Humor Internet Encyclopedia
Humor Internet Encyclopedia
According to the standard analysis, humor theories can be classified into three neatly
identifiable groups:incongruity, superiority, and relief theories. Incongruity theory is
the leading approach and includes historical figures such as Immanuel Kant, Søren
Kierkegaard, and perhaps has its origins in comments made by Aristotle in
the Rhetoric. Primarily focusing on the object of humor, this school sees humor as a
response to an incongruity, a term broadly used to include ambiguity, logical
impossibility, irrelevance, and inappropriateness. The paradigmatic Superiority
theorist is Thomas Hobbes, who said that humor arises from a "sudden glory" felt
when we recognize our supremacy over others. Plato and Aristotle are generally
considered superiority theorists, who emphasize the aggressive feelings that fuel
humor. The third group, Relief theory, is typically associated with Sigmund
Freud and Herbert Spencer, who saw humor as fundamentally a way to release or save
energy generated by repression. In addition, this article will explore a fourth group of
theories of humor: play theory. Play theorists are not so much listing necessary
conditions for something's counting as humor, as they are asking us to look at humor
as an extension of animal play.
While the task of defining humor is a seemingly simple one, it has proven quite
difficult. Each theory attempts to provide a characterization of what is at least at the
core of humor. However, these theories are not necessarily competing; they may be
seen as simply focusing on different aspects of humor, treating certain aspects as
more fundamental than others.
Table of Contents
1. What Is Humor?
a. Humor, Laughter, and the Holy Grail
b. Problems Classifying Theorists
2. Theories of Humor
. Superiority Theory
a. Relief Theory
b. Incongruity Theory
c. Play Theory
d. Summary of Humor Theories
3. Reference and Further Reading
1. What is Humor?
Almost every major figure in the history of philosophy has proposed a theory, but
after 2500 years of discussion there has been little consensus about what constitutes
humor. Despite the number of thinkers who have participated in the debate, the topic
of humor is currently understudied in the discipline of philosophy. There are only a
few philosophers currently focused on humor-related research, which is most likely
due to two factors: the problems in the field have proved incredibly difficult, inviting
repeated failures, and the subject is erroneously dismissed as an insignificant
concern. Nevertheless, scope and significance of the study of humor is reflected in the
interdisciplinary nature of the filed, which draws insights from philosophy,
psychology, sociology, anthropology, film, and literature. It is rare to find a
philosophical topic that bares such direct relevance to our daily lives, our social
interactions, and our nature as humans.
Most definitions of humor are essentialist in that they try to list the necessary and
sufficient conditions something must meet in order to be counted as humor. Some
theories isolate a common element supposedly found in all humor, but hold back
from making claims about the sufficient conditions. Many theorists seem to confuse
offering the necessary conditions for a response to count as humor with explaining
why we find one thing funny rather than another. This second question, what would
be sufficient for an object to be found funny, is the Holy Grail of humor studies, and
must be kept distinct from the goals of a definition of the humor response. The Holy
Grail is often confused with a question regarding the sufficient conditions for our
response to count as humorous amusement, but a crucial distinction needs to be
made: identifying the conditions of a response is different from the isolating the
features something must possess in order to provoke such a response. The first task is
much different from suggesting what features are sufficient to provoke a response of
humorous amusement. What amounts to a humor response is different from what
makes something humorous. The noun (humor) and adjectival (humorous) senses of
the term are difficult to keep distinct due to the imprecision of our language in this
area. Much of the dissatisfaction with traditional humor theories can be traced back
to an equivocation between these two senses of the term.
The popular reduction of humor theories into three groups—Incongruity, Relief, and
Superiority theories—is an over simplification. Several scholars have identified over
100 types of humor theories, and Patricia Keith-Spiegel's classification of humor
theories into 8 major types (biological, superiority, incongruity, surprise,
ambivalence, release, configuration, and psychoanalytic theories) has been fairly
influential. Jim Lyttle suggests that, based on the question they are primarily
addressing humor, theories can be classified into 3 different groups. He argues that,
depending on their focus, humor theories can be grouped under these categories:
functional, stimuli, and response theories. (1) Functional theories of humor ask what
purpose humor has in human life. (2) Stimuli theories ask what makes a particular
thing funny. (3)Response theorists ask why we find things funny. A better way to
phrase this concern is to say that response theorists ask what is particular about
feelings of humor.
A little probing shows that Lyttle's grouping is strained, since many of the humor
theories address more than one of these questions, and an answer to one often
involves an answer to the other questions. For instance, though focused on the
function of humor, relief theories often have something to say about all three
questions: humor serves as a tension release mechanism, the content often concerns
the subject of repressed desires, and finding these funny involves a feeling of relief.
Given this list, we may ask what would a theory of humor amount to? To count as a
humor theory and not just an approach to humor, a theory must attempt an answer
to Question 1—What is humor? Like the relief theories, most humor theorists do not
attempt to answer this question head on, but discuss some important or necessary
characteristics of humor. Since the various theories of humor are addressing different
sets of questions within this cluster as well as related question in the general study of
humor, it is often difficult to put them in competition with each other. Accepting this
limitation, we can proceed to explore a few of the major humor theories listed in the
widely influential standard analysis.
2. Theories of Humor
a. Superiority Theory
We can give two forms to the claims of the superiority theory of humor: (1) the strong
claim holds that all humor involves a feeling of superiority, and (2) the weak claim
suggests that feelings of superiority are frequently found in many cases of humor. It is
not clear that many superiority theorists would hold to the strong claim if pressed,
but we will evaluate as a necessary condition nonetheless.
Neither Plato nor Aristotle makes clear pronouncements about the essence of humor,
though their comments are preoccupied with the role of feelings of superiority in our
finding something funny. In the "Philebus," Plato tries to expose the "mixture of
pleasure and pain that lies in the malice of amusement." He argues that ignorance is a
misfortune that when found in the weak is considered ridiculous. In comedy, we take
malicious pleasure from the ridiculous, mixing pleasure with a pain of the soul. Some
of Aristotle's brief comments in the Poetics corroborate Plato's view of the pleasure
had from comedy. Tragedy deals with subjects who are average or better than
average; however, in comedy we look down upon the characters, since it presents
subjects of lesser virtue than, or "who are inferior to," the audience. The "ludicrous,"
according to Aristotle, is "that is a failing or a piece of ugliness which causes no pain
of destruction" (Poetics, sections 3 and 7). Going beyond the subject of comedy, in
the Rhetoric (II, 12) Aristotle defines wit as "educated insolence," and in
the Nicomachean Ethics (IV, 8) he describes jokes as "a kind of abuse" which should
ideally be told without producing pain. Rather than clearly offering a superiority
theory of humor, Plato and Aristotle focus on this common comic feature, bringing it
to our attention for ethical considerations.
Thomas Hobbes developed the most well known version of the Superiority theory.
Giving emphatic expression to the idea, Hobbes says "that the passion of laughter is
nothing else but sudden glory arising from some sudden conception of some
eminency in ourselves, by comparison with the infirmity of others, or with our own
formerly" (Human Nature, ch. 8). Motivated by the literary conceit of the laugh of
triumph, Hobbes's expression the superiority theory looks like more of a theory of
laughter than a theory of humor. Charles Baudelaire (1956) offers an interesting
variation on Hobbes' superiority theory, mixing it with mortal inferiority. He argues
that that "laughter is satanic"—an expression of dominance over animals and a
frustrated complaint against our being merely mortal.
Critically reversing the superiority theory, Robert Solomon (2002) offers an inferiority
theory of humor. He thinks that self-recognition in the silly antics and self-
deprecating behavior of the Three Stooges is characteristic of a source of humor
based in inferiority or modesty. Rather than comparing our current with our former
inferior selves, Solomon sees the ability to not take yourself seriously, or to see
yourself as less than ideal, as a source of virtuous modesty and compassion.
Solomon's analysis of the Three Stooges is not a full-blown theory of humor, in that it
does not make any pronouncements about the necessary or sufficient conditions of
humor; however, it is a theory of humor in the sense that it suggests a possible source
of humor or what humor can be and how it might function.
Solomon's inferiority theory of humor raises a central objection against the
Superiority theory, namely, that a feeling of superiority is not a necessary condition of
humor. Morreall offers several examples, such as finding a bowling ball in his
refrigerator, that could be found funny, but do not clearly involve superiority. If
feelings of superiority are not necessary for humor, are they sufficient? Undoubtedly,
this is not the case. As an 18th century critic of Hobbes, Francis Hutcheson, points
out, we can feel superior to lots of things, dogs, cats, trees, etc, without being amused:
"some ingenuity in dogs and monkeys, which comes near to some of our own arts,
very often makes us merry; whereas their duller actions, in which the are much below
us, are no matter of jest at all" (p. 29). However, if we evaluate the weaker version of
the superiority theory—that humor is often fueled by feelings of superiority—then we
have a fairly well supported empirical claim, easily confirmable by first hand
observation.
b. Relief Theory
Relief theories attempt to describe humor along the lines of a tension-release model.
Rather than defining humor, they discuss the essential structures and psychological
processes that produce laughter. The two most prominent relief theorists are Herbert
Spencer and Sigmund Freud. We can consider two version of the relief theory: (1) the
strong version holds that all laughter results from a release of excessive energy; (2)
the weak version claims that it is often the case that humorous laughter involves a
release of tension or energy. Freud develops a more specific description of the energy
transfer mechanism, but the process he describes is not essential to the basic claims
of the relief theory of humor.
One criticism of Spencer's theory of energy relief is that it does not seem to describe
most cases of humor that occur quickly. Many instances of jokes, witticisms, and
cartoons do not seem to involve a build up of energy that is then released. Perhaps
Spencer thinks that the best explanation for laughter, an otherwise purposeless
expenditure of energy, must be that it relieves energy produced from humor.
However, since most of our experiences of humor do not seem to involve an energy
build up, and humor does not seem forthcoming when we are generally agitated, a
better explanation might be that laughter is not as purposeless as it seems or that all
expenditures of energy, purposeful or not, need involve a build up.
Spencer might reply that everyone is continuously building up energy simply through
the process of managing everyday stress. As such, most people have excess energy, a
form of energy potential, waiting to be released by humor. For example, one often
hears it said that humor allows one to "blow off steam" after a stressful day at work.
The problem with this line of argument is that those who are most "stressed out"
seem the least receptive to humor. Not only do attempts at humor frequently fall flat
on the hurried, the amusement that results is typically minimal. Perhaps Spencer
could argue that at a certain threshold the pent up energy jams the gates such that
humor is unable to provide a release. This line of defense might be plausible, but the
tension release theory starts to look a bit ad hoc when you have to posit things such as
jammed energy release gates and the like.
In Jokes and Their Relation to the Unconscious (1905), Freud develops a more fine
grained version of the relief theory of laughter, that amounts to a restatement of
Spencer's theory with the addition of a new process. He describes three different
sources of laughter—joking, the comic, and humor—which all involve the saving of
some psychic energy that is then discharged through laughter. In joking, the energy
that would have been used to repress sexual and hostile feelings is saved and can be
released in laughter. In the comic, cognitive energy to be used to solve an intellectual
challenge is left over and can be released. The humorous involves a saving of
emotional energy, since what might have been an emotion provoking situation turns
out to be something we should treat non-seriously. The energy building up for the
serious emotional reaction can then be released.
The details of Freud's discussions of the process of energy saving, are widely regarded
as problematic. His notion of energy saving is unclear, since it is not clear what sense
it makes to say that energy which is never called upon is saved, rather than saying
that no energy was expended. Take his theory of jokes, where the energy that
otherwise would have been used to repress a desire is saved by joking which allows
for aggression to be released. John Morreall and Noel Carroll make a similar criticism
of this theory of energy management. We may have an idea of what it is like to
express pent up energy, but we have no notion of what it would be to release energy
that is used to repress a desire. Beyond the claim of queerness, this theory of joking
does not result in the expected empirical observations. On Freud's explanation, the
most inhibited and repressed people would seem to enjoy joking the most, though the
opposite is the case.
Relief theories of laughter do not furnish us a way to distinguish humorous from non-
humorous laughter. Freud's saved energy is perceptually indistinguishable with other
forms of energy. As we saw with Spencer, Relief theories must be saddled to another
theory of humor. Freud's attempt to explain why we laugh is also an effort to explain
why we find certain tendentious jokes especially funny, though it is not clear what he
is getting at in his account of the saving of energy. He commits the fundamental
mistake of relief theorists—they erroneously assume that since mental energy often
finds release in physical movement, any physical movement must be explainable by
an excess of nervous energy.
c. Incongruity Theory
The incongruity theory is the reigning theory of humor, since it seems to account for
most cases of perceived funniness, which is partly because "incongruity" is something
of an umbrella term. Most developments of the incongruity theory only try to list a
necessary condition for humor—the perception of an incongruity—and they stop
short of offering the sufficient conditions.
In the Rhetoric (III, 2), Aristotle presents the earliest glimmer of an incongruity
theory of humor, finding that the best way to get an audience to laugh is to setup an
expectation and deliver something "that gives a twist." After discussing the power of
metaphors to produce a surprise in the hearer, Aristotle says that "[t]he effect is
produced even by jokes depending upon changes of the letters of a word; this too is a
surprise. You find this in verse as well as in prose. The word which comes is not what
the hearer imagined." These remarks sound like a surprise theory of humor, similar
to that later offered by René Descartes, but Aristotle continues to explain how the
surprise must somehow "fit the facts," or as we might put it today, the incongruity
must be capable of a resolution.
In the Critique of Judgment, Immanuel Kant gives a clearer statement of the role of
incongruity in humor: "In everything that is to excite a lively laugh there must be
something absurd (in which the understanding, therefore, can find no satisfaction).
Laughter is an affection arising from the sudden transformation of a strained
expectation into nothing" (I, I, 54).
Arthur Schopenhauer offers a more specific version of the incongruity theory, arguing
that humor arising from a failure of a concept to account for an object of thought.
When the particular outstrips the general, we are faced with an incongruity.
Schopenhauer also emphasizes the element of surprise, saying that "the greater and
more unexpected [. . .] this incongruity is, the more violent will be his laughter"
(1818, I, Sec. 13).
Henri Bergson's essay "Laughter" (1980) is perhaps the one of the most influential
and sophisticated theories of humor. Bergson's theory of humor is not easily
classifiable, since it has elements of superiority and incongruity theories. In a famous
phrase, Bergson argues that the source of humor is the "mechanical encrusted upon
the living" (p. 84) According to Bergson "the comic does not exist outside of what is
strictly human." He thinks that humor involve an incongruous relationship between
human intelligence and habitual or mechanical behaviors. As such, humor serves as a
social corrective, helping people recognize behaviors that are inhospitable to human
flourishing. A large source of the comic is in recognizing our superiority over the
subhuman. Anything that threatens to reduce a person to an object—either animal or
mechanical—is prime material for humor. No doubt, Bergson's theory accounts for
much of physical comedy and bodily humor, but he seems to over-estimate the
necessity of mechanical encrustation. It is difficult to see how his theory can
accommodate most jokes and sources of humor coming from wit.
Three major criticisms of the incongruity theory are that it is too broad to be very
meaningful, it is insufficiently explanatory in that it does not distinguish between
non-humorous incongruity and basic incongruity, and that revised versions still fail
to explain why some things, rather than others, are funny. We have already addressed
the third criticism: it confuses the object of humor with the response. What is at issue
is the definition of humor, or how to identify humor, not how to create a humor-
generating algorithm. The incongruity theorist has a response to this criticism as well,
since they can claim that humor is pleasure in incongruity.
d. Play Theories
Describing play theories of humor as an independent school or approach might
overstate their relative importance, although they do serve as a good representative of
theories focused on the functional question. By looking at the contextual
characteristic, play theories try to classify humor as a species of play. In this general
categorization effort, the play theorists are not so much listing necessary conditions,
as they are asking us to look at humor as an extension of animal play. They try to call
our attention to the structural similarities between play contexts and humorous
context, to suggest that what might be true of play, might be true of humor as well.
Play theorists often take an ethological approach to studying humor, tracing it back
through evolutionary development. They look at laughter triggers like tickling, that
are found in other species, to suggest that in humor ontogeny recapitulates
phylogeny. In The Enjoyment of Laughter(1936), Max Eastman develops a play theory
of humor with an adaptive story. He thinks we can find analogies of humor in the
behavior of animals, especially in the proto-laughter of chimps to tickling. He goes so
far as to argue that the wagging tail of a happy dog is a form of humorous laughter,
since Eastman wants to broaden the definition of laughter to encompass other
rhythmic responses to pleasure. Speaking more specifically of humor, he argues that
"we come into the world endowed with an instinctive tendency to laugh and have this
feeling in response to pains presented playfully" (p. 45). On Eastman's account, what
is central to humor and play is that both require taking a disinterested attitude
towards what might otherwise be seen as serious.
Eastman considers humor to be a form of play, because humor involves a
disinterested stance, certain kinds of humor involve mock aggression and insults, and
because some forms of play activities result in humorous amusement. Since Eastman
defines play as the adoption of this disinterested attitude, humor would count as a
form of play on his definition, but this seems both too restrictive and too vague to
serve as an adequate definition of play. In Homo Ludens (1938), Johan Huizinga
criticizes identifying play with laughter or the comic. Though both seem to involve
"the opposite of seriousness," there are crucial asymmetries. Laughter, he argues, is
particular to humans, whereas, play is found in other mammals and birds. Also, if we
allow for certain types of competitive play, then a non-serious attitude is not essential
to play, as it seems to be for humor. Identifying the comic, or humor, with play is
problematic, since "in itself play is not comical for either for the player or public"
(1938, p. 6). Huizinga questions whether humor and play share any necessary
conditions, a requirement of the relationship if humor is a subtype of play. This will,
of course, depend on how we describe humor and play, two equally elusive notions.
Play theorists are primarily concerned with the problem of determining the function
of humor in order to explain how it might have adaptive value, a task taken up by
other biological theories of humor. They argue that similarities between play and
humor suggest that the adaptive value of play might be similar to that of humor.
Other researchers focused on the functional questions have described humor as
having value in cognitive development, social skill learning, tension relief, empathy
management, immune system benefits, stress relief, and social bonding. Though
these questions are primarily addressed by psychologists, sociologist,
anthropologists, and medical researchers, their studies rely on and contribute to an
evolving notion of just what counts as humor. Though the functional question is
foremost in these theories, play theory tries to give humor a genus by offering some
differentiating characteristics, essential to humor.
Author Information
Aaron Smuts
Email: [email protected]
University of Wisconsin-Madison
U. s. A.