; and
5 communicate with the international scientific community about future directions of the
discipline in the USA.

Within this context, a report was commissioned from the AAG on the supply of and demand for
geographers. Introducing papers based on that report, Wilbanks (1995) noted some challenges and
opportunities:

many geography programs in universities across the United States are already experiencing
unprecedented growth in student demand. . . . A major concern for geography should be that,
370 A changing discipline?

because of supply limitations (e.g. a lack of additional faculty positions in geography departments)
the demand will be artificially and arbitrarily truncated by limitations on course enrollments.
(p. 316)

This is described as a ‘very welcome but very difficult disciplinary transition from relative penury
to relative abundance’.
The committee’s report on the supply side of the equation (Gober et al., 1995a) referred to an
earlier study (Goodchild and Janelle, 1988) on the internal structure of the discipline which found
that ‘Technical expertise and interest in geographical information systems (GIS) were burgeoning,
especially among young geographers, while regionally oriented specialities were shrinking’ (Gober
et al., 1995a, p. 317). (Turner and Varlyguin’s, 1995, report on foreign-area dissertations, in the
same issue of The Professional Geographer, shows that the latter trend was relative not absolute.) To iden-
tify which skills and interests university departments of geography were focusing on, department
chairs were asked about specialisations and the occupations students were being prepared for. Of
the 212 respondents, 139 identified at least one specialisation, and the full list was:

led by programs in environmental/resource management, techniques (GIS, cartography, and


remote sensing), and urban planning. These tracks appear to be designed to prepare students
for the occupations in which geographers traditionally have found work rather than to develop
their interests in regional geography or the systematic specialties like urban, economic or
physical geography that have traditionally formed the core of the academic discipline.

More specifically:

We also asked chairs to indicate the specific occupations for which students were being prepared.
The occupations indicated by the highest numbers of departments were (1) GIS/remote sensing
specialist, (2) secondary school teacher, (3) cartographer, (4) environmental manager/technician,
and (5) urban/regional planner. . . . GIS was by far the most popular occupational trajectory
(involving almost 11% of students enrolled in programs offering GIS training).

The committee also surveyed the labour market experiences of graduates (Gober et al., 1995b, p.
331), finding that ‘Among those who were employed and listed occupations closely related to
geography, respondents clustered into five predictable occupations: teacher (15.6%), environmental
manager/technician (12.9%), GIS/remote sensing specialist (10.5%), cartographer (8.2%), and
planner (6.7%).’  They also studied the employers and job-seekers using the placement service at the
AAG’s 1994 annual meeting: 45 per cent of the employers were looking for candidates with technical
qualifications, and they comprised 80 per cent of all non-academic employers using the service.
Finally, the committee surveyed the future labour market by asking department chairs the areas
of expertise of staff who would be retiring over the next decade, and also of those which they
would be recruiting (Gober et al., 1995c). Technical areas of the discipline predominated in the
latter category, with GIS specified in 17 per cent of the cases – nearly twelve times more frequently
than it was among the retirements. As the discipline reproduced itself over the next decade,
according to these figures, the relative number of technical specialists would increase substantially,
whereas traditional areas such as agricultural, historical, political, cultural and economic geography
would decline substantially. The committee’s conclusions, based on interviews with the AAG’s
corporate sponsors, implied a major shift in the nature of the discipline as taught to undergraduates
(see also Miyares and McGlade, 1994):

The debate over geography as a broad-based liberal arts discipline or as a technical, semiprofessional
field ignores the realities of the current labor market. Sponsors told us they want employees who
A changing discipline? 371

can combine technical skills with a broad-based background. Geography’s comparative advantage
over other social sciences lies in its ability to combine technical skills with a more traditional liberal
arts perspective. Successful geography programs will be those that are able to find the appropriate
balance of field-based technical skills like GIS, cartography and air-photo interpretation with
competence in literacy, numeracy, decision making, problem solving, and critical thinking.
(p. 346)

In this context, the review’s conclusions – indeed, its whole tenor – focused on technical skills; its
first recommended response was that the discipline should ‘Improve geographic analysis in a new
era of data and analytical tool availability, related to broader needs of science’ (NAS-NRC, 1997, p.
162). Its student base could be enhanced if it were to:

Implement programs to support and assure the quality of the science content in kindergarten
through grade 12 geography education . . .
  [and]
  Foster conceptually sound general education courses in geography as part of a liberal arts
college education . . .
  [while at the same time it should]
  Develop programs that bring geographic perspectives to bear more effectively on business,
government and other organizations at national to community levels.
(p. 164)

Little of this has occurred, however, and although geography was recognised in the mid-1990s
as a ‘core discipline’ for contemporary education, no funding to develop school geography
programmes had been made available (Richardson, 2003); in the 1920s, according to Schulten
(2001), geography academics in the USA distanced themselves from their discipline’s status in the
country’s schools, and this still appears very largely to be the case. A lesser distancing has occurred
more recently in the UK. Until the 1970s the community of academic geographers was closely
linked to that of teachers of the subject in the country’s (mainly secondary/high) schools; they
participated in developing school syllabuses and curricula, and the setting and marking of the
external examinations which were used as indicators of students’ potential for undertaking degree
courses in the discipline, for example, and a number were active in the Geographical Association,
the learned society for geography teachers (Balchin, 1993). Such involvement is now rare, in part
because of other pressures on scholars’ time (such as higher student–staff ratios and a greater
emphasis on research for career advancement in universities). A large number of students who have
studied geography at high school and wish to continue with the discipline at university remain the
strongest foundation to the discipline’s strength in the latter institutions, but academic geographers
now do relatively little to foster that key interaction (Sidaway and Johnston, 2007).
External pressures became just as great in the UK during the 1980s, with expression of the
need for applied geography and the development of ‘transferable skills’ (problem-solving, group-
working, IT awareness, etc.) within undergraduate curricula (see Matthews and Livingstone, 1996;
the Journal of Geography in Higher Education has published widely on this general theme since its
inauguration in 1977). Bennett (1982), for example, found at the 1982 conference of the Institute
of British Geographers that it was:

possible to discern a strong and growing set of foci which, if they do not yet demark a new core,
at least show an emerging commonality of interest. For this writer these foci were a widespread
assertion of ‘relevant’ research, the reassertion of quantitative and analytical methods, and the
rejection of recent anti-empirical movements.
(p. 69)
372 A changing discipline?

He welcomed these, noting that ‘hot [i.e. relevant] issues are not ones which British geographers
are particularly noted for tackling en masse – and, as a result, the discipline has suffered a lack of
public exposure, and a marked inability to influence public and private decisions’. Furthermore:

At a time when higher education as a whole is under considerable challenge, and when geography
as a discipline may suffer particularly severe pressure in some institutions it is heartening to see
the ­emergence of concern with the hot issues expressed at this meeting.
(p. 71)

Beaumont (1987) echoed this a few years later:

the issues raised for the next twenty years are a practical and developmental, rather than a
research, orientation. The future is unknown, but it could be exciting, if geographers are prepared
to become involved (probably with new partners) in doing geography.
(p. 172)

Richards and Wrigley (1996) presented the early 1990s as a period of even greater and faster
change, arguing that in contrast earlier periods:

seem in retrospect almost to have been years of relative stability and calm, prefacing the
maelstrom of change which swept through the whole British education system in the early to
mid-1990s. . . . This period has been one of system-wide expansion, of curriculum and quality
control through external review . . . and of institutional change. . . . These have combined to
alter, quite fundamentally, the size, nature and structure of British geography.
(p. 41)

The assessment of teaching in university departments of geography was set in the context of a
national agenda concerned not only with the quality of the education provided (which some
believe conflicts with an overemphasis on research: Gibbs, 1995; Johnston, 1996f.) but also with
the development of ‘transferable skills’ beyond the traditional focus on subject-based knowledge
and a critical intellect (Johnston, 1996a). The assessment of research produced not only a grading
of all departments but also substantial differentials in funding (Johnston, 1993a), while government
directives on research funding made it (Richards and Wrigley, 1996):

likely that future research will be constrained to ask specific questions, will be increasingly
‘applied’, and will be manipulated by government, business and industry for ends which are
unlikely to assist the less material aspects of the quality of civilized life; and critical (social or
environmental) science will be marginalized.
(p. 47)

To a considerable extent, this was ameliorated because geographers in UK universities have been
able to rely on a continuing stream of potential undergraduates wanting to read for degrees in
geography. At the end of the twentieth century, for example, there were some 7,000 or so
places available each year on geography honours degrees (in which the majority of the
student’s time would be spent on geography courses, especially in the final years), compared to only
4,000 or so who major in geography from all USA universities. This large stream of UK would-be
geographers results from the discipline’s strength in the country’s secondary schools and place in
national curricula – itself a product of successful political lobby by bodies such as the Geographical
Association (Goodson, 1988; Balchin, 1993; Walford, 2001; Johnston, 2003b). Almost all the 7,000
students arriving at UK universities each year to study geography have a strong foundation in the
A changing discipline? 373

subject, having studied it for the previous ten years – a situation very different from that in the
USA where most students arriving at university have not encountered geography as an academic
discipline at high school, and their understanding of the discipline rarely extends beyond basic
geographical knowledge of where places are. Geography has not been perceived as a ‘problem
discipline’ in many UK universities, therefore; (most of) its departments can recruit excellent
students and their graduates can get good jobs. There is relatively little need to focus on courses that
will attract students by the ‘employability value added’ they might provide – though there is attention
to this. The breadth of material in cultural geography and related subject matter taught in many of
the departments currently reflects this: academic geographers in the UK are freer to teach a wide
range of material at undergraduate level than is the case for their North American counterparts.
Despite this important difference between the two sides of the North Atlantic, reflecting long-
established differences in the role of geography in the respective school systems, in the UK, as
elsewhere, there is a need for continual vigilance in order to protect and promote the discipline’s
interests. In his 2002 Presidential Address to the RGS, Ron Cooke (2002) identified several
challenges facing the discipline in the UK. Key among these was the potential reduction of time
given to geography in the school curriculum: the Society was working to sustain geography’s
central role, because it is ‘unquestionably fundamental to public understanding of such enduring
issues as social equity, globalization and the relations between environment and society’ (p. 260;
see also Thrift, 2002; Johnston, 2002b).
The beginning of the new century’s second decade saw a new threat to geography – and other
social science and humanities disciplines – in the UK, with the removal of any direct public subsidy
for its teaching in universities. From 2012 on, undergraduate students were required to repay loans
covering the full cost of their courses (set at most universities as the maximum allowed – £9,000
per annum), after graduation and achievement of a threshold annual income. This stimulated an
immediate substantial decline in the number of applicants, and concerns among geographers as to
the attractiveness of their degrees, relative to those with clearer career prospects, to students who
would face debts (covering both their tuition and living expenses) of £50,000 or more. In addition,
with such debts there was concern whether many students would want subsequently to continue
into graduate schools, many of which are sustained by recruiting large numbers of overseas students
who pay premium fees. The number of independent departments of geography had declined in the
previous decade, especially in the more recently created institutions where relatively small units
were integrated with larger portmanteau, multidisciplinary creations, and this major change in
funding (albeit to one much closer to the long-established American model) accentuated concerns
for the medium-term health of the discipline.

A generational model?
The importance of context as an influence on the nature of the practice of human geography
suggests that the paradigm model might be rephrased as a generational model (Johnston, 1978a,
1979; Taylor, 1976). Changes in the external environment provide necessary, but not sufficient,
stimuli to changes within the discipline which may be interpreted as attempts to develop new
research programmes, if not to launch a revolution and create a new normal science (see the
discussion of Scott’s work on p. 359, this book).
Associated with the external changes must be a set of conditions within the discipline itself
which is sympathetic to the new demands of the milieux. In most cases, these conditions are best
met by younger members of the discipline. Stegmuller (1976, p. 148) argues that ‘it is mostly
young people who bring new paradigms into the world. And it is young people who are most
inclined to champion new causes with religious fervour, to thump the propaganda drums.’ To win
influence, however, especially in times of resource shortage within higher education, younger
374 A changing discipline?

workers need the patronage of some established members of the discipline (see Chapter 1).
According to Lemaine et al. (1976), for example:

Mendel’s work [on what is now termed genetics], and that of his successors, was a response to
scientific problems. But the scientific implications of their results were not pursued until there
existed a strong group of scientists who, owing to their academic background and their position
in the research community, were willing to abandon established conceptions.
(p. 5)

Such responses may involve attempts to create a new paradigm or new research programme, or they
may only require new branches of an existing paradigm/programme. Whichever it is, even when
establishment support has been obtained, success is more likely when certain criteria are met,
including (van den Daele and Weingart, 1976):

1 an autonomous system of evaluation and reputation;


2 an autonomous communication system;
3 acknowledgement of the new ability to solve puzzles within the confines of the disciplinary
matrix;
4 a formal organization providing training programmes which allow reproduction and
expansion of the new group’s membership;
5 an informal structure with leaders; and
6 resources for research.

These rarely create problems if resources are available; Capel (1981), Mikesell (1981) and Taylor
(1976) all indicated that innovation is encouraged if it brings status, charisma and resources to
the discipline. During periods of stagnation and retrenchment, however, conditions are less
favourable because of the lack of resources with which to develop innovations and major shifts – if
any – are more likely to be achieved by revolutions among existing members of the discipline. The
generational model suggests that the latter is rare. With regard to the research record, John Law
(1976) counselled that:

it may well be the case that scientists do lay special emphasis on the accounts in scientific
papers, but my hunch is that there is immense (and non-trivial) variation between scientists on
this count. For some, science is something you do in the laboratory, something you talk about,
and something you get excited about. For others, science is what they write and what they read
in the journals. I would even hypothesize (in conformity with the invisible college notion) that
those who are generally felt to be of higher status locate science less in their journals than in
their own and other people’s heads.
(p. 228)

Many academics are less active as researchers, and some get ‘left behind’ as changes proceed.
The ‘normal science’ that they continue to teach is probably based on the world view, disciplinary
matrix, and exemplars into which they were socialised. But their colleagues, socialised later and
influenced by different environmental conditions, operate in different ways. The academic
career cycle, in combination with a changing milieu, can produce a multiparadigm teaching
discipline.
The key elements in the generational model (modified after Johnston, 1978a) are:

1 the external environment is a major influence on a discipline’s contents, especially in the social
sciences that are closely linked with that environment;
A changing discipline? 375

2 at times, the nature of this environment may change significantly, provoking a reaction among
a minority of members of the discipline who try to stimulate change in disciplinary practice
by its established members and to generate interest in that change among the youngest
generation of research workers – the latter is usually much more successful than the former;
3 together, this grouping presents a new ‘school of thought’, although in some cases opposing
new schools may be stimulated;
4 the new school is co-opted into the disciplinary career structure;
5 the publications of the new school come to dominate the disciplinary research output, as the
productivity of the earlier generation declines;
6 students face two or more separate generational schools in a department’s teaching syllabus;
and
7 over time, members of the new school attain seniority and political influence within the
discipline (and write the textbooks that define their perspectives on the current ‘normal
science’: Johnston, 2006).

Several consequences may follow. If a discipline fails to react to a changing milieu it could stagnate,
and so innovators are encouraged. Another is that some potential innovators may be unable to
influence their discipline, either because conditions are not conducive, the ‘establishment’ does not
react positively to their suggestions, or they cannot obtain permanent positions within the academic
career structure. Simon Duncan (1974b, p. 109) illustrated these ‘processes of resistance’ using the
example of Hägerstrand’s (1968) ideas on spatial diffusion that were originally published in 1953;
citation analysis shows that widespread recognition was much delayed, compared to the average for
all publications in geography (Stoddart, 1967a). This was not, Duncan claims, because of either
language or Hägerstrand’s relative isolation in Sweden (though see Getis, 1993, p. 519, on the
‘excitement’ generated by Hägerstrand’s visit to Seattle in 1960, which led to Morrill doing his Ph.D.
work in Sweden), but the apparent irrelevance of his work to those steeped in another paradigm.
Only when spatial science had been established was Hägerstrand’s contribution recognised:

Hägerstrand’s own attempts to disseminate his work met rejection from adherents to orthodoxy,
but later enthusiasm from those pioneering spatial science. The eventual relay of information to
this community owed more to dogged personal effort than to the formal communication system
of normal science, and general recognition was not achieved until professional allegiances were
reorganized.
(p. 130; see also Johnston, 1993c, 1996c)

Even when a new idea has been recognised, however, several virtually independent groups may be
involved in its development (Gatrell, 1982).
In all these debates about changing communities within geography and orientations to the
discipline, the threefold hierarchy introduced by Kuhn should be remembered (see p. 19, this
book). Changes, whether revolutionary or not, are much more likely to occur at the lowest level of
the exemplar than at the level of the disciplinary matrix, and even less likely with regard to the
world review. Charting an evolving discipline involves separating the changes that occur regularly
within communities, almost as part of normal science, from those which involve much more
radical rethinks of what is done, and why.

Geographies of geography?
Given the importance of context being stressed by observers of geography’s recent history, it should
not be surprising to find that there are significant differences in how the discipline has been
376 A changing discipline?

(and is being) practised, at a variety of scales and across a range of cleavages. It has been suggested,
for example, that there are four main cleavage lines within contemporary geography (Johnston,
1997b, pp. 30–1):

1 the substantive divisions according to subject matter studied;


2 the epistemological divisions according to views on the nature of knowledge and its
production;
3 divisions in rationale, reflecting the reasons for undertaking work; and
4 community divisions which can be found at a variety of scales – language used (macro-scales);
national schools (meso-scales); and intellectual schools (local communities at the micro-scale).

To a considerable extent these all overlap, creating a myriad academic communities and networks
within the discipline with points of contact and interaction, but also considerable difference and
distance.
One of the clearest axes of contemporary differentiation in geographical practices is that
provided by different meso-scale linguistic communities. In the nineteenth century, when
geography was being launched as an academic discipline, there was considerable international
contact and developments in several linguistic realms – not least the English-speaking world – were
much influenced by pioneering ideas emanating from Germany and France (see Chapter 2).
These were enhanced by the personal contacts developed during periods of study by
individual geographers at European universities (as with Dickinson – Johnston, 2000c, 2002b;
and Ogilvie – Clout and Stevenson, 2004) as well as at international congresses and occasional
events such as the Transcontinental Excursion of 1912 when some sixty European geographers
participated in a 21,560km journey across the USA with their American hosts (Chisholm
et al., 1913; Clout, 2004; Maclean, 2011). These contacts waned, however; they were fairly weak by
the time that the First World War further ruptured international intellectual communities, and were
not easily re-established in the subsequent decades.
During the second-half of the twentieth century, geography as practised in countries where
English was either the main language or widely used in universities (including Sweden and the
Netherlands) came to dominate: ‘International’ journals almost invariably published in English
only, which created difficulties for ‘outsiders’, not only in reading the material but, even more so,
in getting their research findings and ideas before wide audiences (Aalbers, 2004; Gutiérrez and
López-Nieva, 2001; Banski and Ferenc, 2013). For some commentators this has amounted to the
formation of an Anglo-American disciplinary hegemony – a debate that was touched upon in the
Preface to this book. Minca (2000, p. 285), for example, reported that ‘the past fifteen years or so
of the postmodern debate in geography have been an almost exclusively Anglo-American domain’,
marginalising those who ‘navigate only on the edges of the Anglo-American academic empire – but
are firmly placed within other geographical traditions’, with a joint conference of Italian and
Anglo-American geographers providing:

further confirmation of the essentially undisputed dominion of Anglo-American geography . . .


today the boundaries as well as the rules/coordinates of what passes for ‘international’ debate
within our discipline are determined from within the Anglo-American universe.
(p. 287)

For many (especially younger) European geographers this created problems of co-location in
their home academic traditions and the ‘languages and methodologies of Anglo-American
geography’, with the (so-called) ‘international’ journals published in English offering a ‘formidable
instrument of internal regulation and legitimation for the Anglo-American community [but] . . .
not a propitious terrain for encounter and debate among diverse geographical traditions’. The result
A changing discipline? 377

was a claimed ‘hegemonic closure’: all debates in ‘international journals’ were ‘essentially internal
to the Anglo-American geographical community’ (p. 288) from which others were effectively
excluded:

It is therefore deceiving, if not intellectually dishonest, to identify these leading journals as the
locus of international debates – unless, of course, one retains the belief that the entirety of
relevant contemporary theoretical contributions in geography can be limited to the Anglo-
American world and to English-language publications.

Samers and Sidaway (2000) took up this debate, citing a wider literature and pointing out the
relative marginalisation of some scholars within the English-language realm; they related the Anglo-
American (i.e. North Atlantic) apparent intellectual hegemony to the wider post-1945 American
economic and geopolitical influence. The period was marked by an upsurge of influence of British
geography (Whitehand and Edmondson, 1977). Nevertheless, they argued that work in other
traditions had influenced that undertaken in the Anglo-American realm (citing regulation theory as
an example; see p. 211, this book), and that all geographical traditions were inherently hybrid
(or ‘transnational’). Garcia-Ramon (2003, p. 1) was unconvinced by this argument, however, and
restated the case regarding Anglo-American hegemony. For Simonsen (2002, p. 391) there was a
paradox that growing cultural globalisation was associated with Anglo-American predominance
within human geography, in which ‘a presumed universality is constructed that tends to conceal a
particularity based, to a large extent, on specific experiences of the USA and United Kingdom’.
There are also significant differences within the Anglo-American realm, however, not least
between the UK and the USA. To some extent these reflect the different inheritances – the intellectual
palimpsests identified by Scott (p. 358, this book) – as with the cultural geography developed by
Sauer and the Berkeley school for several decades from the 1920s on and the parallel school of
historical geographers, with its emphasis on cross-sections, established by Darby in the UK at about
the same time. They also reflect the different educational contexts. In the UK (as noted on p. 372),
geography has long been a strong discipline in the schools, because of successful lobbying
campaigns by institutions such as the RGS and the Geographical Association; indeed, according to
Steve Fuller (2000, p. 228), who based his argument on Goodson (1988), ‘geography . . . is perhaps
the only major academic discipline to have been built from the grassroots of sub-university-level
teachers’, although his claim that it ‘did not have a clear research agenda until elementary- and
secondary-school teachers lobbied Parliament to get the subject established in the universities’ is
historically inaccurate.
This strength in the country’s schools long ensured a continued flow of students to the UK
universities who wish to take a degree in the subject and have a firm foundation in it. This not only
allows more specialist teaching from an early stage than is the case where many students come to
geography new when they reach university but also, because the discipline has little difficulty
recruiting undergraduates, means less direct pressure on its departments to offer ‘relevant’ curricula.
In the USA, on the other hand, geography has typically been weak in the country’s high schools,
and most students have had little exposure to the discipline beyond some basic learning of locational
facts in primary classes. Geography departments are therefore present in only a small minority of
the country’s universities, and they need to attract students once they get to the campus by offering
courses that are attractive, not least because they suggest career paths and benefits that a geographical
training might bring. Thus, introductory courses are usually pitched at a very general level, and
much emphasis is currently put (as discussed on p. 370, this book) on providing courses on
‘saleable, transferable skills’, notably those associated with GIS. Graduate programmes also recruit
widely – whereas most academic geographers in the UK have first degrees in the subject, many in
the USA do not (as shown by the autobiographical accounts in volumes such as Gould and Pitts,
2002) – and many American graduate programmes have particular orientations, not least because
378 A changing discipline?

most of them are small, in terms of the numbers of staff (faculty), when compared with the major
UK departments. Furthermore, in the USA geography is competing for status within the social
sciences with a number of much larger disciplines – notably, economics, political science and
sociology – which considerably constrains its promotion and growth. In the UK, on the other
hand, the creation of university geography departments largely predated that of sociology and
politics departments (if not economics), giving it a comparative advantage, alongside that provided
by its school presence, in promoting itself to potential students.
There are, then, complex geographies of geography, some of whose parameters we have
started to map here. Few departments (even the largest in the UK) cover the full range of the
current subdisciplines in their teaching programmes, for example, let alone in their research
concentrations. Most specialise, reflecting the interests of senior staff at particular times in their
development and institutional resourcing decisions. Thus, the practice of geography as an academic
discipline itself reflects its own fundamental precepts. There are general features that apply to most
geography programmes but also particularities that reflect local characteristics and individual
decision-making. In geography, as in so much else, place matters.

Recapping: human geography as paradigms,


streams or traditions?
Several models of scientific progress have been applied to the task of interpreting changes within
human geography over the last six decades, therefore. This final discussion reconsiders the general
relevance of Kuhn’s concept of a paradigm (at all three scales of definition), without necessarily
suggesting either substantial periods of mono-paradigm dominance and normal science for the
discipline as a whole or major revolutionary events that involved large numbers of geographers
switching from one paradigm to another. (In some ways, paradigms as disciplinary matrices can be
equated with research programmes in Lakatos’s terminology; the Kuhnian term is preferred here.)
In seeking to understand the relative popularity of various paradigms at different times, however, it
is necessary to employ the contextual approach ignored by some advocates of a Kuhnian approach
within geography. In this section we are also mindful of the other ways of narrating disciplinary
change that have been flagged in this and the introductory chapter.

The 1950s and 1960s


Regionalism, with its empiricist and implicit exceptionalist philosophy, dominated the discipline
until the 1940s, though in several versions. In the USA, for example, areal differentiation was
stressed by geographers emanating from the midwest, notably Chicago and Madison, whereas those
from Berkeley focused on the evolving cultural landscape, with a third distinct school based in
Clark University (Bushong, 1981; Prunty, 1979; Koelsch, 1988; Martin, 1998; Monk, 1998). The
regional theme dominated in the UK, too, though with a greater emphasis on physical geography
and less evidence of distinct ‘schools’ (Freeman, 1979; Johnston and Gregory, 1984).
Systematic studies increasingly replaced regional descriptions through the 1950s; their stated
(though often unrealised) aims were to increase the content of regional descriptions, advancing the
understanding of particular places through knowledge of the general processes (especially physical)
which interact to produce unique local characteristics. Nevertheless, regional synthesis remained
the central focus of many (senior) geographers’ conception of their discipline, and regional courses
predominated in many undergraduate degree programmes.
Regionalism was a disciplinary matrix with several competing exemplars, therefore. In the
1950s and 1960s, there was what Entrikin (1981, p. 1) terms ‘transition between reigning
orthodoxies . . . in which the spatial theme superseded the regional theme’. This was marked by the
A changing discipline? 379

further growth of systematic studies, the distancing of many geographers from the core belief in
regional synthesis, and an increasing emphasis on finding laws of spatial organisation, involving
distance as a basic influence on human behaviour. As Guelke (1977a, 1977b, 1978) and Entrikin
(1981) have indicated, the distancing was not rapid – in part no doubt because of the political need
to sustain the unity and identity of the discipline – and some of those promoting the new paradigm
only argued that quantitative analysis and spatial science offered better and more rigorous
procedures for identifying and understanding regions (as in Berry, 1964a). This was seen by some
as a methodological shift only (Chisholm, 1975a), which involved new exemplars but not a new
disciplinary matrix, let alone a new world view.
The methodological shift alone was increasingly portrayed as insufficient, however, and a
philosophical shift slowly emerged (elsewhere termed a ‘quiet revolution’: Johnston, 1978a,
1981b, 1979). Regional synthesis as the disciplinary core was unattractive to many younger
geographers (e.g. Gould, 1979), for whom contact with other social scientists (as in the Second
World War – see p. 59, this book) introduced the excitements of systematic specialisms practised
according to the positivist model of science, which implied the search for laws and applicable
research findings. The links with the regional core were severed and a new disciplinary matrix of
spatial science established, although Batty (1989) argued that by the time its models were well
developed and applicable the demand for them had declined: ‘It is an irony of history that such
good models finally exist which could well have produced excellent advice in their day had they
been available. But that day has passed’ (p. 156). The term ‘region’ took on a very different meaning
(Johnston, 1984a). The shared values of the new disciplinary matrix differed from those of
regionalism, and to the extent that the adherents of spatial science, most of them from the new
generation of geographers who were part of the educational boom of those decades, came to
dominate the discipline (see Mikesell, 1984, on whether they did) so a revolution can be said to
have occurred. Whether it was a revolution in Kuhnian terms is doubtful, however, since, as noted
earlier, the shift hardly fits into the ‘response to anomalies’ component of Kuhn’s model. That would
involve not only a shift in disciplinary matrix but also a shift in world view, in the conception of
the nature of science, but as Hartshorne made clear (see p. 61), traditional regional geography as
he conceived it did not deny the possible relevance of generalisations about processes for the
understanding of places. James Bird (1989) identified a ‘one and only’ revolution, however, dating
it to June 1966 with the publication of Bunge’s (1966b) note which criticised those who argued
that the uniqueness of location meant that positivism was inapplicable in human geography.
The new disciplinary matrix of spatial science was firmly established in Anglo-American
human geography by the end of the 1960s, and has been sustained since. Over nearly 50 years it
has seen many shifts in exemplars, a lot of them linked to methodological – especially technical –
developments in data collection, collation, analysis and display. (Compare, for example, Haggett,
1965c, with Haggett et al., 1977, for shifts in the general orientation; Cliff and Ord, 1973, with Cliff
and Ord, 1981, for a single methodological issue; and Hägerstrand, 1968, with Cliff et al., 1987,
and Haggett, 2000, for a particular substantive topic.) Such paradigm shifts at the level of exemplar
are closer to Kuhn’s original presentation (and later clarified intention), with new ways of doing
research accepted as superior to those previously used. They brought greater substantive success
too: Haggett (1978, p. 161), writing on ‘The spatial economy’, claimed that it:

is more carefully defined than before, we know a little more about its organization, the ways it
responds to shocks, and the way some regional sections are tied to others. There now exist
theoretical bridges, albeit incomplete and shaky, which span from pure, spaceless economics
through to a more spatially disaggregated reality.

In addition to the shifts among methodological exemplars there were also changes within the
spatial science disciplinary matrix which had a wider import. The first was the reorientation away
380 A changing discipline?

from normative modelling, which involved testing observed spatial organisation against a priori
models, and towards behavioural studies; as Kevin Cox (1981, 2014) and Hanson (1993) indicate,
the disciplinary matrix was not queried but there were major shifts in emphasis and style (see also
the discussion of Openshaw’s views on p. 156, this book). The second was the advocacy for ‘welfare
geography’ (p. 337), described by Eyles and Smith (1978) as a response to social conditions and a
desire to make contemporary human geography more relevant to them.
The 1950s and 1960s saw the establishment of a new disciplinary matrix for human
geographers, therefore, with twin concentrations on the spatial organisation of society and human
spatial behaviour. During those decades, and much more so since, particular exemplars have waxed
and waned. They have introduced new methodological procedures and new substantive foci, in part
as reactions to anomalies thrown up within the discipline (the failure of certain normative models,
for example, and the shortcomings of some quantitative procedures) and in part as responses to
trends in society, as illustrated by the many branches and sub-branches of the disciplinary matrix,
reflecting the substantive interests of geographers (urban social, agricultural, etc.) and the technical
arsenal that they deploy. Reviews of American geography have been almost entirely structured
within those systematic specialisms (Gaile and Willmott, 1989, 2004).

The 1970s and 1980s


The spatial-science disciplinary matrix expanded rapidly in the 1960s and early 1970s and in many
departments it was relatively unchallenged until the mid-1970s (Taylor, 1976). Responses to the
output from that disciplinary matrix and to events and issues elsewhere in society then stimulated
two major challenges, contesting not just the exemplars or even the disciplinary matrix, but the
world view implicit in the disciplinary matrix of spatial science.
The first of these challenges – termed humanistic here – was a response both to the nature of
spatial science and to the ideology of society that it reflected. Spatial science is technocratic in its
orientation and application; it tends to reduce people to terms in equations; it thereby ignores their
individuality and freedom of action (Ley, 1981) and ignores the immense variety among places in
favour of a universalistic view of how people think and act. As Trevor Barnes (1996, p. 6ff.) describes
it, spatial-scientists adhered (implicitly in most cases) to the ‘Enlightenment project’ launched in
seventeenth-century Europe (Livingstone and Withers, 1999; Withers, 2007), which emphasised:

1 The notion of progress in the development of scientific understanding, through the application
of the power of reason and the rationality of scientific methods.
2 A belief in autonomous, sovereign, self-consciously directed individuals, so that all are in
essence the same, able to make the same moral and other judgements.
3 A belief that ‘the world had order and humans could find it’ through application of their
rational methods, notably those based on logic and mathematics.
4 An acceptance that there are universal truths, which hold at all times and in all places, and
whose discovery is the goal of all scientific endeavour.

These tenets are questioned by humanistic geographers, whose reading in other social sciences and
philosophy led them to argue for a focus on subjectivity, which was clearly incommensurable with
positivistic spatial science, so that the choice of which to practise was ideological (Johnston,
1986a). According to Barnes (1996, pp. 8–10), they had their own core beliefs (shared with other
counter-Enlightenment scholars) which:

1 Rejected ‘both the epic of progress and the power of rationality and reason’ (p. 8).
2 Contended that individuals are ‘shaped from the outside rather than from the inside’ (p. 9; i.e.
by their context).
A changing discipline? 381

3 Rejected any notions of a ‘monolithic order’.


4 Argued that science advances not through the use of universal constructs but rather through ‘a
set of local social practices of a given time and place’.

Cloke et al. (1991) sustained this case, and criticised spatial science on the grounds that it can
involve treating individuals as members of categories, which they saw as denigrating – at best, it is
only ‘a partial treatment of people’ and at worst it involves their ‘complete neglect’ (p. 67). It treats
them as ‘little more than dots on a map, statistics on a graph or numbers in an equation . . . exercises
. . . that effectively convert . . . human beings into “dehumanised” entities drained of the very
“stuff” (the meanings, values and so on) that made humans into humans as opposed to other
things living or non-living’ (p. 69).
Humanistic geography was introduced as an alternative science of geography, therefore, and
not as a reorientation of the existing way, though some proponents claimed roots in earlier
geographical practices such as those of the French geographer Vidal de la Blache (Buttimer, 1978a).
It had its own disciplinary matrix, and its own variety of exemplars, in terms of both their
philosophy and their subject matter, as set out in Chapter 5. Its introduction did not stimulate a
major switch in the contents of the discipline as a whole, however. Rather, it offered an alternative
conception of human geography and competed (ultimately unsuccessfully) with the others on that
basis.
The second challenge – from radical geography – was also a response to the contents of the
spatial-science disciplinary matrix, but was much more influenced by the wider political conjuncture
than was the humanistic. As detailed in Chapter 6 earlier, those who launched what was initially
known as radical geography were concerned with the failure of positivist spatial science to tackle
and solve pressing societal problems. They advocated applied geography, but defined relevance in a
very different way (Harvey, 1974c; Johnston, 1981a). As with humanistic geography, this involved
promoting a scientific revolution at the level of the world view; the realist science that they advanced
was incommensurable with both positivist and humanistic stances.
Once it was reasonably well established, radical geography also became a kind of disciplinary
matrix; with a variety of exemplars. The core of its programme is the desire to uncover the
mechanisms that drive society, providing accounts of how people act and how the empirical world
is organised. How such understanding can be achieved, and how the knowledge should be used,
has been the subject of much debate – both between Marxists and non-Marxists and among various
types of Marxist – and exemplars have waxed and waned rapidly in recent years as a consequence.
The debates within the realist conception of science are about how to achieve agreed scientific
goals; the debates with positivist and humanistic geographers are about the nature of science. The
former produce internal revolutions; the latter seek to promote major disciplinary revolutions.
(Note, however, Trevor Barnes’s (1996, p. 23) critique of Harvey, the leading advocate of marxism
within geography, and Andrew Sayer, the leading advocate for realism, as both implicit part-
adherents to the Enlightenment project, and hence of the same world view as the spatial-scientists:
‘my argument is that as with Harvey, Sayer totters between Enlightenment and anti-Enlightenment
views’.)
These decades were turbulent for human geography, which Ley (1981) found both exciting
and confusing, in part because of the rapidity with which human geographers explored new ideas.
He believed that such exploration was often superficial, with ideas discarded almost as soon as they
had been adopted: ‘In true North American fashion, obsolescence is setting in more and more
speedily’ (p. 209). Others argued that ideas were often divorced from their original context, and
that geographers who imported them may have been unaware of the controversies surrounding
their use (Agnew and Duncan, 1981; Duncan, 1980; Mohan, 1994). Some sought to reconcile the
various world views (Harrison and Livingstone, 1982; Hay, 1979a; Johnston, 1980b, 1982c;
Livingstone and Harrison, 1981); some argued that is impossible (Eyles and Lee, 1982); and others
382 A changing discipline?

still contended that each of the various world views is informed by the others (e.g. Thrift’s, 1987,
p. 401, claim that Marxist political economy now ‘forms a vital subtext to most theorising’), so that
geographers should use their synthesising powers to integrate the various perspectives (Brookfield,
1989, p. 314).
Whatever the detailed interpretations and attempts to reconcile the competing world views,
the 1980s were characterised by a pluralism that not only challenged the would-be hegemony
of the approaches launched in the 1960s but also presented problems for geographers in presenting
their discipline to others. The intense conflict that these debates engendered is exemplified in a
retrospective essay by Berry (2002c, p. 441). His hope was that:

Urban geography, with a rapidly developing reputation within the social sciences and a penchant
for transdisciplinary inquiry, was to be directed towards and receive its inspiration from a
commitment to help meeting national needs. It was my hope that the challenges of use-oriented
research would stimulate new rounds of theoretical development and leverage the field to new
levels of understanding. I took seriously the notion that geography is the science of which
planning is the art.

But:

By 1980 the excitement had waned, however. The paradigm appeared lost. There was a new
fragmentation as young geographers did what so many have done in earlier epochs of the
discipline’s history – they changed the channel to a different program. The common interest that
seemed to be at hand succumbed to bickering and feuds.

Urban geography – until then in the disciplinary vanguard according to Berry’s view – diverged
along a series of ‘incommensurate paths’ (p. 443) as a result of both internal and external forces.
The latter reflected the sentiments associated with the anti-Vietnam war protests, with many
graduate students mobilised, according to Berry, by ‘left-wing activists’ who turned their anti-
war sentiment into an ‘anti-American anticapitalist radicalism’. Instead of ‘use-inspired basic
research’, these radicals took the stance of the ‘armchair intellectual contrarian’, as exemplified for
him by David Harvey:

There could be no meeting of the minds, no common ground. David disavowed our fumbling
attempts to build a social science, positioning his agenda squarely within the realm of politics
and imprinting in the minds of many young geographers the idea that science is merely one
political viewpoint among many.
(p. 443)

The new generation that followed the radical and humanistic geographers ‘rejected the
Enlightenment ideal of the perfectibility of the human mind – the ideal of an ever-progressing
rationality – devaluing the speaking subject in favor of a highly theoretical linguistic and cultural
determinism’ (p. 444). As a result, Berry shifted away from geography as an institutional base,
while remaining active within his chosen orientation. Twenty years later, he was identifying with ‘a
political economy that we are trying to enrich with an emergent geographic information science
that offers the prospect for new rounds of use-oriented investigation supported by new and more
powerful forms of spatial analysis’. The potential is exciting for him, and ‘once again the social and
environmental sciences are looking to us’, while, however:

There is great promise in the idea of spatially integrated social science, but geography’s
traditional threat, the congenital inability to pull together, remains with us. We should not fritter
A changing discipline? 383

away yet another opportunity because we lack the fortitude to withstand the contrarian responses
of our professional dialecticians.
(p. 444)

For him, at least, the debates of the 1970s and 1980s were not past history: the world view that he
and others pioneered some 50 years previously remains central to their view of the discipline’s
future. For others, the debate seems to have been lost. Looking back at the 1980s, Ford (2002,
p. 438) identified a polarisation of urban geography between ‘social theory and software’ with no
central ground between them: ‘most of the [current] applicants for urban positions are interested
in the city only tangentially, and instead present themselves as experts in aspects of either theory or
technology’.

The 1990s and the turn of the century


The 1990s witnessed yet more turbulence, again reflecting both dissatisfaction with the various
world views and a rapidly changing external environment – economically, socially, politically,
technically and culturally. Within it, the challenge of humanistic geography very substantially
withered, in that very few followed the postulates of idealism, phenomenology and the other
approaches discussed in Chapter 5, although, as stressed in Chapter 6, rejection of the Enlightenment
model of the individual was at the core of the various critiques of Marxism. The ‘new generation’
emphasised difference, although – in part via the ‘cultural turn’ and the influences of feminism and
poststructuralism – in a rather different way from that promulgated by Hartshorne some half a
century earlier (Campbell, 1994). Spatial science did not wither, let alone disappear, however. Its
world view remained strong, although more marginal to the discipline, many of whose members
(in part on political-ideological grounds) rejected not only the implicit positivism but also the
emphasis on technical rigour in data analysis. Some commentators claim otherwise: according to
Hamnett (2003, p. 2), ‘Quantitative techniques and aggregate social research have been largely
abandoned. . . . Analysis of large data sets has become totally passé, the object of suspicion or even
derision as “empiricist”.’ (Similar arguments appear in, inter alia, Cloke et al., 1991, and Peet, 1998;
for responses see Chapter 4, this book; Johnston et al., 2003, 2014a, 2014b; Unwin, 2005.)
By the 1990s, the discipline was substantially fragmented, not only in its world view and
disciplinary matrices but also in its substantive concerns. It comprised a variety of approaches held
together as much by the realpolitik of university politics and funding as by any adherence to core
beliefs, with relatively few of its practitioners interacting across subdisciplinary frontiers (Johnston,
1991, 1996b). This view was challenged by Gould (1994, p. 194): ‘I find the idea of fragmentation
absurd, and too frequently raised by people who long for others to conform to their monolithic
ideological positions.’ He argued that geographers with different specialist interests (as reflected,
for example, by their affiliations to institutional study groups) nevertheless are following his advice
of ‘don’t specialize . . . read eclectically’ and:

Despite some contrary opinion, [there] is no evidence that they are disconnecting from the rich
body of ideas that constitute the geographic ‘way of looking’ today. For their research, they may
be using remotely sensed images, geographic information systems, structural-Marxist concepts,
hydrological science, socially constructed ideas of the environment, Michel Foucault and the
power of surveillance, deconstructions of official government reports, goal programming, a
heightened awareness of gender issues . . . I mean, you name it! . . . to illuminate the spatio-
temporal human condition at a place . . . embedded in a larger regional and national space. With
all that conceptual and methodological integration, where, literally on earth, is the fragmentation?

Others were much more concerned about fragmentation, however. When the AAG Council
decided to initiate a follow-up volume to that edited by James and Jones (1954) thirty years earlier,
384 A changing discipline?

it rejected a proposal from Gaile and Willmott (subsequently published independently: Gaile and
Willmott, 1989) because it drew largely on the AAG’s specialty groups and so reflected a fragmented
view of the discipline rather than focus on ‘cross-cutting and unifying concepts and methods’
(Abler et al., 1992a, p. xvii). The book which they edited for the AAG (Geography’s Inner Worlds:
Pervasive themes in contemporary American geography) had four main sections:

1 What geography is about – geography’s worlds, places and regions, representations of the
world.
2 What geographers do – observation, analysis, modelling, communication.
3 How geographers think – location, place, region and space, movements, cycles and systems,
the local–global continuum, scale in space and time.
4 Why geographers think that way – paradigms for enquiry?, humanism and science in
geography, applications of geographic concepts and methods, the peopling of American
geography.

This was done to counter the perceived fragmentation (Abler et al., 1992b, p. 2):

Specialization and specialty groups foster better communication in a multi-faceted discipline.


They permit scholars and practitioners with common interests to achieve identity without
forming independent associations . . . [but they also] foster intellectual isolation by retarding the
cross-fertilization that occurs when geographers encounter unexpected ideas. Despite the fact
that the fission evident within geography is common in the physical and social sciences,
specialization may have gone as far as it can or should go in American geography.

Hence their book was structured to bring geographers together:

to highlight the common elements within a discipline whose practitioners are in danger of
forgetting their shared heritage and ideals. In their preoccupation with the great diversity of
geographic problems with which they deal on a day to day basis, geographers are prone to
overlook how much they share emotionally and intellectually with other geographers that they
do not share with colleagues in other disciplines.

A few of the chapters are multi-authored, presumably as a way of bringing individuals with
diverse interests together to identify common elements, and the outcome led the editors to
conclude that the discipline is shown to be ‘simultaneously less fragmented than we had feared it
would be and less coherent than we had hoped’ (Abler et al., 1992c, p. 391), but nevertheless
‘wonderfully diverse in substance, method and philosophy’:

Compared with other disciplines, geography has always been tolerant of variety, and often
enthusiastic about multiplicity. With the possible exception of the period before 1920 when
environmental determinism achieved a measure of intellectual hegemony, American geography
has never been a normal, paradigmatic science of the kind postulated by Thomas Kuhn.
(p. 395)

Thus, although concerned about fragmentation they also promote it as a ‘geographical good
thing’:

American geography was postmodern long before the term was invented. It has historically been
eclectic and self-contradictory in many respects. It has often playfully delighted in juxtaposing
dissonant substantive interests and intellectual traditions. American geography will prosper in
A changing discipline? 385

the 1990s not so much because geography will change radically, but rather because the
discipline’s social and intellectual environments have now evolved to where geography has
long been. Geographers are at last professing and practicing a postmodern discipline in a
postmodern age.

Nevertheless, if geography is to prosper, the basis for coherence (necessary in a post-modern


discipline?) has to be realised, which they argued involves: overcoming the indifference to physical
geography among some human geographers; finding ‘the language and narrative forms that will
engage the attention of American society’ (p. 398); and ensuring mutual recognition between the
two main ‘camps’ within human geography – termed spatial scientists and social theorists elsewhere
in this chapter (‘The critical matter is that all parties avoid the whole-sale rejection of each others’
viewpoints that occurred in geography after 1920 and again after 1955’; p. 400).
A few years later, members of the Association returned to the general issue in a forum held at
its Centennial Conference on ‘Where we have come from and where we are going’. In his
introduction, the then president noted that for all the apparent successes of the preceding hundred
years (Murphy, 2004):

The challenge of expanding geographic understanding is as pressing as ever, geographical


research remains marginal to the larger research enterprise, and the study of geography is still
largely absent from many schools, colleges and universities across the United States.
(p. 701)

The collected essays cover a wide range of topics and agendas for geography’s future practices, but
with the general case, as expressed by Hanson (2004, p. 715) that ‘the research questions we ask
should serve society, a society that is richly diverse’. Reflecting contemporary societal concerns,
therefore, much of the discussion focused on environmental challenges and research that bridges
the human and physical sciences (a characteristic also of the NAS-NRC, 2001, review a few years
later). For Kwan (2004, p. 759) this required a ‘post-social-theory, post-spatial analysis future’
which finds ‘ways to make geography a respectable discipline and to enhance its status without
erasing difference within the discipline’. Like many before her (surveyed in Matthews and Herbert,
2004), she sought a more unified discipline (especially in its public face), when all the evidence of
debates within it over the preceding decades suggested the near-impossibility of its achievement.
Several of the authors, too, sought a future in which geography/geographers made an impact but
Don Mitchell (2004, p. 766, following Eliot Hurst, 1985) argued that geographers should not
collaborate ‘with the manifest injustice that makes our wealth, our relative peace, and our relative
good health possible . . . a world and geography in which others have the chance to have what we
have’. Instead:

I say we resist. I say we turn the age of extremes into the age of emancipation, that we turn the
geography of violence and oppression into the geography of justice . . . [using our] limited power
. . . to develop and promote a liberal and liberating education (for all).

As suggested in the previous chapter, it is hard to merge such differing views of what an ‘applied-
applicable’ geography might be.
A second feature of the contemporary world, which is particular to academic life in many of
its aspects yet at the same time linked to changes in the wider milieux, relates to the contexts within
which universities operate. Since the 1980s, as illustrated earlier with regard to the pressures for
applied work and skills-based training (see Chapter 9), universities have come under increasing
pressure to adopt a range of business-like practices and to be accountable for their activities,
including research. This has stimulated what has been termed an ‘audit and accountability culture’
386 A changing discipline?

and a ‘quality industry’ in the UK (Johnston, 1994b), and many have claimed that it has redirected
research (some would say skewed it) in particular directions.
Luke (2000, p. 216) referred to many aspects of this restructuring of the academic milieu in
the USA as a ‘discipline of reputational development’. Within academic networks power is exercised
to ensure conformity to both general academic and specific disciplinary norms, and access to
positions of power and influence is in general restricted to those who conform and win reputation
points as a consequence. (It may also, it is suggested, require conformity in the way that academics
write: Dewsbury, 2014; Badley, 2015.). Thus:

Academic life is an existence pegged to perpetual examinations: seminar discussions,


research papers, dissertation defenses, conference papers, journal submissions, book contracts,
teaching evaluations, committee assignments, tenure hearings, academic promotions,
annual reports . . . these facts about the routines of continual judgment in the disciplinary
operations of the discipline [are] . . . those necessities that ‘constitute a recurrent aspect of
academic life’.
(p. 216)

As we noted in Chapter 1, academic life is a chosen career, and those involved want to get their
share of its rewards, which involves facing up to the continual judgements posed by the ‘perpetual
examinations’ – and to a considerable extent this means conformity, since the allocation of those
rewards is very largely in the hands of others.
Such conformity operates at two levels. At the first it operates within the discipline – or at
least a significant section of it. As Luke expresses it, professional training and acculturation from
graduate school onwards inculcates norms of conformity: each discipline is a ‘powerful regime of
normalizing thoughts and behaviors’ which is ‘intent on creating the correctly disciplined disciple
of its knowledge via personal surveillance and methodological instruction’ (p. 217). This, among
other things, involves a great deal of ranking, of both individuals and departments, according to
their reputations:

The professionally correct gauge the value and position of individual persons and departments,
willingly and openly, as ‘names’. One is ‘a big name’, ‘a name’, or ‘a no-name’. . . . Reputation
and its development in rankings, therefore, boil down, first, to building one’s meganymic profile,
and, second, avoiding anymic obscurity or micronymic ineffectuality.

For Luke, this building a reputation for oneself – and the building of a collective departmental
reputation based on those of its individual members – is not a function of what one studies
(of disciplinary substance) but simply of successful performance on the key reputational indicators,
which may be grant/contract income obtained, for example, or publications in certain journals, or
citations to one’s published work. To some extent, even, an individual’s scholarly reputation is a
function of the university and/or department that he/she works in:

Who gets what, where, when, and why in university departments, professional associations
and grant competitions depends on these ranking systems of invidiously ranked dis-
tinction. While the intrinsic worth of any widely sought after rewards – pay raises, tenure,
promotion, corner offices, or administrative powers – are declining, the battle for them con-
tinues at full tilt. And, the strategies for winning success or evading failure totally
are denominated in these codes of professional correctness: the normalizing judgment of
superiors, peers, and inferiors iterate their evaluations in matrices or performative success
and failure.
(p. 218)
A changing discipline? 387

This, in turn, influences the content of the discipline, at least in the short term, since the
works of those who win in the ranking contests are presumably considered as providing the best
exemplars to follow by those still seeking reputational preferment (unless they perceive that
greater renown as likely to result from successfully challenging the conventional wisdom and
power bases). Thus, a discipline is divided into a range of subcommunities, each of which has its
‘meganyms’ whose ideas and opinions have a substantial impact on not only the allocation of
rewards and resources (leading to claims of overweening power in some instances (Short, 2002)),
but also what is considered good and bad practice within that community.
Many of Luke’s claims relate to the internal operations of disciplines and subdisciplines but
increasingly, as we have already suggested, those operations are subject to external audit and
constraint. This is especially marked in the UK, where reputational rankings of departments
(and therefore, at least implicitly, of their members) is the basis for the allocation of large sums of
public money, especially with regard to research; teaching quality is also evaluated but the results
are not used in selective disbursements. Although these judgements are made by peer review
procedures involving academics (mainly ‘meganyms’ (Short, 2002)) evaluating each other, they are
constructed to meet political agenda regarding accountability and self-reliance (through the
attraction of external support for research work, including contracts for applied work for public
and private sector contractors). Thus they are informed, at least, by reputational metrics such as
income earned and citations to papers published, and the quality of research publications is to some
extent conditioned by the standing of the journals in which they appear.

The first decades of a new century


The most recent decade in human geography’s intellectual history has been one of considerable
contrasts between the earlier and later years. Until 2007, most anglophone universities in general
and research in particular blossomed in a relatively benign economic context, albeit one where
neoliberalism was increasingly hegemonic. With some exceptions, university geography depart-
ments were able to expand – both their staff and their research students – and grants were available
to take a wide range of work forward. By the decade’s end, however, financial crisis and political
shifts saw major changes in higher education and research expenditure, such as the much higher
fees that were to be charged by English universities from 2012 and the likelihood of students gra-
duating with both large debts and encountering very tight labour markets. For those finishing
postgraduate studies and seeking a first university appointment as an academic geographer, pro-
spects were often bleak, especially for those whose skills and training did not give them technical
(read potentially applied) expertise (Gillen, 2015). A decade before, a UK-based survey of ‘The
future for new geographers’ (Shelton, 2005) had been more upbeat, notwithstanding a concern
about the proliferation of fixed-term academic jobs.
In times of relative abundance the contest for resources within universities and their
departments is less, and the potential for conflict smaller, than when opportunities are few. If
expansion is feasible, then it is possible for all types of geographical practices to gain new resources
and for the discipline’s breadth to flourish. If the various practices are acceptable (Johnston, 2006),
it illustrates how during this decade some textbook writers/editors, like their 1960s predecessors,
excluded certain practices using the strategies identified on p. 24, this book). Given the imperative
of the previous decade for university departments, especially the larger ones (more characteristic of
the UK than the USA), to specialise in particular research themes in order to enhance their ‘research
ratings’, potential conflict over which types of geography should be preferred in which places was
less than might otherwise have been the case; departments became more specialised and few
offered a full range of research opportunities within the discipline (or even a full range of advanced
courses in their undergraduate, let alone graduate programmes). The landscape of geography had
become much more varied, and the first years of the twenty-first century fully illustrated that.
388 A changing discipline?

As a consequence, although major differences at the scale of both the world view and the
disciplinary matrix were clearly present, there was little overt conflict between adherents of – as
some simplified the situation (Sheppard, 1995, Kwan, 2004) – spatial analysis and social theory
approaches. Revolution was not in the air and relative peaceful co-existence was generally possible
(There were exceptions, such as the brief and relatively mild ‘spat’ initiated by Hamnett, 2003.)
Thus, human geography throughout the decade was characterised by a wide range of communities
and networks of scholars – some much more closely knit than others – each of which took forward
its own research practices.Those communities had their own journals, conferences (and conferences
within the big conferences) and interaction between them was relatively slight. There were debates
within many of them – at the level of the exemplar (such as that within one of the ‘spatial analysis’
communities on the measurement of segregation: Johnston et al., 2010) – but these were relatively
low-key and had little impact beyond those involved. And they sometimes change what they study
as well as how. In the 1950s–1970s, for example, spatial analysts were much influenced by central
place theory and spent a great deal of energy seeking a particular form of (hierarchical) spatial
order. That model’s underlying assumptions have much less contemporary purchase, so there are
few studies of shopping centres and their organisational matrices (though see Ó hUallacháin and
Leslie, 2013); order is sought in other contexts, as in work that incorporates ideas taken (at least
implicitly) from structuration theory which relate how people behave to their local contexts, and
in turn how their behaviour changes those contexts and how others then behave.
Despite this generally optimistic situation there were concerns, many of them linked to the
interactions between the discipline and wider society, and especially the latter’s expectations of
academics. In the USA, for example, the continued concern about geography’s place in its educational
and research institutions and its wider status within academia stimulated debates regarding
disciplinary futures (as at the AAG’s centennial conference: Murphy, 2004) and the commissioning
of a further report promoting the role of the spatial sciences generally and geography in particular
(NRC, 2011; see also Cutter et al., 2003). In the UK, the continued stress on research assessment
(and the associated league tables – not an exercise confined to the UK – Castree et al., 2006; Cupples
and Pawson, 2012; Liu and Zhan, 2012) raised concerns that certain types of work would be
privileged over others, especially when the terms of the next national exercise (the 2014 Research
Excellence Framework) was to involve assessments of not only the quality of published work and
the local intellectual environment, but also the relative importance to be placed on evaluations of
the demonstrated impact of research on society, especially on the economy in general and ‘wealth
creation’ in particular. This was seen to privilege particular types of research practice, a fear
exacerbated by public money being directed towards some (notably ‘spatial analysis’; the ESRC
launched a number of programmes to enhance training and research in quantitative analysis, for
example, and it was a condition of the British Academy’s public sector settlement in 2011 that it
devote significant parts of that resource to numeracy).
One of the significant features of these years – and to a slightly lesser extent of the 1990s too
– is that there has been much less debate in the discipline’s journals regarding its nature.
Contemporary human geography is well described by Cresswell’s representation of it (quoted at the
start of this chapter) as a series of linked intellectual worlds between which there is relatively little
contact, with mutual tolerance but also misunderstanding and sometimes misrepresentation – to
some extent paralleling Rusu’s (2012) characterisation of contemporary sociology and
misrepresentations (on which, see Johnston et al., 2014a, 2014b). The reason for this change –
which is a major contrast to the debates of the 1950s–1980s – perhaps reflects the volumetric
expansion of geography since the Second World War. A relatively small discipline could readily be
dominated by a small number of gatekeepers, so those who wanted change had to displace them in
order to promote their alternative view of the discipline – which is certainly what was attempted
in the so-called ‘theoretical and quantitative revolutions’. That is much less feasible in a much larger
discipline, and though there is competition for resources within it, attempts to reconfigure the
A changing discipline? 389

entire discipline are unlikely. Cases are made for changes in practices – as described in the later
chapters of this book – but, save at the exemplar level in Kuhn’s hierarchy of paradigms, these rarely
involve attacks on other types of work. This fragmentation of a large discipline into many relatively
isolated intellectual villages – a number of them co-existing with the same university departments
– probably also links to Cresswell’s other representation of contemporary geography – a lack of
contact with disciplinary history; so much contemporary geography has few, if any, roots in
geography as practised no more than a few decades ago. This is undoubtedly linked to the absence
of a ‘geographical canon’, key writings to which practitioners return and students are directed as
core to the discipline’s development (on which see the forum essays convened by Keighren et al.,
2012, and a second set in the Journal of Historical Geography (Powell, 2015)); human geography is
perhaps held together not by its key texts but rather by its key concepts (Johnston and Sidaway,
2015; Agnew, 2014). Geography was a vibrant discipline for several decades; it is now a congeries
of vibrant, many of them sustainable, subdisciplines. The attempted ‘revolution’ of the early post-
Second World War decades, as both Peet (1998) and Kevin Cox (2014) stated: introduced the
importance of explicitly addressing and developing theory; stressed the need for methodological
rigour; and focused geographers’ attention on space – but to many who succeeded the ‘quantifiers’,
they introduced the wrong theory, the wrong methods and a narrow conception of space. With the
core concepts – identified by some as place, space and environment – these imperatives are at the
core of the wide diversity of geographical practices and scholarship.

An abundance of turbulence
Evaluating these turbulent years, when the turbulence shows little sign of abating, is not easy.
Kuhn’s model, sometimes presented to geographers as periods of normal scientific progress
punctuated by major revolutions, is not sufficient to account for what has happened within their
discipline since 1945. But each of the basic Kuhnian definitions of a paradigm (world view,
disciplinary matrix and exemplar) is relevant to appreciating what has occurred and is occurring
within geography, as Mair (1986) argued for the concept of the paradigm as a scientific community
(or disciplinary matrix) with shared values.
At the lowest definitional level of a paradigm, the exemplar, human geographers socialised
within any of the available disciplinary matrices have shifted the orientation of their work as ‘better’
ways have been suggested to them and different topics have come to the foreground; minor
revolutions have occurred – frequently. Such shifts have gone in a variety of directions, presenting
an apparent anarchy – not chaos, which is the vernacular use of that term, but ‘free and voluntary
cooperation of individuals and groups’ (Labedz, 1977, p. 22). But the core values hold.
There is also some evidence of the relevance of the largest scale definition of a paradigm, the
world view, to changes in human geography. Very different and incommensurable conceptions of
the nature of science have competed for geographers’ attention. They differ in their scientific and
their societal goals, and demand choice. Some made a very clear choice, switching from one
conception of science to another because, as Harvey (1973, p. 17) expressed it with regard to
Marxism: ‘I can find no other way of accomplishing what I set out to do or of understanding what
has to be understood’: thirty years later, he noted: ‘now, when the [Marxist] text is so pertinent,
scarcely anyone cares to consider it’ (Harvey, 2000, p. 8).
Some argued that the choice is really between two world views only (spatial science and social
theory (Sheppard, 1995)); others identified three and, according to James Duncan and Trevor
Barnes (1993, p. 248), one of them triumphed:

R. J. Johnston’s Geography and Geographers Since 1945 [sic] . . . could have been subtitled
‘Modernism and its Discontents’. For its narrative structure is compellingly organized around
the contest for intellectual supremacy among the triad of approaches: empiricist, positivist and
390 A changing discipline?

modernist social theory. Although from Johnston’s perspectives the social theorists win the day,
and the others are relegated to the dustbin of geographical history, it is only modernism that
really triumphed, because it is the only game in town.

Each of those positions, they contend, seeks to provide the ‘one best method to explain
geographical phenomena’ and ‘None has seriously entertained the notion that there is no best
method’ (p. 249). The differences among the three approaches are, they claim, ‘relatively minor
when compared to their shared assumptions’, and they fear that the most radical aspects of
postmodern epistemology have been rejected by geographers who ‘wish to incorporate certain of
its important insights into a reconstructed modernist [i.e. Enlightenment] project’. If the
postmodern project was fully embraced, they argue, the discipline would become much more
varied since it would no longer be characterised by the views of ‘trained academics’:

The problem lies in our conceptualization of difference. Difference for geographers is other
spaces, other places, other regions or other landscapes. To embrace difference is in Gregory’s
. . . words to embrace ‘areal differentiation’. It is instructive, however, to compare the
postmodernist geographers’ conception of difference to that of postmodernist ethnographers.
For the latter, difference is other people and, to be more precise, other peoples’ voices. Their
plea is for an end to monovocality and authorial authority. Let us hear direct, they say, from those
from whom we as academics have for so long spoken.
(p. 253)

Such a shift in the nature of geography was politically threatening because of its challenge to the
academics’ authority. Furthermore:

Multivocality (taking others’ voices seriously) is not something that can be easily accomplished
in geography, for we have no tradition of ethnography. Unless we begin to focus more of our
energies on developing our techniques for listening to others our calls for difference are highly
suspect, for we will continue systematically to silence difference. Those outside the academy
have no voice in our work other than the one we choose to give them . . . to speak for another is
not a politically innocent act. We have appropriated their voice – colonized their perspective.

Buttimer (1993, p. 23), drawing on Stephen C. Pepper (1942), identified four ‘root metaphors’
or world views underpinning the practice of geography, each of which ‘projects a distinct
interpretation of reality’:

1 the world as a mosaic of patterns and forms, which she sees as the ‘central root metaphor for
geography’s chorological tradition, the most practiced of all four’ (p. 22);
2 the world as a mechanism of causally integrated interacting systems;
3 the world as an organism, as a whole which comprises unity in diversity; and
4 the world as arena, as the context within which ‘spontaneous and poss­ibly unique events may
occur’.

[To which could be added a fifth:]

5 the world as text, as the landscape is a means of understanding its creators’ intentions and
cultures (an activity also associated with both archaeology and, in different ways, some forms
of theology).

Buttimer did not present her four as exclusive, nor are they treated as such: ‘Most creative scholars
. . . avail themselves of more than one root metaphor in the course of a career. Only the rare
A changing discipline? 391

dogmatist clings to one throughout.’ Nevertheless, she sees them as ‘vectors of distinct thought
styles whose appeal has varied through different moments in Western social history’ (p. 24). Which
styles are dominant when depends on the interaction of people and context:

Acceptance or rejection of a particular paradigm, model, or method within the discipline of


geography has as much to do with the aesthetic, emotional or moral connotations of a root
metaphor as it does with purely epistemological reasoning. The succession of metaphors within
any tradition raises questions about the interplay of internal and external circumstances. Career
stories of geographers reveal important clues about their succession and relative appeal. At any
moment of disciplinary history, all four root metaphors . . . may be simultaneously co-present,
although one or more may appear dominant within particular periods.

Her descriptions of the metaphors, based to a considerable extent on autobiographical data, do


not lead to a detailed appreciation of why one or more has been more visible in some periods than
others. Instead, she identifies a major tension between, on the one hand, ‘the integrated approaches
of organism and mechanism [which] have invited research of wider scale and have apparently
enhanced the status of geography within the academy’ which is desirable given ‘the political
expediency of the times’ and the ‘political economy of research grantsmanship’, and, on the other,
‘The dispersed approaches of mosaic and arena [to which we can add text] have yielded more
sensitive accounts of life and landscape at local and regional scales of inquiry’ (p. 212). Her own
preference is clearly for the latter pairing, for ‘the humanist’s emancipatory hope’ and ‘communication
and understanding’ (p. 219). Humanism must be ‘the leaven in the dough and not a separate loaf
in the smorgasbord of geographic endeavor’ (p. 220); but she does not seek to impose (p. 212):

The integrity of disciplinary practice . . . demands a flexibility to changing educational needs and
to new substantive research challenges. Ideally each individual, department or research team,
given its resources, aims and context, should assume responsibility for designing and adapting
its agenda to such changing demands.

Each world view’s disciplinary matrices identify the framework within which research is conducted.
The shift from regionalism to spatial science involved a change of disciplinary matrix, from mosaic
to machine, for example; while the world view remained constant – that of positivist science with
its foundation in empiricism (although it was hidden until relatively late in the shift) – the shared
goals altered very considerably. The relative popularity of Marxism, realism, structuration and
postmodernism at different times reflects changes in the disciplinary matrix of the ‘geography as
social theory’ world view.
Peet (1998) also mapped some of these trends – and earlier ‘schools of geographical thought’–
as a set of movements, flows and channels in ‘disciplinary space’ (see Figure 10.2). Though Peet
indicates some self-consciousness at such a bold and clear sketch of geography:

Theoretical organizational devices are political tools of power formation. So the map may give a
‘bird’s-eye’ view but the bird is an eagle, symbol of the state, and soaring on high, rather than a
working sparrow pecking up the crumbs of its localized existence.
(p. 10)

A decade later, Chris Philo (2008, p. xxi) commented how Peet’s map ‘has a nicely ‘organic’ feel
suggestive of a braiding river with meanders and eddies devoid of any one main channel’. Some
might prefer to visualise disciplinary nodes and networks, but the appeal of such geo-fluvial
metaphors is strong. Gerike (2012, p. 11) talks about geographical scholarship as a ‘braided’
stream that today ‘reflects changing, braided channels and the merger of rivers of theory and
392 A changing discipline?

(Berkeley school)

Regional geography
Regional science

Quantitative-spatial geography

Radical-Marxist geography

D==iiem-structuration-locaiK)f

Feminist geography

1850 1900 1930 1950 1970 1990 2000

Figure 10.2  Schools of modern and postmodern thought

Source: Peet, 1998, p. 10.

perspective from other ontological and epistemological river systems’. And Janice Monk (2015,
p. 272) says when:

Searching for a geographic metaphor that would capture over four decades of research, writing,
and professional engagement in geography, I settled on ‘braided streams.’ This fluvial form is
characterized by divergent and convergent channels, mostly occurring ‘where there are almost
no lateral confining banks’.

Philo (2008), however, draws another map (see Figure 10.3), while recognising that any such
map would really need to be three-dimensional:

Permitting us to see that, even after their eras of greatest popularity, most approaches have
continued as a presence ‘behind the scenes’, adding to the general intellectual background out
of which subsequently more prominent approaches have emerged, whether as outgrowth or
opponent, and occasionally returning to positions of enhanced recognition. Three dimensionality
would also allow us to discern how some approaches presently sited some distance apart on
the diagram have in actuality ended up ‘folding’ together; and I am particularly aware of how
feminist geography, while emerging on the ‘structure’ side of the map, has reached over in
various ways to parts of the humanistic, cultural and psychoanalytic features drawn on the
‘agency’ side of the map.
(p. xii)
393

towards social structure' towards ‘human agency’


(& other kinds of structure] & voluntarism
& determinism
CONCEPTUAL SPACE
1800
KEY

antecedents
can be found

approach continues
to be followed/
ANARCHIST exert influence
GEOGRAPH\ GISc geographical
information science

1900 ENVIRONMENTAL REGIONAL


ANT actor-network theory

NRT non-representational
DETERMINISM GEOGRAPHY
theory
(areal differentiation]
SSSKT social studies of
scientific knowledge
& technology
1950

SPATIAL SCIENCE
(locational analysis; scientific
1960 decisive
method; quantitative
breaks
revolution; postivism)

1970 GISc
etc,

MARXIST HUMANISTIC
GEOGRAPHY GEOGRAPHIES
(socio-spatial inequality; (senses of place;
radical geography; phenomenology;
historical materialism; existentialism;
1980
dialectics] STRUCTURATION 1ST pragmatism)
GEOGRAPHIES
FEMINIST (& versions
GEOGRAPHIES of realism)
(geographies of
women; gender
division of space; POST
critique of MODERNIST
masculinism) GEOGRAPHIES

1990 POST­
COLONIAL POSTHUMAN ISTIC
GEOGRAPHIES GEOGRAPHIES
POSTSTRUCTURALIST
(black geog­ (nature-human
GEOGRAPHIES
raphies; symmetries';
(multiplicity;
‘imaginative return of
heterogeneity;
geographies') 'biology';
conjuctions
NETWORK practice-based
of anonymous'
& CYBER­ geograph ies/NRT;
forces;
GEOGRAPHIES psychoanalytic
discourse & power)
(biosocio­ geographies)
QUEER ! technologies;
200C SSSKT)
GEOGRAPHIES!"

FEM.
3E0G.

Figure 10.3  Disciplinary space: the ‘map’ of changing approaches in human geography

Source: Philo, 2008, p. xxi.


394 A changing discipline?

He recognises too that extensive reading and toil are needed to make sense of ‘the chaos
and fuss integral to being “down there” working with the depicted approaches on a daily basis’
(p. xxiii).
A relatively rare attempt to (re)narrate the history of geography from such other ‘down there’
viewpoints – drawing upon a departmental geographical magazine produced by students at the
University of Glasgow – was also produced by Philo (1998). He notes that:

little appears to have been said about how academic visions of geography have been received by
the countless students who filter through ‘our’ lecture theatres, tutorial rooms and libraries. It
seems to me that this is an omission of some magnitude, and that therefore more might be done
to ascertain how all manner of shifts in academic geography, as fostered by small numbers of
‘visible’ professional geographers translate into the thinking, writing, fieldworking and
murmurings of the many ‘invisible’ student geographers whose responses are almost never
afforded sympathetic scrutiny.
(p. 345)

Lorimer and Spedding (2002) also stress the wealth, complexity, and value of depart-
mental histories, reconstructing something of the contextual histories of geography – as
practised by staff and students – at another Scottish department (Aberdeen: see also Findlay
and Werritty, 2010, on Dundee), and Withers (2002, p. 306) has pursued a similar task at
Edinburgh:

kindled by hearing stories from older colleagues . . . [and] motivated by the ‘discovery’ at one
time and another of large amounts of textual material relating to an earlier department:
students’ work, personal papers of former staff, photographs, examination papers and old glass
slides. I say ‘discovery’ for a reason: colleagues in my department knew of its existence, but not
until an interest was expressed in ‘that old stuff’ was any value attached to it as a nascent
department archive.

Either way, human geography has long been characterised by a multiparadigm situation
at the world-view level, by competition between disciplinary matrices within at least two of
those world views, and by a wealth of exemplars on which research is based in all three (all
features that appear consistent with Feyerabend’s notion of progress). It is because of the last
element, and because many human geographers have not been deeply schooled into any one
disciplinary matrix, let alone the use of any one exemplar, that the discipline appears replete with
fickle allegiances, as individuals explore various ways of practising geography (Johnston, 1981b,
pp. 313–14):

Much geographical work is exploratory, and is conducted by individuals who operate


independently. Indeed, many, although influenced by what they read, are in no sense socialized
into a particular matrix or set of exemplars which might be associated with a ‘research school’
and its leader. The charisma of certain individuals and their published works may occasionally
produce the prophet and disciple situation. Much more usual, however, is a situation of fickle
allegiances.

Such fickleness suggests anarchy, in the sense used by Feyerabend (1975; Johnston, 1976c, 1978a).
Some human geographers shift frequently among exemplars, sometimes between disciplinary
matrices, and just occasionally between world views. And some, as part of a refutation of Kuhn,
have proposed explicitly hybrid geographies that value differences and diversity within the
discipline, calling for:
A changing discipline? 395

the proliferation of hybrids, or geographies and geographers of the third kind; those that cut
across the divides between the social-cultural and the spatial-analytical, the qualitative and the
quantitative, the critical and the technical, and the social-scientific and the arts-and-humanities.
It is a future not of ‘either/or’ but of ‘both-and’ . . .
(Kwan, 2004, p. 760)

The last six decades have seen individual human geographers occasionally promoting a
particular paradigm (world view, disciplinary matrix or exemplar) in opposition to prevailing
practice. That has rarely been done in isolation; contacts with others or reading (or both) suggest
the argument, and support is then sought within the discipline, and perhaps resources and
sponsorship from within society too. Why are some people better able to promote paradigm
change than others? Little work has been done on such aspects of the sociology of geography as a
discipline, especially with regard to power over the acceptance/rejection of proposed paradigm
shifts and the ability to convince others of the ‘rightness’ of any approach. Studies have also been
undertaken on influential figures in the discipline’s early development (e.g. in Blouet, 1981, and
Smith, 2003) and, as we noted in the Preface, there is a wealth of information and reflection on
these themes recorded in the 552 ‘Geographers on film’ interviews assembled by Maynard
Western Dow, although the process of digitising and making these readily available is incomplete
(Martin, 2013). In more conventional written format, a ‘biobibliography’ series was initiated in
1977 (Armstrong and Martin, 2000). This has now published over 400 biobibliographical essays,
forming, in the words of the editors of a recent volume:

an ongoing critical enquiry into the lives and works of persons who have contributed to what, at
various times and places, has been taken to be geographical knowledge . . . a scholarly site in
which to raise questions about what it means to do geography, then and now, and to think about
it biographically.
(Lorimer and Withers, 2007, p. 4)

The nature of academic geography in the UK has also been explored in sociological and
historical studies (Johnston and Brack, 1983; Sidaway, 1997), but aside from the survey by Tim Hall
(2014) these dynamics have not been the subject of further detailed analysis in more recent years
(notwithstanding reflections on impact agendas, and audits of research ‘excellence’ in the UK
referenced in earlier chapters). Nor, interestingly, has the impact of the ‘commercialisation of
knowledge’ by publishing houses been much scrutinised (though the issues were flagged in Barnett
and Low, 1996). The increased stress on research publications in the UK from the mid-1980s at first
led to problems for textbook publishers (Davey et al., 1995). However, the more recent proliferation
of geographical textbooks, readers, companions and dictionaries that we noted in the Preface
indicates that publishers soon found ways to renew their role and influence. Most scholarly journals
are either owned or produced by commercial publishers too (although their editors are invariably
academics), leading to a growing debate about alternatives to commercial, for-profit publishing in
human geography and other disciplines (Moss et al., 2002).
Meanwhile, within the discipline, analyses of citation patters within such journals were
used:

1 to identify frequently referenced works that can be categorised as exemplars (Whitehand,


1985; Wrigley and Matthews, 1986; Bodman, 1991, 1992; Yeung, 2002);
2 to isolate research communities, groups of scholars who refer to each other’s writings on a
particular topic and so occupy a disciplinary matrix focused on particular exemplars (Gatrell,
1984a, 1984b);
3 to rate journals and chart their interdependence (Whitehand, 1984; Gatrell and Smith, 1984);
396 A changing discipline?

4 to rank departments in the USA and the UK in terms of publications produced, publications
cited and peer evaluation, for example (Morrill, 1980; L. Jones, Lindsey and Coggeshall, 1982;
B. L. Turner and Meyer, 1985, on the USA; on the UK, see Bentham, 1987; D. Smith, 1988b;
Johnston, 2003a);
5 to conduct exploratory studies of particular subdisciplines and the main exemplars which have
stimulated how individuals practise (M. Phillips and Unwin, 1985); and
6 to identify citation patterns across cultural/linguistic divides (Schuermans et al., 2010).

All describe aspects of the discipline’s structure but tell us little of its processes; like spatial science
they provide valuable descriptive data and indicate connections and relations, but not necessarily
much understanding. Whitehand (2002, p. 518–19) admits that:

Citations provide an entrée to a communication network whose understanding is an aspect of the


solution of questions about the geography, history, psychology, demographics, sociology, eco-
nomics, and politics of knowledge – but to understand that network we need to know more about
the environment in which it functions, including the different kinds of intellectual traffic using
the links in the network and the academic life courses of those that generate the traffic.

For that understanding, it is necessary not only to appreciate the contexts in which people
worked but also to realise that those contexts are not straightforwardly determinate. A change in a
country’s economic, social and/or political trajectories will not necessarily bring forth a certain
reaction from geographers; these will be uneven, individuals may respond to their interpretations
of that change, and their responses may stimulate others to follow them. This is the most likely
reason for shifts at the level of the world view and, probably, the disciplinary matrix too, as
exemplified by the introduction of a radical/structuralist world view and by the shift within the
empiricist world view from regionalism to spatial science. But such shifts can stimulate counter-
reactions, as with the advancement of humanistic geography as a response to spatial science; those
promoting the latter cause were influenced both by currents of thinking outwith geography and by
their explorations of World Three. At the level of the exemplar, shifts are most likely to occur as a
response to events within the discipline, as Kuhn suggests; this occurred within the spatial-science
disciplinary matrix with the movement from normative to behavioural analyses, but the later move
towards welfare geography was strongly influenced by external factors.
No simple model can be applied to the changes within human geography to provide an
explanation of why the discipline has altered in the ways described here. Kuhn’s work provides a
valuable vocabulary and organising framework within which to describe the communities, but
what has occurred reflects the perceptions and actions of individual human geographers. Like all
other aspects of society, geography is a discipline created by and for geographers, and is continually
fought over and recreated by them, at a variety of scales and in social, economic and political
contexts that vary over space and through time. The last point is crucial, for – as the structuration
approach stresses – people are socialised in particular contexts and they then create part of the
milieux within which others are socialised; these processes are presented by Bourdieu (1988,
1990) as the construction and evolution of ‘fields’ (see the exegeses by Bassett, 1996, and Painter,
2000) and by Purcell (2003) as ‘islands of practice’. Those places (fields and islands) are not
isolated, and changes in one can influence changes in others. But, as illustrated here, there have
been substantial differences from one place to another within Anglo-American human geography
regarding how the discipline is practised, reflecting both the nature of those places and the
people in them; on the broader international scale, the differences are even greater (Johnston and
Claval, 1984).
What of Kuhn’s model in the context of other frameworks of interpretation that emerged
subsequently? As the number of symposia and other events that occurred to celebrate the fiftieth
A changing discipline? 397

anniversary of the first publication of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) testifies, Kuhn’s ideas
still attract a great deal of attention (Sismondo, 2012) as do other evaluations of his impact
(Machamer and Osbeck, 2003). Few students of the history of science and social science cleave to
his full model of periods of normal science punctuated by revolutions but many identify considerable
value in the sociological approach that he promoted and its emphasis on scientific communities
(Dear, 2012), on paradigms as exemplars that ‘structure the problems, the activities and the material
environments of normal science . . . rather than through rules that guide or dictate science’
(Sismondo, 2012, p. 416; see also Fuller, 2000; Bird, 2003; Delanty, 2003). Such a sociological
approach also characterises Latour’s (1987) Science in Action, published 25 years after Kuhn, which
used a different and broader definition of a community – as an actor network – that Michael Lynch
(2012, pp. 452–3) compares with Kuhn’s disciplinary matrices:

It is not a giant step from Kuhn’s disciplinary matrix to Latour’s actor-network. Both are
heterogeneous, and both fold social, semiotic, and material elements into an overall nexus that
is at once technical and communal . . . both stress that the linkages that integrate and hold
together disciplinary matrices and actor-networks are not limited to semiotic links between
words or citations. The outlines of research ‘communities’ may be indicated by common symbolic
generalizations and citation networks, but the networks are integrated by material practices and
infrastructures. Universities and research institutes provide sites and facilities, but as Latour so
strongly emphasizes, a particular laboratory (or a field station, or some other concentration of
people, instruments, techniques, specimens and archives) is the indispensable ‘passage point’
for specific research ventures.

What Kuhn’s and especially Latour’s sociological approach to scientific communities/networks


makes clear, as Mialet (2012, p. 457) expresses it, is that scientists’ work does not conform to
universal norms or share common presuppositions and paradigms: science is ‘something much
messier, because its practitioners [are] human beings who argue, disagree, misunderstand, ignore,
betray, talk past one another, and sometimes even agree, but who always, and in every eventuality,
talk and write (a lot)’. This messiness has been illustrated by the varying human geographical
practices over the last six decades. Attempts to define those communities and networks precisely
(as in the use of citation analysis (Bodman, 2010)) find it difficult to specify their boundaries.
Although there may be cores defined by their membership – for short periods at least – many
researchers move between them, interact less intensively in some networks at certain periods than
others and may spend considerable periods working largely independently of others (on Les Hepple
as an excellent exemplar of this, see Johnston et al., 2010). Occasionally, a new group may cohere
and not only interact intensively but have a wider impact – drawing others into their orbit; and just
occasionally a group make seek to define the discipline more generally (as illustrated by two groups
of textbooks used – largely by what they exclude – to circumscribe the discipline (Johnston, 2006).
But for most of the time individuals, perhaps with a small number of (and not always the same)
collaborators, take their own ideas forward, publishing them as illustrations of how they are
increasing knowledge in a particular way and context without either explicit preaching of ‘this is
what human geography should be’ or seeking to denigrate other practices. Human geography for
most of the post-1945 period has comprised a fluid structure of ‘micro-worlds’ in which
individuals, in many cases temporarily but in a few permanently, find ‘islands of relative stability’
within which to undertake their own very particular (if not peculiar) practices (Pickering, 2012,
p. 468); only occasionally do iconoclasts and change agents come along who try and establish
‘island empires’, knitting together various communities and networks into some larger, hopefully
coherent whole – often for a political rather than a scientific purpose. For most of the time,
geographers – like most other academics in the social sciences and humanities – practice in
situations of ‘situated messiness’; few regard themselves as permanently located within a
398 A changing discipline?

well-defined ‘community’ but operate, much more actively at some times than others, within
(sometimes minimally) overlapping networks – what Badley (2011a, 2011b, 2015) terms nomadic
fabricators and weavers of stories and texts (see also Hall, 2014).

And the future?


human geography is a profoundly trendy subject, in part because it still tends to import most of
its ideas from outside the discipline. New generations of postgraduates therefore tend, rather
more than in other and larger disciplines, to follow new trends. The discipline is therefore
characterized by generational cycles which leave little room for much work outside the norm.
(Thrift, 2000, p. 692)

In the early 1970s, several leading geographers were asked their views of the discipline’s future
(Chorley, 1973). Little of what they suggested is reflected in what happened; the contents of a
similar book produced twelve years later (Johnston, 1985a) are very different. For J. P. Jones and
Dixon (2004, p. 381) however (in an introduction to a set of essays on ‘what next . . . [for]
geographical theorizing in light of some thirty-plus years of scholarly encounters with critical
social theory’), the answer is:

‘Nothing. We are now repeating ourselves.’ We have come to this position in spite of the fact
that binaries, as socially and relationally constructed, would seem to open up new and dynamic
fields of inquiry. Our view, however, is that the relations among oppositions have long since
been stabilized by the gravitational force field of research practices that hold them
together as systems, and that the form of binary analysis employed in most social theory (that
is, construction ‘deconstruction’ reconstruction) has long since worked its way across the
limited number of possibilities. It is difficult, in the words of the business world, ‘to think
outside the box’.

More recently, however, Gregory and Castree (2012, p. xxv–vi) judged that:

the field of human geography is remarkably fecund. . . . In large part this positive judgement
rests on a rethinking of what we mean by a discipline. An older meaning – inculcation into a
canonical body of knowledge, a sort of academic holy writ, upon which one slowly builds to
become a ‘disciple’ – has given way to a newer meaning: exposure to a variety of knowledges
that share a family resemblance and which provide the means for critical, creative inventions not
mere supplements to the existing stocks of knowledge.

Debates about how geography should be practised and taught and the extent and nature of any
canon have recently resurfaced (Keighren et al., 2012), reflecting not only internal divisions but also
trends in the wider academic milieu and the societies to which human geographers belong. In the
context however of turbulence, university restructurings and uncertainty over funding and
priorities, Richard Powell (2011, p. 2) argues that:

I do not think anyone should go so far as to identify a canon, but should students perhaps be
required to read Mackinder, Isaiah Bowman or Ellen Semple or other geographical thinkers . . .?
Without a sense of these tests, geographers become increasingly divorced from any sense of a
community of practice or, indeed of a shared, contested enterprise.
A changing discipline? 399

In similar terms, John Agnew and David Livingstone (2011, p. 1) note that:

Particularly before the creation of university departments or degree programs in geography, the
label ‘geographer’ or ‘geographical writer’ was not a self-evident one for many who we might
judge today as central figures in the ‘geographical canon’ (e.g. Immanuel Kant or Alexander von
Humboldt). Geography as a discipline is therefore, very largely a retrospectively constituted
tradition. Though there are good grounds for feeling uneasy and self-conscious about the
invention of tradition, we cannot do without a tradition if we are to engage in common dialogue,
avoid historical superficiality, think critically and creatively about the nature of the discipline,
prepare the next generation of students, and ground commitments to our fields of study in
rapidly changing institutional settings. Traditions are inescapable. . . . The issue is to ensure that
they remain vital conversations between past and present . . .

The future contents and contexts of those conversations and other new directions cannot be
readily predicted; one could suggest with some certainty, however, that human geography will not
be characterised by mono-paradigm dominance in the next few decades. The intersections of
generations, ideas, approaches from past and present and the recombinations that have long been
present in the discipline should also make us cautious about predictions. David O’Sullivan (2014,
p. 41) recently argued that ‘It makes sense to think of the quantitative revolution in geography as an
unfinished revolution.’ But we might add that human geography comprises a series of intersecting
partial revolutions that do not readily lend themselves to straightforward explanatory narrative.
Three decades earlier, in the introduction to an autobiographical essay, David Smith (1984, p. 118)
wrote that:

my own professional activities seem to have been a continual struggle to come to terms with (or
keep up with) the rapidly shifting focus of human geography. The struggle arises in large
measure from the difficulty of breaking free from one’s own intellectual heritage. . . . If my own
struggles represent anything more than one half-life experience, it may well be the theme of the
geographer or social scientist as creature of his or her times. . . . If anything is to be learned
from the instant replay of such recent events . . . it is that ‘scientific’ advance is not conducted in
a social vacuum but as an integral part of human history, within which the element of chance
arising from individual personality and creativity plays an important part. So let us proceed with
the recollection of one of the random variables.

We are all random variables, it seems. Robson (1984, p. 104) used a similar turn of phrase:
‘it is clear how small a part in my own development seems to have been played by clearly guided
aims and how much has been contributed by the collage of rather random influences and
serendipitous events to which I both responded and contributed’. Hence our ‘individual’ and
collective projects and life-paths (our ‘geographies’) can be appreciated (perhaps yielding ‘joy’ as
Kearn et al., 2014, see it) and set in context, but no more. We are therefore often uncertain where
we, as individuals, are going, let alone exactly where geography as a set of linked yet frequently
anarchic communities is heading. Yet we are making the future of geography as we practise it, just
as we have been remaking its past by writing this book.
References

Aalbers, M. B. 2004. Creative destruction through the Anglo-American hegemony: A non-Anglo-American


view on publications, referees and language. Area 36, 319–22.
Abler, R. F. 1971. Distance, intercommunications, and geography. Proceedings, Association of American Geographers 3,
1–4.
Abler, R. F. 1993a. Everything in its place: GPS, GIS, and geography in the 1990s. Professional Geographer 45,
131–9.
Abler, R. F. 1993b. Personal perspectives on the fiftieth anniversary of the founding of the ASPG. In
E. W. Miller (ed.) The American Society for Professional Geographers: Papers presented on the occasion of the fiftieth
anniversary of its founding. Washington, DC: Occasional Publication of the Association of American
Geographers.
Abler, R. F., Adams, J. S. and Gould, P. R. 1971. Spatial Organization:The geographer’s view of the world. Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Abler, R. F., Marcus, M. G. and Olson, J. M. 1992a. Preface. In R. F. Abler, M. G. Marcus and J. M. Olson (eds)
Geography’s Inner Worlds: Pervasive themes in contemporary American geography. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University
Press, xv–xx.
Abler, R. F., Marcus, M. G. and Olson, J. M. 1992b. Contemporary American geography. In R. F. Abler, M. G.
Marcus and J. M. Olson (eds) Geography’s Inner Worlds: Pervasive themes in contemporary American geography. New
Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1–8.
Abler, R. F., Marcus, M. G. and Olson, J. M. 1992c. Afterword. In R. F. Abler, M. G. Marcus and J. M. Olson (eds)
Geography’s Inner Worlds: Pervasive themes in contemporary American geography. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University
Press, 391–402.
Abrahamsson, C. and Gren, M. (eds) 2012. GO: On the geographies of Gunnar Olsson. Farnham: Ashgate.
Abrahamson, H. S. 2010. National Geographic: Behind America’s lens on the world, 2nd edn. Bloomington, IN: iUniverse.
Ackerman, E. A. 1945. Geographic training, wartime research, and immediate professional objectives. Annals of
the Association of American Geographers 35, 121–43.
Ackerman, E. A. 1958. Geography as a Fundamental Research Discipline. Chicago: University of Chicago, Department of
Geography Research Paper 53.
Ackerman, E. A. 1963. Where is a research frontier? Annals of the Association of American Geographers 53, 429–40.
Adams, J. S. 1969. Directional bias in intra-urban migration. Economic Geography 45, 302–23.
Adams, J. S. 1972. The geography of riots and civil disorder in the 1960s. Economic Geography 48, 24–42.
Adams, J. S. (ed.) 1976. Urban Policymaking and Metropolitan Dynamics: A comparative geographical analysis. Cambridge, MA:
Ballinger.
Adams, J. S. 1995. Risk. London: Routledge.
Adams, J. S. 2002. The quantitative revolution in urban geography. Urban Geography 22, 530–9.
Adams, P. C. 1995. A reconsideration of personal boundaries in space-time. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 85, 267–85.
Adams, P. C., Hoelscher, S. and Till, K. E. 2001. Place in context: Rethinking humanistic geographies.
In P. C. Adams, S. Hoelscher and K. E. Till (eds) Textures of Place: Exploring humanist geographies. Minneapolis, MN:
University of Minnesota Press, xiii–xxiii.
Adler, S. and Brenner, J. 1992. Gender and space: Lesbians and gay men in the city. International Journal of Urban and
Regional Research 16, 24–34.
Agnew, J. A. 1984. Place and political behaviour: The geography of Scottish nationalism. Political Geography Quarterly
3, 191–202.
References 401

Agnew, J. A. 1987a. The United States in the World-Economy: A regional geography. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Agnew, J. A. 1987b. Place and Politics:The geographical mediation of state and society. Boston, MA: Allen & Unwin.
Agnew, J. A. 1989. The devaluation of place in social science. In J. A. Agnew and J. S. Duncan (eds) The Power of
Place. Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman, 9–29.
Agnew, J. A. 1990. Sameness and difference: Hartshorne’s The Nature of Geography and geography as areal variation.
In J. N. Entrikin and S. D. Brunn (eds) Reflections on Richard Hartshorne’s The Nature of Geography. Washington,
DC: Occasional Publication of the Association of American Geographers, 121–40.
Agnew, J. A. 1993. Representing space: Space, scale and culture in social science. In J. S. Duncan and D. Ley (eds)
Place/Culture/Representation. London: Routledge, 251–71.
Agnew, J. A. 1994. The territorial trap: The geographical assumption of international relations theory. Review of
International Political Economy 1, 53–80.
Agnew, J. A. 1997. Commemoration and criticism: Fifty years after the publication of Harris and Ullman’s ‘The
nature of cities’. Urban Geography 18, 4–6.
Agnew, J. A. 2005. Hegemony:The new shape of global power. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
Agnew, J. A. 2009. Globalization and Sovereignty. Langham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Agnew, J. A. 2014. By words alone shall we know: Is the history of ideas enough to understand the world to
which our concepts refer? Dialogues in Human Geography 4, 311–19.
Agnew, J. A. and Duncan, J. S. 1981. The transfer of ideas into Anglo-American human geography. Progress in
Human Geography 5, 42–57.
Agnew, J. A. and Duncan, J. S. 1989. Introduction. In J. A. Agnew and J. S. Duncan (eds) The Power of Place. Boston,
MA: Unwin Hyman, 1–8.
Agnew, J. A. and Livingstone, D. N. 2011. Introduction. In J. A. Agnew and D. N. Livingstone (eds) The Sage
Handbook of Geographical Knowledge. London, Thousand Oaks, New Delhi and Singapore: Sage, 1–17.
Agnew, J. A., Mitchell, K. and Toal, G. (eds) 2003. A Companion to Political Geography. Oxford: Blackwell.
Aitken, S. C. 1991. A transactional geography of the image-event: The films of Scottish director, Bill Forsyth.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS16, 105–18.
Aitken, S. C. 2001. Geographies of Young People: The morally contested spaces of identity. London and New York:
Routledge.
Aitken, S. C. 2013. Book review: GO: On the geographies of Gunnar Olsson. Edited by Christian Abrahamsson and Martin
Gren. Geographical Review 103, 580–3.
Aitken, S. C., Cutter, S. L., Foote, K. E. and Sell, J. S. 1989. Environmental perception and behavioral geography.
In G. L. Gaile and C. J. Willmott (eds) Geography in America. Columbus, OH: Merrill, 218–38.
Akatiff, C. 1974. The march on the Pentagon. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 64, 26–33.
Alexander, D. 1979. Catastrophic misconception? Area 11, 228–30.
Alexander, J. W. and Zahorchak, G. A. 1943. Population-density maps of the United States: Techniques and
patterns. Geographical Review 33, 457–66.
Alker, H. R. 1969. A typology of ecological fallacies. In M. Dogan and S. Rokkan (eds) Quantitative Ecological Analysis
in the Social Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 69–86.
Allen, C. D. 2011. On actor-network theory and landscape. Area 43, 274-80.
Allen, J. 2003. Lost Geographies of Power. Oxford: Blackwell.
Allen, J., Massey, D. and Cochrane, A. 1998. Rethinking the Region. London: Routledge.
Althusser, L. and Balibar, E. 1970. Reading ‘Capital’. London: New Left Books.
Amedeo, D. and Golledge, R. G. 1975. An Introduction to Scientific Reasoning in Geography. New York: John Wiley.
American Association of Geographers (AAG) 1946. Lessons from the wartime experience for improving
graduate training for geographic research. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 36, 195–214.
Amin, A. (ed.) 1994. Postfordism: A reader. Oxford: Blackwell.
Amin, A. and Robbins, K. 1990. The reemergence of regional economies: The mythical geography of flexible
accumulation. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 8, 7–34.
Amin, A. and Thrift, N. J. 2000. What kind of economic theory for what kind of economic geography? Antipode:
A Radical Journal of Geography 32, 4–9.
Amin, A. and Thrift, N. J. 2002. Cities: Reimagining the urban. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Amin, A. and Thrift, N. J. 2005. Just the future. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 37, 220–38.
Amin, A. and Thrift, N. J. 2013. Arts of the Political: New openings for the Left. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Amin, A., Massey, D. and Thrift, N. J. 2000. Cities for the Many Not the Few. Bristol: Policy Press.
402 References

Anderson, B. 2006. Becoming and being hopeful: Towards a theory of affect. Environment and Planning D: Society and
Space 24, 733–52.
Anderson, B. and Harrison, P. 2006. Questioning affect and emotion. Area 38, 333–5.
Anderson, B. and Harrison, P. 2010. The promise of non-representational theories. In B. Anderson and P.
Harrison (eds) Taking Place: Non-representational theories and geographies. Farnham and Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 1–34.
Anderson, J. 1973. Ideology in geography: An introduction. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 5(3), 1–6.
Anderson, J., Duncan, S. and Hudson, R. 1983. Redundant Spaces in Cities and Regions?: Studies in industrial decline and social
change (special publication series, Institute of British Geographers No. 15). London: Academic Press.
Anderson, K. 1995. Culture and nature at the Adelaide Zoo: At the frontiers of ‘human’ geography. Transactions of
the Institute of British Geographers NS20, 275–94.
Anderson, K., Domosh, M. Pile, S. and Thrift, N. (eds) 2003. The Handbook of Cultural Geography. London, Thousand
Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage.
Anon., 1968. A preliminary contribution to the geographical analysis of a Pooh-scape. IBG Newsletter 6, 54–63.
Anselin, L. 1988. Spatial Econometrics: Methods and models. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Anselin, L. 1995. Local indicators of spatial association – LISA. Geographical Analysis 27, 93–115.
Anselin, L. 1998. Exploratory spatial data analysis in a geocomputational environment. In P. A. Longley,
S. M. Brooks, R. MacDonnell and B. Macmillan (eds) Geocomputation: A primer. Chichester: John Wiley, 77–94.
Anselin, L. 2012. From SpaceStat to CyberGIS: Twenty years of spatial data analysis software. International Regional
Science Review 35, 131–57.
Anselin, L. and Rey, S. (eds) 2010. Perspectives on Spatial Data Analysis. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Anselin, L. and Rey, S. J. 2012. Spatial econometrics in an age of CyberGIScience. International Journal of Geographical
Information Science 26, 2211–26.
Anselin, L., Florax, R. and Rey, S. (eds) 2004. Advances in Spatial Econometrics: Methodology, tools and applications. Berlin:
Springer-Verlag.
Applebaum, W. 1954. Marketing geography. In P. E. James and C. F. Jones (eds) American Geography: Inventory and
prospect. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 245–51.
Appleton, J. 1975. The Experience of Landscape. London: John Wiley.
Appleton, J. 1994. How I Made the World: Shaping a view of landscape. Hull: University of Hull Press.
Archer, J. C. and Taylor. P. J. 1981. Section and Party. Chichester: John Wiley.
Armstrong, M. P. 1993. On automated geography. Professional Geographer 45, 440–2.
Armstrong, M. P. 2000. Geography and computational science. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 90,
146–56.
Armstrong, P. 1999. Charles Darwin’s image of the world: The influence of Alexander von Humboldt
on the Victorian naturalist. In A. Buttimer, S. D. Brunn and U. Wardenga (eds) Text and Image: Social construction
of regional knowledges. Leipzig: Leibniz Institute for Regional Geography, Beiträge zur regionalen Geographie 49,
46–53.
Armstrong, P. H. and Martin, G. J. (eds) 2000. Geographers: Biobibliographical studies. Volume 20. London: Continuum.
Ash, J. and Simpson, P. 2014. Geography and post-phenomenology. Progress in Human Geography. doi: 10.1177/
0309132514544806
Asheim, B. T. 1990. How to confuse rather than guide students: A review of Holt-Jensen’s Geography – History and
Concepts. Progress in Human Geography 14, 281–92.
Atkinson, D. and Dodds, K. 2000. Introduction to geopolitical traditions: A century of geopolitical thought. In
K. Dodds and D. Atkinson (eds) Geopolitical Traditions: A century of geopolitical thought. London and New York:
Routledge, 1–24.
Attoh, K. 2014. Imagining a ‘cultural turn’ in transportation geography. Journal of Cultural Geography 31, 141–51.
Bachmann, V. and Belina, B. 2012. Crisis, critique and the 6th International Conference of Critical Geography.
Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 44, 555–9.
Backhaus, G. 2009. Phenomenology/phenomenological geography. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International
Encyclopedia of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 137–44.
Badcock, B. A. 1970. Central-place evolution and network development in south Auckland, 1840–1968:
A systems analytic approach. New Zealand Geographer 26, 109–35.
Badcock, B. A. 1984. Unfairly Structured Cities. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Badley, G. F. 2011a: Academic scribbling: A frivolous approach? Teaching in Higher Education 16, 255–66.
Badley, G. F. 2011b: Case notes for the impeachment of an ability traitor: A textor’s inquiry. Qualitative Inquiry 17,
483–92.
References 403

Badley, G. F. 2015. Playful and serious adventures in academic writing. Qualitative Inquiry 21. doi:
10.1177/1077800415569785
Bahrenberg, G., Fischer, M. M. and Nijkamp, P. (eds) 1984. Recent Developments in Spatial Data Analysis: Methodology,
measurement, models. Aldershot: Gower Press.
Bailey, T. C. and Gattrell, A. C. 1995. Interactive Spatial Data Analysis. London: Longman.
Baker, A. R. H. 1972. Rethinking historical geography. In A. R. H. Baker (ed.) Progress in Historical Geography. Newton
Abbott: David & Charles, 11–28.
Baker, A. R. H. 1979. Historical geography: A new beginning? Progress in Human Geography 3, 560–70.
Baker, A. R. H. 1981. An historico-geographical perspective on time and space and on period and place. Progress
in Human Geography 5, 439–43.
Baker, A. R. H. 1984. Reflections on the relations of historical geography and the Annales school of history.
In A. R. H. Baker and D. Gregory (eds) Explorations in Historical Geography: Interpretive essays. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1–27.
Baker, A. R. H. 2003. Geography and History: Bridging the Divide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Baker, A. R. H. 2011. Robert Arthur Donkin, 1928–2006. Proceedings of the British Academy 172, 115–39.
Baker, A. R. H. and Gregory, D. 1984. Some terrae incognitae in historical geography: An exploratory discussion. In
A. R. H. Baker and D. Gregory (eds) Explorations in Historical Geography: Interpretive essays. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 180–94.
Balchin, W. G. V. 1987. United Kingdom geographers in the Second World War. Geographical Journal 153,
159–180.
Balchin, W. G. V. 1993. The Geographical Association: The first hundred years, 1893–1993. Sheffield: Geographical
Association.
Balinski, M., Johston, R. J., McLean, I. and Young, H. P. 2010. Drawing a New Constituency Map for the United Kingdom:The
Parliamentary Voting System and Constituencies Bill 2010. London: The British Academy.
Ball, M. 1987. Harvey’s Marxism. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 5, 393–4.
Ballabon, M. B. 1957. Putting the economic into economic geography. Economic Geography 33, 217–23.
Ballas, D., Clarke, G. P. and Turton, I. 2002. A spatial microsimulation model for social policy micro-spatial
analysis. In B. Boots, A. Okabe and R. Thomas (eds) Modelling Geographical Systems: Statistical and computational
applications. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 143–68.
Banks, M. and MacKian, S. 2000. Jump in! The water’s warm: A comment on Peck’s ‘grey geography’. Transactions
of the Institute of British Geographers NS25, 249–54.
Banski, J. and Ferenc, M. 2013. ‘International’ or ‘Anglo-American’ journals of geography? Geoforum 45,
285–95.
Barnes, B. 1974. Scientific Knowledge and Sociological Theory. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Barnes, B. 1982. T. S. Kuhn and Social Science. London: Macmillan.
Barnes, T. J. 1985. Theories of international trade and theories of value. Environment and Planning A 17, 729–46.
Barnes, T. J. 1988. Rationality and relativism in economic geography: An interpretive review of the homo
economicus assumption. Progress in Human Geography 12, 473–96.
Barnes, T. J. 1989a. Place, space and theories of economic value: Contextualism and essentialism in economic
geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS14, 299–316.
Barnes, T. J. 1989b. Structure and agency in economic geography and theories of economic value.
In A. Kobayashi and S. Mackenzie (eds) Remaking Human Geography. Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman, 134–48.
Barnes, T. J. 1996. Logics of Dislocation: Models, metaphors and meaning of economic space. New York: Guilford Press.
Barnes, T. J. 2000. Inventing Anglo-American economic geography, 1889–1960. In E. Sheppard and T. J. Barnes
(eds) A Companion to Economic Geography. Oxford: Blackwell, 11–26.
Barnes, T. J. 2001a. ‘In the beginning was economic geography’ – a science studies approach to disciplinary
history. Progress in Human Geography 25, 521–544.
Barnes, T. J. 2001b. Lives lived and lives told: Biographies of geography’s quantitative revolution. Environment and
Planning D: Society and Space 19, 409–430.
Barnes, T. J. 2001c Retheorizing economic geography: From the quantitative revolution to the ‘cultural turn’.
Annals of the Association of American Geographers 91, 546–65.
Barnes, T. J. 2002. Critical notes on economic geography from an aging radical. Or radical notes on economic
geography from a critical age. ACME: An International E-Journal for Critical Geographies 1, 8–14.
Barnes, T. J. 2003a. What’s wrong with American regional science? A view from science studies. Canadian Journal
of Regional Science 26, 3–26.
404 References

Barnes, T. J. 2003b. The place of locational analysis: A selective and interpretive history. Progress in Human
Geography 27, 69–95.
Barnes, T. J. 2004a. The rise (and decline) of American regional science: Lessons for the new economic
geography? Journal of Economic Geography 4, 107–29.
Barnes, T. J. 2004b. Placing ideas: Genius loci, heterotopias and geography’s quantitative revolution. Progress in
Human Geography 28, 565–95.
Barnes, T. J. 2004c. A paper related to everything but more related to local things. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 94, 278–83.
Barnes, T. J. 2004d. ‘The background of our lives’: David Harvey’s The limits to capital. Antipode: A Radical Journal of
Geography 36, 407–13.
Barnes, T. J. 2006a. Geographical intelligence: American geographers and research and analysis in the Office of
Strategic Services 1941–1945. Journal of Historical Geography 32, 149–68.
Barnes, T. J. 2006b. Between deduction and dialectics: David Harvey on knowledge. In N. Castree and D. Gregory
(eds) David Harvey: A critical reader. Oxford: Blackwell, 26–46.
Barnes, T. J. 2008a. Stuck in a mess (again): A response to Johnston, Fairbrother, Hayes, Hoare and Jones.
Geoforum 30, 1807–10.
Barnes, T. J. 2008b. Geography’s underworld: The military-industrial complex, mathematical modelling and the
quantitative revolution. Geoforum 39, 3–16.
Barnes, T. J. 2014. Geo-historiographies. In R. Lee, N. Castree, R. Kitchin et al. (eds) The SAGE Handbook of Human
Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA, New Delhi, Singapore: Sage, 202–28.
Barnes, T. J. and Abrahamsson, C. 2015. Tangled complicities and moral struggles: The Haushofers, father and
son, and the spaces of Nazi geopolitics. Journal of Historical Geography 47, 64–73.
Barnes, T. J. and Duncan, J. S. 1992. Introduction: Writing worlds. In T. J. Barnes and J. S. Duncan (eds) Writing
Worlds: Discourse, text and metaphor in the representation of landscape. London: Routledge, 1–17.
Barnes, T. J. and Farish, M. 2006. Between regions: Science, militarism, and American geography from world
war to cold war. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 96, 807–26.
Barnes, T. J. and Gregory, D. (eds) 1997. Reading Human Geography:The poetics and politics of enquiry. London: Arnold.
Barnes, T. J. and Minca, C. 2013. Nazi spatial theory: The dark geographies of Carl Schmitt and Walter Christaller.
Annals of the Association of American Geographers 103, 669–87.
Barnett, C. 1995. Awakening the dead: Who needs the history of geography? Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers NS20, 417–19.
Barnett, C. 1998a. The cultural turn: Fashion or progress in human geography. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography
30, 379–94.
Barnett, C. 1998b. Cultural twist and turns. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 16, 631–4.
Barnett, C. 1999. Deconstructing context: Exposing Derrida. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS24,
277–93.
Barnett, C. 2004. A critique of the cultural turn. In J. S. Duncan, N. C. Johnson and R. H. Schein (eds) A Companion
to Cultural Geography. Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell, 38–48.
Barnett, C. 2008. Political affects in public space: Normative blind-spots in nonrepresentational ontologies.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS33, 186–200.
Barnett, C. 2009. Cultural turn. In D. Gregory, R. Johnston, G. Pratt, M. J. Watts and S. Whatmore (eds) The
Dictionary of Human Geography, 5th edn. Malden, MA and Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 134–5.
Barnett, C. and Low, M. 1996. Speculating on theory: Towards a political economy of academic publishing. Area
28, 13–24.
Barrows, H. H. 1923. Geography as human ecology. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 13, 1–14.
Barton, R. 2003. ‘Men of science’: Language, identity and professionalization in the mid-Victorian scientific
community. History of Science 41, 73–119.
Bassett, K. 1996. Postmodernism and the crisis of the intellectual: Reflections on reflexivity, universities and the
scientific field. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 14, 507–27.
Bassett, K. 1999. Is there progress in human geography? The problem of progress in the light of recent work in
the philosophy and sociology of science. Progress in Human Geography 23, 27–47.
Bassett, K. and Short, J. R. 1980. Housing and Residential structure: Alternative approaches. London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Bastow, S., Dunleavy, P. and Tinkler, J. 2014. The Impact of the Social Sciences: How academics and their research make a
difference. London: Sage.
References 405

Batey, P. and Brown, P. 1995. From human ecology to customer targeting: The evolution of geodemographics.
In P. Longley and G. Clarke (eds) GIS for Business and Service Planning. Cambridge: GeoInformation International,
73–103.
Batty, M. 1976. Urban Modelling: Algorithms, calibrations, predictions. London: Cambridge University Press.
Batty, M. 1978. Urban models in the planning process. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and the
Urban Environment, Vol. 1. Chichester: John Wiley, 63–134.
Batty, M. 1989. Urban modelling and planning: Reflections, retrodictions and prescriptions. In B. Macmillan
(ed.) Remodelling Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 147–69.
Batty, M. 2007. Cities and Complexity: Understanding cities with cellular automata, agent-based models, and fractals. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Batty, M. 2013. The New Science of Cities. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Batty, M. and Longley, P. 1994. Fractal Cities: A geometry of form and function. London: Academic Press.
Beaumont, J. R. 1987. Quantitative methods in the real world: A consultant’s view of practice. Environment and
Planning A 19, 1441–8.
Beaumont, J. R. and Gatrell, A. C. 1982. An introduction to Q-analysis. CATMOG 34, Norwich: Geo Books.
Beauregard, R. A. 1988. In the absence of practice: The locality research debate. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography
20, 52–9.
Beauregard, R. A. 1999. Break dancing on Santa Monica Boulevard. Urban Geography 20, 396–399.
Beaver, S.H. 1962. The Le Play Society and fieldwork. Geography 47, 225–40.
Beaverstock, J., Smith, R. G. and Taylor, P. J. 2000. World city network: A new metageography of the future? Annals
of the Association of American Geographers 90, 121–34.
Becher, T. and Trowler, P. R. 2001. Academic Tribes and Territories, 2nd edn. Buckingham: Open University Press.
Beckerman, W. 1995. Small is Stupid: Blowing the whistle on the greens. London: Duckworth.
Beckinsale, R. P. 1976. The international influence of William Morris Davis. Geographical Review 66, 448–66.
Beckinsale, R. P. 1997. Richard J. Chorley: A reformer with a cause. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Process and Form in
Geomorphology. London: Routledge, 3–14.
Bell, C. and Newby, H. 1976. Community, communion, class and community action: The social sources of new
urban politics. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds) Social Areas in Cities.Volume 2: Spatial Perspectives on Problems
and Policies. Chichester: John Wiley, 189–208.
Bell, D. 1973. The Coming of Post-Industrial Society. New York: Basic Books.
Bell, D. J. 1991. Insignificant others: Lesbian and gay geographies. Area 23, 323–29.
Bell, D. J. and Valentine, G. (eds) 1995. Mapping Desire: Geographies of sexualities. London and New York: Routledge.
Bell, D. J., Binne, J., Cream, J. and Valentine, G. 1994. All hyped up and no place to go. Gender, Place and Culture 1,
31–47.
Bell, M. and McEwan, C. 1996. The admission of women fellows to the Royal Geographical Society,
1892–1914: The controversy and the outcome. Geographical Journal 162, 295–312.
Bell, M., Butlin, R. J. and Heffernan, M. (eds) 1995. Geography and Imperialism: 1820–1940. Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
Bennett, R. J. 1974. Process identification for time-series modelling in urban and regional planning. Regional
Studies 8, 157–74.
Bennett, R. J. 1975. Dynamic systems modelling of the Northwest region: 1. Spatio-temporal representation
and identification. 2. Estimation of the spatio-temporal policy model. 3. Adaptive parameter policy model.
4. Adaptive spatio-temporal forecasts. Environment and Planning A 7, 525–38, 539–66, 617–36, 887–98.
Bennett, R. J. 1978a. Forecasting in urban and regional planning closed loops: The examples of road and air
traffic forecasts. Environment and Planning A 10, 145–62.
Bennett, R. J. 1978b. Spatial Time Series: Analysis, forecasting and control. London: Pion.
Bennett, R. J. 1979. Space-time models and urban geographical research. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston
(eds) Geography and the Urban Environment, Vol. 2. London: John Wiley, 27–58.
Bennett, R. J. 1981a. A hierarchical control solution to allocation of the British Rate Support Grant. Geographical
Analysis 13, 300–14.
Bennett, R. J. (ed.) 1981b. European Progress in Spatial Analysis. London: Pion.
Bennett, R. J. 1981c. Quantitative and theoretical geography in Western Europe. In R. J. Bennett (ed.) European
Progress in Spatial Analysis. London: Pion, 1–32.
Bennett, R. J. 1981a. Quantitative geography and public policy. In N. Wrigley and R. J. Bennett (eds) Quantitative
Geography. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 387–96.
406 References

Bennett, R. J. 1982. Geography, relevance and the role of the Institute. Area 14, 69–71.
Bennett, R. J. 1983. Individual and territorial equity. Geographical Analysis 15, 50–87.
Bennett, R. J. 1985a. Quantification and relevance. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography. London: Methuen,
211–24.
Bennett, R. J. 1985b. A reappraisal of the role of spatial science and statistical inference in geography in Britain.
L’Espace Geographique 14, 23–8.
Bennett, R. J. 1989a. Demography and budgetary influence on the geography of the poll tax: Alarm or false
alarm? Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS14, 400–17.
Bennett, R. J. 1989b. Whither models and geography in a post-welfarist world? In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling
Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 273–90.
Bennett, R. J. and Chorley, R. J. 1978. Environmental Systems: Philosophy, analysis and control. London: Methuen.
Bennett, R. J. and Haining, R. P. 1985. Spatial structure and spatial interaction: Modelling approaches to the
statistical analysis of geographical data. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society A 148, 1–36.
Bennett, R. J. and Thornes, J. B. 1988. Geography in the United Kingdom, 1984–1988. Geographical Journal 154,
23–48.
Bennett, R. J. and Wilson, A. G. 2003. Geography applied. In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams (eds) A Century of
British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 463–501.
Bennett, R. J. and Wrigley, N. 1981. Introduction. In N. Wrigley and R. J. Bennett (eds) Quantitative Geography.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 3–11.
Bennett, R. J., Haining, R. P. and Wilson, A. G. 1985. Spatial structure, spatial interaction and their integration:
A review of alternative models. Environment and Planning A 17, 625–46.
Bentham, G. 1987. An evaluation of the UGC’s rating of the research of British university geography departments.
Area 19, 147–54.
Berdoulay, V. 1981. The contextual approach. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Geography, Ideology and Social Concern. Oxford:
Blackwell, 8–16.
Berdoulay, V. 2011. German precursors and French challengers. In J. A. Agnew and J. S. Duncan (eds) The
Wiley-Blackwell Companion to Human Geography. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 73–88.
Berg, L. D. 1993. Between modernism and postmodernism. Progress in Human Geography 17, 490–507.
Berg, L. D. 2003. (Some) spaces of critical geography. In A. Rogers and H. R. Viles (eds) The Students’ Companion to
Geography, 2nd edn. Oxford: Blackwell, 305–11.
Berg, L. D. 2012. Geographies of identity I: geography – (neo)liberalism – white supremacy. Progress in Human
Geography 36, 508–17.
Berg, L. D. and Kearns, R. A. 1998. America Unlimited. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 16, 128–32.
Berg, L. D. and Longhurst, R. 2003. Placing masculinities and geography. Gender, Place and Culture 10, 351–60.
Berman, M. 1974. Sex discrimination in geography: The case of Ellen Churchill Semple. Professional Geographer 26,
8–11.
Berry, B. J. L. 1958. A critique of contemporary planning for business centers. Land Economics 25, 306–12.
Berry, B. J. L. 1959a. Ribbon developments in the urban business pattern. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 49, 145–55.
Berry, B. J. L. 1959b. Further comments ‘geographic’ and ‘economic’ economic geography. Professional Geographer
11(1), 11–12.
Berry, B. J. L. 1964a. Approaches to regional analysis: A synthesis. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 54,
2–11.
Berry, B. J. L. 1964b. Cities as systems within systems of cities. Papers, Regional Science Association 13,
147–63.
Berry, B. J. L. 1965. Research frontiers in urban geography. In P. M. Hauser and L. F. Schnore (eds) The Study of
Urbanization. New York: John Wiley, 403–30.
Berry, B. J. L. 1966. Essays on Commodity Flows and the Spatial Structure of the Indian Economy. Chicago: University of
Chicago, Department of Geography, Research Paper 111.
Berry, B. J. L. 1967. The Geography of Market Centers and Retail Distribution. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Berry, B. J. L. 1968. A synthesis of formal and functional regions using a general field theory of spatial behavior.
In B. J. L. Berry and D. F. Marble (eds) Spatial Analysis. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 419–28.
Berry, B. J. L. 1969. Review of B. M. Russett International Regions and the International System. Geographical Review 59,
450–1.
Berry, B. J. L. (ed.) 1971. Comparative factorial ecology. Economic Geography 47, 209–367.
References 407

Berry, B. J. L (with others) 1974. Land Use, Urban Form and Environmental Quality. Chicago: Department of
Geography, Research Paper 155, University of Chicago.
Berry, B. J. L. 1972a. ‘Revolutionary and counter-revolutionary theory in geography’ – a ghetto commentary.
Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 4(2), 31–3.
Berry, B. J. L. 1972b. More on relevance and policy analysis. Area 4, 77–80.
Berry, B. J. L. 1973a. A paradigm for modern geography. In R. J. Chorley (ed.) Directions in Geography. London:
Methuen, 3–22.
Berry, B. J. L. 1973b. The Human Consequences of Urbanization. London: Macmillan.
Berry, B. J. L. 1974a. Review of H. M. Rose (ed.) Perspectives in Geography 2: Geography of the ghetto, perceptions, problems and
alternatives. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 64, 342–5.
Berry, B. J. L. 1974b. Review of David Harvey, Social Justice and the City. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 6(2),
142–9.
Berry, B. J. L. 1978a. Introduction: A Kuhnian perspective. In B. J. L. Berry (ed.) The Nature of Change in Geographical
Ideas. DeKalb, IL: Northern Illinois University Press, vii–x.
Berry, B. J. L. 1978b. Geographical theories of social change. In B. J. L. Berry (ed.) The Nature of Change in Geographical
Ideas. DeKalb, IL: Northern Illinois University Press, 17–36.
Berry, B. J. L. 1993. Geography’s quantitative revolution: Initial conditions, 1954–1960: A personal memoir.
Urban Geography 14, 434–41.
Berry, B. J. L. 1995. Whither regional science? International Regional Science Review 17, 297–306.
Berry, B. J. L. 1998. On consilience. Urban Geography 19, 95–97.
Berry, B. J. L. 1999. Beyond postmodernism. Urban Geography 20, 589–90.
Berry, B. J. L. 2002a. The Chicago School in retrospect. Urban Geography 22, 559–61.
Berry, B. J. L. 2002b. Clara voce cognito. In P. Gould and F. R. Pitts (eds) Geographical Voices: Fourteen autobiographical
essays. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1–26.
Berry, B. J. L. 2002c. Paradigm lost. Urban Geography 23, 441–5.
Berry, B. J. L. 2002d. Big tents or firm foundations? Urban Geography 23, 501–2.
Berry, B. J. L. 2002e. My Cheshire cat’s smile. Urban Geography 23, 1–2.
Berry, B. J. L. and Baker, A. M. 1968. Geographic sampling. In B. J. L. Berry and D. F. Marble (eds) Spatial Analysis.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 91–100.
Berry, B. J. L. and Garrison, W. L. 1958a. The functional bases of the central place hierarchy. Economic Geography 34,
145–54.
Berry, B. J. L. and Garrison, W. L. 1958b. Recent developments in central place theory. Papers and Proceedings, Regional
Science Association 4, 107–20.
Berry, B. J. L. and Horton, F. E. (eds) 1974. Urban Environmental Management: Planning for Pollution Control. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Berry, B. J. L., Goheen, P. G. and Goldstein, H. 1969. Metropolitan Area Definition: A re-evaluation of the concept and
statistical practice. Washington, DC: US Bureau of the Census.
Best, U. 2009. Critical geography. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human Geography.
Amsterdam: Elsevier, 345–57.
Best, U. 2014. Competitive internationalisation or grassroots practises of internationalism? The changing
international practises of German-language critical geography. Social and Cultural Geography. doi: 10.1080/
14649365.2014.979862
Bettencourt, L. and West, G. 2010. A unified theory of urban living. Nature 467, 912–13.
Bhaskar, R. 1978. A Realist Theory of Science. Brighton: Harvester Press.
Billinge, M. 1977. In search of negativism: Phenomenology and historical geography. Journal of Historical Geography
3, 55–68.
Billinge, M. 1983. The mandarin dialect: An essay on style in contemporary geographical writing. Transactions of
the Institute of British Geographers NS8, 400–20.
Billinge, M., Gregory, D. and Martin, R. L. (eds) 1984. Recollections of a Revolution: Geography as spatial science. London:
Macmillan.
Bingham, N. 1996. Object-ions: From technological determinism towards geographies of relations. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 14, 635–7.
Binnie, J. 1997. Coming out of geography: Towards a queer epistemology? Environment and Planning D: Society and
Space 15, 223–37.
408 References

Binnie, J. and Valentine, G. 1999. Geographies of sexuality – a review of progress. Progress in Human Geography 23,
175–87.
Binnie, J., Madge, C., Pain, R., Raghuram, P. and Rose, G. 2005. Working a fraction and making a fraction work:
A rough guide for geographers in the academy. Area 37, 251–9.
Bird, A. J. 2000. Thomas Kuhn. Chesham: Acumen Books.
Bird, A. J. 2003. Three conservative Kuhns. Social Epistemology 17, 127–33.
Bird, J. H. 1975. Methodological implications for geography from the philosophy of K. R. Popper. Scottish
Geographical Magazine 91, 153–63.
Bird, J. H. 1977. Methodology and philosophy. Progress in Human Geography 1, 104–10.
Bird, J. H. 1978. Methodology and philosophy. Progress in Human Geography 2, 133–40.
Bird, J. H. 1985. Geography in three worlds: How Popper’s system can help elucidate dichotomies and changes
in the discipline. Professional Geographer 37, 403–9.
Bird, J. H. 1993. The Changing Worlds of Geography: A critical guide to concepts and methods, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Birkin, M. 1995. Customer targeting, geodemographics and lifestyle approaches. In P. Longley and G. Clarke
(eds) GIS for Business and Service Planning. Cambridge: GeoInformation International, 104–49.
Birkin, M. and Clarks, M. 1988. SYNTHESIS: A synthetic spatial information system: Methods and examples.
Environment and Planning A 20, 645–71.
Birkin, M. and Clarke, M. 1989. The generation of individual and household incomes at the small area level
using synthesis. Regional Studies 23, 535–48.
Birkin, M. and Wilson, A. G. 1986. Industrial location models 1. A review and integrating framework and 2.
Weber, Palander, Hotelling and extensions within a new framework. Environment and Planning A 18, 175–206
and 293–306.
Birkin, M., Clarke, G. and Clarke, M. 2002. Retail Geography and Intelligent Network Planning. Chichester: John Wiley.
Birkin, M., Clarke, G. and Clarke, M. 2010: Refining and operationalizing entropy-maximizing models for
business applications. Geographical Analysis, 42, 422–45.
Birkin, M., Clarke, M. and George, F. 1995. The use of parallel computers to solve nonlinear spatial optimisation
problems: An application to network planning. Environment and Planning A 27, 1049–68.
Birkin, M., Clarke, G., Clarke, M. and Wilson, A. G. 1990. Elements of a model-based GIS for evaluation of urban
policy. In L. Worrall (ed.) Geographic Information Systems: Development and applications. London: Belhaven Press,
131–62.
Birkin, M., Clarke, G., Clarke, M. and Wilson, A. G. 1996. Intelligent GIS: Location decisions and strategic planning.
Cambridge: Geoinformation International.
Blaikie, P. M. 1978. The theory of the spatial diffusion of innovations: A spacious cul-de-sac. Progress in Human
Geography 2, 268–95.
Blaikie, P. M. 1985. The Political Economy of Soil Erosion. London: Longman.
Blaikie, P. M. 1986. Natural resource use in developing countries. In R. J. Johnston and P. J. Taylor (eds) A  World
in Crisis? Geographical perspectives. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 107–26.
Blaikie, P. M. 2008. Epilogue: Towards a future for political ecology that works. Geoforum 39, 765–72.
Blaikie, P. M. 2012. Should some political ecology be useful? Geoforum 43, 231–9.
Blaikie, P. M. and Brookfield, H. C. (eds) 1987. Land Degradation and Society. London: Methuen.
Blalock, H. M. 1960. Social Statistics. New York: McGraw Hill.
Blaug, M. 1975. Kuhn versus Lakatos, or paradigms versus research programmes in the history of economics.
History of Political Economy 7, 399–419.
Blaut, J. M. 1962. Object and relationship. Professional Geographer 14, 1–6.
Blaut, J. M. 1970. Geographic models of imperialism. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 2, 65–85.
Blaut, J. M. 1975. Imperialism: The Marxist theory and its evolution. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 7, 1–19.
Blaut, J. M. 1979. The dissenting tradition. Annals of the Association of America Geographers 69, 157–64.
Blaut, J. M. 1987. Diffusionism: A uniformitarian critique. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 77, 30–47.
Blouet, B. W. (ed.) 1981. The Origins of Academic Geography in the United States. Hamden, CT: Archon Books.
Blouet, B. W. 1987. Halford Mackinder: A biography. College Station, TX: Texas A&M University Press.
Blowers, A. T. 1972. Bleeding hearts and open values. Area 4, 290–2.
Blowers, A. T. 1974. Relevance, research and the political process. Area 6, 32–6.
Blowers, A. T. 1984. Something in the Air: Corporate power and the environment. London: Harper & Row.
Blumenstock, D. I. 1953. The reliability factor in the drawing of isarithms. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 43, 289–304.
References 409

Blunt, A. 1994. Travel, Gender and Imperialism: Mary Kingsley and West Africa. New York: Guilford.
Blunt, A. and McEwan, C. (eds) 2002. Postcolonial Geographies. New York and London: Continuum.
Blunt, A. and Wills, J. 2000. Dissident Geographies: An introduction to radical ideas and practice. Harlow: Pearson.
Blunt, A. and Dowling, R. 2006. Home. London and New York: Routledge.
Boal, F. W. and Livingston, D. N. 1989. The behavioural environment: Worlds of meaning in a world of facts. In
F. W. Boal and D. N. Livingstone (eds) The Behavioural Environment. London: Routledge, 3–17.
Boddy, M. J. 1976. The structure of mortgage finance: Building societies and the British social formation.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS1, 58–71.
Bodman, A. R. 1991. Weavers of influence: The structure of contemporary geographic research. Transactions of the
Institute of British Geographers NS16, 21–7.
Bodman, A. R. 1992. Holes in the fabric: More on the master weavers in human geography. Transactions of the
Institute of British Geographers NS17, 108–9.
Bodman, A. R. 2010. Measuring the influentialness of economic geographers during the ‘great half century’:
An approach using the h-index. Journal of Economic Geography 10, 141–56.
Bond, D. W. 2014. Hegel’s geographical thought. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 32, 179–98.
Bondi, L. 1993. Locating identity politics. In M. Keith and S. Pile (eds) Place and the Politics Identity. London:
Routledge, 84–101.
Bondi, L. 1997. In whose words? On gender identities, knowledge and writing practices. Transactions of the Institute
of British Geographers NS22, 245–58.
Bondi, L. 2005. Making connections and thinking through emotions; between geography and psychotherapy.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS 30, 433–48.
Bondi, L. and Domosh, M. 1992. Other figures in other places: On feminism, postmodernism and geography.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 10, 199–213.
Bondi, L. and Domosh, M. 1994. Editorial. Gender, Place and Culture 1, 3–4.
Bondi, L., Avis, H., Bingley, A., Davidson, J., Duffy, R., Einagel, V. I., Green, A.-M., Johnston, L., Lilley,
S., Listerborn, C. Marshy, M., McEwan, S., O’Connor, N., Rose, G., Vivat, B. and Wood, N. 2002. Subjectivities,
Knowledges and Feminist Geographies:The subjects and ethics of social research. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Bonnett, A. 1993. Contours of crisis: Anti-racism and reflexivity. In P. Jackson and J. Penrose (eds) Constructions of
Race, Place and Nation. London: UCL Press, 163–80.
Bonnett, A. 1997. Geography, ‘race’, and whiteness: Invisible traditions and current challenges. Area 29, 193–99.
Bonnett, A. 2003. Geography as the world discipline: Connecting popular and academic geographical
imaginations. Area 35, 55–63.
Bonnett, A. 2003. Response to Stannard. Area 35, 323–4.
Bonnett, A. and Knoop, A. 2003. Cultural geographies of racialization – the territory of race. In K. Anderson,
M. Domosh, S. Pile and N. Thrift (eds) The Handbook of Cultural Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and
New Delhi: Sage, 300–12.
Bonnett, A. and Nayak, A. 2003. Racialization – the territory of race. In K. Anderson, M. Domosh, S. Pile and
N. Thrift (eds) The Handbook of Cultural Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage, 300–12.
Bonta, M. 2007. Review of Deleuze and space by Ian Buchanan and Gregg Lambert (eds) Annals of the Association
of American Geographers 97, 811–13.
Boots, B. N. and Getis, A. 1978. Models of Spatial Processes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bosco, F. J. 2006. Actor-network theory, networks, and relational approaches in human geography. In S. Aitken
and G. Valentine (eds) Approaches to Human Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage, 136–46.
Bosker, M., Brakman, S., Garretsen, H. and Schramm, M. 2010. Adding geography to the new economic
geography: Bridging the gap between theory and empirics. Journal of Economic Geography 10, 793–823.
Bosman, J. 2009. The changing position of society journals in geography. Tijdschrift voor economische en sociale geografie
100, 20–32.
Bourdieu, P. 1988. Homo Academicus. Cambridge: Polity.
Bourdieu, P. 1990. The Logic of Practice. Cambridge: Polity.
Bowd, G. P. and Clayton, D. W. 2013. Geographical warfare in the tropics: Yves Lacoste and the Vietnam War.
Annals of the Association of American Geographers 103, 627–46.
Bowen, M. 1970. Mind and nature: The physical geography of Alexander von Humboldt. Scottish Geographical
Magazine 86, 222–33.
Bowen, M. 1981. Empiricism and Geographical Thought from Francis Bacon to Alexander von Humboldt. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
410 References

Bowlby, S. R. and Tivers, J. 2009. Feminist geography, prehistory of. In R. Kitchen and N. Thrift (eds) International
Encyclopedia of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 59–63.
Bowlby, S. R., Foord, J. and McDowell, L. 1986. The place of gender in locality studies. Area 18, 327–31.
Bowlby, S. R., Lewis, J., McDowell, L. and Foord, J. 1989. The geography of gender. In R. Peet and N. J. Thrift
(eds) New Models in Geography, Vol. 2. London: Unwin Hyman, 157–75.
Bowman, I. 1921. The New World: Problems in political geography. New York: Harrap.
Boyce, R. R. (ed.) 1980. Geography as Spatial Interaction by Edward L. Ullman. Seattle, WA: University of Washington
Press.
Boyer, R. and Saillard, Y. (eds) 1995. Regulation Theory:The state of the art. London and New York: Routledge.
Boyle, M. 2005. Biographical approaches in the teaching of history and philosophy of human geography:
Introduction to review essays on Key Thinkers on Space and Place. Environment and Planning A 37, 161–4.
Boyle, M. J. and Robinson, M. E. 1979. Cognitive mapping and understanding. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston
(eds) Geography and the Urban Environment, Vol. 2. Chichester: John Wiley, 59–82.
Boyle, P. J., Cullis, A., Feng, Z., Flowerdew, R. and Gayle, V. 2004. Adding Geographical Variables and Identifiers to
Longitudinal Datasets. A report to the National Longitudinal Strategy Committee and ESRC.
Bracken, I., Higgs, G., Martin, D. and Webster, C. 1990. A classification of geographical information systems
literature and applications. CATMOG 52, Norwich: Environmental Publications.
Bradley, P. N. 1986. Food production and distribution – and hunger. In R. J. Johnston and P. J. Taylor (eds) A
World in Crisis? Geographical perspectives. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 89–106.
Brakman, S., Garretsen, H. and Vav Marrewijk, C. 2009. The New Introduction to Geographical Economics. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Braun, B. and Castree, N. (eds) 1998. Remaking Reality: Nature at the millennium. London and New York:
Routledge.
Breheny, M. 1989. Chalkface to coalface: A review of the academic–practice interface. Environment and Planning
B: Planning and Design 16, 451–68.
Breitbart, M. M. 1981. Peter Kropotkin, the anarchist geographer. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Geography, Ideology and
Social Concern. Oxford: Blackwell, 134–53.
Brenner, N. 2004. New State Spaces: Urban governance and the rescaling of statehood. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brenner, N. and Elden, S. 2009. State, space, world: Henri Lefebvre and the survival of capitalism. In N. Brenner
and S. Elden (eds) Henri Lefebvre, State, Space, World: Selected essays. Minneapolis, MN, and London: Minnesota
University Press, 1–48.
Brenner, N. and Theodore, N. 2002a. From the ‘new localism’ to the spaces of neoliberalis. Antipode: A Radical
Journal of Geography 34, 341–7.
Brenner, N. and Theodore, N. 2002b. Cities and the geographies of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’. Antipode:
A Radical Journal of Geography 34, 349–79.
Brenner, N., Jessop, B., Jones, M. and MacLeod, G. (eds) 2003. State/Space: A reader. Oxford: Blackwell.
Brickell, K., Maddrell, L. A., Martin, A. and Price, L. 2013. By any other name? The Women and Geography Study
Group. Area 45, 11–12.
Briggs, D. J. 1981. The principles and practice of applied geography. Applied Geography 1, 1–8.
Brittan, S. 1977. Economic liberalism. In A. Bullock and O. Stallybrass (eds) The Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thought.
London: William Collins, 188–9.
Brookfield, H. C. 1962. Local study and comparative method: An example from Central New Guinea. Annals of
the Association of American Geographers 52, 242–54.
Brookfield, H. C. 1964. Questions on the human frontiers of geography. Economic Geography 40, 283–303.
Brookfield, H. C. 1969. On the environment as perceived. In C. Board, R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R. Stoddart
(eds) Progress in Geography, Vol. 1. London: Edward Arnold, 51–80.
Brookfield, H. C. 1973. On one geography and a Third World. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 58,
1–20.
Brookfield, H. C. 1975. Interdependent Development. London: Methuen.
Brookfield, H. C. 1989. The behavioural environment: How, what for, and whose? In F. W. Boal and D. N.
Livingstone (eds) The Behavioural Environment. London: Routledge, 311.
Browett, J. 1984. On the necessity and inevitability of uneven spatial development under capitalism. International
Journal of Urban and Regional Research 8, 155–76.
Brown, G., Browne, K. and Lim, J. 2009. Introduction. In K. Browne, J. Lim and G. Brown (eds) Geographies of
Sexualities: Theory, practices and politics. Farnham and Burlington: Ashgate, 1–18.
References 411

Brown, G., Browne, K. and Lim, J. 2011. Sexual life. In V. Del Casino Jr, M. Thomas, P. Cloke and R. Panelli (eds)
A Companion to Social Geography. Chichester and Malden: Blackwell, 293–308.
Brown, L. A. 1968. Diffusion Processes and Location: A conceptual framework and bibliography. Regional Science Research
Institute, Bibliography Series 3, Philadelphia, PA.
Brown, L. A. 1975. The market and infrastructure context of adoption: A spatial perspective on the diffusion of
innovation. Economic Geography 51, 185–216.
Brown, L. A. 1981. Innovation Diffusion: A new perspective. London: Methuen.
Brown, L. A. and Moore, E. G. 1970. The intra-urban migration process: A perspective. Geografiska Annaler 52B,
1–13.
Brown, M. P. 1995. Ironies of distance: An ongoing critique of geographies of AIDS. Environment and Planning D:
Society and Space 13, 159–83.
Brown, M. P. 2000. Closet Space. London and New York: Routledge.
Brown, M. P. and Knopp, L. 2003. Queer cultural geographies – We’re here! We’re queer! We’re over there, too!
In K. Anderson, M. Domosh, S. Pile and N. Thrift (eds) The Handbook of Cultural Geography. London, Thousand
Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage, 313–29.
Brown, R. H. 1943. Mirror for Americans: Likenesses of the eastern seaboard 1810. New York: American Geographical
Society.
Brown, S. E. 1978. Guy-Harold Smith, 1895–1976. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 68, 115–18.
Browne, K., Nash, C. J. and Hines, S. 2010. Introduction: Towards trans geographies. Gender, Place and Culture 17,
573–77.
Browne, K., Norcup, J., Robson, E. and Sharp, J. 2013. What’s in a name? Removing women from the Women
and Geography Study Group. Area 45, 7–8.
Browning, C. E. 1982. Conversations with Geographers: Career pathways and research styles. Studies in Geography 16,
Department of Geography, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, NC.
Brunn, S. D. 1974. Geography and Politics in America. New York: Harper & Row.
Brunsdon, C. 2014. Spatial science – looking outward. Dialogues in Human Geography 4, 45–9.
Brush, J. E. 1953. The hierarchy of central places in southwestern Wisconsin. Geographical Review 43, 380–402.
Buchanan, K. M. 1958a. Review of R. J. Harrison Church, West Africa: A study of the environment and man’s use of it.
Economic Geography 34, 277–8.
Buchanan, K. M. 1958b. Review of R. W. Steel and C. A. Fisher (eds) Geographical Essays on British Tropical Lands. 1956.
Geographical Review, 48, 447–9.
Buchanan, K. M. 1962. West wind, east wind. Geography 47, 333–46.
Buchanan, K. M. 1966. The Chinese People and the Chinese Earth. London: Bell.
Buchanan, K. M. 1973. The white north and the population explosion. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 5(3),
7–15.
Buchanan, K. M. and Pugh, J. C. 1958. Land and People in Nigeria:The human geography of Nigeria and its environmental basis.
London: University of London Press.
Buchanan, R. O. 1968. The man and his work. In C. Embleton and J. T. Coppock (eds) Land Use and Resources: Studies
in applied geography. A memorial volume to Sir Dudley Stamp. London: Institute of British Geographers, Special
Publication 1, 1–12.
Bullock, A. 1977. Liberalism. In A. Bullock and O. Stallybrass (eds) The Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thought. London:
William Collins, 347.
Bulmer, M. 1984. The Chicago School of Sociology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bunge, W. 1962. Theoretical Geography, 1st edn. Lund Studies in Geography, Series C: General and Mathematical
Geography. Lund: Gleerup.
Bunge, W. 1966a. Theoretical Geography, 2nd edn. Lund Studies in Geography, Series C: General and Mathematical
Geography 1. Lund: Gleerup.
Bunge, W. 1966b. Locations are not unique. Annals of the Association of America Geographers 56, 375–6.
Bunge, W. 1968. Fred K. Schaefer and the Science of Geography. Harvard Papers in Theoretical Geography, Special
Papers Series, Paper A, Laboratory for Computer Graphics and Spatial Analysis, Harvard University, Cambridge,
MA.
Bunge, W. 1971. Fitzgerald: Geography of a revolution. Cambridge, MA: Schenkman.
Bunge, W. 1973a. Spatial prediction. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 63, 566–8.
Bunge, W. 1973b. Ethics and logic in geography. In R. J. Chorley (ed.) Directions in Geography. London: Methuen,
317–31.
412 References

Bunge, W. 1973c. The geography of human survival. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 63, 275–95.
Bunge, W. 1973d. The geography. Professional Geographer 25, 331–7.
Bunge, W. 1979. Fred K. Schaefer and the science of geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69,
128–33.
Bunge, W. and Bordessa, R. 1975. Canadian Alternative: Survival, expeditions and urban change. Geographical Monograph
No. 2, Department of Geography, Atkinson College, York University, Toronto, Ontario.
Bunting, T. E. and Guelke, L. 1979. Behavioral and perception geography: A critical appraisal. Annals of the
Association of American Geographers 69, 448–62, 471–4.
Burnett, K. P. (ed.) 1981. Studies in choice, constraints, and human spatial behavior. Special issue, Economic
Geography 57, 291–383.
Burnett, K. P. 1973. Social change, the status of women and models of city form and development. Antipode:
A Radical Journal of Geography 5(3), 57–62.
Burrows, R. 2012. Living with the h-index? Metric assemblages in the contemporary academy. Sociological Review
60, 355–72.
Burton, I. 1963. The quantitative revolution and theoretical geography. Canadian Geographer 7, 151–62.
Burton, I., Kates, R. W. and White, G. F. 1978. The Environment as Hazard. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bushong, A. D. 1981. Geographers and their mentors: A genealogical view of American academic geography. In
B. W. Blouet (ed.) The Origins of Academic Geography in the United States. Hamden, CT: Archon Books, 193–220.
Butler, R. and Bowlby, S. 1997. Bodies and spaces: An exploration of disabled people’s experiences of public
space. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 15, 411–33.
Butler, R. and Parr, H. (eds) 1999. Mind and Body Spaces: Geographies of illness, impairment and disability. London: Routledge.
Butlin, R. A. 1982. The Transformation of Rural England c. 1580–1800. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Butlin, R. A. 2009. Geographies of Empire: European empires and colonies c.1880–1960. Cambridge and New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Buttimer, A. 1971. Society and Milieu in the French Geographical Tradition. Chicago: Rand McNally.
Buttimer, A. 1974. Values in Geography. Commission on College Geography, Resource Paper 24, Association of
American Geographers, Washington, DC.
Buttimer, A. 1976. Grasping the dynamism of lifeworld. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 66, 277–92.
Buttimer, A. 1978a. Charism and context: The challenge of la geographie humaine. In D. Ley and M. S. Samuels (eds)
Humanistic Geography: Prospects and problems. Chicago: Maaroufa Press, 58–76.
Buttimer, A. 1978b. On people, paradigms and progress in geography. Institutionen for Kulturgeografi oeh
Eeonomisk Geografi vid Lunds Universitet, Rapporter och Notiser 47.
Buttimer, A. 1979. Erewhon or nowhere land. In S. Gale and G. Olsson (eds) Philosophy in Geography. Dordrecht: D.
Reidel, 9–38.
Buttimer, A. 1981. On people, paradigms and progress in geography. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Geography, Ideology and
Social Concern. Oxford: Blackwell, 70–80.
Buttimer, A. 1983. The Practice of Geography. London: Longman.
Buttimer, A. 1993. Geography and the Human Spirit. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Buttimer, A. 1995. Book review – Vidal de La Blache: 1845–1918. Un Génie de la Géographie. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers, 85(2), 406–7.
Buttimer, A. 2007. Torsten Hägerstrand (1916–2004). In H. Lorimer and C. W. J. Withers (eds) Geographers:
Biobibliographical studies, Vol. 27. London and New York: Continuum, 119–57.
Buttimer, A. and Fahy, G. 1999. Imagining Ireland through geography texts. In A. Buttimer, S. D. Brunn and U.
Wardenga (eds) Text and Image: Social construction of regional knowledges. Leipzig: Leibniz Institute for Regional
Geography, Beiträge zur regionalen Geographie 49, 179–91.
Buttimer, A. and Hägerstrand, T. 1980. Invitation to Dialogue: A progress report. DIA Paper 1, Lund: University of
Lund.
Buttimer, A. and Mels, T. 2006. By Northern Lights: On the making of geography in Sweden. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Butzer, K. W. 1989. Cultural ecology. In G. L. Gaile and C. J. Willmot (eds) Geography in America. Columbus, OH:
Merrill, 192–208.
Butzer, K. W. 1990. Hartshorne, Hettner, and The Nature of Geography. In J. N. Entrikin and S. D. Brunn (eds)
Reflections on Richard Hartshorne’s The Nature of Geography. Washington, DC: Association of American Geographers,
35–52.
Cadwallader, M. 1975. A behavioral model of consumer spatial decision making. Economic Geography 51,
339–49.
References 413

Cadwallader, M. 1986. Structural equation models in human geography. Progress in Human Geography 10, 24–47.
Cameron, I. 1980. To the Farthest Ends of the Earth. London: Macdonald.
Campaign for Social Sciences 2015. The Business of People: The significance of social science over the next decade. London:
Academy of the Social Sciences.
Campbell, C. S. 1994. The second nature of geography: Hartshorne as humanist. Professional Geographer 46,
411–17.
Campbell, J. A. 1989. The concept of ‘the behavioural environment’, and its origins, reconsidered. In F. W. Boal
and D. N. Livingstone (eds) The Behavioural Environment. London: Routledge, 33–76.
Campbell, J. A. and Livingstone, D. N. 1983. Neo-Lamarckism and the development of geography in the United
States and Great Britain. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS8, 267–94.
Cannon, T. 1975. Geography and underdevelopment. Area 7, 212–6.
Capel, H. 1981. Filosofía y ciencia en la geografía contemporánea: Una introdución a la geografía. Barcelona: Barcano.
Capel, H. 1981. Institutionalization of geography and strategies of change. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Geography,
Ideology and Social Concern. Oxford: Blackwell, 37–69.
Carey, H. C. 1858. Principles of Social Science. Philadelphia, PA: J. Lippincott.
Carlstein, T. 1980. Time, resources, society and ecology. Lund: Department of Geography, University of Lund.
Carlstein, T., Parkes, D. N. and Thrift, N. J. (eds) 1978. Timing Space and Spacing Time (3 vols). London: Edward
Arnold.
Carr, M. 1983. A contribution to the review and critique of behavioural industrial location theory. Progress in
Human Geography 7, 386–402.
Carroll, G. R. 1982. National city-size distributions: What do we know after 67 years of research? Progress in
Human Geography 6, 1–43.
Carrothers, G. A. P. 1956. An historical review of the gravity and potential concepts of human interaction. Journal,
American Institute of Planners 22, 94–102.
Carter, G. 1977. A geographical society should be a geographical society. Professional Geographer 29, 101–2.
Casetti, E. 1999. The evolution of scientific disciplines, mathematical modelling and human geography.
Geographical Analysis 30, 332–9.
Castells, M. 1977. The Urban Question. London: Edward Arnold.
Castree, N. 1994. Teaching history, philosophy and theory: Notes on representing Marxism and ‘Marxist
geography’. Journal of Geography in Higher Education 18, 33–42.
Castree, N. 1995a. Review essay. The lonely hour of the last word: Marx, Althusser, and the critical critics.
Environment and Planning A 27, 1163–78.
Castree, N. 1995b. The nature of produced nature. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 27, 13–48.
Castree, N. 1996. Birds, mice and geography: Marxisms and dialectics. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers
NS21, 342–62.
Castree, N. 1999. Editorial: Situating cultural twists and turns. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 17,
257–260.
Castree, N. 2002. The antinomies of Antipode. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 34, 672–8.
Castree, N. 2003. Geographies of nature in the making. In K. Anderson, M. Domosh, S. Pile and N. Thrift (eds)
The Handbook of Cultural Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage, 168–83.
Castree, N. 2004. Environmental issues: signals in the noise? Progress in Human Geography 28, 79–90.
Castree, N. 2005. Nature (Key Ideas in Geography). Abingdon and New York: Routledge.
Castree, N. 2006a. Geography’s new public intellectuals? Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 38, 396–412.
Castree, N. 2006b. The detour of critical theory. In N. Castree and D. Gregory (eds) David Harvey: A critical reader.
Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell, 247–69.
Castree, N. 2011. Commentary. The future of geography in English universities. Geographical Journal 177, 294–9.
Castree, N. and Braun, B. (eds) 2001. Social Nature:Theory, practice and politics. Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell.
Castree, N. and Gregory, D. (eds) 2006. David Harvey: A critical reader. Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell.
Castree, N., Kitchin, R. and Rogers, A. 2013. Anglo-American geography. In N. Castree, R. Kitchin and A. Rogers
A Dictionary of Human Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 16.
Castree, N., Chatterton, P., Heynen, N., Larner, W. and Wright, M. W. (eds) 2010. The Point is to Change It: Geographies
of hope and survival in an age of crisis. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Castree, N., Kitchin, R., Van Weesep, J., Bohle, H.-G,. Kleine, D., Kulke, E., Munton, R., Pawson, E., Aspinall, R.,
Sheppard, E., Berg, L. D., Hoggart, K. and Powell, J. 2006. Research assessment and the production of
geographical knowledge. Progress in Human Geography 30, 747–82.
414 References

Chan, W. F. 2011. Mourning geography: A punctum, Strathclyde and the death of a subject. Scottish Geographical
Journal 127, 255–66.
Chapman, G. P. 1977. Human and Environmental Systems: A geographer’s appraisal. London: Academic Press.
Chapman, G. P. 1982. The Green Revolution Game. Cambridge: Marginal Context.
Chappell, J. E., Jr 1975. The ecological dimension: Russian and American views. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 65, 144–62.
Chappell, J. E., Jr 1976. Comment in reply. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 66, 169–73.
Chappell, J. M. A. and Webber, M. J. 1970. Electrical analogues of spatial diffusion processes. Regional Studies 4,
25–39.
Charlton, M., Rao, L. and Carver, S. 1995. GIS and the census. In S. Openshaw (ed.) Census Users’ Handbook.
Cambridge: GeoInformation International.
Chatterton, P. and Featherstone, D. 2007. Intervention: Elsevier, critical geography and the arms trade. Political
Geography 26, 3–7.
Chatterton, P. and Maxey, L. 2009. Introduction: Whatever happened to ethics and responsibility in geography?
ACME: An International E-Journal for Critical Geographies 8, 429–39.
Chatterton, P., Gidwani, V., Heynen, N., Kent, A., Larner, W. and Pain, R. 2011. Antipode in an antithetical era.
Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 43, 181–9.
Chisholm, G. G., Beckit, H. O. and Ogilvie, A. G. 1913. The American transcontinental excursion of 1912.
Geographical Journal 42, 321–60.
Chisholm, G. G. 1895. Handbook of Commercial Geography. London: Longman.
Chisholm, G. G. 1899. The Times Gazetteer of the World. London: The Times.
Chisholm, M. 1962. Rural Settlement and Land Use. London: Hutchinson.
Chisholm, M. 1966. Geography and Economics. London: G. Bell & Sons.
Chisholm, M. 1967. General systems theory and geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 42,
45–52.
Chisholm, M. 1971a. In search of a basis for location theory: Micro-economics or welfare economics?
In C. Board , R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R. Stoddart (eds) Progress in Geography, Vol. 3. London: Edward
Arnold, 111–34.
Chisholm, M. 1971b. Geography and the question of ‘relevance’. Area 3, 65–8.
Chisholm, M. 1971c. Research in Human Geography. London: Heinemann.
Chisholm, M. 1973. The corridors of geography. Area 5, 43.
Chisholm, M. 1975a. Human Geography: Evolution or revolution? Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Chisholm, M. 1975b. The reformation of local government in England. In R. Peel, M. Chisholm and P. Haggett
(eds) Processes in Physical and Human Geography: Bristol essays. London: Heinemann, 305–18.
Chisholm, M. 1976. Regional policies in an era of slow population growth and higher unemployment. Regional
Studies 10, 201–13.
Chisholm, M. 1995. Some lessons from the review of local government in England. Regional Studies 29,
563–9.
Chisholm, M. 2000. Structural Reform of British Local Government: Rhetoric and reality. Manchester: Manchester University
Press.
Chisholm, M. 2001. Human geography joins the Social Science Research Council: Personal recollections. Area
33, 428–30.
Chisholm, M. and Leach, S. 2008. Botched Business 2006–2008: The damaging process of reorganising local government.
Coleford: Douglas Mclean.
Chisholm, M. and Manners, G. (eds) 1973. Spatial Policy Problems of the British Economy. London: Cambridge
University Press.
Chisholm, M. and O’Sullivan, P. 1973. Freight Flows and Spatial Aspects of the British Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Chisholm, M. and Rodgers, B. (eds) 1973. Studies in Human Geography. London: Heinemann.
Chisholm, M., Frey, A. E. and Haggett, P. (eds) 1971. Regional Forecasting. London: Butterworth.
Chorley, R. J. 1962. Geomorphology and General Systems Theory. Professional Paper 500–B, United States Geological
Survey, Washington, DC.
Chorley, R. J. 1964. Geography and analogue theory. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 54, 127–37.
Chorley, R. J. 1973. Geography as human ecology. In R. J. Chorley (ed.) Directions in Geography. London: Methuen,
155–70.
References 415

Chorley, R. J. 1995. Haggett’s Cambridge: 1957–1966. In A. D. Cliff, P. R. Gould, A. G. Hoare and N. J. Thrift
(eds) Diffusing Geography. Oxford: Blackwell, 355–74.
Chorley, R. J. and Bennett, R. J. 1981. Optimization: Control models. In N. Wrigley and R. J. Bennett (eds)
Quantitative Geography. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 219–24.
Chorley, R. J. and Haggett, P. 1965a. Trend-surface mapping in geographical research. Transactions and Papers, Institute
of British Geographers 37, 47–67.
Chorley, R. J. and Haggett, P. (eds) 1965b. Frontiers in Geographical Teaching. London: Methuen.
Chorley, R. J. and Haggett, P. (eds) 1967. Models in Geography. London: Methuen.
Chorley, R. J. and Kennedy, B. A. 1971. Physical Geography: A systems approach. London: Prentice-Hall International.
Chorley, R. J., Beckinsale, R. and Dunn, A. J. 1973. The History of the Study of Landforms or the Development of Geomorphology.
The life and work of William Morris Davis, Vol. 2. London: Routledge.
Chouinard, V. and Grant, A. 1995. On being not even anywhere near ‘the project’: Ways of putting ourselves in
the picture. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 27, 137–66.
Chouinard, V., Fincher, R. and Webber, M. 1984. Empirical research in scientific human geography. Progress in
Human Geography 8, 347–80.
Chrisman, N. R. 2006. Charting the Unknown: How computer mapping at Harvard became GIS. Redlands, CA: ESRI.
Chrisman, N. R., Cowen, D. J., Fisher, P. F., Goodchild, M. F. and Mark, D. M. 1989. Geographic information
systems. In G. L. Gaile and C. J. Willmott (eds) Geography in America. Columbus, OH: Merrill, 776–96.
Christaller, W. 1966. Central Places in Southern Germany (translated by C. W. Baskin). Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Christensen, K. 1982. Geography as a human science. In P. Gould and G. Olsson (eds) A Search for Common
Ground. London: Pion, 37–57.
Christopherson, S. 1989. On being outside ‘the project’. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 21, 83–9.
Cirincione, C., Darling, T. A. and O’Rourke, T. G. 2000. Assessing South Carolina’s congressional districting.
Political Geography 19, 189–212.
Clark, A. H. 1949. The Invasion of New Zealand by People, Plants and Animals:The South Island. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers
University Press.
Clark, A. H. 1954. Historical geography. In P. E. James and C. F. Jones (eds) American Geography: Inventory and prospects.
Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 70–105.
Clark, A. H. 1977. The whole is greater than the sum of the parts: A humanistic element in human geography.
In D. R. Deskins et al. (eds) Geographic Humanism, Analysis and Social Action: A half century of geography at Michigan.
Ann Arbor, MI: Michigan Geographical Publication No. 17, 3–26.
Clark, G. L. 1982. Instrumental reason and policy analysis. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and
the Urban Environment, Vol. 5. Chichester: John Wiley, 41–62.
Clark, G. L. 1985. Judges and the Cities. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Clark, G. L. 1992. Real regulation reconsidered. Environment and Planning A 24, 615–27.
Clark, G. L. and Dear, M. J. 1984. State Apparatus. Boston, MA: George Allen & Unwin.
Clark, G. L., Feldman, M. P. and Gertler, M. S. 2000. Economic geography: Transition and growth. In G. L. Clark,
M. P. Feldmann and M. S. Gertler (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Economic Geography. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 3–17.
Clark, K. G. T. 1950. Certain underpinnings of our arguments in human geography. Transactions and Papers (Institute
of British Geographers) 16, 15–22.
Clark, M. 1991. Developments in human geography: Niches for a Christian contribution. Area 23,
339–44.
Clark, W. A. V. 1975. Locational stress and residential mobility in a New Zealand context. New Zealand Geographer
31, 67–79.
Clark, W. A. V. 1981. Residential mobility and behavioral geography: Parallelism or interdependence? In K. R.
Cox and R. C. Golledge (eds) Behavioral Problems in Geography Revisited. London: Methuen, 182–205.
Clark, W. A. V. 1991. Geography in court: Expertise in adversarial settings. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers NS16, 5–20.
Clark, W. A. V. 1993. Applying our understanding: Social science in government and the marketplace. Environment
and Planning A Anniversary Issue, 38–47.
Clark, W. A. V. 2002. Pacific views of urban geography in the 1960s. Urban Geography 22, 540–8.
Clarke, D. B. 2006. Postmodern geographies and the ruins of modernity. In S. Aitken and G. Valentine (eds)
Approaches to Human Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage, 107–21.
416 References

Clarke, D. B. and Doel, M. 1995. Transpolitical geography. Geoforum 25, 505–24.


Clarke, D. B., Davies, W. K. D. and Johnston, R. J. 1974. The application of factor analysis in human geography.
Statistician 23, 259–81.
Clarke, G. P. (ed.) 1996. Microsimulation for Urban and Regional Policy Analysis. London: Pion.
Clarke, K. C. 1998. Visualising different geofutures. In P. A. Longley, S. M. Brooks, R. MacDonnell and B.
Macmillan (eds) Geocomputation: A primer. Chichester: John Wiley, 119–37.
Clarke, M. and Holm, E. 1987. Towards an applicable human geography: Some developments and observations.
Environment and Planning A 19, 1525–41.
Clarke, M. and Holm, E. 1988. Microsimulation methods in spatial analysis and planning. Geografiska Annaler 69B,
145–64.
Clarke, M. and Wilson, A. G. 1985. The dynamics of urban spatial structure: The progress of a research
programme. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS10, 427–51.
Clarke, M. and Wilson, A. G. 1989. Mathematical models in human geography. In R. Peet and N. J. Thrift (eds)
New Models in Geography, Vol. 2. London: Unwin Hyman, 30–42.
Clarkson, J. D. 1970. Ecology and spatial analysis. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 60, 700–16.
Clauset, A., Shalizi, C. R. and Newman, M. E. J. 2009. Power–law distributions in empirical data. Siam Review 51,
661–703.
Claval, P. 1981. Epistemology and the history of geographical thought. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Geography, Ideology
and Social Concern. Oxford: Blackwell, 227–39.
Claval, P. 1983. Models of Man in Geography. Syracuse: Department of Geography, Syracuse University, Discussion
Paper 79.
Claval, P. 1999. Historians, geography and the general public in France. In A. Buttimer, S. D. Brunn and U.
Wardenga (eds) Text and Image: Social construction of regional knowledges. Leipzig: Leibniz Institute for Regional
Geography, Beiträge zur regionalen Geographie 49, 70–6.
Claval, P. 2009. National schools of geography. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift et al. (eds) International Encyclopedia of
Human Geography. Oxford: Elsevier, 236–41.
Clayton, D. 2001. Questions of postcolonial geography. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 33, 749–51.
Clayton, D. 2002. Critical imperial and colonial geographies. In K. Anderson, M. Domosh, S. Pile and N. Thrift
(eds) The Handbook of Cultural Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage, 531–57.
Clayton, D. 2011. Colonizing, settling and the origins of academic geography. In J. A. Agnew and J. S. Duncan
(eds) The Wiley-Blackwell Companion to Human Geography. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 50–70.
Clayton, D. and Barnes, T. J. 2015. Continental European geographers and World War II. Journal of Historical
Geography 47, 11–15.
Clayton, K. M. 1985a. New blood by (government) order. Area 17, 321–2.
Clayton, K. M. 1985b. The state of geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS10, 5–16.
Cliff, A. D. and Haggett, P. 1988. Atlas of Disease Distributions: Analytical approaches to epidemiological data. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Cliff, A. D. and Haggett, P. 1989. Spatial aspects of epidemic control. Progress in Human Geography 13, 315–47.
Cliff, A. D. and Haggett, P. 1995. Disease implications of global change. In R. J. Johnston, P. J. Taylor and
M. J. Watts (eds) Geographies of Global Change: Remapping the world in the late twentieth century. Oxford: Blackwell,
206–22.
Cliff, A. D. and Haggett, P. 1998. On complex geographical space: Computing frameworks for spatial diffusion
processes. In P. A. Longley, S. M. Brooks, R. MacDonnell and B. Macmillan (eds) Geocomputation: A primer.
Chichester: John Wiley, 231–56.
Cliff, A. D. and Haggett, P. 2003. The geography of disease distributions. In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams (eds)
A Century of British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 463–501.
Cliff, A. D. and Ord, J. K. 1973. Spatial Autocorrelation. London: Pion.
Cliff, A. D. and Ord, J. K. 1981. Spatial Process. London: Pion.
Cliff, A. D., Haggett, P. and Ord, J. K. 1987. Spatial Aspects of Influenza Epidemics. London: Pion.
Cliff, A. D., Haggett, P. and Smallman-Raynor, M. 1993. Measles: An historical geography of a major human viral disease from
global expansion to local retreat, 1840–1990. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cliff, A. D., Hagett, P., Ord, J. K. and Versey, G. 1981. Spatial Diffusion: An historical geography of epidemics in an island
community. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cliff, A. D., Haggett, P., Ord, J. K., Bassett, K. and Davies, R. B. 1975. Elements of Spatial Structure: A quantitative
approach. London: Cambridge University Press.
References 417

Cliff, A. D., Smallman-Raynor, M., Haggett, P., Stroup, D. F. and Thacker, S. B. 2009. Emergence and Re-emergence.
Infectious Diseases: A geographical analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Clifford, N. 2002. The future of geography: When the whole is less than the sum of the parts. Geoforum 33,
421–5.
Cloke, P. 2004. Enumeration. In P. Cloke, P. Crang and M. Goodwin (eds) Envisioning Human Geographies. London:
Arnold.
Cloke, P. and Goodwin, M. 1992. Conceptualising countryside change: From Post-Fordism to rural structural
coherence. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS17, 321–36.
Cloke, P. 2002. Deliver us from evil? Prospects for living ethically and acting politically in human geography.
Progress in Human Geography 26, 587–604.
Cloke, P., Crang, P. and Goodwin, M. (eds) 1999. Introducing Human Geographies, 1st edn. London: Arnold.
Cloke, P., Crang, P. and Goodwin, M. (eds) 2005. Introducing Human Geographies, 2nd edn. London: Arnold.
Cloke, P., Philo, C. and Sadler, D. 1991. Approaching Human Geography: An introduction to contemporary theoretical debates.
London: Paul Chapman.
Clout, H. D. 2002. John Terence Coppock, 1921–2000. Proceedings of the British Academy 115, 207–24.
Clout, H. D. 2003a. Place description, regional geography and area studies: The chorographic inheritance.
In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams (eds) A Century of British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the
British Academy, 247–74.
Clout, H. D. 2003b. Albert Demangeon, 1872–1940: Pioneer of la géographie humaine. Scottish Geographical Journal 119,
1–24.
Clout, H. D. 2003c. Geography at University College London:  A brief history. Department of Geography, University
College London, London.
Clout, H. D. 2004. Lessons from experience: French geographers and the transcontinental excursion of 1912.
Progress in Human Geography 28, 597–618.
Clout, H. D. 2009. Patronage and the Production of Geographical Knowledge in France: The testimony of the first hundred regional
monographs, 1905–1966. Historical Geography Research Series, 41. London: Royal Geographical Society (with
The Institute of British Geographers).
Clout, H. D. 2011a. Lionel William Lyde (1863–1947). In C. W. J. Withers and H. Lorimer (eds) Geographers:
Biobibliographical studies, Vol. 30. London and New York: Continuum, 1–21.
Clout, H. D. 2011b. Professor Michael Williams 1935–2009. Proceedings of the British Academy 172, 355–75.
Clout, H. D. 2014. Jean Tricart (1920–2003). In H. Lorimer and C. W. J. Withers (eds) Geographers: Biobibliographical
studies, Vol. 33. London: Bloomsbury, 11–42.
Clout, H. D. and Gosme, C. 2003. The Naval Intelligence Handbooks: A monument in geographical writing.
Progress in Human Geography 27, 153–73.
Clout, H. D. and Stevenson, I. 2004. Jules Sion, Alan Grant Ogilvie and the College des Ecossais in Montpellier:
A network of geographers. Scottish Geographical Journal 120, 181–98.
Coates, B. E., Johnston, R. J. and Knox, P. L. 1977. Geography and Inequality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cochrane, A. 1987. What a difference the place makes: The new structuralism of locality. Antipode: A Radical Journal
of Geography 19, 354–63.
Cockings, S. L., Harfoot, A., Martin, D. and Hornby, D. 2011. Maintaining existing zoning systems using
automated zone design techniques for creating the 2011 census geographies for England and Wales.
Environment and Planning A 43, 2399–2418.
Coffey, W. J. 1981. Geography:Towards a general spatial systems approach. London: Methuen.
Cohen, S. B. 1988. Reflections on the elimination of geography at Harvard, 1947–51. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 78, 148–51.
Cole, J. P. 1969. Mathematics and geography. Geography 54, 152–63.
Cole, J. P. and King C. A. M. 1968. Quantitative Geography. London: John Wiley.
Coleman, A. 1985. Utopia on Trial: V  ision and reality in planned housing. London: Hilary Shipman.
Collini, S. 2012. What are Universities For? London: Penguin.
Collins, M. J. 2002. Cold War Laboratory: RAND, the Air Force and the American state, 1945–1950. Washington, DC:
Smithsonian Institute Press.
Colls, R. 2012. Feminism, bodily difference and non-representational geographies. Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers NS 37, 430–45.
Conant, J. B. and Haugeland, J. (eds) 2000. The Road Since Structure: Philosophical essays 1970–1993, with an autobiographical
interview. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
418 References

Conzen, M. P. 1981. The American urban system in the nineteenth century. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston
(eds) Geography and the Urban Environment, Vol. 4. Chichester: John Wiley, 295–348.
Cook, I. and Crang, M. 1995. Doing Ethnographies (CATMOG 58). Norwich: Geo Books.
Cook, I., Crouch, D., Naylor, S. and Ryan, J. R. 2000. Foreword. In I. Cook, D. Crouch, S. Naylor and J. R. Ryan
(eds) Cultural Turns/Geographical Turns: Perspectives on cultural geography. Harlow: Prentice Hall, xi–xii.
Cooke, P. N. 1986. The changing urban and regional system in the United Kingdom. Regional Studies 20,
243–52.
Cooke, P. N. 1987. Clinical inference and geographic theory. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 19, 69–78.
Cooke, P. N. (ed.) 1989a. Localities:The changing face of urban Britain. London: Unwin Hyman.
Cooke, P. N. 1989b. Locality theory and the poverty of ‘spatial variation’ (A response to Duncan and Savage).
Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 21, 261–73.
Cooke, P. N. 1990. Back to the Future: Modernity, postmodernity and locality. London: Unwin Hyman.
Cooke, R. U. 1992. Common ground, shared inheritance: Research imperatives for environmental geography.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS17, 131–51.
Cooke, R. U. 2002. Presidential address. Geographical Journal 168, 260–3.
Cooke, R. U. and Harris, R. 1970. Remote sensing of the terrestrial environment: Principles and progress.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 50, 1–23.
Cooke, R. U. and Reeves, R. W. 1976. Arroyos and Environmental Change in the American South-West. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Cooke, R. U. and Robson, B. T. 1976. Geography in the United Kingdom, 1972–1976. Geographical Journal 142,
3–22.
Coombes, M. G., Dixon, J. S., Goddard, J. B., Openshaw, S. and Taylor, P. J. 1982. Functional regions for the
population census of Great Britain. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and the Urban Environment,
Vol. 5. Chichester: John Wiley, 63–111.
Cooper, A. 1992. New directions in the geography of religion. Area 24, 123–9.
Cooper, W. 1952. The Struggles of Albert Woods. London: Jonathan Cape.
Coppock, J. T. 1974. Geography and public policy: Challenges, opportunities and implications. Transactions of the
Institute of British Geographers 63, 1–16.
Coppock, J. T. and Duffield, B. S. 1975. Recreation in the Countryside: A spatial analysis. London: Macmillan.
Corbridge, S. 1986. Capitalist World Development. London: Macmillan.
Corbridge, S. 1988. Deconstructing determinism. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 20, 239–69.
Corbridge, S. 1989. Marxism, post-Marxism, and the geography of development. In R. Peet and N. J. Thrift (eds)
New Models in Geography, Vol. 1. London: Unwin Hyman, 224–54.
Corbridge, S. 1993. Marxists, modernities, and moralities: Development praxis and the claims of distant
strangers. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 11, 449–72.
Corbridge, S., Martin, R. L. and Thrift, N. J. (eds) 1994. Money, Space and Power. Oxford: Blackwell.
Cormack, L. B. 1997. Charting an Empire: Geography at English universities, 1580–1620. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Cosgrove, D. 1983. Towards a radical cultural geography: Problems of theory. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography
15, 1–11.
Cosgrove, D. 1984. Social Formation and Symbolic Landscape. London: Croom Helm.
Cosgrove, D. 1989a. Geography is everywhere: Culture and symbolism in human landscapes. In D. Gregory and
R. Walford (eds) Horizons in Human Geography. London: Macmillan, 118–35.
Cosgrove, D. 1989b. Models, description and imagination in geography. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling
Geography. Oxford: Blackwell, 23–44.
Cosgrove, D. 1993. Commentary. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 83, 515–17.
Cosgrove, D. 1996. Classics in human geography revisited. Progress in Human Geography 20, 197–9.
Cosgrove, D. 2001. Apollo’s Eye: A cartographic genealogy of the earth in western imagination. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins
University Press.
Cosgrove, D. 2003. Landscape of the European sense of sight – eyeing nature. In K. Anderson, M. Domosh,
S. Pile and N. Thrift (eds) The Handbook of Cultural Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage,
249–68.
Cosgrove, D. and Daniels, S. (eds) 1988. The Iconography of Landscape. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cosgrove, D. and Daniels, S. 1989. Fieldwork as theatre: A week’s performance in Venice and its region. Journal of
Geography in Higher Education 13, 169–82.
References 419

Cosgrove, D. and Jackson, P. 1987. New directions in cultural geography. Area 19, 95–101.
Couclelis, H. 1986a. Artificial intelligence in geography: Conjectures on the shape of things to come. Professional
Geographer 38, 1–10.
Couclelis, H. 1986b. A theoretical framework for alternative models of spatial decision and behavior. Annals of the
Association of American Geographers 76, 95–113.
Couclelis, H. and Golledge, R. G. 1983. Analytic research, positivism, and behavioral geography. Annals of the
Association of American Geographers 73, 331–9.
Couper, P. 2015. A Student’s Introduction to Geographical Thought: Theories, philosophies, methodologies. London, Thousand
Oaks, CA: Sage.
Court, A. 1972. All statistical populations are estimated from samples. Professional Geographer 24, 160–1.
Cowen, D. J. 1983. Automated geography and the DIDS. Professional Geographer 35, 339–40.
Cox, K. R. 1969. The voting decision in a spatial context. In C. Board, R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R. Stoddart
(eds) Progress in Geography, Vol. 1. London: Edward Arnold, 81–118.
Cox, K. R. 1973. Conflict, Power and Politics in the City: A geographic view. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Cox, K. R. 1976. American geography: Social science emergent. Social Science Quarterly 57, 182–207.
Cox, K. R. 1979. Location and Public Problems. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Cox, K. R. 1981. Bourgeois thought and the behavioral geography debate. In K. R. Cox and R. G. Golledge (eds)
Behavioral Problems in Geography Revisited. London: Methuen, 256–79.
Cox, K. R. 1989. The politics of turf and the question of class. In J. Wolch and M. Dear (eds) The Power of Geography.
Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman, 61–90.
Cox, K. R. 1995. Concepts of space, understanding in human geography, and spatial analysis. Urban Geography 16,
304–26.
Cox, K. R. 2013. Notes on a brief encounter: Critical realism, historical materialism and human geography.
Dialogues in Human Geography 3, 3–21.
Cox, K. R. 2014. Making Human Geography. London and New York: Guildford Press.
Cox, K. R. and Golledge, R. G. (eds) 1969. Behavioral Problems in Geography: A symposium. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
University Studies in Geography 17.
Cox, K. R. and Golledge R. G. (eds) 1981. Behavioural Problems in Geography Revisited. London: Methuen.
Cox, K. R. and Macmillan, B. 2001. W. Bunge, theoretical geography. Progress in Human Geography 25, 71–7.
Cox, K. R. and Mair, A. 1989. Levels of abstraction in locality studies. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 21,
121–32.
Cox, K. R. and McCarthy, J. J. 1982. Neighbourhood activism as a politics of turf: A critical analysis. In K. R. Cox
and R. J. Johnston, (eds) Conflict, Politics and the Urban Scene. London: Longman, 196–219.
Cox, K. R., Reynold, D. R. and Rokkan, S. (eds) 1974. Locational Approaches to Power and Conflict. New York: Halsted Press.
Cox, N. J. 1989. Modelling, data analysis and Pygmalion’s problem. In B. MacMillan (ed.) Remodelling Geography.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 204–10.
Cox, N. J. and Jones, K. 1981. Exploratory data analysis. In N. Wrigley and R. J. Bennett Cox (eds) Quantitative
Geography. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 135–43.
Crampton, J. W. 2009. Cartography: Maps 2.0. Progress in Human Geography 33, 91–100.
Crampton, J. W. and Elden, S. (eds) 2007. Space, Knowledge and Power: Foucault and Geography. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Crampton, J. W., Dobson, J. E., Smith, N. and Morin, K. M. 2012. Forum: Karen Morin’s Civic Discipline. Geographical
Review 102, 539–62.
Crane, D. 1972. Invisible Colleges. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Crang, M. 1994. On the heritage trail: Maps of and journeys to olde Englande. Environment and Planning D: Society and
Space 12, 341–56.
Crang, M. 2002. Qualitative methods: The new orthodoxy? Progress in Human Geography 26, 647–55.
Crang, M. and Cook, I. 2007. Doing Ethnographies. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi and Singapore:
Sage.
Crang, M. and Thrift, N. J. (eds) 2000. Thinking Space. London: Routledge.
Crang, M. and Tolia-Kelly, D. P. 2010. Nation, race, and affect: Senses and sensibilities at national heritage sites.
Environment and Planning A 42, 2315–31.
Crang, P. 1992. The politics of polyphony: Reconfigurations in geographical authority. Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space 10, 527–49.
Crang, P. 1995. It’s showtime: On the workplace geographies of display in a restaurant in southeast England.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 12, 675–704.
420 References

Cresswell, T. 2010. New cultural geography – an unfinished project? Cultural Geography 17, 169–74.
Cresswell, T. 2012. Review essay. Nonrepresentational theory and me: Notes of an interested sceptic. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 30, 96–105.
Cresswell, T. 2013. Geographic Thought: A critical introduction. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Crewe, L. 2000. Geographies of retailing and consumption. Progress in Human Geography 24, 275–90.
Cromley, R. G. 1993. Automated geography ten years later. Professional Geographer 45, 442–3.
Crowe, P. R. 1936. The rainfall regime of the Western Plains. Geographical Review 26, 463–84.
Crowe, P. R. 1938. On progress in geography. Scottish Geographical Magazine 54, 1–19.
Crowe, P. R. 1970. Review of Progress in Geography Vol l. Geography 55, 346–7.
Crowther, J. G., Cotter, C. H., Wallis, H., Sadler, D. H. and Hague, R. 1967. Eva G. R. Taylor. Journal of Navigation 20,
94–101.
Crush, J. 1994. Post-colonialism, decolonization and geography. In A. Godlewska and N. Smith (eds) Geography
and Empire. Oxford: Blackwell, 333–50.
Cullen, I. G. 1976. Human geography, regional science, and the study of individual behaviour. Environment and
Planning A 8, 397–411.
Cumberland, K. B. 1947. Soil Erosion in New Zealand. Wellington: Whitcombe & Tombs.
Cumbers, A. 2009. Marxism/Marxist geography I. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of
Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 461–73.
Cupples, J. 2002. The field as a landscape of desire: Sex and sexuality in geographical fieldwork. Area 34, 382–90.
Cupples, J. and Pawson, E. 2012. Giving an account of oneself: The PBRF and the neoliberal university.
New Zealand Geographer 68, 14–23.
Curran, P. J. 1984. Geographic information systems. Area 16, 153–8.
Curran, P. J. 1996. Differential research funding. Area 28.
Curran, P. J. 2000. Competition in UK higher education: Competitive advantage and Porter’s diamond model.
Higher Education Quarterly 54, 386–410.
Curran, P. J. 2001a. Competition in UK higher education: Applying Porter’s diamond model to geography
departments. Studies in Higher Education 26, 223–51.
Curran, P. J. 2001b. Remote sensing: Using the spatial domain. Environmental and Ecological Statistics 8, 331–44.
Curry, L. 1967. Quantitative geography. Canadian Geographer 11, 265–74.
Curry, L. 1972. A spatial analysis of gravity flows. Regional Studies 6, 131–47.
Curry, M. 1982a. The idealist dispute in Anglo-American geography. Canadian Geographer 26, 37–50.
Curry, M. 1982b. The idealist dispute in Anglo-American geography: A reply. Canadian Geographer 26, 57–9.
Curry, M. 1992. Reply. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 82, 310–12.
Curry, M. 1994. Image, practice and the hidden impacts of geographic information systems. Progress in Human
Geography 18, 460–90.
Curry, M. 1995. GIS and the inevitability of ethical inconsistency. In J. Pickles (ed.) Ground Truth:The social implications
of geographical information systems. New York: Guilford Press, 68–87.
Curry, M. 1996. On space and spatial practice in contemporary geography. In C. Earle, K. Mathewson and
M. S. Kenzer (eds) Concepts in Human Geography. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 3–32.
Curry, M. 1998. Digital Places: Living with geographic information technologies. London and New York: Routledge.
Curti, G. H., Aitken. S. C., Bosco, F. J. and Goesrisch D. D. 2011. For not limiting emotional and affectual geo-
graphies: A collective critique of Steve Pile’s ‘Emotions and affect in recent human geography’. Transactions
of the Institute of British Geographers NS 36, 590–4.
Cutter, S. L., Golledge, R. and Graf, W. L. 2002. The big questions in geography. Professional Geographer 54,
305–17.
Cutter, S. L., Richardson, D. B. and Wilbanks, T. J. (eds) 2003. The Geographical Dimensions of Terrorism. London and
New York: Routledge.
Cutter, S. L., Richardson, D. B. and Wilbans, T. J. 2004. The geographical dimensions of terrorism: Future
directions. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 94, 1001–2.
Dacey, M. F. 1962. Analysis of central-place and point patterns by a nearest-neighbor method. In K. Norborg
(ed.) Proceedings of the IGU Symposium in Urban Geography, Lund 1960. Lund: C. W. K. Gleerup, 55–76.
Dacey, M. F. 1968. A review on measures of contiguity for two and k-color maps. In B. J. L. Berry and D. F. Marble
(eds) Spatial Analysis. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 479–95.
Dacey, M. F. 1973. Some questions about spatial distributions. In R. J. Chorley (ed.) Directions in Geography. London:
Methuen, 127–52.
References 421

Dalby, S. 1991. Critical geopolitics: Discourse, difference, and dissent. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 9,
261–83.
Dalby, S. 1994. Gender and critical geopolitics: Reading security discourse in the new world disorder. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 9, 261–83.
Dale, A. 1993. Office of Population Censuses and Surveys longitudinal study. Environment and Planning A 25, 83–6.
Daly, M. T. 1972. Techniques and Concepts in Geography: A review. Melbourne: Thomas Nelson.
Daniels, S. J. 1989. Marxism, culture and the duplicity of landscape. In R. Peet and N. Thrift (eds) New Models in
Geography, Vol. 2. London: Unwin Hyman, 196–220.
Daniels, S. J. 1991. The making of Constable country. Landscape Research 16, 9–18.
Darby, H. C. (ed.) 1936. An Historical Geography of England before 1800. Fourteen Studies. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Darby, H. C. (ed.) 1973. A New Historical Geography of England. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Darby, H. C. 1940a. The Medieval Fenland. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Darby, H. C. 1940b. The Draining of the Fens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Darby, H. C. 1948. The regional geography of Thomas Hardy’s Wessex. Geographical Review 38, 426–43.
Darby, H. C. 1951. The changing English landscape. Geographical Journal 117, 377–98.
Darby, H. C. 1953. On the relations of geography and history. Transactions and Papers, Institute of British Geographers
19, 1–11.
Darby, H. C. 1962. The problem of geographical description. Transactions and Papers, Institute of British Geographers
30, 1–14.
Darby, H. C. 1977. Domesday England. London: Cambridge University Press.
Darby, H. C. 1983a. Historical geography in Britain, 1920–1980: Continuity and change. Transactions of the Institute
of British Geographers NS8, 421–8.
Darby, H. C. 1983b. Academic geography in Britain, 1918–1946. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS8,
14–26.
Darby, H. C. 2002. The Relations of History and Geography: Studies in England, France and the United States (edited by
M. Williams, H. Clout, T. Coppock and H. Prince). Exeter: University of Exeter Press.
Davey, J., Jones, R., Lawrence, V., Stevenson, I., Jenkins, A. and Shepherd, I. D. H. 1995. Issues and trends in textbook
publishing: The views of geography editors/publishers. Journal of Geography in Higher Education 19, 11–28.
Davies, R. B. and Pickles, A. R. 1985. Longitudinal versus cross-sectional methods for behavioural research:
A first-round knockout. Environment and Planning A 17, 1315–30.
Davies, W. K. D. 1972a. Geography and the methods of modern science. In W. K. D. Davies (ed.) The Conceptual
Revolution in Geography. London: University of London Press, 131–9.
Davies, W. K. D. 1972b. Introduction: The conceptual revolution in geography. In W. K. D. Davies (ed.) The
Conceptual Revolution in Geography. London: University of London Press, 9–18.
Davies, W. K. D. 1984. Factorial Ecology. Aldershot: Gower.
Davis, W. M. 1906. An inductive study of the content of geography. Bulletin of the American Geographical Society 38,
67–84.
Dawney, L. 2011. The motor of being: clarifying and defending the concept of affect: a response to Steve Pile’s
‘Emotions and affect in recent human geography’. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS 36, 599–602.
Dawson, J. and Unwin, D. J. 1976. Computing for Geographers. Newton Abbott: David & Charles.
Dawson, J., Larke, R. and Mukoyama, M. (eds) 2006. Strategic Issues in International Retailing. London: Routledge.
Day, M. and Tivers, J. 1979. Catastrophe theory and geography: A Marxist critique. Area 11, 54–8.
Daysh, G. H. J. (ed.) 1949. Studies in Regional Planning. London: Philip & Son.
Dear, M. J. (ed.) 2002. From Chicago to L.A.: Making sense of urban theory. London: Sage.
Dear, M. J. 1987. Society, politics and social theory. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 5, 363–6.
Dear, M. J. 1988. The postmodern challenge: Reconstructing human geography. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers NS13, 262–74.
Dear, M. J. 1991a. The premature demise of postmodern urbanism. Cultural Anthropology 6, 538–52.
Dear, M. J. 1991b. Review of Harvey, The condition of postmodernity. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 81,
533–9.
Dear, M. J. 1994a. Postmodern human geography: An assessment. Erdkunde 48, 2–13.
Dear, M. J. 1994b. Commentary. Who’s afraid of postmodernism? Reflections on Symanski and Cosgrove. Annals
of the Association of American Geographers 84, 295–300.
Dear, M. J. 1995. Practising postmodern geography. Scottish Geographical Magazine 111, 179–81.
422 References

Dear, M. J. 2000. The Condition of Postmodern Urbanism. Oxford: Blackwell.


Dear, M. J. 2001. The politics of geography: Hate mail, rabid referees, and culture wars. Political Geography 20,
1–12.
Dear, M. J. 2011. Historical moments in the rise of the geohumanities. In M. Dear, J. Ketchum, S. Luria and
D. Richardson (eds) GeoHumanities: Art, history, text at the edge of place. Abingdon and New York: Routledge, 309–14.
Dear, M. J. and Clark, G. L. 1978. The state and geographic process: A critical review. Environment and Planning A 10,
173–84.
Dear, M. J. and Dahmann, N. 2008. Urban politics and the Los Angeles school of urbanism. Urban Affairs Review
44, 266–79.
Dear, M. J. and Flusty, S. 1998. Postmodern urbanism. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 88, 50–72.
Dear, M. J. and Flusty, S. 1999. Engaging postmodern urbanism. Urban Geography 20, 412–16.
Dear, M. J. and Flusty, S. 2002. Preface. In M. J. Dear and S. Flusty (eds) Spaces of Postmodernity: Readings in human
geography. Oxford: Blackwell, ix–xiii.
Dear, M. J. and Moos, A. I. 1986. Structuration theory in urban analysis: 2. Empirical application. Environment and
Planning A 18, 351–74.
Dear, M. J. and Scott, A. J. (eds) 1981. Urbanization and Urban Planning in Capitalist Society. London: Methuen.
Dear, P. 2012. Fifty years of Structure. Social Studies of Science 42, 424–28.
Dearden, J. and Wilson, A. G. 2011. Using participatory computer simulation to explore the process of urban
simulation. Transactions in GIS 15, 273–289.
Delaney, D. 2002. The space that race makes. Professional Geographer 54, 6–14.
Delanty, G. 2003. Rethinking Kuhn’s legacy without paradigms: Some remarks on Steve Fuller’s Thomas Kuhn:
A philosophical history for our times. Social Epistemology 17, 153–6.
Delyser, D. and Starrs, P. F. 2001. Doing fieldwork: Editors’ introduction. Geographical Review 91, iv–viii.
Demeritt, D. 1998. Science, social constructivism and nature. In B. Braun and N. Castree (eds) Remaking Reality:
Nature at the millennium. London: Routledge, 177–97.
Demeritt, D. 2008. Dictionaries, disciplines and the future of geography. Geoforum 39, 1811–13.
Dennis, R. J. 1984. English Industrial Cities in the Nineteenth Century: A social geography. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Derrida, J. 1976. Of Grammatology. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Derudder, B. 2011. Some reflections on the ‘problematic’ dominance of ‘Web of Science’ journals in academic
human geography. Area 43, 110–12.
Derudder, B., Hoyler, M., Taylor, P. J. and Witlox, F. (eds) 2012. The International Handbook of Globalization and World
Cities. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Desbarats, J. 1983. Spatial choice and constraints on behavior. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 73,
340–57.
Desbiens, C. 2002. Speaking in tongues, making geographies. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 20, 1–3.
Desbiens, C. and Smith, N. 1999. The international critical geography group: forbidden optimism? Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 18, 379–82.
Detwyler, T. R. and Marcus, M. G. (eds) 1972. Urbanization and Environment. Belmont, CA: Duxbury Press.
Deutsch, R. 1991. Boy’s town. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 9, 5–30.
DeVivo, M. S. 2015. Leadership in American Geography: The twentieth century. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Dewsbury, J.-D. 2014. Inscribing thoughts: the animation of an adventure. Cultural Geographies in Practice 21,
147–152.
Dewsbury, J.-D., Harrison, P., Rose, M. and Wylie, J. 2002. Enacting geographies. Geoforum 33, 437–40.
Dicken, P. 1986. Global Shift. London: Harper & Row.
Dicken, P. 2003. Global Shift:Transforming the world economy. London: Sage.
Dicken, P. 2011. Global Shift: Mapping the changing contours of the world economy, 6th edn. New York: Guildford Press.
Dickens P., Duncan, S. S., Goodwin, M. and Gray, F. 1985. Housing, States and Localities. London: Methuen.
Dickenson, J. P. and Clarks, C. G. 1972. Relevance and the ‘newest geography’. Area 3, 25–7.
Dickinson, R. E. 1930. The regional functions and zones of influence of Leeds and Bradford. Geography 15,
548–57.
Dickinson, R. E. 1933. The distribution and functions of smaller urban settlements of East Anglia. Geography 18,
19–31.
Dickinson, R. E. 1938. Landscape and society. Scottish Geographical Magazine 55, 1–15.
Dickinson, R. E. 1947. City Region and Regionalism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
References 423

Dickinson, R. E. 1976. Regional Concept:The Anglo-American Leaders. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Dingemans, D. 1979. Redlining and mortgage lending in Sacramento. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
69, 225–39.
Dittmer, J. 2010. Popular Culture, Geopolitics, and Identity. Plymouth and Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Dixon, D. P. 2014. The way of the flesh: Life, geopolitics and the weight of the future. Gender, Place & Culture:
A Journal of Feminist Geography 21, 136–51.
Dixon, D. P. and Jones III, J. P. 1996. Editorial: For a supercalifragilisticexpialidocious scientific geography. Annals
of the Association of American Geographers 86, 767–79.
Dixon, D. P. and Jones III, J. P. 2004. What next? Environment and Planning A 36, 381–90.
Dixon, D. P. and Jones III, J. P. 2005. Derridean geographies. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 37, 242–5.
Doan, P. L. 2007. Queers in the American city: Transgendered perceptions of urban space. Gender, Place and Culture
14, 57–74.
Doan, P. L. 2010. The tyranny of gendered spaces – reflections from beyond the gender dichotomy. Gender, Place
and Culture 17, 635–54.
Dobson, J. E. 1983a. Automated geography. Professional Geographer 35, 135–43.
Dobson, J. E. 1983b. Reply to comments on ‘Automated geography’. Professional Geographer 35, 349–53.
Dobson, J. E. 1993. The geographic revolution: A retrospective on the age of automated geography. Professional
Geographer 45, 431–9.
Dodds, K. and Atkinson, D. (eds) 2000. Geopolitical Traditions: A century of geopolitical thought. London and New York:
Routledge.
Dodgson, R. A. 1998. Society in Time and Space: A geographical perspective on change. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Doel, M. A. 1993. Proverbs for paranoids: Writing geography on hollowed ground. Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers NS18, 377–94.
Doel, M. A. 1999. Poststructuralist Geographies: The diabolical art of spatial science. Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh
Press.
Doel, M. A. and Clarke, D. B. 1999. Dark panopticon. Or, attack of the killer tomatoes. Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space 17, 427–50.
Domosh, M. 1991a. Towards a feminist historiography of geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers
NS16, 95–104.
Domosh, M. 1991b. Beyond the frontiers of geographical knowledge. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers
NS16, 488–90.
Domosh, M. and Bondi, L. 2014. Remembering the making of Gender, Place and Culture. Gender, Place and Culture:
A Journal of Feminist Geography 21, 1063-70.
Donaghy, T. 2014. Walter Isard’s evolving sense of the scientific in regional science . . . International Regional Science
Review 37, 78–95.
Dorling, D. 1995. A Social Atlas of Britain. Chichester: John Wiley.
Dorling, D. 1998. Human cartography: When is it good to map? Environment and Planning A 30, 277–88.
Dorling, D. 2010. Injustice:   Why social inequality persists. Bristol: Policy Press.
Dorling, D. 2014. Inequality and the 1%. London: Verso Books.
Dorling, D. and Fairbairn, D. 1997. Mapping:   Ways of representing the world. London: Longman.
Dorling, D. and Shaw, M. 2002. Geographies of the agenda: Public policy, the discipline and its (re)’turns’.
Progress in Human Geography 26, 629–42.
Dorling, D. and Thomas, B. 2011. Bankrupt Britain: An atlas of social change. Bristol: Policy Press.
Dorling, D., Newmman, M. and Barford, A. 2010. The Atlas of the Real World: Mapping the way we live. London: Thames
& Hudson.
Douglas, I. 1983. The Urban Environment. London: Edward Arnold.
Douglas, I. 1986. The unity of geography is obvious. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS11, 459–63.
Douglas, I. 2013. Cities: An environmental history. London: I. B. Tauris.
Downs, R. M. 1970. Geographic space perception: Past approaches and future prospects. In C. Board, R. J.
Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R. Stoddart (eds) Progress in Geography, Vol. 2. London: Edward Arnold, 65–108.
Downs, R. M. 1979. Critical appraisal or determined philosophical skepticism? Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 69, 468–71.
Downs, R. M. and Meyer, J. T. 1978. Geography and the mind. Human geography: Coming of age. American
Behavioral Scientist 22, 59–78.
424 References

Downs, R. M. and Stea, D. (eds) 1973. Image and Environment. London: Edward Arnold.
Downs, R. M. and Stea, D. 1977. Maps in Mind. New York: Harper & Row.
Drake, C. and Horton, J. 1983. Comment on editorial essay: Sexist bias in political geography. Political Geography
Quarterly 2, 329–37.
Driver, F, 1995, Sub-merged identities: Familiar and unfamiliar histories. Annals of the Institute of British Geographers
NS20, 403-4.
Driver, F. 1998. Geography Militant: Cultures of exploration in an age of empire. Oxford: Blackwell.
Driver, F. 2003. On geography as a visual discipline. Antipode 35, 227–31.
Driver, F. and Philo, C. 1986. Implications of ‘scientific’ geography. Area 18, 161–2.
Drysdale, A. and Watts, M. 1977. Modernization and social protest movements. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography
9, 40–55.
Duffy, P. 1995. Literary reflections on Irish migration in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. In R. King,
J. Connell and P. White (eds) Writing  Across   Worlds: Literature and migration. London: Routledge, 20–38.
Dunbar, G. S. (ed.) 2002. Geography: Discipline, profession and subject since 1870. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Dunbar, G. S. 1981. Geography in the University of California (Berkeley and Los Angeles) 1868–1941. In G. S.
Dunbar, The History of Geography: Collected essays. Utica, NY: G. S. Dunbar, 66–75.
Duncan, J. S. 1980. The superorganic in American cultural geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
70, 181–98.
Duncan, J. S. 1985. Individual action and political power: A structuration perspective. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The
Future of Geography. London: Methuen, 174–89.
Duncan, J. S. 1993a. Representing power: The politics and poetics of urban form in the Kandyan Kingdom. In
J. S. Duncan and D. Ley (eds) Place/Culture/Representation. London: Routledge, 232–50.
Duncan, J. S. 1993b. Commentary. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 83, 517–19.
Duncan, J. S. 1994. After the civil war: Reconstructing cultural geography as heterotopia. In K. E. Foote, P. J.
Hugill, K. Mathewson and J. M. Smith (eds) Re-reading Cultural Geography. Austin: University of Texas Press, 401–8.
Duncan, J. S. and Barns, T. S. 1993. Afterword. In T. J. Barnes and J. S. Duncan (eds) Writing W   orlds: Discourse,
text and metaphor in the representation of landscape. London: Routledge, 248–53.
Duncan, J. S. and Ley, D. 1982. Structural Marxism and human geography: A critical assessment. Annals of the
Association of American Geographers 72, 30–59.
Duncan, J. S. and Ley, D. 1993. Introduction: Representing the place of culture. In J. S. Duncan and D. Ley (eds)
Place/Culture/Representation. London: Routledge, 1–21.
Duncan, N. (ed.) 1996a. Body Space: Destabilizing geographies of gender and sexuality. London: Routledge.
Duncan, N. 1996b. Postmodernism in human geography. In C. V. Earle, K. Mathewson and M. S. Kenzer (eds)
Concepts in Human Geography. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 429–58.
Duncan, N. 1999. Postmodernism/postmodernity. In L. McDowell and J. P. Sharp (eds) A Feminist Glossary of Human
Geography. London: Arnold, 211–13.
Duncan, O. D. 1959. Human ecology and population studies. In P. M. Hauser and O. D. Duncan (eds) The Study
of Population. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 678–716.
Duncan, O. D. and Schore, L. F. 1959. Cultural, behavioral and ecological perspectives in the study of social
organization. American Journal of Sociology 65, 132–46.
Duncan, O. D., Cuzzort, R. P. and Duncan, B. 1961. Statistical Geography. New York: The Free Press.
Duncan, S. S. 1974a. Cosmetic planning or social engineering? Improvement grants and improvement areas in
Huddersfield. Area 6, 259–70.
Duncan, S. S. 1974b. The isolation of scientific discovery: Indifference and resistance to a new idea. Science Studies
4, 109–34.
Duncan, S. S. 1975. Research directions in social geography: Housing opportunities and constraints. Transactions
of the Institute of British Geographers NS1, 10–19.
Duncan, S. S. 1979. Radical geography and Marxism. Area 11, 124–6.
Duncan, S. S. 1981. Housing policy, the methodology of levels, and urban research: The case of Castells.
International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 5, 231–54.
Duncan, S. S. 1989a. Uneven development and the difference that space makes. Geoforum 20, 131–9.
Duncan, S. S. 1989b. What is a locality? In R. Peet and N. J. Thrift (eds) New Models in Geography, Vol. 2. London:
Unwin Hyman, 221–54.
Duncan, S. S. and Goodwin, M. 1985. The local state and local economic policy. Capital and Class 27, 14–36.
Duncan, S. S. and Savage, M. 1989. Space, scale and locality. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 21, 179–206.
References 425

Dunford, M. 1990. Theories of regulation. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 8, 297–322.
Dunford, M. and Perrons, D. 1983. The Arena of Capital. London: Macmillan.
Dwyer, C. and Bressey, C. 2008. Introduction: Island geographies: New geographies of race and racism. In C.
Dwyer and C. Bressey (eds) New Geographies of Race and Racism. Aldershot: Ashgate, 1–13.
Dwyer, M. B. and Baird, I. G. 2014. Principled engagement: Political ecologists and their interactions
outside the academy. Introduction to a set of short interventions. ACME: An International E-Journal for Critical
Geographies 13, 473–7.
Dyck, I. 1990. Space, time and renegotiating motherhood: An exploration of the domestic workplace. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 8, 459–83.
Dyck, I. 2011. Embodied life. In V. Del Casino, M. Thomas, P. Cloke and R. Panelli (eds) A Companion to Social
Geography. Oxford: Blackwell, 346–61.
Earle, C. V. 1996. Classics in human geography revisited. Progress in Human Geography 20, 195–7.
Eden, S. 2003. People and the contemporary environment. In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams (eds) A Century of
British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 213–46.
Eilon, S. 1975. Seven faces of research. Operational Research Quarterly 26, 359–67.
Ekers, M., Hart, G., Kipfer, S. and Loftus, A. (eds) 2013. Gramsci: Space, nature, politics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Elden, S. 2013. The Birth of Territory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Elden, S. and Mendietta, E. (eds) 2011. Reading Kant’s Geography. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Elder, G. S. 1999. ‘Queering’ boundaries in the geography classroom. Journal of Geography in Higher Education 23,
86–93.
Eliot Hurst, M. E. 1972. Establishment geography: Or how to be irrelevant in three easy lessons. Antipode: A Radical
Journal of Geography 5, 40–59.
Eliot Hurst, M. E. 1980. Geography, social science and society: Towards a de-definition. Australian Geographical
Studies 18, 3–21.
Eliot, M. E. 1985. Geography has neither existence nor future. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography.
London: Methuen, 59–91.
Ellegård, K. and Svedin, U. 2012. Torsten Hägerstrand’s time – geography as the cradle of the activity approach
in transport geography. Journal of Transport Geography 23, 17–25.
Elliott, P., Cuzick, J., English, D. and Stern, R. (eds) 1996. Geographical and Environmental Epidemiology: Methods for small-
area studies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Elliott, P., Wakefield, J., Best, N. and Briggs, D. (eds) 2001. Spatial Epidemiology: Methods and Applications. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Elwood, S. 2006: Critical issues in participatory GIS: Deconstructions, reconstructions and new research
directions. Transactions in GIS, 10, 693–708.
Elwood, S. 2010. Geographic information science: Emerging research on the societal implications of the
geospatial web. Progress in Human Geography 34, 349–57.
Elwood, S. and Leszczynski, A. 2011. Privacy, reconsidered: New representations, data practices, and the
GeoWeb. Geoforum 42, 6-15.
England, K. (ed.) 1996. Who Will Mind the Baby?: Geographies of childcare and working mothers. London and New York:
Routledge.
England, K. 1994. Getting personal: Reflexivity, positionality and feminist research. Professional Geographer 46,
80–9.
England, K. 1999. Sexing geography, teaching sexualities [1]. Journal of Geography in Higher Education 23, 94–101.
England, K. and Stiell, B. 1997. ‘They think you’re as stupid as your English is’: Constructing foreign domestic
workers in Toronto. Environment and Planning A 29, 195–215.
Entrikin, J. N. 1976. Contemporary humanism in geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 66,
615–32.
Entrikin, J. N. 1980. Robert Park’s human ecology and human geography. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 70, 43–58.
Entrikin, J. N. 1981. Philosophical issues in the scientific study of regions. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston
(eds) Geography and the Urban Environment, Vol. 4. Chichester: John Wiley, 1–27.
Entrikin, J. N. 1989. Place, region, and modernity. In J. A. Agnew and J. S. Duncan (eds) The Power of Place. Boston,
MA: Unwin Hyman, 30–43.
Entrikin, J. N. 1990. Introduction: The Nature of Geography in perspective. In J. N. Entrikin and S. D. Brunn (eds)
Reflections on Richard Hartshorne’s The Nature of Geography. Washington: Association of American Geographers, 1–16.
426 References

Entrikin, J. N. and Tepple, J. H. 2006. Humanism and democratic place-making. In S. Aitken and G. Valentine
(eds) Approaches to Human Geography. London: Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage, 30–41.
Economic and Social Research Council (ESRC) 1988. Horizons and Opportunities in Social Science. London: ESRC.
Evans, M. 1988. Participant observation: The researcher as research tool. In J. Eyles and D. M. Smith (eds)
Qualitative Methods in Human Geography. Cambridge: Polity Press, 197–218.
Eyles, J. 1971. Pouring new sentiments into old theories: How else can we look at behavioural patterns? Area 3,
242–50.
Eyles, J. 1973. Geography and relevance. Area 5, 158–60.
Eyles, J. 1974. Social theory and social geography. In C. Board, R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R. Stoddart (eds)
Progress in Geography, Vol. 6. London: Edward Arnold, 27–88.
Eyles, J. 1981. Why geography cannot be Marxist: Towards an understanding of lived experience. Environment and
Planning A 13, 1371–88.
Eyles, J. 1989. The geography of everyday life. In D. Gregory and R. Walford (eds) Horizons in Human Geography.
London: Macmillan, 102–17.
Eyles, J. and Lee, R. 1982. Human geography in explanation. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS7,
117–21.
Eyles, J. and Smith, D. M. 1978. Social geography. Human geography: Coming of Age. American Behavioral Scientist
22, 41–58.
Eyre, J. D. (ed.) 1978. A Man for All Regions:The contributions of Edward L. Ullman to geography. Chapel Hill, NC: University
of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, Department of Geography, Studies in Geography 11.
Eyre, S. R. 1978. The Real Wealth of Nations. London: Edward Arnold.
Fahey, S., Gibson, K., Huxley, M., Johnson, L. C., Mcoughin, J. B., Walker, J., O’Neill, P., Webber, M. J., Fagan,
R. H., Massey, D. B. and Fincher, R. 1989. Spatial Divisions of Labour in practice. Environment and Planning A 21,
655–700.
Falah, G. 1989. Israelization of Palestine human geography. Progress in Human Geography 13, 535–50.
Falah, G. 1994. The frontier of political criticism in Israeli geographic practice. Area 26, 1–12.
Falah, G. and Nagel, C. (eds) 2005. Geographies of Muslim Women: Gender, religion, and space. London and New York:
Guildford Press.
Falah, G. and Newman, D. 1995. The spatial manifestation of threat: Israelis and Palestinians seek a ‘good
boundary’. Political Geography 14, 689–706.
Falconer Al-Hindi, K. 2000. Focus: Women in geography in the 21st century. Introductory remarks: Structure,
agency, and women geographers in academia at the end of the long twentieth century. Professional Geographer
52, 697–702.
Falconer Al-Hindi, K. 2001. Guest editorial. Do you get it? Feminism and quantitative geography. Environment and
Planning D: Society and Space 19, 505–13.
Fawcett, C. B. 1919. The Provinces of England. London: Williams & Norgate.
Featherston, D. and Painter, J. (eds) 2013. Spatial Politics: Essays for Doreen Massey. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Feldman, E. J. 1986. The citizen-scholar: Education and public affairs. In R. W. Kates and I. Burton (eds) Geography,
Resources and Environment, Vol. 2. Themes from the work of Gilbert F. White. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
188–206.
Fellmann, J. D. 1986. Myth and reality in the origin of American economic geography. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 76, 313–30.
Ferguson, R. I. 2003. Publication practices in physical and human geography: A comment on Nigel Thrift’s
‘The future of geography’. Geoforum 34, 9–11.
Feyerabend, P. 1975. Against Method. London: New Left Books.
Fieldhouse, E., Pattie, C. J. and Johnston, R. J. 1996. Tactical voting and party constituency campaigning at the
1992 British general election in England. British Journal of Political Science 26, 403–18.
Findlay, A. and Werritty, A. 2010. Putting geography in its place. Scottish Geographical Journal 126, 215–30.
Fingleton, B. 1984. Models of Category Counts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fischer, M. M. and Getis, A. (eds) 2009. Handbook of Applied Spatial Analysis: Software tools, methods and applications.
Berlin: Springer.
Fischer, M. M. and Gopal, S. 1993. Neurocomputing – a new paradigm for geographic information processing.
Environment and Planning A 25, 757–60.
Fisher, P. F. 1989a. Geographical information system software for teaching. Journal of Geography in Higher Education
13, 69–80.
References 427

Fisher, P. F. 1989b. Expert system applications in geography. Area 21, 279–87.


Fitzsimmons, M. 1989. The matter of nature. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 21, 106–21.
Fleming, D. K. 1973. The regionalizing ritual. Scottish Geographical Magazine 89, 196–207.
Fleure, H. J. 1919. Human regions. Scottish Geographical Magazine 35, 94–105.
Flint, C. (ed.) 2005. The Geography of War and Peace. New York: Oxford University Press.
Flowerdew, R. 1986. Three years in British geography. Area 18, 263–4.
Flowerdew, R. 1989. Some critical views of modelling in geography. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling Geography.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 245–54.
Flowerdew, R. 1998. Reacting to ground truth. Environment and Planning A 30, 289–302.
Flowerdew, R. 2011. How serious is the modifiable areal unit problem for analysis of English census data?
Population Trends 145, 106–18.
Folch-Serra, M. 1990. Place, voice and space: Mikhail Bakhtin’s dialogical landscape. Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space 8, 255–74.
Foley, B. and Goldstein, H. 2012. Measuring success: League tables in the public sector. London: The British
Academy.
Folke, S. 1972. Why a radical geography must be Marxist. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 4(2), 13–18.
Folke, S. 1973. First thoughts on the geography of imperialism. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 5(3),
16–20.
Folke, S. and Sayer, A. 1991. What’s left to do? Two views from Europe. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 23,
240–8.
Foord, J. and Gregson, N. 1986. Patriarchy: Towards a reconceptualisation. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 18,
186–211.
Foote, D. G. and Greer-Wootten, B. 1968. An approach to systems analysis in cultural geography. Professional
Geographer 20, 86–90.
Ford, L. R. 1982. Beware of new geographies. Professional Geographer 34, 131–5.
Ford, L. R. 2002. Emerging political paradigms. Urban Geography 23, 433–40.
Forer, P. C. 1974. Space through time: A case study with New Zealand airlines. In E. L. Cripps (ed.) Space-time
Concepts in Urban and Regional Models. London: Pion, 22–45.
Foresman, T. W. (ed.) 1998. The History of Geographic Information Systems: Perspectives from the pioneers. Upper Saddle River,
NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Forest, B. 1995. West Hollywood as a symbol: The significance of place in the construction of a gay identity.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 13, 133–57.
Forrester, J. W. 1969. Urban Dynamics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Foster, J., Muellerleile, C., Olds, K. and Peck, J. 2007. Circulating economic geographies: Citation patterns and
citation behaviour in economic geography, 1982–2006. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS32,
295–312.
Fotheringham, A. S. 1981. Spatial structure and distance-decay parameters. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 71, 425–36.
Fotheringham, A. S. 1993. On the future of spatial analysis: The role of GIS. Environment and Planning A Anniversary
Issue, 30–4.
Fotheringham, A. S. 1997. Trends in quantitative methods I: Stressing the local. Progress in Human Geography 21,
81–96.
Fotheringham, A. S. and MacKinnon, R. D. 1989. The National Center for Geographic Information and Analysis.
Environment and Planning A 21, 141–4.
Fotheringham, A. S. and Rogerson, P. A. (eds) 2009. The SAGE Handbook of Spatial Analysis. London: Sage.
Fotheringham, A. S., Brunsdon, C. and Charton, M. E. 2000. Quantitative Geography: Perspectives on spatial data analysis.
London: Sage.
Fotheringham, A. S., Brundson, C. and Charton, M. E. 2002. Geographically Weighted Regression: The analysis of spatially
varying relationships. Chichester: John Wiley.
Foucault, M. 1972. The Archaeology of Knowledge. London: Tavistock Publications.
Franklin, R. S. and Ketchum, J. 2013. Working in a landscape of recession and expansion: Academic jobs in
geography in the United States, 1990–2011. Professional Geographer 65, 205–20.
Freeman, T. W. 1962. A Hundred Years of Geography. Chicago: Aldine.
Freeman, T. W. 1977. Geographers: Biobibliographical studies. London: Mansell.
Freeman, T. W. 1979. The British school of geography. Organon 14, 205–16.
428 References

Freeman, T. W. 1980a. A History of Modern British Geography. London: Longman.


Freeman, T. W. 1980b. The Royal Geographical Society and the development of geography. In E. H. Brown (ed.)
Geography, Yesterday and Tomorrow. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1–99.
Frickel, S. and Gross, N. 2005. A general theory of scientific/intellectual movements. American Sociological Review
70, 204–32.
Fukuyama, F. 1992. The End of History and the Last Man. London: Penguin Books.
Fuller, G. A. 1971. The geography of prophylaxis: An example of intuitive schemes and spatial competition in
Latin America. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 3(1), 21–30.
Fuller, S. 2000. Thomas Kuhn: A philosophical history for our times. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gaile, G. L. and Willmott, C. J. (eds) 1984. Spatial Statistics and Models. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
Gaile, G. L. and Willmott, C. J. (eds) 1989. Geography in America. Columbus, OH: Merrill.
Gaile, G. L. and Willmott, C. J. (eds) 2004. Geography in America at the Dawn of the 21st Century. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Gale, N. and Golledge, R. G. 1982. On the subjective partitioning of space. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 72, 60–7.
Gamble, A. 1988. The Free Economy and the Strong State. London: Macmillan.
Garcia-Ramon, M. D. 2003. Globalization and international geography: The questions of languages and
scholarly traditions. Progress in Human Geography 27, 1–5.
Garcia-Ramon, M. D., Simonsen, K. and Vaiou, D. 2006. Guest Editorial: Does anglophone hegemony permeate
Gender, Place and Culture? Gender, Place and Culture 13, 1–5.
Garrison, W. L. 1953. Remoteness and the passenger utilization of air transportation. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 43, 169.
Garrison, W. L. 1956a. Applicability of statistical inference to geographical research. Geographical Review 46,
427–9.
Garrison, W. L. 1956b. Some confusing aspects of common measurements. Professional Geographer 8, 4–5.
Garrison, W. L. 1959a. Spatial structure of the economy I. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 49, 238–49.
Garrison, W. L. 1959b. Spatial structure of the economy II. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 49,
471–82.
Garrison, W. L. 1960a. Spatial structure of the economy III. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 50,
357–73.
Garrison, W. L. 1960b. Connectivity of the interstate highway system. Papers and Proceedings, Regional Science Association
6, 121–37.
Garrison, W. L. 1962. Simulation models of urban growth and development. In K. Norborg (ed.) IGU Symposium
in Urban Geography, Lund Studies in Geography B 24. Lund: C. W. K. Gleerup, 91–108.
Garrison, W. L. 1979. Playing with ideas. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69, 118–20.
Garrison, W. L. 1995. Living with and loving a no-win situation. International Regional Science Review 17, 327–32.
Garrison, W. L. 2002. Lessons from the design of a life. In P. Gould and F. R. Pitts (eds) Geographical Voices:
Fourteen autobiographical essays. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 99–123.
Garrison, W. L. and Marble, D. F. (eds) 1967a. Quantitative Geography. Part I: Economic and cultural topics. Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Studies in Geography, Number 13.
Garrison, W. L. and Marble, D. F. (eds) 1967b. Quantitative Geography, Part II: Physical and cartographic topics. Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Studies in Geography, Number 14.
Garrison, W. L. and Marble, D. F. 1957. The spatial structure of agricultural activities. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 47, 137–44.
Garrison, W. L., Berry, B. J. L., Marble, D. F., Nystuen, J. D. and Morrill, R. L. 1959. Studies of Highway Development and
Geographic Change. Seattle, WA: University of Washington Press.
Gatrell, A. C. 1982. Geometry in Geography and the Geometry of Geography. Discussion Paper 6, Department of Geography,
Salford: University of Salford.
Gattrell, A. C. 1983. Distance and Space: A geographical perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gatrell, A. C. 1984a. The geometry of a research specialty: Spatial diffusion modelling. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 74, 437–53.
Gatrell, A. C. 1984b. Describing the structure of a research literature: Spatial diffusion modelling in geography.
Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design 11, 29–45.
Gatrell, A. C. 1985. Any space for spatial analysis? In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography. London: Methuen,
190–208.
References 429

Gatrell, A. C. and Lovett, A. A. 1986. The geography of hazardous waste disposal in England and Wales. Area 18,
275–83.
Gatrell, A. C. and Smith, A. 1984. Networks of relations among a set of geographical journals. Professional Geographer
36, 300–7.
Gauthier, H. L. 2002. Edward ‘Ned’ Taaffe (1921–2001). Annals of the Association of American Geographers 92, 573–83.
Gauthier, H. L. and Taaffe, E. J. 2003. Three 20th century ‘revolutiuons’ in American geography. Urban Geography
23, 503–27.
Geary, R. C. 1954. The contiguity ratio and statistical mapping. Incorporated Statistician 5, 115–41.
Geertz, C. 1983. Local Knowledge: Further essays in interpretive anthropology. New York: Basic Books.
Gehlke, C. E. and Biehl, H. 1934. Certain effects of grouping upon the size of the correlation coefficient in
census tract material. Journal of the American Statistical Association, Supplement 29, 169–70.
Gerike, M. J. 2012. Explorations in Historiographies of Geographical Knowledges. PhD thesis. University of Kansas. Available
at: http://hdl.handle.net/2097/15043
Gertler, M. 1992. Flexibility revisited: Districts, nation-states, and the forces of production. Transactions of the
Institute of British Geographers NS17, 259–78.
Getis, A. 1963. The determination of the location of retail activities with the use of a map transformation.
Economic Geography 39, 1–22.
Getis, A. 1993. Scholarship, leadership and quantitative methods. Urban Geography 14, 517–25.
Getis, A. and Boots, B. N. 1978. Models of Spatial Processes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gibbons, W. 2001. ‘Critical of what?’: Past and current issues in critical human geography. History of Intellectual
Culture 1. Available at: www.ucalgary.ca/hic/issues/vol1/4
Gibbs, G. 1995. The relationship between quality in research and quality in teaching. Quality in Higher Education 1,
147–57.
Gibson, K. 1991. Considerations on northern Marxist geography: A review from the Antipodes. Australian
Geographer 22, 75–81.
Gibson, K. and Graham, J. 1992. Rethinking class in industrial geography: Creating a space for alternative
politics of class. Economic Geography 68, 109–27.
Gibson-Graham, J. K. 1994. Stuffed if I know! Reflections on post-modern feminist social research. Gender, Place
and Culture 1, 205–24.
Gibson-Graham, J. K. 1996. The End of Capitalism (As We Knew It): A feminist critique of political economy. Oxford and
Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Gibson-Graham, J. K. 2006. The End of Capitalism (As We Knew It) – With a New Introduction. Minneapolis, MN:
University of Minnesota Press.
Giddens, A. 1976. New Rules of Sociological Method. London: Hutchinson.
Giddens, A. 1981. A Critique of Contemporary Historical Materialism. London: Macmillan.
Giddens, A. 1984. The Constitution of Society. Oxford: Polity Press.
Giddens, A. 1985. The Nation State and Violence. Oxford: Polity Press.
Gier, J. and Walton, J. 1987. Some problems with reconceptualising patriarchy. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography
19, 54–8.
Gilbert, A. 1988. The new regional geography in English- and French-speaking countries. Progress in Human
Geography 12, 208–28.
Gilbert, D. 1995. Between two cultures: Geography, computing and the humanities. Ecumene 2, 1–13.
Gilbert, D. 1996. Between two cultures: Geography, computing and the humanities. Ecumene 2, 1–14.
Gilbert, D. 1999. Sponsorship, academic independence and critical engagement: A forum on Shell, the Ogoni
dispute and the Royal Geographical Society (with the Institute of British Geographers). Ethics, Place and
Environment 2, 219–28.
Gilbert, D. 2009. Time to shell out? Reflections on the RGS and corporate sponsorship. ACME: An International
E-Journal for Critical Geographies 8, 521–9.
Gille, Z. 2010. Reassembling the macrosocial: Modes of production, actor networks and waste regimes. Environment
and Planning A 42, 1049–64.
Gillen, J. 2015. On the spatiality of the academic job market in critical human geography. Social and Cultural
Geography 16, 721–9.
Gilmartin, M. and Berg, L. D. 2007. Locating postcolonialism. Area 39, 120-4.
Gilmore, R. 2002. Race and globalization. In R. J. Johnston, P. J. Taylor and M. J. Watts (eds) Geographies of Global
Change: Remapping the world. Oxford: Blackwell, 261–74.
430 References

Ginsburg, N. S. 1961. Atlas of Economic Development. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.


Ginsburg, N. S. 1972. The mission of a scholarly society. Professional Geographer 24, 1–6.
Ginsburg, N. S. 1973. From colonialism to national development: Geographical perspectives on patterns and
policies. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 63, 1–21.
Glacken, C. J. 1956. Changing ideas of the habitable world. In W. L. Thomas (ed.) Man’s Role in Changing the Face of
the Earth. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 70–92.
Glacken, C. J. 1967. Traces on the Rhodian Shore: Nature and culture in Western thought from ancient times to the end of the eighteenth
century. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Glacken, C. J. 1983. A late arrival in academia. In A. Buttimer (ed.) The Practice of Geography. London: Longman, 20–34.
Glasmeier, A. K. 2005. An Atlas of Poverty in America: One nation, pulling apart, 1960–2003. Abingdon and New York:
Routledge.
Gleeson, B. 1996. A geography for disabled people? Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS21, 63–85.
Glennie, P. and Thrift, N. J. 1996. Shaping the Day: A history of timekeeping in England and Wales, 1300–1800. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Glennie, P. D. and Thrift, N. J. 1992. Modernity, urbanism and modern consumption. Environment and Planning D:
Society and Space 10, 423–44.
Gober, P., Glasmeier, A. K., Goodman, J. M., Plane, D. A., Stafford, H. A. and Wood, J. S. 1995a. Employment
trends in geography, Part 1: Enrollment and degree patterns. Professional Geographer 47, 317–28.
Gober, P., Glasmeier, A. K., Goodman, J. M., Plane, D. A., Stafford, H. A. and Wood, J. S. 1995b. Employment
trends in geography, Part 2: Current demand conditions. Professional Geographer 47, 329–35.
Gober, P., Glasmeier, A. K., Goodman, J. M., Plane, D. A., Stafford, H. A. and Wood, J. S. 1995c. Employment
trends in geography, Part 3: Future demand conditions. Professional Geographer 47, 336–46.
Goddard, J. B. and Armstrong, P. 1986. The 1986 Domesday project. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers
NS11, 279–89.
Godlewska, A. M. C. 1999. Geography Unbound: French geographic science from Cassini to Humboldt. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Goheen, P. G. 1970. Victorian Toronto. Chicago: University of Chicago, Department of Geography, Research Paper
127.
Gold, J. R. 1980. An Introduction to Behavioural Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gold, J. R. 1992. Image and environment: The decline of cognitive-behaviouralism in human geography and
grounds for regeneration. Geoforum 23, 239–47.
Gold, J. R. 2010. Reginald Golledge and behavioural geography. Progress in Human Geography 34, 683–5.
Golinski, J. 1998. Making Natural Knowledge: Constructivism and the history of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Golledge, R. G. 1969. The geographical relevance of some learning theories. In K. R. Cox and R. G. Golledge
(eds) Behavioral Problems in Geography: A symposium. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Studies in Geography
17, 101–45.
Golledge, R. G. 1970. Some equilibrium models of consumer behavior. Economic Geography 46, 417–24.
Golledge, R. G. 1980. A behavioral view of mobility and migration research. Professional Geographer 32, 14–21.
Golledge, R. G. 1981a. Misconceptions, misinterpretations, and misrepresentations of behavioral approaches in
human geography. Environment and Planning A 13, 1325–44.
Golledge, R. G. 1981b. A critical response to Guelke’s ‘Uncritical rhetoric’. Professional Geographer 33, 247–51.
Golledge, R. G. 1983. Models of man, points of view, and theory in social science. Geographical Analysis 15, 57–60.
Golledge, R. G. 1993. Geography and the disabled: A survey with special reference to vision impaired and blind
populations. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS18, 63–85.
Golledge, R. G. 1996. A response to Gleeson and Imrie. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS21,
404–11.
Golledge, R. G. 2002. The nature of geographic knowledge. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 92,
1–14.
Golledge, R. G. 2007. Building on the down-under experience. In L. J. King (ed.) North American Explorations: Ten
memoirs of geographers from down under. Victoria: Trafford Publications, 18–35.
Golledge, R. G. and Amedeo, D. 1968. On laws in geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 58,
760–74.
Golledge, R. G. and Brown, L. A. 1967. Search, learning and the market decision process. Geografiska Annaler B 49,
116–24.
References 431

Golledge, R. G. and Couclelis, H. 1984. Positivist philosophy and research in human spatial behavior. In T. F.
Saarinen, D. Seamon and J. L. Sell (eds) Environmental Perception and Behavior: An inventory and prospect. Chicago:
Department of Geography, University of Chicago, Research Paper 209, 179–90.
Golledge, R. G. and Rayner, J. N. (eds) 1982. Proximity and Preference: Problems in the multidimensional analysis of large data
sets. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Golledge, R. G. and Rushton, G. 1984. A review of analytic behavioural research in geography. In D. T. Herbert
and R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and the Urban Environment, Vol. 6. Chichester: John Wiley, 1–44.
Golledge, R. G. and Stimson R. J. 1997. Spatial Behavior: A geographic perspective. New York: Guilford Press.
Golledge, R. G. and Stimson, R. J. 1987. Analytical Behavioural Geography. London: Croom Helm.
Golledge, R. G. and Timmermans, H. (eds) 1988. Behavioural Modelling in Geography and Planning. London: Croom
Helm.
Golledge, R. G. and Timmermans, H. 1990. Applications of behavioural research on spatial problems:
I. Cognition. Progress in Human Geography 14, 57–100.
Golledge, R. G., Brown, L. A. and Williamson, F. 1972. Behavioral approaches in geography: An overview.
Australian Geographer 12, 59–79.
Golledge, R. G., Couclelis, H. and Gould, P. R. (eds) 1988. A Ground for Common Search. Santa Barbara, CA: The Santa
Barbara Geographical Press.
Golledge, R. G., Church, R., Dozier, J., Estes, J. E., Michaelsen, J., Simonett, D. S., Smith, R., Smith, T. R., Strahler,
A. H. and Tobler, W. R. and Hart, J. F. 1982. Commentary on ‘The highest form of the geographer’s art’. Annals
of the Association of American Geographers 72, 557–9.
Goodchild, M. F. 1992. Geographical information science. International Journal of Geographical Information Systems 6,
31–46.
Goodchild, M. F. 1993. The years ahead: Dobson’s automated geography in 1993. Professional Geographer 45,
444–6.
Goodchild, M. F. 1995a. Future directions for geographic information science. Annals of GIS 1, 1–7.
Goodchild, M. F. 1995b. GIS and geographic research. In J. Pickles (ed.) Ground Truth: The social implications of
geographic information systems. New York: Guilford, 31–50.
Goodchild, M. F. 2009. NeoGeography and the nature of geographic expertise. Journal of Location Based Services 3,
82–96.
Goodchild, M. F. 2010. Twenty years of progress: GIScience in 2010. Journal of Spatial Information Science 1, 3–20.
Goodchild, M. F. and Janelle, D. G. 1988. Specialization in the structure and organization of geography. Annals
of the Association of American Geographers 78, 11–28.
Goodchild, M. F. and Mark, D. M. 1987. The fractal nature of geographic phenomena. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 87, 265–78.
Goodchild, M. F., Yuan, M. and Cova, T. J. 2007. Towards a general theory of geographic representation in GIS.
International Journal of Geographical Information Science 21, 239–60.
Goodson, I. 1981. Becoming an academic subject: Patterns of explanation and evolution. British Journal of Sociology
of Education 2, 163–79.
Goodson, I. 1988. School Subjects and Curriculum Change: Studies in curriculum history. Brighton: The Falmer Press.
Goodwin, M., Duncan, S. and Halford, S. 1993. Regulation theory, the local state, and the transition of urban
politics. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 11, 67–88.
Gordon, P. E. 2012. Forum: Kuhn’s Structure at fifty. Introduction. Modern Intellectual History 9, 73–6.
Gorman-Murray, A. 2008. Masculinity and the home: A critical review and conceptual framework. Australian
Geographer 38, 367–79.
Goss, J. 1995. Marketing the new marketing: The strategic discourse of geodemographic information systems.
In J. Pickles (ed.) Ground Truth:  The social implications of geographic information systems. New York: Guilford, 130–70.
Gottmann, J. 1951. Geography and international relations. World Politics 3, 153–73.
Gottmann, J. 1952. The political partitioning of our world: An attempt at analysis. World Politics 4, 512–19.
Goudie, A. S. 1986a. The Human Use of the Environment. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Goudie, A. S. 1986b. The integration of human and physical geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers
NS11, 454–58.
Goudie, A. S. 1993. Land transformation. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Challenge for Geography: A changing world:
A changing discipline. Oxford: Blackwell, 117–37.
Gould, P. R. 1963. Man against his environment: A game theoretic framework. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 53, 290–7.
432 References

Gould, P. R. 1965. Wheat on Kilimanjaro: The perception of choice within game and learning theory
frameworks. General Systems Theory 10, 157–66.
Gould, P. R. 1969. Methodological developments since the fifties. In C. Board, R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R.
Stoddart (eds) Progress in Geography 1, London: Edward Arnold, 1–50.
Gould, P. R. 1970a. Is statistix inferens the geographical name for a wild goose? Economic Geography 46,
439–48.
Gould, P. R. 1970b. Tanzania 1920–63: The spatial impress of the modernization process. World Politics 22,
149–70.
Gould, P. R. 1972. Pedagogic review. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 62, 689–700.
Gould, P. R. 1973 [1966]. On mental maps (Michigan Inter-University Community of Mathematical
Geographers, Discussion Paper 9, reprint). In R. M. Downs and D. Stea (eds) Image and Environment: Cognitive
mapping and spatial behaviour. London: Edward Arnold, 182–220.
Gould, P. R. 1975. Mathematics in geography: conceptual revolution or new tool? International Social Science Journal
27, 303–27.
Gould, P. R. 1977. What is worth teaching in geography? Journal of Geography in Higher Education 1, 20–36.
Gould, P. R. 1978. Concerning a geographic education. In D. A. Lanegran and R. Palm (eds) An Invitation to
Geography. New York: McGraw-Hill, 202–26.
Gould, P. R. 1979. Geography 1957–1977: The Augean period. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69,
139–51.
Gould, P. R. 1980. Q-analysis, or a language of structure: An introduction for social scientists, geographers and
planners. International Journal of Man-Machine Studies 12, 169–99.
Gould, P. R. 1981a. Letting the data speak for themselves. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 71,
166–76.
Gould, P. R. 1981b. Space and rum: An English note on espacien and rumian meaning. Geografiska Annaler B 63,
1–3.
Gould, P. R. 1985a. The Geographer at Work. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Gould, P. R. 1985b. Will geographical self-reflection make you blind? In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography.
London: Methuen, 276–90.
Gould, P. R. 1988. The only perspective: A critique of Marxist claims to exclusiveness in geographical inquiry.
In R. G. Golledge, H. Couclelis and P. R. Gould (eds) A Ground for Common Search. Santa Barbara, CA: Santa
Barbara Geographical Press, 1–10.
Gould, P. R. 1993. Why not? The search for spatio-temporal structure. Environment and Planning A Anniversary Issue,
48–55.
Gould, P. R. 1994. Sharing a tradition – geographies from the enlightenment. Canadian Geographer 38, 194–202.
Gould, P. R. 1999. Becoming a Geographer. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press.
Gould, P. R. and Ola, D. 1970. The perception of residential desirability in the Western Region of Nigeria.
Environment and Planning 2, 73–8.
Gould, P. R. and Olsson, G. (eds) 1982. A Search for Common Ground. London: Pion.
Gould, P. R. and Pitts, F. R. (eds) 2002. Geographical Voices: Fourteen autobiographical essays. Syracuse: Syracuse
University Press.
Gould, P. R. and White, R. 1974. Mental Maps. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Gould, P. R. and White, R. 1986. Mental Maps, 2nd edn. London: George Allen & Unwin.
Graham, E. 1995. Postmodernism and the possibility of a new human geography. Scottish Geographical Magazine
111, 175–8.
Graham, M. and Shelton, T. 2013. Geography and the future of big data, big data and the future of geography.
Dialogues in Human Geography 3, 255–61.
Granger, A. 1990. The Threatening Desert. London: Earthscan.
Gräno, O. 1981. External influence and internal change in the development of geography. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.)
Geography, Ideology and Social Concern. Oxford: Blackwell, 17–36.
Graves, N. J. 1981. Can geographical studies be subsumed under one paradigm or are a plurality of paradigms
inevitable? Terra 93, 85–90.
Gray, F. 1975. Non-explanation in urban geography. Area 7, 228–35.
Gray, F. 1976. Selection and allocation in council housing. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS1, 34–46.
Green, N. P., Finch, S. and Wiggins, J. 1985. The ‘state of the art’ in Geographical Information Systems. Area 17,
295–301.
References 433

Greenberg, D. 1984. Whodunit? Structure and subjectivity in behavioral geography. In T. F. Saarinen, D. Seamon
and J. L. Sell (eds) Environmental Perception and Behavior: An inventory and prospect. Chicago: Department of Geography,
University of Chicago, Research Paper 209, 191–208.
Greer-Wootten, B. 1972. The Role of General Systems Theory in Geographic Research. Department of Geography, Toronto:
York University, Discussion Paper No. 3.
Gregory, D. 1976. Rethinking historical geography. Area 8, 295–9.
Gregory, D. 1978a. Ideology, Science and Human Geography. London: Hutchinson.
Gregory, D. 1978b. The discourse of the past: Phenomenology, structuralism, and historical geography. Journal of
Historical Geography 4, 161–73.
Gregory, D. 1980. The ideology of control: Systems theory and geography. Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale
Geografie 71, 327–42.
Gregory, D. 1981. Human agency and human geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS6,
1–18.
Gregory, D. 1982a. Regional Transformation and Industrial Revolution: A geography of the Yorkshire woollen industry. London:
Macmillan.
Gregory, D. 1982b. Solid geometry: Notes on the recovery of spatial structure. In P. R. Gould and G. Olsson (eds)
A Search for Common Ground. London: Pion, 187–222.
Gregory, D. 1985a. Suspended animation: The stasis of diffusion theory. In D. Gregory and J. Urry (eds) Social
Relations and Spatial Structures. London: Macmillan, 296–336.
Gregory, D. 1985b. People, places and practices: The future of human geography. In R. King (ed.) Geographical
Futures. Sheffield: Geographical Association, 56–76.
Gregory, D. 1989a. Areal differentiation and post-modern human geography. In D. Gregory and R. Walford
(eds) Horizons in Human Geography. London: Macmillan, 67–96.
Gregory, D. 1989b. The crisis of modernity? Human geography and critical social theory. In R. Peet and
N. J. Thrift (eds) New Models in Geography, Vol. 2. London: Unwin Hyman, 348–85.
Gregory, D. 1990. Chinatown, Part Three? Soja and the missing spaces of social theory. Strategies: A Journal of
Theory, Culture and Politics 3, 40–104.
Gregory, D. 1994. Geographical Imaginations. Oxford: Blackwell.
Gregory, D. 1995a. Between the book and the lamp: Imaginative geographies of Egypt, 1849–50. Transactions of
the Institute of British Geographers NS20, 29–57.
Gregory, D. 1995b. Imaginative geographies. Progress in Human Geography 19, 447–85.
Gregory, D. 1997. Explorations in Critical Human Geography. Heidelberg: Department of Geography, University of
Heidelberg.
Gregory, D. 2004. The Colonial Present: Afghanistan, Palestine, Iraq. Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell.
Gregory, D. 2006. Introduction: Troubling geographies. In N. Castree and D. Gregory (eds) David Harvey: A critical
reader. Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell, 1–25.
Gregory, D. 2009. Geographical imagination. In D. Gregory, R. Johnston, G. Pratt, M. J. Watts and S. Whatmore
(eds) The Dictionary of Human Geography, 5th edn. Malden, MA and Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 282–5.
Gregory, D. and Castree, N. (eds) 2006. David Harvey: A critical reader, Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell.
Gregory, D. and Castree, N. 2012. Editors’ introduction: Human geography. In D. Gregory and N. Castree (eds)
Human Geography (5 vols). London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi and Singapore: Sage, xxv-lxxix.
Gregory, D. and Ley, D. 1988. Culture’s geographies. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 6, 115–16.
Gregory, D. and Urry, J. 1985. Introduction. In D. Gregory and J. Urry (eds) Social Relations and Spatial Structures.
London: Macmillan, 1–8.
Gregory, D. and Walford, R. 1989. Introduction: Making geography. In D. Gregory and R. Walford (eds) Horizons
in Human Geography. London: Macmillan, 1–7.
Gregory, K. J. 2003. Physical geography and geography as an environmental science. In R. J. Johnston and
M. Williams (eds) A Century of British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy,
93–136.
Gregory, S. 1963. Statistical Methods and the Geographer. London: Longman.
Gregory, S. 1976. On geographical myths and statistical fables. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS1,
385–400.
Gregson, N. 1986. On duality and dualism: The case of structuration and time geography. Progress in Human
Geography 10, 184–205.
Gregson, N. 1987a. The CURS initiative: Some further comments. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 19, 364–70.
434 References

Gregson, N. 1987b. Structuration theory: Some thoughts on the possibilities for empirical research. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 5, 73–91.
Gregson, N. 1995. And now it’s all consumption. Progress in Human Geography 19, 135–41.
Gregson, N. and Crang, M. 2014. Waste, resource recovery and labour: Recycling economies in the EU. In
J. Michie and C. Cooper (eds) Why the Social Sciences Matter. Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.
Gregson, N. and Foord, J. 1987. Patriarchy: Comments on critics. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 19, 371–5.
Gregson, N. and Lowe, M. 1994. Servicing the Middle Classes: Class, gender and waged domestic labour in contemporary Britain.
London and New York: Routledge.
Gregon, N. and Rose, G. 1997. Contested and negotiated histories of feminist geographies. In Women
and Geography Study Group (eds) Feminist Geographies: Explorations in diversity and difference. Harlow: Longman,
13–48.
Gregson, N., Crewe, L. and Brooks, K. 2002. Retailing, space and practice. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space
20, 597–617.
Gregson, N., Rose, G., Cream, J. and Laurie, N. 1997. Conclusions. In Women and Geography Study Group (eds)
Feminist Geographies: Explorations in diversity and difference. Harlow: Longman, 191–200.
Gribbin, J. 2002. Science: A history 1543–2001. London: Penguin.
Griffiths, M. J. and Johnston, R. J. 1991. What’s in a place? An approach to the concept of place as illustrated by
the British National Union of Mineworkers’ strike, 1984–1985. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 23,
185–213.
Grigg, D. B. 1977. E. G. Ravenstein and the laws of migration. Journal of Historical Geography 3, 41–54.
Grossman, L. 1977. Man–environment relationships in anthropology and geography. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 67, 126–44.
Gudgin, G. and Taylor, P. J. 1979. Seats,Votes and the Spatial Organisation of Elections. London: Pion. (Reprinted 1992 by
ECPR Press, Colchester.)
Guelke, L. 1971. Problems of scientific explanation in geography. Canadian Geographer 15, 38–53.
Guelke, L. 1974. An idealist alternative in human geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 14,
193–202.
Guelke, L. 1975. On rethinking historical geography. Area 7, 135–8.
Guelke, L. 1976. The philosophy of idealism. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 66, 168–9.
Guelke, L. 1977a. The role of laws in human geography. Progress in Human Geography 1, 376–86.
Guelke, L. 1977b. Regional geography. Professional Geographer 29, 1–7.
Guelke, L. 1978. Geography and logical positivism. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and the Urban
environment: Progress in research and applications, Vol. 1. London: John Wiley, 35–61.
Guelke, L. 1981a. Uncritical rhetoric: ‘A classic disservice’. Professional Geographer 33, 246–7.
Guelke, L. 1981b. Idealism. In M. E. Harvey and B. P. Holly (eds) Themes in Geographic Thought. London: Croom
Helm, 133–47.
Guelke, L. 1982. The idealist dispute in Anglo-American geography: A comment. Canadian Geographer 26, 51–7.
Guelke, L. 1995. Review of Geographical imaginations by Derek Gregory. Canadian Geographer 39, 184–6.
Gutierréz, J. and López-Nieva, P. 2001. Are international journals of human geography really international?
Progress in Human Geography 25, 55–71.
Gutting, G. 1980. Introduction. In G. Gutting (ed.) Paradigms and Revolutions. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1–22.
Habermas, J. 1972. Knowledge and Human Interests. London: Heinemann.
Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hägerstrand, T. 1967. The computer and the geographer. Transactions and Papers of the Institute of British Geographers 42,
1–20.
Hägerstrand, T. 1968. Innovation Diffusion as a Spatial Process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hägerstrand, T. 1975. Space, time and human conditions. In A. Karlquist, L. Lundquist and F. Snickars (eds)
Dynamic Allocation of Urban Space. Farnborough: Saxon House, 3–12.
Hägerstrand, T. 1977. The geographers’ contribution to regional policy: The case of Sweden. In D. R. Deskins
et al. (eds) Geographic Humanism, Analysis and Social Action: A half century of geography at Michigan. Ann Arbor, MI: Michigan
Geographical Publications No. 17, 329–46.
Hägerstrand, T. 1982. Diorama, path and project. Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie 73, 323–39.
Hägerstrand, T. 1984. Presence and absence: A look at conceptual choices and bodily necessities. Regional Studies
18, 373–8.
References 435

Haggett, P. 1964. Regional and local components in the distribution of forested areas in southeast Brazil:
A multivariate approach. Geographical Journal 130, 365–77.
Haggett, P. 1965a. Changing concepts in economic geography. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds) Frontiers in
Geographical  Teaching. London: Methuen, 101–17.
Haggett, P. 1965b. Scale components in geographical problems. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds) Frontiers in
Geographical Teaching. London: Methuen, 164–85.
Haggett, P. 1965c. Locational Analysis in Human Geography. London: Edward Arnold.
Haggett, P. 1967. Network models in geography. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds) Models in Geography. London:
Methuen, 609–70.
Haggett, P. 1969. On geographical research in a computer environment. Geographical Journal 135, 497–507.
Haggett, P. 1972. Geography: A modern synthesis. New York: Harper & Row.
Haggett, P. 1973. Forecasting alternative spatial, ecological and regional futures: Problems and possibilities.
In R. J. Chorley (ed.) Directions in Geography. London: Methuen, 217–36.
Haggett, P. 1978. The spatial economy. Human geography: Coming of age. American Behavioral Scientist 22, 151–67.
Haggett, P. 1990. The Geographers’ Art. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Haggett, P. 1991. Classics in human geography revisited. Progress in Human Geography 15, 300–2.
Haggett, P. 1994. Prediction and predictability in geographical systems. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers
NS19, 6–20.
Haggett, P. 2000. The Geographical Structure of Epidemics. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
Haggett, P. 2001. Geography: A global synthesis. Harlow: Pearson Education.
Haggett, P. 2005. Peter Robin Gould (1932–2000). In P. H. Armstrong and G. J. Martin (eds) Geographers:
Biobibliographical studies, Vol. 24. London and New York: Continuum, 42–62.
Haggett, P. 2012.The Quantocks: Biography of an English region. Chew Magna, Somerset: Point Walter Press.
Haggett, P. 2015. Madingley: Half-century reflections on a geographical experiment. Geography 100, 5–11.
Haggett, P. and Chorley, R. J. 1965. Frontier movements and the geographical tradition. In R. J. Chorley and
P. Haggett (eds) Frontiers in Geographical Teaching. London: Methuen, 358–78.
Haggett, P. and Chorley, R. J. 1967. Models, paradigms, and the new geography. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett
(eds) Models in Geography. London: Methuen, 19–42.
Haggett, P. and Chorley, R. J. 1969. Network Models in Geography. London: Edward Arnold.
Haggett, P. and Chorley, R. J. 1989. From Madingley to Oxford. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling Geography.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, xv–xx.
Haggett, P., Clifee, A. D. and Frey, A. E. 1977. Locational Analysis in Human Geography, 2nd edn. London: Edward
Arnold.
Hagood, M. J. 1943. Development of a 1940 rural farm level of living index for counties. Rural Sociology 8,
171–80.
Hague, E. 2002. Intervention roundtable. Antipode, Inc? Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 34, 655–61.
Haigh, M. J. 1992. The crisis in American geography. Area 14, 185–9.
Haines-Young, R. 1989. Modelling geographical knowledge. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling Geography. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, 22–39.
Haines-Young, R. and Petch, J. R. 1978. The Methodological Limitations of Kuhn’s Model of Science. Salford: University of
Salford, Department of Geography, Discussion Paper 8.
Haines-Young, R. and Petch, J. R. 1985. Physical Geography: Its nature and methods. London: Harper & Row.
Haining, R. P. 1980. Spatial autocorrelation problems. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and the
Urban Environment, Vol. 3. Chichester: John Wiley, 1–44.
Haining, R. P. 1981. Analysing univariate maps. Progress in Human Geography 5, 58–78.
Haining, R. P. 1989. Geography and spatial statistics: Current positions, future developments. In B. Macmillan
(ed.) Remodelling Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 191–203.
Haining, R. P. 1990. Spatial Data Analysis in the Social and Environmental Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Haining, R. P. 2009. Spatial methodologies to support local policing in the UK: Glimpsing the future. 21st
Century Society 4, 161–74.
Haklay, M., Singleton, A. and Parker, C. 2008. Web mapping 2.0. The necrogeography of the GeoWeb. Geography
Compass 2, 2011–39.
Halas, M. 2014. Searching for the perfect footnote: Friedrich Ratzel and the others at the roots of Lebensraum.
Geopolitics 19, 1–18.
436 References

Hall, P. 1974. The new political geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 63, 48–52.
Hall, P. 1981a. Great Planning Disasters. London: Penguin.
Hall, P. 1981b. The geographer and society. Geographical Journal 147, 145–52.
Hall, P. 1982. The new political geography: Seven years on. Political Geography Quarterly 1, 65–76.
Hall, P. 1989. London 2001. London: Unwin Hyman.
Hall, P. 1998. Cities in Civilization: Culture, innovation and urban order. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
Hall, P. 2003. Geographers and the urban century. In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams (eds) A Century of British
Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 545–62.
Hall, P. 2014. Good Cities, Better Lives: How Europe discovered the lost art of urbanism. London: Routledge.
Hall, P., Drewett, R., Gracey, H. and Thomas, R. 1973. The Containment of Urban England. London: Allen & Unwin.
Hall, P., Jackson, P., Massey, D., Robson, B. T., Thrift, N. J. and Wilson, A. G. 1987. Horizons and opportunities in
research. Area 19, 266–72.
Hall, T. 2014. Making their own futures? Research change and diversity amongst contemporary British human
geographers. Geographical Journal 180, 39–51.
Hall, T., Toms, P., McGuinness, M., Parker, C. and Roberts, N. 2015. Where’s the Geography department? The
changing administrative place of Geography in UK higher education. Area 47, 56–64.
Halvorson, P. and Stave, B. M. 1978. A conversation with Brian J. L. Berry. Journal of Urban History 4, 209–38.
Hamilton, F. E. J. 1974. A view of spatial behaviour, industrial organizations, and decision-making. In F. E. I.
Hamilton (ed.) Spatial Perspectives on Industrial Organization and Decision-making. London: John Wiley, 3–46.
Hammett, D. 2012. Tales from the road: Reflections on power and disciplining within the academy. Environment
and Planning A 44, 445–457.
Hamnett, C. 1977. Non-explanation in urban geography: Throwing the baby out with the bath water. Area 9,
143–5.
Hamnett, C. 1991. The blind men and the elephant: The explanation of gentrification. Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers NS16, 259–7.
Hamnett, C. 1997. The sleep of reason? Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 16, 127–8.
Hamnett, C. 2003. Contemporary human geography: Fiddling while Rome burns? Geoforum 34, 1–3.
Hannah, M. and Strohmayer, U. 1992. Postmodernism (s)trained. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 82,
308–10.
Hansen, K. (ed.) 2010. Millennium Cohort Study: First, second, third and fourth surveys – a guide to the datasets. London:
Institute for Education, University of London.
Hanson, S. 1992. Geography and feminism: Worlds in collision? Annals of the Association of American Geographers 82,
569–86.
Hanson, S. 1993. ‘Never question the assumptions’ and other scenes from the revolution. Urban Geography 14,
552–6.
Hanson, S. 2002. Connections. Gender, Place and Culture 9, 301–3.
Hanson, S. 2004. Who are ‘we’? An important question for geography’s future. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 94, 715–22.
Hanson, S. and Pratt, G. 1995. Gender,Work and Space. London: Routledge.
Hare, F. K. 1974. Geography and public policy: A Canadian view. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 63,
25–8.
Hare, F. K. 1977. Man’s world and geographers: A secular sermon. In D. R. Deskins, G. Kish, J. D. Nystuen and
G. Olsson (eds) Geographic Humanism, Analysis and Social Action: Proceedings of symposia celebrating a half century of geography
at Michigan. Ann Arbor, MI: Michigan Geographical Publication No. 17, 259–73.
Haritaworn, J. 2007. Queer mixed race? Interrogating homonormativity through Thai interraciality.
In K. Browne, J. Lim and G. Brown (eds) Geographies of Sexualities: Theory, practices and politics. Farnham and
Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 101–12.
Haritaworn, J. 2007. Shifting positionalities: Reflections on a queer/trans of colour methodology. Sociological
Research Online 13 (1). Available at: www.socresonline.org.uk/13/1/13.html
Haritaworn, J. 2009. Hybrid border crossers? Towards a radical socialisation of ‘mixed race’. Journal of Ethnic and
Migration Studies 35, 115–32.
Haritaworn, J. 2012. The Biopolitics of Mixing: Thai multiracialities and haunted ascendancies. Farnham: Ashgate.
Harland, R. 1987. Superstructuralism:The philosophy of structuralism and post-structuralism. London: Methuen.
Harley, J. B. 1989. Deconstructing the map. Cartographica 26, 1–20.
Harley, J. B. 1990. Cartography, ethics and social theory. Cartographica 27, 1–23.
References 437

Harley, J. B. 1992. Rereading the maps of the Columbian encounter. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
82, 522–42.
Harries, K. D. 1974. The Geography of Crime and Justice. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Harries, K. D. 1975. Rejoinder to Richard Peet: ‘The geography of crime: a political critique’. Professional Geographer
27, 280–2.
Harries, K. D. 1976. Observations on radical versus liberal theories of crime causation. Professional Geographer 28,
100–13.
Harris, C. D. 1954. The market as a factor in the localization of industry in the United States. Annals of the Association
of American Geographers 44, 315–48.
Harris, C. D. 1977. Edward Louis Ullman, 1912–1976. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 67, 595–600.
Harris, C. D. 1978. Patterns of cities. In J. D. Eyre (ed.) A Man for All Regions: The contributions of Edward L. Ullman to
geography. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina, Department of Geography, Studies in Geography No.
11, 66–79.
Harris, C. D. 1990. Urban geography in the United States: The formative years. Urban Geography 11, 403–17.
Harris, C. D. 1992. Areal patterns of cities through time and space: Technology and culture (‘The nature of
cities’ further considered). Colloquium Geographicum 22, 41–53.
Harris, C. D. 1997a. Geographers in the U. S. government in Washington, DC, during World War II. Professional
Geographer 49, 245–56.
Harris, C. D. 1997b. ‘The nature of cities’ and urban geography in the last half century. Urban Geography 18,
15–35.
Harris, C. D. and Ullman, E. L. 1945. The nature of cities. Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 242,
7–17.
Harris, P., Brunsdon, C. and Charlton, M. 2011. Geographically weighted principal components analysis.
International Journal of Geographical Information Science 25, 1717–36.
Harris, R. C. 1971. Theory and synthesis in historical geography. Canadian Geographer 15, 157–72.
Harris, R. C. 1978. The historical mind and the practice of geography. In D. Ley and M. S. Samuels (eds)
Humanistic Geography: Problems and prospects. Chicago: Maaroufa Press, 123–37.
Harris, R., Sleight, P. and Webber, R. 2005. Geodemographics, GIS and Neighbourhood Targeting. Chichester: John
Wiley.
Harrison, P. 2002. The caesura: Remarks on Wittgenstein’s interruption of theory, or, why practices elude
representation. Geoforum 32, 487–503.
Harrison, R. T. and Livingstone, D. N. 1982. Understanding in geography: Structuring the subjective. In D. T.
Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and the Urban Environment, 5. Chichester: John Wiley, 1–40.
Harrison Church, R. J. 1957. West Africa: A study of the environment and man’s use of it. London: Longmans Green.
Hart, J. F. 1982a. The highest form of the geographer’s art. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 72, 1–29.
Hart, J. F. 1982b. Comment in reply. Commentary on ‘The highest form of the geographer’s art’. Annals of the
Association of American Geographers 72, 559.
Hart, J. F. 1990. Canons of good editorship. Professional Geographer 42, 354–8.
Hartshorne, R. 1927. Location as a factor in geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 17, 92–9.
Hartshorne, R. 1939. The Nature of Geography. Lancaster, PA: Association of American Geographers.
Hartshorne, R. 1948. On the mores of methodological discussion in American geography. Annals of the Association
of American Geographers 38, 492–504.
Hartshorne, R. 1954a. Political geography. In P. E. James and C. F. Jones (eds) American Geography: Inventory and
prospect. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 167–225.
Hartshorne, R. 1954b. Comment on ‘Exceptionalism in geography’. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
44, 108–9.
Hartshorne, R. 1955. ‘Exceptionalism in Geography’ re-examined. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 45,
205–44.
Hartshorne, R. 1958. The concept of geography as a science of space from Kant and Humboldt to Hettner. Annals
of the Association of American Geographers 48, 97–108.
Hartshorne, R. 1959. Perspective on the Nature of Geography. Chicago: Rand McNally.
Hartshorne, R. 1972. Review of Kant’s concept of geography. Canadian Geographer 16, 77–9.
Hartshorne, R. 1979. Notes towards a bibliography of The Nature of Geography. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 69, 63–76.
Hartshorne, R. 1984. Meetings: Session 1983–84. Geographical Journal 150, 429.
438 References

Harvey, D. 1967a. Models of the evolution of spatial patterns in geography. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds)
Models in Geography. London: Methuen, 549–608.
Harvey, D. 1967b. Editorial introduction: The problem of theory construction in geography. Journal of Regional
Science 7, 211–16.
Harvey, D. 1969a. Explanation in Geography. London: Edward Arnold.
Harvey, D. 1969b. Review of A. Pred, Behavior and location: Part I. Geographical Review 59, 312–14.
Harvey, D. 1969c. Conceptual and measurement problems in the cognitive-behavioral approach to location
theory. In K. R. Cox and R. G. Golledge (eds) Behavioral Problems in Geography: A symposium. Northwestern
University Studies in Geography 17, 35–68.
Harvey, D. 1970. Behavioral postulates and the construction of theory in human geography. Geographica Polonica
18, 27–46.
Harvey, D. 1972. Revolutionary and counter-revolutionary theory in geography and the problem of ghetto
formation. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 4(2), 1–13.
Harvey, D. 1973. Social Justice and the City. London: Edward Arnold.
Harvey, D. 1974a. A commentary on the comments. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 4(2), 36–41.
Harvey, D. 1974b. Discussion with Brian Berry. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 6(2), 145–8.
Harvey, D. 1974c. What kind of geography for what kind of public policy? Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers 63, 18–24.
Harvey, D. 1974d. Population, resources and the ideology of science. Economic Geography 50, 256–77.
Harvey, D. 1974e. Class-monopoly rent, finance capital and the urban revolution, Regional Studies 8, 239–55.
Harvey, D. 1975a. Class structure in a capitalist society and the theory of residential differentiation. In R. Peel,
M. Chisholm and P. Haggett (eds) Processes in Physical and Human Geography: Bristol essays. London: Heinemann,
354–69.
Harvey, D. 1975b. The political economy of urbanization in advanced capitalist societies: The case of the United
States. In G. Gappert and H. M. Rose (eds) The Social Economy of Cities. Beverly Hills: Sage, 119–63.
Harvey, D. 1975c. Review of B. J. L. Berry, The Human Consequences of Urbanization. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 65, 99–103.
Harvey, D. 1976. The Marxian theory of the state. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 8(2), 80–9.
Harvey, D. 1978. The urban process under capitalism: A framework for analysis. International Journal of Urban and
Regional Research 2, 101–32.
Harvey, D. 1979. Monument and myth. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69, 362–81.
Harvey, D. 1982. The Limits to Capital. Oxford: Blackwell.
Harvey, D. 1984. On the history and present condition of geography: An historical materialist manifesto.
Professional Geographer 36, 1–11.
Harvey, D. 1985. The world-systems theory trap. Studies in Comparative International Development 22, 42–7.
Harvey, D. 1985a. The Urbanization of Capital. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Harvey, D. 1985b. The geopolitics of capitalism. In D. Gregory and J. Urry (eds) Social Relations and Spatial Structures.
London: Macmillan, 128–63.
Harvey, D. 1985c. Consciousness and the Urban Experience. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Harvey, D. 1987. Three myths in search of a reality in urban studies. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space
5, 367–76.
Harvey, D. 1989a. The Condition of Postmodernity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Harvey, D. 1989b. From models to Marx: Notes on the project to ‘remodel’ contemporary geography. In
B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 211–16.
Harvey, D. 1989c. From managerialism to entrepreneurialism: The transformation of urban governance in late
capitalism. Geografiska Annaler 71B, 3–17.
Harvey, D. 1990. Between space and time: Reflections on the geographical imagination. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 80, 418–34.
Harvey, D. 1992. Postmodern morality plays. Antipode:  A Radical Journal of Geography 24, 300–26.
Harvey, D. 1993a. Class relations, social justice and the politics of difference. In M. Keith and S. Pile (eds) Place
and the Politics of Identity. London: Routledge, 41–66.
Harvey, D. 1993b. From space to place and back again: Reflections on the condition of postmodernity. In J. Bird
et al. (eds) Mapping the Futures: Local cultures, global change. London: Routledge, 3–29.
Harvey, D. 1994. The nature of environment: The dialectics of social and environmental change. In R. Miliband
and L. Panitch (eds) Real Problems, False Solutions: Socialist Register 1993. London: The Merlin Press, 1–51.
References 439

Harvey, D. 1995. Militant particularism and global ambition: The conceptual politics of place, space, and
environment in the work of Raymond Williams. Social Text 42, 69–98.
Harvey, D. 1996a. Justice, Nature and the Geography of Difference. Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press.
Harvey, D. 1996b. Cities or urbanization. City 1–2, 38–61.
Harvey, D. 1999. The Limits to Capital, 2nd edn. London: Verso.
Harvey, D. 2000. Spaces of Hope. Berkeley, CA and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Harvey, D. 2002. Memories and desires. In P. Gould and F. R. Pitts, (eds) Geographical Voices: Fourteen autobiographical
essays. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 149–88.
Harvey, D. 2003. The New Imperialism. (Clarendon lectures in geography and environmental studies.) Oxford and
New York: Oxford University Press.
Harvey, D. 2005. ‘For a ruthless criticism of everything existing’: Jim Blaut’s contribution to geographical
knowledge. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 37, 927–35.
Harvey, D. 2005a. The sociological and geographical imaginations. International Journal of Politics, Culture and Society
18, 211–55.
Harvey, D. 2005b. A Brief History of Neoliberalism. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Harvey, D. 2005c. The New Imperialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harvey, D. 2006. The geographies of critical geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS31, 409–12.
Harvey, D. 2009. Cosmopolitanism and the Geographies of Freedom. New York: Columbia University Press.
Harvey, D. 2011. The urban roots of financial crisis: Reclaiming the city for anti-capitalist struggle. Socialist Register
48, 1–35.
Harvey, D. 2012. Rebel Cities: From the right to the city to the urban revolution. London: Verso.
Harvey, D. 2014. Seventeen Contradictions and the End of Capitalism. London: Profile Books.
Harvey, D. and Scott, A. J. 1989. The practice of human geography: Theory and empirical specificity in the
transition from Fordism to flexible accumulation. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling Geography. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 217–29.
Harvey, F. and Wardenga, U. 2006. Richard Hartshorne’s adaptation of Alfred Hettner’s system of geography.
Journal of Historical Geography 32, 422–40.
Harvey, M. E. and Holly, B. P. 1981. Paradigm, philosophy and geographic thought. In M. E. Harvey and B. P.
Holly (eds) Themes in Geographic Thought. London: Croom Helm, 11–37.
Hay, A. M. 1978. Some problems in regional forecasting. In J. I. Clarke and J. Pelletier (eds) Régions géographique et
régions d’aménagement. Collection les hommes et les lettres, 7. Lyon: Editions Hermes.
Hay, A. M. 1979a. Positivism in human geography: Response to critics. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds)
Geography and the Urban Environment, Vol. 2. London: John Wiley, 1–26.
Hay, A. M. 1979b. The geographical explanation of commodity flow. Progress in Human Geography 3, 1–12.
Hay, A. M. 1985a. Scientific method in geography. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography. London: Methuen,
129–42.
Hay, A. M. 1985b. Statistical tests in the absence of samples: A comment. Professional Geographer 37, 334–8.
Hay, A. M. and Jophston, R. J. 1983. The study of process in quantitative human geography. L’Espace Géographique
12, 69–76.
Hayford, A. M. 1974. The geography of women: An historical introduction. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography
6, 1–19.
Haynes, R. M. 1975. Dimensional analysis: Some applications in human geography. Geographical Analysis 7, 51–68.
Haynes, R. M. 1978. A note on dimensions and relationships in human geography. Geographical Analysis 10,
288–92.
Haynes, R. M. 1982. An introduction to dimensional analysis for geographers. CATMOG 33, Norwich: Geo
Books.
Hayter, R. and Watt, H. D. 1983. The geography of enterprise. Progress in Human Geography 7, 157–81.
Heffernan, M. 2000. Balancing visions: Comments on Gearoid O’Tuathail’s Critical geopolitics. Political Geography
19, 347–52.
Heffernan, M. 2001. History, geography and the French national spaces: The question of Alsace-Lorraine,
1914–1918. Space and Polity 5, 27–48.
Heffernan, M. 2003. Histories of geography. In S. L. Holloway, S. P. Rice and G. Valentine (eds) Key Concepts in
Geography. London: Sage, 3–22.
Held, D. 1980. Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas. London: Hutchinson.
Hendrikse, R. P. and Sidaway, J. D. 2010. Neoliberalism 3.0. Environment and Planning A 42, 2037–42.
440 References

Hepple, L. W. 1989. Destroying local Leviathans and designing landscapes of liberty? Public choice theory and
the poll tax. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS14, 387–399.
Hepple, L. W. 1992. Metaphor, geopolitical discourse and the military in South America. In T. J. Barnes and
J. S. Duncan (eds) Writing Worlds: Discourse, text and metaphor in the representation of landscape. London: Routledge,
136–54.
Hepple, L. W. 2008. Geography and the pragmatic tradition: The threefold engagement. Geoforum 39,
1530–41.
Herberet, D. T. and Johnston, R. J. 1978. Geography and the urban environment. In D. T. Herbert and
R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and the Urban Environment, Vol. 1. London: John Wiley, 1–29.
Herbert, S. 2000. For ethnography. Progress in Human Geography 24, 550–68.
Herbertson, A. J. 1905. The major natural regions, Geographical Journal 25, 300–10.
Herod, A. 1999. Reflections on interviewing foreign elites: Praxis, positionality, validity, and the cult of the
insider. Geoforum 30, 313–27.
Herod, A. 2001. Labor Geographies:Workers and the landscapes of capitalism. New York: Guilford.
Herod, A. 2009. Geographies of Globalization. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Herod, A. and Wright, A. (eds) 2002. Geographies of Power: Placing scale. Oxford: Blackwell.
Herod, A., Ó Tuathail, G. and Roberts, S. (eds) 1998. An Unruly World? Globalization, Governance and Geography. London
and New York: Routledge.
Hewitt, K. (ed.) 1983. Interpretations of Calamity. London: George Allen & Unwin.
Hill, M. R. 1982. Positivism: A ‘hidden’ philosophy in geography. In M. E. Harvey and B. P. Holly (eds) Themes in
Geographic Thought. London: Croom Helm, 38–60.
Hinchliffe, S. 1996. Technology, power, and space – the means and ends of geographies of technology. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 14, 659–82.
Hinchliffe, S. 2007. Geographies of Nature: Societies, environments, ecologies. London: Sage.
Hinshaw, R. E. 2006. Living with Nature’s Extremes:The life of Gilbert Fowler White. Boulder, CO: Johnson Books.
Hix, S., Johnston, R. J. and McLean, I. 2010. Choosing an Electoral System. London: The British Academy.
Hodder, I. and Orton, C. 1976. Spatial Analysis in Archaeology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hodgart, R. L. 1978. Optimizing access to public services: A review of problems, models, and methods of
locating central facilities. Progress in Human Geography 2, 17–48.
Hodges, A. 2014 [1983]. Alan Turing:The enigma. London: Vintage.
Hoggart, K., Lees, L. and Davies, A. (eds) 2002. Researching Human Geography. London: Arnold.
Hohn, U. 1994. The bomber’s Baedeker – target book for strategic bombing in the economic warfare against
German towns 1943-45. GeoJournal 34, 213–30.
Hollowat, J. 2000. Institutional geographies of the new age movement. Geoforum 31, 553–65.
Holloway, L. and Hubbard, P. 2001. People and Place:The extraordinary geographies of everyday life. Harlow: Prentice Hall.
Holloway, S. L. and Valentine, G. (eds) 2000. Children’s Geographies: Playing, living, learning. London and New York:
Routledge.
Holmes, J. H. 2002. Geography’s emerging cross-disciplinary links: Process, causes, outcomes and challenges.
Australian Geographical Studies 40, 2–20.
Holt-Jensen, A. 1981. Geography: Its history and concepts. London: Harper & Row.
Holt-Jensen, A. 1988. Geography: Its history and concepts, 2nd edn. London: Harper & Row.
Holt-Jensen, A. 2009. Geography: History and concepts: A student’s guide, 4th edn. London: Sage.
Hook, J. C. 1955. Areal differentiation of the density of the rural farm population in the northeastern United
States. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 45, 189–90.
Hooper, B. 2009. Los Angeles school of post-modern urbanism. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International
Encyclopedia of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 293–7.
Hooson, D. J. M. 1981. Carl O. Sauer. In B. W. Blouet (ed.) The Origins of Academic Geography in the United States.
Hamden, CT: Archon Books, 165–74.
Hooson, D. J. M. 1984. The Soviet Union. In R. J. Johnston and P. Claval (eds) Geography since the Second W   orld
War:  An international survey. London: Croom Helm, 79–106.
Hooson, D. J. M. 2002. Geography in Russia: Glories and disappointments. In G. S. Dunbar (ed.) Geography:
Discipline, profession and subject since 1870. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 225–44.
Hopkins P. and Noble, G. 2009. Masculinities in place: Situated identities, relations and intersectionality.
Social and Cultural Geography 10, 811–19.
Hopkins, P. and Jackson, P. 2013. Researching masculinities and the future of the WGSG. Area 45, 9–10.
References 441

House, J. W. 1973. Geographers, decision takers and policy makers. In M. Chisholm and B. Rodgers (eds) Studies
in Human Geography. London: Heinemann, 272–305.
Howell, P. 2009. Sexuality. In R. Kitchen and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human Geography. Amsterdam:
Elsevier, 59–63.
Howitt, R. 2002. Scale and the other: Levinas and geography. Geoforum 33, 299–313.
Hoyningen-Huene, P. 1993. Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hsu, J.-Y. and Sidaway, J. D. 2009. Commentary: In-between sessions at the AAG. Environment and Planning A 41,
2288–92.
Hubbard, P. 2000. Desire/disgust: Moral geographies of heterosexuality. Progress in Human Geography 24,
191–217.
Hubbard, P. and Kitchin, R. 2007. Battleground geographies and conspiracy theories: A response to Johnston
(2006). Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 32, 428–34.
Hubbard, P., Kitchin, R. and Valentine, G. (eds) 2004. Key Thinkers on Space and Place. London: Sage.
Hubbard, P., Kitchin, R. and Valentine, G. (eds) 2008. Key Texts in Human Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA
and New Delhi and Singapore: Sage.
Hubbard, P., Kitchin, R., Bartley, B. and Fuller, D. 2002. Thinking Geographically: Space, theory and contemporary human
geography. London and New York: Continuum.
Huckle, J. 1985. Geography and schooling. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography. London: Methuen,
291–306.
Hudson, R. 1983. The question of theory in political geography: Outlines for a critical theory approach.
In N. Kliot and S. Waterman (eds) Pluralism and Political Geography. London: Croom Helm, 39–55.
Hudson, R. 1988. Uneven development in capitalist societies. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS13,
484–96.
Hudson, R. 2003. Geographers and the regional problem. In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams (eds) A Century of
British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 583–602.
Hudson, R. 2012. Critical political economy and material transformation. New Political Economy 17, 373–97.
Huggett, R. J. 1980. Systems Analysis in Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Huggett, R. J. 1994. Geoecology: An evolutionary approach. London: Routledge.
Huggett, R. J. and Thomas, R. W. 1980. Modelling in Geography. London: Harper & Row.
Hughes, T. P. 2000. Rescuing Prometheus: Four monumental projects that changed the modern world. New York: Vintage.
Hugill, P. J. and Foote, K. E. 1994. Foreword: Culture and geography: Thirty years of advance. In K. E. Foote,
P. J. Hugill, K. Mathewson and J. M. Smith (eds) Re-reading Cultural Geography. Austin, TX: University of Texas
Press, 9–26.
Huntington, E. 1915. Civilization and Climate. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Huntington, E. 1945. Mainsprings of Civilization. New York: John Wiley.
Huntington, E., Williams, F. E. and Van Valkenburg, S. 1933. Economic and Social Geography. New York: John Wiley.
Hyndman, J. 2001. Towards a feminist geopolitics. Canadian Geographer 45, 210–22.
Imrie, R. F. 1996. Ableist geographies, disablist spaces: Towards a reconstruction of Golledge’s ‘geography and
the disabled’. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS21, 397–403.
Imrie, R. F. 2000. Disability and discourses of mobility and movement. Environment and Planning A 32,
1641–56.
Isard, W. 1956a. Location and Space Economy. New York: John Wiley.
Isard, W. 1956b. Regional science, the concept of region, and regional structure. Papers and Proceedings, Regional Science
Association 2, 13–39.
Isard, W. 1960. Methods of Regional Analysis: An introduction in regional science. New York: John Wiley.
Isard, W. 1975. An Introduction to Regional Science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Isard, W. 2003. History of Regional Science and the Regional Science Association International: The beginnings and early history.
Berlin: Springer.
Isard, W. with Smith, T. and Isard, P., Tung, T. H., Dacey, M. 1969. General Theory: Social, political, economic and regional
with particular reference to decision-making analysis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Isserman, A. M. 1995. The history, status, and future of regional science: An American perspective. International
Regional Science Review 17, 249–96.
Jackson, P. 1984. Social disorganization and moral order in the city. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers
NS9, 168–80.
Jackson, P. 1985. Urban ethnography. Progress in Human Geography 9, 157–76.
442 References

Jackson, P. 1988. Definitions of the situation. In J. Eyles and D. M. Smith (eds) Qualitative Methods in Human
Geography. Cambridge: Polity Press, 49–74.
Jackson, P. 1989. Maps of Meaning: An introduction to cultural geography. London and Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman.
Jackson, P. 1991a. Mapping meanings – a cultural critique of locality studies. Environment and Planning A 23,
215–28.
Jackson, P. 1991b. The cultural politics of masculinity: Towards a social geography. Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers NS16, 199–213.
Jackson, P. 1993a. Changing ourselves: A geography of position. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Challenge for Geography.
A changing world: A changing discipline. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 198–214.
Jackson, P. 1993b. Berkeley and beyond: Broadening the horizons of cultural geography. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 83, 519–20.
Jackson, P. 1999. Postmodern urbanism and the ethnographic void. Urban Geography 20, 400–2.
Jackson, P. and Jacobs, J. M. 1996. Postcolonialism and the politics of race. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space
14, 1–3.
Jackson, P. and Penrose, J. 1993. Introduction: Placing ‘race’ and nation. In P. Jackson and J. Penrose (eds)
Constructions of Race, Place and Nation. London: UCL Press, 1–26.
Jackson, P. and Smith, S. J. 1981. Introduction. In P. Jackson and S. J. Smith (eds) Social Interaction and Ethnic
Segregation. London: Academic Press, 1–18.
Jackson, P. and Smith, S. J. 1984. Exploring Social Geography. London: George Allen & Unwin.
Jackson, P., Smith, S. J. and Johnston, R. J. 1988. An equal opportunities policy for the IBG. Area 20,
279–80.
Jacobs, J. 1994a. Negotiating the heart: Heritage, development and identity in postimperial London. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 12, 751–72.
Jacobs, J. 1994b. Earth honouring: Western desires and indigenous knowledges. In A. Blunt and G. Rose (eds)
Writing Women and Space. New York: Guilford, 169–96.
Jacobs, J. 1996. Edge of Empire: Postcolonialism and the city. London: Routledge.
Jacobs, J. 2001. Postcolonial geography. In N. J. Smelser and P. B. Baltes (eds) International Encyclopedia of the Social and
Behavioral Sciences. Oxford: Elsevier Science, 11838–41.
Jacobs, J. and Jackson, P. 1996. Postcolonialism and the politics of race. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space
14, 1–4.
Jacobs, J. and Lees, L. 2013. Defensible space on the move: Revisiting the urban geography of Alice Coleman.
International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 37, 1559–83.
James, P. E. 1942. Latin America. London: Cassell.
James, P. E. 1952. Toward a further understanding of the regional concept. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 42, 195–222.
James, P. E. 1954. Introduction: The field of geography. In P. E. James and C. F. Jones (eds) American Geography:
Inventory and prospect. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 2–18.
James, P. E. 1965. The President’s session. Professional Geographer 17(4), 35–7.
James, P. E. 1972. All Possible Worlds: A history of geographical ideas. Indianapolis, IN: Odyssey Press.
James, P. E. and Jones, C. F. (eds) 1954. American Geography: Inventory and prospect. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press.
James, P. E. and Martin, G. J. 1978. The Association of American Geographers: The first seventy-five years, 1904–1979.
Washington, DC: The Association of American Geographers.
James, P. E. and Martin, G. J. 1981. All Possible Worlds: A history of geographical ideas, 2nd edn. New York: John Wiley.
James, P. E. and Mather, E. C. 1977. The role of periodic field conferences in the development of geographical
ideas in the United States. Geographical Review 67, 446–61.
Janelle, D. G. 1968. Central-place development in a time-space framework. Professional Geographer 20, 5–10.
Janelle, D. G. 1969. Spatial reorganization: A model and concept. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 59,
348–64.
Janelle, D. G. 1973. Measuring human extensibility in a shrinking world. Journal of Geography 72, 8–15.
Jayne, M., Valentine, G. and Holloway, S. L. 2011. What use are units? Critical geographies of alcohol policy.
Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 44, 828–46.
Jazeel, T. 2014. Subaltern geographies: Geographical knowledge and postcolonial strategy. Singapore Journal of
Tropical Geography 35, 88–103.
Jenkins, A. 1995. The impact of Research Assessment Exercises on teaching in selected geography departments
in England and Wales. Geography 80, 367–74.
References 443

Jenkins, A. and Smith, P. 1993. Expansion, efficiency and teaching quality: The experience of British geography
departments, 1986–1991. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS18, 500–15.
Johannesson, G. T. and Bærenholddt, J. O. 2009. Actor-network theory/network geographies. In R. Kitchin and
N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 15–19.
Johnson, J. H. and Pooley, C. G. (eds) 1982. The Structure of Nineteenth-Century Cities. London: Croom Helm.
Johnson, L. C. 1987. (Un)realist perspectives: Patriarchy and feminist challenges in geography. Antipode: A Radical
Journal of Geography 19, 210–15.
Johnson, L. C. 1989. Geography, planning and gender. New Zealand Geographer 45, 85–91.
Johnson, L. C. 1994. What future for feminist geography? Gender, Place and Culture 1, 103–13.
Johnson, L. C. 2009. Feminism/feminist geography. In R. Kitchen and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of
Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 44–58.
Johnson, L. C. 2012. Feminist geography 30 years on: They came, they saw but did they conquer? Geographical
Research 50, 345–55.
Johnston, R. J. 1969. Urban geography in New Zealand 1945–1969. New Zealand Geographer 25, 121–35.
Johnston, R. J. 1971. Urban Residential Patterns: An introductory review. London: G. Bell & Sons.
Johnston, R. J. 1974. Continually changing human geography revisited: David Harvey: Social Justice and the City.
New Zealand Geographer 30, 180–92.
Johnston, R. J. 1975. But some are more equal . . . who gets what where, and how, in New Zealand. Geography
60, 255–68.
Johnston, R. J. 1976a. Observations on accounting procedures and urban-size policies. Environment and Planning
A 8, 327–40.
Johnston, R. J. 1976b. The World Trade System: Some enquiries into its spatial structure. London: G. Bell & Sons.
Johnston, R. J. 1976c. Anarchy, conspiracy and apathy: The three conditions of geography. Area 8, 1–3.
Johnston, R. J. 1978a. Paradigms and revolutions or evolution: Observations on human geography since the
Second World War. Progress in Human Geography 2, 189–206.
Johnston, R. J. 1978b. Multivariate Statistical Analysis in Geography: A primer on the general linear model. London:
Longman.
Johnston, R. J. 1978c. Political, Electoral and Spatial Systems. London: Oxford University Press.
Johnston, R. J. 1979. Geography and Geographers: Anglo-American human geography since 1945, 1st edn. London: Edward
Arnold.
Johnston, R. J. 1980a. City and Society. London: Penguin.
Johnston, R. J. 1980b. On the nature of explanation in human geography. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers NS5, 402–12.
Johnston, R. J. 1981a. Applied geography, quantitative analysis and ideology. Applied Geography 1, 213–19.
Johnston, R. J. 1981b. Paradigms, revolutions, schools of thought and anarchy: Reflections on the recent history
of Anglo-American human geography. In B. W. Blouet (ed.) The Origins of Academic Geography in the United States.
Hamden, CT: Archon Books, 303–18.
Johnston, R. J. 1982a. On ecological analysis and spatial autocorrelation. In L. le Rouzic (ed.) L’autocorrelation
spatiale. Reims: Travaux de l’Institut de Géographie, 3–16.
Johnston, R. J. 1982b. Geography and the State. London: Macmillan.
Johnston, R. J. 1982c. On the nature of human geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS7,
123–5.
Johnston, R. J. 1983a. Philosophy and Human Geography: An introduction to contemporary approaches, 1st edn. London: Edward
Arnold.
Johnston, R. J. 1983b. Resource analysis, resource management and the integration of human and physical
geography. Progress in Physical Geography 7, 127–46.
Johnston, R. J. 1983c. On geography and the history of geography. History of Geography Newsletter 3, 1–7.
Johnston, R. J. 1984a. The region in twentieth century British geography. History of Geography Newsletter 4,
26–35.
Johnston, R. J. 1984b. Quantitative ecological analysis in human geography: An evaluation of four problem
areas. In G. Bahrenberg, M. Fischer and P. Nijkamp (eds) Recent Developments in Spatial Data Analysis. Aldershot:
Gower, 131–44.
Johnston, R. J. 1984c. Residential Segregation,The State and Constitutional Conflict in American Urban Areas. London: Academic
Press.
Johnston, R. J. 1984d. The world is our oyster. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS9, 443–59.
444 References

Johnston, R. J. 1984e. A foundling floundering in World Three. In M. Billinge, D. Gregory and R. Martin (eds)
Recollections of a Revolution. London: Macmillan, 39–56.
Johnston, R. J. (ed.) 1985a. The Future of Geography. London: Methuen.
Johnston, R. J. 1985b. The Geography of English Politics:  The 1983 general election. London: Croom Helm.
Johnston, R. J. 1985c. Places matter. Irish Geography 18, 58–63.
Johnston, R. J. 1985d. To the ends of the earth. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography. London: Methuen,
326–38.
Johnston, R. J. 1986a. On Human Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Johnston, R. J. 1986b. Four fixations and the quest for unity in geography. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers NS11, 449–53.
Johnston, R. J. 1986c. Philosophy and Human Geography: An introduction to contemporary approaches, 2nd edn. London:
Edward Arnold.
Johnston, R. J. 1986d. Placing politics. Political Geography Quarterly 5, s63–s78.
Johnston, R. J. 1986d. The neighbourhood effect revisited: Spatial science or political regionalism. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 4, 41–56.
Johnston, R. J. 1989. Environmental Problems: Nature, economy and state. London: Belhaven Press.
Johnston, R. J. 1990a. The challenge for regional geography: Some proposals for research frontiers. In
R. J. Johnston, J. Hauer and G. A. Hoekveld (eds) The Challenge of Regional Geography. London: Routledge, 124–41.
Johnston, R. J. 1990b. Some misconceptions about conceptual issues. Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie
81, 14–18.
Johnston, R. J. 1991. A Question of Place: Exploring the practice of human geography. Oxford: Blackwell.
Johnston, R. J. 1992. The rise and decline of the corporate-welfare state: A comparative analysis in global
context. In P. J. Taylor (ed.) Political Geography of the Twentieth Century: A global analysis. London: Belhaven Press,
115–70.
Johnston, R. J. 1993a. Removing the blindfold after the game is over: The financial outcomes of the 1992
Research Assessment Exercise. Journal of Geography in Higher Education 17, 174–80.
Johnston, R. J. 1993b. The geographer’s degrees of freedom: Wreford Watson, postwar progress in human
geography and the future of scholarship in UK geography. Progress in Human Geography 17, 319–32.
Johnston, R. J. 1993c. A voice in the wilderness. Geography 78, 204–7.
Johnston, R. J. 1993d. Meet the challenge: Make the change. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Challenge for Geography:
A changing world: A changing discipline. Oxford: Blackwell, 151–80.
Johnston, R. J. 1993e. Real political geography. Political Geography 12, 473–80.
Johnston, R. J. (ed.) 1993f. The Challenge for Geography: A changing world: A changing discipline. Oxford: Blackwell.
Johnston, R. J. 1994a. Resources, student: Staff ratios and teaching quality in British higher education: Some
speculations aroused by Jenkins and Smith. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS19, 359–65.
Johnston, R. J. 1994b. The ‘quality industry’ in British higher education and the AAG’s publications. Professional
Geographer 46, 491–7.
Johnston, R. J. 1994c. On spatial analysis, place and realism. Urban Geography 15, 290–5.
Johnston, R. J. 1994d. One world, millions of places: The end of History and the ascendancy of Geography.
Political Geography 13, 111–22.
Johnston, R. J. 1995a. Geographical research, geography and geographers in the changing British university
system. Progress in Human Geography 19, 355–71.
Johnston, R. J. 1995b. The business of British geography. In A. D. Cliff, P. R. Gould, A. G. Hoare and N. J. Thrift
(eds) Diffusing Geography: Essays for Peter Haggett. Oxford: Blackwell, 317–41.
Johnston, R. J. 1996a. And now it’s all over was it worth all the effort? Journal of Geography in Higher Education 20,
159–65.
Johnston, R. J. 1996b. The expansion and fragmentation of geography in higher education. In R. J. Huggett,
M. Robinson and Douglas, I. (eds) Companion Encyclopedia of Geography. London: Routledge, 794–817.
Johnston, R. J. 1996c. Jean Gottmann: French regional and political geographer extraordinaire. Progress in Human
Geography 20, 183–93.
Johnston, R. J. 1996d. Nature, State and Economy:  The political economy of environmental problems. Chichester: John Wiley.
Johnston, R. J. 1996e. Academic tribes and territories: The realpolitik of opening up the social sciences.
Environment and Planning A 28.
Johnston, R. J. 1996f. Quality in research, quality in teaching and quality in debate: A response to Graham
Gibbs. Quality in Higher Education 2, 165–70.
References 445

Johnston, R. J. 1997a. Where’s my bit gone? Reflections on Rediscovering Geography. Urban Geography 18, 353–9.
Johnston, R. J. 1997b. Australian geography seen from afar: Through a glass darkly. Australian Geographer 28,
29–37.
Johnston, R. J. 1998. Fragmentation around a defended core: The territoriality of geography. Geographical Journal
164, 139–47.
Johnston, R. J. 1999. Classics in human geography revisited. Progress in Human Geography 23, 253–66.
Johnston, R. J. 2000a. On disciplinary history and textbooks: Or where has spatial analysis gone. Australian
Geographical Studies 38, 125–37.
Johnston, R. J. 2000b. Intellectual respectability and disciplinary transformation? Radical geography and the
institutionalisation of geography in the USA since 1945. Environment and Planning A 32, 971–90.
Johnston, R. J. 2000c. City-regions and a federal Europe: Robert Dickinson and post-World War II reconstruction.
Geopolitics 5, 153–76.
Johnston, R. J. 2002a. Robert E Dickinson and the growth of urban geography: An evaluation. Urban Geography
22, 702–36.
Johnston, R. J. 2002b. Reflections on Nigel Thrift’s optimism: Political strategies to implement his vision.
Geoforum 33, 421–5.
Johnston, R. J. 2003a. Geography: A different sort of discipline? Transaction of the Institute of British Geographers NS29,
133–41.
Johnston, R. J. 2003b. The institutionalisation of geography as an academic discipline. In R. J. Johnston and
M. Williams (eds) A Century of British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy,
45–90.
Johnston, R. J. 2003c. Order in space: Geography as a discipline in distance. In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams
(eds) A Century of British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 303–46.
Johnston, R. J. 2003d. Regionalization and classification. In K. Kempf-Leonard, J. Heckman, G. King and P. Tracy
(eds) Encyclopaedia of Social Measurement. New York: Academic Press, 337–50.
Johnston, R. J. 2004a. Communications technology and the production of geographical knowledge.
In S. D. Brunn, S. L. Cutter and J. W. Harrington Jr. (eds) Geography and Technology. Boston, MA: Kluwer,
17–36.
Johnston, R. J. 2004b. Geography – coming apart at the seams. In N. Castree, A. Rogers and D. Sherman (eds)
Questioning Geography: Fundamental debates. Oxford: Blackwell, 9–25.
Johnston, R. J. 2004c. Institutions and disciplinary fortunes: Two moments in the history of UK geography in
the 1960s – 1. Progress in Human Geography 28, 57–78.
Johnston, R. J. 2004d. Territory and territoriality in a globalizing world. Ekistics 70, 64–70.
Johnston, R. J. 2004e. Disciplinary change and career paths. In R. Lee and D. M. Smith (eds) Geographies and
Moralities: International perspectives on justice, development and place. Oxford: Blackwell , 265–83.
Johnston, R. J. 2005. Learning our history from our pioneers: UK academic geographers in the Oxford Dictionary
of National Biography. Progress in Human Geography 29, 651–67.
Johnston, R. J. 2006. The politics of changing human geography’s agenda: Textbooks and the representation of
increasing diversity. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS31, 286–303.
Johnston, R. J. 2007a. Author’s response. Progress in Human Geography 31, 47–52.
Johnston, R. J. 2007b. On duplicitous battleground conspiracies. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 32,
435–8.
Johnston, R. J. 2008. Emrys Jones. In Proceedings of the British Academy 153: Biographical Memoirs of Fellows VII. Oxford:
Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 243–92.
Johnston, R. J. 2009a. The extent of influence: An alternative approach to identifying dominant contributors to
a discipline’s literature. Scientometrics 78, 409–20.
Johnston, R. J. 2009b. On Geographic and geography. New Zealand Geographer 65, 167–70.
Johnston, R. J. 2009c. On geography, Geography and geographical magazines. Geography 94, 207–14.
Johnston, R. J. 2009d. Popular geographies and geographical imaginations: Contemporary English-language
geographical magazines. GeoJournal 74, 347–62.
Johnston, R. J. 2010a. Book review essay: What every human geography student needs to read to know the
discipline? Progress in Human Geography 34, 528–35.
Johnston, R. J. 2010b. Leslie Curry (1922–2009): The scholar, the teacher and the climatologist. Progress in Human
Geography 34, 387–98.
Johnston, R. J. 2011. Promoting geography (or part of it) – yet again? Professional Geographer 63, 325–331.
446 References

Johnston, R. J. 2012. Seats, votes and the spatial organisation of elections revisited. In G. Gudgin and P. J. Taylor,
Seats,Votes and the Spatial Organisation of Elections. Colchester: ECPR Press, ix–xxxix.
Johnston, R. J. 2013. Review essay. Geographical societies, academics and publics: Reading Civic Discipline:
Geography in America, 1860–1890. Geographical Journal 179, 87–91.
Johnston, R. J. and Brack, E. V. 1983. Appointment and promotion in the academic labour market: A preliminary
survey of British University Departments of Geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS8,
100–11.
Johnston, R. J. and Claval, P. (eds) 1984. Geography Since the Second World War: An international survey. London: Croom
Helm.
Johnston, R. J. and Gregory, S. 1984. The United Kingdom. In R. J. Johnston and P. Claval (eds) Geography Since the
Second World War: An international survey. London: Croom Helm, 107–31.
Johnston, R. J. and Pattie, C. J. 1990. The regional impact of Thatcherism: Attitudes and votes in Great Britain in
the 1980s. Regional Studies 24, 479–93.
Johnston, R. J. and Pattie, C. J. 2000. Ecological inference and entropy-maximizing: An alternative estimation
procedure for split-ticket voting. Political Analysis 8, 333–45.
Johnston, R. J. and Pattie, C. J. 2001. On geographers and ecological inference. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 91, 281–2.
Johnston, R. J. and Pattie, C. J. 2003. Evaluating an entropy-maximizing solution to the ecological inference
problem: Split-ticket voting in New Zealand 1999. Geographical Analysis 35, 1–23.
Johnston, R. J. and Pattie, C. J. 2006. Putting Voters in their Place: Geography and elections in Great Britain. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Johnston, R. J. and Sidaway, J. D. 2004. Geography and Geographers: Anglo-American human geography since 1945, 6th edn.
London: Arnold.
Johnston, R. J. and Sidaway, J. D. 2015. Have the human geographical can(n)ons fallen silent; or were they never
primed? Journal of Historical Geography, 49, 49–60.
Johnston, R. J. and Taylor, P. J. (eds) 1986. A World in Crisis? Geographical Perspectives. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Johnston, R. J. and Taylor, P. J. (eds) 1989. A World in Crisis? Geographical Perspectives, 2nd edn. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Johnston, R. J. and Thrift, N. J. 1993. Ringing the changes: The intellectual history of Environment and Planning
A. Environment and Planning A Anniversary Issue, 14–21.
Johnston, R. J., Jones, K. and Gould, M. 1995. Department size and research in English Universities: Inter-
university variations. Quality in Higher Education 1, 41–7.
Johnston, R. J., Hauer, J. and Hoekveld, G. A. (eds) 1990. Regional Geography: Current developments and future prospects.
London: Routledge.
Johnston, R. J., Poulsen, M. F. and Forrest, J. 2009. Measuring ethnic residential segregation: Putting some more
geography in. Urban Geography 30, 91–109.
Johnston, R. J., Poulsen, M. F. and Forrest, J. 2010. Moving on from indices, refocusing on mix: On measuring
and understanding ethnic patterns of residential segregation. Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 36,
697–706.
Johnston, R. J., Taylor, P. J. and O’Loughlin, I. 1987. The geography of violence and premature death. In Vayrynen,
R. (ed.) The Quest for Peace. London: Sage, 241–59.
Johnston, R. J., Taylor, P. J. and Watts, M. J. (eds) 1995. Geographies of Global Change: Remapping the world in the late twentieth
century. Oxford: Blackwell.
Johnston, R. J., Taylor, P. J. and Watts, M. J. (eds) 2002. Geographies of Global Change: Remapping the world, 2nd edn.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Johnston, R. J., Harris, R., Jones, K. and Manley, D. 2014. A response to Gorard. Psychology of Education Review
38 (Autumn), 5–8.
Johnston, R. J., Jones, K., Haggett, P. and Dodds, K. 2010. Leslie Wilson Hepple (1947–2007). In H. Lorimer
and C. W. J. Withers (eds) Geographers: Biobibliographical studies, Vol. 29. London and New York: Continuum, 73-96.
Johnston, R. J., Pattie, C. J., Dorling, D. F. L. and Rossiter, D. J. 2001. From Votes to Seats: The operation of the UK electoral
system since 1945. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Johnston, R. J., Fairbrother, M., Hayes, D., Hoare, T. and Jones, K. 2008. The Cold War and geography’s
quantitative revolution: Some messy reflections on Barnes’ geographical underworld. Geoforum 39, 1802–6.
Johnston, R. J., Manley, D., Jones, K., Harris, R. and Hoare, A. G. 2015. University admissions and the prediction
of degree performance: An analysis in the light of changes to the English schools’ examination system. Higher
Education Quarterly. doi: 10.1111/hequ.12067
References 447

Johnston, R. J., Harris, R., Jones, K., Manley, D., Sabel, C. E. and Wang, W. W. 2014a. Mutual misunderstanding
and avoidance, misrepresentations and disciplinary politics: Spatial science and quantitative analysis in
(United Kingdom) geographical curricula. Dialogues in Human Geography 4, 3–25.
Johnston, R. J., Harris, R., Jones, K., Manley, D., Sabel, C. E. and Wang, W. W. 2014b. One step forwards but two
steps back to the proper appreciation of spatial science. Dialogues in Human Geography 4, 59–69.
Johnston, R. J., Hepple, L. W., Hoare, A. G., Jones, K. and Plummer, P. 2003. Contemporary fiddling in human
geography while Rome burns: Has quantitative analysis been largely abandoned – and should it? Geoforum 34,
157–61.
Johnston, R. J., Propper, C., Burgess, S., Sarker, R., Bolster, A. and Jones, K. 2005a. Spatial scale and the
neighbourhood effect: Multinomial models of voting at two recent British general elections. British Journal of
Political Science 35, 487–514.
Johnston, R. J., Propper, C., Sarker, R., Jones, K., Bolster, A. and Burgess, S. 2005b. Neighbourhood social capital
and neighbourhood effects. Environment and Planning A 37, 1143–59.
Jonas, A. E. G. 1988. A new regional geography of localities? Area 20, 101–10.
Jonas, A. E. G. 2012. Region and place: Regionalism in question. Progress in Human Geography 36, 263-72.
Jones, A. 1998. (Re)producing gender cultures: Theorizing gender in investment banking recruitment. Geoforum
29, 451–74.
Jones, A. 1999. Dialectics and difference: Against Harvey’s dialectical ‘post-Marxism’. Progress in Human Geography
23, 529–55.
Jones, A. 2009. Marxism/Marxist geographies II. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human
Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 474.
Jones, E. 1956. Cause and effect in human geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 46,
369–77.
Jones, E. 1980. Social geography. In E. H. Brown (ed.) Geography Yesterday and Tomorrow. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 251–62.
Jones III, J. P. and Casetti, E. (eds) 1992. Applications of the Expansion Method. London: Routledge.
Jones III, J. P. and Dixon D. P. 2004, Guest editorial. What next? Environment and Planning A 36, 381–90.
Jones III, J. P. and Hanham, R. Q. 1995. Contingency, realism and the expansion method. Geographical Analysis 4,
185–207.
Jones III, J. P., Nast, H. and Roberts, S. (eds) 1997. Thresholds in Feminist Geography. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Jones, K. 1984. Graphical methods for exploring relationships. In G. Bahrenberg, M. M. Fischer and P. Nijkamp
(eds) Recent Developments in Spatial Data Analysis. Aldershot: Gower, 215–30.
Jones, K. 1991. Specifying and estimating multi-level models for geographical research. Transactions of the Institute
of British Geographers NS16, 148–60.
Jones, K. 1997. Multilevel approaches to modeling contextuality: From nuisance to substance in the analysis
of voting behaviour. In G. P. Westert and R. N. Verhoeef (eds) Places and People: Multilevel modeling in geographical
research. Nederlandse Geografische Studies no. 227. Utrecht: Royal Dutch Geographical Society and Faculty of
Geosciences, Utrecht University, 19–43.
Jones, K. 2010. The practice of quantitative methods. In B. Somekh and C. Lewin (eds) Research Methods in the Social
Sciences, 2nd edn. London: Sage, 201–11.
Jones, K. and Almond, S. 1992. Moving out of the linear rut: The possibilities of generalized additive models.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS17, 434–47.
Jones, K. and Bullen, N. 1994. Contextual models of urban house prices: A comparison of fixed- and random-
coefficient models developed by expansion. Economic Geography 70, 252–72.
Jones, K. and Duncan, C. 1996. People and places: The multilevel model as a general framework for the
quantitative analysis of geographical data. In P. A. Longley and M. Batty (eds) Spatial Analysis: Geographical modelling
in a GIS environment. New York: John Wiley, 1–16.
Jones, K. and Duncan, C. 1998. Modelling context and heterogeneity: Applying multilevel models. In E.
Scarbrough and E. Tanenbaum (eds) Research Strategies in the Social Sciences: A guide to new approaches, Volume 9.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 94–123.
Jones, K. and Wrigley, N. 1995. Generalized additive models, graphical diagnostics and logistic regression.
Geographical Analysis 27, 1–21.
Jones, K., Johnston, R. J. and Pattie, C. J. 1992. People, places and regions: Exploring the use of multi-level
modelling in the analysis of electoral data. British Journal of Political Science 22, 343–80.
448 References

Jones, L. V., Lindley, G. and Coggeshall, P. E. (eds) 1982. An Assessment of Research-Doctorate Programs in the United States:
Social and behavioral sciences. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
Joseph, A. E. and Phillips, D. R. 1984. Accessibility and Utilization: Perspectives on health care delivery. London: Harper &
Row.
Kahneman, D. 2012. Thinking Fast and Slow. London: Penguin.
Kain, R. and Delano-Smith, C. 2003. Geography displayed: Maps and mapping. In R. J. Johnston and
M. Williams (eds) A Century of British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy,
371–427.
Kansky, K. J. 1963. Structure of Transportation Networks. Chicago: University of Chicago, Department of Geography,
Research Paper 84.
Kaolan, R. 2012. The Revenge of Geography: What the map tells us about coming conflicts and the battle against fate. New York:
Random House
Kariya, P. 1993. The Department of Indian Affairs and Northern Development: The culture-building process
within an institution. In J. S. Duncan and D. Ley (eds) Place/Culture/Representation. London: Routledge,
187–204.
Kasbarian, J. A. 1996. Mapping Edward Said: Geography, identity, and the politics of location. Environment and
Planning D: Society and Space 14, 529–57.
Kasperson, R. E. 1971. The post-behavioral revolution in geography. British Columbia Geographical Series 12,
5–20.
Kates, R. W. 1962. Hazard and Choice Perception in Flood Plain Management. Chicago: University of Chicago, Department
of Geography, Research Paper 78.
Kates, R. W. 1972. Review of Perspectives on Resource Management. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 62,
519–20.
Kates, R. W. 1987. The human environment: The road not taken, the road still beckoning. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 77, 525–34.
Kates, R. W. 1995. Labnotes from the Jeremiad experiment: Hope for a sustainable transition. Annals of the
Association of American Geographers 85, 623–40.
Kates, R. W. and Burton, I. (eds) 1986a. Geography Resources and Environment (2 vols). Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Kates, R. W. and Burton, I. 1986b. Introduction. In R. W. Kates and I. Burton (eds) Geography, Resources and Environment,
Vol. 1. Selected writings of Gilbert F. White. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, xi–xiv.
Katz, C. and Monk, J. (eds) 1993. Full Circles: Geographies of women over the life course. London and New York: Routledge.
Kearn, L., Hawkins, R., Al-Hindi, K. F., Moss, P. 2014, A collective biography of joy in academic practice. Social
and Cultural Geography 15, 834–51.
Kearns, G. 1984. Closed space and political practice: Frederick Jackson Turner and Halford Mackinder. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 2, 23–34.
Kearns, G. 2009. Geopolitics and Empire:  The legacy of Halford Mackinder. New York: Oxford University Press.
Keighren, I. M. 2006. Bringing geography to the book: Charting the reception of Influences of Geographic Environment.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 31, 525-40.
Keighren, I. M. 2010. Bringing Geography to Book: Ellen Semple and the reception of geographical knowledge. London: I.B. Taurus.
Keighren, I. M., Abrahamsson, C. and Della Dora, V. 2012. On canonical geographies. Dialogues in Human Geography
2, 296–312.
Keighren, I. M. (ed.) 2015. Teaching the history of geography: Current challenges and future directions. Progress
in Human Geography. doi: 10.1177/0309132515575940
Kelly, A. and Burrows, R. 2011. Measuring the value of sociology? Some notes on performative metricization
in the contemporary academy. Sociological Review 59, 130–50.
Keltie, J. S. 1886. Report of the Proceedings of the Royal Geographical Society in Reference to the Improvement of Geographical Education.
London: John Murray.
Keltie, J. S. 1908. Applied Geography: A preliminary sketch. London: G. Philip.
Keylock, C. J. 2003. Mark Melton’s geomorphology and geography’s quantitative revolution. Transactions of the
Institute of British Geographers NS28, 142–57.
Kimble, G. H. T. 1951. The inadequacy of the regional concept. In L. D. Stamp and S. W. Wooldridge (eds) London
Essays in Geography: Rodwell Jones memorial volume. London: Longmans Green, 151–74.
Kindon, S., Pain, R. and Kesby, M. (eds) 2007. Participatory Action Research Approaches and Methods: Connecting people.
London: Routledge.
References 449

King, G. 1997. A Solution to the Ecological Inference Problem: Reconstructing individual behavior from aggregate data. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
King, L. J. 1960. A note on theory and reality. Professional Geographer 12(3), 4–6.
King, L. J. 1961. A multivariate analysis of the spacing of urban settlement in the United States. Annals of the
Association of American Geographers 51, 222–33.
King, L. J. 1962. A quantitative expression of the pattern of urban settlement sin selected parts of the United
States. Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie 53, 1–7.
King, L. J. 1969a. Statistical Analysis in Geography. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
King, L. J. 1969b. The analysis of spatial form and relationship to geographic theory. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 59, 573–95.
King, L. J. 1976. Alternatives to a positive economic geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 66,
293–308.
King, L. J. 1979a. Areal associations and regressions. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69, 124–8.
King, L. J. 1979b. The seventies: Disillusionment and consolidation. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69,
155–7.
King, L. J. 1993. Spatial science and the institutionalization of geography as a social science. Urban Geography 14,
538–51.
King, L. J. (ed.) 2008. North American Explorations: Ten memoirs of geographers from down under. Victoria, BC: Trafford
Publishing.
King, L. J. and Clark, G. L. 1978. Government policy and regional development. Progress in Human Geography 2,
1–16.
King, R., Connell, J. and White, P. (eds) 1995. Writing Across Worlds: Literature and migration. London: Routledge.
Kingsbury, P. and Pile, S. 2014. Introduction. The unconscious transference, drives, repetition and other
things tied to geography. In P. Kingsbury and S. Pile (eds) Psychoanalytic Geographies. Farnham: Ashgate,
1–38.
Kirk, W. 1951. Historical geography and the concept of the behavioural environment. Indian Geographical Journal
25, 152–60.
Kirk, W. 1963. Problems of geography. Geography 48, 357–71.
Kirk, W. 1978. The road from Mandalay: Towards a geographical philosophy. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers NS3, 381–94.
Kish, G. and Ward, R. 1981. A survival package for geography and other endangered disciplines. Newsletter
Association of American Geographers, 16, 8,14.
Kitchin, R. 1996. Increasing the integrity of cognitive mapping research: Appraising conceptual schemata of
environment-behaviour interaction. Progress in Human Geography 20, 56–84.
Kitchin, R. 2013. Big data and human geography: Opportunities, challenges and risks. Dialogues in Human Geography
3, 262–7.
Kitchin, R. and Dodge, M. 2007. Rethinking maps. Progress in Human Geography 31, 331–44.
Kitchin, R. and Dodge, M. 2011. Code/Space: Software and everyday life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kitchin, R. and Kneale, J. 2001. Science fiction or future fact? Exploring imaginative geographies of the new
millennium. Progress in Human Geography 25, 19–36.
Kitchin, R. and Lysacht, K. 2003. Heterosexism and geographies of everyday life in Belfast, Northern Ireland.
Environment and Planning A 35, 489–510.
Knopp, L. 1990. Some theoretical implications of gay involvement in an urban land market. Political Geography
Quarterly 9, 337–52.
Knopp, L. 1992. Sexuality and the spatial dynamics of capitalism. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 10,
651–69.
Knopp, L. 2007. On the relationship between queer and feminist geographies. Professional Geographer 59, 47–55.
Knopp, L. and Lauria, M. 1987. Gender relations and social relations. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 19,
48–53.
Knos, D. S. 1968. The distribution of land values in Topeka, Kansas. In B. J. L. Berry and D. F. Marble (eds) Spatial
Analysis. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 269–89.
Knox, P. L. 1975. Social Well-being: A spatial perspective. London: Oxford University Press.
Knox, P. L. 1987. The social production of the built environment: Architects, architecture and the post-modern
city. Progress in Human Geography 11, 354–78.
Knox, P. L. and Agnew, J. A. 1989. The Geography of the World-Economy. London: Edward Arnold.
450 References

Knox, P. L. and Taylor, P. J. (eds) 1995. World Cities in a World-System. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Knox, P. L., Bartels, E. H., Bohland, J. R., Holcomb, B. and Johnston, R. J. 1988. The United States: A contemporary human
geography. London: Longman.
Kobayashi, A. and Mackenzie, S. (eds) 1989. Remaking Human Geography. Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman.
Kobayshi, A. and Peake, L. 2000. Racism out of place: Thoughts on whiteness and antiracist geography in the
new millennium. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 90, 392–403.
Koelsch, W. A. 1988. Geography at Clark: The first fifty years, 1921–1971. In J. E. Harmon and T. J. Rickard (eds)
Geography in New England. New Britain, CT: New England-St Lawrence Valley Geographical Society, 40–8.
Koelsch, W. A. 2002. Academic geography, American style: An institutional perspective. In G. S. Dunbar (ed.)
Geography: Discipline, profession and subject since 1870. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 245–80.
Kofman, E. 1988. Is there a cultural geography beyond the fragments? Area 20, 85–7.
Kofman, E. and England, K. 1997. Guest editorial. Citizenship and international migration: taking account of
gender, sexuality, and ‘race’. Environment and Planning A 29, 191–3.
Kofman, E. and Peake, L. 1990. Into the 1990s: A gendered agenda for political geography. Political Geography
Quarterly 9, 313–36.
Kollmorgen, W. N. 1979. Kollmorgen as a bureaucrat. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69, 77–89.
Kong, L. 1990. Geography and religion: Trends and prospects. Progress in Human Geography 14, 355–71.
Kong, L. 2007. The promises and prospects of geography in higher education. Journal of Geography in Higher Education
31, 13–17.
Kost, K. 1989. The conception of politics in political geography and geopolitics in Germany 1920–1950.
Political Geography Quarterly 8, 369–86.
Kroeber, A. L. 1952. The Nature of Culture. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Krumbein, W. C. and Graybill, F. A. 1965. An Introduction to Statistical Models in Geology. New York: McGraw Hill.
Kuhn, T. S. 1957. The Copernican Revolution: Planetary astronomy in the development of western thought. Cambridge MA: Harvard
University Press.
Kuhn, T. S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kuhn, T. S. 1969. Comment on the relations of science and art. Comparative Studies in Society and History 11, 403–12.
Kuhn, T. S. 1970a. The Structure of Scientific Resolutions, 2nd edn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kuhn, T. S. 1970b. Logic of discovery or psychology of research? In I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds) Criticism and
the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–23.
Kuhn, T. S. 1970c. Reflections on my critics. In I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 231–78.
Kuhn, T. S. 1977. Second thoughts on paradigms. In F. Suppe (ed.) The Structure of Scientific Theories. Urbana,
IL: University of Illinois Press, 459–82, plus discussion 500–17.
Kuhn, T. S. 1991. The natural and the human sciences. In D. J. Hiley, R. Bohman and R. Shusterman (eds) The
Interpretative Turn: Philosophy, science, culture. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 17–24.
Kwan, M.-P. 2002. Feminist visualization: Re-envisioning GIS as a method in feminist geographic research.
Annals of the Association of American Geographers 92, 645–61.
Kwan, M.-P. 2004. Beyond difference: From canonical geography to hybrid geographies. Annals of the Association
of American Geographers 94, 756–63.
Kwan, M.-P. 2012. The uncertain geographic concept problem. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 102,
958–68.
Kwan, M.-P. (ed.) 2014. Geographies of Health, Disease and Well-being. London and New York Routledge.
Kwan, M.-P. and Schwanen, T. 2009a. Critical quantitative geographies. Environment and Planning A 41, 261–4.
Kwan, M.-P. and Schwanen, T. 2009b. Quantitative revolution 2: The critical (re)turn. Professional Geographer 61,
283–91.
Labedz, L. 1977. Anarchism. In A. Bullock and O. Stallybrass (eds) The Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thought. London:
William Collins, 22.
Lacoste,Y. 1973. An illustration of geographical warfare: Bombing of the dikes on the Red River, North Vietnam.
Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 5, 1–13.
Lakatos, I. 1978a. Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In J. Worrall and
G. Currie (eds) The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes: Philosophical papers, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 8–101.
Lakatos, I. 1978b. History of science and its rational reconstructions. In J. Worrall and G. Currie (eds) The Methodology
of Scientific Research Programmes: Philosophical Papers,Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 102–38.
References 451

Landström, C., Whatmore, S. J., Lane, S. N., Odoni, N. A., Ward, N. and Brady, S. 2011. Coproducing flood risk
knowledge: Redistributing expertise in critical ‘participatory modelling’. Environment and Planning A 43,
1617–33.
Langton, J. 1972. Potentialities and problems of adapting a systems approach to the study of change in human
geography. In C. Board, R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R. Stoddart (eds) Progress in Geography, Vol. 4. London:
Edward Arnold, 125–79.
Langton, J. 1984. The industrial revolution and the regional geography of England. Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers NS9, 145–67.
Laponce, J. A. 1980. Political science: An import-export analysis of journals and footnotes. Political Studies 28,
401–19.
Larkin, R. P. and Peters, G. L. 1993. Biographical Dictionary of Geography. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
Larner, W. 2011. C-change: Geographies of crisis? Dialogues in Human Geography 1, 319–35.
Lash, S. and Urry, J. 1987. The End of Organized Capitalism. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Latour, B. 1987. Science in Action: How to follow scientists and engineers around society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Latour, B. 1999. Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the reality of science studies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Latour, B. and Woolgar, S. 1979. Laboratory Life:The construction of scientific facts. Beverly Hills: Sage.
Lauria, M. and Knopp, L. 1985. Toward an analysis of the role of gay communities in urban renaissance. Urban
Geography 6, 152–69.
Laurie, N., Dwyer, C., Holloway, S. and Smith, F. 1999. Geographies of New Femininities. Harlow: Longman.
Lavalle, P., McConnell, H. and Brown, R. G. 1967. Certain aspects of the expansion of quantitative methodology
in American geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 57, 423–36.
Law, J. 1976. Theories and methods in the sociology of science: an interpretative approach. In G. Lemaine et al.,
Perspectives on the Emergence of Scientific Disciplines. The Hague: Mouton, 221–31.
Law, J. and Hassard, J. (eds) 1999. Actor Network Theory and After. Oxford and Keele: Blackwell and The Sociological
Review.
Law, R. 1999. Beyond ‘women and transport’: Towards new geographies of gender and daily mobility. Progress in
Human Geography 23, 567–88.
Lawson, V. 2007. Geographies of care and responsibility. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 97, 1–11.
Lawson, V. and Staeheli, L. A. 1991. On critical realism, geography, and arcane sects! Professional Geographer 43,
231–3.
Lawton, R. and Miller, E. W. 2001. Two economic geography texts. Progress in Human Geography 25, 303–9.
Leach, B. 1974. Race, problems and geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 63, 41–7.
Leach, E. R. 1974. Lévi-Strauss. London: William Collins.
Lee, R. 1984. Process and region in the A-level syllabus. Geography 69, 97–107.
Lee, R. 1985. The future of the region: Regional geography as education for transformation. In R. King (ed.)
Geographical Futures. Sheffield: Geographical Association, 77–91.
Lee, R. and Philo, C. 2009. Welfare geography. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human
Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 224–9.
Lee, R. and Wills, J. (eds) 1997. Geographies of Economies. London: Arnold.
Lee, R., Castree, N., Kitchin, R., Lawson, V., Paasi, A., Philo, C., Radcliffe, S., Roberts, S. M. and Withers, C. 2014.
Prologue: The vital requirement of reflexivity. In Lee, R. et al. (eds) The SAGE Handbook of Human Geography.
Thousand Oaks, CA and London, New Delhi, Singapore: Sage, Vol. 1, ix–x.
Lee, Y. 1975. A rejoinder to ‘The geography of crime: A political critique’. Professional Geographer 27, 284–5.
Lees, L. 2000. A reappraisal of gentrification: Towards a ‘geography of gentrification’. Progress in Human Geography
24, 389–408.
Lees, L. 2012. The geography of gentrification: Thinking through comparative urbanism. Progress in Human
Geography 36, 155–71.
Lees, L., Slater, T. and Wyly, E. (eds) 2010. The Gentrification Reader. Abingdon and New York: Routledge.
Leighley, J. 1937. Some comments on contemporary geographic methods. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 27, 125–41.
Leighley, J. 1955. What has happened to physical geography? Annals of the Association of American Geographers 45,
309–18.
Lemaine, G., MacLeod, R., Mulkay, M. and Weingart, P. 1976. Introduction: Problems in the emergence of new
disciplines. In G. Lemaine et al. (eds) Perspectives on the Emergence of Scientific Disciplines. The Hague: Mouton, 1–24.
452 References

Leonard, S. 1982. Urban managerialism: A period of transition. Progress in Human Geography 6, 190–215.
Leszczynski, A. 2014. On the neo in neogeography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 104, 60–79.
Lewis, G. M. 1966. Regional ideas and reality in the Cis-Rocky Mountain West. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers 38, 135–50.
Lewis, G. M. 1968. Levels of living in the Northeastern United States c. 1960: A new approach to regional
geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 45, 11–37.
Lewis, G. M. (ed.) 1998. Cartographic Encounters: Perspectives on native American mapmaking and map use. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Lewis, M. W. and Wigen, K. 1997. The myth of continents: A critique of metageography. Berkeley, CA: University
of California Press.
Lewis, P. W. 1965. Three related problems in the formulation of laws in geography. Professional Geographer 17(5),
24–7.
Lewis, P. W. 1977. Maps and Statistics. London: Methuen.
Lewthwaite, G. R. 1966. Environmentalism and determinism: A search for clarification. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 56, 1–23.
Ley, D. 1974. The Black Inner City as Frontier Outpost. Washington, DC: Association of American Geographers.
Ley, D. 1977a. The personality of a geographical fact. Professional Geographer 29, 8–13.
Ley, D. 1977b. Social geography and the taken-for-granted world. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS2,
498–512.
Ley, D. 1978. Social geography and social action. In D. Ley and M. S. Samuels (eds) Humanistic Geography: Problems
and prospects. Chicago: Maaroufa Press, 41–57.
Ley, D. 1980. Geography Without Man: A humanistic critique. Oxford Research Paper 24, School of Geography,
Oxford: University of Oxford.
Ley, D. 1981. Behavioral geography and the philosophies of meaning. In K. R. Cox and R. G. Golledge (eds)
Behavioral Problems in Geography Revisited. London: Methuen, 209–30.
Ley, D. 1983. A Social Geography of the City. New York: Harper & Row.
Ley, D. 1989. Fragmentation, coherence, and the limits to theory in human geography. In A. Kobayashi and S.
Mackenzie (eds) Remaking Human Geography. Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman, 227–44.
Ley, D. 1993. Postmodernism, or the cultural logic of advanced industrial capital. Tijdschrift voor Economische en
Sociale Geografie 84, 171–4.
Ley, D. and Duncan, J. S. 1993. Epilogue. In J. S. Duncan and D. Ley (eds) Place/Culture/Representation. London:
Routledge, 329–36.
Ley, D. and Samuels, M. S. 1978. Introduction: Contexts of modern humanism in geography. In D. Ley and
M. S. Samuels (eds) Humanistic Geography: Prospects and problems. Chicago: Maaroufa Press, 1–18.
Leyshon, A. 1995. Missing words: Whatever happened to the geography of poverty? Environment and Planning A 27,
1021–5.
Leyshon, A., Matless, D. and Revill, G. 1995. The place of music. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS20,
423–33.
Lichtenberger, E. 1984. The German-speaking countries. In R. J. Johnston and P. Claval (eds) Geography Since the
Second World War: An international survey. London: Croom Helm, 156–84.
Lichtenberger, E. 1997. Harris and Ullman’s ‘The nature of cities’:  The paper’s historical context and its impact
for further research. Urban Geography 18, 7–14.
Lipietz, A. 1993. From Althusserianism to ‘regulation theory’. In E. A. Kaplan and M. Sprinker (eds) The
Althusserian Legacy. London and New York: Verso, 99–138.
Little, J., Peake, L. and Richardson, P. (eds) 1988. Women in Cities. London: Macmillan.
Liu, X. and Zhan, F. B. 2011. Placement of graduates in PhD-granting departments as a measure of productivity
of doctoral geography programs in the United States: 1960–2008. Professional Geographer 64, 1–16.
Liu, X. and Zhan, F. B. 2012. Productivity of doctoral graduate placement among PhD–granting geography
programs in the United States: 1960–2010. Professional Geographer 64, 475–90.
Liverman, D. M. 2009. The geopolitics of climate change: Avoiding determinism, fostering sustainable
development. Climate Change 96, 7–11.
Livingstone, D. N. 1984. Natural theory and neo-Lamarckism: The changing context of nineteenth century
geography in the United States and Great Britain. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 74, 9–28.
Livingstone, D. N. 1992. The Geographical Tradition: Episodes in the history of a contested enterprise. Oxford: Blackwell
Publishers.
References 453

Livingstone, D. N. 1995. Geographical traditions. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS20, 420–2.
Livingstone, D. N. 2000a. Putting geography in its place. Australian Geographical Studies, 39, 1–9.
Livingstone, D. N. 2000b. Making space for science. Erdkunde 54, 285–96.
Livingstone, D. N. 2002. Science, Space and Hermeneutics. Heidelberg: Department of Geography, University of
Heidelberg.
Livingstone, D. N. 2003a. British geography, 1500–1900: An imprecise review. In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams
(eds) A Century of British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 11–44.
Livingstone, D. N. 2003b. Putting Science in its Place: Geographies of scientific knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Livingstone, D. N. 2005. Science, text and space: Thoughts on the geography of reading. Transactions of the Institute
of British Geographers 30, 391–401.
Livinstone, D. N. 2007. Johnston, R. J. 1979: Geography and Geographers: Anglo–American human geography since 1945.
London: Edward Arnold. Commentary 1. Progress in Human Geography 31, 43–5.
Livingstone, D. N. and Harrison, R. T. 1981. Immanuel Kant, subjectivism, and human geography: A preliminary
investigation. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS6, 359–74.
Livingstone, D. N. and Withers, C. W. J. (eds) 1999. Geography and Enlightenment. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Lloyd, C. D., Pawlowsky–Glahn, V. and Egozcue, J. J. 2012. Compositional data analysis in population studies.
Annals of the Association of American Geographers 102, 1–16.
Lobben, A., Lawrence, M. and Pickett, R. 2014. The map effect. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 104,
96–113.
Longhurst, R. 1995. Viewpoint – The body and geography. Gender, Place & Culture: A Journal of Feminist Geography 2,
97–106.
Longhurst, R. 1997. (Dis)embodied geographies. Progress in Human Geography 21, 486–501.
Longhurst, R. 2000. ‘Corporeographies’ of pregnancy: ‘Bikini babes’. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 18,
453–72.
Longley, P. A. 1995. GIS and planning for businesses and services. Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design 22,
127–9.
Longley, P. A. 1998. Foundations. In P. A. Longley, S. M. Brooks, R. MacDonnell and B. Macmillan (eds)
Geocomputation: A primer. Chichester: John Wiley, 3–16.
Longley, P. A. 2000. Spatial analysis in the new millennium. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 90, 157–65.
Longley, P. A. 2002. Geographical Information Systems: Will developments in urban remote sensing and GIS
lead to ‘better’ urban geography? Progress in Human Geography 26, 240–51.
Longley, P. A. 2004. Geographical Information Systems: On modelling and representation. Progress in Human
Geography 28.
Longley, P. A. 2012. Geodemographics and the practice of geographical information science. Special issue in
honor of Michael Goodchild, International Journal of Geographic Information Science 26, 2227–37.
Longley, P. A. and Mesev, V. 2000. On the measurement and generalisation of urban form. Environment and Planning
A 32, 473–88.
Longley, P. A., Webber, R. and Lloyd, D. 2007. The quantitative analysis of family names: Historic migration and
the present day neighborhood structure of Middlesbrough, England. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
97, 31–48.
Longley, P. A., Goodchild, M. F., Maguire, D. J. and Rhind, D. W. (eds) 1999a. Geographical Information Systems:
Principles, techniques, management and applications (2 vols). New York: Wiley.
Longley, P. A., Goodchild, M. F., Maguire, D. J. and Rhind, D. W. (eds) 1999b. Introduction. In P. A. Longley,
M. F. Goodchild, D. J. Maguire and D. W. Rhind (eds) Geographical Information Systems: Principles, techniques, management
and applications (2 vols). New York: Wiley, 1–20.
Longley, P. A., Goodchild, M. F., Maguire, D. J. and Rhind, D. W. 2001. Geographic Information Systems and Science,
1st edn. Chichester: John Wiley.
Longley, P. A., Goodchild, M. F., Maguire, D. J. and Rhind, D. W. (eds) 2005. Geographical Information Systems and
Science: Principles, techniques, management and applications, 2nd edn (abridged). Harlow, NJ: Wiley.
Longley, P. A., Goodchild, M. F., Maguire, D. J. and Rhind, D. W. 2011. Geographic Information Systems and Science, 3rd
edn. Chichester: John Wiley.
Longley, P. A., Goodchild, M. F., Maguire, D. J. and Rhind, D. W. 2016. Geographic Information Systems and Science, 4th
edn. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley.
454 References

Loomis, J. M., Montello, D. R. and Klatzky, R. L. 2010. Reginald G. Golledge. Progress in Human Geography 34, 678–90.
Lorimer, H. 2003. Telling small stories: Spaces of knowledge and the practice of geography. Transactions of the
Institute of British Geographers NS28, 197–217.
Lorimer, H. 2005. Cultural geography: The busyness of being ‘more-than-representational’. Progress in Human
Geography 29, 83–94.
Lorimer, H. and Spedding, N. 2002. Excavating geography’s hidden spaces. Area 34, 294–302.
Lorimer, H. and Withers, C. 2007. Geographers: Lives, works, possibilities. In H. Lorimer and C. Withers (eds)
Geographers: Biobibliographical Studies,Vol. 26. London and New York: Continuum, 1–5.
Lorimer, H. and Withers, C. W. J. (eds) 2014. Geographers: Biobibliographical Studies, Vol. 33. London: Bloomsbury
Academic.
Lösch, A. 1954. The Economics of Location. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Louden, R. B. 2014. The last frontier: The importance of Kant’s Geography. Environment and Planning D: Society and
Space 32, 1–16.
Lovering, J. 1987. Militarism, capitalism and the nation-state: Towards a realist synthesis. Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space 5, 283–302.
Lowe, M. S. and Short, J. R. 1990. Progressive human geography. Progress in Human Geography 14, 1–11.
Lowenthal, D. (ed.) 1965. George Perkins Marsh: Man and nature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Lowenthal, D. 1958. George Perkins Marsh:   Versatile   Vermonter. New York: Columbia University Press.
Lowenthal, D. 1961. Geography, experience, and imagination: Towards a geographical epistemology. Annals of the
Association of American Geographers 51, 241–60.
Lowenthal, D. 1968. The American scene. Geographical Review 48, 61–88.
Lowenthal, D. 1975. Past time, present place: Landscape and memory. Geographical Review 65, 1–36.
Lowenthal, D. 1985. The Past is a Foreign Country. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lowenthal, D. 2001. George Perkins Marsh: Prophet of conservation. Seattle, WA: University of Washington Press.
Lowenthal, D. 2014. Essay: Albion’s other islets: Offshore, overseas, out of sorts. Geographical Reivew 104, 101–8.
Lowenthal, D. and Bowden, M. J. (eds) 1975. Geographies of the Mind: Essays in historical geosophy in honor of John Kirkland
Wright. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lowenthal, D. and Prince, H. C. 1965. English landscape tastes. Geographical Review 55, 186–222.
Lowenthal, D., Burton, I., Cooley, R. and Mikesell, M. 1973. Report of the AAG task force on environmental
quality. Professional Geographer 25, 39–46.
Luke, T. W. 2000. The discipline as disciplinary normalization: Networks of research. In R. Sil and E. M. Doherty
(eds) Beyond Boundaries? Disciplines, paradigms, and theoretical integration in international studies. Albany: State University
of New York Press, 207–29.
Lukermann, F. 1958. Towards a more geographic economic geography. Professional Geographer 10(1), 2–10.
Lukermann, F. 1960a. On explanation, model, and prediction. Professional Geographer 12(1), 1–2.
Lukermann, F. 1960b. The geography of cement? Professional Geographer 12(4), 1–6.
Lukermann, F. 1961. The role of theory in geographical inquiry. Professional Geographer 13(2), 1–6.
Lukermann, F. 1964a. Geography Among the Sciences. Minneapolis, MN: Kalamata.
Lukermann, F. 1964b. Geography as a formal intellectual discipline and the way in which it contributes to
knowledge. Canadian Geographer 8, 167–72.
Lukermann, F. 1965. Geography: De facto or de jure. Journal of the Minnesota Academy of Science 32, 189–96.
Lukermann, F. 1990. The nature of geography: Post hoc, ergo propter hoc? In J. N. Entrikin and S. D. Brunn
(eds) Reflections on Richard Hartshorne’s The Nature of Geography. Washington, DC: Association of American
Geographers, 53–68.
Lutz, C. A. and Collins, J. L. 1993. Reading National Geographic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lynch, K. 1960. The Image of the City. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lynch, M. 2012. Notes on Kuhn and Latour. Social Studies of Science 42, 449–55.
Mabogunje, A. K. 1977. In search of spatial order: Geography and the new programme of urbanization in
Nigeria. In D. R. Deskins et al. (eds) Geographic Humanism, Analysis and Social Action: A half century of geography at
Michigan. Ann Arbor, MI: Michigan Geography Publications No. 17, 347–76.
MacAllister, I., Pattie, C. J., Tunstall, H., Dorling, D. F. L. and Rossiter, D. J. 2001. Class dealignment and the
neighbourhood effect: Miller revisited. British Journal of Political Science 31, 41–60.
MacDonald, N., Chester, D., Sangster, H., Todd, B. and Hooke, J. 2012. The significance of Gilbert F. White’s 1945
paper ‘Human adjustment to floods’ in the development of risk and hazard management. Progress in Physical
Geography 35, 125–33.
References 455

MacEachren, A. 1995. How Maps Work. New York: Guilford.


MacGill, S. M. 1983. The Q-controversy: Issues and nonissues. Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design 10, 371–80.
Machamer, P. and Osbeck, L. 2003. Scientific normativity as non-epistemic: A hidden Kuhnian legacy. Social
Epistemology 17, 3–11.
Mackinder, H. J. 1887. On the scope and methods of geography. Proceedings, Royal Geographical Society and Monthly
Record of Geography 9, 141–74.
Mackinder, H. J. 1890. The physical basis of political geography. Scottish Geographical Magazine 6, 78–84.
Mackinder, H. J. 1904. The geographical pivot of history. Geographical Journal 23, 421–37.
Mackinder, H. J. 1919. Democratic Ideals and Reality: A study in the politics of reconstruction. London: Constable.
MacKinnon, D. 2009. Regional Geography II. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human
Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 228–35.
MacLean, K. 2011. G. G. Chisholm, A. G. Ogilvie and the 1912 America transcontinental excursion. Scottish
Geographical Journal 127, 231–48.
MacLeod, G. 1997. Globalizing Parisian thought-waves: Recent advances in the study of social regulation,
politics, discourse and space. Progress in Human Geography 21, 530–3.
MacLeod, G. 1998. In what sense a region? Place, hybridity, symbolic shape, and institutional formation in
(post-)modern Scotland. Political Geography 17, 622–63.
MacLeod, G. and Goodwin, M. 1999. Space, scale and state strategy: Towards a reinterpretation of contemporary
urban and regional governance. Progress in Human Geography 23, 503–28.
MacLeod, G. and Holden, A. 2009. Regulation. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human
Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 309–13.
MacLeod, G. and Jones, M. 2001. Renewing the geography of regions. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space
19, 695–99.
Macmillan, B. 1989a. Quantitative theory construction in human geography. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling
Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 89–107.
Macmillan, B. 1989b. Modelling through: An afterword to Remodelling Geography. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling
Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 291–313.
Macmillan, B. 1998c. Epilogue. In P. Longley, S. M. Brooks, R. MacDonnell and B. Macmillan (eds) Geocomputation:
A primer. Chichester: John Wiley, 257–64.
Maddrell, A. 2006. Revisiting the region: The ‘ordinary’ and ‘exceptional’ regions in the work of Hilda Ormsby:
1917–1940. Environment and Planning A 38, 1739–1752.
Maddrell, A. 2008. The ‘map girls’: British women geographers’ war work, shifting gender boundaries and
reflections on the history of geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers, NS33, 127–48.
Maddrell, A. 2009. Complex Locations: Women’s geographical work in the UK 1850–1970. Oxford and Malden, MA:
Wiley-Blackwell.
Madge, C. 1993. Boundary disputes: Comments on Sidaway (1992). Area, 25, 294–9.
Made, C. 1997. An ode to geography. In Women and Geography Study Group (eds) Feminist Geographies: Explorations
in diversity and difference. Harlow: Longman, 32–3.
Magee, B. 1975. Popper. London: William Collins.
Maguire, D. J. 1989. The Domesday interactive videodisc system in geography teaching. Journal of Geography in
Higher Education 13, 55–68.
Maguire, D. J., Goodchild, M. F. and Rhind, D. W. (eds) 1991. Geographical Information Systems. London: Longman.
Mahtiani, M. 2001. Racial ReMappings: The potential of paradoxical space. Gender, Place and Culture 8, 299–305.
Mahtani, M. 2006. Challenging the ivory tower: Proposing antiracist geographies in the academy. Gender, Place and
Culture 13, 21–5.
Mair, A. 1986. Thomas Kuhn and understanding geography. Progress in Human Geography 10, 345–70.
Manion, T. and Whitelegg, J. 1979. Radical geography and Marxism. Area 11, 122–4.
Mann, M. 1996. Neither nation-state nor globalism. Environment and Planning A 28.
Manners, I. R. and Mikesell, M. W. (eds) 1974. Perspectives on Environment. Washington, DC: Commission on College
Geography, Association of American Geographers.
Mao, L. 2014. The geography, structure, and evolution of the GIS research community in the US: A network
analysis from 1992 to 2011. Transactions in GIS 18, 704–17.
Marble, D. F. and Peuquet, D. F. 1993. The computer and geography: Ten years later. Professional Geographer 45,
446–8.
Marchand, B. 1978. A dialectical approach in geography. Geographical Analysis 10, 105–19.
456 References

Marcus, M. G. 1979. Coming full circle: Physical geography in the twentieth century. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 69, 521–32.
Marginson, S. 2004. Higher education. In R. Manne (ed.) The Howard Years. Melbourne: Black Inc., 216–44.
Mark, D. M., Chrisman, N., Frank, A. U., McHaffie, P. and Pickles, J. 1996. The GIS History Project. Available at:
www.geog.buffalo.edu/ncgia/gishist
Mark, D. M., Freksa, C., Hirtle, S. C., Lloyd, R. and Tverske, B. 1999. Cognitive models of geographic space.
International Journal of Geographical Information Science 13, 747–74.
Markusen, A. 1999. Fuzzy concepts, scanty evidence, policy distance: The case for rigour and policy relevance
in critical regional studies. Regional Studies 33, 868–94.
Marsh, G. P. 1864. Man and Nature, or Physical Geography as Modified by Human Action. New York: Charles Scribner.
Marshall, J. U. 1985. Geography as a scientific enterprise. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography. London:
Methuen, 113–28.
Marston, S. Jones, J. P. and Woodward, K. 2005. Human geography without scale. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers NS30, 416–32.
Martin, A. F. 1951. The necessity for determinism. Transactions and Papers, Institute of British Geographers 17, 1–12.
Martin, D. 2002. Output areas for 2001. In P. Rees, D. Martin and P. Williamson (eds) The Census Data System.
Chichester: John Wiley, 37–46.
Martin, D., Nolan, A. and Tranmer, M. 2001. The application of zone-design methodology in the 2001 UK
census. Environment and Planning A 33, 1949–62.
Martin, G. J. 1980. The Life and Thought of Isaiah Bowman. Hamden, CT: Archon Books.
Martin, G. J. 1981. Ontography and Davisian physiography. In B. W. Blouet (ed.) The Origins of Academic Geography
in the United States. Hamden, CT: Archon Books, 279–90.
Martin, G. J. 1988. On Whittlesey, Bowman and Harvard. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 78,
152–8.
Martin, G. J. 1990. The Nature of Geography and the Schaefer-Hartshorne debate. In J. N. Entrikin and S. D. Brunn
(eds) Reflections on Richard Hartshorne’s The Nature of Geography. Washington, DC: Association of American
Geographers, 69–88.
Martin, G. J. 2005. All Possible Worlds: A history of geographical ideas, 4th edn. New York: Oxford University Press.
Martin, G. J. 1998. The emergence and development of geographic thought in New England. Economic Geography
(special issue), 1–13.
Martin, G. J. and James, P. E. 1993. All Possible Worlds: A history of geographical ideas, 3rd edn. New York:
Wiley.
Martin, G. J. 2013. Maynard Weston Dow (1929–2011) and ‘Geographers on Film’. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 103, 1–4.
Martin, G. J. 2015. American Geography and Geographers: Towards geographic science. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press.
Martin, G. J. and James, P. E. 1993. All Possible Worlds: A history of geographical ideas, 3rd edn. New York: John Wiley.
Martin, R. L. 1999. The ‘new geographical turn’ in economics: Some critical reflections. Cambridge Journal of
Economics 23, 65–92.
Martin, R. L. 2000. In memory of maps. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS25, 3–6.
Martin, R. L. 2001a. The geographer as social critic – getting indignant about income inequality. Transactions of
the Institute of British Geographers NS26, 267–72.
Martin, R. L. 2001b. Geography and public policy: The case of the missing agenda. Progress in Human Geography 25,
189–210.
Martin, R. L. 2002. A geography for policy or a policy for geography? A response to Dorling and Shaw. Progress
in Human Geography 26, 642–4.
Martin, R. L. and Oeppen, J. E. 1975. The identification of regional forecasting models using space-time
correlation functions. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 66, 95–118.
Martin, R. L. and Sunley, P. J. 2001. Rethinking the ‘economic in economic geography: Broadening our vision
or losing our focus? Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 33, 148–61.
Mason, K., Brown, G. and Pickerill, J. 2013. Epistemologies of participation, or, what do critical human
geographers know that’s of any use? Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 45, 252–5.
Massam, B. H. 1976. Location and Space in Social Administration. London: Edward Arnold.
Massey, D. 1975. Behavioral research. Area 7, 201–3.
Massey, D. 1984a. Spatial Divisions of Labour: Social structures and the geography of production. London: Macmillan.
References 457

Massey, D. 1984b. Introduction: Geography matters. In D. Massey and J. Allen (eds) Geography Matters! A reader.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–11.
Massey, D. 1985. New directions in space. In D. Gregory and J. Urry (eds) Social Relations and Spatial Structures.
London: Macmillan, 9–19.
Massey, D. 1991. Flexible sexism. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 9, 31–58.
Massey, D. 1992. Politics and space/time. New Left Review 196, 65–84.
Massey, D. 1995. Spatial Divisions of Labour: Social structures and the geography of production, 2nd edn. London:
Macmillan.
Massey, D. 2000. Practising political relevance. Transaction of the Institute of British Geographers NS25, 131–3.
Massey, D. 2001. Geography on the agenda. Progress in Human Geography 25, 5–17.
Massey, D. 2002. Geography, policy and politics: A response to Dorling and Shaw. Progress in Human Geography 26,
645–6.
Massey, D. 2005. For Space. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage.
Massey, D. and Meegan, R. A. 1979. The geography of industrial reorganization. Progress in Planning 10,
155–237.
Massey, D. and Meegan, R. A. 1982. The Anatomy of Job Loss. London: Methuen.
Massey, D. and Meegan, R. A. 1985. Introduction: The debate. In D. Massey and R. Meegan (eds) Politics and Method:
Contrasting studies in industrial geography. London: Methuen, 1–12.
Masaterman, M. 1970. The nature of a paradigm. In I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds) Criticism and the Growth of
Knowledge. London: Cambridge University Press, 59–90.
Mather, J. R. and Sanderson, M. 1996. The Genius of C. Warren Thornthwaite, Climatologist–Geographer. Norman, OK:
University of Oklahoma Press.
Mather, P. M. 1999. Computer Processing of Remotely-sensed Images: An introduction, 2nd edn. Chichester: John
Wiley.
Mather, P. M. and Koch, M. 2010. Computer Processing of Remotely-sensed Images:  An introduction, 4th edn. Chichester:
John Wiley.
Mathewson, K. (ed.) 1993. Culture, Form and Place: Essays in cultural and historical geography. Baton Rouge: Louisiana
State University, Department of Geography and Anthropology, Geoscience and Man publication, no. 32.
Mathewson, K. and Wisner, B. 2005. Introduction: The geographical and political vision of J M Blaut. Antipode
37, 900–10.
Matless, D. 1992. An occasion for geography: Landscape, representation and Foucault’s corpus. Environment and
Planning D: Society and Space 10, 41–56.
Matless, D. 1995. Effects of history. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS20, 405–9.
Matthews, H. and Livinstone, I. 1996. Geography and lifelong learning. Journal of Geography in Higher Education
20, 5–10.
Matthews, J. A. and Herbert, D. T. (eds) 2004. Unifying Geography: Common heritage, shared future. London: Routledge.
Mattingly, D. and Falconer Al-Hindi, K. 1995. Should women count? A context for the debate. Professional Geographer
47, 427–35.
May, J. 1996a. ‘A little taste of something more exotic’: The imaginative geographies of everyday life. Geography
81, 57–64.
May, J. 1996b. Globalization and the politics of place: Place and identity in an inner London neighbourhood.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS21, 194–215.
May, J. A. 1970. Kant’s Concept of Geography: And its relation to recent geographical thought. Toronto: Department of
Geography, University of Toronto, Research Publication 4.
May, J. A 1972. A reply to Professor Hartshorne. Canadian Geographer 16, 79–81.
Mayer, H. M. 1954. Urban geography. In P. E. James and C. F. Jones (eds) American Geography: Inventory and prospect.
Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 142–66.
Mayer, H. M. and Kohn, C. F. (eds) 1959. Readings in Urban Geography. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Mayer. T. 1989. Consensus and invisibility – the representation of women in human-geography textbooks.
Professional Geographer 41(4), 397–409.
Mayhew, R. J. 2011a. Cosmographers, explorers, cartographers, chorographers: Defining, inscribing and
practicing early modern geography, c. 1450–1850. In J. A. Agnew and J. S. Duncan (eds) The Wiley-Blackwell
Companion to Human Geography. Chichester: Wiley–Blackwell, 23–49.
Mayhew, R. J. 2011b. Geography’s genealogies. In J. A. Agnew and D. N. Livingstone (eds) The Sage Handbook of
Geographical Knowledge. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi and Singapore: Sage, 21–38.
458 References

Mayhew, R. J. 2014. Malthus:The life and legacies of an untimely prophet. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
McCarty, H. H. 1940. The Geographic Basis of American Economic Life. New York: Harper & Brothers.
McCarty, H. H. 1952. McCarty on McCarthy: The spatial distribution of the McCarthy vote, 1952. Unpublished paper,
Department of Geography, State University of Iowa, Iowa City.
McCarty, H. H. 1953. An approach to a theory of economic geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
43, 183–4.
McCarty, H. H. 1954. An approach to a theory of economic geography. Economic Geography 30, 95–101.
McCarty, H. H. 1958. Science, measurement, and area analysis. Economic Geography 34, facing page 283.
McCarty, H. H. 1979. Geography at Iowa. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69, 121–4.
McCarty, H. H. and Lindberg, J. B. 1966. A Preface to Economic Geography. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
McCarty, H. H., Hook, J. C. and Knos, D. S. 1956. The Measurement of Association in Industrial Geography. Iowa
City: Department of Geography, State University of Iowa.
McCormack, D. P. 2003. An event of geographical ethics in spaces of affect. Transaction of the Institute of British
Geographers 28, 488–507.
McDaniel, R. and Eliot Hurst, M. E. 1968. A Systems Analytic Approach to Economic Geography. Washington,
DC: Commission on College Geography, Publication 8, Association of American Geographers.
McDowell, L. 1986a. Feminist geography. In R. J. Johnston, D. Gregory and D. M. Smith (eds) The Dictionary of
Human Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 151–2.
McDowell, L. 1986b. Beyond patriarchy: A class-based explanation of women’s subordination. Antipode: A Radical
Journal of Geography 18, 311–21.
McDowell, L. 1989. Women, gender and the organisation of space. In D. Gregory and R. Walford (eds) Horizons
in Human Geography. London: Macmillan, 136–51.
McDowell, L. 1990. Sex and power in academia. Area 22, 323–32.
McDowell, L. 1991. Life without father and Ford: The new gender order of post-fordism. Transactions of the Institute
of British Geographers NS 16, 400–19.
McDowell, L. 1991. The baby and the bath water: Diversity, deconstruction and feminist theory in geography.
Geoforum 22, 122–33.
McDowell, L. 1992. Valid games? Professional Geographer 44, 212–15.
McDowell, L. 1993a. Space, place and gender relations: Part I. Feminist empiricism and the geography of social
relations. Progress in Human Geography 17, 157–79.
McDowell, L. 1993b. Space, place and gender relations: Part II. Identity, difference, feminist geometries and
geographies. Progress in Human Geography 17, 305–18.
McDowell, L. 1994. Polyphony and pedagogic authority. Area 26, 241–8.
McDowell, L. 1995. Bodywork: Heterosexual gender performances in city workplaces. In D. Bell and G.
Valentine (eds) Mapping Desire: Geographies of sexualities. London and New York: Routledge, 75–98.
McDowell, L. 1999. Feminist geography. In L. McDowell and J. P. Sharp (eds) A Feminist Glossary of Human Geography.
London: Arnold, 90–3.
McDowell, L. 2000. Economy, culture, difference and justice. In I. Cook, D. Crouch, S. Naylor and J. R. Ryan
(eds) Cultural Turns/Geographical Turns: Perspectives on cultural geography. Harlow: Prentice Hall, 182–95.
McDowell, L. 2002. Masculine discourse and dissonances: Strutting ‘lads’, protest masculinity and domestic
respectability. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 20, 97–119.
McDowell, L. and Court, G. 1994. Missing subjects: Gender, power and sexuality in merchant banking. Economic
Geography 70, 229–51.
McDowell, L. and Massey, D. 1984. A woman’s place? In D. Massey and J. Allen (eds) Geography Matters! Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 128–47.
McDowell, L. and Sharp, J. P. (eds) 1997. Space, Gender, Knowledge: Feminist readings. London: Arnold.
McDowell, L. and Sharp, J. P. 1999. A Feminist Glossary of Human Geography. London: Arnold.
McEwan, C. 1998. Cutting power lines within the palace? Countering paternity and eurocentrism in the
‘geographical tradition’. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS 23, 371–84.
McGuiness, M. 1999. Geography matters? Whiteness and contemporary geography. Area 32, 225–30.
McKendrick, J. 1995. The provincial geographical socities in Britain, 1884–1914. In M. Bell, R. A. Butlin and
M. Heffernan (eds) Geography and Imperialism: 1820–1940. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
McKinney, W. M. 1968. Carey, Spencer, and modern geography. Professional Geographer 20, 103–6.
McTaggart, W. D. 1974. Structuralism and universalism in geography: Reflections on contributions by
H. C. Brookfield. Australian Geographer 12, 510–16.
References 459

Mead, W. R. 1963. The adoption of other lands: Experiences in a Finnish context. Geography 48, 241–54.
Mead, W. R. 1980. Regional geography. In E. H. Brown (ed.) Geography Yesterday and Tomorrow. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 292–302.
Mead, W. R. 1993. An Experience of Finland. London: Hurst & Company.
Mead, W. R. 2002. A Celebration of Norway. London: Hurst & Company.
Mead, W. R. 2004. Obituary: Torsten Hägerstrand 1916–2004. Geographical Journal 170, 279.
Mead, W. R. 2007. Adopting Finland. Helsinki: Hakapaino Oy.
Meadows, D. H., Meadows, D. L., Randers, J. and Behrens III, W. W. 1972. The Limits to Growth. New York:
Universal Books.
Meeus, B., Schuermans, N. and de Maesschalck, F. 2011. Is there a world beyond academic geography? A reply
to Ben Derudder. Area 43, 113–14.
Meinig, D. W. 1972. American wests: Preface to a geographical introduction. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 62, 159–84.
Meinig, D. W. 1978. The continuous shaping of America: A prospectus for geographers and historians. American
Historical Review 83, 1186–217.
Meinig, D. W. 1983. Geography as an art. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS8, 314–28.
Meinig, D. W. 1986. The Shaping of America: A geographical perspective on 500 years of history. Vol. 1: Atlantic America,
1492–1800. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Meinig, D. W. 1986–2004. The Shaping of America: A geographical perspective on 500 years of history.Vols. 1–4. New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
Meinig, D. W. 1989. The historical geography imperative. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 79,
79–87.
Meinig, D. W. 1993. The Shaping of America: A geographical perspective on 500 years of history. Vol. 2. Continental America 1800–
1867. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Meinig, D. W. 2002. The life of learning. In P. Gould and F. R. Pitts (eds) Geographical Voices: Fourteen autobiographical
essays. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 189–210.
Mercer, D. C. 1977. Conflict and Consensus in Human Geography. Clayton, Victoria, Australia: Monash Publications in
Geography No. 17.
Mercer, D. C. 1984. Unmasking technocratic geography. In M. Billinge, D. Gregory and R. Martin (eds) Recollections
of a Revolution. London: Macmillan, 153–99.
Mercer, D. C. and Powell, J. M. 1972. Phenomenology and Related Non-positivistic Viewpoints in the Social Sciences. Clayton,
Victoria, Australia: Monash Publications in Geography, No. 1.
Merrifield, A. 1995. Situated knowledge through exploration: Reflections on Bunge’s ‘geographical expeditions’.
Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 27, 49–70.
Merriman, P., Jones, M., Olsson, G., Sheppard, E., Thrift, N. J. and Tuan, Y.-F. 2012. Space and spatiality in theory.
Dialogues in Human Geography 2, 3–22.
Mesev, V. 2003. Remotely Sensed Cities. London: Taylor & Francis.
Meyer, D. R. 1972. Geographical population data: Statistical description not statistical inference. Professional
Geographer 24, 26–8.
Mialet, H. 2012. Where would STS be without Latour? What would be missing? Social Studies of Science 42, 456–61.
Michie, J. and Cooper, C. (eds) 2015. Why the Social Sciences Matter. Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.
Middleton, N. and Thomas, D. S. G. 1994. Desertification: Exploding the myth. Chichester: John Wiley.
Mikesell, M. W. (ed.) 1973. Geographers Abroad: Essays on the prospects of research in foreign areas. Chicago: Department of
Geography, University of Chicago, Research Paper 152.
Mikesell, M. W. 1967. Geographical perspectives in anthropology. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 57,
617–34.
Mikesell, M. W. 1969. The borderlands of geography as a social science. In M. Sherif and C. W. Sherif (eds)
Interdisciplinary Relationships in the Social Sciences. Chicago: Aldine Publishing Company, 227–48.
Mikesell, M. W. 1974. Geography as the study of environment: An assessment of some old and new commitments.
In I. R. Manners and M. W. Mikesell (eds) Perspectives on Environment, Washington, DC: Commission on College
Geography, Association of American Geographers, 1–23.
Mikesell, M. W. 1978. Tradition and innovation in cultural geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
68, 1–16.
Mikesell, M. W. 1981. Continuity and change. In B. W. Blouet (ed.) The Origins of Academic Geography in the United States.
Hamden, CT: Archon Books, 1–15.
460 References

Mikesell, M. W. 1984. North America. In R. J. Johnston and P. Claval (eds) Geography Since the Second World War:
An international survey. London: Croom Helm, 185–213.
Mikesell, M. W. 1999. Afterword: New interests, unsolved problems and persisting tasks. In K. E. Foote,
P. J. Hugill, K. Mathewson and J. M. Smith (eds) Re-reading Cultural Geography. Austin, TX: University of Texas
Press, 437–44.
Miller, D. and Hashmi, S. H. (eds) 2001. Boundaries and Justice: Diverse ethical perspectives. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Miller, E. W. (ed.) 1993. The American Society for Professional Geographers. Papers presented on the occasion of the
fiftieth anniversary of its founding. Washington, DC: Association of American Geographers, Occasional
Publication 3.
Miller, H. J. 2004. Tobler’s first law and spatial analysis. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 94, 284–9.
Miller, H. J. and Wentz, E. 2003. Geographic representation and spatial analysis in geographic information
systems. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 93, 574–94.
Mills, C. W. 1959. The Sociological Imagination. New York: Oxford University Press.
Minca, C. 2000. Guest editorial: Venetian geographical praxis. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 18,
285–9.
Minca, C. 2001. Acknowledgements. In C. Minca (ed.) Postmodern Geography: Theory and praxis. Oxford: Blackwell,
xii–xiii.
Minca, C. 2003. Guest editorial: Critical peripheries. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 21, 160–8.
Minca, C. 2009. Postmodernism/postmodern geography. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia
of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 363–72.
Mitchell, B. and Draper, D. 1982. Relevance and Ethics in Geography. London: Longman.
Mitchell, D. 1995. There’s no such thing as culture: Towards a reconceptualization of the idea of culture in
geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS20, 102–16.
Mitchell, D. 2003. Dead labour and the political economy of landscape – California living, California dying. In
K. Anderson, M. Domosh, S. Pile and N. Thrift (eds) The Handbook of Cultural Geography. London, Thousand Oaks,
CA and New Delhi: Sage, 233–48.
Mitchell, D. 2004. Geography in an age of extremes: A blueprint for a geography of justice. Annals of the Association
of American Geographers 94, 764–70.
Mitchell, D. 2009. People’s geography. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human Geography.
Amsterdam: Elsevier, 116–19.
Mitchell, R., Martin, D. and Foody, G. M. 1998. Unmixing aggregate data: Estimating the social composition of
enumeration districts. Environment and Planning A 30, 1929–42.
Miyares, I. M. and McGlade, M. S. 1994. Specialization in ‘jobs in geography’ 1980–1993. Professional Geographer
46, 170–7.
Mohammad, R. 1999. Marginalisation, Islamism and the production of the ‘Other’s Other’. Gender, Place and Culture
6, 221–40.
Mohammad, R. and Sidaway, J. D. 2012. Reflections on affect: A meta-commentary occasioned by Pile (2010)
and subsequent exchanges. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS37, 655–7.
Mohan, G. 1994. Destruction of the con: Geography and the commodification of knowledge. Area 26,
387–90.
Mohan, J. 2000. Geographies of welfare and social exclusion. Progress in Human Geography 24, 291–300.
Mohan, J. 2003. Geography and social policy: Spatial divisions of welfare. Progress in Human Geography 27,
363–74.
Monk, J. 1998. The women were always welcome at Clark. Economic Geography (special issue), 14–30.
Monk, J. 2015. Spaces and flows. In S. C. Aitken and G. Valentine (eds) Approaches to Human Geography: Philosophies,
theories, people and practices, 2nd edn. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi and Singapore: Sage, 272–8.
Monk, J. and Hanson, S. 1982. On not excluding half of the human in human geography. Professional Geographer
34, 11–23.
Monmonier, M. S. 1993. What a friend we have in GIS. Professional Geographer 45, 448–50.
Monmonier, M. S. 1996. How to Lie Within Maps, 2nd edn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Montefiore, A. G. and Williams, W. M. 1955. Determinism and possibilism. Geographical Studies 2, 1–11.
Moodie, D. W. and Lehr, J. C. 1976. Fact and theory in historical geography. Professional Geographer 28, 132–6.
Moos, A. I. and Dear, M. J. 1986. Structuration theory in urban analysis: 1. Theoretical exegesis. Environment and
Planning A 18, 231–52.
References 461

Moran, W. 2000. Exceptionalism in the Antipodes. Progress in Human Geography 24, 429–38.
Moreton, B. 2009. To Serve God and Wal-Mart:The making of Christian free enterprise. Cambridge MA: Harvard University
Press.
Morgan, M. A. 1967. Hardware models in geography. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds) Models in Geography.
London: Methuen, 727–74.
Morgan, W. B. and Moss, R. P. 1965. Geography and ecology: The concept of the community and its relationship
to environment. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 55, 339–50.
Morin, K. M. 2009. Feminist groups within geography. In R. Kitchen and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia
of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 64–70.
Morin, K. M. 2011. Civic Discipline: Geography in America, 1860–1890. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Morin, K. M. and Rothenberg, T. Y. 2011. Our theories, ourselves: Hierarchies of place and status in the U.S.
academy. ACME: An International E-Journal for Critical Geographies 10, 58–68.
Morrell, J. 1990. Professionalisation. In R. Olby (ed.) Companion to the History of Modern Science. London: Routledge,
980–9.
Morrill, R. L. 1965. Migration and the growth of urban settlement. Lund Studies in Geography, Series B. 24,
Lund: C. W. K. Gleerup.
Morrill, R. L. 1968. Waves of spatial diffusion. Journal of Regional Science 8, 1–18.
Morrill, R. L. 1969. Geography and the transformation of society. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 1(1), 6–9.
Morrill, R. L. 1970a. The Spatial Organization of Society, 2nd edn. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Morrill, R. L. 1970b. Geography and the transformation of society: Part II. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography
2(1), 4–10.
Morrill, R. L. 1973. Ideal and reality in reapportionment. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 63,
463–77.
Morrill, R. L. 1974. Review of D. Harvey, Social Justice and the City. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 64,
475–7.
Morrill, R. L. 1978. Geography as spatial interaction. In J. D. Eyre (ed.) A Man for all Regions: The contributions of
Edward L. Ullman to geography. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina, Department of Geography, Studies
in Geography no. 11, 16–29.
Morrill, R. L. 1980. Productivity of American Ph.D-granting Departments of Geography. Professional Geographer 32,
85–9.
Morrill, R. L. 1981. Political Redistricting. Washington, DC: Resource Publications in Geography, Association of
American Geographers.
Morrill, R. L. 1984. Recollections of the ‘Quantitative Revolution’s’ early years: The University of
Washington 1955–65. In M. Billinge, D. Gregory and R. Martin (eds) Recollections of a Revolution. London:
Macmillan, 57–72.
Morrill, R. L. 1985. Some important geographic questions. Professional Geographer 37, 263–70.
Morrill, R. L. 1993. Geography, spatial analysis and social science. Urban Geography 14, 442–6.
Morrill, R. L. 1994. Response to Johnston. Urban Geography, 15, 296.
Morrill, R. L. 2002. Pausing for breath. In P. R. Gould and F. R. Pitts (eds) Geographical Voices: Fourteen auto-
biographical essays. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 211–36.
Morrill, R. L. 2005. Hägerstrand and the ‘quantitative revolution’: A personal appreciation. Progress in Human
Geography 28, 328–32.
Morrill, R. L. and Dormtzer, J. 1979. The Spatial Order: An introduction to modern geography. North Scituate, RI: Duxbury.
Morrill, R. L. and Garrison, W. L. 1960. Projections of interregional patterns of trade in wheat and flour. Economic
Geography 36, 116–26.
Morrill, R. L. and Wohlenberg, E. H. 1971. The Geography of Poverty in the United States. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Morton, P. A. 2011. The uses and abuses of human geography. Journal of Architecture 16, 805–20.
Moss, P. (ed.) 2001. Placing Autobiography in Geography. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press.
Moss, P. and Falconer Al-Hindi, K. 2008. An introduction: Feminisms, geographies, knowledges. In P. Moss
and K. Falconer Al-Hindi (eds) Feminisms in Geography: Rethinking space, place and knowledges. Lanham, MA: Rowan
& Littlefield, 1–27.
Moss, P., Berg, L. D. and Desbiens, C. 2002. The political economy of publishing in geography. ACME: An
International Journal for Critical Geographies 7, 1–7.
Moss, R. P. 1970. Authority and charisma: Criteria of validity in geographical method. South African Geographical
Journal 52, 13–37.
462 References

Moss, R. P. 1977. Deductive strategies in geographical generalization. Progress in Physical Geography 1, 23–39.
Moss, R. P. and Morgan, W. B. 1967. The concept of the community: Some applications in geographical research.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 41, 21–32.
mrs kinpaisby 2008. Taking stock of participatory geographies: Envisioning the communiversity. Transactions of
the Institute of British Geographers NS33, 292–9.
Muir, R. 1975. Modern Political Geography. London: Macmillan.
Muir, R. 1978. Radical geography or a new orthodoxy? Area 10, 322–7.
Muir, R. 1979. Radical geography and Marxism. Area 11, 126–7.
Mulkay, M. J. 1975. Three models of scientific development. Sociological Review 23, 509–26.
Mulkay, M. J. 1976. Methodology in the sociology of science: Some reflections on the study of radio astronomy.
In G. Lemaine et al. (eds) Perspectives in the Emergence of Scientific Disciplines. The Hague: Mouton, 207–20.
Mulkay, M. J. 1978. Consensus in science. Social Science Information 17, 107–22.
Mulkay, M. J., Gilbert, G. N. and Woolgar, S. 1975. Problem areas and research networks in science. Sociology
9, 187–203.
Müller-Wille, C. 1978. The forgotten heritage: Christaller’s antecedents. In B. J. L. Berry (ed.) The Nature of
Change in Geographical Ideas. DeKalb, IL: Northern Illinois University Press, 37–64.
Mumford, L. 1956. Prospect. In W. L. Thomas (ed.) Man’s Role in Changing the Face of the Earth. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1141–52.
Murdie, R. A. 1969. Factorial Ecology of Metropolitan Toronto 1951–1961. Chicago: University of Chicago, Department
of Geography, Research Paper 116.
Murdoch, J. 1998. The spaces of actor-network theory. Geoforum 29, 357–74.
Murdoch, J. 2006. Post-Structuralist Geography. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage.
Murphy, A. B. 1991. Regions as social constructs: The gap between theory and practice. Progress in Human Geography
15, 22–35.
Murphy, A. B. 2004. Centennial forum: Where we have come from and where we are going. Annals of the Association
of American Geographers 94, 701–2.
Murphy, A. B. 2007. Geography’s place in higher education in the United States. Journal of Geography in Higher
Education 31, 121–41
Murphy, A. B. 2013. Advancing geographical understanding: Why engaging grand regional narratives matters.
Dialogues in Human Geography 3, 131–49 (with subsequent discussion and response).
Myrdal, G. 1957. Economic Theory and Underdeveloped Regions. London: Duckworth.
Nagar, R., Lawson, V., McDowell, L. and Hanson, S. 2002. Locating globalization: Feminist (re)readings of
subjects and spaces of globalization. Economic Geography 78, 257–84.
Nairn, T. 1977. The Break-up of Britain: Crisis and neo-nationalism. London: New Left Books.
Nash, C. 1996. Reclaiming vision: Looking at landscape and the body. Gender, Place and Culture 3, 149–69.
Nash, C. 2000. Performativity in practice: Some recent work in cultural geography. Progress in Human Geography 24,
653–64.
Nast, H. 1994. Opening remarks on ‘Women in the field’. Professional Geographer 46, 54–66.
Nast, H. 2002. Special Issue: Queer patriarchies, queer racisms, international. Prologue: Crosscurrents. Antipode
34, 835–44.
National Academy of Sciences-National Research Council (NAS-NRC) 1965. The Science of Geography. Washington,
DC: NAS-NRC.
National Academy of Sciences-National Research Council (NAS-NRC) 1997. Rediscovering Geography: New relevance
for science and society. Washington, DC: National Research Council.
National Research Council (NRC) 2010. A Data–Based Assessment of Research–Doctorate Programs in the United States.
Washington, DC: National Academies Press.
National Research Council (NRC) 2011. Understanding the Changing Planet: Strategic directions for the geographical sciences.
Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.
Natter, W. 2003. Geopolitics in Germany, 1919–45. In J. Agnew, K. Mitchell and G. Toal (eds) A Companion to
Political Geography. Oxford: Blackwell, 187–203.
Nayak, A. 2003. Last of the ‘real Geordies’? White masculinities and the subcultural response to deindus-
trialisation. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 21, 7–25.
Nayak, A. 2010. Race, affect, and emotion: Young people, racism, and graffiti in the postcolonial English
suburbs. Environment and Planning A 42, 2370–92.
Nayak, A. and Jeffrey, A. 2011. Geographical Thought: An introduction to ideas in human geography. London: Pearson.
References 463

Neft, D. 1966. Statistical Analysis for Areal Distributions. Philadelphia, PA: Monograph 2, Regional Science Research
Institute.
Nelson, L. and Seager, J. 2005. A Companion to Feminist Geography. Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell.
Nelson, T. A. 2012. Trends in spatial statistics. Professional Geographer 64, 83–94.
Newman, D. 1996. Writing together separately: Critical discourse and the problems of cross-ethnic
co-authorship. Area 28, 1–12.
Newman, D. and Portugali, J. 1987. Israeli–Palestinian relations as reflected in the scientific literature. Progress in
Human Geography 11, 315–32.
Newman, J. L. 1973. The use of the term ‘hypothesis’ in geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
63, 22–7.
Newman, O. 1972. Defensible Space: Crime prevention through urban design. New York: Macmillan.
Nicholls, W. J. 2011. The Los Angeles school: Difference, politics, city. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research
35, 189–206.
Nickles, T. (ed.) 2003. Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nijman, J. 2000. The paradigmatic city. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 90, 135–45.
Nystuen, J. D. 1968 [1963]. Identification of some fundamental spatial concepts. Papers of the Michigan Academy of
Science, Arts, and Letters, 48, 373–84. Reprinted in B. J. L. Berry and D. F. Marble (eds) Spatial Analysis: A reader in
statistical geography. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 35–41.
Nystuen, J. D. 1984. Comment on ‘Artificial intelligence and its applicability to geographical problem solving’.
Professional Geographer 36, 358–9.
Ó hUallacháin, B. and Leslie, T. F. 2013. Spatial pattern and order in sunbelt retailing: Shopping in Phoenix in
the twenty-first century. Professional Geographer 65, 396–420.
O’Kelly, M. 1999. Introduction to the thirtieth anniversary special issue. Geographical Analysis 30, 311–17.
O’Loughlin, J. 2002. The electoral geography of Weimar Germany: Exploratory spatial data analyses (ESDA) of
Protestant support for the Nazi party. Political Analysis 10, 217–43.
O’Riordan, T. 1971a. Environmental management. In C. Board, R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R. Stoddart (eds)
Progress in Geography, Vol. 3. London: Edward Arnold, 173–231.
O’Riordan, T. 1971b. Perspectives in Resource Management. London: Pion.
O’Riordan, T. 1976. Environmentalism. London: Pion.
O’Riordan, T. 1981. Environmentalism, 2nd edn. London: Pion.
O’Sullivan, D. 2014, Commentary. Don’t panic! The need for change and for curricular pluralism. Dialogues in
Human Geography 4, 39–44.
O’Sullivan, D. and Unwin, D. J. 2003. Geographic Information Analysis. New York: John Wiley.
Ó Tuathail, G. 1992. Foreign policy and the hyperreal: The Reagan administration and the ‘scripting’ of South
Africa’. In T. J. Barnes and J. S. Duncan (eds) Writing Worlds: Discourse, text and metaphor in the representation of landscape.
London: Routledge, 155–75.
Ó Tuathail, G. 1994. (Dis)placing geopolitics: Writing on the maps of global politics. Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space 12, 525–46.
Ó Tuathail, G. 1996. Critical Geopolitics. London and New York: Routledge.
Ó Tuathail, G. 2000. Dis/placing the geo-politics which one cannot not want. Political Geography 19, 385–96.
Ó Tuathail, G. 2003. ‘Just out looking for a fight’: American affect and the invasion of Iraq. Antipode: A Radical
Journal of Geography 35, 856–70.
Ó Tuathail, G. and Dalby, S. 1994. Critical geopolitics: Unfolding spaces for thought in geography and global
politics. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 12, 513–14.
Ó Tuathail, G. and Dalby, S. 1998. Introduction. Rethinking geopolitics: Towards a critical geopolitics. In G. Ó
Tuathail and S. Dalby (eds) Rethinking Geopolitics. London and New York: Routledge, 1–15.
Öberg, S. 2005. Hägerstrand and the remaking of Sweden. Progress in Human Geography 29, 340–9.
Obermeyer, N. J. 1994. GIS: A new profession? Professional Geographer 46, 498–503.
Odum, H. W. and Moore, H. E. 1938. American Regionalism: A cultural–historical approach to national integration. New York:
H. Holt & Company.
Olds, K. 2001. Practices for ‘process geographies’: A view from within and outside the periphery. Environment and
Planning D: Society and Space 19, 127–36.
Ollman, B. 1993. Dialectical Investigations. London and New York: Routledge.
Olsson, G. 1965. Distance and Human Interaction: A review and bibliography. Philadelphia, PA: Regional Science
Research Institute, Bibliography Series Number 2.
464 References

Olsson, G. 1969. Inference problems in locational analysis. In K. R. Cox and R. G. Golledge (eds) Behavioral
Problems in Geography: A symposium. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Studies in Geography 17, 14–34.
Olsson, G. 1978. Of ambiguity or far cries from a memorializing mamafesta. In D. Ley and M. S. Samuels (eds)
Humanistic Geography. London: Croom Helm, 109–20.
Olsson, G. 1979. Social science and human action or on hitting your head against the ceiling of language. In S.
Gale and G. Olsson (eds) Philosophy in Geography. Dordrecht: Reidel, 287–308.
Olsson, G. 1980. Birds in Egg/Eggs in Bird. London: Pion.
Olsson, G. 1982. -/-. In P. R. Gould and G. Olsson (eds) A Search for Common Ground. London: Pion, 223–31.
Olsson, G. 1991. Lines of Power/Limits of Language. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Olsson, G. 1992. Lines of power. In T. J. Barnes and J. S. Duncan (eds) Writing Worlds: Discourse, text and metaphor in the
representation of landscape. London: Routledge, 86–96.
Olsson, G. 2007. Abysmal: A critique of cartographic reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Openshaw, S. 1984a. The modifiable areal unit problem. CATMOG 38, Norwich: Geo Books.
Openshaw, S. 1984b. Ecological fallacies and the analysis of areal census data. Environment and Planning A 16,
17–32.
Openshaw, S. 1986. Nuclear Power: Siting and safety. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Openshaw, S. 1989. Computer modelling in human geography. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling Geography.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 70–88.
Openshaw, S. 1991. A view on the GIS crisis in geography: Or, using GIS to put Humpty-Dumpty back together
again. Environment and Planning A 23, 621–8.
Openshaw, S. 1992. Further thoughts on geography and GIS: A reply. Environment and Planning A 24, 463–6.
Openshaw, S. 1994. Computational human geography: Towards a research agenda. Environment and Planning A 26,
499–505.
Openshaw, S. 1995. Human systems modelling as a new grand challenge area in science: What has happened
to the science in social science? Environment and Planning A 27, 159–64.
Openshaw, S. 1996. Fuzzy logic as a new scientific paradigm for doing geography. Environment and Planning A 28,
761–8.
Openshaw, S. 1998. Building automated geographical analysis and explanation machines. In P. Longley,
S. Brooks, R. MacDonnell and B. Macmillan (eds) Geocomputation: A primer. Chichester: John Wiley, 95–116.
Openshaw, S. and Goddard, J. B. 1987. Some implications of the commodification of information and the
emerging information economy for applied geographical analysis in the United Kingdom. Environment and
Planning A 19, 1423–40.
Openshaw, S. and Openshaw, C. 1997. Artificial Intelligence in Geography. Chichester: John Wiley.
Openshaw, S. and Rao, L. 1995. Algorithms for reengineering 1991 census geography. Environment and Planning
A 27, 425–46.
Openshaw, S. and Taylor, P. J. 1979. A million or so correlation coefficients: Three experiments on the modifiable
areal unit problem. In N. Wrigley (ed.) Statistical Applications in the Spatial Sciences. London: Pion, 127–44.
Openshaw, S. and Taylor, P. J. 1981. The modifiable areal unit problem. In N. Wrigley and R. J. Bennett, (eds)
Quantitative Geography: A British view. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 60–70.
Openshaw, S. and Turton, I. 2001. Using a geographical explanations machine to explore spatial factors relating
to primary school performance. Geographical and Environmental Modelling 5, 85–101.
Openshaw, S., Blake, M. and Wymer, C. 1995. Using neurocomputing methods to classify Britain’s residential
areas. In P. F. Fisher (ed.) Innovations in GIS 2. London: Taylor & Francis, 97–112.
Openshaw, S., Carver, S. and Fernie, J. 1989. Britain’s Nuclear Waste: Siting and safety. London: Belhaven Press.
Openshaw, S., Charlton, M., Craft, A. W. and Birch, J. 1988. Investigation of leukaemia clusters by use of a
geographical analysis machine. Lancet, 6 February, 272–3.
Openshaw, S., Steadman, P. and Greene, O. 1983. Doomsday: Britain after nuclear attack. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Openshaw, S., Wymer, C. and Charlton, M. 1986. A geographical information and mapping system for the BBC
Domesday optical discs. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS11, 296–304.
Openshaw, S., Wymer, C. and Craft, A. W. 1988. A Mark I geographical analysis machine for the automated
analysis of point data sets. International Journal of Geographical Information Systems 1, 335–58.
Ord, J. K. and Getis, A. 1995. Local spatial autocorrelation statistics: Distributional issues and an application.
Geographical Analysis 27, 286–96.
Orme, A. R. 2002. Shifting paradigms in geomorphology: The fate of research ideas in an educational context.
Geomorphology 47, 325–42.
References 465

Östh, J., Clark, W. A. V. and Malmberg, B. 2015. Measuring the scale of segregation using k-nearest neighbour
aggregates. Geographical Analysis 47, 34–49.
Owens, P. L. 1984. Rural leisure and recreation research: A retrospective evaluation. Progress in Human Geography
8, 157–88.
Ozouf-Marignier, M.-V. and Robic, M.-C. 1999. The Tableau is alive and well . . . reactions to the Tableau de la
Géographie de la France of Paul Vidal de la Blache. In A. Buttimer, S. D. Brunn and U. Wardenga (eds) Text and Image:
Social construction of regional knowledges. Leipzig: Leibniz Institute for Regional Geography, Beiträge zur regionalen
Geographie 49, 54–66.
Paasi, A. 1991. Deconstructing regions: Notes on the scales of social life. Environment and Planning A 23, 239–56.
Paasi, A. 2005. Globalisation, academic capitalism, and the uneven geographies of international journal
publishing spaces. Environment and Planning A 37, 769–89.
Pacione, M. (ed.) 1999. Applied Geography: Principles and practice. London: Routledge.
Pacione, M. 1990a. Conceptual issues in applied urban geography. Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie 81,
3–13.
Pacione, M. 1990b. On the dangers of misinterpretation. Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie 81, 26–8.
Pacione, M. 2014. Scottish Geography:  A historiography. Glasgow: Royal Scottish Geographical Society.
Pagliara, F. and Wilson, A. G. 2010. The state-of-the-art in building residential location models. In F. Pagliara,
J. Preston and D. Simmons (eds) Residential Location Choice. New York: Springer, 1–20.
Pahl, R. E. 1965. Trends in social geography. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds) Frontiers in Geographical Teaching.
London: Methuen, 81–100.
Pahl, R. E. 1969. Urban social theory and research. Environment and Planning 1, 143–54. (Reprinted in R. E. Pahl
1970, Whose City? London: Longman, 209–25.)
Pahl, R. E. 1975. Whose city? And Other Essays, 2nd edn. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Pahl, R. E. 1979. Socio-political factors in resource allocation. In D. T. Herbert and D. M. Smith (eds) Social
Problems and the City: Geographical perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 33–46.
Pain, R. 1991. Space, sexual violence and social control: Integrating geographical and feminist analyses of
women’s fear of crime. Progress in Human Geography 15, 415–31.
Pain, R. 2003. Social geography: On action-orientated research. Progress in Human Geography 27, 649–57, 677–85.
Pain, R., Kesby, M. and Askins, K. 2011. Geographies of impact: Power, participation and potential. Area 43,
183–88.
Painter, J. 2000. Pierre Bourdieu. In M. Crang and N. Thrift (eds) Thinking Space. New York and London: Routledge,
239–59.
Painter, J. 2002. The rise of the workfare state. In R. J. Johnston, P. J. Taylor and M. J. Watts (eds) Geographies of Global
Change: Remapping the world. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 158–73.
Painter, J. and Philo, C. 1995. Spaces of citizenship: An introduction. Political Geography 14, 107–20.
Palfreyman, D. and Tapper, T. 2014. Reshaping the University: The rise of the regulated market in higher education. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Palm, R. 1979. Financial and real estate institutions in the housing market. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston
(eds) Geography and the Urban Environment, Vol. 2. Chichester: John Wiley, 83–124.
Palm, R. 2003. Textbooks that moved generations. Progress in Human Geography 27, 515–18.
Palm, R. and Pred, A. R. 1978. The status of American women: A time-geographic view. In D. Lanegran and R.
Palm (eds) Invitation to Geography, 2nd edn. New York: McGraw-Hill, 99–109.
Papageorggiou, G. J. (ed.) 1976. Mathematical Land Use Theory. Lexington, MA: D. C. Heath.
Papageorgiou, G. J. 1969. Description of a basis necessary to the analysis of spatial systems. Geographical Analysis 1,
213–15.
Pappenberger, F., Cloke, H. L., Parker, D. J., Wetterhall, F., Richardson, D. S. and Theilen, J. 2015. The monetary
benefit of early flood warnings in Europe. Environmental Science and Policy 51, 278–91.
Park, C. P. 1994. Sacred Worlds: An introduction to geography and religion. London and New York: Routledge.
Parker, G. 1985. Western Geopolitical Thought in the Twentieth Century. London: Croom Helm.
Parker, W. H. 1982. Mackinder: Geography as an aid to statecraft. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
Parkes, D. N. and Thrift, N. J. 1980. Times, Spaces and Places. Chichester: John Wiley.
Parkinson, S., Searle, B. A., Smith, S. J., Stoakes, A. and Wood, G. 2009. Mortgage equity withdrawal in Australia
and Britain: Towards a wealth–fare state? European Journal of Housing Policy 9, 363–87.
Parr, D. A. and Lu,Y. 2010. The landscape of GIScience publications 1997–2007: An empirical investigation with
latent semantic analysis. Transactions in GIS 14, 689–708.
466 References

Parry, M. and Duncan, R. 1995. The Economic Implications of Climate Change. London: Earthscan.
Parsons, J. J. 1977. Geography as exploration and discovery. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 67, 1–16.
Paterson, J. H. 1974. Writing regional geography. In C. Board, R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R. Stoddart (eds)
Progress in Geography, Vol. 6. London: Edward Arnold, 1–26.
Paterson, J. L. 1985. David Harvey’s Geography. London: Croom Helm.
Patmore, J. A. 1970. Land and Leisure. Newton Abbott: David & Charles.
Patmore, J. A. 1983. Recreation and Resources: Leisure patterns and leisure places. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Patterson, T. C. 1986. The last sixty years: Toward a social history of Americanist archaeology in the United
States. American Anthropologist 88, 7–26.
Pattie, C. J. and Johnston, R. J. 1995. ‘Its not like that round here’: Region, economic evaluations and voting at
the 1992 British general election. European Journal of Political Research 28, 1–32.
Pattie, C. J. and Johnston, R. J. 2000. ‘People who talk together vote together’: An exploration of contextual
effects in Great Britain. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 90, 41–66.
Pattison, W. D. 1964. The four traditions of geography. Journal of Geography 63, 211–16.
Pawson, E. J. 1999. Postcolonial New Zealand? In K. Anderson and F. Gale (eds) Cultural Geographies. Melbourne:
Longman, 25–50.
Pawson, E. J. 2009. Oxbridge geographies. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (ed.) International Encyclopedia of Human
Geography. Oxford: Elsevier, 56–62.
Pawson, E. J. 2011. Creating public spaces for geography in New Zealand: Towards an assessment of the
contributions of Kenneth Cumberland. New Zealand Geographer 67, 102–15.
Peach, C. 2002. Social geography: New religions and ethnoburbs – contrasts with cultural geography. Progress in
Human Geography 26, 252–60.
Peach, C. 2003. Geography and the fragmented city. In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams (eds) A Century of British
Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 563–82.
Peach, C. and Smith, S. J. 1981. Introduction. In C. Peach, V. Robinson and S. J. Smith (eds) Ethnic Segregation in
Cities. London: Croom Helm, 9–24.
Peake, L. 1993. Race and Sexuality: Challenging the patriarchal structuring of urban social space. Environment and
Planning D: Society and Space 11, 415–32.
Peake, L. 1994. ‘Proper words in proper places . . .’ Or, of young Turks and old turkeys. Canadian Geographer 38,
204–6.
Peake, L. and Kobayashi, A. 2002. Policies and practices for an antiracist geography at the millennium. Professional
Geographer 54, 50–61.
Peake, L. and Sheppard, E. 2014. The emergence of radical/critical geography in North America. ACME: An
International E-Journal for Critical Geographies 13, 305–27.
Peck, J. 1996. Work-place:The social regulation of labor markets. New York: Guilford.
Peck, J. 1999. Grey geography? Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS24, 131–5.
Peck, J. 2000. Jumping in, joining up and getting on. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS25,
255–8.
Peck, J. 2001. Workfare States. New York: Guilford.
Peck, J. 2013. Making space for labour. In D. Featherstone and J. Painter (eds) Spatial Politics: Essays for Doreen Massey.
Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 99–114.
Peck, J. and Tickell, A. 1992. Local modes of social regulation? Regulation theory, Thatcherism and regional
development. Geoforum 23, 347–64.
Peck, J. and Tickell, A. 1994. ‘Jungle law breaks out’: Neoliberalism and global–local disorder. Area 26,
317–26.
Peck, J. and Tickell, A. 1995. The social regulation of uneven development: ‘Regulatory deficit’, England’s South
East, and the collapse of Thatcherism. Environment and Planning A 27, 15–40.
Peck, J. and Tickell, A. 1996. The return of the Manchester men: Men’s words and men’s deeds in the remaking
of the local state. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 21, 595–616.
Peck, J. and Tickell, A. 2002. Neoliberalizing space. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 34, 380–404.
Peck, J. and Tickell, A. 2012. Apparitions of neoliberalism: Revisiting ‘Jungle law breaks out’. Area 44, 245–9.
Peet, R. (ed.) 1978. Radical Geography: Alternative viewpoints on contemporary social issues. London: Methuen.
Peet, R. 1971. Poor, hungry America. Professional Geographer 23, 99–104.
Peet, R. 1975a. Inequality and poverty: A Marxist-geographic theory. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
65, 564–71.
References 467

Peet, R. 1975b. The geography of crime: A political critique. Professional Geographer 27, 277–80.
Peet, R. 1976. Further comments on the geography of crime. Professional Geographer 28, 96–100.
Peet, R. 1977. The development of radical geography in the United States. Progress in Human Geography 1, 240–63.
Peet, R. 1979. Societal contradiction and Marxist geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69,
164–9.
Peet, R. 1980. The transition from feudalism to capitalism. In R. Peet (ed.) An Introduction to Marxist Theories of
Underdevelopment. Canberra. Canberra: Australian National University, Research School of Pacific Studies,
Department of Human Geography, 51–74.
Peet, R. 1985a. The social origins of environmental determinism. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 75,
309–33.
Peet, R. 1985b. Radical geography in the United States: A personal history. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 17,
1–7.
Peet, R. 1989. World capitalism and the destruction of regional cultures. In R. J. Johnston and P. J. Taylor (eds)
A World in Crisis? Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 175–99.
Peet, R. 1991. Global Capitalism:Theories of societal development. London: Routledge.
Peet, R. 1993. Reading Fukuyama: Politics at the end of history. Political Geography 12, 64–78.
Peet, R. 1996a. A sign taken for history: Daniel Shays’ memorial in Peterham, Massachusetts. Annals of the Association
of American Geographers 86, 21–43.
Peet, R. 1996b: Discursive idealism in the ‘landscape-as-text’ school. Professional Geographer 48, 96–8.
Peet, R. 1998. Modern Geographical Thought. Oxford and Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Peet, R. 2005. Bio-gaze: Review essays on Key Thinkers on Space and Place. Environment and Planning A 37, 165–7.
Peet, R. and Lyons, J. V. 1981. Marxism: Dialectical materialism, social formation and the geographic relations.
In M. E. Harvey and B. P. Holly (eds) Themes in Geographic Thought. London: Croom Helm, 187–205.
Peet, R. and Thrift, N. J. 1989. Political economy and human geography. In R. Peet and N. J. Thrift (eds)
New Models in Geography,  Vol. 1. London: Unwin Hyman, 3–27.
Peet, R. and Watts, M. (eds) 1996. Liberation Ecologies: Nature, development and social movements. London and New York:
Routledge.
Peet, R. and Watts, M. (eds) 2004. Liberation Ecologies, 2nd edn. London and New York: Routledge.
Peet, R., Robbins, R. and Watts, M. (eds) 2011. Global Political Ecology. Abingdon and New York: Routledge.
Peltier, L. C. 1954. Geomorphology. In P. E. James and C. F. Jones (eds) American Geography: Inventory and prospect.
Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 362–81.
Penning-Rowsell, E. C. 1981. Fluctuating fortunes in gauging landscape value. Progress in Human Geography
5, 25–41.
Penning-Rowsell, E. C. and Pardoe, J. 2012. Who benefits and who loses from flood risk reduction? Environment
and Planning C: Government and Policy 30, 448–66.
Penrose, J. and Jackson, P. 1993. Identity and the politics of difference. In P. Jackson and J. Penrose (eds)
Constructions of Race, Place and Nation. London: UCL Press, 202–10.
Pepper, D. 1984. The Roots of Modern Environmentalism. London: Croom Helm.
Pepper, D. 1996. Modern Environmentalism: An introduction. London: Routledge.
Pepper, D. and Jenkins, A. (eds) 1985. The Geography of Peace and War. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Pepper, D. and Jenkins, A. 1983. A call to arms: Geography and peace studies. Area 15, 202–8.
Pepper, S. C. 1942. World Hypotheses. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Perry, P. J. 1969. H. C. Darby and historical geography: A survey and review. Geographische Zeitschrift 57, 161–77.
Perry, P. J. 1979. Beyond Domesday. Progress in Human Geography 3, 407–16.
Persson, O. and Ellegård, E. 2011. Torsten Hägerstrand in the citation time web. Professional Geographer 64,
1–12.
Petch, J. R. and Haines-Young, R. H. 1980. The challenge of critical rationalism for methodology in physical
geography. Progress in Physical Geography 4, 63–78.
Peter, L. and Hull, R. 1969. The Peter Principle. London: Bantam Books.
Phelps N. A. and Tewdwr-Jones, M. 2008. If geography is anything, maybe it’s planning alter ego? Reflections
on policy relevance in two disciplines concerned with place and space. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers 33, 566–84.
Philbrick, A. K. 1957. Principles of areal functional organization in regional human geography. Economic Geography
33, 299–366.
Phillips, M. and Unwin, T. 1985. British historical geography: Places and people. Area 17, 155–64.
468 References

Phillips, R. 2006. Book review: Spaces of Masculinities, edited by Bettina van Hoven and Kathrin Horschelmann.
Progress in Human Geography 30, 550–2.
Phillips, R. 2010. The impact agenda and geographies of curiosity. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 35,
447–52.
Philo, C. (comp.) 1991. New Words, New Worlds: Reconceptualising social and cultural geography – conference
proceedings. Aberystwyth: Cambrian Printers.
Philo, C. 1992. Foucault’s geography. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 10, 137–61.
Philo, C. 1994. Political geography and everything: Invited notes on ‘transpolitical geography’. Geoforum 25,
525–32.
Philo, C. 1995. Animals, geography and the city: Notes on inclusions and exclusions. Environment and Planning D:
Society and Space 13, 655–81.
Philo, C. 1998. Reading Drumlin: Academic geography and a student geographical magazine. Progress in Human
Geography 22, 344–67.
Philo, C. 2000. More words, more worlds: Reflections on the ‘cultural turn’ and human geography. In I. Cook,
D. Crouch, S. Naylor and J. R. Ryan (eds) Cultural Turns/Geographical Turns: Perspectives on cultural geography. Harlow:
Prentice Hall, 26–53.
Philo, C. 2005. Spacing lives and lively spaces: Partial remarks on Sarah Whatmore’s Hybrid Geographies. Antipode:
A Radical Journal of Geography 37, 824–33.
Philo, C. (ed.) 2008. Theory and Methods: Critical essays in human geography. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Philo, C. 2009. Cultural turn. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human Geography.
Amsterdam: Elsevier, 442–50.
Philo, C. 2012. A ‘new Foucault’ with lively implications – or ‘the crawfish advances sideways’. Transactions of the
Institute of British Geographers NS37, 496–514.
Philo, C. and Wilbert, C. (eds) 2000. Animal Spaces, Beastly Places: New geographies of human–animal relations. London:
Routledge.
Phipps, A. G. 2001. Empirical applications of structuration theory. Geografiska Annaler: Series B, Human Geography 83,
189–204.
Pickerill, J. and Chatterton, P. 2006. Notes towards autonomous geographies: Creation, resistance and self-
management as survival tactics. Progress in Human Geography 6, 730–46.
Pickering, A. 2012. The world since Kuhn. Social Studies of Science 42, 467–73.
Pickles, J. 1985. Phenomenology, Science and Geography: Spatiality and the human sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Pickles, J. 1986. Geography and Humanism. CATMOG 44, Norwich: Geo Books.
Pickles, J. 1988. From fact-world to life-world: The phenomenological method and social science. In J. Eyles
and D. M. Smith (eds) Qualitative Methods in Human Geography. Cambridge: Polity Press, 233–54.
Pickles, J. 1992. Texts, hermeneutics and propaganda. In T. J. Barnes and J. S. Duncan (eds) Writing Worlds:
Discourse, text and metaphor in the representation of landscape. London: Routledge, 193–230.
Pickles, J. 1993. Discourse on method and the history of discipline: Reflections on Dobson’s 1983 automated
geography. Professional Geographer 45, 451–5.
Pickles, J. (ed.) 1995a. Ground Truth: The social implications of geographical information systems. New York: The Guilford
Press.
Pickles, J. 1995b. Representations in an electronic age: Geography, GIS and democracy. In J. Pickles (ed.) Ground
Truth:The social implications of geographical information systems. New York: The Guilford Press, 1–30.
Pickles, J. 2004. A History of Spaces: Cartographic reason, mapping and the geo-coded world. London and New York: Routledge.
Pickles, J. 2007. Radical thought-in-action: Gunnar Olsson’s critique of cartographic reason. Geografiska
Annaler: Series B, Human Geography 89, 394–97.
Pickles, J. and Smith, A. (eds) 1998. Theorising Transition: The political economy of post-Communist transformations. London
and New York: Routledge.
Pickvance, C. 1976. Housing, reproduction of capital and reproduction of labour power: Some recent French
work. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 8, 58–68.
Pile, S. 1991. Practising interpretative geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS16, 458–69.
Pile, S. 1993. Human agency and human geography revisited: A critique of ‘new models’ of the self. Transaction
of the Institute of British Geographers NS18, 122–39.
Pile, S. 1994. Masculinism, the use of dualistic epistemologies and third spaces. Antipode: A Radical Journal of
Geography 26, 255–77.
References 469

Pile, S. 1996. The Body and the City. Psychoanalysis, space and subjectivity. London: Routledge.
Pile, S. 2010. Emotions and affect in recent human geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 35,
5–20.
Pile, S. and Keith, M. 1997. Geographies of Resistance. London: Routledge.
Pile, S. and Rose, G. 1992. All or nothing – politics and critique in the modernism-postmodernism debate.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 10, 123–36.
Pile, S. and Thrift, N. (eds) 1995. Mapping the Subject: Geographies of cultural transformation. London and New York:
Routledge.
Pinch, S. P. 1985. Cities and Services:The geography of collective consumption. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Pinch, S. P. 1997. Worlds of Welfare. London: Routledge.
Pinch, S. P. 1998. Knowledge communities, spatial theory and social policy. Social Policy and Administration, 32, 104–9.
Pipkin, J. S. 1981. Cognitive behavioral geography and repetitive travel. In K. R. Cox and R. G. Golledge (eds)
Behavioral Problems in Geography Revisited. London: Methuen, 145–80.
Pirie, G. H. 1976. Thoughts on revealed and spatial behaviour. Environment and Planning A 8, 947–55.
Pitman, A. J. 2005. On the role of geography in earth system science. Geoforum 36, 137–48.
Pitts, F. R. 1965. A graph theoretic approach to historical geography. Professional Geographer 17(5), 15–20.
Platt, R. H. 1986. Floods and man: A geographer’s agenda. In R. W. Kates and I. Burton (eds) Geography, Resources
and Environment,Vol. 2:Themes from the work of Gilbert F. White. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 28–68.
Ploszajska, T. 1999. Geographical Education, Empire and Citizenship: Geography teaching and learning in English schools, 1870–1944.
Historical Geography Research Series, 35. London: Royal Geographical Society (with the Institute of British
Geographers).
Plummer, P. 2001. Vague theories, sophisticated techniques and poor data. Environment and Planning A 33, 761–4.
Plummer, P. and Sheppard, E. S. 2001. Must emancipatory economic geography be qualitative? Antipode 33,
194–9.
Pocock, D. C. D. 1983. The paradox of humanistic geography. Area 15, 355–8.
Pocock, D. C. D. and Hudson, R. 1978. Images of the Urban Environment. London: Macmillan.
Poiker, T. K. 1983. The shining armor of the white knight. Professional Geographer 35, 348–9.
Pollard, J. S., Henry, N., Bryson, J. and Daniels, P. 2000. Shades of grey? Geography and policy. Transactions of
the Institute of British Geographers NS25, 243–8.
Pooler, J. A. 1977. The origins of the spatial tradition in geography: An interpretation. Ontario Geography 11,
56–83.
Popper, K. R. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.
Popper, K. R. 1967. Replies to my critics. In P. A. Schipp (ed.) The Philosophy of Karl Popper, Vol. 2. La Salle, IN:
Open Court Publishing Company, 961–97.
Popper, K. R. 1970. Normal science and its dangers. In I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds) Criticism and the Growth of
Knowledge. London: Cambridge University Press, 51–8.
Porteous, J. D. 1977. Environment and Behavior. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Porteous, J. D. 1985. Literature and Humanist Geography. Area 17, 117–22.
Porteous, J. D. 1986. Bodyscape: The body-landscape metaphor. Canadian Geographer 30, 2–19.
Porteous, J. D. 1988. Topocide: The annihilation of place. In J. Eyles and D. M. Smith (eds) Qualitative Methods in
Human Geography. Cambridge: Polity Press, 75–93.
Porter, J. R. 2011. Context, location, and space:The continued development of our geo-sociological imaginations.
American Sociologist 42, 288–302.
Porter, P. W. 1978. Geography as human ecology. Human geography: Coming of age. American Behavioral Scientist
22, 15–40.
Porter, P. W. and Lukermann, F. 1975. The geography of utopia. In D. Lowenthal and M. J. Bowden (eds) Geography
of the Mind: Essays in historical geosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 197–224.
Poulsen, M. F., Johnston, R. J. and Forrest, J. 2011. Using local statistics and neighbourhood classifications to
portray ethnic residential segregation: A London example. Environment and Planning B 38, 636–58.
Powell, J. M. 1970. The Public Lands of Australia Felix: Settlement and land appraisal in Victoria 1834–1891. Melbourne:
Oxford University Press.
Powell, J. M. 1971. Utopia, millennium and the cooperative ideal: A behavioral matrix in the settlement process.
Australian Geographer 11, 606–18.
Powell, J. M. 1972. Images of Australia. Clayton, Victoria, Australia: Monash University Publications in Geography
No. 3.
470 References

Powell, J. M. 1977. Mirrors of the New World: Images and image-makers in the settlement process. Folkestone: Dawson.
Powell, J. M. 1980a. Thomas Griffith Taylor 1880–1963. In T. W. Freeman and P. Pinchemel (eds) Geographers:
Biobibliographical studies, Vol. 5. London: Mansell, 141–54.
Powell, J. M. 1980b. The haunting of Saloman’s house: Geography and the limits of science. Australian Geographer
14, 327–41.
Powell, J. M. 1981. Editorial comment: ‘Professional’ geography into the eighties? Australian Geographical Studies 19,
228–30.
Powell, M. and Boyne, G. A. 2001. The spatial strategy of equality and the spatial division of welfare. Social Policy
and Administration 35, 181–94.
Powell, R. C. 2011. Echoes of the new geography? History and philosophy of geography I. Progress in Human
Geography 36, 518–26.
Powell, R. C. 2015. Notes on a geographical canon? Measures, models and scholarly enterprise. Journal of Historical
Geography, 49, 2–8.
Power, M. 1998. The dissemination of development. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 16, 577–98.
Power, M. and Sidaway, J. D. 2004. The degeneration of tropical geography. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 94, 585–601.
Pratt, G. 1989. Quantitative techniques and humanistic–historical materialist perspectives. In A. Kobayashi and
S. Mackenzie (eds) Remaking Human Geography. Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman, 101–15.
Pratt, G. 1992. Spatial metaphors and speaking positions. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 10, 241–4.
Pratt, G. 1999. From registered nurse to registered nanny: Discursive geographies of Filipina domestic workers
in Vancouver, BC. Economic Geography 75, 215–36.
Pratt, G. 2000. Feminist geographies. In R. J. Johnston, D. Gregory, G. Pratt and M. Watts (eds) The Dictionary of
Human Geography, 4th edn. Oxford: Blackwell, 259–62.
Pratt, G. 2009. Critical realism/critical realist geographies. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia
of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 379–84.
Pratt, G. and Hanson, S. 1988. Gender, class and space. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 6, 15–35.
Pratt, G. and Hanson, S. 1994. Geography and the construction of difference. Gender, Place and Culture 1, 5–29.
Pred, A. 2005. Hägerstrand matters: life(-path) and death matters – some touching remarks. Progress in Human
Geography 29, 328–32.
Pred, A. R. 1965a. The concentration of high value-added manufacturing. Economic Geography 41, 108–32.
Pred, A. R. 1965b. Industrialization, initial advantage, and American metropolitan growth. Geographical Review 55,
158–85.
Pred, A. R. 1967. Behavior and Location: Foundations for a geographic and dynamic location theory. Part I. Lund: C. W. K.
Gleerup.
Pred, A. R. 1969. Behavior and Location: Foundations for a geographic and dynamic location theory. Part II. Lund: C. W. K.
Gleerup.
Pred, A. R. 1973. Urbanization, domestic planning problems and Swedish geographic research. In C. Board, R.
J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R. Stoddart (eds) Progress in Geography, Vol. 5. London: Edward Arnold, 1–77.
Pred, A. R. 1977a. The choreography of existence: Comments on Hägerstrand’s time geography and its
usefulness. Economic Geography 53, 207–21.
Pred, A. R. 1977b. City-Systems in Advanced Economies. London: Hutchinson.
Pred, A. R. 1979. The academic past through a time-geographic looking glass. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 69, 175–80.
Pred, A. R. 1981a. Production, family, and free-time projects: A time-geographic perspective on the individual
and societal change in nineteenth century US cities. Journal of Historical Geography 7, 3–36.
Pred, A. R. 1981b. Of paths and projects: Individual behavior and its societal context. In K. R. Cox and
R. G. Golledge (eds) Behavioral Problems in Geography Revisited. London: Methuen, 231–55.
Pred, A. R. 1984a. From here and now to there and then: Some notes on diffusions, defusions, and disillusions.
In M. Billinge, D. Gregory and R. Martin (eds) Recollections of a Revolution. London: Macmillan, 86–103.
Pred, A. R. 1984b. Structuration, biography formation, and knowledge: Observations on port growth during
the late mercantile period. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 2, 251–76.
Pred, A. R. 1984c. Place as historically contingent process: Structuration and the time geography of becoming
places. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 74, 279–97.
Pred, A. R. 1985. The social becomes the spatial and the spatial becomes the social. In D. Gregory and J. Urry
(eds) Social Relations and Spatial Structures. London: Macmillan, 336–75.
References 471

Pred, A. R. 1986. Becoming Places, Practice and Structure:The emergence and aftermath of enclosures in the plains villages of southwestern
Skane. Oxford: Polity Press.
Pred, A. R. 1988. Lost words as reflections of lost worlds. In R. G. Golledge, H. Couclelis and P. R. Gould (eds)
A Ground for Common Search. Santa Barbara, CA: The Santa Barbara Geographical Press, 138–47.
Pred, A. R. 1989. The locally spoken word and local struggles. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 7, 211–34.
Pred, A. R. 1990. In other wor(l)ds: Fragmented and integrated observations on gendered languages, gendered
spaces and local transformation. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 22, 33–52.
Pred, A. R. 1992. Straw men build straw houses. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 82, 305–8.
Pred, A. R. 1996. Interfusions: Consumption, identity and the practices and power relations of everyday life.
Environment and Planning A 28, 11–24.
Pred, A. R. and Kibel, B. M. 1970. An application of gaming simulation to a general model of economic
locational processes. Economic Geography 46, 136–56.
Pred, A. R. and Palm, R. 1978. The status of American women: A time-geographic view. In D. A. Lanegran and
R. Palm (eds) An Invitation to Geography, 2nd edn. New York: McGraw-Hill, 99–109.
Preticeille, E. 1976. Urban planning: The contradiction of capitalist urbanization. Antipode: A Radical Journal of
Geography 8, 69–76.
Price, M. and Lewis, M. 1993a. The reinvention of cultural geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
83, 1–17.
Price, M. and Lewis, M. 1993b. Reply: On reading cultural geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
83, 520–2.
Price, P. L. 2010. At the crossroads: Critical race theory and critical geographies of race. Progress in Human Geography
34, 147–74.
Prince, H. C. 1961–2. The geographical imagination. Landscape 11, 21–5.
Prince, H. C. 1971a. Real, imagined and abstract worlds of the past. In C. Board, R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D.
R. Stoddart (eds) Progress in Geography, Vol. 3. London: Edward Arnold, 1–86.
Prince, H. C. 1971b. America! America? Views on a pot melting 1. Questions of social relevance. Area 3, 150–3.
Prince, H. C. 1979. About half Marx for the transition from feudalism to capitalism. Area 11, 47–51.
Prince, H. C. 2000. Geographers Engaged in Historical Geography in British Higher Education 1931–1991. Historical Geography
Research Series, 36. London: Royal Geographical Society (with The Institute of British Geographers).
Proctor, J. D. 1998a. Ethics in geography: Giving moral form to the geographical imagination. Area 30, 8–18.
Proctor, J. D. 1998b. The social construction of nature: Relativist accusations, pragmatist and critical realist
responses. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 88, 352–76.
Proctor, J. D. and Smith, D. M. (eds) 1999. Geography and Ethics: Journeys in a moral terrain. London: Routledge.
Proudfoot, M. J. 1937. City retail structure. Economic Geography, 13, 425–8.
Pruitt, E. L. 1979. The Office of Naval Research and geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69,
103–8.
Prunty, M. C. 1979. Clark in the early 1940s. Annals of the Association of America Geographers 69, 42–5.
Puar, J. K., Rushbrook, D. and Schein, L. 2003. Sexuality and space: Queering geographies of globalization.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 21, 383–7.
Pudup, M. B. 1988. Arguments within regional geography. Progress in Human Geography 12, 369–90.
Pulido, L. 2002. Reflections on a white discipline. Professional Geographer 54, 42–9.
Purcell, M. 2003. Islands of practice and the Marston/Brenner debate: Toward a more synthetic critical human
geography. Progress in Human Geography 27, 317–32.
Quaini, M. 1982. Geography and Marxism. Oxford: Blackwell.
Radcliffe, S. A. 1990. Ethnicity, patriarchy and incorporation into the nation: Female migrants as domestic
servants in Peru. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 8, 379–93.
Radcliffe, S. A. 1994. (Re)presenting post-colonial women: Authority, difference and feminism. Area 26, 25–32.
Radcliffe, S. A. 1996. Gendered nations: Nostalgia, development and territory in Ecuador. Gender, Place and Culture
3, 5–21.
Radcliffe, S. A. and Westwood, S. (eds) 1996. Remaking the Nation: Place, identity and politics in Latin America. London:
Routledge.
Radcliffe, S. A., 2005. Development and geography: Towards a postcolonial development geography? Progress in
Human Geography 29, 291–98.
Radford, J. P. 1981. The social geography of the nineteenth century US city. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston
(eds) Geography and the Urban Environment 4. Chichester: John Wiley, 257–93.
472 References

Rana, S. and Joliveau, T. 2009. NeoGraphy: An extension of mainstream geography for everyone made by
everyone. Journal of Location Based Services 3, 75–81.
Ratzel, F. 1882–91. Anthropogeographie. Stuttgart: J. Engelghorn.
Ratzel, F. 1897. Politische Geografie, oder die Geographie der Staaten, des Verkhers, und der Krieges. Munich: R. Oldenbourg.
Ravenstien, E. G. 1885. The laws of migration. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society 48, 167–235.
Rawstron, E. M. 1958. Three principles of industrial location. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 25,
135–42.
Rawstron, E. M. 2002. Textbooks that moved generations. Progress in Human Geography 26, 831–6.
Ray, D. M., Villeneuve, P. Y. and Roberge, R. A. 1974. Functional prerequisites, spatial diffusion, and allometric
growth. Economic Geography 50, 341–51.
Rees, J. 1985. Natural Resources: Allocation economics, and policy. London: Methuen.
Rees, P. H. 1986. Developments in the modelling of spatial populations. In R. I. Woods and P. H. Rees (eds)
Population Structures and Models: Developments in spatial demography. London: Allen & Unwin, 97–125.
Rees, P. H. and Wilson, A. G. 1977. Spatial Population Analysis. London: Edward Arnold.
Reitsma, F. 2013. Revisiting the ‘Is GIScience a science?’ debate (or is it quite possibly scientific gerry-
mandering?). International Journal of Geographic Information Science 27, 211–21.
Relph, E. 1970. An inquiry into the relations between phenomenology and geography. Canadian Geographer 14,
193–201.
Relph, E. 1976. Place and Placelessness. London: Pion.
Relph, E. 1977. Humanism, phenomenology, and geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 67,
177–9.
Relph, E. 1981a. Phenomenology. In M. E. Harvey and B. P. Holly (eds) Themes in Geographic Thought. London:
Croom Helm, 99–114.
Relph, E. 1981b. Rational Landscapes and Humanistic Geography. London: Croom Helm.
Renfrew, A. C. 1981. Space, time and man. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS6, 257–78.
Reynolds, R. B. 1956. Statistical methods in geographical research. Geographical Review 46, 129–32.
Rhind, D. W. 1981. Geographical information systems in Britain. In N . Wrigley and R. J. Bennett (eds) Quantitative
Geography. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 17–35.
Rhind, D. W. 1986. Remote sensing, digital mapping and GIS: The creation of government policy in the UK.
Environment and Planning C: Government and Policy 4, 91–100.
Rhind, D. W. 1989. Computing, academic geography, and the world outside. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling
Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 177–90.
Rhind, D. W. 1996. Differential research funding – a comment on Smith. Area 28, 96–7.
Rhind, D. W. 2003. The geographical underpinning of society and its radical transformation. In R. J. Johnston
and M. Williams (eds) A Century of British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy,
429–62.
Rhind, D. W. and Adams, T. A. 1980. Recent developments in surveying and mapping. In E. H. Brown (ed.)
Geography,Yesterday and Tomorrow. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 181–99.
Rhind, D. W. and Hudson, R. 1981. Land Use. London: Methuen.
Rhind, D. W. and Mounsey, H. 1989. The Chorley Committee and ‘Handling geographical information’.
Environment and Planning A 21, 571–86.
Richards, K. and Wrigley, N. 1996. Geography in the United Kingdom 1992–1996. Geographical Journal 162,
41–62.
Richards, K., Batty, M., Edwards, K., Findlay, A., Foody, G., Frostick, L., Jones, K., Lee, R., Livingstone, D.,
Marsden, T., Petts, J., Philo, C., Simon, D. and Thomas, D. 2009. The nature of publishing and assessment in
geography and environmental studies: Evidence from the Research Assessment Exercise 2008. Area 41,
231–43.
Richardson, D. 2003. Federal funding for geography education. AAG Newsletter 38 (June), 2–4.
Richardson, H. W. 1973. The Economics of Urban Size. Farnborough: Saxon House.
Riddell, J. B. 1970. The Spatial Dynamics of Modernization in Sierra Leone. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
Press.
Rieser, R. 1973. The territorial illusion and the behavioural sink: Critical notes on behavioural geography.
Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 5(3), 52–7.
Ritter, K. 1817–59. Die Erdkunde, 19 vols. Berlin: G. Reimer.
Robbins, P. 2004. Political Ecology: A critical introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.
References 473

Roberts, S. 2000. Realizing critical geographies of the university. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 32,
230–44.
Robinson, A. H. 1954. Geographical cartography. In P. E. James and C. F. Jones (eds) American Geography: Inventory
and prospects. New York: Syracuse University Press, 553–77.
Robinson, A. H. 1956. The necessity of weighting values in correlation analysis of area data. Annals of the Association
of American Geographers 46, 233–6.
Robinson, A. H. 1961. On perks and pokes. Economic Geography 37, 181–3.
Robinson, A. H. 1962. Mapping the correspondence of isarithmic maps. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 52, 414–25.
Robinson, A. H. and Bryson, R. A. 1957. A method for describing quantitatively the correspondence of
geographical distributions. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 47, 379–91.
Robinson, A. H., Lindberg, J. B. and Brinkman, L. W. 1961. A correlation and regression analysis applied to rural
farm densities in the Great Plains. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 51, 211–21.
Robinson, G. M. 1991. An appreciation of James Wreford Watson with a bibliography of his work. In G. M.
Robinson (ed.) A Social Geography of Canada. Toronto: Dundurn Press, 492–506.
Robinson, G. M. 1998. Methods and Techniques in Human Geography. New York: John Wiley.
Robinson, J. 2003a. Postcolonialising geography: Tactics and pitfalls. Singapore Journal of Tropical Geography 24,
273–89.
Robinson, J. 2003b. Political geography in a postcolonial context. Political Geography 22, 647–52.
Robinson, J. L. 1976. A new look at the four traditions of geography. Journal of Geography 75, 520–30.
Robinson, M. E. 1982. Representation, misrepresentation, and ‘uncritical rhetoric’. Professional Geographer 34,
224–6.
Robinson, W. S. 1950. Ecological correlation and the behavior of individuals. American Sociological Review 15,
351–57.
Robson, B. T. 1969. Urban Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Robson, B. T. 1972. The corridors of geography. Area 4, 213–14.
Robson, B. T. 1982. Introduction. In B. T. Robson and J. Rees (eds) Geographical Agenda for a Changing world. London:
Social Science Research Council, 1–6.
Robson, B. T. 1984. A pleasant pain. In M. Billinge, D. Gregory and R. Martin (eds) Recollections of a Revolution.
London: Macmillan, 104–6.
Roche, M. 2011. New Zealand geography, biography and autobiography. New Zealand Geographer 67, 73–8.
Rocheleau, D. 1995. Maps, numbers, text and context: Mixing methods in feminist political ecology. Professional
Geographer 47, 458–66.
Rodaway, P. 1994. Sensuous Geographies: Body, sense and place. London and New York, Routledge.
Roder, W. 1961. Attitudes and knowledge on the Topeka flood plain. In G. F. White (ed.) Papers on Flood Problems.
Chicago: University of Chicago, Department of Geography, Research Paper 70, 62–83.
Rodríguez-Pose, A. 2001. Killing economic geography with a ‘cultural turn’ overdose. Antipode: A Radical Journal of
Geography 33, 176–82.
Rodríguez-Pose, A. 2004. On English as a way to preserve geographical diversity. Progress in Human Geography
28.
Rogers, A. 2006. Review of Geography and Geographers: Anglo–American human geography since 1945, 6th edn. Progress in
Human Geography 30, 546–8.
Rogers, A., Bear, C., Hunt, M., Mills, S. and Sandover, R. 2014. Intervention: The impact agenda and human
geography in UK higher education. ACME: An International E-Journal for Critical Geographies 13, 1–9.
Rose, C. 1980. Human geography as text interpretation. In A. Buttimer and D. Seamon (eds) The Human Experience
of Space and Place. London: Croom Helm, 123–34.
Rose, C. 1981. Wilhelm Dilthey’s philosophy of human understanding. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Geography, Ideology
and Social Concern. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 99–133.
Rose, C. 1987. The problem of reference and geographic structuration. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space
5, 93–112.
Rose, D. 1987. Home ownership, subsistence, and historical change: The mining district of West Cornwall
in the late nineteenth century. In N. J. Thrift and P. Williams (eds) Class and Space: The making of urban society.
London: Routledge, 108–53.
Rose, D. and Pevalin, D. J. (eds) 2003. A Researcher’s Guide to the National Statistics Socio-Economic Classification. London:
Sage.
474 References

Rose, G. 1989. Locality-studies and waged labour – an historical critique. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers NS14, 317–28.
Rose, G. 1993a. Feminism and Geography. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Rose, G. 1993b. Progress in geography and gender: Or something else. Progress in Human Geography 17, 531–7.
Rose, G. 1994. The cultural politics of place: Local representation and oppositional discourse in two films.
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS19, 46–60.
Rose, G. 1995. Tradition and paternity: Same difference? Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS20,
414–16.
Rose, G. 1997. Situating knowledges: Positionality, reflexivities and other tactics. Progress in Human Geography 21,
305–20.
Rose, G. 2001. Visual Methodologies: An introduction to the interpretation of visual materials. London: Sage.
Rose, G., Gregson, N., Foord, J., Bowlby, S., Dwyer, C., Hollowat, S. Laurie, N., Maddrell, A. and Skelton, T. 1997.
Introduction. In Women and Geography Study Group (eds) Feminist Geographies: Explorations in diversity and difference.
Harlow: Longman, 1–12.
Rose, J. K. 1936. Corn yield and climate in the Corn Belt. Geographical Review 26, 88–102.
Rossiter, D. J. and Johnston, R. J. 1981. Program GROUP: The identification of all possible solutions to a
constituency-delimitation problem. Environment and Planning A 13, 231–8.
Rothenberg, T. Y. 2007. Presenting America’s World: Strategies of innocence in National Geographic Magazine, 1888–1945.
Aldershot: Ashgate.
Rothstein, J. 1958. Communication, Organization and Science. Colorado: Falcon’s Wing Press.
Rouhani, F. 2007. Religion, identity and activism: Queer Muslim diasporic identities. In K. Browne, J. Lim and
G. Brown (eds) Geographies of Sexualities. Farnham and Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 169–180.
Routledge, P. 2009. Activist geographies. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human
Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 7–14.
Rowles, G. D. 1978. Reflections on experiential field work. In D. Ley and M. S. Samuels (eds) Humanistic Geography:
Problems and prospects. London: Croom Helm, 173–93.
Rowntree, L., Foote, K. E. and Domosh, M. 1989. Cultural geography. In G. L. Gaile and C. J. Willmott (eds)
Geography in America. Columbus, OH: Merrill, 209–17.
Ruming, K. 2009. Following the actors: Mobilising an actor–network theory methodology in geography.
Australian Geographer 40, 451–69.
Rupke, N. A. 2005. Alexander von Humboldt: A metabiography. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.
Rushton, G. 1969. Analysis of spatial behavior by revealed space preference. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 59, 391–400.
Rushton, G. 1979. On behavioral and perception geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69,
463–4.
Russell, A. T. 1997. A question of interaction: Using logistic regression to examine geographic effects on
British voting behaviour. In C. J. Pattie et al. (eds) British Elections and Parties Review, Vol. 7. London: Frank Cass,
91–109.
Russell, C. A. 1977. Chemists by Profession: The origins and rise of the Royal Institute of Chemistry. Milton Keynes: The Open
University Press.
Rusu, M. S. (2012) Multi-paradigmacity, scattered cumulativity, multi-localized ignorance: The tumultuous
condition of sociological knowledge. Revista de Cercetare si Interventie Sociola 39, 187–203.
Rycroft, S. and Cosgrove, D. 1999. Regional knowledge for pedagogy and planning: Dudley Stamp and the Land
Utilisation Survey. In A. Buttimer, S. D. Brunn and U. Wardenga (eds) Text and Image: Social construction of regional
knowledges. Leipzig: Leibniz Institute for Regional Geography, Beiträge zur regionalen Geographie 49, 122–9.
Saarinen, T. F. 1979. Commentary: Critique of Bunting-Guelke paper. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
69, 464–8.
Sachs, A. 2007. The Humboldt Current: A European explorer and his American disciples. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sack, R. D. 1972. Geography, geometry and explanation. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 62,
61–78.
Sack, R. D. 1973a. Comment in reply. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 63, 568–9.
Sack, R. D. 1973b. A concept of physical space in geography. Geographical Analysis 5, 16–34.
Sack, R. D. 1974a. The spatial separatist theme in geography. Economic Geography 50, 1–19.
Sack, R. D. 1974b. Chorology and spatial analysis. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 64, 439–52.
Sack, R. D. 1981. Conceptions of Space in Social Thought. London: Macmillan.
References 475

Sack, R. D. 1983. Human territoriality: A theory. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 73, 55–74.
Sack, R. D. 1986. Human Territoriality: Its theory and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sack, R. D. 1997. Homo Geographicus: A framework for action, awareness and moral concern. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins
University Press.
Sack, R. D. 2001. The geographic problematic: Empirical issues. Norsk Geografisk Tidsskrift 55, 107–16.
Said, E. 1978. Orientalism. New York: Harper.
Saldanha, A. 2010. Skin, affect, aggregation: Guattarian variations on Fanon. Environment and Planning A 42,
2410–27.
Samers, M. and Sidaway, J. D. 2000. Guest editorial: Exclusions, inclusions and occlusions in ‘Anglo-American
geography’: Reflections on Minca’s ‘Venetian geographical praxis’. Environment and Planning D 18, 663–6.
Samuels, M. S. 1978. Existentialism and human geography. In D. Ley and M. S. Samuels (eds) Humanistic Geography:
Problems and prospects. Chicago: Maaroufa Press, 22–40.
Sandbach, F. 1980. Environment, Ideology and Policy. Oxford: Blackwell.
Sanders, R. 2006. Social justice and women of colour in geography: Philosophical musings, trying again. Gender,
Place and Culture 13, 49–55.
Sanderson, M. 1988. Griffith Taylor: Antarctic scientist and pioneer geographer. Ottawa: Carleton University Press.
Santos, M. 1974. Geography, Marxism and underdevelopment. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 6(3), 1–9.
Sarre, P. 1987. Realism in practice. Area 19, 3–10.
Sarre, P., Phillips, D. and Skellington, R. 1989. Ethnic Minority Housing: Explanations and policies. Aldershot: Avebury.
Sauer, C. O. 1918. Geography and the gerrymander. American Political Science Review 12, 403–26.
Sauer, C. O. 1925. The morphology of landscape. University of California Publications in Geography 2, 19–54.
Sauer, C. O. 1941. Foreword to Historical Geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 31, 1–24.
Sauer, C. O. 1956a. The education of a geographer. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 46, 287–99.
Sauer, C. O. 1956b. The agency of man on earth. In W. L. Thomas (ed.) Man’s Role in Changing the Face of the Earth.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 49–69.
Sauer, C. O. 1956c. Retrospect. In W. L. Thomas (ed.) Man’s Role in Changing the Face of the Earth. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1131–5.
Saunders, A. 2010. Literary geography: Reforging the connections. Progress in Human Geography 34, 436–52.
Saunders, P. and Williams, P. R. 1986. The new conservatism: Some thoughts on recent and future developments
in urban studies. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 4, 393–9.
Saunders, P. and Williams, P. R. 1987. For an emancipated social science. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space
5, 427–30.
Sayer, A. 1979. Epistemology and conceptions of people and nature in geography. Geoforum 10, 19–44.
Sayer, A. 1981. Defensible values in geography. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and the Urban
Environment, Vol. 4. Chichester: John Wiley, 29–56.
Sayer, A. 1982. Explanation in economic geography. Progress in Human Geography 6, 68–88.
Sayer, A. 1983. Notes on geography and the relationship between people and nature. In T. Cannon, M. Forbes
and J. Mackie (eds) Society and Nature: Socialist perspectives on the relationship between human and physical geography. London:
Union of Socialist Geographers, 47–57.
Sayer, A. 1984. Method in Social Science: A realist approach. London: Hutchinson.
Sayer, A. 1985a. Realism and Geography. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography. London: Methuen, 159–73.
Sayer, A. 1985b. The difference that space makes. In D. Gregory and J. Urry (eds) Social Relations and Spatial Structures.
London: Macmillan, 49–66.
Sayer, A. 1987. Hard work and its alternatives. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 5, 395–9.
Sayer, A. 1989a. The new regional geography and problems of narrative. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space
7, 253–76.
Sayer, A. 1989b. On the dialogue between humanism and historical materialism in geography. In A. Kobayashi
and S. Mackenzie (eds) Remaking Human Geography. Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman, 206–26.
Sayer, A. 1992a. Method in Social Science: A realist approach, 2nd edn. London: Routledge.
Sayer, A. 1992b. What’s left to do? A reply to Hadjimichalis and Smith. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 24,
214–17.
Sayer, A. 1995. Radical Political Economy: A critique. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Sayer, A. 2000. Critical and uncritical turns. In I. Cook, D. Crouch, S. Naylor and J. R. Ryan (eds) Cultural Turns/
Geographical Turns: Perspectives on cultural geography. Harlow: Prentice Hall, 166–81.
Sayer, A. 2001. For a critical cultural political economy. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 33, 687–708.
476 References

Sayer, A. 2013. Looking forward to new realist debates. Dialogues in Human Geography 3, 22–5.
Sayer, A. 2015. Why We Can’t Afford the Rich. Bristol: Policy Press.
Sayer, A. and Morgan, K. 1985. A modern industry in a declining region: Links between method, theory and
policy. In D. Massey and R. Meegan (eds) Politics and Method: Contrasting studies in industrial geography. London:
Methuen, 144–68.
Sayer, A. and Storper, M. 1997. Ethics unbound: For a normative turn in social theory. Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space 15, 1–17.
Sayer, A. and Walker, R. A. 1992. The New Social Economy: Reworking the division of labour. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Sayer, D. 2015. Rank Hypocrisies:The insult of the REF. London: Sage.
Scargill, D. I. 1976. The RGS and the foundations of geography at Oxford. Geographical Journal 142, 438–61.
Schaefer, F. K. 1953. Exceptionalism in geography: A methodological examination. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 43, 226–49.
Schelhaas, B. and Hönsch, I. 2002. History of German geography: Worldwide reputation and strategies of
nationalisation and institutionalisation. In G. S. Dunbar (ed.) Geography: Discipline, profession and subject since 1870.
Dordrecht: Kluwer, 9–44.
Schlemper, M. B., Adams, J. K. and Solem, M. 2014. Geographers in business, government and nonprofit
organizations: Skills, challenges, and professional identities. Professional Geographer 66, 480–92.
Schoenberger, E. 1992. Self-criticism and self-awareness in research: A reply to Linda McDowell. Professional
Geographer 44, 215–18.
Schoenberger, E. 1993. On knowing what to know. Environment and Planning A 25, 1225–8.
Schoenberger, E. 1997. The Cultural Crisis of the Firm. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Schoenberger, E. 2001. Interdisciplinarity and social power. Progress in Human Geography 25, 365–82.
Schuermans, N., Meeus, B. and De Maeschalck, F. 2010. Is there a world beyond the Web of Science? Publication
practices outside the heartland of academic geography. Area 42, 417–24.
Schulten, S. 2001. The Geographical Imagination in America, 1880–1950. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Schuurman, N. 1999. An interview with Michael Goodchild, January 6, 1998, Santa Barbara, California.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 17, 3–15.
Schuurman, N. 2000. Trouble in the heartland: GIS and its critics in the 1990s. Progress in Human Geography 24,
569–90.
Schuurman, N. 2006. Formalization matters: Critical GIS and ontology research. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 96, 726–39.
Schwanen, T. and Kwan, M.-P. 2009. ‘Doing’ critical geographies with numbers. Professional Geographer 61, 459–64.
Scott, A. J. 1982. The meaning and social origins of discourse on the spatial foundations of society. In P. R. Gould
and G. Olsson (eds) A Search for Common Ground. London: Pion, 141–56.
Scott, A. J. 1985. Location processes, urbanization, and territorial development: An exploratory essay. Environment
and Planning A 17, 479–501.
Scott, A. J. 1986. Industrialization and urbanization: A geographical agenda. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 76, 25–37.
Scott, A. J. 1988. Metropolis. Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.
Scott, A. J. 2000. Economic geography: The great half-century. In G. L. Clark, M. P. Feldmann and M. S. Gertler
(eds) The Oxford Handbook of Economic Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 19–43.
Scott, A. J. and Cooke, P. N. 1988. The new geography and sociology of production. Environment and Planning D:
Society and Space 6, 241–4.
Scott, A. J. and Storper, M. (eds) 1985. Production,Work,Territory. Boston, MA: George Allen & Unwin.
Seager, J. and Enloe, C. 2011. The Real State of America Atlas. London: University of California Press.
Seager, J. and Olson, A. 1986. Women in the World: An international atlas. London: Pan.
Seager, J., Reed, C. and Stott, P. 1995. The State of the Environment Atlas, 2nd edn. London: Pan.
Seamon, D. 1984. Phenomenology and environment-behavior research. In G. T. Moore and E. Zube (eds)
Advances in Environment, Behavior and Design. New York: Plenum, 3–36.
Seamon, D. 1984. The question of reliable knowledge: The irony and tragedy of positivist research. Professional
Geographer 36, 216–18.
Seamon, D. and Sowers, J. 2009. Existentialism/existential geography. In R. Kitchin and N.Thrift (eds) International
Encyclopedia of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 666–71.
Seemann, J. 2015. vii Provocations for effective teaching in the history of geography. Progress in Human Geography.
doi: 10.1177/0309132515575940
References 477

Self, A., Thomas, J. and Randall, C. (ONS). 2012. Measuring National Well-Being: Life in the UK, 2012. Office of
National Statistics, UK. Available at: www.ons.gov.uk/ons/dcp171766_287415.pdf
Semple, E. C. 1911. Influences of Geographical Environment. New York: Henry Holt.
Shannon, G. W. and Dever, G. E. A. 1974. Health Care Delivery: Spatial perspectives. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Sharp, J. P. 1993. Publishing American identity: Popular geopolitics, myth, and The Reader’s Digest. Political Geography
12, 491–504.
Sharp, J. P. 2000. Remasculinising geo-politics? Comments on Gearoid O’Tuathail’s Critical Geopolitics. Political
Geography 19, 361–4.
Sharp, J. P. 2009. Geographies of Postcolonialism. London: Sage.
Sharp, J. P., Routledge, P., Philo, C. and Paddison, R. (eds) 2000. Entanglements of Power: Geographies of domination/
resistance. London: Routledge.
Sharrock, W. and Read, R. 2002. Kuhn: Philosopher of scientific revolution. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Shaw, W. 2013. Auto-ethnography and autobiography in geographical research. Geoforum 46, 1–4.
Shelton, N. J. 2005. The future for new geographers. Area 37, 110–14.
Sheppard, E. S. 1979. Gravity parameter estimation. Geographical Analysis 11, 120–33.
Sheppard, E. S. 1993. Automated geography: What kind of geography for what kind of society? Professional
Geographer 45, 457–60.
Sheppard, E. S. 1995. Dissenting from spatial analysis. Urban Geography 16, 283–303.
Sheppard, E. S. and Barnes, T. J. (eds) 2000. A Companion to Economic Geography. Oxford: Blackwell.
Sheppard, E. S. and Barnes, T. J. 1990. The Capitalist Space Economy: Geographical analysis after Ricardo, Marx and Sraffa.
London and Boston: Unwin Hyman.
Short, J. R. 1984. The Urban Arena: Capital, state and community in contemporary Britain. London: Macmillan.
Short, J. R. 2002. The disturbing case of the concentration of power in human geography. Area 34, 323–4.
Short, J. R., Boniche, A., Kim,Y. and Li, P. L. 2001. Cultural globalization, global English, and geography journals.
Professional Geographer 53, 1–11.
Shevky, E. and Bell, W. 1955. Social Area Analysis. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Sibley, D. 1995. Geographies of Exclusion. London and New York: Routledge.
Sibley, D. 1998. Sensations and spatial science: Gratification and anxiety in the production of ordered landscapes.
Environment and Planning A 30, 235–46.
Sibley, D. 2000. Placing anxieties. In I. Cook, D. Crouch, S. Naylor and J. R. Ryan (eds) Cultural Turns/Geographical
Turns: Perspectives on cultural geography. Harlow: Prentice Hall, 359–69.
Sidaway, J. D. 1992. In other worlds: On the politics of research by First World geographers in the Third World.
Area 24, 403–8.
Sidaway, J. D. 1997. The production of British geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS22,
488–504.
Sidaway, J. D. 2000a. Post-colonial geographies: An exploratory essay. Progress in Human Geography 24, 591–612.
Sidaway, J. D. 2000b. Recontextualising positionality: Geographic research and academic fields of power. Antipode:
A Radical Journal of Geography 32, 260–70.
Sidaway, J. D. and Johnston, R. J. 2007. Geography in higher education in the UK. Journal of Geography in Higher
Education 31, 57–80.
Sidaway, J. D., Woon, C. Y. and Jacobs, J. M. 2014. Planetary postcolonialism. Singapore Journal of Tropical Geography 35,
4–21.
Siddall, W. R. 1961. Two kinds of geography. Economic Geography 36, facing page 189.
Simandan, D. 2002. On what it takes to be a good geographer. Area 34, 284–93.
Simmons, I. G. 1993. Interpreting Nature: Cultural constructions of the environment. London: Routledge.
Simmons, I. G. 1997. Humanity and Environment: A cultural ecology. London: Addison, Wesley Longman.
Simon, H. A. 1957. Models of Man: Social and rational. New York: John Wiley.
Simonsen, K. 2002. Global–local ambivalence. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS27, 391–4.
Sinclair, J. C. and Kissling, C. C. 1971. A network analysis approach to fruit distribution planning. In
R. J. Johnston and J. M. Soons (eds) Proceedings, Sixth New Zealand Geography Conference, Christchurch, August 1970,
Vol. 1. Christchurch: New Zealand Geographical Society, 131–6.
Singleton, A. D. and Spielman, S. E. 2014. The past, present and future of geodemographic research in the
United States and the United Kingdom. Professional Geographer 66, 558–67.
Sismondo, S. 2012. Fifty years of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, twenty–five of Science in Action. Social Studies of
Science 42, 415–19.
478 References

Skupin, A. 2014. Making a Mark: A computational and visual analysis of one researcher’s intellectual domain.
International Journal of Geographical Information Science 28, 1209–32.
Slater, D. 1973. Geography and underdevelopment – 1. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 5(3), 21–53.
Slater, D. 1977. Geography and underdevelopment – 2. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 9, 1–31.
Slater, T. 2012. Commentary: Impacted geographers: A response to Pain, Kesby and Askins. Area 44, 117–19.
Slater, T. R. 1988. Redbrick academic geography. Geographical Journal 154, 169–80.
Smailes, A. E. 1946. The urban mesh of England and Wales. Transactions and Papers, Institute of British Geographers 11,
85–101.
Smallman-Raynor, M. and Cliff, A. D. 1990. Aquired Immune Deficiency Syndrome (AIDS): Literature,
geographical origins and global patterns. Progress in Human Geography 14, 157–213.
Smallman-Raynor, M., Cliff, A. D. and Haggett, P. 1992. Atlas of AIDS. Oxford: Blackwell Reference.
Smallman-Raynor, M., Cliff, A. D. and Haggett, P. 2004. World Atlas of Epidemic Diseases. London: Hodder.
Smith, C. T. 1965. Historical geography: Current trends and prospects. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds)
Frontiers in Geographical Teaching. London: Methuen, 118–43.
Smith, D. M. 1971. America! America? Views on a pot melting. 2. Radical geography – the next revolution? Area
3, 153–7.
Smith, D. M. 1973a. Alternative ‘relevant’ professional roles. Area 5, 1–4.
Smith, D. M. 1973b. The Geography of Social Well-Being in the United States. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Smith, D. M. 1975. On the concept of welfare. Area 7, 33–6.
Smith, D. M. 1977. Human Geography: A welfare approach. London: Edward Arnold.
Smith, D. M. 1979. Where the Grass is Greener: Living in an unequal world. London: Penguin.
Smith, D. M. 1981. Industrial Location: An economic geographical analysis, 2nd edn. New York: John Wiley.
Smith, D. M. 1984. Recollections of a random variable. In M. Billinge, D. Gregory and R. Martin (eds) Recollections
of a Revolution. London: Macmillan, 117–33.
Smith, D. M. 1985. The ‘new blood’ scheme and its application to geography. Area 17, 237–43.
Smith, D. M. 1986. UGC research ratings: Pass or fail? Area 18, 247–9.
Smith, D. M. 1988a. Towards an interpretative human geography. In J. Eyles and D. M. Smith (eds) Qualitative
Methods in Human Geography. Cambridge: Polity Press, 255–67.
Smith, D. M. 1988b. On academic performance. Area 20, 3–13.
Smith, D. M. 1994a. Geography and Social Justice. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Smith, D. M. 1994b. On professional responsibility to distant others. Area 26, 359–67.
Smith, D. M. 1995. Against differential research funding. Area 27, 79–83.
Smith, D. M. 1996. Reply to Rhind – value for money, the continuing debate. Area 28, 97–101.
Smith, D. M. 1997a. Geography and ethics: A moral turn? Progress in Human Geography 21, 583–90.
Smith, D. M. 1997b. Back to the good life: Towards an enlarged conception of social justice. Environment and
Planning D: Society and Space 15, 19–35.
Smith, D. M. 1998. How far should we care? On the spatial scope of beneficence. Progress in Human Geography 22,
15–38.
Smith, D. M. 2000. Moral Geographies: Ethics in a world of difference. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Smith, G. D. and Winchester, H. P. M. 1998. Negotiating space: Alternative masculinities at the work/home
boundary. Australian Geographer 29, 327–39.
Smith, J. M. 1996. Geographical rhetoric: Modes and tropes of appeal. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
86, 1–20.
Smith, J. M. 2001. Constructing the nation: Eighteenth-century geographies for children. Mosaic 34, 133–48.
Smith, J. M. 2004. Unlawful relations and verbal inflation. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 94,
294–9.
Smith, J. M. 2009. Humanism/humanistic geography. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of
Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 239–50.
Smith, N. 1979a. Geography, science and post-positivist modes of explanation. Progress in Human Geography 3,
365–83.
Smith, N. 1979b. Toward a theory of gentrification: A back to the city movement by capital, not people. Journal
of the American Planning Association 45, 538–48.
Smith, N. 1984. Uneven Development: Nature, capital and the production of space. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Smith, N. 1986. On the necessity of uneven development. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 10,
87–104.
References 479

Smith, N. 1987a. ‘Academic war over the field of geography’: The elimination of geography at Harvard,
1947–1951. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 77, 155–72.
Smith, N. 1987b. Danger of the empirical turn: The CURS initiative. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 19,
59–68.
Smith, N. 1987c. Rascal concepts, minimalizing discourse, and the politics of geography. Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space 5, 377–83.
Smith, N. 1990. Geography as museum: Private history and conservative idealism in The Nature of Geography. In
J. N. Entrikin and S. D. Brunn (eds) Reflections on Richard Hartshorne’s The Nature of Geography. Washington, DC:
Association of American Geographers, 89–120.
Smith, N. 1991. What’s left? A lot’s left. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 23, 406–18.
Smith, N. 1992. History and philosophy of geography: Real wars, theory wars. Progress in Human Geography 16,
257–71.
Smith, N. 1994. Shaking loose the colonies: Isaiah Bowman and the ‘de-colonization’ of the British Empire. In
A. Godlewska and N. Smith (eds) Geography and Empire. Oxford: Blackwell, 270–99.
Smith, N. 2001. Marxism and geography in the Anglophone world. Geographische Revue 3, 5–22.
Smith, N. 2003. American Empire: Roosevelt’s geographer and the prelude to globalization. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press.
Smith, N. 2005a. Neo–critical geography, or, the flat pluralist world of business class. Antipode: A Radical Journal of
Geography 37, 887–97.
Smith, N. 2005b. Endgame of Globalization. Abingdon, Oxford and New York: Routledge:
Smith, R. G. 2003. Baudrillard’s non-representational theory: Burn the signs and journey without maps.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 21, 67–84.
Smith, R. G. and Doel, M. A. 2001. Baudrillard unwound: The duplicity of post-Marxism and deconstruction.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 19, 137–59.
Smith, S. J. 1984. Practising humanistic geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 74, 353–74.
Smith, S. J. 1986. Crime, Space and Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Smith, S. J. 1988. Constructing local knowledge: The analysis of self in everyday life. In J. Eyles and D. M. Smith
(eds) Qualitative Methods in Human Geography. Cambridge: Polity Press, 17–38.
Smith, S. J. 1989. Society, space and citizenship: A human geography for the ‘new times’? Transactions of the Institute
of British Geographers NS14, 144–56.
Smith, S. J. 2008. Owner-occupation: At home with a hybrid of money and materials. Environment and Planning
A 40, 520–35.
Smith, S. J. 2015. Owner occupation: At home in a spatial financial paradox. International Journal of Housing Policy 15,
61–83.
Smith, S. J. and Searle, B. A. 2010. Housing futures: A role for derivatives. In S. J. Smith and B. A. Searle (eds) The
Blackwell Companion to the Economics of Housing. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Smith, S. J., Munro, M. and Christie, H. 2006. Performing (housing) markets. Urban Studies 43, 81–98.
Smith, S. J., Searle, B. A. and Cooke, N. 2008. Rethinking the risks of home ownership. Journal of Social Policy 38,
83–102.
Smith, T. R. 1984. Artificial intelligence and its applicability to geographical problem solving. Professional Geographer
36, 147–58.
Smith, T. R., Clark, W. A. V. and Cotton, J. W. 1984. Deriving and testing production system models of sequential
decision-making behavior. Geographical Analysis 16, 191–222.
Smith, W. 1949. An Economic Geography of Great Britain. London: Methuen.
Soffer, A. and Minghi, J. 1986. Israel’s security landscapes: The impact of military considerations on land uses.
Professional Geographer 38, 28–41.
Soja, E. W. 1968. The Geography of Modernization in Kenya. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press.
Soja, E. W. 1980. The socio-spatial dialectic. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 70, 207–25.
Soja, E. W. 1985. The spatiality of social life: Towards a transformative retheorization. In D. Gregory and J. Urry
(eds) Social Relations and Spatial Structures. London: Macmillan, 90–127.
Soja, E. W. 1989. Postmodern Geographies:  The reassertion of space in critical social theory. London: Verso.
Soja, E. W. 2001a. Postmodernism in geography. In N. J. Smelser and P. B. Baltes (eds) International Encyclopedia
of the Social and Behavioral Sciences. Oxford: Elsevier Science, 11860–5.
Soja, E. W. 2001b. Afterword. In C. Minca (ed.) Postmodern Geography: Theory and praxis. Oxford: Blackwell,
282–94.
480 References

Soja, E. W. and Hooper, B. 1993. The spaces that difference makes: Some notes on the geographical margins of
the new cultural politics. In M. Keith and S. Pile (eds) Place and the Politics of Identity. London: Routledge,
183–205.
Sparke, M. 1994a. Negotiating national action: Free trade, constitutional debate and the gendered geopolitics
of Canada. Political Geography 15, 615–39.
Sparke, M. 1994b. Writing on patriarchal missiles: The chauvinism of the ‘Gulf War’ and the limits of critique.
Environment and Planning A 26, 1061–89.
Sparke, M. 2013. From global dispossession to local repossession: Towards a wordly cultural geography of
occupy activism. In N. C. Johnson, R. H. Schein and J. Winders (eds) The Wiley-Blackwell Companion to Cultural
Geography. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 387–408.
Spate, O. H. K. 1957. How determined is possibilism? Geographical Studies 4, 3–12.
Spate, O. H. K. 1960a. Quantity and quality in geography. Annals of the Association of America Geographers 50, 477–94.
Spate, O. H. K. 1960b. Lord Kelvin rides again. Economic Geography 36, facing page 1.
Spate, O. H. K. 1963. Letter to the editor. Geography 48, 206.
Spate, O. H. K. 1989. Foreword. In F. W. Boal and D. N. Livingstone (eds) The Behavioural Environment. London:
Routledge, xvii–xx.
Spencer, H. 1892. A System of Synthetic Philosophy,Vol. 1. First principles, 4th edn. New York: Appleton.
Spencer, J. E. 1979. A geographer west of the Sierra Nevada. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69,
46–52.
Speth, W. W. 1999. How it Came to Be: Carl O. Sauer, Franz Boas and the meaning of anthropogeography. Berkeley, CA: University
of California Press.
Springer, S. 2013. Anarchism! What geography still ought to be. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 44, 1605–24.
Springer, S. 2014. Why a radical geography must be anarchist. Dialogues in Human Geography 3, 249–70.
Staeheli, L. A. and Cope, M. 1994. Empowering women’s citizenship. Political Geography 13, 443–60.
Staeheli, L. A. and Nagar, R. 2002. Feminists talking across worlds. Gender, Place and Culture 9, 167–72.
Staeheli, L. A. and Mitchell, D. 2005. The complex politics of relevance in geography. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 95, 357–72.
Stamp, L. D. 1934. Planning the land for the future. Science 80, 510–12.
Stamp, L. D. 1946a. The Land of Britain. London: Longman.
Stamp, L. D. 1946b. The place of science in town and country planning. Advancement of Science 3, 337–48.
Stamp, L. D. 1948. Applied geography. In L. D. Stamp and S. W. Wooldridge (eds) London Essays in Geography: Rodwell
Jones memorial volume. London: Longmans, Green, 1–18.
Stamp, L. D. 1949. The planning of land use. Advancement of Science 6, 224–32.
Stamp, L. D. 1960. Applied Geography. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Stamp, L. D. 1966. Ten years on. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 40, 11–20.
Stamp, L. D. and Beaver, S. H. 1947. The British Isles. London: Longman.
Stannard, K. 2003. Commentary. Earth to academia: On the need to reconnect university and school geography.
Area 35, 316–22.
Steel, R. W. (ed.) 1987. British Geography 1918–1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Steel, R. W. 1974. The Third World: Geography in practice. Geography 59, 189–207.
Steel, R. W. 1982. Regional geography in practice. Geography 67, 2–8.
Stegmuller, W. 1976. The Structure and Dynamics of Theories. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Steinitz, C. 2014. The beginnings of geographical information systems: A personal historical perspective.
Planning Perspectives 29, 239–54.
Stevens, A. 1921. Applied Geography. Glasgow: Blackie.
Stewart, J. Q. 1945. Coasts, W  aves and Weather. Boston, MA: Ginn & Co.
Stewart, J. Q. 1947. Empirical mathematical rules concerning the distribution and equilibrium of population.
Geographical Review 37, 461–85.
Stewart, J. Q. 1956. The development of social physics. American Journal of Physics 18, 239–53.
Stewart, J. Q. and Warntz, W. 1958. Macrogeography and social science. Geographical Review 48, 167–84.
Stewart, J. Q. and Warntz, W. 1959. Physics of population distribution. Journal of Regional Science 1, 99–123.
Stiell, B. and England, K. 1997. Domestic distinctions: Constructing difference among paid domestic workers
in Toronto. Gender, Place and Culture 4, 339–59.
Stimson, R. J. 2012. You don’t need sight to have vision: Reginald G. Golledge was a giant in analytical human
geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 102, 234–43.
References 481

Stoddart, D. R. 1965. Geography and the ecological approach: The ecosystem as a geographic principle and
method. Geography 50, 242–51.
Stoddart, D. R. 1966. Darwin’s impact on geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 56, 683–98.
Stoddart, D. R. 1967a. Growth and structure of geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 41, 1–19.
Stoddart, D. R. 1967b. Organism and ecosystem as geographic models. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds)
Models in Geography. London: Methuen, 511–47.
Stoddart, D. R. 1975a. The RGS and the foundations of geography at Cambridge. Geographical Journal 141, 216–39.
Stoddart, D. R. 1975b. Kropotkin, Reclus and relevant geography. Area 7, 188–90.
Stoddart, D. R. 1977. The paradigm concept and the history of geography. Abstract of a paper for the conference
of the International Geographical Union Commission on the History of Geographic Thought, Edinburgh.
Stoddart, D. R. 1981a. The paradigm concept and the history of geography. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Geography,
Ideology and Social Concern. Oxford: Blackwell, 70–80.
Stoddart, D. R. 1981b. Ideas and interpretation in the history of geography. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Geography,
Ideology and Social Concern. Oxford: Blackwell, 1–7.
Stoddart, D. R. 1986. On Geography: And its history. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Stoddart, D. R. 1987. To claim the high ground: Geography for the end of the century. Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers NS12, 327–36.
Stoddart, D. R. 1990. Epilogue: Homage to Richard Hartshorne. In J. N. Entrikin and S. D. Brunn (eds) Reflections
on Richard Hartshorne’s The Nature of Geography. Washington, DC: Association of American Geographers, 163–6.
Stoddart, D. R. 1991. Do we need a feminist historiography of geography – and if we do, what should it be?
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS16, 484–7.
Stoddart, D. R. 1997a. Richard J. Chorley and modern geomorphology. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Process and Form in
Geomorphology. London: Routledge, 383–99.
Stoddart, D. R. 1997b. Carl Sauer: Geomorphologist. In D. R. Stoddart (ed.) Process and Form in Geomorphology.
London: Routledge, 340–79.
Stoddart, D. R. 2001. Be of good cheer, my weary readers, for I have espied land. Atoll Research Bulletin 494,
234–72.
Stone, K. H. 1979. Geography’s wartime service. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69, 89–97.
Storey, D. W. 2001. Territory:The claiming of space. Harlow: Longman.
Storper, M. 1987. The post-Enlightenment challenge to Marxist urban studies. Environment and Planning D: Society and
Space 5, 418–26.
Storper, M. 2001. The poverty of radical theory today: From the false promises of Marxism to the mirage of the
cultural turn. International Journal of Urban and Regional Studies 25, 155–79.
Stouffer, S. A. 1940. Intervening opportunities: A theory relating mobility and distance. American Sociological Review
5, 845–67.
Strange, C. and Bashford, A. 2008. Griffith Taylor: Visionary environmentalist explorer. Toronto: University of Toronto
Press.
Subramanian, S. V., Jones, K., Kaddour, A. and Krieger, N. 2008. Revisiting Robinson: The perils of individualistic
and ecologic fallacy. International Journal of Epidemiology 38, 342–60.
Sui, D. Z. 1994. GIS and urban studies: Positivism, post-positivism and beyond. Urban Geography 15, 258–78.
Sui, D. Z. 1999. Postmodern urbanism disrobed: Or why postmodern urbanism is a dead end for urban
geography. Urban Geography 20, 403–11.
Sui, D. Z. 2004a. GIS, cartography, and the ‘third culture’: Geographic imaginations in the computer age.
Professional Geographer 56, 62–72.
Sui, D. Z. 2004b. Tobler’s first law of geography: A big idea for a small world? Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 94, 269–77.
Sui, D. Z. (ed.) 2011. Focus: Discussions on NRC report’s section: Strategic directions for the geographical
sciences. Professional Geographer 63, 305–42.
Sui, D. Z. 2012. Looking through Hägerstrand’s dual vistas: Towards a unifying framework for time geography.
Journal of Transport Geography 23, 5–16.
Sui, D. Z., Fotheringham, A. S., Anselin, L., O’Loughlin, J. and King, G. 2000. Book review forum on A Solution to
the Ecological Problem by Gary King. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 90, 579–606.
Sullivan, R. 2011. Geography Speaks: Performative aspects of geography. Farnham: Ashgate.
Summerfield, M. A. 1983. Population, samples and statistical inference in geography. Professional Geographer 35,
143–8.
482 References

Suppe, F. 1977a. The search for philosophic understanding of scientific theories. In F. Suppe (ed.) The Structure of
Scientific Theories. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 3–233.
Suppe, F. 1977b. Exemplars, theories and disciplinary matrices. In F. Suppe (ed.) The Structure of Scientific Theories.
Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 473–99.
Suppe, F. 1977c. Afterword – 1977. In F. Suppe (ed.) The Structure of Scientific Theories. Urbana, IL: University of
Illinois Press, 617–730.
Sviatlovsky, E. E. and Eels, W. C. 1937. The centrographical method and regional analysis. Geographical Review 27,
240–54.
Swanton, D. 2010. Sorting bodies: Race, affect, and everyday multiculture in a mill town in northern England.
Environment and Planning A 42, 2332–50.
Swartz, D. 1997. Culture and Power: The sociology of Pierre Bourdieu. London and Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Symankski, R. 1994. Why we should fear postmodernists. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 84,
301–4.
Symanski, R. 2002. Geography Inside Out. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press.
Symanski, R. 2007. The world’s foremost living cultural geographer. In R. Symanski, Irreverent Essays on Geographers.
Irvine, CA: Estrilda, 193–210.
Symanski, R. and Agnew, J. A. 1981. Order and Skepticism: Human geography and the dialectic of science. Washington, DC:
Association of American Geographers.
Symanski, I. R. and Pickard, J. 1996. Rules by which we are judged. Progress in Human Geography 20, 175–82.
Taaffe, E. J. 1970. Geography. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Taaffe, E. J. 1974. The spatial view in context. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 64, 1–16.
Taaffe, E. J. 1979. In the Chicago area. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 69, 133–8.
Taaffe, E. J. 1993. Spatial analysis: Development and outlook. Urban Geography 14, 422–33.
Taaffe, E. J., Morrill, R. L. and Gould, P. R. 1963.Transport expansion in underdeveloped countries: A comparative
analysis. Geographical Review 53, 503–29.
Tambolo, L. 2015. A tale of three theories: Feyerabend and Popper on progress and the aim of science. Studies in
the History and Philosophy of Science 51, 33–41.
Tarrant, J. R. 1968. Computers in geography. Institute of British Geographers, Newsletter 6, 11–25.
Tatham, G. 1953. Environmentalism and possibilism. In G. Taylor (ed.) Geography in the Twentieth Century. London:
Methuen, 128–64.
Taylor, P. J. 1971. Distance decay curves and distance transformations. Geographical Analysis 3, 221–38.
Taylor, P. J. 1976. An interpretation of the quantification debate in British geography. Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers NS1, 129–42.
Taylor, P. J. 1977. Quantitative Methods in Geography. New York: Harper & Row.
Taylor, P. J. 1978. Political geography. Progress in Human Geography 2, 53–62.
Taylor, P. J. 1979. ‘Difficult-to-let’, ‘difficult-to-live-in’, and sometimes ‘difficult-to-get-out-of’: An essay on the
provision of council housing. Environment and Planning A 11, 1305–20.
Taylor, P. J. 1982. A materialist framework for political geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS7,
15–34.
Taylor, P. J. 1985a. The value of a geographical perspective. In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Future of Geography. London:
Methuen, 92–110.
Taylor, P. J. 1985b. The geography of elections. In M. Pacione (ed.) Progress in Political Geography. London: Croom
Helm, 243–72.
Taylor, P. J. 1988. History’s dialogue: An exemplification from political geography. Progress in Human Geography 12,
1–14.
Taylor, P. J. 1990a. Journeyman editor. Professional Geographer 42, 359–60.
Taylor, P. J. 1990b. Editorial comment: GKS. Political Geography Quarterly 9, 211–12.
Taylor, P. J. 1990c. Britain and the Cold War: 1945 as geopolitical transition. London: Belhaven Press.
Taylor, P. J. 1993. Full circle, or new meaning for the global? In R. J. Johnston (ed.) The Challenge for Geography:
A changing world: A changing discipline. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 181–97.
Taylor, P. J. 1994. The state as container: Territoriality in the modern world-system. Progress in Human Geography 18,
151–62.
Taylor, P. J. 1995. Beyond containers: Internationality, interstateness, interterritoriality. Progress in Human Geography
19, 1–15.
References 483

Taylor, P. J. 1996. Embedded statism and the social sciences: Opening up to new spaces. Environment and Planning A
28, 1917–28.
Taylor, P. J. 1999. Spaces, places and Macy’s: Place-space tensions in the political geography of modernities.
Progress in Human Geography 23, 7–26.
Taylor, P. J. 2003. Radical political geographies. In J. Agnew, K. Mitchell and G. Toal (eds) A Companion to Political
Geography. Oxford: Blackwell, 47–58.
Taylor, P. J. and Goddard, J. (eds) 1974. Geography and statistics: An introduction. Statistician 23, 149–56.
Taylor, P. J. and Gudgin, G. 1976. A statistical theory of electoral redistricting. Environment and Planning A 8, 43–58.
Taylor, P. J. and Johnston, R. J. 1979. Geography of Elections. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Taylor, P. J. and Overton, M. 1991. Further thoughts on geography and GIS. Environment and Planning A 23,
1087–94.
Taylor, T. G. 1927. Environment and Race. London: Oxford University Press.
Taylor, T. G. 1937. Environment, Race and Migration. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Taylor, T. G. 1957. Introduction: The scope of the volume. In G. Taylor (ed.) Geography in the Twentieth Century: A study
of growth, fields, techniques, aims and trends. London: Methuen, 1–27.
Taylor, T. G. 1958. Journeyman Taylor:The education of a scientist. London: Robert Hale.
Tesch, R. 1990. Qualitative Research: Analysis types and research tools. Brighton: Falmer Press.
Tewdwr-Jones, M., Phelps, N. A. and Freestone, R. 2014. The Planning Imagination: Peter Hall and the study of urban and
regional planning. London: Routledge.
Thien, D. 2005. After or beyond feeling? A consideration of affect and emotion in geography. Area 37, 450–6.
Thien, D. 2009. Feminist methodologies. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human
Geography, V  ol. 1. Oxford: Elsevier, 71–8.
Thoman, R. S. 1965. Some comments on The Science of Geography. Professional Geographer 17(6), 8–10.
Thomas, E. N. 1960. Areal associations between population growth and selected factors in the Chicago
urbanized area. Economic Geography 36, 158–70.
Thomas, E. N. and Anderson, D. L. 1965. Additional comments on weighting values in correlation analysis of
areal data. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 55, 492–505.
Thomas, R. W. 1982. Information Statistics in Geography. Norwich: Geo Books.
Thomas, R. W. 1992. Geomedical Systems: Intervention and control. Routledge: London.
Thomas, W. L. Jr. (ed.) 1956. Man’s Role in Changing the Face of the Earth. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Thompson, D’Arcy W. 1917. On Growth and Form, 1st edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Thompson, J. H., Sufrin, S. C., Gould, P. R., Buck, M. A. 1962. Toward a geography of economic health: The case
of New York state. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 52, 1–20.
Thorne, C. R. (ed.) 1993. University Funding Council Research Selectivity Exercise, 1992: Implications for
higher education in geography. Journal of Geography in Higher Education 17, 167–99.
Thornes, J. B. 1989a. Geomorphology and grass roots models. In B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling Geography. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, 3–21.
Thornes, J. B. 1989b. Environmental systems. In M. J. Clark, K. J. Gregory and A. M. Gurnell (eds) Horizons in
Physical Geography. London: Macmillan, 27–46.
Thrall, G. I. 1985. Scientific geography. Area 17, 254.
Thrall, G. I. 1986. Reply to Felix Driver and Christopher Philo. Area 18, 162–3.
Thrift, N. J. and Olds, K. 1996. Refiguring the economic in economic geography. Progress in Human Geography 20,
311–37.
Thrift, N. J. 1977. An introduction to time geography. CATMOG 13, Norwich: Geo Books.
Thrift, N. J. 1979. Unemployment in the inner city: Urban problem or structural imperative? A review of the
British experience. In D. T. Herbert and R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and Urban Environment: Progress in Research and
Applications, Vol. 2. London: John Wiley, 125–226.
Thrift, N. J. 1981. Behavioural geography. In N. Wrigley and R. J. Bennett (eds) Quantitative Geography. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 352–65.
Thrift, N. J. 1983. On the determination of social action in space and time. Environment and Planning D: Society and
Space 1, 23–57.
Thrift, N. J. 1987. No perfect symmetry. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 5, 400–7.
Thrift, N. J. 1990. For a new regional geography 1. Progress in Human Geography 14, 272–9.
Thrift, N. J. 1991. For a new regional geography 2. Progress in Human Geography 15, 456–565.
Thrift, N. J. 1993. For a new regional geography 3. Progress in Human Geography 17, 92–100.
484 References

Thrift, N. J. 1994. Taking aim at the heart of the region. In D. Gregory, R. Martin and G. Smith (eds) Human
Geography: Society, space and social science. London: Macmillan, 200–31.
Thrift, N. J. 2000. Pandora’s box? Cultural geographies of economies. In G. L. Clark, M. P. Feldmann and M. S.
Gertler (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Economic Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 689–704.
Thrift, N. J. 2002. The future of geography. Geoforum 33, 291–8.
Thrift, N. J. 2005. Hägerstrand and social theory. Progress in Human Geography 29, 337–40.
Thrift, N. J. 2008. Non-representational Theory: Space/politics/affect. Abingdon and New York: Routledge.
Thrift, N. J. and Dewsbury, J.-D. 2000. Dead geographies – and how to make them live. Environment and Planning D:
Society and Space 18, 411–32.
Thrift, N. J. and Olds, K. 1996. Refiguring the economic in economic geography. Progress in Human Geography 20,
311–17.
Thrift, N. J. and Pred, A. R. 1981. Time geography: A new beginning. Progress in Human Geography 5, 277–86.
Tickell, A. and Peck, J. 1992. Accumulation, regulation and the geographies of post-Fordism: Missing links in
regulationist research. Progress in Human Geography 16, 190–218.
Tickell, A. and Peck, J. 1996. The return of the Manchester Men: Men’s words and men’s deeds in the remaking
of the local state. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS21, 595–616.
Tiefelsdof, M. 2003. Misspecifications in interaction model distance decay relations: A spatial structure effect.
Journal of Geographical Systems 5, 25–50.
Timmermans, H. J. P. and Golledge, R. G. 1990. Applications of behavioural research on spatial problems:
II Preference and choice. Progress in Human Geography 14, 311–54.
Timmermans, H. J. P., Aremze, T. and Joh, C.-H. 2001. Analysing space-time behaviour: New approaches to old
problems. Progress in Human Geography 26, 175–90.
Timmins, N. 1995. The Five Giants: A biography of the welfare state. London: HarperCollins.
Timms, D. 1965. Quantitative techniques in urban social geography. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds) Frontiers
in Geographical Teaching. London: Methuen, 239–65.
Timms, D. 1971. The Urban Mosaic: Towards a theory of residential differentiation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tivers, J. 1978. How the other half lives: The geographical study of women. Area 10, 302–6.
Tobler, W. R. 1959. Automation and cartography. Geographical Review 49, 526–34.
Tobler, W. R. 1970. A computer movie simulating urban growth in the Detroit region. Economic Geography 46,
234–40.
Tobler, W. R. 1995. Migration: Ravenstein, Thornthwaite and beyond. Urban Geography 16, 327–43.
Tobler, W. R. 2002. Ma vie: Growing up in America and Europe. In P. Gould and F. R. Pitts (eds) Geographical
Voices: Fourteen autobiographical essays. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 293–322.
Tocalis, T. R. 1978. Changing theoretical foundations of the gravity concept of human interaction. In
B. J. L. Berry (ed.) The Nature of Change in Geographical Ideas. DeKalb, IL: Northern Illinois University Press,
65–124.
Tolia-Kelly, D. P. 2006. Affect – an ethnocentric encounter? Exploring the ‘universalist’ imperative of emotional/
affectual geographies. Area 38, 213–17.
Tomlinson, R. F. 1989. Geographic information systems and geographers in the 1990s. Canadian Geographer 33,
290–8.
Tomlinson, R. F. 2007. Thinking about GIS, 3rd edn. Redlands: ESRI Press.
Tomlinson, R. F. 2009. Changing the face of geography: GIS and the IGU. ArcNews Online. Available at: www.esri.
com/news/arcnews/spring09articles/changing-the-face.html
Toulmin, S. E. 1970. Does the distinction between normal and revolutionary science hold water? In I. Lakatos
and A. Musgrave (eds) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. London: Cambridge University Press, 39–48.
Trewartha, G. T. 1973. Comments on geography and public policy. Professional Geographer 25, 78–9.
Trudgill, S. T. 1990. Barriers to a Better Environment. London: Belhaven Press.
Tso, B. and Mather, P. M. 2001. Classification Methods for Remotely Sensed Data. London: Taylor & Francis.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1968. The Hydrological Cycle and the Wisdom of God: A theme in geoteleology. Toronto: University of Toronto
Press.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1971. Geography, phenomenology, and the study of human nature. Canadian Geographer 15, 181–92.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1974a. Space and place: Humanistic perspectives. In C. Board, R. J. Chorley, P. Haggett and D. R.
Stoddart (eds) Progress in Geography, Vol. 6. London: Edward Arnold, 211–52.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1974b. Topophilia: A study of environmental perception, attitudes and values. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1975a. Images and mental maps. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 65, 205–13.
References 485

Tuan, Y.-F. 1975b. Place: An experiential perspective. Geographical Review 65, 151–65.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1976. Humanistic geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 66, 266–76.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1977. Space and Place. London: Edward Arnold.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1978. Literature and geography: Implications for geographical research. In D. Ley and M. S. Samuels
(eds) Humanistic Geography: Prospects and problems. Chicago: Maaroufa Press, 194–206.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1979. Landscapes of Fear. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1982. Segmented Worlds and Self. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1984. Dominance and Affection. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1999. Who am I? An autobiography of emotion, mind and spirit. Madison, WI: The University of Wisconsin
Press.
Tuan, Y.-F. 2002a. Dear Colleague: Common and uncommon observations. Minneapolis, MN and London: University
of Minnesota Press.
Tuan, Y.-F. 2002b. A life of learning. In P. Gould and F. R. Pitts (eds) Geographical Voices: Fourteen autobiographical essays.
Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 323–40.
Tullock, G. 1976. The Vote Motive. London: Institute of Economic Affairs.
Turner, A. 2006. Introduction to Neogeography. Sebastopol, CA: O’Reilly.
Turner, B. L. II. 1989. The specialist-synthesis approach to the revival of geography: The case of cultural ecology.
Annals of the Association of American Geographers 79, 88–100.
Turner, B. L. II. 2002. Contested identities: Human-environment geography and disciplinary implications in a
restructuring academy. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 92, 52–74.
Turner, B. L. II. 2005. Geography’s profile in public debate: ‘Inside the beltway’ and the national academies.
Professional Geographer 57, 462–7.
Turner, B. L. II and Meyer, W. B. 1985. The use of citation indices in comparing geography programs:
An exploratory study. Professional Geographer 37, 271–8.
Turner, B. L. II and Varlyguin, D. 1995. Foreign-area expertise in U.S. geography: An assessment of capacity
based on foreign-area dissertations, 1977–1991. Professional Geographer 47, 308–14.
Turner, B. L. II, Clark, W. C., Kates, R. W., Richards, J. F., Matthews, J. T. and Meyer, W. B. (eds) 1990. The Earth as
Transformed by Human Action: Global and regional changes in the biosphere over the past 300 years. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Turner, R. K. 1993. Sustainability: Principles and practice. In R. K. Turner (ed.) Sustainable Environmental Economics and
Management: Principles and practice. London: Belhaven Press, 3–36.
Ullman, E. L. 1941. A theory of location for cities. American Journal of Sociology 46, 853–64.
Ullman, E. L. 1953. Human geography and area research. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 43, 54–66.
Ullman, E. L. 1954a. Geography as spatial interaction. In Interregional Linkages: Proceedings of the Western Committee on
Regional Economic Analysis. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 63–71. Reprinted in R. R. Boyce (ed.)
1980, 13–27.
Ullman, E. L. 1954b. Transportation geography. In P. E. James and C. F. Jones (eds) American Geography: Inventory and
prospect. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 310–33.
Ullman, E. L. 1956. The role of transportation and the bases for interaction. In W. L. Thomas (ed.) Man’s Role in
Changing the Face of the Earth. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 862–80.
Ullman, E. L. 1959 [1957]. American Commodity Flow: A geographical interpretation of rail and water traffic based on principles of
spatial interchange. Seattle, WA: University of Washington Press.
Ullman, E. L. 1962. Presidential address: The nature of cities reconsidered. Papers in Regional Science 9, 7–23.
Unstead, J. F. 1933. A system of regional geography. Geography 18, 175–87.
Unwin, A. 1996. Exploratory spatial analysis and local statistics. Computing and Statistics 11, 387–400.
Unwin, D. J. 1981. Introductory Spatial Analysis. London: Methuen.
Uunwin, D. J. 1994. Cartography, VisC and GIS. Progress in Human Geography 18, 516–22.
Unwin, D. J. 2005. Fiddling on a different planet. Geoforum 36, 681–84.
Unwin, D. J. and Dawson, J. A. 1985. Computer Programming for Geographers. London: Longman.
Unwin, D. J. and Hepple, L. W. 1974. The statistical analysis of spatial series. Statistician 23, 211–28.
Unwin, T. 1992. The Place of Geography. Harlow: Longman.
Upton, G. J. G. and Fingleton, B. 1985. Spatial Data Analysis by Example, Vol. 1: Point pattern and quantitative data.
Chichester: John Wiley.
Upton, G. J. G. and Fingleton, B. 1989. Spatial Data Analysis by Example, Vol. 2: Categorical and directional data.
Chichester: John Wiley.
486 References

Urlich-Cloher, D. U. 1972. Migrations of the North Island Maoris 1800–1840: A systems view of migration.
New Zealand Geographer 28, 23–35.
Urlich-Cloher, D. U. 1975. A perspective on Australian urbanization. In J. M. Powell and M. Williams (eds)
Australian Space, Australian Time: Geographical perspectives. Melbourne: Oxford University Press, 104–59.
Urry, J. 1985. Space, time and the study of the social. In H. Newby et al. (eds) Restructuring Capital. London:
Macmillan, 21–40.
Urry, J. 1986. Locality research: The case of Lancaster. Regional Studies 20, 233–42.
Urry, J. 1987. Society, space and locality. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 5, 435–44.
Vaiou, D. 2003. Guest editorial. Radical debate between ‘local’ and ‘international’: A view from the periphery.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 21, 133–7.
Vale, T. R. 2002. From Clements and Davis to Gould and Botkin: Ideals of progress in physical geography. In R.
D. Sack (ed.) Progress: Geographical essays. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1–21.
Valentine, G. 1993a. (Hetero)sexing space: Lesbian perceptions and experiences of everyday spaces. Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 11, 395–413.
Valentine, G. 1993b. Negotiating and maintaining multiple sexual identities. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers NS18, 237–43.
Valentine, G. 1998. ‘Sticks and stones may break my bones’: A personal geography of harassment. Antipode:
A Radical Journal of Geography 30, 305–32.
Valentine, G. 2003. Geography and ethics: in pursuit of social justice. Progress in Human Geography 27, 375–80.
Valentine, G. 2005. Geography and ethics: Moral geographies? Ethical commitment in research and teaching.
Progress in Human Geography 29, 483–87.
Van den Daele, W. and Weingart, P. 1976. Resistance and receptivity of science to external direction: The
emergence of new disciplines under the impact of science policy. In G. Lemaine et al. (eds) Perspectives on the
Emergence of Scientific Disciplines. The Hague: Mouton, 247–75.
Van der Laan, L. and Piersma, A. 1982. The image of man: Paradigmatic cornerstone in human geography. Annals
of the Association of American Geographers 73, 411–26.
Van der Wusten, H. and O’Loughlin, J. 1986. Claiming new territory for a stable peace: How geography can
contribute. Professional Geographer 38, 18–27.
Van Hoven, B. and Hörschelmann, K. (eds) 2005. Spaces of Masculinities. London and New York: Routledge.
Van Paassen, C. 1981. The philosophy of geography: From Vidal to Hägerstrand. In A. Pred and G. Tornquist
(eds) Space and Time in Geography. Lund: C. W. K. Gleerup, 17–29.
Vance, J. E. 1970. The Merchant’s World. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Vance, J. E. 1978. Geography and the study of cities. Human geography: Coming of age. American Behavioral Scientist
22, 131–49.
Velikonja, J. 1994. Geography at the University of Washington. Yearbook of the Association of Pacific Coast Geographers,
56.
Vidal de la Blache, P. 1903. Tableau de la Géographie de la France. Paris: Hachette.
von Bertalanffy, L. 1950. An outline of general systems theory. British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 1,
134–65.
von Humboldt, A. 1845–1862. Kosmos, Entwurf einer physichien Weltbescheibung. Stuttgart: J. C. Gotta Verlag.
Wagner, P. L. 1976. Reflections on a radical geography. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 8(3), 83–5.
Wainwright, E., Barker, J., Ansell, N., Buckingham, S., Hemming, P. and Smith, F. 2014. Geographers out of
place: Institutions, (inter)disciplinarity and identity. Area 46, 410–17.
Wainwright, J. 2010. On Gramsci’s ‘conceptions of the world’. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 35,
507–21.
Wainwright, J. 2013. Geopiracy: Oaxaca, militant empiricism, and geographical thought. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Wakefield, J., Quinn, M. and Raab, G. (eds) 2001. Disease clusters and ecological studies. Special issue, Journal of
the Royal Statistical Society Series A: Statistics in Society 164, 1–207.
Walby, S. 1986. Patriarchy at Work. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Walford, R. 2001. Geography in British Schools 1850–2000: Making a world of difference. London: Woburn Press.
Walker, R. A. 1981a. A theory of suburbanization. In M. J. Dear and A. J. Scott (eds) Urbanization and Urban Planning
in Capitalist Societies. London: Methuen, 383–430.
Walker, R. A. 1981b. Left-wing libertarianism, an academic disorder: A reply to David Sibley. Professional Geographer
33, 5–9.
Walker, R. A. 1989a. What’s left to do? Antipode 21, 133–65.
References 487

Walker, R. A. 1989b. Geography from the left. In G. L. Gaile and C. J. Willmott (eds) Geography in America. Columbus,
OH: Merrill Publishing Company, 619–51.
Wallace, I. 1989. The Global Economic System. London: Unwin Hyman.
Walmsley, D. J. 1972. Systems Theory: A framework for human geographical enquiry. Research School of Pacific
Studies. Department of Human Geography Publication HG/7, Canberra: Australian National University.
Walmsley, D. J. 1974. Positivism and phenomenology in human geography. Canadian Geographer 18, 95–107.
Walmsley, D. J. and Sorensen, A. D. 1980. What Marx for the radicals? An antipodean viewpoint. Area 12,
137–41.
Ward, D. 1971. Cities and Immigrants: A geography of change in nineteenth-century America. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Ward, K. 2006. Geography and public policy: Towards public geographies. Progress in Human Geography 30,
495–503.
Ward, K. 2007. ‘Public intellectuals’, geography, its representations and publics. Geoforum 38, 1058–64.
Ward, K. 2001. The re-interpretation of urban politics: Three authors, four papers and the ‘shibboleth of
regulation theory’. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS26, 127–33.
Ward, K., Blunt, A., Norcup, J., Sidaway, J. D., Withers, C. W. J. and Maddrell, A. 2010. Book Review Forum:
Complex locations: Women’s geographical work in the UK 1850–1970 – by Avril Maddrell. Area 42,
394–400.
Ward, K., Johnston, R. J., Richards, K., Gandy, M., Taylor, Z., Paasi, A., Fox, R., Serje, M., Yeung, H.W.C., Barnes,
T., Blunt, A. and McDowell, L. 2009. The future of research monographs: An international set of perspectives.
Progress in Human Geography 33, 101–26.
Ward, M. D. and Gleditsch, K. S. 2002. Location, location, location: An MCMC approach to modelling the spatial
context of war and peace. Political Analysis 10, 244–60.
Wardenga, U. 1999. Constructing regional knowledge in German geography: The Central Commission on the
Regional Geography of Germany, 1882–1941. In A. Buttimer, S. D. Brunn and U. Wardenga (eds) Text and
Image: Social construction of regional knowledges. Leipzig: Leibniz Institute for Regional Geography, Beiträge zur
regionalen Geographie 49, 77–84.
Warf, B. 1986. Ideology, everyday life and emancipatory phenomenology. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 18,
268–83.
Warf, B. 1988. The resurrection of local uniqueness. In R. G. Golledge, H. Couclelis and P. R. Gould (eds)
A Ground for Common Search. Santa Barbara, CA: The Santa Barbara Geographical Press, 51–62.
Warf, B. 1993. Postmodernism and the localities debate: Ontological questions and epistemological
implications. Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie 84, 162–8.
Warf, B. 1995. Separated at birth? Regional science and social theory. International Regional Science Review 17,
185–94.
Warf, B. 2006. Humanistic geography. In B. Warf (ed.) Encyclopedia of Human Geography. London: Thousand Oaks,
CA and New Delhi: Sage, 233–6.
Warf, B. and Arias, S. (eds) 2009. The Spatial Turn: Interdisciplinary perspectives. London: Routledge.
Warntz, W. 1959a. Toward a Geography of Price. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Warntz, W. 1959b. Geography at mid-twentieth century. World Politics 11, 442–54.
Warntz, W. 1959c. Progress in economic geography. In P. E. James (ed.) New Viewpoints in Geography. Washington,
DC: National Council for the Social Studies, 54–75.
Warntz, W. 1968. Letter to the editor. Professional Geographer 20, 357.
Warntz, W. 1984. Trajectories and coordinates. In M. Billinge, D. Gregory and R. Martin (eds) Recollections of a
Revolution. London: Macmillan, 134–52.
Waterman, S. 1985. Not just the milk and honey – now a way of life: Israeli human geography since the six-day
war. Progress in Human Geography 9, 194–234.
Waterman, S. and Kliot, N. 1990. The political impact on writing the geography of Palestine-Israel. Progress in
Human Geography 14, 237–60.
Waterstone, M. 2002. A radical journal of geography or a journal of radical geography? Antipode 34,
662–6.
Watkins, J. W. N. 1970. Against normal science. In I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds) Criticism and the Growth of
Knowledge. London: Cambridge University Press, 25–38.
Watson, J. D. 1968. The Double Helix: A personal account of the discovery of the structure of DNA. London: Weidenfeld &
Nicolson.
488 References

Watson, J. W. 1953. The sociological aspects of geography. In G. Taylor (ed.) Geography in the Twentieth Century.
London: Methuen, 453–99.
Watson, J. W. 1955. Geography: A discipline in distance. Scottish Geographical Magazine 71, 1–13.
Watson, J. W. 1983. The soul of geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS8, 385–99.
Watson, M. K. 1978. The scale problem in human geography. Geografiska Annaler 60B, 36–47.
Watts, M. 1988. Deconstructing determinism. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 20, 142–68.
Watts, M. 2000. Struggles over Geography: Violence, freedom and development at the millennium. Heidelberg: Department
of Geography, University of Heidelberg.
Weaver, J. C. 1943. Climatic relations of American barley production. Geographical Review 33, 569–88.
Weaver, J. C. 1954. Crop-combination regions in the Middle West. Geographical Review 44, 175–200.
Webber, M. J. 1972. Impact of Uncertainty on Location. Canberra: Australian National University Press.
Webber, M. J. 1977. Pedagogy again: What is entropy? Annals of the Association of American Geographers 67, 254–66.
Webber, M. M. 1964. The urban place and the non-place urban realm. In M. M. Webber, J. W. Dyckman, D. L.
Foley, A. Z. Guttenberg and C. Bauer Wurster (eds) Explorations into Urban Structure. Philadelphia, PA: University
of Pennsylvania Press, 79–153.
Weightman, B. 1981. Gay bars as private places. Landscape 24, 9–17.
Werritty, A. G. 2010. D’Arcy Thompson’s ‘On growth and form’ and the rediscovery of geometry within the
geographic tradition. Scottish Geographical Journal 126, 231–57.
Wescoat, J. L. 1992. Common themes in the work of Gilbert White and John Dewey: A pragmatic appraisal.
Annals of the Association of American Geographers 82, 587–607.
Western, J. S. 1978. Knowing one’s place: ‘The coloured people’ and the Group Areas Act in Cape Town. In D.
Ley and M. S. Samuels (eds) Humanistic Geography: Problems and prospects. Chicago: Maaroufa Press, 297–318.
Whatmore, S. 1997. Dissecting the autonomous self: Hybrid cartographies for a relational ethics. Environment and
Planning D: Society and Space 15, 37–54.
Whatmore, S. 1999. Hybrid geographies: Rethinking the human in human geography. In D. Massey, J. Allen and
P. Sarre (eds) Human Geography Today. Cambridge: Polity Press, 281–307.
Whatmore, S. 2002. Hybrid Geographies: Natures, cultures, spaces. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi: Sage.
Whatmore, S. 2005. Hybrid Geographies: Author’s responses and reflections. Antipode 37, 842–5.
Wheeler, J. O. 1998. Mappophobia in geography? 1980–1996. Urban Geography 19, 1–5.
Wheeler, J. O. 2002a. Assessing the role of spatial analysis in urban geography in the 1960s. Urban Geography 22,
549–58.
Wheeler, J. O. 2002b. From urban economic to social/cultural geography, 1980–2001. Urban Geography 22,
97–102.
Wheeler, P. B. 1982. Revolutions, research programmes and human geography. Area 14, 1–6.
White, G. F. 1945. Human Adjustment to Floods. Chicago: University of Chicago, Department of Geography, Research
Paper 29.
White, G. F. 1972. Geography and public policy. Professional Geographer 24, 101–4.
White, G. F. 1973. Natural hazards research. In R. J. Chorley (ed.) Directions in Geography. London: Methuen,
193–216.
White, G. F. 1985. Geographers in a perilously changing world. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 75,
10–16.
White, G. F. 2002. Autobiographical essay. In P. Gould and F. R. Pitts, (eds) Geographical Voices: Fourteen autobiographical
essays. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 341–64.
White, P. E. 1985. On the use of creative literature in migration study. Area 17, 277–83.
White, P. E. 1995. Geography, literature and migration. In R. King, J. Connell and P. White (eds) Writing Across
Worlds: Literature and migration. London: Routledge, 1–19.
Whitehand, J. W. R. 1970. Innovation diffusion in an academic discipline: The case of the ‘new’ geography. Area
2, 19–30.
Whitehand, J. W. R. 1984. The impact of geographical journals: A look at ISI data. Area 16, 185–7.
Whitehand, J. W. R. 1985. Contributors to the recent development and influence of human geography: What
citation analysis suggests. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS10, 222–3.
Whitehand, J. W. R. 2002. Contributors to the recent development and influence of human geography: What
citation analysis suggests. Progress in Human Geography 26, 511–19.
Whitehand, J. W. R. and Edmondson, P. M. 1977. Europe and America: The reorientation in geographical
communication in the post-war period. Professional Geographer 29, 278–82.
References 489

Whitehand, J. W. R. and Patten, J. H. C. (eds) 1977. Change in the town. Transaction of the Institute of British Geographers
NS2, 257–416.
Whittlesey, D. 1954. The regional concept and the regional method. In P. E. James and C. F. Jones (eds) American
Geography: Inventory and prospect. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 19–68.
Wilbanks, T. J. 1995. Employment trends in geography: Introduction. Professional Geographer 47, 315–17.
Wilbanks, T. J. and Libbee, M. 1979. Avoiding the demise of geography in the United States. Professional Geographer
31, 1–7.
Wilbert, C. 2009. Animal geographies. In R. Kitchen and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human Geography.
Amsterdam: Elsevier, 122–6.
Williams, M. 1983. The apple of my eye: Carl Sauer and historical geography. Journal of Historical Geography 9, 1–28.
Williams, M. 1989. Americans and their Forests: A historical geography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, M. 2003. Deforesting the Earth: From prehistory to global crisis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Williams, M. 2009. Berkeley school. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human Geography.
Amsterdam: Elsevier, 300–4.
Williams, M. 2012. The creation of humanized landscapes. In R. J. Johnston and M. Williams (eds) A Century of
British Geography. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 196–212.
Williams, M. 2014. To Pass on a Good Earth: The Life and work of Carl Sauer. Charlottesville, VA: University of Virginia
Press.
Williams, W. M. and Herbert, D. T. 1962. The social geography of Newcastle-under-Lyme. North Staffordshire Journal
of Field Studies 2, 108–26.
Williamson, P., Birkin, M. and Rees, P. H. 1998. The estimation of population microdata by using data from
small area statistics and samples of anonymised records. Environment and Planning A 30, 785–816.
Wills, J. 2000. Political economy II: The politics and geography of capitalism. Progress in Human Geography 24,
641–52.
Wills, J. 2002. Political economy III: Neoliberal chickens, Seattle and geography. Progress in Human Geography 26,
90–100.
Wills, J. 2014. Engaging. In R. Lee, N. Castree, V. Kitchin, A. Paasi, C. Philo, S. Radcliffe, S. M. Roberts and
C. Withers (eds) The SAGE Handbook of Human Geography. London: Sage, 363–80.
Wills, J. and Peck, J. 2002. Progress or retreat? Antipode and the radical geographical project. Antipode: A Radical
Journal of Geography 34, 667–71.
Wilson, A. C. and Henry, M. 2011. Evolving disciplinary imaginaries: Mapping the New Zealand Geographer,
1945–1969. New Zealand Geographer 67, 116–25.
Wilson, A. G. 1967. A statistical theory of spatial distribution models. Transportation Research 1, 253–69.
Wilson, A. G. 1970. Entropy in Urban and Regional Modelling. London: Pion.
Wilson, A. G. 1974. Urban and Regional Models in Geography and Planning. London: John Wiley.
Wilson, A. G. 1976a. Catastrophe theory and urban modelling: An application to modal choice. Environment and
Planning A 8, 351–46.
Wilson, A. G. 1976b. Retailers’ profits and consumers’ welfare in a spatial interaction shopping model.
In I. Masser (ed.) Theory and Practice in Regional Science. London: Pion, 42–57.
Wilson, A. G. 1978. Mathematical Education for Geographers. Department of Geography, University of Leeds,
Discussion Paper 211, Leeds
Wilson, A. G. 1981a. Geography and the Environment: Systems Analytical Methods. Chichester: John Wiley.
Wilson, A. G. 1981b. Catastrophe Theory and Bifurcation: Applications to urban and regional systems. London: Croom
Helm.
Wilson, A. G. 1984a. One man’s quantitative geography: Frameworks, evaluations, uses and prospects. In M.
Billinge, D. Gregory and R. L Martin (eds) Recollections of a Revolution: Geography as spatial science. London: Macmillan,
200–26.
Wilson, A. G. 1984b. Making urban models more realistic: Some strategies for future research. Environment and
Planning A 16, 1419–32.
Wilson, A. G. 1989a. Mathematical models and geographic theory. In D. Gregory and R. Walford (eds) Horizons
in Human Geography. London: Macmillan, 29–47.
Wilson, A. G. 1989b. Classics, modelling and critical theory: Human geography as structured pluralism. In
B. Macmillan (ed.) Remodelling Geography. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 61–9.
Wilson, A. G. 2000. Complex Spatial Systems: The modelling foundations of urban and regional analysis. Chichester: John
Wiley.
490 References

Wilson, A. G. 2011. Catastrophe Theory and Bifurcation: Applications to urban and regional systems. Routledge Revivals reprint.
London: Routledge.
Wilson, A. G. and Bennett, R. J. 1985. Mathematical Methods in Human Geography and Planning. Chichester:
John Wiley.
Wilson, A. G. and Kirkby, M. J. 1975. Mathematics for Geographers and Planners. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wilson, A. G., Rees, P. H. and Leigh, C. 1977. Models of Cities and Regions. London: John Wiley.
Wilson, E. O. 1998. Consilience among the great branches of learning. Daedalus 127, 131–50.
Wilton, R. and Evans, J. 2009. Disability and chronic illness. In R. Kitchen and N. Thrift (eds) International
Encyclopedia of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 205–10.
Winter, C. 1997. Ethnocentric bias in geography textbooks: A framework for reconstruction. In D. Tilbury and
M. Williams (eds) Teaching and Learning in Geography. London: Routledge, 180–8.
Wise, M. J. 1968. Sir Dudley Stamp: His life and times. Land use and resources: studies in applied geography. London:
Institute of British Geographers, Special Publication 1, 261–70.
Wise, M. J. 1975. A university teacher of geography. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 66, 1–16.
Wise, M. J. 1977. On progress and geography. Progress in Human Geography 1, 1–11.
Wise, M. J. 1986. The Scott Keltie Report 1885 and the teaching of geography in Great Britain. Geographical Journal
152, 367–82.
Wisner, B. 1970. Introduction: On radical methodology. Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography 2, 1–3.
Withers, C. W. J. 2001. Geography, Science and National Identity: Scotland since 1520. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Withers, C. W. J. 2002. Constructing ‘the geographical archive’. Area 34, 303–11.
Withers, C. W. J. 2007. Placing the Enlightenment: Thinking geographically about the age of reason. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Withers, C. W. J. 2009. Place and the ‘spatial turn’ in geography and in history. Journal of the History of Ideas
70, 637–58.
Withers, C. W. J. 2010. Geography and Science in Britain, 1831–1939: A study of the British Association for the Advancement of
Science. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Withers, C. W. J. 2011. Geography’s narratives and intellectual history. In J. A. Agnew and D. N. Livingstone (eds)
The Sage Handbook of Geographical Knowledge. London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi and Singapore: Sage,
39–50.
Withers, C. W. J. and Mayhew, R. J. 2002. Rethinking ‘disciplinary’ history: Geography in British universities,
c.1580–1887. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS27, 11–29.
Wolch, J. and Dear, M. J. (eds) 1989. The Power of Geography: How territory shapes social life. Boston, MA: Unwin
Hyman.
Woldenberg, M. J. and Berry, B. J. L. 1967. Rivers and central places: Analogous systems? Journal of Regional Science
7, 129–40.
Wolf, A. 2002. Does Education Matter? Myths about education and economic growth. London: Penguin.
Wolf, L. G. 1976. Comments on the Harries–Peet controversy. Professional Geographer 28, 196–8.
Wolpert, J. 1964. The decision process in spatial context. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 54,
337–58.
Wolpert, J. 1965. Behavioral aspects of the decision to migrate. Papers and Proceedings Regional Science Association 15,
159–72.
Wolpert, J. 1967. Distance and directional bias in inter-urban migratory streams. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 57, 605–16.
Wolpert, J. 1970. Departures from the usual environment in locational analysis. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 60, 220–9.
Wolpert, J., Dear, M. J. and Crawford, R. 1975. Satellite mental health facilities. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 65, 24–35.
Women and Geography Study Group-IBG (WGSG). 1984. Geography and Gender: An introduction to feminist geography.
London: Hutchinson.
Women and Geography Study Group-IBG (WGSG). 1997. Feminist Geographers: Explorations in diversity and difference.
Harlow: Longman.
Woods, M. and Gardner, G. 2011. Applied policy research and critical human geography: Some reflection on
swimming in murky waters. Dialogues in Human Geography 2, 198–214.
Woods, R. I. 1982. Theoretical Population Geography. London: Longman.
References 491

Woods, R. I. and Rees, P. H. (eds) 1986. Population Structures and Models: Developments in spatial demography. London: Allen
& Unwin.
Woodward, K., Dixon, D. P. and Jones, J. P. III. 2009. Poststructuralism/poststructuralist geographies. In R.
Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International Encyclopedia of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 396–407.
Wooldridge, S. W. 1956. The Geographer as Scientist. London: Thomas Nelson.
Wooldridge, S. W. and East, W. G. 1958. The Spirit and Purpose of Geography. London: Hutchinson.
Wright, D. J. 2012. Theory and application in a post-GISystems world. International Journal of Geographical
Information Science 26, 2197–2209.
Wright, J. K. 1925. The Geographical Lore of the Time of the Crusades: A study in the history of medieval science and tradition in
western Europe. New York: American Geographical Society.
Wright, J. K. 1947. Terrae incognitae: The place of imagination in geography. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 37, 1–15.
Wright, J. K. 1952. Geography in the Making: The American Geographical Society, 1851–1951. New York: American
Geographical Society.
Wright, J. K. 1962. Miss Semple’s Influences of Geographic Environment: Notes towards a bibliography. Geographical Review
52, 346–61.
Wright, R. and Koch, N. 2009. Ivy League and geography in the US. In R. Kitchin and N. Thrift (eds) International
Encyclopedia of Human Geography. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 616–21.
Wrigley, E. A. 1965. Changes in the philosophy of geography. In R. J. Chorley and P. Haggett (eds) Frontiers in
Geographical Teaching. London: Methuen, 3–24.
Wrigley, N. 1973. The use of percentages in geographical research. Area 5, 183–6.
Wrigley, N. 1976. Introduction to the use of logit models in geography. CATMOG 10, Norwich: Geo
Books.
Wrigley, N. 1983. Quantitative methods: On data and diagnostics. Progress in Human Geography 7, 567–77.
Wrigley, N. 1984. Quantitative methods: Diagnostics revisited. Progress in Human Geography 8, 525–35.
Wrigley, N. 1985. Categorical Data Analysis for Geographers and Environmental Scientists. London: Longman.
Wrigley, N. 1995. Revisiting the modifiable areal unit problem and the ecological fallacy. In A. D. Cliff, P. R.
Gould, A. G. Hoare and N. J. Thrift (eds) Diffusing Geography: Essays for Peter Haggett. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers,
49–71.
Wrigley, N. 2002. ‘Food deserts’ in British cities: Policy context and research priorities. Urban Studies 39,
2029–40.
Wrigley, N. 2013. Towards a policy engaged retail geography. In C. Garrocho (ed.) Advances in Commercial Geography:
Prospects, methods and applications. Zinacantepec, MX: El Colegio Mexiquense, 59–93.
Wrigley, N. and Bennett, R. J. (eds) 1981. Quantitative Geography: A British view. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Wrigley, N. and Longley, P. A. 1984. Discrete choice modelling in urban analysis. In D. T. Herbert and
R. J. Johnston (eds) Geography and the Urban Environment, Vol. 6. Chichester: John Wiley, 45–94.
Wrigley, N. and Matthews, S. 1986. Citation classics and citation levels in geography. Area 18, 185–94.
Wylie, J. 2005. A single day’s walking: Narrating self and landscape on the South West Coast Path. Transactions of
the Institute of British Geographers NS30, 234–47.
Wyly, E. 2009. Strategic positivism. Professional Geographer 61, 310–22.
Wyly, E. 2011. Positively radical. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 35, 889–912.
Wyly, E. 2014. The new quantitative revolution. Dialogues in Human Geography 4, 26–38.
Wyly, E., Moos, M., Foxcroft, H. and Kabahizi, E. 2008. Subprime mortgage segmentation in the American
urban system. Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie 99, 3–23.
Wyly, E., Moos, M., Hammel, D. and Kabahizi, E. 2009. Cartographies of race and class: Mapping the
class–monopoly rents of American subprime mortgage capital. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research
33, 332–54.
Yang, C., Goodchild, M., Huang, Q,. Nebert, D., Raskin, R., Xu, Y. Bambacus, M. and Fay, D. 2011. Spatial cloud
computing: How can the geospatial sciences use and help shape cloud computing? International Journal of Digital
Earth 4, 305–29.
Yeates, M. H. 2001. Yesterday as tomorrow’s song: The contribution of the 1960s ‘Chicago School’ to urban
geography. Urban Geography 22, 514–29.
Yeung, H.W.C. 1997. Critical realism and realist research in human geography: A method or a philosophy in
search of a method? Progress in Human Geography 21, 51–74.
Yeung, H.W.C. 2002. Deciphering citations. Environment and Planning A 34, 2093–2101.
492 References

Young, I. M. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Yule, G. U. and Kendall, M. G. 1950. An Introduction to the Theory of Statistics. London: Griffin.
Zelinsky, W. 1970. Beyond the exponentials: The role of geography in the great transition. Economic Geography 46,
499–535.
Zelinsky, W. 1973a. The Cultural Geography of the United States. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Zelinsky, W. 1973b. Women in geography: A brief factual report. Professional Geographer 25, 151–65.
Zelinsky, W. 1974. Selfward bound? Personal preference patterns and the changing map of American society.
Economic Geography 50, 144–79.
Zelinsky, W. 1975. The demigod’s dilemma. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 65, 123–43.
Zelinsky, W. 1978. Introduction. Human geography: Coming of age. American Behavioral Scientist 22, 5–13.
Zelinsky, W., Monk, J. and Hanson, S. 1982. Women and geography: A review and prospectus. Progress in Human
Geography 6, 317–66.
Zimmerer, K. S. 2010. Retrospective on nature–society geography: Tracing trajectories (1911–2010) and
reflecting on translations. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 100, 1076–94.
Zimmermann, E. W. 1972. World Resources and Industries, 3rd edn. New York: Harper & Row.
Zipf, G. K. 1949. Human Behavior and the Principle of Least Effort. Cambridge, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Zolnik, E. J. 2009. Context in human geography: A multilevel approach to study human–environment
interactions. Professional Geographer 61, 336–49.
Author index

Aalbers, M. B. 376 Baker, A. M. 145


Abler, R. F. 83, 104–5, 107, 109, 158, 384 Baker, A. R. H. xix, 96, 98, 133–4, 216, 364
Abrahamson, H. S. 27 Balchin, W. G. V. 37, 41, 291, 319, 371–2
Abrahamsson, C. 44, 189 Balinski, M. 337
Ackerman, E. A. 59, 61, 64, 74, 76–7, 85, 315 Ball, M. 226
Adams, J. S. 76, 104, 107, 314, 323 Ballabon, M. B. 82
Adams, P. C. 131, 134, 181, 329, 361 Ballas, D. 117
Adams, T. A. 319 Banks, M. 342
Adler, S. 301 Banski, J. 376
Agnew, J. A. 47, 78, 80, 90, 215, 217, 230, 280, Barford, A. 323
331, 346–7, 381, 389, 399 Barnes, B. 14–19, 27, 346
Aitken, S. C. 138, 306 Barnes, T. J. xiii, xviii, xx, 24, 27, 37, 43–4, 65, 74,
Akatiff, C. 200 77–8, 83–4, 90–1, 99, 135, 165, 201, 207–8,
Alexander, D. 233 231, 234, 235, 249, 255, 258–9, 261, 280, 346,
Alexander, J. 67 351, 359, 361, 364, 380–1
Alker, H. R. 152 Barnes, T. S. 389–90
Allen, C. D. 269 Barnett, C. xiv, 245–6, 264, 271, 278, 395
Allen, J. 218, 265 Barrows, H. H. 45
Almond, S. 157 Barton, R. 9, 86
Althusser, L. 207, 211 Bashford, A. 44–5
Amadeo, D. 81–3, 105 Baskin, C. W. 72
Amin, A. 211, 238, 251, 279, 343, 359 Bassett, K. 203, 346, 396
Anderson, B. 270–1 Bastow, S. 337
Anderson, D. 67 Batey, P. 159, 335
Anderson, J. 207, 212 Batty, M. 109, 115, 117, 120, 155, 320, 379
Anderson, K. 280 Beaumont, J. R. 146, 372
Anselin, L. 148, 154, 156–7 Beauregard, R. A. 214, 251
Applebaum, W. 335 Beaver, S. H. 51, 79
Appleton, J. 180, 185 Beaverstock, J. 237
Arias, S. 88, 355 Becher, T. 1
Armstrong, M. P. 155, 161, 395 Beckerman, W. 311, 330
Armstrong, P. 43, 158 Beckinsale, R. P. 43, 90–1
Asheim, B. T. 348 Belina, B. 238
Atkinson, D. 264 Bell, C. 215
Bell, D. J. 301–2
Bachmann, V. 238 Bell, M. 39, 41, 55, 273, 300–1, 358
Backhaus, G. 179 Bell, W. 92
Badcock, B. A. 113, 203, 294 Bennett, R. J. 78, 110–11, 113–15, 121, 124,
Badley, G. F. 386, 398 145–6, 148–9, 166, 213, 229, 231, 232, 234,
Baerenholdt, J. O. 269 239, 308, 320, 337–9, 371–2
Bahrenberg, G. 145 Bentham, G. 396
Bailey, T. C. 145 Berdoulay, V. 22, 38, 40, 44, 357, 360
Baird, I. 328 Berg, L. D. 275, 277–8, 288, 395
494 Author index

Bergmann, G. 65, 77 Bressey, C. 277


Berman, M. 283 Brickell, K. 306
Berry, B. J. L. 65, 68, 71–6, 82–6, 88–92, 94–5, 109, Briggs, D. J. 335
111, 119, 145–6, 148, 151, 182, 228–9, 239, Brookfield, H. C. 125, 135, 173, 223, 328, 382
312, 314, 319, 327, 332, 348–9, 363, 365, 379, Brown, G. 300
382 Brown, L. A. 75, 107, 128, 138
Best, U. xx, 198 Brown, M. P. 300–1, 303
Bettencourt, L. 1 Brown, P. 159, 335
Bhaskar, R. 219 Brown, R. G. 79
Biehl, H. 150 Brown, R. H. 53
Billinge, M. 133, 183–4, 351–2, 360 Brown, S. E. 67
Bingham, N. 268 Browne, K. 304, 306
Binnie, J. 8, 301–3 Browning, C. E. 149
Bird, A. J. 15, 19, 25–6, 397 Brunn, S. D. 324
Bird, J. H. xvi, xviii, 80, 138–9, 240, 328, 351, 361, Brunsdon, C. 157
379 Brush, J. E. 72
Birkin, M. 110, 117, 159, 162, 335 Bryson, R. A. 67, 85
Blaikie, P. M. 121, 222–3, 328 Buchanan, K. M. 58, 222, 312, 324
Blalock, H. M. 77 Buchanan, R. O. 51
Blaut, J. M. 200, 209, 247, 269, 317 Bullen, N. 153
Blouet, B. W. 42, 395 Bullock, A. 319
Blowers, A. T. 314–15 Bunge, W. 60–1, 69, 71–4, 76–8, 105, 122, 135,
Blunt, A. 197–8, 273–4, 287–9, 344 200, 237, 322, 343, 348, 351, 379
Boal, F. W. 172, 190 Burgess, S. 121
Boddy, M. J. 202 Burnett, K. P. 283
Bodman, A. R. 6, 351, 395, 397 Burrows, I. 36
Bondi, L. xiii, 281, 284, 297–9, 326 Burrows, R. 34
Bonnett, A. 275–6, 343 Burton, I. 75, 77, 80, 83, 85, 87, 126–7, 347
Bonta, M. 271 Bushong, A. D. 53, 378
Boots, B. N. 134 Butler, R. 295, 304
Bordessa, R. 237, 322 Butlin, R. A. 39
Borges, J. L. 247–8 Buttimer, A. 41, 46, 49, 107, 133, 176, 182, 184–5,
Bosco, F. J. 269 239, 348–9, 360, 381, 390–1
Bosker, M. 84 Butzer, K. W. 47, 53, 60, 64, 191
Bosman, J. 5
Bourdieu, P. 21, 396 Cadwaller, M. 138, 146
Bowd, G. P. 200 Caesar, A. A. L. 94
Bowden, M. J. 174 Campbell, C. S. 383
Bowen, M. 46 Campbell, J. A. 43, 173
Bowlby, S. R. 283, 288, 293, 304 Cannon, T. 209
Bowman, I. 41, 398 Capel, H. 200, 357, 362, 374
Boyce, R. R. 59 Carey, H. C. 108
Boyer, R. 211 Carlstein, T. 131
Boyle, M. xviii, 20 Carr, M. 138
Boyle, M. J. 130 Carroll, G. R. 68
Boyle, P. J. 159 Carrothers, G. A. P. 108
Boyne, G. A. 343 Carter, G. 300
Brack, E. V. 281, 395 Casetti, E. 75, 153, 167
Bracken, I. 158 Castells, M. 203, 208
Bradley, P. N. 222 Castree, N. xix, 1, 8–9, 34, 37, 198, 206–10, 223,
Brakman, S. 84 238, 241, 278, 327, 331, 343–4, 388, 398
Braun, B. 223 Chan, W. F. 368
Breheny, M. 335 Chapman, G. P. 114–16, 128
Brenner, J. 301 Chappell, J. E. Jr 177
Brenner, N. 197, 212, 339 Chappell, J. M. A. 119
Author index 495

Charlton, M. 152, 320 Cooke, R. U. 121, 156, 310, 369, 373


Chatterton, P. 197–8, 238 Coombes, M. G. 151, 319
Chisholm, G. G. 43, 51, 376 Cooper, A. 195
Chisholm, M. 57, 92, 94–5, 100, 120, 147–8, 229, Cooper, C. 337
313–14, 319, 322–3, 353, 379 Cooper, W. 14
Chorley, R. J. 14, 25, 43, 63, 78, 81, 90–1, 93–4, Cope, M. 288
101, 110–15, 121, 145, 347, 349, 352, 366, 398 Coppock, J. T. 315, 324
Chouinard, V. 304 Corbridge, S. 209
Chrisman, N. R. 157–8 Cormack, L. B. 38
Christaller, W. 60, 65, 69, 72, 74, 90–1, 121 Cosgrove, D. 51–2, 159, 169, 175, 190–1, 223, 246,
Christensen, K. 233 258, 328
Christopherson, S. 295, 304 Couclelis, H. 119, 140–1, 161
Church, H. 58 Couper, P. xviii
Cirincione, C. 150 Court, A. 79
Clark, A. H. 53, 62, 92, 175 Court, G. 288
Clark, C. 69 Cowen, D. J. 160
Clark, D. B. 75, 89–90 Cox, K. R. xviii, 55–6, 60, 73, 75, 101, 124, 128,
Clark, G. L. 84, 211–12, 229, 324, 332–3, 337, 351, 140, 166, 198, 214, 241, 322–4, 348–9,
359 380, 389
Clark, K. G. T. 81 Cox, N. J. 146, 167
Clark, M. 195, 333 Crampton, J. W. 39, 165, 355
Clark, W. A. V. 75–6 Crane, D. 16
Clarke, D. B. 243, 266 Crang, M. 187, 193, 244, 276, 280, 331
Clarke, G. P. 117 Crang, P. 264, 301
Clarke, K. C. 117, 155 Cresswell, T. xvi, xviii, xx, 1, 155, 169, 198, 271,
Clarke, M. 117, 119, 154 345, 388–9
Clarks, C. G. 314 Cromley, R. G. 161
Clarkson, J. D. 114 Crowe, P. R. 50, 90–1, 121
Clauset, A. 2 Crowther, J. G. 291
Claval, P. 26, 38, 40, 46, 231, 396 Crush, J. 273
Clayton, D. 37, 39, 200, 273–4 Cullen, I. G. 145
Clayton, K. M. 321 Cumberland, K. B. 327
Cliff, A. D. 106–7, 147–8, 308, 379 Cumbers, A. 198
Clifford, J. 261 Cupples, J. 298, 388
Cloke, P. xviii, 130, 142, 155, 170, 194–5, 198, Curran, P. J. 156–7, 321
211, 221, 248–50, 292, 326, 381, 383 Curry, L. 65, 68, 71, 137, 147
Clout, H. D. 37, 39, 43, 46–7, 52, 98, 312, 315, Curry, M. 159, 177–8, 185–6, 262, 361
319, 364, 376 Curti, G. H. 297
Cochrane, A. 214, 218 Cutter, S. L. 105, 159, 320, 332, 341, 388
Cockings, S. L. 151
Coffey, W. J. 115, 119, 166 Dacey, M. F. 71–2, 74, 147, 152
Coggeshall, P. E. 396 Dahmann, N. 365
Cohen, S. B. 12, 85 Dalby, S. 264–5, 288
Colby, C. 75 Dale, A. 138
Cole, J. P. 79 Daly, M. 57
Colebrook, R. 175 Daniels, S. 191, 223, 258, 328
Coleman, A. 335 Darby, H. C. 43, 50, 52–5, 57, 95–6, 188, 247,
Collini, S. 5, 33–4, 321, 337 365, 377
Collins, J. L. 11, 110 Darwin, C. 43–4
Collins, M. J. 110 Davey, J. 395
Conant, J. B. 15 Davies, R. B. 138
Conkling, E. 75 Davies, W. K. D. 66, 89, 347
Conzen, M. P. 96 Davis, W. M. 40–4
Cook, I. 193, 246 Dawney, L. 297
Cooke, P. N. 212–13, 247 Dawson, J. 156, 335
496 Author index

Day, M. 233 Duncan, N. 250, 297, 301


De Maesschalck, F. 6, 396 Duncan, O. D. 67–8, 114, 146
Dear, M. J. 196, 221, 227, 243, 248–51, 254–6, Duncan, R. 329
324, 365 Duncan, S. S. 199, 202, 214, 230, 363, 375
Dear, P. 397 Dunford, M. 211, 216
Dearden, J. 154 Dwyer, C. 277
Delaney, D. 276 Dwyer, M. B. 328
Delano-Smith, C. 165 Dyck, I. 295–6
Delanty, G. 397
Deleuze, G. 266–7, 271 Earle, C. V. 63
DeLyser, D. 187 Eden, S. 327
Demeritt, D. xxi, 248–9 Edmondson, P. M. 377
Demko, G. 75 Eels, W. C. 69
Derrida, J. 259–60, 264 Ekers, M. 211
Derudder, B. 6, 237 Elden, S. 60, 105, 197, 355
Desbarats, J. 138 Elder, G. S. 302
Desbiens, C. 238 Eliot Hurst, M. E. 111, 204, 207, 227, 317,
Detwyler, T. R. 327 385
Deutsch, R. 226, 254 Ellegård, E. 107, 131
Dever, G. E. A. 322 Ellegård, K. 134
DeVivo, M. S. xviii Elliott, P. 152
Dewey, J. 330 Elwood, S. 162, 168, 320
Dewsbury, J.-D. 269–70, 386 England, K. 295, 299–300
Dicken, P. 31, 138, 144 Enloe, C. 323
Dickens, P. 215 Entrikin, J. N. 63, 109, 170, 179, 184–5, 195, 215,
Dickenson, J. P. 314 378–9
Dickinson, R. E. 39, 51, 59, 90–1, 363, 376 Evans, J. 304
Dingemans, D. 202 Evans, M. 186
Dittmer, J. 265 Eyles, J. 188, 194, 234, 313, 315, 380–1
Dixon, D. P. xix, 243, 278, 398 Eyre, J. D. 59
Doan, P. L. 304 Eyre, S. R. 328
Dobson, J. E. 160–1
Dodds, K. 264 Fahey, S. 212
Dodge, M. 168, 264 Fahy, G. 41
Dodgson, R. A. 216 Fairbairn, D. 157
Doel, M. A. 239, 242, 261, 265–6 Falah, G. 305, 333
Domosh, M. xiii, 281, 289, 297 Falconer Al-Hindi, K. 282, 283, 298, 299
Donaghy, T. 84 Farish, M. xviii, 74
Donkin, R. 364–5 Fawcett, C. B. 51
Dorling, D. 30, 157, 160, 165, 228, 309, 323, Featherstone, D. 212, 238, 341
341–3 Febvre, L. 45
Dormtzer, J. 104 Feldman, E. J. 330
Douglas, I. 327–8 Fellmann, J. D. 40, 43
Dowling, R. 288 Ferenc, M. 376
Downs, R. M. 130, 178 Feyeraben, P. 20, 394
Drake, C. 305 Fieldhouse, E. 140
Draper, D. 333 Findlay, A. 394
Dresch, J. 312 Fingleton, B. 145–6
Driver, F. xiii, 39, 41, 232, 354 Fischer, M. M. 155–6
Duffield, B. S. 315 Fisher, P. F. 158, 161
Duffy, P. 188 Fitzsimmons, M. 222
Dunbar, G. S. 10, 40 Fleming, D. K. 216
Duncan, C. 146 Fleure, H. J. 45
Duncan, J. S. 191–2, 215, 225, 230–1, 239, 246, Flint, C. 331
258, 260, 346, 381, 389–90 Flowerdew, R. 150, 234, 262
Author index 497

Flusty, S. 243, 250–1 Gleditsch, K. S. 152


Foley, B. 35 Gleeson, B. 143
Folke, S. 200, 204, 236–7 Glennie, P. D. 133, 257
Foord, J. 292–4 Gober, P. 370
Foote, D. G. 110 Goddard, J. 145, 158
Foote, K. E. 171, 190–1 Godlewska, A. M. C. 354
Ford, L. R. 368, 383 Goheen, P. G. 96
Forer, P. C. 109 Gold, J. R. 130, 140, 142
Foresman, T. W. 157–8 Goldstein, H. 35
Forest, B. 301 Golinski, J. 9
Forrester, J. W. 113 Golledge, R. G. 66, 77, 81–3, 98, 105, 124, 128,
Foster, J. 6 130–1, 137–8, 140, 142–4, 154, 160, 172, 211,
Fotheringham, A. S. 109, 145, 147, 153, 155, 158 234
Foucault, M. 22–3, 266–7, 354–5 Goodchild, M. F. 120, 157, 159–63, 320, 370
Franklin, R. S. 31 Goodson, I. 347, 357, 372, 377
Freeman, T. W. xvi, 40–1, 48, 50, 58, 63, 72, 264, Goodwin, M. 211, 217, 239
319, 349, 357, 378 Gopal, S. 156
Frey, A. E. 148 Gordon, P. E. 15, 349
Frickel, S. 24 Gorman-Murray, A. 288
Fukuyama, F. 236 Gosme, C. 37, 43, 319
Fuller, G. A. 322 Goss, J. 159
Fuller, S. 15, 357, 377, 397 Gottmann, J. 105
Goudie, A. S. 121, 328
Gaile, G. L. xiv, 52, 63, 380, 384 Gould, P. R. 59, 75–7, 79, 84, 87, 100, 102, 104,
Gale, N. 137 117, 128–30, 137, 146, 148, 184, 226, 230,
Gamble, A. 31, 367 234–5, 240, 278, 305, 349, 351, 360, 379,
Garcia-Ramon, M. D. 304, 377 383
Gardiner, G. 344 Graham, E. 256
Garner, B. 75 Graham, M. 157, 347
Garrison, W. L. 59, 67, 69–75, 77, 79, 84, 110, 145, Gramsci, A. 211
366 Granger, A. 329
Gatrell, A. C. 124, 145–6, 234, 375, 395 Gräno, O. 336, 357, 360
Gauthier, H. L. 75, 87, 349, 353 Grant, A. 304
Geary, R. C. 147 Graves, N. J. 350
Geertz, C. 1, 14, 23, 353, 366 Gray, F. 201–2
Gehlke, C. E. 150 Graybill, F. A. 77
Gerike, M. xix, 391 Green, N. P. 157
Gertler, M. 211 Greenberg, D. 141
Getis, A. 60, 71, 74, 134, 154–5, 167, 348, 375 Greer-Wootten, B. 110, 119–20
Gibbons, W. 344 Gregory, D. 1, 26, 37, 46–7, 56, 61, 63, 65, 76–8,
Gibbs, G. 372 102, 124, 133–4, 142, 149, 176–8, 180, 183,
Gibson, K. 198, 212 192, 195, 206, 216–17, 221, 230–1, 234, 235,
Gibson-Graham, J. K. 286 249–50, 258, 261, 272–3, 275, 279, 343, 351,
Giddens, A. 133–4, 189, 198, 213, 217, 221, 353, 356, 359–60, 398
355 Gregory, K. J. 50
Gier, J. 293 Gregory, S. 52, 77, 90–1, 99, 178, 378
Gilbert, A. 217 Gregson, N. 133, 214, 221, 257, 292–5, 307, 331
Gilbert, D. 165, 238, 264, 334 Gren, M. 189
Gille, Z. 269 Gribbin, J. 14
Gillen, J. 387 Griffiths, M. J. 215
Gilmartin, M. 275 Grigg, D. B. 95, 108
Gilmore, R. 340 Gross, N. 24
Ginsburg, N. S. 75, 87, 312 Grossman, L. 114
Glacken, C. J. 45, 53–4, 174, 222 Guattari, F. 267, 271, 379
Glasmeier, A. K. 228, 309 Gudgin, G. 116, 149–50, 324
498 Author index

Guelke, L. 63–4, 78, 130, 175–9, 272 Haynes, R. M. 106–7


Gutiérrez, J. 376 Hayter, R. 138
Hefferman, M. 39, 46, 265
Hägerstrand, T. 71, 73, 107, 128, 131–4, 148, 156, Hendrikse, R. P. 31
221, 320, 336, 363, 375, 379 Henry, M. 26
Haggett, P. 14, 25, 57, 63, 78, 81, 90–4, 100–4, Hepple, L. W. 113, 143, 397
106–7, 120, 145–9, 156, 216, 308, 347, 352, Herbert, D. T. 92, 348, 385
360, 364, 366, 379 Herbert, S. 299
Hagood, M. J. 322 Herbertson, A. J. 40, 50
Hague, E. 238 Herod, A. xix, 207, 211–12, 298
Haigh, M. J. 368 Hewitt, K. 327
Haines-Young, R. 80, 161, 350 Hinchliffe, S. xix, 268
Haining, R. P. 134, 146–7, 149, 322 Hinshaw, R. E. 126, 330
Haklay, M. 168 Hix, S. 337
Halas, M. 44 Hodder, I. 95
Hall, P. 94, 240, 315, 319–20, 336, 398 Hodgart, R. L. 324
Hall, T. 9, 369, 395 Hodges, A. 56
Halvorson, P. 71, 83, 90–1 Hoggart, K. 248
Hamilton, F. E. J. 138 Hohn, U. 37
Hammett, D. 8 Holden, A. 212
Hamnett, C. 278, 341–2, 383, 388 Holloway, L. 292
Hanham, R. 153 Holloway, S. L. 195, 295, 306, 322
Hansen, K. 159 Holly, B. P. 346, 348
Hanson, S. 75, 91, 283–4, 294–5, 299, 306, 363–4, Holm, E. 117
380, 385 Holmes, J. H. 9, 329, 368
Hare, F. K. 315, 341 Holt-Jensen, A. xviii, 345, 348, 350
Haritaworn, J. 301 Hönsch, I. 38
Harley, B. 262–4 Hook, J. C. 65, 67
Harries, K. D. 227, 322 Hooper, B. 242
Harris, C. D. 59, 65, 69, 70, 72, 75, 90 Hooson, D. J. M. 53
Harris, P. 153 Hopkins, P. 288, 307
Harris, R. (Ray) 156 Hörschelmann, K. 288
Harris, R. (Rich) 151, 335 Horton, F. 75, 327
Harris, R. C. 63, 175, 176 Horton, J. 305
Harrison, P. 269–71 House, J. W. 312, 319
Harrison, R. T. 231, 233, 381 Howell, P. 303
Hart, J. F. 6, 98, 216, 234, 315 Hoyningen-Huene, P. 25
Hartshorne, R. 47–50, 53, 60–4, 73–4, 89, 93, 175, Hsu, J.-Y. 12
348–9, 379, 383 Hubbard, P. xix, 25, 194, 242, 244,
Harvey, D. 7, 11, 15, 45, 56, 60, 70, 77–80, 93, 95, 251, 259–60, 280, 292, 300–2,
100, 105, 107, 110–11, 136–7, 147–8, 175, 350, 356
197–8, 200, 202–7, 209, 211, 216, 222–9, 231, Huckle, J. 239
234, 237, 239–40, 252–5, 269, 311, 316–18, Hudson, G. D. 71
325, 332, 334, 337–8, 343–4, 347, 351, 362, Hudson, R. 130, 234, 319, 331, 366–7
381–2, 389 Huggett, R. J. 115, 121
Harvey, F. 47 Hughes, T. P. 110
Harvey, M. 346, 348 Hugill, P. J. 171, 190–1
Hashmi, S. H. 280, 325 Hull, R. 5
Hassard, J. 268 Huntington, E. 44, 69
Haugeland, J. 15 Huxley, M. 212
Haushofer, K. 44 Hyndman, J. 288, 305
Hawkins, R. 399
Hay, A. M. 70–1, 79–80, 109, 119, 134, 146, 149, Imrie, R. F. 295
178, 233, 240, 381 Isard, W. 69, 84, 111, 120, 137
Hayford, A. M. 283 Isserman, A. M. 84
Author index 499

Jackson, P. 109, 183, 186, 190–2, 241, 246, 251, Kimble, G. H. T. 58


272, 275, 277, 285, 288, 293, 299, 304, Kindon, S. 343
307 King, G. 152
Jacobs, J. 187, 272, 275, 286, 336 King, L. J. 65–7, 75, 77, 82–3, 99, 105, 118, 147,
James, P. E. 12, 38, 40, 46–9, 54, 59, 64–5, 80, 86, 152–3, 229, 360, 363
165, 348, 383 King, R. 188
Janelle, D. G. 109, 134, 370 Kingsbury, P. 270
Jayne, M. 322 Kirk, W. 172–3
Jazell, T. 274 Kirkby, M. J. 145
Jeffrey, A. xvi, xviii, 198, 245–6, 271, 276, 284–5 Kish, G. 367
Jenkins, A. 5, 33, 331 Kissling, C. C. 114
Jóhannesson, G. T. 269 Kitchin, R. 25, 34, 138, 157, 168, 188, 264, 302,
Johnson, J. H. 96 347
Johnson, L. C. 285–8, 296, 305 Kjellen, R. 44
Johnston, R. J. xiii, xvi, xvii, xviii, xix, xxi, xxii, 5–7, Kliot, N. 333
9, 11, 14, 16, 20, 25–6, 28–9, 31, 33–4, 39, Kneale, J. 188
41–3, 48–52, 54–9, 65, 71–2, 74, 76, 79–81, Knopp, L. 292, 294, 300–1, 303
85, 87–91, 94, 99, 101, 105, 108, 110, 114, Knos, D. S. 65, 67
116–19, 134, 137, 140, 142, 146–8, 150, 152, Knox, P. L. 237, 247, 322
154–5, 159, 165–7, 172, 179, 184, 186, 203, Kobayashi, A. 275–6
207, 215–17, 222–3, 227, 232–5, 236, 244, Koch, N. 12, 368
281, 316–17, 321, 323–4, 328–9, 331–3, 337, Koelsch, W. A. 39, 368, 378
342, 346, 348, 351, 354, 356, 358, 361–3, Kofman, E. 191, 295, 305
365–7, 371–6, 378–81, 383, 386–90, 394–8 Kohn, C. F. 75
Joliveau, T. 320 Kollmorgen, W. N. 319
Jonas, A. E. G. 214, 219 Kong, L. 195, 345
Jones III, J. P. xix, 146, 153, 157, 159, 243, 278, Kost, K. 44
283, 351, 398 Kroeber, A. L. 53
Jones, A. 211, 223, 238, 288 Krumbein, W. C. 77, 84
Jones, C. F. 48, 54, 59, 64, 383 Kuhn, T. S. 15, 17–22, 25–6, 36, 205, 346–50,
Jones, E. 63, 81, 92 352–3, 359, 366, 375, 378–9, 384, 389, 394,
Jones, K. 146, 153, 155, 397 396–7
Jones, L. V. 396 Kwan, M.-P. 159, 162, 299, 308, 350, 385,
Jones, M. 217 388, 395
Joseph, A. E. 322
Labedz, L. 389
Kahneman, D. 126, 185 Lacoste, Y. 200
Kain, R. 165 Lakatos, I. 19, 354, 363, 378
Kansky, K. J. 73 Landström, C. 331
Kant, I. 45, 47–8, 60–1, 399 Langton, J. 112–13, 216
Kaolan, R. 356 Laponce, J. A. 166
Kasbarian, J. A. 273 Larkin, R. P. 360
Kasperson, R. E. 310 Larner, W. 238
Kates, R. W. 75, 126–7, 129, 327, 329–30 Latour, B. 14, 24
Katz, C. 283 Lauria, M. 292, 294
Kearn, L. 399 Laurie, N. 288
Kearns, G. 40–2, 308 LaValle, P. 79, 84
Keighren, I. M. xvii, xix, 44, 362, 389, 398 Law, J. 268, 374
Kelly, A. 34 Law, R. 294
Keltie, J. S. 39, 308 Lawson, V. 199, 325
Kendall, M. G. 150 Lawton, R. 43
Kennedy, B. A. 111–14 Leach, B. 316
Ketchum, J. 31 Leach, E. R. 211
Keylock, C. J. xiv Leach, S. 313
Kibel, B. M. 136 Lee, R. xv, 193, 201, 216, 234, 243, 381
500 Author index

Lee, Y. 227 Mackinder, H. J. 40–2, 308, 398


Lees, L. 203, 336 MacKinnon, D. 158, 218
Lehr, J. C. 174 Maclean, K. 376
Leighley, J. 47, 51, 53 MacLeod, G. 211–12, 217
Lemaine, G. 374 Macmillan, B. 73, 141, 154, 156, 339
Leslie, T. F. 388 Maddrell, A. xviii, xix, 37, 291
Leszcynski, A. 163, 168, 320 Madge, C. 281, 298
Lewis, G. M. 131, 174, 322 Maguire, D. J. 158
Lewis, M. W. 191, 246, 265 Mahtani, M. 276
Lewis, P. W. 73, 81, 145 Mair, A. 25, 214, 347, 350, 352, 389
Lewthwaite, G. R. 45 Manion, T. 230
Ley, D. 169, 172, 182, 185–6, 190–2, 225, 230–1, Manners, G. 94
260, 380–1 Manners, I. R. 54, 327
Leyshon, A. 341 Marble, D. F. 71, 73, 84, 161
Libbee, M. 368 Marcus, M. G. 52, 84–5, 105, 327
Lichtenberger, E. 20, 90, 366 Marginson, S. 368
Lindberg, J. B. 65 Mark, D. M. 120, 158, 165
Lindley, G. 396 Markusen, A. 279
Lipietz, A. 211 Marsh, G. P. 54, 327
Little, J. 294 Marshall, J. U. 80, 240
Liu, X. 7, 35, 388 Marston, S. 269
Liverman, D. M. 329 Martin, A. F. 63, 81
Livingstone, D. N. xvi–xvii, 12, 14, 35, 43–4, 47, 76, Martin, G. J. xviii, xxi, 12, 41, 43, 46, 60, 66, 165,
172, 189–90, 231, 233, 291, 349–50, 353–4, 341, 348, 378, 395
356, 361, 371, 380–1, 399 Martin, R. L. 84, 149, 151, 279, 320, 341–3, 351,
Lloyd, C. D. 146 395
Lobben, A. 144 Mason, K. 43, 343
Longhurst, R. 288, 296 Massam, B. H. 324
Longley, P. A. 120, 138, 151, 155–9, 164, Massey, D. 207–8, 212, 214–15, 218, 226, 234,
335, 338 239, 241, 247, 254, 293, 340–1, 343, 351
Loomis, J. M. 140 Masterman, M. 19
López-Nieva, P. 376 Mather, E. C. 47
Lorimer, H. xiv, xix, 271, 394–5 Mather, J. R. 327
Lösch, A. 65, 73, 82, 91, 121, 149 Mather, P. M. 146
Low, M. 278, 395 Mathewson, K. 97, 200, 269
Lowe, M. S. 295, 345 Matless, D. 266, 354
Lowenthal, D. 54, 171–4, 185, 187, 327 Matthews, H. 371
Lowry, I. 109–10 Matthews, J. A. 385
Lu, Y. 163 Matthews, S. 395
Luke, T. W. 6, 34, 386–7 Mattingly, D. 298–9
Lukermann, F. 47, 53, 82–3, 87, 105, 121, 124, Maxey, L. 238
141, 159, 174, 361 May, J. 344
Lutz, C. A. 11 May, J. A. 45, 60–1, 123
Lyde, L. W. 39 Mayer, H. M. 49, 75, 175
Lynch, K. 130 Mayer, T. 292
Lynch, M. 397 Mayhew, R. J. 10, 37–9, 221, 272, 329
Lysacht, K. 302 McCarty, H. H. 59, 61, 65–7, 69, 75–6
McConnell, H. 79
Mabogunje, A. K. 178 McCormack, D. P. 270
MacAllister, I. 140 McDaniel, R. 111
MacDonald, N. 126 McDowell, L. 212, 278, 283–6, 288, 293–8, 301
MacEachren, A. 160 McEwan, C. 55, 274, 289–90
Macgill, S. M. 146 McGlade, M. S. 370
Machamer, P. 397 McGuiness, M. 275
MacKian, S. 342 McKendrick, J. 39
Author index 501

McKinney, W. M. 108 Mumford, L. 53


Mead, W. R. 50, 98, 180 Murdoch, J. 267–8
Meadows, D. H. 328 Murphy, A. B. 98, 217, 366–8, 385, 388
Meeus, B. 6, 396 Myrdal, G. 113
Meinig, D. W. 96–7, 170, 188, 216
Mels, T. 107 Nagar, R. 304–5
Mendietta, E. 60 Nagel, C. 305
Mercer, D. C. 178, 181, 233 Nash, C. 296
Merrifield, A. 237, 322–3 Nast, H. 299, 301
Merriman, P. 280 Natter, W. 44
Mesev, V. 156 Nayak, A. xvi, xviii, 198, 245–6, 271, 276, 284–5,
Meyer, D. R. 79 288
Meyer, J. T. 130 Neft, D. 69
Meyer, W. B. 396 Nelson, L. 283
Mialet, H. 397 Nelson, T. A. 100, 154, 167–8
Michie, J. 337 Newby, H. 215
Middleton, N. 329 Newman, D. 333
Mikesell, M. W. 53–4, 97–8, 278, 326–8, 348, Newman, J. L. 177
362–3, 369, 374, 379 Newman, M. 323
Miller, D. 280, 325 Newman, O. 336
Miller, E. W. 12, 43, 319 Newton, I. 16
Miller, H. J. 165 Nicholls, W. J. 251
Mills, C. W. 56, 176 Nickles, T. 15
Minca, C. 44, 74, 242–3, 257, 376 Nijman, J. 251
Minghi, J. 333 Noble, G. 288
Mitchell, B. 333 Nystuen, J. D. 71, 76, 105–7, 141
Mitchell, D. 192–3, 223, 235, 237, 241, 246, 278,
385 Ó hUallacháin, B. 388
Mitchell, R. 151 Ó Tuathail, G. 264–5, 271
Miyares, I. M. 370 O’Kelly, M. 167
Mohammad, R. 270, 301 O’Loughlin, J. 154, 331
Mohan, G. 278, 355 O’Riordan, T. 326–8, 330–1
Mohan, J. 21, 308, 343 O’Sullivan, D. 145, 158, 399
Monk, J. 282–3, 378, 392 O’Sullivan, P. 94
Monmonier, M. S. 161, 262 Öberg, S. 320
Montefiore, A. G. 81 Obermeyer, N. J. 162
Moodie, D. W. 174 Odum, H. W. 47
Moore, E. G. 128 Oeppen, J. E. 149
Moore, H. E. 47 Ola, D. 130
Moos, A. I. 221 Olds, K. xxii, 193, 243, 257
Moreton, B. 31 Ollman, B. 209
Morgan, K. 220 Olson, A. 323
Morgan, M. A. 78 Olsson, G. 76, 108, 136, 189, 240, 261, 264, 266,
Morgan, W. B. 114 351
Morin, K. M. 7, 39, 41, 283, 308, 358 Openshaw, C. 142, 151, 157
Morrell, J. 9 Openshaw, S. 142, 150–3, 156–9, 234, 331, 335,
Morrill, R. L. 70–4, 76, 103–4, 107, 150, 167, 339, 380
203–4, 229, 319, 322, 349, 363, 375, 396 Ord, J. K. 147, 154, 379
Morton, P. A. 355 Orme, A. R. 349
Moss, P. J. 283, 360 Ormsby, H. 291
Moss, R. P. 77–8, 80, 82, 93, 114, 123 Orton, C. 95
Mounsey, H. 158 Osbeck, L. 397
Muir, R. 95, 230, 324 Östh, J. 159
Mulkay, M. J. 13–14, 16 Owens, P. L. 327
Müller-Wille, C. 60, 72 Ozouf-Marignier, M.-V. 46
502 Author index

Paasi, A. 26, 217 Phipps, A. G. 221


Pacione, M. xviii, 333, 337, 344 Picard, J. 6
Pagliara, F. 154 Pickerill, J. 198
Pahl, R. E. 92, 202 Pickering, A. 397
Pain, R. 294, 337, 343 Pickles, A. R. 138
Painter, J. 212–13, 340–1, 396 Pickles, J. 159, 161, 168, 178–9, 184–6, 190, 194,
Palfreyman, D 32 237, 262, 264
Palm, R. 104, 133, 202 Pickvance, C. 208
Papegeorgiou, G. J. 106 Piersma, A. 231
Pappenberger, F. 331 Pile, S. 249, 270, 290, 297
Pardoe, J. 335 Pinch, S. P. 203, 361
Park, R. 109, 195 Pipkin, J. S. 141
Parker, C. 168 Pirie, G. H. 137
Parker, G. 44 Pitman, A. J. 328
Parker, W. H. 42, 308 Pitts, F. R. 84, 360
Parkes, D. N. 133 Platt, R. H. 75, 330
Parkinson, S. 336 Ploszajka, T. 39, 41, 276
Parr, D. A. 163 Plummer, P. 279
Parr, H. 295 Pocock, D. C. D. 130, 187–8
Parry, M. 329 Poiker, T. K. 161
Parsons, J. J. 53, 97 Pollard, J. S. 342
Paterson, J. H. 97–8 Pooler, J. A. 108–9
Paterson, J. L. 360 Pooley, C. G. 96
Patmore, J. A. 327 Popper, K. R. 15, 19–20, 80, 346, 361, 366
Patten, J. H. C. 96 Porteous, J. D. 130, 140, 183, 187–8
Patterson, T. C. 362 Porter, J. R. 355
Pattie, C. J. 117–18, 140, 146, 152, 215, 367 Porter, P. W. 174, 362
Pattison, W. D. xx Portugali, J. 333
Pawson, E. J. 39, 273, 315, 388 Poulsen, M. F. 151
Peach, C. 109, 251, 365 Powell, J. M. 45, 174, 178, 181, 183, 185, 191, 368
Peake, L. xviii, 197, 200–1, 275–6, 301, 305 Powell, M. 343
Peck, J. 211–12, 237, 238, 288, 340–2, 359, 367 Powell, R. C. xix, 10, 389, 398
Peet, R. xviii, 197–9, 201, 203, 206–9, 217, 223, Power, M. 44, 200
227–8, 236, 239, 241, 257, 269, 292, 298, 309, Pratt, G. 220, 285–7, 294–5
312, 351, 383, 389, 391–2 Pred, A. R. 69, 96, 113, 131–7, 172, 189, 221, 261,
Peltier, L. C. 51 360–1
Penning-Rowsell, E. C. 131, 335 Preticeille, E. 208
Penrose, J. 277 Price, M. 191, 246
Pepper, D. 222, 329, 331 Price, P. L. 276–7
Pepper, S. C. 390 Prince, H. C. 52, 172, 174, 313, 365
Perrons, D. 216 Proctor, J. D. 326
Perry, P. J. 52 Proudfoot, M. J. 70
Persson, O. 107, 131 Pruitt, E. L. 85
Petch, J. R. 80, 350 Prunty, M. C. 378
Peter, L. 5 Puar, J. K. 301
Peters, G. L. 360 Pudup, M. B. 216–17
Peuquet, D. F. 161 Pugh, J. C. 58
Pevalin, D. J. 236 Pulido, L. 276
Phelps, N. A. 319 Purcell, M. 396
Philbrick, A. K. 72
Phillips, D. R. 322 Radcliffe, S. A. 273, 288, 295, 304
Phillips, M. 396 Radford, J. P. 96
Phillips, R. 288, 344 Rana, S. 320
Philo, C. xix, 171, 201, 213, 232, 244–5, 261, Rao, L. 151, 157
266–7, 269, 279, 306, 341, 391–2, 394 Ratzel, F. 43–4, 46, 348
Author index 503

Ravenstein, E. G. 108 Russell, C. A. 86


Rawstron, E. M. 90–1 Rusu, M. S. 388
Ray, D. M. 120 Rycroft, S. 51
Rayner, J. 75
Read, R. 15 Saarinen, T. 75, 131, 178
Rees, J. 327 Sachs, A. 46
Rees, P. H. 117, 120–1 Sack, R. D. 54, 105, 121–4, 211, 326
Reeves, R. W. 121 Said, E. 273, 275
Reitsma, F. 162 Saillard, Y. 211
Relph, E. 179, 183–6 Saldanha, A. 276
Renfrew, A. C. 95 Samers, M. 377
Rey, S. 148, 156 Samuels, M. S. 184–5, 190–1
Reynolds, D. 75 Sanders, R. 276
Reynolds, R. B. 72 Sanderson, M. 45, 327
Rhind, D. W. 155, 157–8, 163, 165, 234, 319, 321 Sauer, C. 53–4, 62, 97, 110, 186, 190, 192, 246,
Richards, K. 34, 372 362, 365
Richardson, D. 158, 371 Saunders, A. 188
Richardson, H. W. 137 Saunders, P. 223–6
Rieser, R. 357 Saussure, F. de 209
Ritter, K. 40, 46 Savage, M. 214
Robbins, K. 211 Sayer, A. 34, 137, 199, 217, 219–20, 225–6, 235–7,
Robbins, P. 328 246, 278, 321, 323, 325, 333, 381
Roberts, S. 212 Scargill, D. I. 39
Robic, M.-C. 46 Schaefer, F. K. 60–6, 68–9, 73, 76, 109, 121, 123,
Robinson, A. H. 67, 80, 130, 145, 165 348–9
Robinson, G. M. 283, 363 Schelhaas, B. 38
Robinson, J. 273 Schlemper, M. B. 337
Robinson, J. L. xx Schoenberger, E. 84, 138, 144, 298
Robinson, M. E. 130 Schore, L. F. 114
Robinson, W. S. 152 Schuermans, N. 6, 396
Robson, B. T. 92, 109, 241, 310, 399 Schulten, S. 11, 27, 39, 55, 165, 263, 371
Roche, M. 360 Schuurman, N. 159–60, 162
Rocheleau, D. 299 Schwanen, T. 162
Rodaway, P. 195 Scott, A. J. 137, 145, 203, 212, 252, 351, 358–60,
Roder, W. 126 373, 377
Rodgers, B. 95 Seager, J. 283, 323
Rodríguez-Pose, A. 279 Seamon, D. 179, 186, 195, 232
Rogers, A. xviii, 337 Searle, B. A. 336
Rogerson, P. A. 155 Seemann, J. xx
Rose, C. 189 Semple, E. C. 44, 282, 362, 398
Rose, D. 212, 236 Shannon, G. W. 322
Rose, G. 193, 281, 288–90, 292–3, 298–9, 303, Sharp, J. P. 265, 273, 275, 277, 283
354 Sharrock, W. 15
Rose, J. K. 67 Shaw, M. 342–3
Rossiter, D. J. 150 Shaw, W. 360
Rothenberg, T. Y. 7, 11 Shelton, N. J. 347, 387
Rothstein, J. 115 Shelton, T. 157
Rouhani, F. 301 Sheppard, E. S. xviii, 147, 161, 197, 200–1, 207–8,
Routledge, P. 198, 277 279–80, 295, 351, 361, 388–9
Rowles, G. D. 185 Shevky, E. 92
Rowntree, L. 190, 192 Short, J. R. 34, 203, 345, 387
Ruming, K. 269 Sibley, D. 211, 249
Rupke, N. A. 46 Sidaway, J. D. xiii, 5, 12, 21, 26, 31, 33, 44, 200, 270,
Rushton, G. 131, 136–7, 140, 142, 178 273–4, 298, 346, 354, 371, 377, 389, 395
Russell, A. T. 146 Simmons, I. G. 329
504 Author index

Simon, H. 126–7 Stone, K. H. 37


Simonsen, K. 304 Storper, M. 238, 325
Sinclair, J. C. 114 Stouffer, S. A. 109
Singleton, A. D. 337 Strahler, A. H. 74
Sismondo, S. 397 Strange, C. 44–5
Skupin, A. 158 Subramanian, S. V. 152
Slater, D. 207, 209 Sui, D. Z. 131, 152, 158, 160, 162, 165–6
Slater, T. 337 Sullivan, R. xix
Slater, T. R. 39 Summerfield, M. A. 146
Smailes, A. E. 90–1 Sunley, P. 279, 341
Smallman-Raynor, M. 107 Suppe, F. 346
Smith, A. 237, 395 Svedin, U. 134
Smith, C. T. 92 Sviatlovsky, E. E. 69
Smith, D. M. 127, 138, 141, 194, 197, 201, 203, Swanton, D. 276
206, 223, 229–30, 232, 313–14, 320–2, 324–6, Swartz, D. 21
351, 380, 396, 399 Symanski, R. 6, 53, 78, 80, 251, 310, 347
Smith, G. D. 288
Smith, G.-H. 67 Taaffe, E. J. 69, 75, 84–5, 87, 90, 349, 353
Smith, J. M. 41, 60, 63, 159, 165, 169–70, 260 Tambolo, L. 346
Smith, N. xiii, 12, 197, 214, 222, 226, 236–7, 238, Tapper, T. 32
239–40, 244, 252, 343 Tarrant, J. R. 156
Smith, P. 33 Tatham, G. 44
Smith, R. G. 239, 257, 269, 395 Taylor, E. G. R. 291
Smith, S. J. 109, 183, 186, 213, 336, 343 Taylor, P. J. 6, 21, 27, 38, 80, 82, 116, 128, 145,
Smith, T. R. 141 149–50, 159, 181, 187, 202, 223, 227, 234,
Smith, W. 90–1 237, 238, 265, 273, 324, 332, 336, 348, 351–2,
Soffer, A. 333 357–8, 360, 373–4, 380
Soja, E. W. 206, 221, 242–3, 246–8, 250, 255, 351 Taylor, T. G. 44–5, 54–5
Sorensen, A. D. 230 Tepple, J. H. 195
Sowers, J. 195 Tesch, R. 193
Sparke, M. 238, 288 Tewdwr-Jones, M. 319, 336
Spate, O. H. K. 45, 80, 173 Theodore, N. 339–40
Spedding, N. 394 Thien, D. 270, 298
Spencer, H. 108 Thoman, R. S. 86
Spencer, J. E. 365 Thomas, B. 323
Speth, W. W. 53 Thomas, D. S. 329
Spielman, S. E. 337 Thomas, E. N. 65, 67
Springer, S. 198, 343 Thomas, M. 74
Staeheli, L. A. 199, 288, 304, 344 Thomas, R. W. 107, 115–16
Stafford, H. A. 65 Thomas, W. L. Jr 53, 85, 97
Stamp, L. D. 50, 54, 79–81, 308, 319, 334 Thompson, D’Arcy W. 120
Starrs, P. F. 187 Thompson, J. H. 322
Stave, B. M. 71, 83, 90–1 Thorne, C. R. 321
Stea, D. 130 Thornes, J. B. 149
Steel, R. W. 39, 94, 216, 315 Thrall, G. I. 232
Stegmuller, W. 18, 373 Thrift, N. J. xiv, 12, 110, 133–4, 142, 193, 199,
Steinitz, C. 157 201, 217, 231, 238, 241, 243, 251, 257, 268,
Stevens, A. 308 270–1, 279–80, 351, 359, 373, 382, 398
Stevenson, I. 47, 376 Tickell, A. 211, 237, 288, 359, 367
Stewart, J. Q. 68–9, 108 Tiefelsdorf, M. 147
Stiell, B. 295 Timmermans, H. J. P. 124, 138, 142
Stimson, R. J. 124, 140, 143–4 Timms, D. 90, 92
Stoddart, D. R. 20–1, 29, 39, 43, 47, 49–50, 53, 65, Tivers, J. 233, 283
90–1, 101, 114, 289, 312, 328–9, 347, 351–2, Toal, G. 264–5
355, 357, 375 Tobler, W. R. 71, 74, 76, 108, 148, 156, 163, 165
Author index 505

Tocalis, T. R. 108 Wardenga, U. 38, 47


Tolia-Kelly, D. P. 271, 276 Warf, B. 84, 88, 195, 217, 256, 355
Tomlinson, R. 158, 368 Warntz, W. 68–9, 82, 108
Trewartha, G. T. 312 Warren, K. 94
Trowler, P. 1 Waterman, S. 333
Trudgill, S. T. 328 Waterstone, M. 238
Tuan, Y.-F. 54, 130, 169, 179–81, 183, 345 Watkins, J. W. N. 18
Tullock, G. 9 Watson, J. D. 14
Turner, A. 163 Watson, J. W. 14, 49, 101, 105, 188
Turner, B. L. II 53–4, 87, 126, 191, 308, 327–9, Watson, M. K. 137
370, 396 Watts, H. D. 138
Turner, F. J. 41 Watts, M. 209, 223, 334
Turner, R. K. 329 Weaver, J. C. 67
Webber, M. J. 116–19, 137, 348, 351
Ullman, E. L. 12, 59, 64–5, 69–72, 74, 90, 109, Webber, M. M. 135
121, 366 Weightman, B. 300
Unstead, J. F. 50 Weingart, P. 374
Unwin, A. 153 Wentz, E. 165
Unwin, D. J. 145, 156–8, 383 Werritty, A. G. 120, 394
Unwin, T. xviii, 291, 396 Wescoat, J. L. 330
Upton, G. 145–6 West, G. 2
Urlich-Cloher, D. U. 114 Westwood, D. 288
Urry, J. 214, 221 Whatmore, S. 268–9, 306, 325–6, 331
Wheeler, J. O. 76, 83, 165–6, 348
Vaiou, D. 304 Wheeler, P. B. 354
Vale, T. R. 43 White, G. F. 75, 100, 126–7, 312, 330–1
Valentine, G. 195, 286, 295, 300–1, 306, 322, 326 White, P. E. 187–8
van den Daele, W. 374 White, R. 100, 130
van der Laan, L. 231 Whitehand, J. W. R. 6, 90–1, 96, 377, 395–6
van der Wusten, H. 331 Whitelegg, J. 230
Van Hoven, B. 288 Whittlesey, D. 48, 54
Van Paassen, C. 133 Wigen, K. 265
Van Valkenburg, S. 69 Wilbanks, T. J. 368, 369–70
Van Weesep, J. 34 Wilbert, C. 306
Vance, J. E. 96 Williams, F. E. 69
Varlyguin, D. 370 Williams, M. 53, 97, 328, 364–5
Velikonja, J. 71–2, 74 Williams, P. R. 224–6
Vidal de la Blache, P. 46, 49, 176, 186, 190, 348, Williams, W. M. 81, 92
381 Williamson, P. 117
von Bertalanffy, L. 119 Willmott, C. J. xiv, 52, 63, 380, 384
von Humboldt, A. 40, 43, 45–7, 399 Wills, J. 193, 197–8, 212, 237–8, 243, 273, 287,
344
Wagner, P. L. 87 Wilson, A. G. 26, 108, 110, 115–17, 119, 121,
Wainwright, E. 9 145–6, 149, 154, 162, 240, 308,
Wainwright, J. 211, 275 319–20, 335
Wakefield, J. 152 Wilson, E. O. 312
Walby, S. 292 Wilson, W. 41
Walford, R. 41, 258, 372 Wilton, R. 304
Walker, R. A. 199, 203, 236 Winchester, H. P. M. 288
Walmsley, D. J. 119–20, 182, 230 Winter, C. 276
Walton, J. 293 Wise, M. J. 39, 43, 51, 345
Ward, D. 95 Wisner, B. 200, 269
Ward, K. 7–8, 217, 291, 343 Withers, C. W. J. xix, 10, 38–40, 55, 88, 380, 394–5
Ward, M. D. 152 Wohlenberg, E. H. 203, 322
Ward, R. 367 Woldenberg, M. J. 94, 119
506 Author index

Wolf, L. G. 32, 228 Wylie, J. 269


Wolman, M. G. 84–5 Wyly, E. 203, 233–4
Wolpert, J. 107, 127–9, 172, 333
Woods, M. 344 Yang, C. 168
Woods, R. I. 120 Yeates, M. H. 74–5, 314, 365
Woodward, K. 280 Yeung, H.W.C. 6, 199, 395
Wooldridge, S. W. 50, 52, 54, 129 Yule, G. U. 150
Woolgar, S. 14
Wright, A. 211–12 Zahorchak, G. A. 67
Wright, D. J. 340 Zelinsky, W. 97, 283, 285, 309–10, 312, 314, 348
Wright, J. K. 39, 44, 171–4, 362 Zhan, F. B. 7, 35, 388
Wright, R. 12, 368 Zimmerer, K. S. xix
Wrigley, E. A. 91–2, 146 Zimmerman, E. W. 222
Wrigley, N. 138, 145–6, 150, 157, 166, 232, 335, Zipf, G. K. 108
341, 372, 395 Zolnik, E. J. 162
Subject index

Aberdeen University 394 American Academy of Arts and Sciences 8, 11


abstract geographies 105–6 American Air Force Research and Development
abstractions 220, 225, 230, 312, 342 110
academic communities and subcommunities 14–16, American Geographical Society 39, 41, 69, 308
19, 23, 26 American Geography: Inventory and Prospect (James and
in changing discipline 353, 357–9, 361, 364, Jones) 54
366, 376, 388, 397–9 American National Academy 85
academic disciplines 1–36 American Society for Professional Geographers
academic life 2–9 12
academic work 4–7 Analytical Behavioural Geography (Golledge and Stimson)
career structure 2–4, 3 143
contemporary situation 32–5 analytical research 140–2
disciplines and institutionalisation 9–12 anarchy 342–3, 394, 399
external environment 26–35 Anglo-American hegemony 376–7
frames and interpretations (Bourdieu and anglophone hegemony 305
Foucault) 21–3 Annals of the Association of American Geographers 47, 59, 61,
and gender 290–1 83, 85, 320, 332
geographers, Kuhn and contexts 25–6 Annals of GIS 163
Kuhnian model 15–21 Anthropogeographie (Ratzel) 46
patronage (appointment and promotion) 7–8 anthropology 53, 96–7, 209, 249
policies 320–1 anticapitalism 30
rewards and sources of status 8–9 Antipode 201, 203–4, 226, 237–8, 283, 292, 313,
social sciences (daily life, texts and authority) 344
23–5 anti-racist geography 275–7
working environment (disciplines and division of anti-war movements 30
labour) 12–15 applied geography 232–4, 308–44, 357, 369,
academic division of labour 11–15, 85–8, 177 371–2, 381, 385
gendered 282–3, 288, 291 changing contexts 336–40
academic influence 362–6, 373–5, 386 debates 340–3
academic journals 6, 10–11, 23, 33–4, 43, 83, 163, disillusion in academic geography 310–13
238, 309, 335–6, 376 environmentalism 326–32
academic values 13–14 inequality, justice and ethics 325–6
Academy of the Social Sciences 8 liberal contributions 319–25
accountability 33, 385, 387 mapping welfare 321–3
activism 196, 198, 230, 237, 239, 276, 314, 341, place of 337–40
382 policy and geographers 332–6
actor-network theory 268–71, 361, 364, 397 relevance 313–18
administration 4–9 understanding 323–5
affect 268–71, 276, 297 Applied Geography 328, 331, 334
Africa Geographic 11 appointment and promotion 2–5, 7–8
agency 134, 220, 225, 230–1, 244–5, 362 Approaching Human Geography (Cloke) 292
aggregate data 152 archaeology 95
allometry 120 The Archaeology of Knowledge (Foucault) 22
508 Subject index

Area 227, 313 Cambridge University 43, 52, 91, 93, 101, 104,
areal differentiation 47–8, 62, 71, 378, 390 149, 272
art of geography 96, 98, 102, 169–70, 270 Canada 272, 319
artefact/construct paradigms 19 Canadian Geographic 11
Artificial Intelligence 141–2, 150–1 Canterbury University, New Zealand 75
assessment capitalism
of individual abilities 5, 7 applied geography 317, 324
of research 33–4, 321 changing discipline 358
Association of American Geographers 8, 12, 47, feminism 286, 293–5, 301
54–5, 59, 83, 87, 158, 200, 300, 308, new regional geography 217
310, 312–14, 320, 327, 332, 340, 367, post-communist contexts 235–9
369–70, 383–4, 388 postmodernism 244, 252, 254
Association of Professional Geographers 55 production of nature 222
Australia 9, 45, 183, 319, 321, 368 radical debates 223–5, 227–8, 230–1, 233–4
authority issues 250, 256, 299, 390 radical geography 199, 203–12, 217, 222–37
autobiographical theme 360–1, 365, 399 radical trajectories 203, 205–7
awards 8 regulation theory 211–12
structuralist Marxisms 207, 209
Behavior and Location (Pred) 135 career structure 2–4, 3, 4–5, 7–9, 375
behavioural environments 172–3, 335–6 cartography 157–8, 369–71
behavioural geography 124–45 deconstructing maps 262–5
applied 310 and descriptive mathematics 73
changing discipline 363, 380 map interpretation 48, 65, 67, 165
cultural turn 245 technical developments 156, 319–21
humanistic 169, 172, 182, 185, 194 see also Geographical Information Systems (GIS)
methods 135–40, 136 cascading systems 111, 112
radical 234–5 catallaxy 236
spatial science 104, 107, 124–31, 133, 135–40, catastrophe theory 149
136, 138, 139, 140–5, 143 categorical data modelling 146
understanding and explanation 139, 140–5, 143 causal relationships 112, 152, 220, 227, 320,
behavioural location theory 136–7 326–7
behavioural matrix 135, 136 see also determinism
Berkeley school 40, 53–4, 97, 192, 246, 362, 365, census statistics 319
377–8 Center for Geographical Analysis 368
Beveridge Report 29 central place theory 72, 74–5, 107, 122, 125, 135,
biased-coefficients problem 148 388
binary oppositions 268–9, 398 changing contexts
biobibliographical essays 395 applied geography 336–40
biography approach 246, 260, 323, 360, 364–5 changing discipline 345–99
body/embodiment 296, 300–1 1950s to 21st century 378–89
botany 53 critiques of Kuhnian model 349–55
boundaries environment of geography 355–60, 357
disciplinary 12, 15, 287, 289 future prospects 398–9
social 302 generational model 373–5
boundary-drawing 265 geographers and their networks 360–4
bounded spaces 105–6 geographies of geography 375–8
braided streams metaphor 392 human geographers and models of disciplinary
Bristol University 147, 149, 335 progress 346–55
British Academy 8, 11, 337, 388 human geography’s response to challenges
British Admiralty Handbooks 43 366–73
British Columbia University 272 map of 393
The British Isles (Stamp and Beaver) 51, 79 paradigms, streams, traditions 378–89
bureaucracies 9 structure of geography 364–6
The Business of People (Campaign for the Social Sciences) turbulence 389–98, 392–3
337 Changing Urban and Regional System 212–14
Subject index 509

Chicago school 53, 75, 89, 92, 108–9, 126, 186, antecedents 171–4
250–1, 362, 365, 367, 378 old and new 189–94
chorological science, geography as 63 postmodernist turns 244–6
chronological paradigm 348 systematic studies 95–8
citation counts/indices 6, 365, 395–7 cultural turn 243–6, 254, 271, 278–80, 294,
Cities in Civilization (Hall) 336 303, 344, 359, 383
citizenship 213, 301, 331 cyberspaces 268
civil/human rights 30, 200, 309, 334
Clark University 201, 282, 378 data handling 108–9, 145–7, 152, 165
class issues 202–3, 206, 212, 223–4, 229, 293, technical developments 319–20
295, 318 decentralisation 34
closed systems 111 decision-making
Closet Space (Brown) 303 applied geography 338
codes of practice 334 assumption of preferences 201–2
cognitive mapping 130–1 choice sets 138–40, 139
Cold War 28, 74, 110 humanistic geography 173–4, 185
collectivism 299 irrational/rational 18, 73
The Colonial Present (Gregory) 275, 343, 359 mental maps 129–31
colonial trend 41, 43 spatial science 103–4, 124–31, 135–40, 139
colonialism 39, 272–3, 275, 277 theories 320
Columbia University 367 decolonisation 274–5
commercial contracts 309–10, 335, 337 deconstruction 259–60, 290, 295, 297
Commission on College Geography (AAG) 327 maps 262–5
commodity flows 109 departmental competition 378, 388
community perspective 322–3 departmental heads 9
A Companion to Feminist Geography (Nelson and Seager) description 79, 96, 179, 260, 319, 323
283 determinism 61, 63, 121, 260, 348, 363
Complex Locations:Women’s Geographical Work in the UK environmental 43–5, 53, 55, 81, 97, 222, 275,
1850–1970 (Maddrell) 290–1 362
complexity 249, 253 development geography 223
computer mapping 156 dialectic processes 209–10, 217, 229, 254
The Conceptual Revolution in Geography (Davies) 347 dialectic theorizing 224
The Condition of Postmodernity (Harvey) 226, 252–5 dialectical reproduction 231
conformity 386 The Dictionary of Human Geography (Pratt) 285–6
connectivity 106–7 difference 250, 253–6, 277, 279, 285–6, 305, 390
conservation 54, 327 diffusion patterns 148–9
constructivism 249 diffusion processes 107–8, 138
consultancy work 315 digital mapping 321
consumption 257 dioramas 132–3
context of geography 355–60, 357, 373 direction 106–7
contextual approaches 175, 215, 221, 244, 258, disability issues 304
269, 284, 296, 336, 378 disaster response 330
continuous space 105–6 disciplinary boundaries 13
control systems 112, 114–15 disciplinary content, changing 14–15
corporate sponsorship 334–5 disciplinary matrices 379–81, 383, 388–9, 391,
counter-culture 200 394, 396–7
Crime, Space and Society (Smith) 343 disciplinary progress models 346–55
critical geography 234, 237–9, 272, 278, 344 discourses 22, 258–9
critical geopolitics 198, 233, 262–5 distance 105–9
critical rationalism 80 and time 131–2, 134
critical realism 155, 198–9, 219–21 distance-decay effects 325
cross-sectional laws 82 distributive justice 325
cultural ecology 329 diversity 245, 249, 251, 256, 285–8, 303
cultural geography 53, 95–8, 171–3, 195, 237–8, division of knowledge 235–6, 376
243, 245, 301, 328, 373, 377 ‘Doing fieldwork’ (DeLyser and Starrs) 186–7
510 Subject index

Domesday Book project 158 environment of geography


dominant paradigms 278, 351, 378, 399 changing discipline 355–60, 357
Dundee University 394 Environmental Change Centre, Oxford 329
Durham University 158, 335 environmental determinism 43–5, 53, 55, 81, 97,
dynamic laws/processes 82, 118–19 222, 275, 362
environmental influences 311–12
Earth Summit, 1992 Rio de Janeiro 329 environmental issues 126–7, 256, 315, 327, 331,
The Earth as Transformed by Human Action 335
Symposium (1990) 329 environmentalism in applied geography 326–32
Eastern Europe 235–7 epoch in postmodernism 248
ecofeminism 296 equilibrium laws 82
ecological inference 149–52 ESRI conferences 340
ecological society 331 essences 179, 184
eco-Marxist human geography 223 ethics 195, 325–6, 334
economic depression 27–9, 336, 367 Ethics, Place and Environment 195, 326
economic geography ethnocentrism 262, 271, 275–8
applied geography 324 ethnography 186, 193–4, 299, 390
changing discipline 358–9, 361, 364 evaluation
feminist geographies 301 of policies 320, 324, 333, 339, 341
postmodernism 245, 279–80 of practice 288
radical geography 212, 229 evolutionary views 43–4, 50
systematic studies 66, 69, 72–3, 75, 82–4, 92 exceptionalism 60–1, 378
Economic Geography 83 exemplars 379–81, 388–9, 394, 396–7
economic restructuring 213 existentialism 184–5
Economic and Social Research Council 94, 158, 212, Expeditions Advisory Service 334
367, 388 Experimental Cartography Unit, London 158
economism 230 Explanation in Geography (Harvey) 77, 105, 205, 232
ecosystems 114–15 explanations 60–1, 77–80, 82–3, 179, 230, 342
Edinburgh University 158, 315, 335, 394 exploration 42–3, 290
education 317, 357, 366, 368, 377 exploratory data analysis 146
educational trend (geographical literature) 41 extensibility 134
efficiency and distance 103 external environment (academic disciplines) 26–35,
electoral geography 118, 146, 149–50, 215, 319, 356, 373–5, 383
324
emancipatory approach 266, 273, 279, 284, 343–4 factorial ecology 89–90, 321–2
empathy 181–2, 323 feedback 112, 113
empiricism 249, 273, 296, 313, 316, 320–1, 334, Feminism and Geography (Rose) 290
342, 344, 378, 383, 389, 391 Feminisms in Geography (Moss and Al-Hindi) 283
feminist geography 293, 295 feminist critiques 226, 241, 254–5, 272
humanistic geography 182–3, 188, 190 feminist empiricism 296
radical geography 214, 216–17, 225, 230–1, feminist geographies 243, 276, 281–307, 383, 392
234–5 of difference 285–6, 287
spatial science 120–1, 124, 155 diverse strands 285–8, 287
systematic studies 64, 73, 78, 82 geographies of difference 296–9
employment opportunities 163, 227, 282, 309, queering geography 302–4
370, 373, 387 reassessing histories of geography 288–92
encyclopaedic trend (geographical literature) 41, 43 sexuality and space 300–1
The End of Capitalism (Gibson-Graham) 286–7 socialist feminisms 292–6
end of history 236 A Feminist Glossary of Human Geography (McDowell and
The Endgame of Globalization (Smith) 343 Sharp) 283
Enlightenment 45, 255, 351, 380–3, 390 feminist standpoint theory 296
entropy 116–17 Festival International de Géographie 8
entropy-maximising models 117–18 field theory 89
Environment and Behavior 130 fieldwork 49, 186–7, 298
Environment and Planning 110, 212, 304 financial crises 32, 203, 320, 387
Subject index 511

the first law 165 Geographical Information Systems (GIS) 86, 101,
Flood Hazard Research Centre 335 262–4, 275, 299
flow data 108–9 applied geography 309, 319, 331, 337–8, 340
flow patterns 116–17, 155 changing discipline 364, 368–71, 377, 382
Fontana Mix (Cage) 270 responses to 159–62
forecasting 109–10, 113, 118–19, 147–8, 311 spatial science 157–67
formal regions 48, 59 The Geographical Journal 331
foundations of geography 37–56 geographical literature trends 40–3
1950s 54–5 geographical mind/imagination 175–6
American 47–9 Geographical Positional Systems 159
British 49–52 The Geographical Review 83, 186
historical geography 52–4 Geographical Thought (Nayak and Jeffrey) 284
modern period (geography) 38–42 The Geographical Tradition (Livingstone) 291, 354, 356
modern period (paradigms) 42–52 Geographically Weighted Regression 153
foundations of science 311 Géographie Universelle (Vidal) 46
fractals 120 geographies of difference 296–9
fragmentation 166, 236, 245, 250, 254, 274, geographies of geography 375–8
383–4, 389 Geographies of Global Change (Johnston, Taylor and Watts)
frames and interpretations 21–3 332
France 211, 257, 267, 273, 376 geographies of governance 211
French Annales school of history 45–6 Geographies of Muslim Women (Falah and Nagel) 305
Frontiers in Geographical Teaching (Chorley and Haggett) Geographies of Postcolonialism (Sharp) 275
63, 91–3 geographies of production 212
Full Circles: Geographies of Women (Katz and Monk) 283 geographism 185
functional magnetic resonance imaging 144 Geography and Gender (WGSG) 281
functional regions 51, 59, 72 Geography and Social Justice (Smith) 325
funding 27, 31–4, 201, 321, 336, 367, 371–3, Geography as a Fundamental Research Discipline
387–8 (Ackerman) 76
‘The future for new geographers’ survey 387 Geography in America (Gaile and Willmott) 63
future prospects of academic discipline 398–9 Geography in the Twentieth Century (Taylor) 54–5
fuzzy set logic 157 geography matrix 88, 88–90
‘Geography matters’ (Massey) 212
game theory 137 geography of crime 227, 322
Gazetteer of the World (Chisholm) 43 geography of women 286, 287
gender inequality approaches 292–4 geoinformatics 156
gender issues 245, 254, 272, 282, 291, 304–5 geometry 73–4, 94, 102, 104–5, 120–3, 155
Gender, Place and Culture 281, 304–5 geomorphology 51–2, 62, 180, 349
Gender Space and Culture 283 geopolitics 44, 193, 206, 223, 254, 264, 271, 332,
generalisations 43–4, 46, 58, 77–80, 140–1, 173, 343
175–6, 185, 379 geosophy 171, 174
generalising trend (geographical literature) 41 German intellectual tradition 38, 40–1, 43–7, 376
generational model 373–5, 382–3 German universities 38, 40
gentrification 203, 301 ghettoes 228
geocomputation 155–7 GISRUK conferences 340
geodemographics 311, 335 Global Environmental Change 331
Geoforum 298 global environmental policies 329
‘Geographers on film’ interviews 395 global geographies 235
Geographical Analysis 76, 83, 167 globalisation 237, 244, 251, 305, 359, 377
Geographical Analysis Machine 152–3 Globalization and World Cities Study Group and
Geographical Association 41, 91, 371–2, 377 Network 237
geographical canon 398–9 GMap company 335
Geographical Imaginations (Gregory) 178–9, 272, Good Cities: Better Lives (Hall) 336
356 Google Scholar 6
Geographical Information Science (GISci) 88, 101, Graduate School of Design 69, 158
162–6 grand theory critiques 249–50, 295
512 Subject index

graph theory 73 humanities 180, 191, 196, 252, 280, 355


gravity model 108–10, 116–17, 121–2, 147, 153, human–nature relations 268–9, 293, 326
261 hybrid geographies 268, 377, 394–5
Green movement 200 The Hydrological Cycle (Tuan) 54
‘Grey geography?’ (Peck) 340
growth syndrome 310–11 iconography 191
ideal type cores 151
Handbook of Commercial Geography (Chisholm) 43, 51 idealist method 175, 177–8
Harvard University 41, 69, 158, 366–8 identity politics 277, 284, 286, 296, 300, 302, 344
hermeneutics 189, 261 image of geography 341–3, 349, 356, 366
heteronormative geographical knowledge 301–3 immature/mature science 25–6, 368
heuristics 354 impact agenda 337, 344, 367, 388
hierarchicalization of space 262 The Impact of the Social Sciences (Bastow) 337
Histoire de la France (Vidal) 46 imperialism 222, 228, 271, 273, 275, 277, 289–90
historical geography 52–4, 92, 95–8, 171–5, 178, ‘The inadequacy of the regional concept’ (Kimble)
180, 216, 245, 318, 365, 377 58
historicism 246–7 indeterminacy 92
historicity of nature 222–3 industrial geography 212
historicogeographical materialism 221 inequalities 29–31
histories of geography 350, 353, 356, 359–60, 364, applied geography 309, 313–14, 322–6, 335,
366, 394 341
reassessment 288–92 gender 284–6
history and geography 175–6, 187 radical geography 201, 228, 232, 237
holism 230 Influences of Geographic Environment (Semple) 44, 362
home/away and insider/outsider perspectives information gathering and synthesis 319
188 information theory 116, 128
homeostatic systems 112–14 infrastructure and superstructure 230–1
horizontal interdependence 101 innovation 362–3, 365, 374–5
The Human Consequences of Urbanisation (Berry) 228 inscapes 181
Human Environmental Sciences Section (NAS) Institute for Retail Studies 335
327 Institute for Scientific Information (ISI) 6
human geographers Institute of British Geographers 8, 90–1, 191, 193,
models of disciplinary progress 346–55 281, 306, 312, 315–16, 337, 371
Human Geography and Planning Committee institutionalisation and disciplines 9–12, 357, 368
94–5 instrumentalism 124, 142
Human Geography: Coming of Age (Zelinsky) 348 intelligence services 43, 291
human geography’s response to challenges 366–73 interactionism 140, 186
human system modelling 157 interdependence 115
human–environment relations 221, 241, 270, interdisciplinary links 11, 53, 76, 120, 130, 227,
327–9 333
human–environment systems 114–15, 121, 127, International Boundaries Research Unit 335
136 International Boundary Studies Series 335
humanistic geography 169–96 International Critical Geography Group 238
applied geography 331, 336 international financial links of South East England
changing discipline 358, 380–1, 383 218
cultural geography 189–94 International Geographical Union 8
historical and cultural geography 171–4 Commission on Quantitative Methods 84
phenomenology 179–86 international journals 376
positivism 175–9 International Journal of Geographical Information Science 163
postmodernism 245, 278 International Journal of Geographical Information Systems 158
practice 186–9 International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 202
radical geography 232–3 International Sociological Association 202
spatial science 174 intersubjectivity 245
‘Humanistic thought and poetic geographies’ intertextuality 258
(Hubbard) 194 interventionism 338
Subject index 513

intradisciplinary politics/contestation 23–5 Lévi-Strauss cam-shaft for structuralism


invisible college notion 16, 172, 374 (geographical interpretation) 210
Iowa school 65–7, 362 liberalisation 31
irony 260 liberalism 201, 227–34, 309, 312, 319–25, 330–1
Ivy League universities 12 liberation ecologies 223
lifeworld 182–3
Joint Matriculation Board 91 The Limits to Capital (Harvey) 206, 235
Journal of Geography in Higher Education 371 The Limits to Growth (Meadows) 328
Journal of Historical Geography 389 Limits to Growth study 221
journals see academic journals linear programming 72
justice 237, 314, 325–6 literature and geography 180, 187–8, 247–8,
261–2, 299, 305–6
Kentucky University 320 Liverpool University 39
Keynesian principles 31 lobby groups 10–11, 377
knowledge Local Government Boundary Commission 313
circulation of 361 local knowledge 361–2
commodification of 355 local statistics 153–4
constructed 297 localities research programme 212–15, 247, 269,
contexts 26–31 293
production 10, 13, 16, 21–2, 255, 273, 296, localized geometry 250
318, 354, 361–2 location analysis 66–7, 69–70, 73–4, 104
situated 286, 297, 361 location theory 66, 71–2, 75, 83, 85–6, 104,
Kosmos (von Humboldt) 46 108–9, 148, 154, 162
Kuhnian model Locational Analysis in Human Geography (Haggett) 101
academic disciplines 15–21 location-allocation models 335
changing discipline 346–54, 359, 375, 378–9, London School of Economics 91
389, 394–7 lone scholars 364–5
critiques 18–21, 349–55 Los Angeles school 242, 250–1, 361, 365
Lowry model 109–10, 115
Laboratory for Computer Graphics and Spatial
Analysis 69, 158 macrogeography 69, 75, 82–3, 116–18
labour geographies 212 Madison University 378
labour markets 337–8, 370–1, 387 male gaze 296
Lancaster University 94 Man and Nature (Marsh) 54
The Land of Britain (Stamp) 51 managerial approach 202
Land Utilisation Survey of Britain 51, 319 Man’s Role in Changing the Face of the Earth
landform development 43, 62 (symposium) 53, 327
landscape 245, 296, 348 map interpretation 48, 65, 67, 165
modification 223, 327 Mapping Desire (Bell and Valentine) 300–1
of postmodernity 251, 256, 258 Maps of Meaning (Jackson) 192
land-use decisions 125–7, 319–20 marginalisation of geography 94, 367–8, 372
see also planning issues marketisation 31–5, 232, 236, 244, 319, 335,
land-use mapping 48, 51, 71 338–9
language issues 249, 257–8, 260, 354 Markov Chain Monte Carlo methods 152
sexism 283, 303, 307 Marxism
law-seeking 60–6, 69, 74, 77–8, 81–2, 155, 176, applied geography 312, 314, 317–18, 339
232 changing discipline 351, 381–3, 389, 391
and law-applying 175, 177 feminist geographies 284, 286, 293, 295, 299,
league tables 34 301
learned societies 10–12, 23, 39, 164, 312, postmodern geography 244–5, 251–2, 254–5,
337 265, 269, 278
least effort principle 108 radical debates 223–6, 228–34
Leeds University 109–10, 157, 335 radical geography 198–201, 203–11, 219, 221,
left-wing approaches 31, 199–201, 238 223–6, 228–31, 234–41
level-of-living concept 322 structuralist 207–11, 209–10
514 Subject index

Marxist humanism 134 National Academy of Sciences 8, 327


masculinism 290, 297 Committee on Science and Public Policy 86–7
masculinities 288, 291, 296, 299, 303 National Academy of Sciences-National Research
Mathematical Methods in Human Geography and Planning Council 77, 85, 95, 163, 369, 385
(Wilson and Bennett) 146 National Defense Education Act 75
mathematics 79, 154 National Flood Insurance Program 330
see also geometry; quantitative geography National Geographic 11, 43
meaning 172, 179, 181–4, 186–90 National Geographic Society 39, 43, 87
construction of 256, 258–9, 263, 271 National Health Service 29
systems 245 national interests 358
mechanism paradigm 391 National Research Council 34, 87–8, 159, 163, 165
mental maps 129–31 National Science Foundation 87, 367
mergers and closures of geography departments natural sciences 15, 21, 23–6, 29–30, 69, 124, 219,
367–9 233, 249, 296, 311, 329
meta-narratives 225, 253, 261 naturalism 249
metaparadigms 19 nature as social construction 222, 331
metaphors 258–61, 306 The Nature of Change in Geographical Ideas (Berry) 348
meta-theories 225 The Nature of Geography (Hartshorne) 47, 61
methodological shifts 379 nature, production of 221–3
Methods and Techniques in Human Geography (Robinson) see also human–nature relations
283 Nazism 44, 74
metonymy 260–1 neogeography 320
metropolitan theory 273 neoliberalism 31, 206–7, 218, 228, 237–8, 319,
Michigan Inter-University Community of 337, 339, 359, 367, 387
Mathematical Geographers 76 the Netherlands 376
Michigan State University 76, 367 networks 360–6, 376, 388, 397–8
micro-geography 173 neutrality 332–3
Middlesex University 335 new cultural geography 245–6
migrations 107–8, 114, 129, 188, 202–3, 301 New Deal 27
militarisation 275 new geography 75, 77, 91, 169–71, 347
mimesis 260–1 The New Imperialism (Harvey) 343
Minneapolis University 361 New Mappings Collaboratory 320
Minnesota University 105, 361 new regional geography 215–19, 218, 247
mobility 294 The New Science of Cities (Batty) 155
model-based paradigm 347 New Words, New Worlds (Philo) 245
modelling and analytical techniques 146–7, 318 New Zealand 26, 319, 321, 327
Models in Geography (Chorley and Haggett) 63, 93–5, New Zealand Geographic 11, 43
99, 318, 347 New Zealand Geographical Society 312
Modern Geographical Thought (Peet) 292, 298 nineteenth-century contexts 38–9, 42, 289–90
modern period 38–52 nodal regions analysis 101
modernism 249–54, 257, 390 nomological geography 234
modifiable areal unit problem 149–52 nomothetic philosophy 60–4, 100, 121
moral geographies 325–6 non-representational theories 268–71, 298
morphogenetic systems 112–14 non-universalism 249
morphological laws/systems 61, 64–6, 72, 111, normal science 16–17, 19–20, 23, 25–6, 348,
112 350–2, 373–4, 378, 397
Morphology of Landscape (Sauer) 97 norms 13–14, 16
The Morphology of Landscape (Sauer) 110 Northern Ireland turmoil 309
movement patterns 101 Northwestern University 75, 363, 367
multiculturalism 272 nuclear weapons and power 331
multi-level modelling 153
multi-paradigm situation 394 objectivity 180, 232, 262, 299, 332–3
multiple determination 211 occupational structure 2–9
multivariate statistical analyses 156 occupational trajectory 370
multivocality 390 Office of Strategic Services 74
Subject index 515

Ogoniland controversy 334 political contexts 26–35, 236–7, 284


On Growth and Form (D’Arcy Thompson) 120 political economy 199, 235–7, 290
On the Origin of Species (Darwin) 43 political-economy approach 201, 237
order/disorder 249, 263, 347, 388 political geography 41, 211–12, 223, 266–7, 316,
and power 266–7 318, 328
and welfare 104–5 polyphonic approach 264
Ordnance Survey 319 population geography 108, 120–1, 301, 321, 326–7
organic paradigm 347, 391 positionality 272, 298, 307
Orientalism (Said) 273, 275 positivism
otherness 254, 273, 299 applied geography 311–12, 317–18, 320–1, 334,
Overseas Development Administration 315 342
Oxford University 41–3, 329 changing discipline 379–81, 383, 389, 391
critics and defenders 175–9
Panel on Environmental Education (AAG) 327 feminist geography 297, 299, 301
paradigms humanistic geography 169–71, 173, 175–6,
academic discipline 15–19, 21, 25 178–9, 181–5, 193
changing discipline 346, 348–50, 352–3, 373–4, radical geography 217, 219, 224, 230–1, 234–5
378–89, 392–3, 397 spatial science 124, 130, 133, 138, 140–3,
humanistic geography 177, 195 153–4
paradigm shift process 395–6 systematic studies 60, 63, 65, 76, 78–80, 83, 85,
parochialism 273 90–1, 96
participatory geographies 186, 320, 343–4 possibilism 46, 81, 348
Participatory Geographies Research Group 343 post-9/11 context 206, 271, 320, 332, 341
particularities 225, 249–50 postcolonialism 243, 271–8
patriarchal values 288–90, 293–5, 297 post-communist contexts 31, 235–9
patronage (appointment and promotion) 7–8 post-Marxist geographers 239, 241, 257
peace studies 331 postmodern feminism 296–7
Pennsylvania University 71, 104, 367 Postmodern Geographies (Soja) 243
People’s Geography Project 237 postmodern geography 303
perceived environments 174, 182 Postmodern Geography (Minca) 243
performance 270–1, 302 ‘Postmodern urbanism’ (Dear) 250
personal boundaries 134 postmodernism 239, 242–57, 278–80, 312, 390–1
Personal Finance Research Centre 335 definitions 246–51
Perspective on the Nature of Geography (Hartshorne) 62–3 posts- and turns 242–6
Perspectives on Environment (Manners and Mikesell) 327 time–space compression and landscapes 251–7,
phenomenology 179–86, 246, 249, 271 253
philosophical realism 198 see also postcolonialism; poststructuralism
philosophical shifts 379 postmodernist method 248
Philosophy and Geography 195, 326 Poststructural Geographies (Doel) 265–6
physical geography 51–2, 84–5, 91, 94, 102, poststructuralism 239, 251, 257–71, 279–80, 286,
114–15, 122, 156, 315, 328, 331, 378, 383
385 actor-network theory 268–71, 361, 364, 397
Place and Placelessness (Relph) 183 affect 268–71, 276, 297
The Place of Geography (Unwin) 291 deconstructing maps and critical geopolitics
place perspectives 181, 215, 247, 256 262–5
see also central place theory geography of 257–62
planetary approach 274 non-representational theories 268–71, 298
planning 49, 109–10, 186, 201–3, 319–20, 332, poststructuralist geographies 243, 265–8, 303
336 Post-structuralist Geography (Murdoch) 267
pluralism 234, 238, 240–1, 246, 265, 348, 382 postwar context 28–9, 37–8, 44, 308–9
point/line pattern analysis 72–3, 145, 152 post-welfarism 337–40
policy appraisal 320, 324, 333, 339, 341 poverty 206, 222, 322
policy and geographers 229, 313–15, 323–4, 332–6 The Power of Place (Agnew and Duncan) 215
policy research 340–1, 343 power relations 257, 261–5, 267, 270, 277–8, 282,
policy-making 239, 316, 324, 332 284, 313, 323–4
516 Subject index

pragmatism 186, 309, 330, 344 structuralist Marxisms 207–11, 209–10


prediction 78, 80, 124–5, 148, 176, 221 trajectories 201–7
Princeton University 68, 108 Rangoon University 50
‘The problem of geographic description’ (Darby) rankings 386–7, 396
247 rank-ordering procedures 129–30
problem solving 15–18, 72–3, 333, 336 Reaganism 339
process laws/theories 61, 64, 105, 121 realism 133, 153, 219–21, 224–6, 234, 240, 333,
process-response systems 112, 114, 118–19 381, 391
product cycle notion 355 Rebel Cities (Harvey) 318
production of nature 221–3 Recent Developments in Spatial Data Analysis (Bahrenberg)
production of space 221 145
The Professional Geographer 88, 160, 276, 282, 298–9, Rediscovering Geography Committee 369
369–70 Rediscovering Geography (NAS-NRC) 163–4
professionalisation 9, 163, 363 reductionism 142, 226, 255
Progress in Human Geography 237 reformism 230
progress notions 345–6, 380, 382, 394 regional analysis 145–6
disciplinary progress models 346–55 regional autonomy/devolution 218
protest 309 regional development 319
protopostmodern urbanism 251 regional geography 54–5, 180, 234, 349, 378–9,
psychoanalysis 209, 270, 286, 297 391, 396
psychology 181 critical responses and debate 58–9
public geographies 343–4 critique of 58–9
public policy 312, 315, 337, 341–2 foundations of contemporary geography 45–7
public sector 335, 388 new 215–19, 218
publication 5–7, 33–4, 343, 364–5, 396 systematic studies 58–9, 95, 97–8
Regional Research Laboratories 158
qualitative methods 244, 279, 298 regional science 83–4
quantitative geography 155, 229, 232–4, 299, 307, Regional Science Association 84
313, 321, 338, 342, 347, 361, 371, 379, Regional Studies 110, 145
383, 388, 399 regionalisations 149–50
Quantitative Geography (Wrigley and Bennett) 166 regions, delineation of 50–1, 58
quantitative methods 67, 74–5, 77, 79, 81–4, 95–6, regression methods 147–8, 153
138, 145, 154, 185, 298 regularities and laws 68–9, 108, 176
quantitative revolution 85–8, 388 regulation theory 211–12, 217, 219–20, 293
queer theory 302–4 reification 231, 278
relativism 249, 251, 257, 342
race issues 30, 44, 228, 263, 295 relevance 230, 308, 310, 312–18, 333–4, 337,
anti-racist geography 275–7 340–2, 344, 367, 371–2, 381
ethnocentrism 262, 271, 275–8 remote sensing 156, 321, 369–70
racism 272, 275, 277 representation issues 257–9, 261–4, 269, 272–3,
‘Race, racism and geography’ (The Professional 296
Geographer) 276–7 see also non-representational theories (NRTs)
radical geography 192, 197–241, 272 reputation 386–7
applied geography 309–10, 312, 344 research 4–7, 13, 312
changing discipline 358, 381, 396 analytical 140–2
critical realism and structuration theory 219–21 assessment 33–4, 321, 337, 364, 387–8
left-wing approaches 199–201 commercial 309–10, 335, 337
liberals, radicals, post-marxists in debate community 322–3
227–34 influences on 321
nature, production of 221–3 Kuhnian model (paradigms and revolutions)
new regional geography 215–19, 218 15–18
post-communist contexts 235–9 localities programme 212–15, 247, 269, 293
radicals in debate 223–7 Marxist 244
regulation theory 211–12 militarisation of 27–8
spatial divisions of labour, localities 212–15 policy 340–1, 343
Subject index 517

UK authorities 94, 158, 212, 321, 337, 364, 367, signification 259–60, 264
388 situationism 255, 258, 274, 297
US authorities 34, 77, 85, 87–8, 95, 159, 163, ‘skepticism’ 347
165, 369, 385 Social and Cultural Geography Study Group 191
Research Assessment Exercises 33–4, 321 social and cultural theory 286
research contracts 309–10, 335, 337 social anthropology 210–11
Research Councils 33, 86, 95, 149, 367 social democracy 338–9
UK 94, 158, 212, 321, 337, 364, 367, 388 social division of labour 236
US 34, 77, 85, 87–8, 95, 159, 163, 165, 369, social engineering 312
385 social geography 212, 245, 301, 322, 324
Research Excellence Framework 321, 337, 364, 388 Social Geography Study Group 191
resistance 277, 287–8, 290, 305, 375 social justice 314, 325
resource exploitation 313, 327, 329, 335 Social Justice and the City (Harvey) 204–5, 228–9
resource-population ratios 221–2 social organisation 173
restructuring 251–2 social physics school 68–9
revolutionary theory 316–18, 334 and spatial science 107–10
revolutions 76–7, 347, 349–53, 373, 379, 389, 397 social planning 322
rewards and status 8–9 social problems 313–16, 321, 333, 358, 360, 381
rhetorical devices 260–3, 299, 305–6 social reform 317
right-wing politics 234, 235–6 Social Science Research Council 94–5, 149, 367
risk 328–9 Problems and Policy Committee 86–7
role of geography 328 social sciences
root metaphors 390–2 academic discipline 21, 23–6, 29–32
Royal Geographical Society (RGS) 8, 11–12, 39, 41, applied geography 311, 329, 338, 340
44, 55, 238, 306, 319, 325, 331, 373, 377 changing discipline 352, 355, 363, 374
Royal Geographical Society and Institute of British humanistic geography 191
Geographers 334, 343 postmodernism 247, 252
rural geographies 211, 301 radical geography 208, 213–15, 219–20, 229,
234
scale 269, 274, 333, 342 spatial science 114
schools of modern and postmodern thought 392 systematic studies 60, 87
Science in Action (Latour) 397 social scientific paradigm 309
The Science of Geography (NAS-NRC) 85–6 social theory 351, 388, 390
scientific discourse 360 socialisation 374, 396
scientific method 312 socialism, eclipse of 235
human geography 76–83 socialist feminisms 287, 292–6
reactions to 80–3, 232–3 Socially and Ecologically Responsible Geographers
spread of 83–98 200, 314
systematic studies 60–4, 69, 70, 77–80, 93 Society and Space 192
see also spatial science Society of Friends 330
scientific progress models 378 society–environment interface 143, 315, 327–8,
scientific revolutions 15, 17–18, 20 334
scientistic rhetoric 262 sociological paradigms 19
Scopus 6 soil erosion and conservation 327
Scottish Geographical 50, 91 sources of status 8–9
second wave feminism 284 Soviet Union 235–7
Second World War 27–8, 37, 43–4, 49, 74, 319 space
secondary schools 368, 371–3, 377 bounded 105–6
security issues 332 continuous 105–6
sexualities 245, 272, 282, 286, 295, 300–2, 307 hierarchicalization of 262
The Shaping of America (Meinig) 96 of poststructuralism 266
Shell Oil 334 production of 221, 279
‘Should women count?’ (Mattingly and Falconer sexuality and 300–1
Al-Hindi) 298 and time 131, 132, 247, 251–7, 253, 254
significance tests 79 Space, Gender and Knowledge (McDowell and Sharp) 283
518 Subject index

space preferences 129–31 The Statistician 145


Spaces of Masculinities (Van Hoven and Hörschelmann) status 388
288 STEM disciplines 33
The Spaces of Postmodernity (Dear and Flusty) 243 stereotyping 297
spatial analysis 157, 333, 338, 351, 382, 388 Stirling University 335
spatial association 66–7 stochastic location theory 137
spatial autocorrelation 147–8, 152, 154 structural Marxisms 207–11, 209–10
Spatial Behavior (Golledge and Stimson) 143 structuralisms 207–11, 217, 222, 234, 396
spatial construction of society 221 structuration theory 133–4, 198–9, 219–21, 224–5,
spatial data analysis 165 230–1, 241, 362, 388, 391
spatial dependence 148 structure and agency 219
spatial diffusion 102, 375 structure of geography 364–6
spatial divisions of labour 212–15 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Kuhn) 15, 346, 397
Spatial Divisions of Labour (Massey) 207–9, 212 students 32–4
‘The spatial economy’ (Haggett) 379 enrolment 367–8, 371–3, 377
spatial efficiency 315 loans 373, 387
Spatial Expansion Method 153 Study Group in Quantitative Methods 90–1
spatial forecasting 148–9 style in postmodernism 248
spatial modelling 154–5 subfields 4, 23, 88–90, 245, 280, 304, 366, 389
Spatial Organization (Abler) 104 subjectivity 96, 171–4, 179–80, 184–6, 220, 249,
The Spatial Organization of Society (Morrill) 103 380
spatial organization paradigm 348 substantive laws 122
spatial patterns 60, 73, 77–8, 86, 128, 137 supply and demand 369–70
spatial planning 320 survival strategies 366, 368, 387
spatial policies 322, 324–5 Sussex University 94
spatial reorganisation 323–4 sustainable development 310–11, 329
spatial science 100–68 Sweden 107, 128, 320, 376
alternatives to 174 Swedish Society for Anthropology and Geography
applied geography 311–12, 344 8
behavioural geography 124–45, 136, 139, Sydney University 45
140–5, 143 synchronicity 247
changing discipline 349, 351, 358, 363, 378–81, synthesis 175–6, 180, 319
383, 385, 391, 396 systematic geography 57–99, 378
critical responses and debate 159–62, 169–71 geography matrix 88–9
feminist geographies 290, 303 historical and cultural geography 95–8
Geographical Information Science 162–6 regional geography 49–50, 55, 58–9, 62–3, 65
Geographical Information Systems 157–9 revolution 76–7
postmodernism 266, 278 Schaefer’s paper (1953) and responses 59–64
social physics and 107–10 scientific method 76–83
spatial theory 105–10 scientific method (reactions to) 80–3
spatial variables and spatial systems 101–5, 102 scientific method (spread of) 83–98
spatial/geo-statistics 145–57 UK developments 90–5
systems 110–15, 112–13, 115–21 USA developments 64–76
spatial spread 107 systematic order and disorder 249
spatial turn 280, 355–6 systematic specialisms 59
spatiality 184 systems theory 101, 110–21
specialisation 42, 52, 166, 370
Standing Committee on Society and Public Policy Tableau de la Géographie de la France (Vidal) 46
312 Task Force on Environmental Quality (AAG)
Stanford University 367 327
static laws 121 teaching 2, 4–7, 33–4, 343, 367, 387
statistical analysis 145–6, 154 technocratic approach 232–3, 263–4, 309, 319,
Statistical Geography (Duncan) 67 371, 380
statistical laws 82 technologies 361
statistical methods 67–8, 71–2, 79, 84, 90–2, 148 digital mapping 321
Subject index 519

Geographical Information Science (GISci) 86, 88, external environment 27–9, 31–2, 35
101, 162–6 foundations of contemporary geography 38–9,
remote sensing 156, 321, 369–70 40, 41–3, 46–7, 49–53, 55–6
see also Geographical Information Systems (GIS) humanistic geography 191
Technology Foresight exercise 33 postmodernism 273
testing laws 77–8, 81–2, 230, 380 spatial science 103–4, 147–51
textbooks 6, 292, 395 systematic studies 90–5
textual communities 258–9 UK Academy of Social Sciences 337
Textures of Place (Hoelscher and Till) 181 UK Millennium Birth Cohort Study 159
Thatcherism 338 uncertainty 302
theoretical pluralism 19 understanding 182, 263, 323–5
theoretical revolution 347, 388 Understanding the Changing Planet (NRC) 165
theoreticism 226 uneven development 212, 214–15, 221, 223, 237,
theory borrowing 346, 355, 398 250, 341
theory development 65–6, 69, 77–8, 80–3, 93, 107, Uneven Development (Smith) 206
175, 177, 191, 232–3, 312, 316, 389 Union of Socialist Geographers 200, 229
theory-free approach 246 uniqueness 57, 60, 62, 64, 225, 249, 379
Third World 236, 244, 314 universalism 261, 380
Thompson Reuters 6 universities
Thresholds in Feminist Geography (Jones) 283 changing discipline 348, 361–3, 365–8, 377–8,
time-geography 123, 131, 131–5, 247 394
time-series data 147 feminist geographies 282, 315, 320, 329,
time-space compression 251–7, 253 335
time-space prism 131, 132 foundations of geography 39–43, 45, 52–4
togetherness principle 132 humanistic geography 179, 186, 192
topical geography 44 postmodernism 246, 250–1, 272
topical specialisms 49, 55, 59, 64, 93 radical geography 201, 242
Toronto University 179 spatial science 101, 104–5, 108–10, 126, 147,
totalising discourses 225–6, 249, 254–5, 273 149, 157–8
Tourism Geographies 327 systematic studies 65–76, 89, 91–4, 97
Tourism and Recreation Research Unit 315 see also academic disciplines; students; individual
Toward a Geography of Price (Warntz) 69 universities
Traces on the Rhodian Shore (Glacken) 45, 53–4 University College London 39, 91
tradition as construct 288–9, 354 University Grants Committee 321
traditional perspective 371, 399 urban geography
transactional positions 140 applied geography 333
Transactions in GIS 163 changing discipline 362–3, 382–3
Transcontinental Excursion (1912) 376 radical geography 202–3, 205, 223–4, 229
transferable skills 309, 337, 367, 369–72, 377, 385 spatial science 109, 114, 120, 130
transgendered geographies 304 systematic studies 72–3, 75, 83, 89, 92
translations 275 urban planning 319, 370
transport geography 101, 301, 319–20 The Urban Question (Castells) 208
transversal feminist geography 286 urbanisation 206, 224, 228, 237, 336
travel writing 289–90 urbanisms 250–1, 365
truth claims 249, 255, 333 US Geological Survey 87
typifications 185 USA
academic institutions 11–12
UK applied geography 309, 313–14, 319, 322–3,
academic institutions 9–12 326–7, 335, 339–41
applied geography 309, 312–15, 319–20, 325, appointments and promotions 7–8
335–7, 339–41, 344 career structure 3, 4
appointments and promotions 7 changing discipline 366–9, 371–3, 378, 386,
career structure 2, 3, 4 388, 396
changing discipline 364, 367, 369, 371–3, external environment 26–32, 35
377–8, 386–8, 394, 396 feminist geography 282, 302
520 Subject index

USA (continued) well-being 324


foundations of contemporary geography 39–44, West Africa (Church) 58
46–53, 55 Western hegemony 273
humanistic geography 191 ‘What kind of geography for what kind of public
spatial science 149–51 policy?’ (Harvey) 316
spatial systems 110 Where we have come from and where we are going
systematic studies 59–60, 64–76, 83–5, 90, 97 (conference) 385
utility 85, 138, 151, 227, 229, 233, 308, 337 whiteness of academic discipline 275–7
see also relevance Why the Social Sciences Matter (Michie and Cooper) 337
Wisconsin school 67–8
values 332–3 Women and Geography Study Group 281, 299,
Vancouver University 361 306–7
Vienna school 65 ‘Women in geography in the 21st century’
Vietnam War 29–30, 200, 309, 314, 382 (The Professional Geographer) 282
voluntarism 231 World Boundaries Series 335
A World in Crisis? (Johnston and Taylor) 332
Wall Street crash 27 World Health Organization 149
Washington school 69–74, 348, 363, 365 World Three concept 361, 366, 396
Wayne State University, Detroit 76 world views 380–3, 388–91, 394, 396
Weberianism 224, 225
welfare economics 319 Yale University 367
welfare geography 201–2, 232–3, 314, 321–5, 380
Welfare State 29 Zeitgeist 357

You might also like