0% found this document useful (0 votes)
158 views

Humor Internet Encyclopedia

This document summarizes different theories of humor and the challenges of defining humor. It discusses three main theories - incongruity, superiority, and relief theories. However, these theories are an oversimplification and do not fully capture the complexity of humor. Defining humor has proven difficult as theorists address different aspects like the object, response, or purpose of humor. The document also distinguishes between humor, laughter, and comedy and analyzes problems with how theorists have traditionally been classified.

Uploaded by

kekosa
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
158 views

Humor Internet Encyclopedia

This document summarizes different theories of humor and the challenges of defining humor. It discusses three main theories - incongruity, superiority, and relief theories. However, these theories are an oversimplification and do not fully capture the complexity of humor. Defining humor has proven difficult as theorists address different aspects like the object, response, or purpose of humor. The document also distinguishes between humor, laughter, and comedy and analyzes problems with how theorists have traditionally been classified.

Uploaded by

kekosa
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 12

Humor

The philosophical study of humor has been focused on the development of a


satisfactory definition of humor, which until recently has been treated as roughly co-
extensive with laughter. The main task is to develop an adequate theory of just what
humor is.

According to the standard analysis, humor theories can be classified into three neatly
identifiable groups:incongruity, superiority, and relief theories. Incongruity theory is
the leading approach and includes historical figures such as Immanuel Kant, Søren
Kierkegaard, and perhaps has its origins in comments made by Aristotle in
the Rhetoric. Primarily focusing on the object of humor, this school sees humor as a
response to an incongruity, a term broadly used to include ambiguity, logical
impossibility, irrelevance, and inappropriateness. The paradigmatic Superiority
theorist is Thomas Hobbes, who said that humor arises from a "sudden glory" felt
when we recognize our supremacy over others. Plato and Aristotle are generally
considered superiority theorists, who emphasize the aggressive feelings that fuel
humor. The third group, Relief theory, is typically associated with Sigmund
Freud and Herbert Spencer, who saw humor as fundamentally a way to release or save
energy generated by repression. In addition, this article will explore a fourth group of
theories of humor: play theory. Play theorists are not so much listing necessary
conditions for something's counting as humor, as they are asking us to look at humor
as an extension of animal play.
While the task of defining humor is a seemingly simple one, it has proven quite
difficult. Each theory attempts to provide a characterization of what is at least at the
core of humor. However, these theories are not necessarily competing; they may be
seen as simply focusing on different aspects of humor, treating certain aspects as
more fundamental than others.

Table of Contents

1. What Is Humor?
a. Humor, Laughter, and the Holy Grail
b. Problems Classifying Theorists
2. Theories of Humor
. Superiority Theory
a. Relief Theory
b. Incongruity Theory
c. Play Theory
d. Summary of Humor Theories
3. Reference and Further Reading
1. What is Humor?
Almost every major figure in the history of philosophy has proposed a theory, but
after 2500 years of discussion there has been little consensus about what constitutes
humor. Despite the number of thinkers who have participated in the debate, the topic
of humor is currently understudied in the discipline of philosophy. There are only a
few philosophers currently focused on humor-related research, which is most likely
due to two factors: the problems in the field have proved incredibly difficult, inviting
repeated failures, and the subject is erroneously dismissed as an insignificant
concern. Nevertheless, scope and significance of the study of humor is reflected in the
interdisciplinary nature of the filed, which draws insights from philosophy,
psychology, sociology, anthropology, film, and literature. It is rare to find a
philosophical topic that bares such direct relevance to our daily lives, our social
interactions, and our nature as humans.

a. Humor, Laughter, Comedy, and the Holy Grail


The majority of the work on humor has been occupied with the following
foundational question: What is humor? The word "humor" itself is of relatively recent
origin. According to the Oxford English Dictionary, it arose during the 17th century
out of psycho-physiological scientific speculation on the effects of various humors
that might affect a person's temperament. Much of the earlier humor research is
riddled with equivocations between humor and laughter, and the problem continues
into recent discussions. John Dewey states one reason to make the distinction: "The
laugh is by no means to be viewed from the standpoint of humor; its connection with
humor is only secondary. It marks the ending [. . .] of a period of suspense, or
expectation, all ending which is sharp and secondary" (John Dewey, 558). We laugh
for a variety of reasons—hearing a funny joke, inhaling laughing gas, being tickled—
not all of which result from what we think of as humor. Attempting to offer a general
theory of laughter and humor, John Morreall (manuscript) makes a finer distinction:
laughter results from a pleasant psychological shift, whereas, humor arises from a
pleasant cognitive shift. Noting the predominance of non-humorous laughter,
researcher Robert Provine (2000) argues that laughter is most often found in non-
humorous social interactions, deployed as some sort of tension relief mechanism. If
humor is not a necessary condition of laughter, then we might ask if it is sufficient.
Often humor will produce laughter, but sometimes it results in only a smile.
Obviously, these relatively distinct phenomena are intimately connected in some
manner, but to understand the relationship we need clearer notions of both laugher
and humor.
Laughter is a fairly well described physiological process that results in a limited range
of characteristic vocal patterns that are only physiologically possible, as Provine
suggests, for bi-pedal creatures with breath control. If we describe humorous laughter
as laughter in response to humor, then we must answer the question, What is humor?
This topic will be explored in the next few sections, but for starters, we can say that
humor or amusement is widely regarded as a response to a certain kind of stimulus.
The comic, on the other hand, is best described as a professionally produced source of
humor, a generic element of various artforms. In distinguishing between humorous
and non-humorous laughter we presuppose a working definition of humor, based
partly on the character of our response and partly on the properties of humorous
objects. This is not necessarily to beg the question about what is humor, but to enter
into the real world process of correctively developing a definition. The first goal of a
humor theory is to look for the basis of our practical ability to identify humor.

Most definitions of humor are essentialist in that they try to list the necessary and
sufficient conditions something must meet in order to be counted as humor. Some
theories isolate a common element supposedly found in all humor, but hold back
from making claims about the sufficient conditions. Many theorists seem to confuse
offering the necessary conditions for a response to count as humor with explaining
why we find one thing funny rather than another. This second question, what would
be sufficient for an object to be found funny, is the Holy Grail of humor studies, and
must be kept distinct from the goals of a definition of the humor response. The Holy
Grail is often confused with a question regarding the sufficient conditions for our
response to count as humorous amusement, but a crucial distinction needs to be
made: identifying the conditions of a response is different from the isolating the
features something must possess in order to provoke such a response. The first task is
much different from suggesting what features are sufficient to provoke a response of
humorous amusement. What amounts to a humor response is different from what
makes something humorous. The noun (humor) and adjectival (humorous) senses of
the term are difficult to keep distinct due to the imprecision of our language in this
area. Much of the dissatisfaction with traditional humor theories can be traced back
to an equivocation between these two senses of the term.

b. Problems Classifying Theorists


The standard analysis, developed by D. H. Monro, that classifies humor theories into
superiority, incongruity, and relief theories sets up a false expectation of genuine
competition between the views. Rarely do any of the historical theorists in any of
these schools state their theories as listing necessary of sufficient conditions for
something to count as humor, much less put their views in competition with others. A
further problem concerns just what the something is that might be called humor.
Some theories address the object of humor, whereas others are concerned primarily
with the characteristics of the response, and other theories discuss both.

The popular reduction of humor theories into three groups—Incongruity, Relief, and
Superiority theories—is an over simplification. Several scholars have identified over
100 types of humor theories, and Patricia Keith-Spiegel's classification of humor
theories into 8 major types (biological, superiority, incongruity, surprise,
ambivalence, release, configuration, and psychoanalytic theories) has been fairly
influential. Jim Lyttle suggests that, based on the question they are primarily
addressing humor, theories can be classified into 3 different groups. He argues that,
depending on their focus, humor theories can be grouped under these categories:
functional, stimuli, and response theories. (1) Functional theories of humor ask what
purpose humor has in human life. (2) Stimuli theories ask what makes a particular
thing funny. (3)Response theorists ask why we find things funny. A better way to
phrase this concern is to say that response theorists ask what is particular about
feelings of humor.
A little probing shows that Lyttle's grouping is strained, since many of the humor
theories address more than one of these questions, and an answer to one often
involves an answer to the other questions. For instance, though focused on the
function of humor, relief theories often have something to say about all three
questions: humor serves as a tension release mechanism, the content often concerns
the subject of repressed desires, and finding these funny involves a feeling of relief.

Regardless of the classificatory scheme, when analyzing the tradition of humor


theories we need to consider how each of the traditionally defined schools answers
the major questions that occupy the bulk of the discussion. The primary questions of
humor theory include:

1. Humor question: What is humor?


(An answer to this question often entails answers to questions regarding the object
and the response. This is the central question of any humor theory.)

2. Object Feature Questions:

a. Are there any features frequently found in what is found funny?


b. Are there any features necessary for something to have in order to be found funny?
c. Are there any features that by themselves or considered jointly are sufficient for
something to be found funny? (Answering this question affirmatively would amount
to discovering the holy grail of humor theory.)
3. Response Question: Is there anything psychologically or cognitively distinctive or
characteristic about finding something funny?

4. Laughter Question: How is humor related to laughter?

Given this list, we may ask what would a theory of humor amount to? To count as a
humor theory and not just an approach to humor, a theory must attempt an answer
to Question 1—What is humor? Like the relief theories, most humor theorists do not
attempt to answer this question head on, but discuss some important or necessary
characteristics of humor. Since the various theories of humor are addressing different
sets of questions within this cluster as well as related question in the general study of
humor, it is often difficult to put them in competition with each other. Accepting this
limitation, we can proceed to explore a few of the major humor theories listed in the
widely influential standard analysis.

2. Theories of Humor
a. Superiority Theory
We can give two forms to the claims of the superiority theory of humor: (1) the strong
claim holds that all humor involves a feeling of superiority, and (2) the weak claim
suggests that feelings of superiority are frequently found in many cases of humor. It is
not clear that many superiority theorists would hold to the strong claim if pressed,
but we will evaluate as a necessary condition nonetheless.

Neither Plato nor Aristotle makes clear pronouncements about the essence of humor,
though their comments are preoccupied with the role of feelings of superiority in our
finding something funny. In the "Philebus," Plato tries to expose the "mixture of
pleasure and pain that lies in the malice of amusement." He argues that ignorance is a
misfortune that when found in the weak is considered ridiculous. In comedy, we take
malicious pleasure from the ridiculous, mixing pleasure with a pain of the soul. Some
of Aristotle's brief comments in the Poetics corroborate Plato's view of the pleasure
had from comedy. Tragedy deals with subjects who are average or better than
average; however, in comedy we look down upon the characters, since it presents
subjects of lesser virtue than, or "who are inferior to," the audience. The "ludicrous,"
according to Aristotle, is "that is a failing or a piece of ugliness which causes no pain
of destruction" (Poetics, sections 3 and 7). Going beyond the subject of comedy, in
the Rhetoric (II, 12) Aristotle defines wit as "educated insolence," and in
the Nicomachean Ethics (IV, 8) he describes jokes as "a kind of abuse" which should
ideally be told without producing pain. Rather than clearly offering a superiority
theory of humor, Plato and Aristotle focus on this common comic feature, bringing it
to our attention for ethical considerations.
Thomas Hobbes developed the most well known version of the Superiority theory.
Giving emphatic expression to the idea, Hobbes says "that the passion of laughter is
nothing else but sudden glory arising from some sudden conception of some
eminency in ourselves, by comparison with the infirmity of others, or with our own
formerly" (Human Nature, ch. 8). Motivated by the literary conceit of the laugh of
triumph, Hobbes's expression the superiority theory looks like more of a theory of
laughter than a theory of humor. Charles Baudelaire (1956) offers an interesting
variation on Hobbes' superiority theory, mixing it with mortal inferiority. He argues
that that "laughter is satanic"—an expression of dominance over animals and a
frustrated complaint against our being merely mortal.
Critically reversing the superiority theory, Robert Solomon (2002) offers an inferiority
theory of humor. He thinks that self-recognition in the silly antics and self-
deprecating behavior of the Three Stooges is characteristic of a source of humor
based in inferiority or modesty. Rather than comparing our current with our former
inferior selves, Solomon sees the ability to not take yourself seriously, or to see
yourself as less than ideal, as a source of virtuous modesty and compassion.
Solomon's analysis of the Three Stooges is not a full-blown theory of humor, in that it
does not make any pronouncements about the necessary or sufficient conditions of
humor; however, it is a theory of humor in the sense that it suggests a possible source
of humor or what humor can be and how it might function.
Solomon's inferiority theory of humor raises a central objection against the
Superiority theory, namely, that a feeling of superiority is not a necessary condition of
humor. Morreall offers several examples, such as finding a bowling ball in his
refrigerator, that could be found funny, but do not clearly involve superiority. If
feelings of superiority are not necessary for humor, are they sufficient? Undoubtedly,
this is not the case. As an 18th century critic of Hobbes, Francis Hutcheson, points
out, we can feel superior to lots of things, dogs, cats, trees, etc, without being amused:
"some ingenuity in dogs and monkeys, which comes near to some of our own arts,
very often makes us merry; whereas their duller actions, in which the are much below
us, are no matter of jest at all" (p. 29). However, if we evaluate the weaker version of
the superiority theory—that humor is often fueled by feelings of superiority—then we
have a fairly well supported empirical claim, easily confirmable by first hand
observation.

b. Relief Theory
Relief theories attempt to describe humor along the lines of a tension-release model.
Rather than defining humor, they discuss the essential structures and psychological
processes that produce laughter. The two most prominent relief theorists are Herbert
Spencer and Sigmund Freud. We can consider two version of the relief theory: (1) the
strong version holds that all laughter results from a release of excessive energy; (2)
the weak version claims that it is often the case that humorous laughter involves a
release of tension or energy. Freud develops a more specific description of the energy
transfer mechanism, but the process he describes is not essential to the basic claims
of the relief theory of humor.

In "The Physiology of Laughter" (1860), Spencer develops a theory of laughter that is


intimately related to his "hydraulic" theory of nervous energy, whereby excitement
and mental agitation produces energy that "must expend itself in some way or
another." He argues that "nervous excitation always tends to beget muscular motion."
As a form of physical movement, laughter can serve as the expressive route of various
forms of nervous energy. Spencer did not see his theory as a competitor to the
incongruity theory of humor; rather, he tried to explain why it is that a certain mental
agitation arising from a "descending incongruity" results in this characteristically
purposeless physical movement. Spencer never satisfactorily answers this specific
question, but he presents the basic idea that laughter serves to release pent up
energy.

One criticism of Spencer's theory of energy relief is that it does not seem to describe
most cases of humor that occur quickly. Many instances of jokes, witticisms, and
cartoons do not seem to involve a build up of energy that is then released. Perhaps
Spencer thinks that the best explanation for laughter, an otherwise purposeless
expenditure of energy, must be that it relieves energy produced from humor.
However, since most of our experiences of humor do not seem to involve an energy
build up, and humor does not seem forthcoming when we are generally agitated, a
better explanation might be that laughter is not as purposeless as it seems or that all
expenditures of energy, purposeful or not, need involve a build up.

Spencer might reply that everyone is continuously building up energy simply through
the process of managing everyday stress. As such, most people have excess energy, a
form of energy potential, waiting to be released by humor. For example, one often
hears it said that humor allows one to "blow off steam" after a stressful day at work.
The problem with this line of argument is that those who are most "stressed out"
seem the least receptive to humor. Not only do attempts at humor frequently fall flat
on the hurried, the amusement that results is typically minimal. Perhaps Spencer
could argue that at a certain threshold the pent up energy jams the gates such that
humor is unable to provide a release. This line of defense might be plausible, but the
tension release theory starts to look a bit ad hoc when you have to posit things such as
jammed energy release gates and the like.

In Jokes and Their Relation to the Unconscious (1905), Freud develops a more fine
grained version of the relief theory of laughter, that amounts to a restatement of
Spencer's theory with the addition of a new process. He describes three different
sources of laughter—joking, the comic, and humor—which all involve the saving of
some psychic energy that is then discharged through laughter. In joking, the energy
that would have been used to repress sexual and hostile feelings is saved and can be
released in laughter. In the comic, cognitive energy to be used to solve an intellectual
challenge is left over and can be released. The humorous involves a saving of
emotional energy, since what might have been an emotion provoking situation turns
out to be something we should treat non-seriously. The energy building up for the
serious emotional reaction can then be released.
The details of Freud's discussions of the process of energy saving, are widely regarded
as problematic. His notion of energy saving is unclear, since it is not clear what sense
it makes to say that energy which is never called upon is saved, rather than saying
that no energy was expended. Take his theory of jokes, where the energy that
otherwise would have been used to repress a desire is saved by joking which allows
for aggression to be released. John Morreall and Noel Carroll make a similar criticism
of this theory of energy management. We may have an idea of what it is like to
express pent up energy, but we have no notion of what it would be to release energy
that is used to repress a desire. Beyond the claim of queerness, this theory of joking
does not result in the expected empirical observations. On Freud's explanation, the
most inhibited and repressed people would seem to enjoy joking the most, though the
opposite is the case.

Relief theories of laughter do not furnish us a way to distinguish humorous from non-
humorous laughter. Freud's saved energy is perceptually indistinguishable with other
forms of energy. As we saw with Spencer, Relief theories must be saddled to another
theory of humor. Freud's attempt to explain why we laugh is also an effort to explain
why we find certain tendentious jokes especially funny, though it is not clear what he
is getting at in his account of the saving of energy. He commits the fundamental
mistake of relief theorists—they erroneously assume that since mental energy often
finds release in physical movement, any physical movement must be explainable by
an excess of nervous energy.

c. Incongruity Theory
The incongruity theory is the reigning theory of humor, since it seems to account for
most cases of perceived funniness, which is partly because "incongruity" is something
of an umbrella term. Most developments of the incongruity theory only try to list a
necessary condition for humor—the perception of an incongruity—and they stop
short of offering the sufficient conditions.

In the Rhetoric (III, 2), Aristotle presents the earliest glimmer of an incongruity
theory of humor, finding that the best way to get an audience to laugh is to setup an
expectation and deliver something "that gives a twist." After discussing the power of
metaphors to produce a surprise in the hearer, Aristotle says that "[t]he effect is
produced even by jokes depending upon changes of the letters of a word; this too is a
surprise. You find this in verse as well as in prose. The word which comes is not what
the hearer imagined." These remarks sound like a surprise theory of humor, similar
to that later offered by René Descartes, but Aristotle continues to explain how the
surprise must somehow "fit the facts," or as we might put it today, the incongruity
must be capable of a resolution.
In the Critique of Judgment, Immanuel Kant gives a clearer statement of the role of
incongruity in humor: "In everything that is to excite a lively laugh there must be
something absurd (in which the understanding, therefore, can find no satisfaction).
Laughter is an affection arising from the sudden transformation of a strained
expectation into nothing" (I, I, 54).
Arthur Schopenhauer offers a more specific version of the incongruity theory, arguing
that humor arising from a failure of a concept to account for an object of thought.
When the particular outstrips the general, we are faced with an incongruity.
Schopenhauer also emphasizes the element of surprise, saying that "the greater and
more unexpected [. . .] this incongruity is, the more violent will be his laughter"
(1818, I, Sec. 13).

As stated by Kant and Schopenhauer, the incongruity theory of humor specifies a


necessary condition of the object of humor. Focusing on the humorous object, leaves
something out of the analysis of humor, since there are many kinds of things that are
incongruous which do not produce amusement. A more robust statement of the
incongruity theory would need to include the pleasurable response one has to
humorous objects. John Morreall attempts to find sufficient conditions for
identifying humor by focusing on our response. He defines humorous amusement as
taking pleasure in a cognitive shift. The incongruity theory can be stated as a
response focused theory, claiming that humor is a certain kind of reaction had to
perceived incongruity.

Henri Bergson's essay "Laughter" (1980) is perhaps the one of the most influential
and sophisticated theories of humor. Bergson's theory of humor is not easily
classifiable, since it has elements of superiority and incongruity theories. In a famous
phrase, Bergson argues that the source of humor is the "mechanical encrusted upon
the living" (p. 84) According to Bergson "the comic does not exist outside of what is
strictly human." He thinks that humor involve an incongruous relationship between
human intelligence and habitual or mechanical behaviors. As such, humor serves as a
social corrective, helping people recognize behaviors that are inhospitable to human
flourishing. A large source of the comic is in recognizing our superiority over the
subhuman. Anything that threatens to reduce a person to an object—either animal or
mechanical—is prime material for humor. No doubt, Bergson's theory accounts for
much of physical comedy and bodily humor, but he seems to over-estimate the
necessity of mechanical encrustation. It is difficult to see how his theory can
accommodate most jokes and sources of humor coming from wit.

Three major criticisms of the incongruity theory are that it is too broad to be very
meaningful, it is insufficiently explanatory in that it does not distinguish between
non-humorous incongruity and basic incongruity, and that revised versions still fail
to explain why some things, rather than others, are funny. We have already addressed
the third criticism: it confuses the object of humor with the response. What is at issue
is the definition of humor, or how to identify humor, not how to create a humor-
generating algorithm. The incongruity theorist has a response to this criticism as well,
since they can claim that humor is pleasure in incongruity.

d. Play Theories
Describing play theories of humor as an independent school or approach might
overstate their relative importance, although they do serve as a good representative of
theories focused on the functional question. By looking at the contextual
characteristic, play theories try to classify humor as a species of play. In this general
categorization effort, the play theorists are not so much listing necessary conditions,
as they are asking us to look at humor as an extension of animal play. They try to call
our attention to the structural similarities between play contexts and humorous
context, to suggest that what might be true of play, might be true of humor as well.

Play theorists often take an ethological approach to studying humor, tracing it back
through evolutionary development. They look at laughter triggers like tickling, that
are found in other species, to suggest that in humor ontogeny recapitulates
phylogeny. In The Enjoyment of Laughter(1936), Max Eastman develops a play theory
of humor with an adaptive story. He thinks we can find analogies of humor in the
behavior of animals, especially in the proto-laughter of chimps to tickling. He goes so
far as to argue that the wagging tail of a happy dog is a form of humorous laughter,
since Eastman wants to broaden the definition of laughter to encompass other
rhythmic responses to pleasure. Speaking more specifically of humor, he argues that
"we come into the world endowed with an instinctive tendency to laugh and have this
feeling in response to pains presented playfully" (p. 45). On Eastman's account, what
is central to humor and play is that both require taking a disinterested attitude
towards what might otherwise be seen as serious.
Eastman considers humor to be a form of play, because humor involves a
disinterested stance, certain kinds of humor involve mock aggression and insults, and
because some forms of play activities result in humorous amusement. Since Eastman
defines play as the adoption of this disinterested attitude, humor would count as a
form of play on his definition, but this seems both too restrictive and too vague to
serve as an adequate definition of play. In Homo Ludens (1938), Johan Huizinga
criticizes identifying play with laughter or the comic. Though both seem to involve
"the opposite of seriousness," there are crucial asymmetries. Laughter, he argues, is
particular to humans, whereas, play is found in other mammals and birds. Also, if we
allow for certain types of competitive play, then a non-serious attitude is not essential
to play, as it seems to be for humor. Identifying the comic, or humor, with play is
problematic, since "in itself play is not comical for either for the player or public"
(1938, p. 6). Huizinga questions whether humor and play share any necessary
conditions, a requirement of the relationship if humor is a subtype of play. This will,
of course, depend on how we describe humor and play, two equally elusive notions.
Play theorists are primarily concerned with the problem of determining the function
of humor in order to explain how it might have adaptive value, a task taken up by
other biological theories of humor. They argue that similarities between play and
humor suggest that the adaptive value of play might be similar to that of humor.
Other researchers focused on the functional questions have described humor as
having value in cognitive development, social skill learning, tension relief, empathy
management, immune system benefits, stress relief, and social bonding. Though
these questions are primarily addressed by psychologists, sociologist,
anthropologists, and medical researchers, their studies rely on and contribute to an
evolving notion of just what counts as humor. Though the functional question is
foremost in these theories, play theory tries to give humor a genus by offering some
differentiating characteristics, essential to humor.

e. Summary of Humor Theories


We discussed four different schools of humor theories and noted how each reveals
aspects common, if not necessary, to humor. Presenting these theories as rivals is
misleading since, as we have seen, theorists in each classification focus on different
problems and may draw upon the answers to different questions from another school.
For instance, while focusing on why we find something funny, Spencer offers a
functional explanation and relies on the answer incongruity theorists give to the
question of what we find funny. Relief theories and Play theories tend to focus on the
function humor serves in human life, though the functional question cannot be
separated from characterizing amusement, or the humor response. Superiority
theorists tend to focus on what feelings are necessary for there to be humor, or why
we find some things funny. Incongruity theories have the most to say about the object
of humor, though variants identify humor with the way we respond to a perceived
incongruity. Though the functional, stimuli, and response questions are not neatly
separated, the differing schools tend to assume that one question is more basic than
the others.
3. References and Further Reading
 Audi, Robert (1994). "Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe." Nous 28
(4), pp. 419-434.
 Bateson, Gregory (2000). Steps to an Ecology of Mind. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
 Baudelaire, Charles (1956). "The Essence of Laughter and More Especially of the
Comic in Plastic Arts." Trans. Gerald Hopkins. In The Essence of Laughter and other
Essays, Journals, and Letters, ed. Peter Qeennell. New York: Meridian Books.
 Bergson, Henri (1980). "Laughter." Trans. Wylie Sypher, in Comedy, eds. Wylie
Sypher. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
 Berman, Merrie (1986). "How Many Feminists Does It Take To Make A Joke?
Sexist Humor and What's Wrong With It." Hypatia, vol. 1, no. 1, Spring, pp. 63-82.
 Caplow, Theodore (1968). Two Against One: Coalitions in Triads. Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice Hall.
 Carroll, Noel, ed. (2001a). Beyond Aesthetics: Philosophical Essays. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
 Carroll, Noel (2001b). "Horror and Humor" in Carroll (2001a), pp. 235-253.
 Carroll, Noel (2001c). "Moderate Moralism" in Carroll (2001a), pp. 293- 306.
 Carroll, Noel (2001d). "On Jokes" in Carroll (2001), pp. 317-334.
 Carroll, Noel (1996). "Notes on the Sight Gag" in Noel Carroll Theorizing the
Moving Image. New York, Cambridge Univesrity Press.
 Carroll, Noel (1997). "Words, Images, and Laughter." Persistence of Vision, no.
14, pp. 42-52.
 Chapman, A. J., & Foot, H. C., eds. (1976). Humour and laughter: Theory,
research, and applications. London: John Wiley & Sons.
 Cohen, Ted (1999). Jokes: Philosophical Perspectives on Laughing Matters.
Chicago: Chicago Univesrity Press.
 Critchley, Simon (2002). On Humour. New York: Routledge.
 De Sousa, Ronald (1987). "When is it Wrong to Laugh?" Ch. 11 of The Rationality
of Emotion. Cambridge, MIT.
 Descartes, René. (1649/1987). Les Passions de L'ame. Paris. Excerpts in Morreall.
 Dundes, Alan (1987). Cracking Jokes: Studies of Sick Humor Cycles and
Stereotypes. Berkeley: Ten Speed Press.
 Dwyer, Tom (1991). "Humor, Power, and Change in organizations." Human
Relations, vol. 44, no. 1, pp. 1-19.
 Eastman, Max (1936). Enjoyment of Laughter. New York: Halcyon House.
 Eitzen, Dirk (2000). "Comedy and Classicism." Film Theory and Philosophy. Eds.
Richard Allen and Murray Smith. New York: Oxford Univesrity Press.
 Freud, Sigmund (1928). "Humor." International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 9, pp.
1-6.
 Freud, Sigmund (1905/1960). Jokes and their Relation to the Unconscious. Trans.
J. Strachey. New York: W. W. Norton. (Original work published 1905).
 Gaut, Berys (1998). "Just Joking: The Ethics and Aesthetics of
Humor." Philosophy and Literature, 22 (1), pp. 51-68.
 Goldstein, J. H., & McGhee, P. E., eds. (1972). The Psychology of Humor:
Theoretical Perspectives and Empirical Issues. New York: Academic Press.
 Gregory, J. C. (1924). The Nature of Laughter. New York: HBC.
 Handelman, Don (1990/1998). Models and Mirrors: towards and anthropology of
public events. New York: Berghahn Books. (Originally published by Cambridge
University Press in 1990.)
 Hobbes, Thomas (1840). Human Nature, in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes
of Malmesbury, Volume IV,ed. William Molesworth, London: Bohn.
 Horton, Andrew S. (1991). Comedy Cinema / Theory. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
 Huizinga, Johan (1938/1971). Homo Ludens. Beacon Press. (Originally published
in 1938).
 Kant, Immanuel. (1951). Critique of Judgment. J. H. Bernard, Trans. New York:
Hafner.
 Keith-Spiegel, P. C. (1972). "Early Conceptions of Humor: Varieties and Issues."
In Goldstein & McGhee (1972).
 Koestler, Arthur (1964). The Act of Creation: A Study of the Conscious and
Unconscious Processes of Humor, Scientific Discovery and Art. London: Hutchison
Press.
 Layng, Anthony (1991). "Sexism and Classroom Humor." College Teaching, vol.
39, no. 2, Spring, p. 43.
 Ludovici. Anthony M. (1933). The Secret of Laughter. New York: Viking Press.
 Lyttle, Jim (manuscript). The Effectiveness of Humor in Persuasion: The Case of
Business Ethics Training. URL = <http://www.jimlyttle.com/Dissert/l>.
 Mast, Gerald (1979). The Comic Mind: Comedy and the Movies. Chicago;
Univesrity of Chicago Press. (First published in 1973.)
 McGhee, P. E., & Goldstein, J. H., eds. (1983). Handbook of Humor Research:
Basic Issues, Vol. 1. New York: Springer-Verlag.
 McGinn, Colin (1997). Ethics, Evil, and Fiction. New York: Oxford.
 Morreall, John. (1983). "Humor and emotion." American Philosophical Quarterly,
20, pp. 297-304.
 Morreall, John. (1989). "Enjoying incongruity." HUMOR: International Journal of
Humor Research, 2, pp. 1-18.
 Morreall, John. (1987). The Philosophy of Laughter and Humor. New York,
SUNY.
 Morreall, John. (1983). Taking Laughter Seriously. New York: SUNY.
 Nilsen, Alleen Pace & Don L. F. Nilsen (2000). Encyclopedia of 20th-Century
American Humor. Phoenix: Oxry Press.
 Philips, Michael (1984). "Racist Acts and Racist Humor." Canadian Journal of
Philosophy, vol. 14, no. 1, March, pp. 75-96.
 Piaget, Jean (1962). Play, Dreams, and Imitation in Childhood. Trans. C. Gattegno
and F. M Hodgson. New York: Norton and Company.
 Plato. Philebus. In J. Morreall (1987).
 Provine, R. R. (2000). "The Science of Laughter." Psychology Today, 33 (6), pp.
58-62.
 Roberts, Robert C. (1987). "Humor and the Virtues." Inquiry, 31, pp. 127-49.
 Roberts, Robert C. (1988). "Is Amusement and Emotion.' American Philosophical
Quartery, vol. 5, no. 3, July, pp. 269-273.
 Rothenberg, Paula S, ed. (1988). Racism and Sexism: An Integrated Study. New
York: St. Martin's Press.
 Ryan, Kathryn M. & Jeanne Kanjorski (1998). "The Enjoyment of Sexist Humor,
Rape Attitudes, and Relationship Aggression in College Students." Sex Roles, vol. 38,
no. 9/10, May, pp. 743-756.
 Sankowski, Edward (1977). "Responsibility of persons for Their
Emotions." Canadian Journal of Philosophyvol. VIII, no. 4, December, pp. 829-840.
 Schopenhauer, Arthur (1818). The World as Will and Representation.
 Shultz, T. R. (1972). The role of incongruity and resolution in children's
appreciation of cartoon humor. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 13 (3), pp.
456-477.
 Snyder, Mark (1998). "Self-Fulfilling Stereotypes." In Rothenberg (1998), pp. 263-
268.
 Solomon, Robert (2002). "Are the Three Stooges Funny? Soitainly! (or When is it
OK to Laugh?)." Ethics and Values in the Information Age, eds. Joel Rudinow and
Anthony Graybosch. Wadsworth.
 Spencer, Herbert. (1860). "The Physiology of Laughter." Macmillan's Magazine, 1,
pp. 395-402.
 Wiseman, Richard & the LaughLab (2002). The Scientific Quest for the World's
Funniest Joke. London: Arrow.

Author Information
Aaron Smuts
Email: [email protected]
University of Wisconsin-Madison
U. s. A.

You might also like