Jose Colen, Elisabeth Dutartre-Michaut (Eds.) Companion To Raymond Aron
Jose Colen, Elisabeth Dutartre-Michaut (Eds.) Companion To Raymond Aron
Edited by
José Colen and Elisabeth Dutartre-Michaut
THE COMPANION TO RAYMOND ARON
Copyright © José Colen and Elisabeth Dutartre-Michaut, 2015.
Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 2015 978-1-137-52242-9
All rights reserved.
First published in 2015 by
PALGRAVE MACMILLAN®
in the United States— a division of St. Martin’s Press LLC,
175 Fifth Avenue, New York, NY 10010.
Where this book is distributed in the UK, Europe and the rest of the world,
this is by Palgrave Macmillan, a division of Macmillan Publishers Limited,
registered in England, company number 785998, of Houndmills,
Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS.
Palgrave Macmillan is the global academic imprint of the above companies
and has companies and representatives throughout the world.
Palgrave® and Macmillan® are registered trademarks in the United States,
the United Kingdom, Europe and other countries.
ISBN 978-1-349-57463-6 ISBN 978-1-137-52243-6 (eBook)
DOI 10.1007/978-1-137-52243-6
Foreword ix
Pierre Manent
Series Editors’ Preface xi
Introduction 1
Elisabeth Dutartre-Michaut and José Colen
1. Life and Works: Raymond Aron, Philosopher and Freedom Fighter 3
Nicolas Baverez
Pierre Manent
T his volume succeeds in bringing to light, with sobriety and nuance, the rare
virtues and uncommon merits of an outstanding political thinker. After his
death in 1983, friends and foes alike were inclined to think that Raymond Aron’s
star would dim with the passing of the political order on which he had shed so
much light. The demise of communism and the ensuing end of the Cold War
were supposed to usher us into a new world definitively safe for democracy, and
which was more in need of brand new “democratic theories” cleverly deduced
than of old-fashioned political wisdom painstakingly acquired. The events of
September 11 cruelly dispelled these fond illusions. We were confronted anew
with the tragedy of history. Raymond Aron, while well aware of the variety of
“processes” which brought peace, comfort and order to the life of modern man,
had always been alert to the uncertainty, accidents, and disorder, to the “drama”
of human history. However impressive the accomplishments of modern science,
economy and politics, they have not freed human beings from the risks, the
greatness and misery of political life. Raymond Aron is a writer and thinker for
difficult times, and human beings always live in difficult times.
Raymond Aron was a learned man, and he constantly improved on an impres-
sive command of social sciences, including sociology, economics, strategy, and
political science and philosophy. While he delighted in analyzing the theoretical
subtleties of these sciences, and mapping out their relations and respective limits,
and thus greatly contributed to enlightening his various listeners and readers, he
never lost sight of their practical, especially political bearing. In this sense, he
was this very rare bird, a theoretical man who took very seriously the realm of
action. On the one hand, he never tired of questioning the limits of historical
knowledge, the relationship between economy and politics, or the possibility of
a science of international relations; on the other hand, he was constantly, even
anxiously asking the question: “what is to be done?” The cynosure of his deep-
est ambition was the producing of what he called “praxeology,” or theory of
action, a theoretical endeavor for which Clausewitz’s theory of war provided the
template. Using more traditional terms, we could say that his multifaceted œuvre
x F OR E WOR D
embodies one of the most successful efforts in the twentieth century to elaborate
a political philosophy as practical philosophy.
The most potent and enduring hindrance to practical philosophy in the past
century was the prestige of History and the prevalence of what was called “phi-
losophy of history.” While very different in their style and content, the theo-
retical endeavors belonging to this genus have this character in common: they
consider that the innumerable human actions in the past constitute a coherent
system that gives us the clue to future human actions. What has been done is
the clue to what is to be done. From the time of writing his dissertation to his
last courses and publications, Aron made strenuous efforts to break free from
the stranglehold of this kind of “evolutionist” or necessitarian thinking. The
most politically influential of these doctrines was of course Marxism, of which
Aron became the nemesis in France. But he was also very interested in Comte’s
positivism which, while no friend of socialism, nourished the hope of bringing
action under the rule of a demonstrative science. Marxism and Comteanism
shared the ambition to fi nally substitute the administration of things for the
governing of men. Now, Aron maintained that men could not rid themselves
of the burden of politics because it was up to them as free and moral beings to
manage and order their lives. This inescapable end or purpose calls for two kinds
of theoretical endeavors.
The fi rst deals with the internal order of the political association, which
comes under the jurisdiction of a fairly complete and rigorous, but not demon-
strative, knowledge: following on the examples of Aristotle and Montesquieu,
Aron understood his task as the elucidation, by means of comparison, of the
several modern political régimes. For him, just as for his predecessors, this the-
oretical or analytical effort had an immediate practical import: Aron did not
tire of explaining that modern people had to choose between a “constitutional-
pluralist” regime or a one-party, totalitarian regime. The sobriety, justice, and
fi rmness with which Aron conducted this effort are for the reader a political
education by itself.
The second deals, so to speak, with the political disorder that obtains between
political bodies or nations. It is much less amenable to a complete and rigorous
knowledge. In a sense, Aron was even more interested in understanding inter-
national disorder than national (relative) order. It was more of a challenge. How
do you give an account of what has been done or what should be done in a realm
where laws are unavailable and which lacks the (relative) stability and predict-
ability of a cohesive society? He gave much thought to what Thucydides in
ancient times and Clausewitz in modern times accomplished. I am confident that
the next generation, if they are thoughtful, will ponder what Aron accomplished
on this score in the twentieth century.
The contributors to this volume originate from various European coun-
tries and from the United States of America. They are witness to the breadth of
Raymond Aron’s appeal, which their contributions will enlarge and deepen.
SERIES EDITORS’ PREFACE
This Companion offers a guide to the most important themes in those works. Its
editors have assembled a group of outstanding scholars intimately familiar with
both Aron’s work and the work of the thinkers with whom he entered into dia-
logue. Their essays offer valuable guidance in the three major strands of Aron’s
thought: the theory and history of international relations, political sociology and
philosophy, and the history of ideas.
INTRODUCTION
R aymond Aron, certainly one of the great political thinkers of the twentieth
century, is known especially for his criticism of and committed struggle
against totalitarianism. While even his contemporaries had become increasingly
aware that his work in this connection was wide ranging and significant, it is
clear today that he is a major figure among twentieth-century French intellectu-
als, and that his inf luence is especially pronounced among French liberals of the
twenty-first century. We are therefore pleased to introduce, or to reintroduce,
English readers to a lucid and demanding body of thought that makes no conces-
sions to intellectual indolence or cowardice. Henry Kissinger loved to speak of
Raymond Aron as his teacher, as someone who encouraged the effort to under-
stand, explain, and interpret the movement of modern society by confronting
reality and our awareness of it.
Many people have already paid homage to Aron’s unusual intellectual cour-
age: he often ran against the current and found himself ostracized, and his exam-
ple is still inspiring. Nicolas Baverez, author of the fi nest biography of Aron,
will briefly give us such an account in the initial chapter of this work. However,
many scholars have recently devoted serious academic studies to his thought and
his theories, if not his philosophy. The rich legacy of this thinker is coming into
ever-sharper focus.
The Companion to Raymond Aron is meant to supplement Raymond Aron’s
autobiography (Mémoires), biographies, and main works that are still read in uni-
versities in the Anglo-Saxon world, and to help guide the reader through his
thought. While the book does not entirely ignore his political commitments and
activities, its main purpose will be to aid in the study of Aron’s political, socio-
logical, and philosophical thought and writings. This is especially important,
even necessary, due to the breadth of Aron’s corpus and the lack of good English
translations of many of his works. He is one of the few important modern politi-
cal thinkers currently lacking a companion of this sort.
Aron’s work ranges over the most diverse academic disciplines, from nuclear
strategy to sociology to the philosophy of history, making it almost impossible
for any researcher to address his thought in all these areas. Aron published more
than 35 books during his lifetime, some with hundreds or even thousands of
2 E L I S A BE T H DU TA RT R E - M IC H AU T A N D JO S É C OL E N
pages, and almost as many posthumous texts of equal length have been pub-
lished as well (and these do not include his more than 200 academic articles and
countless editorials for newspapers.) In the words of Hoff mann, “the breadth of
Raymond Aron’s work has always led commentators, and even his disciples, to
despair.”1 To forestall this despair, we have gathered here a rare group of fi rst-
rate experts and thinkers, all animated by a desire to provide a comprehensive
Companion to this most comprehensive of thinkers, which is long overdue. In
addition, this book offers a useful guide to English translations of Aron’s work as
well as to a selection of the secondary literature on it in the fi nal chapter.
The book is organized into three parts that together encompass the three main
strands of his thought: theory and history of international relations, political soci-
ology and philosophy, and the history of ideas. After a brief presentation of the
theme, prepared with the help of Bryan-Paul Frost and Scott Nelson, the open-
ing chapter of each part presents an account of Aron’s main works on the sub-
ject within the framework of his thought. Each part is composed of six chapters
written by contributors from different countries with different backgrounds and
viewpoints, with their scholarship on Raymond Aron being the only common
denominator among them. The fi nal part was the most challenging to accomplish,
since it required both an excellent knowledge of Aron’s own work and a mastery
of the thinkers and philosophers with whom Aron engaged in fruitful dialogue.
Some subjects and a few of Aron’s works are approached in different chapters,
and hence there is a certain degree of overlap. The editors have not tried to
force any consensus among the perspectives offered here, and so they have limited
themselves simply to pointing out, at the beginning of each part, the “meeting
points” of this plurality. Michael Oakeshott, the British philosopher, suggests that
a conversation is a meeting-place among different universes of discourse, and that
such a conversation “is impossible in the absence of a diversity of voices” mutually
recognizing each other,2 that there is no place in it, however, for a symposiarch
or arbiter, and, if there are at times arguments and answers, that there does not
exactly need to be a conclusion or an assimilation of the various theories. Such an
approach is in harmony with the spirit of Aron’s work itself.
We would like to thank all the contributors and we are grateful for the sup-
port of the Societé des Amis de Raymond Aron as well as the encouragement of
Dominique Schnapper. We also would like to thank the editors at Palgrave
for their patience and help and Chris Schaefer and Linda Haapajärvi for their
translations. But special acknowledgments should go to Scott Nelson, Samuel
Wigutow, Gabriel Bartlett, and Daniel Mahoney, whose assistance and boundless
efforts have helped make this volume possible.
Notes
1. Stanley Hoffmann, “Raymond Aron et la théorie des relations internationales,”
Politique étrangère, no. 4, 2006, [reimp. 1983], 723.
2. Michael Oakeshott, “The Voice of Poetry in the Conversation of Mankind,”
Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays. Foreword by Timothy Fuller, Indianapolis,
Liberty Press, 1991, 490.
CHAPTER 1
Nicolas Baverez
the ranks of “Free France” to wage war against Hitler’s Germany. In 1945, con-
tinuing his reflections on ideologies as secular religions, he exposed the totalitar-
ian and expansionist nature of the USSR, which was leading inevitably to the
bipolarization of the world. During the 1950s, he became a proponent of the
strategic revolution carried out by nuclear deterrence and of the balance of ter-
ror that regulated the Cold War, defi ned by the formula, “Peace impossible; war
improbable.”1 In 1957, in his work La Tragédie algérienne, he exposed the political
and strategic reasons that made Algeria’s independence inevitable in a continu-
ation of the disintegration of the European empires.2 From the 1960s onward,
he cast light on the contradictions of modern freedom and democracy, always
recalling their political and moral superiority to Soviet totalitarianism, includ-
ing its post-Stalinist versions. Finally, as far as economics were concerned, he
was a proponent of the market economy of the Trente Glorieuses (postwar boom)
and the reopening of planned and administered production systems, up to the
evolution of the Bretton-Woods system, and passing through the creation of the
European common market.
Aron’s thinking was both fully political and fully liberal, and it influenced
French philosophy and sociology profoundly. Aron contributed in a decisive way
to introducing Max Weber’s work in particular, and German phenomenology
and sociology in general, to France, thereby paving the way for the criticism
of positivism and the birth of French philosophy of history—as Jean Cavaillès
emphasizes. He was one of the fathers of existentialism, his dissertation having
been a clear existentialist manifesto. He rediscovered Tocqueville, and paved the
way for François Furet’s work. He was the best French scholar on Marx, making
allowances, on the one hand, for the fertile analyst of industrial society, and on
the other for the accursed prophet of revolution. He was also a biographer and an
interpreter of Clausewitz, on the basis of whose works he examined the muta-
tions of that chameleon—war.
Historically and politically, Raymond Aron remains one of the heroes of the
struggle for freedom and reason in the twentieth century: “When we fight for
something,” he insists in Le Spectateur engagé, “we don’t calculate the probabilities
of winning or losing . . . when the choice is to survive or to die, we do not cal-
culate, we fight.”3 His essays, editorials, and interventions served as an antidote
to the dominant influence of Marxism and contributed primarily—both to the
resistance of French society to communism and to the conversion of intellectuals
to anti-totalitarianism. He was also one of the few Frenchmen to gain a truly
international audience, a fact that led him to have contacts among great scholarly
figures (Hayek, Oppenheimer, and Polanyi), political leaders (Kissinger), and
dissidents from Eastern Europe (Solzhenitsyn) who had their books circulated in
samizdat form. As for the French and their rulers, Aron served, in the formula-
tion of Claude Lévi-Strauss, as the “teacher of intellectual hygiene.” As for other
countries, he was one of the very few who saved the honor of French intellectuals
through his action against Nazism in the ranks of Free France, against Stalinism
during the Cold War, thereby serving freedom and the victims of totalitarian-
ism, and supporting both Eastern dissidents and boat people. His choices show
L I F E A N D WOR K S 5
that courage is not the monopoly of men of action, but can also be the privilege
of men of thought.
* * *
The life of Raymond Aron, whose career should have followed the path of a
conventional scholar and philosopher, was telescoped by the very history that he
had chosen as his subject of study, marked by ruptures and personal trials.
Raymond Aron was born in 1905 into a family of Jewish origin that was,
however, fully integrated, patriotic, and republican. A brilliant school record
led him to the École normale supérieure in 1924, where he befriended Sartre
and Nizan while at the same time he met frequently with Alain. After obtain-
ing a graduate diploma (agrégation) in philosophy, Aron lived in Germany from
1930 to 1933—fi rst in Cologne and then in Berlin. His fi rst turning point was
intellectual: reading Max Weber and the phenomenologists—including Husserl
and Heidegger—he parted ways with the idealism and positivism that then
dominated the Sorbonne. He decided upon his destiny during a walk along the
Rhine: “to understand or know my time as honestly as possible, without losing
awareness of the limits of my knowledge; to detach myself from the current time
without being resigned to the role of a spectator.”4 His second turning point was
political: the rise of Nazism and the elimination of the Weimar Republic led him
to break with the pacifi sm of his youth.
Assigned on his return from Germany first to a high school in Le Havre, and
then to the Centre de documentation économique et sociale at the École normale
supérieure, Aron worked on his dissertation while publishing an essay on German
sociology—“La Sociologie allemande contemporaine” (1935)—and assiduously
attending Alexandre Kojève’s seminars (on the Phenomenology of Spirit), which
introduced Hegel to French philosophy. The dissertation dedicated to the phi-
losophy of history5 that he defended in 1938 under the supervision of Brunschvicg
caused a scandal in France by inaugurating the “epistemology of suspicion” within
the social sciences. The 1930s therefore passed under the shadow of a growing
tension between Aron’s personal happiness and intellectual success, on the one
hand, and his desperation as a citizen faced with the passivity of democracies and
the paralysis of France in the face of the Great Depression and the rise of totalitari-
anism, on the other. Alongside Élie Halévy, Raymond Aron was therefore among
the first to highlight the novelty of, and the common traits linking, Fascism,
Nazism, and Communism, their common opposition to democracy, and the lack
of any solution other than war to the challenge they presented. This became espe-
cially clear during a communication to the French Philosophical Society (Société
française de philosophie) that he delivered on June 17, 1939.
Drafted into the army in 1939 and assigned as chief of a weather station to the
north of Mézières, which proved to be at the center of the German onslaught,
Aron managed to withdraw his platoon just north of Paris, and then cross the
Loire to reach Bordeaux. He answered General de Gaulle’s call in June of 1940
and left for London, where he headed the magazine France Libre, until the allied
6 N I C O L A S B AV E R E Z
liberation. The Second World War was a sequence of shocks, what with the mul-
tiple dramas of defeat, the exile that forced him to leave his wife Suzanne and his
daughter Dominique behind, his dismissal from the university due to the statute
against the Jews that the Vichy regime applied, the destruction of his books, and
fi nally, above all else, the genocide of the Jews.
On his return to France, Raymond Aron chose not to take up the post from
which he had been dismissed at the University of Toulouse, and instead became
a journalist; fi rst in Point de Vue, and then, after the short-lived direction of the
Ministry of Information by André Malraux on behalf of General de Gaulle, in
Combat and Le Figaro. The launching of the Cold War by Stalin saw Aron stand
with André Malraux as one of the few French intellectuals to oppose commu-
nism directly, and this led him to campaign in the RPF and participate in the
Movement for Cultural Freedom especially. This commitment to democracy
against the Soviet system brought him into complete isolation. Ostracized by the
university and the intelligentsia, he quarreled with his classmate, Sartre, as well
as with most of his friends from his years at the École normale supérieure. From
1947 to 1955, he was a lonely man.
Aron made his return to the University in 1955. Despite the smear cam-
paign fueled by the publication of The Opium of the Intellectuals,6 he was elected
with a majority of one vote to the chair in sociology at the Sorbonne in June of
1955. Aron then pursued, until his death in 1983, a fruitful double activity as a
scholar—at the Sorbonne and at the Collège de France, to which he was elected
in 1970 while passing through the École des hautes études—and as a columnist,
fi rst for Le Figaro (1947–1977) and then for L’Express (1977–1983).
Fully recognized abroad both as a scholar and as a leading analyst, in France,
Aron remained in a marginal position while always defending the minority view.
He unleashed the fury of the nationalist right—to the point of becoming a target
of the OAS—by taking a stand in 1957 in favor of Algerian independence. He
became the Gaullists’ bête noire owing to his criticism of de Gaulle’s concept of
national independence and the resulting weakness of the democracies against
the Soviet Union. While he had initially been one of the harshest critics of the
university’s archaism and a strong advocate for its reform, in May of 1968, his
stance against the nihilism of the students and their mythical revolution (révolu-
tion introuvable) made him the scapegoat of the furious revolutionaries and their
sycophants, including Sartre. Aron wanted to reform the university, not destroy
it. Again, the facts proved him right.
Even though the defense of democracy and anti-totalitarianism prevailed
in the 1970s—especially under the influence of the shocking revelations of
Solzhenitsyn—Aron’s reconciliation with the family of leftist intellectuals from
which he had come had to be deferred until the end of the decade: a symbolic
handshake with Sartre took place on June 20, 1979, on the occasion of a press
conference in the Hotel Lutétia gathered in support of the boat people fleeing
communist Vietnam. The French reserved their enthusiasm for the Spectateur
engagé (1981) and Mémoires (1983), which remain the greatest commentaries on
the history of the twentieth century. Raymond Aron died a few weeks after
their publication in October 17, 1983, while working on a new book about the
L I F E A N D WOR K S 7
last years of the twentieth century,7 succumbing to a heart attack while leaving
the law courts to which he had come in order to testify on behalf of Bertrand de
Jouvenel, whom Zeev Sternhell had accused of fascism.
Aron did not see the outcome of the history of the twentieth century in 1989,
with the fall of the Berlin Wall marking the victory of democracy against the
Soviet system and of nations against empires, things for which he had fought
so hard. He paid a high price for his struggle on behalf of freedom and reason,
but his lucidity and courage enabled him to overcome both the attacks—the
violence and the bad faith that are illustrated by the absurd dictum that “it is
better to be wrong with Sartre than to be right with Raymond Aron”—and
the personal misfortunes that marked his life. The latter involved the collapse
of his father Gustave, who was ruined by the crisis of the 1930s, the death of
his mother Suzanne in May 1940, the debacle of his departure for London and
the anguish of leaving his wife and daughter in France, the shock of the Shoah,
the birth of his daughter Laurence with Down’s Syndrome, and the death of
his daughter Emmanuelle, who suffered from a devastating case of leukemia in
1950.
Aron defi ned his work as “a reflection on the twentieth century in the light of
Marxism, and an attempt to illuminate all areas of modern society—the economy,
social relations, class relations, political systems, and relations between nations
and ideological discussions.”8 He followed the principle of thinking about his-
tory as it is and not as we dream of it.
Freeing himself from the traditional divisions among academic disciplines,
Aron explored many fields of knowledge—philosophy, sociology, history, inter-
national relations, ideological controversy, and commentary on current events.
His thought fi nds its unity in a conception of the human condition that he devel-
oped in his thesis, Introduction to the Philosophy of History (1938)9. It is summarized
in one formula: “Man is in history; man is historical; man is a history.” Human
existence is tragic, which requires each person to decide his fate based on partial
knowledge and limited reasoning. However, that does not mean that we are
doomed to despair and absurdity, because commitment allows one to overcome
the relativity of history and the conditioned character of knowledge in order
to access a part of freedom and truth. For Aron, freedom comes fi rst, but this
primacy is historical and not philosophical. It should both be built and defended
while taking into account the geopolitical configurations, the political and social
institutions, the economic systems, and the values of the age.
In light of the fact that the twentieth century took place under the shadow of
ideologies,—secular religions that intended to supplant democracy—Aron dedi-
cated a large part of his work to a critical commentary on Marx—in which he
separates the sociologist of the industrial revolution from the accursed prophet
of the revolution—and on Marxists—fi rst and foremost among them Sartre,
Merleau-Ponty, and Althusser. He demonstrated the impossibility of reconcil-
ing the idea of a predetermined direction of history with liberty; he contrasted
Western economies’ development with the prediction that capitalism would
meet an inevitable crisis; and he emphasized the perverse mixture of faith and
terror that served as the cement of the Soviet empire. He found himself regularly
8 N I C O L A S B AV E R E Z
opposed to Sartre, the “petit camarade” (little companion) of his Normale School
years, with whom he fell out in 1947 when the Cold War began.
Both Aron and Sartre are philosophers of freedom and commitment. Man
is what he chooses to be, and it is by deciding about himself that he establishes
himself and translates his freedom into actions. However, while such freedom
is rooted in history and democratic institutions for Aron, for Sartre, it takes the
shape of a metaphysics of violence. For Sartre, consciousness, which is in essence
free, fi nds itself alienated by others; it can only overcome this contradiction and
gain freedom by engaging in a collective revolt, welded by a pact of mutual
terror. Personal rebellion and collective violence are at once the instrument of
empowerment of individuals and the motor of history. This anarcho-metaphysi-
cal theory contains three risks: absolute freedom of conscience allows all options,
including that of totalitarian ventures; fragmentation and discontinuity of con-
sciousness in time eliminate any accountability; and the glorification, especially
of violence and terrorism, is sheer historical nonsense in a century character-
ized by mass killings and terror. Aron, by contrast, starts by noting the fragility
of political freedom and the need to preserve it. A miraculous creation of the
European Enlightenment is gradually consolidated by the joining of the demo-
cratic movement and the radical transformation of capitalism, on the one hand,
and comes under fi re from totalitarianism, nationalism, and other threats, on
the other. Deprived of a transcendent foundation or a unitary principle, it fi nds
itself torn by the heterogeneity of political, civil, and social equality, undermined
by egalitarian tensions, and threatened by collective passions and demagogues.
Freedom is always something to be won, the result of the daily action of citizens
and peoples who, with the help of the institutions, govern their impulses toward
violence, chaos, and unreason.
From this point of view, Aron’s sociology of industrial societies explores the
similarities and differences between liberal and socialist regimes through his
trilogy, which consists of Eighteen Lectures on Industrial Society (1962), The Class
Struggle (1964), and Democracy and Totalitarianism (1965).10 For Aron, “industrial
society is the society in which large companies are the characteristic form of
labor organization” that is associated with the accumulation of capital and the
generalization of economic calculation. The traits that capitalist and communist
societies share do not necessarily converge, since their political structures remain
implacably antagonistic. Pluralism is opposed to a single party, fundamental free-
doms to the existence of a state “truth,” the independence of social agents to
their political control, the rule of law to a bloated apparatus of repression, and
the market to central planning. The primacy of political variables excludes any
symmetry between the two blocs. He also fights the urge to convert pluralism or
the market into “values” in themselves; they are means, not ends. Aron’s politi-
cal liberalism is thus clearly different from liberalism in the utilitarian tradition,
the most complete version of which is presented by Hayek in The Constitution
of Liberty.11 Aron reserves a prominent place for the state, to which it falls to
establish a “civil state” within society and to defend the sovereignty of the nation
within the state of nature that governs the global system.
The study of international relations represents a natural counterpoint to the
analysis of industrial society. On one hand there is the upsurge in violence, with
L I F E A N D WOR K S 9
the alternation of war and peace and the struggles of nations and empires; on the
other hand there is the logic of the market society, bearer at the same time of
a peaceful competition and an individualism that seeks to free itself from state
supervision. His analysis of the operational theaters of World War II, carried out
during his stay in London, led him to the strategic studies field, which he con-
nected early on with his reflections on the conceptualization of the use of nuclear
weapons. He was also a regular commentator on international affairs. In Paix et
guerre (1962), Aron suggests a theoretical interpretation of the global diplomatic
and strategic system based on the key role of states as the only referees in any
recourse to arms. This prominence attributed to sovereign states with respect to
movements in civil societies won him a reputation outside France as the deviser
of Gaullist foreign policy, even though within France he was considered the most
severe critic of General de Gaulle’s “grand design.” Penser la guerre, Clausewitz
(1976) continues the exploration of the paradoxical relationship between vio-
lence and reason, sovereignty and empire. From the ambivalence of the thought
of Clausewitz, who is the theorist both of total war and of limited confl ict, of
the rise to extremes and of the restraint of force, Aron shows how the different
configurations of the international system during the twentieth century—the
European age inherited from the nineteenth century, the period between the
two world wars, and the Cold War—combine popular passions and the interests
of states, the vision of strategists, and the unstable balance of rival powers.
In addition to his academic work, Aron exercised a moral and intellec-
tual authority over French public opinion through his articles in Le Figaro and
L’Express, the liberal journals Preuves, Contrepoint or Commentaire—the last of
which he founded—and even more importantly through his essays shedding
light on geopolitical developments and the domestic situation. The Opium of the
Intellectuals, published in 1955 just before the Soviet invasion of Hungary, awak-
ened a fi rst generation of communist fellow travelers, including François Furet.
Starting in 1957, he took a stance in favor of Algerian independence, which
caused a great scandal among conservatives. In 1968, he analyzed the events
of May as a pseudo-revolution: ideological talk masked the lack of a political
project, leading to a destructive nihilism for both the Republic and the universi-
ties. Les Désillusions du progrès (1969) sets out a meditation on disenchantment in
democratic societies, while Plaidoyer pour l’Europe décadente (1977) urges Europe,
rich and vulnerable, to regain its status as a major political player, escaping the
alternatives of integration into the United States’ sphere of influence or submis-
sion within the Soviet empire.
Aron’s thought combines a philosophy of history and a moral code of action
based on both statesmen’s wisdom and citizens’ engagement. It challenges the
traditional divide between liberalism and politics, for liberalism often under-
estimates the weight of history, the strength of passions and the clash of ambi-
tions, and politics is quick to exonerate itself from any connection with truth
and reason. The formulation of the multiple dimensions of modern societies
reveals the complicated interactions existing between structural changes, the
play of political forces and rival interests and, in sum, men’s irreducible freedom:
“Men create their own history, even if they do not know the history they cre-
ate.” Hence, his method is both realistic, probabilistic, and dialectic. It is realistic
10 N I C O L A S B AV E R E Z
because it rejects any transcendent principle and constantly calls for a moral code
of responsibility; it is probabilistic because it seeks to shed light on the complex-
ity of decisions in history by studying the full range of possible choices; and it is
dialectical because it refuses determinism and Manichaeism, and tries to handle
complexity and uncertainty.
Raymond Aron’s liberal political science fi nds its ultimate horizon in a gam-
ble for the idea of reason, in Kant’s sense. Nothing is more false than to accuse
him of pessimism or to blame him for a kind of resignation. History is only
tragic because man is in the end free to act for better or for worse. This does not
legitimize withdrawal or indifference, but is instead a call to action, a salutary
invitation to citizens and leaders to take charge of their own destiny. Aron’s
ultimate message is made of optimism and hope. It is not inevitable that the last
word should be one of hatred and violence. Against fanatics and cynics, the best
antidote remains reason: “If all civilizations, both ambitious and precarious, are
to achieve the prophets’ dreams in a distant future, what universal vocation could
unite them other than Reason?”12
Aron respected religious faith, for which he reserved a place to which he him-
self did not have access, the idea of a revelation or sacred history remaining funda-
mentally alien to him. He instead considered reason “a hidden universal,” capable
of releasing man from naturalism and historicity, which opens up the possibility
of a reconciliation between power and freedom. After the “death of God” and the
end of ideologies, at the heart of the struggle against the barbarism of genocide and
the mass terror of totalitarian regimes, Aron puts together and traces the outlines
of a moderate and sensible policy, mobilizing the margins of freedom and human
reason to contain unbridled passions and violence. He reminds statesmen that
there is something above politics, namely truth; he reminds men of science and
faith that only partial knowledge is possible; and he reminds citizens that freedom
is never a given but must always be conquered with hard work, determination,
and sometimes the use of arms. A patriot, a cosmopolitan, and a fierce opponent
of totalitarianism, Aron remains one of the major thinkers about freedom in the
twentieth century. His liberal definition of freedom remains just as topical in the
open economy and society of the twenty-fi rst century.
Raymond Aron’s life and work were caught up in the violent history of the
twentieth century and in his fight against totalitarian ideologies. It can therefore
be tempting to celebrate his vision but to lock it up in the past and reduce it to a
historical record: Raymond Aron, a victim of his willingness to look closely into
politics and history, is invaluable for explaining the twentieth century but would
be useless for understanding the twenty-fi rst century.
In fact, the globalization era is radically different from the century of ideolo-
gies, which have been permanently transformed by the disintegration of the Soviet
Union. Capitalism has become universal, and at the same time, its center of grav-
ity has been swinging to Asia and the south. The digital economy has replaced
industrial society. The confl ict between democracy and totalitarianism has faded
before the violent confrontation between identities, cultures, and religious faiths.
The bipolar world of the Cold War, dominated by the two superpowers and regu-
lated by nuclear deterrence, has given way to a very unstable multi-polar system.
L I F E A N D WOR K S 11
The actors are multiplying and diversifying at the same time as states are losing
the monopoly of international politics to markets, and the monopoly of violence
with the rise of terrorist and criminal organizations that now control large areas
and even entire populations. A power capable of preventing strategic or economic
shocks, like the United Kingdom in the nineteenth century or the United States
in the second half of the twentieth century, no longer exists.
Crises, revolutions, and wars have in no way disappeared; they have changed.
Keynesian regulation of closed and administered economies has been replaced by
a globalized capitalism and a growth model characterized by speculative bubbles,
the implosion of which in 2008 came close to causing a new great deflation.
Revolutions are no longer guided by the secular religions of race and class, but
by nationalism, by the revival of empires, and by the reawakening of ancient
religions—from Islamism to orthodoxy. War is reoccupying the front stage of
history, even in democracies. It is no longer cold but hot; it is permanent, in spite
of its varying intensity; it is no longer peripheral but central—from American
defeats in Iraq and Afghanistan to the rising tensions in the South China Sea or
to Russian intervention in Crimea and eastern Ukraine, while the chaos of civil
war devastates Iraq, Syria, and Libya, and a terrorist arc runs from Senegal to
Afghanistan, and from Boko Haram to the Taliban, via ISIS.
The conceptual framework underlying the Aronian analysis of the history of
the twentieth century as resulting from the confluence of the Enlightenment and
the German philosophy of history is now called into question. It was based, on
the one hand, on a clear distinction between the civil state governing the internal
affairs of nations and the jungle dominating international relations and, on the
other, on the central role of the state as the guarantor of civil peace and national
sovereignty. It was thus around the state, including in particular the form of
the nation-state emerging in Europe from the sixteenth century onwards, that
both the international system and societies were organized. But globalization
has blown these categories apart. The West has lost its monopoly of rule over
capitalism and world history. An international society is emerging, with its own
institutions, norms, and mores, while whole swathes of territory and populations
have gone back to a state of nature. States are bypassed from above, by the open
economy and the birth of continental blocs, and from below, with individuals’
and societies’ increasing independence.
Nothing could be further from the truth, however, than to conclude from this
that Aron’s thinking is out of date, and for at least four reasons.
Aron was one of the fi rst theorists to recognize the advent of the global age,
even if he did not foresee either the collapse of the Soviet Union from inside or
the advent of global capitalism. Starting in 1960, he imagined the future prin-
ciples of globalization—a concept he used starting in 196913 —in a conference
on “The Dawn of Universal History,” which he defi ned as the birth of a human
society living a single history. The globalization age rests precisely on a dialecti-
cal movement between the universal nature of capitalism and technology, on the
one hand, and the instability of a multi-polar system, with a radical heterogene-
ity of values and political institutions, on the other. Twenty-fi rst-century men
share the same history but live in very different places and times: the competition
12 N I C O L A S B AV E R E Z
for leadership between China and the United States; the legacy of the twentieth
century in Cuba or Korea; national rivalries and territorial disputes in Asia, as
in nineteenth-century Europe; the African enlightenment and economic take-
off; and religious wars tearing apart the Arab-Muslim world; all these lie in
seventeenth-century Europe. The fundamental dilemma of our time therefore
appears to be the one that Aron explained in these terms: “Never have men had
so many reasons not to kill each other. Never have they had so many reasons to
feel involved in a single venture. I do not conclude that the age of universal his-
tory will be peaceful. We know that man is a reasonable being, but are men?”14
History, according to Aron, is neither linear nor fi xed. It moves, in accor-
dance with the formula of Arnold Toynbee that he appreciated: “history is again
on the move.” There is a sudden and brutal acceleration of history when the
destinies of individuals, peoples, and states are at stake. In the age of universal
history, cold societies, in Lévi-Strauss’s sense of the word, are confi ned to a few
peoples in Amazonia and Oceania, while almost all of humanity lives in warm
societies, where change is permanent. There are three engines: the long-lasting
evolutions of capitalism, of the international system, and of mentalities; the con-
figuration of power and power relations between states; and political leaders’
will, imagination, and vision.
Far from representing the end of history, globalization has re-ignited history
after the glacial period of the Cold War. If the historical pattern has changed, the
critical issues are still those upon which Aron sought to shed light. The three dia-
lectical transformations he discerned at the heart of modern society—the issues of
equality, socialization, and universality—are still at work, but have spread across
the globe and gained hold in the emerging countries. The contradictions of mod-
ern liberty—torn between an increasingly demanding rationalization of technol-
ogy, behavior, and institutions, on the one hand, and soaring collective passions
on the other, remain: the contradictions of the democracies, which have lost their
ideals and their force as a result of individualism, the atomization of society, the
rise of populism and demagoguery, and the loss of trust in institutions, and which
therefore prove powerless in the face of economic shocks such as the 2008 crash
or the multiplication of external threats—from China’s ambitions to the Russian
imperial revival to the disintegration of the Middle East or the ascent of ISIS and
its project of reconstituting the caliphate; the difficulty of reforming free nations
that have lost control of capitalism and world history; the decisive choice of war or
peace, in the context of the great fatigue from confl ict that has gripped the United
States and launched it on the path of a new isolationism while Europe is trapped
in the illusion of an escape from reality and a farewell to arms; the conditions for
the development and the regulation of global capitalism, when it swings toward
the south and has to tackle the challenges of an aging population, information
technologies, over-indebtedness, and unemployment caused by the bursting of
the speculative bubbles of the 2000s; and fi nally the ecological crisis.
Political liberalism, of which Aron was the greatest representative in the France
of the twentieth century, is the key to the future of democracies. The conclusion
at which Aron arrives in his Opium of the Intellectuals15 has lost none of its urgency:
“Freedom is the essence of Western culture, the foundation of its success, the
secret of its size and influence.” However, this freedom is primarily political, not
L I F E A N D WOR K S 13
economic; it cannot be reduced to the market, which falls within the category of
means, not values; it must, in Karl Popper’s words, “be defended against its own
fanatics.” Aron’s political liberalism is thus an effective antidote to the excesses
that gripped the American superpower in the 1990s and, at the same time, a call
to action issued to the rulers and citizens of the democracies, which need to be
reinvented in order to meet economic and geopolitical upheavals. Free nations are
simultaneously confronted with the legacy of the shock of 2008—low growth,
mass unemployment, and public and private debt—and the rise of populist and
extremist parties, as well as the desire for revenge on the part of new powers in the
south and the revival of empires and jihad launched by part of the Muslim world.
Faced with these shocks in a chain that destabilizes the middle classes constitut-
ing its base, the temptation is to yield to demagoguery or resignation. Aron is a
valuable guide: he calls us to reason and moderation, but also to mobilization and
action. The spiral of violence, the threat to freedom, the exaltation of national-
ism, and the use of protectionism constitute the best services that can be done to
the enemies of freedom. But prudence and equanimity do not necessarily imply
the dissolution of public authority or paralysis—at least passivity—in the face of
groups, forces, and powers whose purpose is to destroy democracy.
Raymond Aron always avoided developing a dogmatic system, imposing a
fi xed doctrine, or founding a school. Aronianism does not gather together the
faithful in receiving communion from the hand of their master. It is a mindset,
an intellectual attitude, and a pedagogy. The mindset consists in constantly com-
paring ideas and facts, and analyzing the course of history without losing sight
of the universality of certain values. His method is composed of four stages—
history, analysis, interpretation, criticism—which make it possible to understand
before judging and committing to action. His pedagogy is one of freedom that is
not innate but that results from the patient work of education. Neither prophet
nor guru, Aron does not give us a recipe that we should apply regardless of
historical configurations, but he warns us against giving up the defense of the
values that enabled the West, particularly in Europe, to invent capitalism and
democracy. At a time when developed countries are subjected to the crossfi re
of competition from the South and the revival of imperial ambitions, Raymond
Aron emphasizes that the leadership won by the West over the modern world
from the late fi fteenth century to the late twentieth century was not the result of
innate advances in the fields of economics, technology, politics, or culture, but
of the ability to bring about a civilization that respects freedoms and the dignity
of men, of the ability to question itself, and of the protection of pluralism and
critical thought. Far from reproducing the patterns of the past and sinking into
the laziness of conservatism, each generation is called to reflect on the principles
of the historical age in which it is immersed, to find in it the will and the means
to adapt to it, without leaving its fate in the hands of an illusory Providence or
an improbable savior.
* * *
to enhance the considerable potential for progress it contains and master the risks
involved. Deifying or cursing it is equally inconsequential. We need to think
about it and take action to put it at the service of freedom. This history can have
no meaning or purpose. Its course is determined entirely by men who can make
it swing toward a radical violence and inhumanity, multiplied by technology,
or put it at the service of prosperity, justice, and peace. In the age of “univer-
sal history,” in the face of the return to major economic crises, the revival of
national and religious fanaticism, and the rebirth of empires, the survival of
freedom requires mobilization and commitment, but also knowledge and politi-
cal reason. This is why Raymond Aron remains inextricably the greatest figure
in French liberal thought of the twentieth century and, at the same time, our
contemporary.
Notes
1. Raymond Aron, Le Grand Schisme, Paris, Gallimard, 1948; Les Guerres en chaîne,
Paris, Gallimard, 1951.
2. Raymond Aron, La Tragédie algérienne, Paris, Plon, 1957.
3. Raymond Aron, Le Spectateur engagé, Paris, Julliard, 1981, 286.
4. Raymond Aron, Mémoires. 50 ans de réflexion politique, Paris, Julliard, 1983, 53.
5. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire: Essai sur les limites de
l’objectivité historique, Paris, Gallimard, “Bibliothèque des Idées,” 1938.
6. Raymond Aron, L’Opium des intellectuels, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, “Liberté de
l’esprit,” 1955.
7. Raymond Aron, Les Dernières Années du siècle, Paris, Julliard, 1984.
8. Raymond Aron, Le Spectateur engagé, Paris, Julliard, 1981, 299–300.
9. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire. Essai sur les limites de
l’objectivité historique, Paris, Gallimard. « Bibliothèque des Idées », 1938.
10. Raymond Aron, Dix-Huit Leçons sur la société industrielle, Paris, Gallimard, “Idées”,
1962 ; La Lutte de classes. Nouvelles leçons sur les sociétés industrielles, Paris, Gallimard,
« Idées », 1964 ; Démocratie et totalitarisme, Paris, Gallimard, « Idées », 1965.
11. Friedrich A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago, University, of Chicago
Press, 1960.
12. Aron, Mémoires, 729.
13. Raymond Aron, Les Désillusions du progrès. Essai sur la dialectique de la modernité,
Paris, Calmann-Lévy, “Liberté de l’esprit,” 1969, 231.
14. Raymond Aron, “L’Aube de l’histoire universelle,” conference given in London
on February 18, 1960, under the sponsorship of the Society of Friends of the
Hebrew University of Jerusalem, published in Dimensions de la Conscience histo-
rique, Paris, Plon, 1961, 295.
15. 11 Raymond Aron, L’Opium des intellectuels, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, “Liberté de
l’esprit,” 1955, 315.
PART I
INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS:
“HISTORY IS ON THE MOVE”
history and praxeology, and how each informs the other. Aron was one of the
few international relations theorists who put praxeology at the forefront of his
analysis, but only because he had so carefully surveyed the historical landscape
(and vice versa).
Jean-Vincent Holeindre’s chapter explores Aron’s writings on war and strat-
egy. Holeindre begins by reminding us of the essentially interdisciplinary char-
acter of Aron’s oeuvre. This is apparent from even a cursory glance at the table
of contents of his massive work Peace and War, which comprehensively analyzes
international relations by systematizing theory, sociology, history, and praxeol-
ogy. As Holeindre reminds us, Aron was the fi rst to introduce into France a
sociological theory of international relations, refusing to reduce such a crucial
project to the study of history or legal rules (although he integrated these two
topics into his analysis as well). Holeindre also fi nds room for the applicability
of Aron’s observations to the state of war today. Aron had a great deal to say
about the decisive effect that atomic weapons had on diplomacy in his era, but
he also recognized the impact of psychological and guerrilla warfare, terror-
ism, and irregular confl icts—as waged, for example, by the Algerians and the
Vietnamese.
In the next chapter, Matthias Oppermann argues that we should understand
Aron’s spirited defense of liberal democracy in light of his experience of the
convulsions of German politics and society in the 1930s. For Aron’s sojourn in
Germany from 1930 to 1933 had not only introduced him to a wide array of
important German thinkers, it had also underscored the fundamental fragil-
ity of liberal democracy, especially in France, and thus awakened him from his
pacifist slumber and brought him back to French Republican patriotism. His
commentary during the lead-up to the Second World War was a plea to his
countrymen—and to any defender of liberal democracy more generally—for
them to demonstrate the bravery and resolution necessary to conserve their cur-
rent political system, however great its faults, in the face of the much greater
threat of tyranny. Aron also discovered after the war that “history was again on
the move,” and he would spend much more time and effort rephrasing and reiter-
ating his stance on totalitarianism in order to deal with its deceptively friendlier
incarnation.
Raymond Aron’s ongoing commentary on the Cold War is the topic of Carlos
Gaspar’s chapters. Here Gaspar makes extensive use of Aron’s works on histoire-
se-faisant, including his many articles published in Le Figaro and L’Express. Aron’s
versatility in political commentary, sociology, international relations, and phi-
losophy placed him at a unique vantage point from which he could survey the
unfolding of history little by little and integrate these details within a broader
vision of the main trends of the twentieth century in particular and his philoso-
phy of history in general. Gaspar confirms the validity of Aron’s central insights
into the nature of the Cold War: decolonization brought about the end of the
old empires, and while the rivalry between the West and the Soviet Union never
erupted into nuclear war, it nevertheless remained a “bellicose peace.” Even
though the liberal democracies began to reveal problems of their own, namely,
I N T E R NAT IONA L R E L AT ION S 17
a diminished capacity for collective action, Aron had faith that the confl ict
between the West and the Soviet Union would result in liberty.
Peace and War among Nations is clearly Aron’s masterpiece in the field of inter-
national relations, and Bryan-Paul Frost seeks here to unpack its main tenets.
Beginning with Aron’s rich historical analysis, Frost shows that although the
twentieth century was unique (what with nuclear weapons and the worldwide
extension of the diplomatic field), it could still be understood by using the same
conceptual tools used previously—most notably, those elaborated by Clausewitz
and others. In fact, Frost shows that Aron did not believe that nuclear weapons
had effaced traditional notions of diplomatic, strategic, and moral conduct: the
Machiavellian and Kantian dilemmas faced in the past were the same ones faced
in the present. Consequently, Aron’s theoretical and sociological framework was
equally applicable during the Cold War as it had been in the past.
Joël Mouric discusses Aron’s gradual discovery of Clausewitz, as well as the
many misinterpretations and injustices from which both the German strategist’s
magnum opus, Vom Kriege, and what one might also call Aron’s magnum opus,
Penser la guerre, Clausewitz, suffered. Although it is a shame that Aron did not
write the great work expected of him on Marx, his opting for Clausewitz as the
subject of a major study should come as no surprise: both Clausewitz and Aron
had lost their homelands for some time during a war; moreover, of all the think-
ers Aron had dealt with, Clausewitz most accurately fit the description of a man
who made critical decisions and who withdrew to ponder the nature of his field.
In Aron’s in-depth study of that man we are made privy to the various facets of
Aron’s thinking that justify this Companion: the relation between knowledge or
theory and action; the interweaving of process and drama; the need to explain
how our era is both fundamentally the same and fundamentally different (for
Clausewitz the new factor was Napoleon and total war; for Aron it was nuclear
weapons); the desire to mitigate the increasingly destructive effects of war, even
if it is inevitable.
Carlos Gaspar rounds off this part with a chapter on Aron and the end of the
Cold War, an end that caught everyone by surprise, but would have comforted
Raymond Aron.
CHAPTER 2
Jean-Vincent Holeindre
which paved the way to the war. They are also conceptually connected, as
“thinking history” has, according to Aron, a double meaning: it implies, on
the one hand, that you must think history in the making, and, on the other
hand, that you must consider events comprehensively within the framework of
universal history.
As a committed spectator and as a philosopher, Aron questioned both real-
ism and pacifism. He indeed pointed to the fact that both these radical views led
to a cul-de sac: the realist gives in to fatalism (“history as usual”) and fails to
identify any progress in history while the pacifist is not fully aware of the tragic
dimension of history and of the reasons why humans are led to resort to violence.
Trained by Alain, the pacifist philosopher, and Leon Brunschvicg, a prominent
representative of French Neo-Kantianism, the young Aron broke with the ideal-
ism of his masters when he was a teaching fellow in Germany in the early 1930s.
A witness to the Second World War, he converted to the classical form of realism
inherited from Machiavelli and Hobbes. He remained, however, faithful to the
rationalism inherited from Kant, as he considered that men could still learn from
history and act more reasonably.
Because he placed war and the state at the center of international relations,
Aron was often regarded as a member of the realist school of international rela-
tions (with Hans Morgenthau and Henry Kissinger as the most prominent fig-
ures). Aron himself rejected this label, considering that international reality
never fits in frozen theoretical models and never corresponds to academic appel-
lations. This is not merely a political issue; it is an epistemological one. Unlike
Morgenthau, Aron did not believe it was possible to develop a general theory
of international politics with one sole, essential criterion of analysis, namely the
national interest of states defi ned in terms of power. For Aron, national interest
largely determines the behavior of states, but the latter cannot be reduced to the
former. Aron argued that passions are added to the national interest defi ned as a
rational choice. Aron never despaired of reason, but he could not accept the idea
that reason was no more than the theory of “rational choice.”
These controversies illustrate a fundamental discussion on the status and scope
of theory in political science, more specifically, in international relations. For
Aron, there could not be any theory of international relations if what that meant
was a set of patterns that would make it possible to explain and predict the actors’
actions and behaviors. Aron favored a comprehensive theory of international
relations, which relied on fi ne sociological studies of the actors that make up the
international system. He was in line with the Weberian project of interpretative
sociology that built on the achievements of philosophy and on the empirical
material provided by history. In this context, the critical philosophy of history,
inherited from Kant and Hegel, has led to a political science that relies on the
contributions of the Weber-inspired historical sociology.
In short, the essential part of Aron’s intellectual effort was to take war, as a
part of politics, seriously. He considered it possible to lay the foundation of a
political science that was to help us understand reality and to enlighten us when we
have to choose between several political options.
22 J E A N -V I NC E N T HOL E I N DR E
Aron’s Oeuvre
Before considering Aron’s actual strategic oeuvre, it is important to recall a few
details of his biography. When Aron became a doctor of philosophy on March
26, 1938, Hitler had just annexed Austria, thereby challenging the European
democracies. Then, after General de Gaulle established himself as the leader
of the opposition to the Vichy government and denounced collaboration in his
June 18, 1940 radio appeal, Aron decided to follow him to London. He became
one of the leading figures of the Resistance journal, La France libre. He wrote
a number of articles on current events, in which he attempted to identify the
issues at stake in the confl ict while expressing his commitment to the cause of
the Resistance. At this time, he developed an interest in strategic thought and
the study of international relations, which became his favorite subject. There is
therefore no doubt that the immediate context played a major role in Aron’s stra-
tegic thought. However, while his project was initially closely linked to personal
experience, it also had a far wider scope.
At the end of the Second World War, Raymond Aron published his first two
works of strategic analysis, Le Grand Schisme (1948) and Les Guerres en chaîne
(1951),6 with a view to exploring in reasoned discourse the idea that the old
world had just come to an end and the new one was just being born. As early as
1948, he was one of the fi rst observers to shed light on the specific nature of the
Cold War by coining what was to become a famous phrase: “impossible peace,
improbable war.” Aron indeed explained that peace was impossible between the
two great victors of World War II, namely the United States and the USSR,
because the ideological opposition between American liberalism and Soviet
communism was a radical one.
War was, however, improbable, as the two Great Powers each possessed atomic
weapons, the power of which had been proven in Hiroshima and Nagasaki in
1945. The atomic bomb completely transformed the strategic landscape: hence-
forth, it would be possible to annihilate the entire planet simply by pressing a
button. The world had entered a cycle of nuclear deterrence and the “balance of
terror,” according to the theory developed by Albert Wohlstetter, the American
strategist of the Rand Corporation, whom Aron first introduced in France in
Le Grand Débat (1963).7 Aron explained that France had no other option than
to become an ally of the United States, so that it might be protected by the
American nuclear umbrella by way of the North Atlantic Treaty Organization
(NATO).
On this point, he disagreed with De Gaulle, who, following his return to
power in 1958, gambled on French strategic independence from the United
States, notably in the nuclear realm. At the time, Aron was one of the main
defenders of the American democracy and one of the main opponents of the
Soviet regime. Yet he was also critical of American policy, warning Europeans
about the American tendency to build an “imperial hegemonic republic.”8 But
most of Aron’s arrows were directed at the Soviets, who, he maintained, were
guilty of depriving their citizens of freedom in the name of equality. This has to
be understood in the context of France’s intellectual battle between the liberals
R A Y M O N D A R O N O N WA R A N D S T R A T E G Y 23
(with Aron as a leading figure) and the communists and their fellow-travelers
(supported by Jean-Paul Sartre, his classmate at the École normale supérieure).
For Aron, depriving citizens of their freedom could never be justified, not
even for the noblest purposes. In his view, socialist collectivism was doomed
because it disregarded the fact that in the modern world, society as a free and
orderly entity is the creation of individuals themselves. The social order can never
be imposed from the top down, by the power of the state. According to Aron,
progressives also err when they claim that perpetual peace can be achieved, as
the human condition feeds on confl ict and the division of the political order into
particular nations.
Raymond Aron’s election as a professor of sociology in the Sorbonne in 1955
allowed him to dedicate himself completely to the theory of international rela-
tions. He then set himself a new challenge, as demanding as his dissertation on
the philosophy of history. He undertook to write a theoretical treatise on inter-
national relations and war, which he published in 1962 under the title Peace and
War: A Theory of International Relations.9 With this book, Raymond Aron sought
to introduce one of the fields of political science to France: international rela-
tions. This field had long been recognized in the Anglo-American world, but in
French universities, it had until this point been explored only by historians and
legal scholars.
Raymond Aron pleaded for a sociological theory of international relations,
arguing that its aim was not merely to study military and diplomatic history, or
the legal rules that structured the international order, but to analyze the relations
between the various actors who made up the “international system.” At the core
of his analysis was the state, which he saw as the key actor in the international
arena. He also argued that as long as there was no world government, states lived
permanently “in the shadow of war.” For Aron, two figures loomed large in
interstate relations: the diplomat, on the one hand, who represents the state in
peacetime; and the soldier, on the other, who wears the nation’s colors in times
of war.
“War is not a man-to-man relation, but a state-to-state relation.” This quota-
tion from Rousseau provided Aron with his initial hypothesis. Aron analyzed
the relations between states in peacetime (through the play of diplomacy) as well
as in wartime (when soldiers and strategists intervene). The book consists of two
main parts. First, Aron explains the theoretical tools and the sociological patterns
that shed light on international relations in general, regardless of the particular
circumstances. Then Aron puts his theory to the test by examining the history
of the Cold War, inviting his readers “to think and to act with the fi rm intention
that the absence of war will be prolonged until the day when peace has become
possible—supposing it ever will.”10 We can see here Aron’s constant concern for
linking the past, the present, and the future.
Peace and War is a pioneering book that opened fertile paths in the area of
strategic and international studies on issues that are still topical at the beginning
of the twenty-fi rst century. For example, Raymond Aron analyzed with great
acumen the terrorist phenomenon in which the use of physical force is closely
related to its psychological effects. Aron explained that terrorism differed from
24 J E A N -V I NC E N T HOL E I N DR E
other forms of violent action in that it generates fear in the civilian population.
Terrorism consists in acting in the midst of populations, making no distinction
between civilians and the military. It does not necessarily cause many casual-
ties, but it triggers a feeling of public fear. Since no one is targeted in particular,
everyone becomes a potential target. This absence of discrimination makes ter-
rorism akin to guerrilla tactics, which themselves operate in the midst of the
population. War, in the classic sense of the term, is based on the discrimination
between fighters and civilians, a discrimination that today tends to disappear. In
fact, most of the victims of today’s confl icts are civilians. Terrorism can therefore
be regarded as the spearhead of the transformation in war. But can we still speak
of war when suicide bombers attack civilians? Does terrorism fall within the
scope of military strategy or of police work?
Aron also analyzed the concept of power, which is often reduced to the mili-
tary and economic capabilities of a state. Being powerful, however, cannot be
reduced to having a set number of weapons or a high GDP. Power depends not
only on having human and material resources available, but also on being able to
deploy them in order to defeat the enemy. In this sense, power is not so much a
possession as a “relationship.” This view of Aron’s has a specific echo in the cur-
rent policy context. Indeed, in today’s confl icts, no matter how competent, over-
equipped, and highly trained armies are, they often fail to make a difference
strategically and politically. The examples of Iraq and Afghanistan are illustra-
tive of this fact: US military supremacy has not prevented political failure. The
United States may still be the world’s largest military power, but US hegemony
has been greatly undermined by the difficulties encountered since the attacks of
September 11, 2001. As early as the 1960s, Aron foresaw the fragility of states
in the face of the guerrilla strategies carried out by groups of “insurgents.” The
issues these groups present have now become central in strategic thinking.
Let us now turn to Aron’s second great strategic piece, Clausewitz, Philosopher
of War (1976)11. This book is divided into two volumes: the fi rst, The European
Age, is dedicated to a meticulous reconstruction of the political and military
thought of Clausewitz; the second, The Global Age, questions the Prussian strate-
gist’s legacy in a context in which war had become protean. After World War II,
“conventional” war between states had indeed been supplanted by the threat of
a nuclear apocalypse, as well as by asymmetric confl icts, such as those between
former European empires (France, the United Kingdom) and colonized peoples
striving for independence.
This last work echoed Aron’s fi rst doctoral dissertation, in which he con-
fronted the German philosophers of history. In his Clausewitz, Aron once again
summoned his core philosophical theory, which he had neglected in works of
more limited scope. Finally, this book allowed him to contribute to a Franco-
German dialogue, to which he was predisposed, owing to the time he had spent
as a young man on the other side of the Rhine and his love of German civiliza-
tion. Thus, analyzing war via Clausewitz was a way for Aron to consider not
only twentieth-century Europe, but also his own personal story.
From a theoretical point of view, this work reflected Aron’s one and only
ambition: to consider with Clausewitz the nature of war while recognizing the
R A Y M O N D A R O N O N WA R A N D S T R A T E G Y 25
diversity of its forms. For Aron, the Prussian strategist had hesitated between
two conceptions of war: war as “a duel” and “a rise to extremes,” and war as an
instrument of politics. Aron believed that Clausewitz had opted for the second
view toward the end of his life (see on this point Joël Mouric’s chapter in this
book): war was, fi rst and foremost, a means to settle through the force of arms
a confl ict that diplomacy had failed to resolve. The role of the ruler was then to
adapt military means to political ends. The ruler had to identify which type of
war he might have to deal with in order to resort to adequate means.
Aron’s “Clausewitz” is a great book not only because it deeply reinvigorated
the interpretation of Clausewitz’s ideas, but mainly because it underlined the
relevance of the Prussian strategist for thinking about the twentieth century wars
marked by totalitarianism. Aron analyzed the way totalitarian ideologues such as
Lenin, then Stalin, Mao and Hitler read Clausewitz. He showed how totalitari-
anism reversed Clausewitz’s formula both in theory and in practice. In totalitar-
ian regimes, war is no longer a military means to achieve a political objective;
war becomes the very purpose of a policy that seeks legitimacy by resorting to
force coupled with terror. War infects the entire political arena, blurring the
distinction between war and politics. The exception becomes the rule; terror is
institutionalized and justified. In the face of totalitarian excesses, democratic and
liberal regimes are given an even greater responsibility. They must perpetuate
Clausewitz’s legacy of a limited and politically controlled war. This responsibil-
ity is all the greater as nuclear power has dramatically altered the strategic land-
scape. With the atomic bomb, politicians now have the power of life and death
over the planet itself. It is up to politicians to prevent the Apocalypse by seeking
diplomatic solutions. By a set of chain reactions, any war may indeed entail the
extinction of humankind. In this new thermonuclear world, politics recovers
a prominent role and democracy is the main warden of a peace that remains
precarious.
Aron’s Legacy
Having clarified the driving ideas of Aron’s strategic thought, let us turn next to
his legacy. To what extent is his approach still relevant to understanding strategic
problems today? As we shall see, Aron did not confi ne himself to interstate con-
fl icts. In the age of “asymmetric” confl icts and nuclear proliferation, his theory
of war remains highly relevant.
The transformation of war12 is undoubtedly one of the major emerging stra-
tegic problems of recent times. The post-Cold War military situation is charac-
terized by a growing vagueness concerning the nature of contemporary armed
confl icts. We may even wonder if interstate wars, which so clearly marked the
twentieth century, have not disappeared for good.
Can terrorism and irregular confl icts, which seem to dominate the strategic
arena today, be considered actual wars? Has war been transformed to the point
that we should abandon the very concept of war and, by the same token, the
Clausewitzian legacy that Aron evokes? We have only to read Aron—among
others—to realize that, in fact, these transformations do not date back to the end
26 J E A N -V I NC E N T HOL E I N DR E
of the Cold War. If we simply consider the modern period (after the French and
American revolutions), we realize that transformations have regularly occurred
in the past. At the beginning of the nineteenth century, during the wars of the
Revolution and the Empire, Clausewitz pointed to a change from the ancien
régime’s limited wars to mass wars employing a greater share of the population
through mass conscription.
A century later, during World War I, the question also arose as to whether the
mechanization of war did not imply a profound transformation of the methods
of war—Aron called it the “technical surprise” in the fi rst chapter of Les Guerres
en chaîne. By “technical surprise,” we must understand the combination of the
unpredictable nature of any war, on the one hand, and the technical progress that
has made weapons, including artillery, deadlier than they were in previous con-
fl icts, on the other. For Aron, the destructive effects of new military techniques
have stirred up hatred between enemies and introduced the logic of total war.
The excesses of technology have reduced the chances for diplomatic success to
naught. Thus, World War I inaugurated the age of total wars, in which all tech-
nological means were deployed to achieve the destruction of the enemy.
From this point of view, the Second World War can be interpreted as a con-
tinuation of the first one. The invention of the nuclear bomb in 1945 is to be
understood in the context of technical bidding; it was the culmination of a process
begun in 1914. It then became possible to destroy the planet by means of nuclear
weapons. The atomic bomb is thus merely a continuation of the “technical sur-
prise” that appeared in World War I. At the same time, the year 1945 is also a
turning point, because the invention of the atomic bomb created an unbridgeable
gap between those countries that had the weapon and those that did not. In Les
Guerres en chaîne, Aron explained that during World War II there were two types
of armed violence—violence linked to the weapons of mass destruction that were
themselves linked to scientific advances, on the one hand, and the violence of
individuals fighting not as soldiers but as rebels clad as civilians, on the other.
After 1945, the world split into two: the West continued to pursue the idea of
a scientific war as it entered “the atomic age,” while Asia and Africa turned to
guerrilla warfare as they fought for independence. And alongside the soldier, the
traditional symbol of interstate wars, two new figures appeared in these confl icts:
the fi rst was the nonhuman, purely technical figure of the atomic bomb; the
second was a human, all-too-human, figure—the partisan. In this new strategic
context, interstate war is caught, on the one hand, between a war of ultimate ends
based on technology and the threat of total destruction and irregular warfare,
in which technological omnipotence is thwarted through psychological means,
on the other. Societies and parties that do not possess either regular armies or
industries or nuclear weapons will respond with guerrilla warfare.
The so-called cold war period that began in 1945 combined two strategic
trends—the nuclear powers’ military superiority on the one hand and the former
colonies’ claims by means of guerrillas on the other.
The cold war, Aron says, “is located at the meeting point of two historical series,
one leading to the development of thermonuclear bombs and ballistic missiles, to
the incessant increase of ever more destructive weapons and even swifter carrying
R A Y M O N D A R O N O N WA R A N D S T R A T E G Y 27
vehicles, the other accentuating the psychological element of the conf lict at the
cost of physical violence. The conjunction of these two series is in itself intelligible:
the more the instruments of force exceed the human scale, the less usable they are.
Technological excess brings war back to its essence as a trial of wills, either because
threat is substituted for action, or because the reciprocal impotence of the great
powers forbids direct conf licts and thereby enlarges the spaces in which clandes-
tine or scattered violence f lourishes, without too much risk to humanity.”13
We fi nd here an echo of the current strategic situation. The wars of our time
seem to oscillate between two options—the technological option, with the
atomic weapon as its traditional symbol, and the rebellion option, for those who
have no access to technology. On one side, the western armies resort to alleg-
edly “surgical” warfare, employing drones and satellites; on the other side, those
whom we name “insurgents,” “rebels,” and “terrorists” engage in psychological
warfare, using individual fights, ambushes, and terrorist attacks in the hearts of
the cities as they mock the West’s obsession with zero-casualty confl icts.
Conventional wars, which were prevalent in Europe and elsewhere during
the twentieth century, have therefore been superseded by both “nuclear” warfare
and “partisan” warfare. At the same time, globalization has not resulted in a stan-
dardization of confl icts. Rather, it has made war even more polymorphous and
indecipherable: “the more unified the planet becomes, the less does diplomacy
seem to obey the ordinary circulations of force and the more military technique
differs from continent to continent and confl ict to confl ict. It is as though some
artistic genius were trying to reunite in a grand finale every method of warfare
practiced by men for thousands of years, on the eve of the day when the progress
of science condemns the human race to choose between wisdom and death.”14
At the crossroads of philosophy and sociology, Aron proposes a typology of
war that draws from the long history of war and strategy, but that is also relevant
to the contemporary situation. As he sees it, there have been three forms of war
since 1945: interstate war, which is also known as “conventional war” and which
did not disappear with the Second World War (one thinks, e.g., of the Six-Day
War in 1967, or the war between India and Pakistan in 1971); next, nuclear war,
based on scientific and technological knowledge, which is a war that leaves no
footprints, as it is based on deterrence, that is, the fact that weapons are not used
as such but are wielded as threats (according to the famous principle of the non-
use of weapons that Guy Brossollet names the “non-battle”); and, fi nally, guer-
rilla or popular warfare, which sets groups of rebels against regular armies.
These “intra-state” confl icts pit an organized power against populations that
refuse to obey. These confl icts (the Jews against Rome, the Chouans against the
French Revolution, pro-independence Algerians against the French army) are
most often civil wars, but Aron rightly explains that guerrilla warfare or subver-
sion is not resorted to in all civil wars (the American Civil War being a case in
point).
We should notice here that the Aronian typology of war is not “state-cen-
tered.” If Aron makes the state the cornerstone of international relations, he
does not reduce the phenomenon of war to its interstate dimension. His interest
in guerrilla warfare is obvious in his fi rst books on international relations (The
28 J E A N -V I NC E N T HOL E I N DR E
Grand Schism, The Century of Total War) and in other writings that are wrongly
considered secondary (the chapter titled “On War” in Hope and Fear of the Century,
for example).
Regarding guerrilla warfare, there are several ways of defi ning the armed
confl icts in which the weakest party compensates for its inferiority with strate-
gies that seek to harass and wear out its enemies in order to undermine them psy-
chologically. It is significant that this type of confl ict has many names: “popular
war,” “supporter’s war,” “revolutionary war,” “national war of liberation,” or,
again, “subversive war.”
Aron suggests a method to make things somewhat clearer: we should start
studying the military dimension (with both strategy and tactics) and then con-
sider politics. For the French thinker, there is no guerrilla warfare or subversive
war; there are only techniques of guerrilla warfare and subversion. The common
point of all the forms of guerrilla warfare is the refusal to leave the monopoly of
fighting to regular armies. Therefore, guerrilla warfare is “a fighting technique,
not a political action. But this fighting technique (individual attacks, surprise
attacks by small groups, rejection of the battle) is admirably suited to revolution-
ary action.”15 Aron very seriously considers guerrilla warfare as an instrument
for revolutionary action; he even argues that guerrilla warfare “could change
the map of the world.”16 From a tactical and strategic point of view, he also calls
attention to the subtlety of this kind of fighting; it should not be regarded as a
“wild” form of war, as opposed to “civilized” or interstate war. Aron rejects this
distinction: “Fighting between archaic tribes, however different in other ways,
is no less organized than the wars of civilized peoples. Guerrilla warfare is not
the original form of human hostilities, any more than the individuals or families
necessarily preceded clans.”17 And later on: “guerrilla warfare is not a return to
anarchy. It is a form of organized combat, although the organization is at the
opposite extreme from nuclear war.”18
If guerrilla warfare is capable of success, it has, however, never triumphed
over a regular army during the twentieth century. To win, guerrillas must be
associated with either a counter-administration or a counter-state (as in China
or Vietnam). In the case of wars of decolonization, such as the Algerian War,
the political context, not the military factor, proved decisive in resolving these
confl icts (independence, in this particular case).
“The Europeans’ loss of prestige, the weakening of the imperialist will of the
British and the French, the enthusiasm of a minority inspired by nationalism,
Communism, or both, the vague inspiration of the masses to an independence
which promises both the foreigner’s departure and the beginning of an era of
prosperity: all the facts together prepare the ground on which guerrilla action
eventually triumphs.”19
If one studies the case of Algeria, political criteria, not military factors, made
the difference. Aron fi nds here an asymmetry between the West’s large armies
and rebellious troops. In reality, the rebels of the FLN did not need a decisive
success to win, whereas, on the contrary, for France, even a “total” military vic-
tory of the French army would not have been enough: “what the French army
could not do in Algeria was reply to Algerian patriotism by creating a French
R A Y M O N D A R O N O N WA R A N D S T R A T E G Y 29
patriotism; nor could it inspire the metropolitan French with the will to main-
tain French sovereignty over Algeria at any price so as to make a million fellow
countrymen permanently safe.”20
In the case of contemporary guerrilla warfare, “it would be enough for the
rebel side not to lose militarily in order to gain politically.”21 Even if the strong
have military superiority, they cannot win as long as the popular will of local
populations is against them. On the contrary, in the confl icts that oppose the
weak to the strong, the weak need only not to lose in order to hope for victory.
In wars of attrition, political concerns will always override military concerns.
As with any war, guerrilla warfare must thus be studied according to political
criteria. Whatever the strategies, on both sides, the success of guerrilla warfare is
dependent upon the support provided by the local population.
Aron here shares the views of Gérard Chaliand, the contemporary specialist
on irregular wars. As we saw in Sri Lanka, the guerrilla warfare of the Tamil
Tigers failed because it ran contrary to the people’s wish to become independent.
In Algeria, guerrilla warfare eventually won because it succeeded in lasting in
spite of the imbalance of power and because most Algerians desired indepen-
dence or, in any case, no longer accepted French domination.
All these points highlight the relevance of Aron’s strategic thought to under-
standing the present. The arguments of the French thinker on guerrilla warfare
are still valid approaches for considering the confl icts in Iraq and in Afghanistan,
which ended with tactical and strategic successes, but also with political fail-
ures, as the Western armies proved incapable of imposing their will on reluctant
peoples. The problem for interventions today lies in the fact that military success
is not transformed into political success, in particular because Western armies
run into the wall of public opinion: for one, Western public opinion does not
accept the war effort, which is necessarily long and entails human loss; and on
the other side, local public opinion refuses to bend before outside powers who
resort to strength. Here is Aron’s main message, in the wake of Clausewitz: at a
fundamental level, war not only raises the strategic issue of victory; it also raises
the highly political question of legitimacy.
For Aron, war is never an end in itself. It is primarily a military means that
is always resorted to for political purposes once diplomacy has failed. It is above
all an indicator of permanence and change in human history: fi rst, war reveals
the centrality and permanence of politics as a structuring element of society; sec-
ondly, the polymorphism of war reveals the intrinsic diversity of human experi-
ence in time and in space. War is both the product of political action and a mirror
in which the aspirations and weaknesses of the societies involved are reflected.
Notes
1. I would like to thank Michael C. Behrent, José Colen, Giulio De Ligio, Elisabeth
Dutartre-Michaut, Annie Lhérété, Daniel J. Mahoney, and Pierre Manent for
their comments and their help.
2. See for example Frédéric Gros, Etats de violence: Essai sur la fin de la guerre, Paris,
Gallimard, 2007.
30 J E A N -V I NC E N T HOL E I N DR E
3. Jean-Vincent Holeindre and Frédéric Ramel (ed.), La Fin des guerres majeures?,
Paris, Economica, 2010.
4. This is a quotation from the title of a book of conversations with Jean-Louis
Missika and Dominique Wolton that was published shortly before his Memoirs.
Aron considered himself a committed spectator, standing aloof from political
action, yet he never renounced expressing his views on political action.
5. Pierre Manent, “Aron éducateur,” in Pierre Manent, Enquête sur la démocratie.
Études de philosophie politique, Paris, Gallimard, 2007.
6. Raymond Aron, The Century of Total War, New York, Doubleday, 1954.
7. Raymond Aron, The Great Debate: Theories of Nuclear Strategy, New York,
Doubleday, 1965.
8. Raymond Aron, The Imperial Republic: The United States and the World 1945–1973,
Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice Hall, 1974; New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction
Publishers, 2009 (with a new introduction by Irving Louis Horowitz).
9. Raymond Aron, Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, New York,
Doubleday, 1966; New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction Publishers, 2003 (with a new
introduction by Daniel J. Mahoney and Brian C. Anderson).
10. Ibid., 787.
11. Raymond Aron, Clausewitz: Philosopher of War (1976), New York, Simon and
Schuster, 1986,
12. On this subject the debate was started by Martin Van Creveld, The Transformation
of War, New York, Free Press, 1991.
13. Aron, Peace and War, 173.
14. Raymond Aron, On War: Atomic Weapons and Global Diplomacy, New York,
Doubleday, 1959, 71.
15. Ibid., 74.
16. Ibid., 75.
17. Ibid., 79–80.
18. Ibid., 85.
19. Ibid., 83.
20. Raymond Aron, Clausewitz: Philosopher of War, New York, Simon and Schuster,
1986, 370.
21. Aron, Peace and War, 34.
CHAPTER 3
Matthias Oppermann
I t all started with Germany. Without having experienced German politics and
philosophy during the first three years of the 1930s, Raymond Aron would
have hardly become the thinker we know today. In this respect, many of those
who have dealt with his thought have made much of his academic or philosophi-
cal experience—of his discovery of the newer German philosophy of history,
of phenomenology, of Marx’s original thought, and of Max Weber’s political
sociology. All this was important, of course. Studying German philosophy and
sociology helped Aron to overcome what he regarded as the shortcomings of the
academic education he received in his native France. However, this academic or
philosophical discovery only put him on the path to political liberalism. It was
not congruent with it. Far from it: Although Weber gave Aron the munition
to repel the positivistic trust in progress, based on several varieties of historical
determinism he had been confronted with during his studies at the prestigious
École normale supérieure in Paris, the great German sociologist bequeathed him
another problem: the naive faith in value-free science totally unfit to an age
of ideologies. It took him nearly twenty years to free himself from this intel-
lectual burden, but after the Second World War he came to regard Weber as a
“nearly Nietzschean”1 nihilist. By contrast, the political insights Aron received
in Germany were much more inf luential in bringing about his own brand of
conservative liberalism. One should never forget that he denied being the repre-
sentative of an abstract liberalism based on any speculative theory.
His liberalism was, as he used to say, the result of the study of reality; that
is to say, of his analysis of the history of the twentieth century, in particular,
of the confl ict between liberal democracies and totalitarian regimes in all their
variations. In order to find the sources of this Aristotelian or Burkean approach
to politics, we must thus analyze Aron’s historical reasoning about the twen-
tieth century, motivated in the fi rst place by his witnessing the crisis of the
32 M AT T H I A S OPPE R M A N N
Weimar Republic.2 Germany was the scene of what he later called his “political
education.”3
Facing Hitler
When Aron arrived in Cologne in the spring of 1930, he was a well-meaning pac-
ifist with socialist leanings who thought France always in the wrong when it came
to her policy vis-à-vis Germany. Like German nationalists, but for other reasons,
the young philosopher considered the Treaty of Versailles as in some ways a cruel
diktat and perceived France as a “wealthy Bourgeois who defends his strongbox.”4
He was very similar in his views to British Liberals like John Maynard Keynes,
who spoke of a “Carthaginian Peace.”5 It is not that Aron did not care about the
security of France, but in his eyes there could be no security without a general
disarmament in Europe; and he was certain that France had to start it, because
when “France does not disarm, Germany will rearm, and legitimately, even if
not legally.”6 In particular, he never linked his desire for peace and security to the
slightest patriotic feeling. This was by all means remarkable, for patriotism was
quite natural in the upper-middle-class-family of Jewish descent into which he
was born on 14 March 1905. Having lost nearly all bonds with the faith of their
ancestors, the Arons were intransigent Republicans. The French Republic was at
the heart of their social and political identity, and therefore patriotism was not a
choice but an obligation. But already in his last grammar-school year, as a student
of the classe de philosophie at the Lycée Hoche in Versailles, Raymond Aron took
a different path than his father and grand-father had.
Discovering philosophy totally changed his political consciousness. “Whatever
may be the politics of the teacher,” he later wrote in his memoirs, “the climate of
a classe de philosophie usually nourishes left-wing sentiments.” 7 Aron substituted a
certain kind of philosophical pacifism, inspired by the then-famous philosopher
Alain, for his inherited patriotism.
When he decided to spend some years in Germany, he was still marked by this
pacifism. Of course, it could not last. It could not survive the daily experience of
German politics. The “passionate pacifist”8 had to face a country where politi-
cal passions ran even higher than in France; a country where the armed wings
of parties grimly fought each other, a country where nearly everyone wanted to
alter the consequences of the Great War. Moreover, he witnessed the crisis of the
Weimar Republic—in other words, the total corruption of a liberal-democratic
regime—and the rise of Hitler. How could pacifism, the longing for the preser-
vation of peace, have triggered his foremost political interest? In fact, in Weimar
Germany, he felt for the fi rst time that not only peace, but the entire European
civilization was endangered. Or, in the words he used thirty years later in his
inaugural lecture at the Collège de France:
active pessimism. I ceased forever believing that History voluntarily follows the
imperatives of reason or the wishes of well-meaning men. I lost my faith, but made
an effort to preserve hope. I discovered the enemy that I do not grow tired of chas-
ing: totalitarianism.9
In Germany, Aron learned that evil was not a mere religious category. It was a
trait of humankind: “there was Hitler, and I apprehended his satanic nature.”
Little by little, he reached the conclusion that “the totalitarian régime was the
absolute evil.”10 Here lies the main reason for his conversion from an irresponsi-
ble, left-leaning pacifism to a realistic and militant liberalism, by which he would
abide through the rest of his life. Hitler and his recently erected tyranny freed
Aron of nearly all of his youthful illusions and later, in his memoirs, he explained
that his “conversion” had been accomplished when he returned to France in
the autumn of 1933. There is good reason, however, to assume that he had
arrived at this point already some months earlier. In February of the same year he
described his position in an article published in Esprit, the illustrious magazine of
the French Catholic left, in terms of an unorthodox middle course between some
of the main political currents of the Third Republic: “I am neither on the left
nor on the right, neither communist nor nationalist, no more a Radical than a
socialist. I do not know whether I will fi nd kindred spirits.”11 Interestingly, there
was one political group he did not mention: the Moderates, the liberals of the
republic and the conservative liberals of the Alliance démocratique.12 Though,
publicly, he never professed support for any party, I do not shrink from locating
him intellectually during these years in that region of the political spectrum. It
seems quite obvious: after the Second World War, he expressed a great deal of
admiration for Paul Reynaud, of whom he said that he should have been the
“guiding star”13 of his generation; and he took up positions—both in economics
and in foreign policy—close to those of moderate politicians like Reynaud and
André Tardieu.14
Aron drew near to these politicians by substituting the advocacy of absolute
peace for the defense of freedom in all its facets. And there was one great ques-
tion that bound together all his academic and journalistic writings: how could
liberals preserve freedom in an “era of tyrannies”?15 The postwar period seemed
to be over. Without the majority of politicians and intellectuals knowing it,
Western liberal democracies were by now travelling on the road to war. There is
no proof that Aron had already gained certainty by 1933 that war with Hitler’s
Germany would be inevitable, as he later claimed in his memoirs.16 But at least
he could no longer ignore the friction that burdened Franco-German relations.
He thus asked the French political left to stop moralizing and to move on to a
foreign policy guided by pursuit of interests and realism: they should not forget
that “a good policy was defi ned by its effectiveness and not by its moral virtue”.17
Aron knew very well that this plea only could irritate the left-wing intellectuals
for whom he was writing. So, in 1933, he still restrained himself from being too
explicit. Some years later he became much bolder. In a now famous talk called
États démocratiques et États totalitaires, which Aron delivered before the Société
française de philosophie in June of 1939, he explained that it would be dangerous
34 M AT T H I A S OPPE R M A N N
to close one’s eyes to the political reality of a continent divided between liberal
and authoritarian or even totalitarian régimes.18
This was not just a rejection of the spirit of capitulation, but also the fi rst allusion
to the fact that the confl ict between liberal democracies and totalitarian states
took place not only in international relations, but also inside the liberal system.
36 M AT T H I A S OPPE R M A N N
As we have already mentioned, Aron did not think that the French Republic
could be destroyed by the few fascist-like but sectarian right-wing groups that
existed in France; rather, he was worried by the sympathy some members of the
political right felt for National Socialism. He was occupied with a problem that
also applied to the French Communist Party, namely the danger that totalitarian
regimes could weaken liberal democracies by using “fi fth columns.”29 Hence,
there was only one task for every patriotic Frenchmen, as he wrote to Roger
Martin du Gard: “Amongst the men of my age I only meet people who are like
me ashamed, repelled and desperate. Warmongering was not my specialty. The
feeling of French decadence is general and intense: everyone wonders what to
do. Nobody dares to call himself a pacifist or a democrat . . . There is a sole ques-
tion for us: how could one work for the resurrection of France?”30
These insights were, of course, the fruits of political observation and historical
reflection. But they also had a philosophical underpinning. In his doctoral the-
sis, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire, written in the same year, he explained
that “peoples who would forget in the name of ethics the abiding necessities of
the internal order of international competition would sentence themselves to
decadence.”31 Consistently, he stressed in États démocratiques et États totalitaires the
duty of the Western liberal democracies in one sentence: “Be capable of the same
virtues!”32 How could one be surprised that Aron’s left-wing audience criticized
him severely for this phrase?33 How could a democracy cultivate the same vir-
tues as a totalitarian regime? What did he actually mean by virtues? Aron left
no doubt that it did not make sense to advocate pacifi sm in the face of regimes
that vaunted themselves as heroic and thought democracies to be weak-kneed,
because this only would confi rm their opinion that democracies were prone
to die. Considering the threat of war-mongering totalitarian tyrannies, liberal
regimes had no choice but to demonstrate that they too could be brave.
To Aron there were three necessary steps to strengthen the ability of liberal
democracies to put up a fight: fi rst, liberal democrats should stop warning of
“fascism” whenever somebody encourages the strengthening of authority or the
use some methods practiced by totalitarian regimes. Aron told his audience that
as political techniques, “some measures taken by totalitarian regimes are excel-
lent” and democracies would not make a blunder in adopting them, “for example
in encouraging procreation or in the field of welfare policy.”34 It was certainly
no mistake to reflect about a way to fight unemployment as effectively as Hitler
did. Having said this, he qualified his remarks by stating that state intervention
in the economy must be restricted carefully because a liberal system could not be
sustained without a large degree of economic liberty.
Secondly, democracies had to possess a “governing elite” that “would be nei-
ther cynical nor craven,” that “would have political courage without lapsing into
a pure and simple Machiavellianism,” and that “would have confidence in itself
and in its own mission.”35 True, such a democratic and dutiful elite could not
make the community work by itself. Thus, it was vital to a liberal-democratic
regime, thirdly, to care for a “minimum of common faith or will.”36 And that
task, Aron thought, was the most difficult of all. After all, in contrast to a totali-
tarian tyranny a liberal system could not decree something like civic virtue.37
IN TH E “ER A OF T Y R A NNIES” 37
Liberal democracy was a complicated matter, and Aron had a rather complex idea
of it. Aron displayed this idea for the fi rst time in his lecture États démocratiques
et États totalitaires. His democracy was not defi ned by the ambiguous notion of
“popular sovereignty,” which could be claimed by liberal and totalitarian states
alike, but by the rule of law and a mixed constitution for the purpose of pre-
venting the holders of political office from abusing their power. In speaking of
democracy, Aron referred only to liberal democracy, that is to say a blend of
liberalism and democracy. Of course, he could have learned about the nature of
mixed constitutions by perusing the history of political philosophy from Aristotle
to Edmund Burke or François Guizot. Instead, his insights into the nature of lib-
eral democracy were occasioned by his examination of Hitler’s tyranny. After the
Second World War, he chose for his defi nition of liberal democracy as a mixed
system the more accurate term “constitutional-pluralist régime.”38
In a way, Aron’s entire oeuvre can be read as a defense of this complicated
political regime. The experience of National Socialism in Germany and the
German threat after 1933 taught him that liberal democracy was the only politi-
cal regime capable in the twentieth century of preserving the fundamental tenets
of liberalism and human dignity. Those who wanted to destroy this system were
revolutionaries to him. He thus told his audience at the Société française de phi-
losophie that the defense of democracy was a conservative task. And, what was
more, compared to revolutionary totalitarian regimes, liberal democracy was
a conservative regime: “I think that democracies are fundamentally conserva-
tive insofar as they want to conserve the traditional values our civilization is
grounded on. Compared to those who want to establish a completely new life—a
military life grounded on permanent mobilization—we are conservatives. And,
compared to those who want to control the entire economy, to those who want
to deploy the means of technology for the use of propaganda, to men who want
to misuse all men as objects of propaganda, we are all the more conservatives
because we are liberals who want to preserve something of personal dignity and
autonomy.”39
The threat of National Socialist Germany taught Aron that in the “era of tyr-
annies,” a liberal was inevitably a conservative as well. Citizens in the 1930s had
to make a “historical choice,”40 as Aron called it in the Introduction à la philosophie
de l’histoire, between two models of politics.41 They had to choose between revo-
lution or conservation and reform—in domestic politics as much as in foreign
policy. In a somewhat Burkean manner, Aron expressed his anxiety that in this
confl ict the wrong side could still enjoy the greater prestige among French intel-
lectuals: “I am afraid that people appreciate the term ‘revolutionary’ and despise
the term ‘conservative.’ From a historical perspective it is important to know if
we want to conserve something by transforming and ameliorating it, whereas
revolution means destruction. I am not in favor of the radical destruction of our
existing society.”42
It was necessary for Aron to expound his thought about the confl ict between
democratic and totalitarian states at length because they were instrumental in the
development of his later political thought. If Aron was a kind of conservative, his
conservatism was nothing more than the temperamental disposition explained
38 M AT T H I A S OPPE R M A N N
the first step was the invasion of Poland. At that time it was not about more than
the extension, the rounding off, if one might say, of Greater Germany as the basis
of the imperial project. The second step was the invasion of France, which had
already a greater outlook. It was about placing all Europe, from the Vistula to the
Atlantic and from the Baltic Sea to the Aegean, at the disposal of the Wehrmacht.
But he who wants to erect the empire of the world today firstly has to erect the
empire of old Europe, which is the intellectual and moral center of the world.
Germany first would have to secure the maritime connections with the tracts of
land that possess indispensable additional resources, the tropical products of Africa
IN TH E “ER A OF T Y R A NNIES” 39
or the mineral deposits of the Orient. In particular, she would have to subjugate
Russia in order to form a continental block and to make it invincible; in other
words, to bring about that unity of the ‘Heartland’ which, as Mackinder said,
would earn the conqueror dominion of the world.” 47
Hence, to Aron, Hitler’s fi nal aim was world domination, and this aim was
motivated by ideological convictions or rather by ideological chimera. In twenti-
eth-century international politics, ideology mattered; and, as Aron apprehended
in the course of the Second World War, it made the confl ict between totalitarian
and liberal-democratic regimes inevitable. Tyrannies like the “Third Reich”
were driven by a “secular religion” to seek the annihilation of liberal Western
civilization. Moreover, the clash between National Socialism and liberalism
turned the war started by Hitler into a very special kind of war, as Aron noted as
early as 1942, “Regarding the clash of ideologies it is similar to a war of religion.”
Did not the liberal democracies fight for much more than their material survival,
that is to say, for a just cause? Aron was sure about it: “A war that aims to save
the independence of the small nations, the equality of races and peoples, and
the principles proper to a humane order is just par excellence. This is not even
explicit enough. Our idea of justice and injustice is at stake in this confl ict.”48
Though Aron certainly was no Manichaean, he did believe that the Second
World War was about justice and injustice. Like the American protestant theolo-
gian Reinhold Niebuhr, he regarded the war as a struggle between the “Children
of Light” and the “Children of Darkness.”49 But what about the Soviet Union?
Undoubtedly, in this struggle, the communist empire fought on the side of the
just. However, to be on the side of the “Children of Light” does not necessar-
ily mean to belong to them. In fact, in Aron’s eyes, the Soviets were “Children
of Darkness” whose assistance was temporarily required by the “Children of
Light.” They were needed to overcome a greater and, above all, more urgent
threat. Very soon after the war, Aron applied the principles that had guided him
in his intellectual struggle against National Socialism against Soviet communism
as well. Though he allowed for subtle differences between National Socialism
and Soviet communism in his conception of totalitarianism, he thought that
these differences did not matter very much on the international stage. True,
unlike Hitler, Stalin and his successor were not adventurers who wanted to
accomplish all foreign policy goals in one lifetime. They did not see themselves
as providential men but as high priests of Marxism-Leninism, and as believers in
their hyper-rationalist “secular religion” they were sure that communism would
prevail in the historical struggle with liberalism. But in principle their hostility
toward the West was as absolute as Hitler’s had been. As Aron himself wrote,
“Stalin had stepped into Hitler’s shoes.”50
As early as 1945, he had suspected that the West’s most urgent responsibil-
ity would be to contain Soviet expansionism. And after Harry S. Truman had
announced the policy of containment on March 12, 1947, Aron was sure that
the time for a new “historical choice” had come. “History was again on the
move,” but this time the confl ict would be long and probably remain below
the threshold of war. As he wrote in 1948 in one of his most political books, Le
40 M AT T H I A S OPPE R M A N N
Grand Schisme, Stalin and his successor would try everything to annihilate the
West without daring war: “Peace impossible, war improbable.”51 Nevertheless,
no citizen of a Western democracy could shrink from making his choice. There
was no neutrality possible. We could deal at great length with Aron’s political
commentaries about the Cold War. We could look at many of his judgments
about Western policy, about the character of the Soviet Union and the develop-
ment of different crises. But I daresay that all that is not necessary to grasp the
meaning of the role Aron played in France during the Cold War. To put the
whole matter in a nutshell, let us confi ne ourselves to two points. Firstly, during
the Cold War—or the “warlike peace,”52 as Aron himself called it—he acted in
accordance with the militant and in some ways conservative liberalism he had
acquired in the 1930s. There was no great difference between the anti-National
Socialist of the 1930s and the time of the Second World War on the one hand and
the anti-communist of the Cold War on the other. He was not simply a “Cold
War Liberal”53 but, since the 1930s, just a political liberal who applied his prin-
ciples in all seasons. He stood up against all forms of modern tyranny. Secondly,
Aron observed the developments of the Cold War era from the perspective of a
conception of international relations that was not a mere theory, but was rooted
in historical experiences collected in the 1930s and 1940s.
Aron was no orthodox realist like Hans J. Morgenthau, who believed that all
foreign policy was, independently of the domestic regime of the state in question,
“a struggle for power.”54 Ideology mattered to Aron, and so did internal regimes.
With this insight, he grounded the concept that he presented in 1962 in Paix et
guerre entre les nations, his magnum opus on international relations: “true realism
consists nowadays in acknowledging the effect of ideologies on diplomacy and
strategy. In our time, instead of repeating over and over again that all regimes
have got ‘the same kind of foreign policy,’ we should be adamant about a truth
that is not contradictory but complementary: nobody understands the diplomacy
and strategy of a state without knowing the regime, without scrutinizing which
philosophy motivates the political leaders of that state.”55
As a staunch defender of liberal democracy as a kind of best regime—that is
to say, the best of the regimes possible in the twentieth century—Aron naturally
had moral objections to orthodox realism as well. He was afraid that the empha-
sis on the national interest and the accumulation of power could lead realists
toward an amoral Machiavellianism. Though he shared their critique of foreign
policy idealism, he denied a clear dividing line between realism and idealism.
Despite the fact that state sovereignty was defi ned by the possibility to decide
when to fight or not to fight, there always had been, as Aron thought, norms
that states had respected. However, they did not respect them because they were
forced by a supranational power, but for the sole reason of prudence.56 To Aron,
the international order was subjected to two different kinds of moralities: the
“morality of law” and the “morality of combat.”57 He believed that the oscilla-
tion of the international order between Kant and Machiavelli should withhold
statesmen from deciding for one of the two sorts of moralities alone. They had
to fi nd a middle course, because “what tradition teaches is not cynicism but
IN TH E “ER A OF T Y R A NNIES” 41
Notes
1. Raymond Aron, “Introduction,” in Max Weber, Le Savant et le politique, Paris,
Plon, 1959, 9–57, 42.
2. For an explanation of Aron’s Aristotelian approach to politics, see Pierre Manent,
“La politique comme science et comme souci,” in Raymond Aron, Liberté et
égalité. Cours au Collège de France. Édition établie et présentée par Pierre Manent,
Paris, Éditions de l'École des hautes études en sciences sociales, 2013, 5–26, in
particular 20–23. For two attempts to dissect the Burkean features of Aron’s
political thought, see Joël Mouric, Raymond Aron et l’Europe. Préface de Fabrice
Bouthillon, Rennes, Presses universitaires de Rennes, 2013, 69–70, 88–89, 97,
106, 234–235, and Matthias Oppermann, “Burkeanischer Liberalismus. Raymond
Aron und die Tugend der Klugheit,” in Tobias Bevc and Matthias Oppermann
(eds.), Der souveräne Nationalstaat. Das politische Denken Raymond Arons, Stuttgart,
Franz Steiner Verlag, 2012, 157–179.
3. Raymond Aron, Mémoires. 50 ans de réflexion politique, Paris, Juillard, 1983, 7.
4. Raymond Aron, “Simples propositions du pacifisme,” Libres Propos vol. 5, no. 2,
1931, 81–83, 81–82.
5. John Maynard Keynes, The Economic Consequences of the Peace, London, Macmillan,
1920, 51.
6. Aron, “Simples propositions du pacifisme,” 82.
7. Aron, Mémoires, 22.
42 M AT T H I A S OPPE R M A N N
24. See Pierre Manent, “Raymond Aron éducateur,” Commentaire, vol. 8, 1985:
155–168.
25. Aron, “États démocratiques et États totalitaires,” 705, 707–708, 710. Cf. in
addition Ibid., 715.
26. See Ibid., 708.
27. See Aron, Mémoires, 136; Aron, Spectateur engagé, 44. Furthermore Raymond
Aron, “Contribution to Golo Mann’s Talk in Front of the Académie des sci-
ences morales et politiques (Structure et accident en histoire politique),” Revue des
travaux de l’Académie des sciences morales et politiques, vol. 129, no. 4, 1976, 381–384,
382. This view was inspired by a lucid article by Alfred Fabre-Luce, as Aron
stated at different occasions. See Alfred Fabre-Luce, “Le tragique de la politique
extérieure française,” L’Europe nouvelle, January 25, 1936. Cf. Aron, Mémoires,
140–141; Raymond Aron’s Papers, Box 206, Raymond Aron to Alfred Fabre-
Luce, May 11, 1980 (Copy). I worked through Aron’s private papers while they
were kept at the École des hautes études en sciences sociales in Paris. In the
meantime they were transferred to the Bibliothèque Nationale. All materials
quoted here can be found by means of Élisabeth Dutartre, Fonds Raymond Aron:
Inventaire, Paris, BNF, 2007.
28. Raymond Aron to Father Gaston Fessard, October 28, 1938, in Raymond Aron,
“Lettres inédites,” Commentaire, vol. 26, 2003, 611–615, 613–614.
29. See Aron, “Essais sur le machiavélisme modern,” 118, 132. The term “fifth col-
umn” originates from the Spanish Civil War. See Jean-Baptiste Duroselle, La
Décadence, 1932–1939, Paris, Imprimerie nationale, 1979, 208.
30. Aron Papers, Box 208, Aron to Roger Martin du Gard, October 7, 1938.
31. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire: Essai sur les limites de
l’objectivité historique. Nouvelle édition revue et annotée par Sylvie Mesure, Paris,
Gallimard, 1986 [originally 1938], 398.
32. Aron, “États démocratiques et États totalitaires,” 708.
33. For the following see Ibid., 708–709.
34. Ibid.
35. Ibid.
36. Ibid.
37. For the following see Ibid., 708–710.
38. Raymond Aron, Démocratie et totalitarisme, reprint, Paris, Gallimard, 1985 [origi-
nally 1965], 111. See furthermore Ibid., passim.
39. Aron, “États démocratiques et États totalitaires,” 711–712. See also Ibid., p. 710.
40. Aron, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire, 408.
41. See Aron, “États démocratiques et États totalitaires,” 716.
42. Ibid., 712.
43. See Michael Oakeshott, “On Being Conservative (1956),” in Rationalism in
Politics and Other Essays: New and Expanded Edition. Foreword by Timothy Fuller,
Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1991 [originally 1962], 407–437.
44. See Raymond Aron, “Les racines de l’impérialisme allemand (1943),” in
Raymond Aron, Chroniques de guerre: La France libre 1940–1945, Paris, Gallimard,
1990, 596–607.
45. For the 1930s, see Raymond Aron, “La révolution nationale en Allemagne
(1933),” in Raymond Aron, Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, Paris, Éditions de
Fallois, 1993; reissue Paris, Le Livre de Poche, “Biblio Essais,” 1995, 271–285,
284; Raymond Aron, “Une révolution antiprolétarienne. Idéologie et réalité du
national-socialisme (1936),” Commentaire, vol. 8, 1985, 299–310, 304, 306. For a
44 M AT T H I A S OPPE R M A N N
full development of the concept, see Raymond Aron, “L’avenir des religions sécu-
lières, part I and II (1944),” in Raymond Aron, Chroniques de guerres, 925–948. For
an explanation of the development of the concept in Aron’s thought, cf. further-
more Matthias Oppermann, Raymond Aron und Deutschland. Die Verteidigung der
Freiheit und das Problem des Totalitarismus, Ostfildern, Thorbecke, 2008, 124–140,
178–200.
46. Joachim Fest, Der Untergang: Hitler und das Ende des Dritten Reiches. Eine historische
Skizze, 5th paperback edition, Hamburg, Rowohlt, 2005, 58.
47. Raymond Aron, “Pour l’alliance de l’Occident (1944),” in Chroniques de guerre,
949–961, 951. For Aron’s opinion in 1933, see Aron, “La Révolution nationale
en Allemagne,” 285. For other discussions of Hitler’s “program” in Aron’s writ-
ings dating from the Second World War and the postwar period, cf. Raymond
Aron and Stanislas Szymonzyk, L’Année cruciale. Juin 1940–juin 1941, London,
Hamilton, 1944, 7–6, 13–14; Raymond Aron, “Philosophie du pacifisme (1941),”
in Chroniques de guerre, 481–491, 489; Raymond Aron, “Mythe révolutionnaire
et impérialisme germanique (1941),” in Chroniques de guerre, 440–451, 440;
Raymond Aron, “La menace des Césars (1942),” in Chroniques de guerre, 584–595,
591; Aron Papers, Box 1, École Normale d’Administration, La Crise du XXe
siècle. Cours dactylographiés, 5e cours, May 4, 1946, 111; Raymond Aron, Les
Guerres en chaîne, Paris, Gallimard, 1951, 49, 52–55, 108–109; Raymond Aron,
“Des comparaisons historiques,” in Raymond Aron, Études politiques, Paris,
Gallimard, 1972, 426–445, 439.
48. Raymond Aron, “La stratégie totalitaire et l’avenir des démocraties (1942),” in
Raymond Aron, Chroniques de guerre, 559–571, 563; Aron, “Philosophie du paci-
fisme,” 485.
49. See Reinhold Niebuhr, The Children of Light and the Children of Darkness: A
Vindication of Democracy and a Critique of Its Traditional Defense, New York, Scribner,
1944.
50. Raymond Aron, “France in the Cold War,” The Political Quarterly, vol. 22, no. 1,
1951, 57–66, 63. Cf. Raymond Aron, Le Grand Schisme, Paris, Gallimard, 1948,
13: “Hitler is dead and for good. But a new Caesar’s shadow tarnishes the world.”
Cf. furthermore Aron, Mémoires, 447. For Aron’s conception of totalitarianism,
see Oppermann, Raymond Aron und Deutschland, 363–387.
51. Aron, Le Grand Schisme, 13. For the year 1945 see Raymond Aron, “Le partage
de l’Europe,” Point de vue, July 26, 1945.
52. Raymond Aron, “La paix belliqueuse (1946),” Commentaire, vol. 19, 1996–1997,
S. 913–917, p. 914.
53. For a short discussion of this problematic term, see Matthias Oppermann, “Ein
transatlantisches Vital Center? Raymond Aron und der amerikanische Liberalismus
(1945–1983),” Geschichte in Wissenschaft und Unterricht, vol. 3–4, 2014, 161–176,
166–167.
54. Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 5th
ed., New York, Knopf, 1972 [originally 1948], 27.
55. Raymond Aron, Paix et guerre entre les nations, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1962, 587.
56. See Ibid., 20, 595.
57. Ibid.
58. Raymond Aron, “Is Isolationism Possible?” Commentary, vol. 57, no. 4, 1974,
41–46, 46. Cf. Aron, Paix et guerre, 596.
59. Ibid.
CHAPTER 4
Carlos Gaspar
R aymond Aron was deeply engaged with the Cold War as a philosopher and
university professor, as a commentator and political scientist, and as a com-
mitted intellectual and citizen.
On returning to Paris from his exile in London, Aron could see the profound
transformation in the international system brought about by the Second World
War. Instead of returning to the university, he decided to immerse himself in the
struggle for freedom and peace, which were threatened by Soviet totalitarianism,
and he sought to combine his political and journalistic activities with teach-
ing and research. This was essentially tantamount to a continuation of his fight
against Nazism as a member of the French Resistance.
The Cold War was at the core of his reflections, writings, and political action.
In 1947, he became “diplomatic correspondent” at Le Figaro, for which he wrote
every week over the course of the next 30 years. This instilled in him the dis-
cipline of political analysis and granted him an important place in all the rel-
evant debates of the Cold War. This involvement was complemented by the
controversial positions he took, in particular in L’Opium des intellectuels, pub-
lished in 1955, which confi rmed his parting of ways with Jean-Paul Sartre and
his left-wing friends, who couldn’t refrain from wanting to be revolutionaries,
and in La Tragédie algérienne, published in 1957, which left this cold-warrior, for
whom decolonization was both historically inevitable and politically necessary
in the name of consistency in Western opposition to Communism, isolated on
the right. In the same way, on the “ideological front” of the Cold War, he was
a major international figure in the Congress for Cultural Freedom; he edited an
important collection of books—Liberté de l’esprit—in which he published essays
by James Burnham, Arthur Koestler, and Hannah Arendt; and later on, during
the 1970s, he founded the journal Commentaire.
In 1948 he published Le Grand Schisme and in 1951, Les Guerres en chaîne, his
fi rst books on the Cold War in which his theoretical rigor and historical vision
46 C A R L O S G A S PA R
combined with his experience of political analysis to portray the diplomatic con-
stellations and point out the hidden conventions of the Cold War and grasp the
main trends of the international system. This hybrid model would be repeated
over the following decades in the successive writings updating his ideas about
the Cold War, such as Espoir et peur du siècle, published in 1957, Le Grand Débat,
published in 1963, the Plaidoyer pour l’Europe décadente, published in 1977, and
Dernières Années du siècle, his last book, published posthumously.
The Cold War also had an impact on his theoretical works. In his sociological
triptych about modern times—Dix-Huit Leçons sur la société industrielle, La Lutte de
classes, and Démocratie et totalitarisme—he chose as a central issue the comparison
between the liberal and totalitarian models of industrial society, a key issue in
the strategic competition between the United States and the Soviet Union. His
masterpiece of international relations theory—Paix et guerre entre les nations—
would not have been complete without its extensive analysis of the Cold War. In
his erudite study on Clausewitz—Penser la guerre, Clausewitz—he dealt with the
nuclear revolution, which played a decisive role in the peaceful impasse in bipolar
competition, calling into question the validity of the classic formula stating that
war was but the continuation of politics by other means.
The combination of different genres—political commentary, ideological
debate, historical and sociological essays, and treatises on international theory
and strategy—is a quality unique to Aron. Hans Morgenthau, Martin Wight,
and Kenneth Waltz recognized him as a peer in the field of international relations
theory, but none of them had either his experience as a journalist or a compa-
rable level of political activity. The columnist for Le Figaro and L’Express wrote
thousands of newspaper articles, just like his friend Walter Lippmann, the great
American journalist, but the latter did not, like Aron, produce scholarly works or
theoretical essays. George Kennan and Henry Kissinger—diplomats, academics,
and fellow cold-warriors—also published key studies about international poli-
tics, but they could not claim the Parisian master’s journalistic résumé, did not
produce theoretical works, and lacked Aron’s level of philosophical insight.
Similarly, the permanent dialectic between history, political science, and the-
ory of international relations is a specific quality of his work, which reinvented
the way in which the critical issues of the Cold War were thenceforward studied.
His approach considered the dilemmas of universality and division in the inter-
national system, the tensions between the inertia of states and the dynamics of
industrialization, and the heterogeneity imposed by the incompatibility between
constitutional regimes and totalitarian regimes.
His fundamental ideas about the Cold War, set out in his fi rst essays, withstood
the test of time: nuclear war did not take place, a lasting collaboration between
the American republic and the Soviet empire was never made possible, and the
unification of the international system was completed with decolonization and
the end of the old empires. His core liberal beliefs and political positions—
opposition to “secular religions” and the old and new imperialisms, and defense
of the Western alliance and European integration—remained intact in both his
less pessimistic and his more pessimistic periods, without preventing him from
recognizing the changes that shaped the “bellicose peace” over the years.
A R O N A N D T H E C O L D WA R 47
nature. The fi rst were the “unification of the diplomatic field” and a bipolar divi-
sion arising from the “concentration of power in two giant states placed at the
periphery of the Western world.” 7 These changes imposed a permanent tension
between the unity of the system and the duality of its structure, which could
only be overcome either by imperial unification or by the return of multipolar-
ity. Hitler’s war, and the progress in science and technology, had accelerated the
emergence of a “fi nite world,” and the new great powers both dreamed of a uni-
versal empire. This made for the inherent instability of bipolarity: “Between two
candidates to empire, rivalry, not entente, is the natural order of things.”8 The
greater dangers of their confl ict, however, were limited by the atomic bomb,
because no one knew whether this would not be the “absolute weapon” that
could destroy civilization; and this unprecedented circumstance created a form
of equilibrium that, however fragile, could be long-lasting: “This uncertainty
favors peace. One does not decide upon the fate of humankind with a throw of
the dice.”9
The transitional changes were the destruction of “partial balances” and the
amplification of the rivalry between the empires into a “global diplomacy.” The
preponderance of the United States and the Soviet Union in Europe and Asia
could only be an exceptional state of affairs and by defi nition was but a tem-
porary one. The resurgence of European and Asian powers would restore the
relative autonomy of regional balances, demarcating “intermediate spaces,” and
reducing the extent of the imperial contest. This possibility, however, was ham-
pered by the ideological dimension of the bipolar division: “what is at stake is
both power and ideas.”10 The stable distribution of spheres of influence was not
possible while the totalitarian nature of the Soviet regime persisted, despite the
fact that Stalin’s imperialism was less impatient than Hitler’s.11
Aron summarized the strategic impasse of the Cold War with the classic for-
mula “paix impossible, guerre improbable” (peace impossible, war improbable).12 The
claims to universality of both empires prevented an agreement on the terms of
the peace, or even a defi nition of the strategic boundaries between the United
States and the Soviet Union; but the fundamental balance between the two great
powers, consolidated by the atomic surprise, made a return to total war unlikely,
at least temporarily.
In this context, the “bellicose peace” was at once a continuation of the
sequence of total wars and totalitarian revolutions and an interruption of the
cycle of “hyperbolic wars.” The Cold War was going to be fought everywhere,
and the two superpowers seemed determined to fight for their empire in every
way except one: war. The Cold War was a “third way on which both camps are
engaged since 1946: neither peace, nor war.”13
International changes and the shift represented by the Cold War demanded
a revision of the major powers’ strategies. This issue was at the center of a great
debate in which Aron took part, looking for alternatives to both imperial peace
and the ascension aux extrêmes (rise to the extremes), the escalation leading to total
nuclear war.14
The outcome of World War II was at the same time the end of a nightmare
and a catastrophe. The dynamics of total war, which demanded the annihilation
A R O N A N D T H E C O L D WA R 49
of the enemy, created the conditions for a new war. The United States and
Britain imposed unconditional surrender and forced Germany and Japan to con-
tinue hostilities until their destruction, which opened the doors of Europe and
Asia to the Soviet Union. Britain and France ceased to be fi rst-rank powers: in
the new system, “the European concert no longer exists; there is only a world
concert.”15
What was to be done? To begin with, it was necessary to avoid repeating
the scenario in which the democracies capitulated before the totalitarian threat.
The Munich syndrome persisted both in the tendency to surrender before the
strength of the Soviet Union and in the unconditional defense of the United
Nations alliance. At the end of the war, the Soviet Union had a unique prestige,
and communism could become the “wave of the future,” even if only the most
fanatical communists in the West refused to recognize the victory of commu-
nism as a calamity equivalent to Nazism.16 However, it was also necessary to
reject the temptations of a preventive nuclear war against the Soviet Union, tak-
ing advantage of the atomic monopoly of the United States: “the victory of one
state at the cost of the total destruction of its rival infl icts a wound from which
civilization cannot heal.”17
Between the extremes of capitulation and war, Aron defended the virtues of
the strategy of containment as contemplated by George Kennan: “The imme-
diate aim is containment. The ulterior aim is fi lling up the no man’s land with
regimes that are not subordinate to communism. The means to achieve them
are economic and political aid under the protection of the nuclear threat.”18 The
American strategy was defensive, moderate, and patient: its essence was time. If
totalitarian expansion was to be stopped, internal forces needed time to make
their way, whether in the Soviet Union or inside the communist bloc. Change
would thus be possible without war: Tito’s survival, after being expelled from the
Kominform, meant a serious defeat for the Soviet Union.19 Communist totali-
tarianism turned out not to be invulnerable after all, and the Soviet empire was
not indestructible.
Playing for time was the only possible strategy for Europe, where the immedi-
ate alternative to the Cold War would be a third world war, which would inevi-
tably be a nuclear war.20 To ensure the duration of a precarious truce, it seemed
crucial to establish a European balance at the center of the bipolar competition
through the division of Germany, the consolidation of the principle of demo-
cratic legitimacy, and the defi nition of a political program with a vision of the
future centered on European integration. Germany was the key to the European
problem, and its division, which was imposed by the breaking up of the war alli-
ance, made the creation of a democratic regime in Western Germany, Franco-
German reconciliation, and Western integration imperative.
Hitler’s war caused the total defeat of Germany and closed the cycle of its
imperial power: “The defeat of Germany in 1945 is comparable to that of France
in 1815. It marks the end of a period of hegemony.” 21 The German question, no
longer about the threat of the resurgence of the old Reich as the leading power,
was reduced to its future alignment in the bipolar division:22 “Only a Germany
converted to communism, as the avant-garde of the Stalinist empire, could once
50 C A R L O S G A S PA R
At the peak of the fi rst transatlantic crisis, France itself destroyed the EDC.
The refusal of the National Assembly to ratify the Treaty of Paris brought into
question European and Western integration and forced Britain to intervene in
order to save both: the Federal Republic was thus permitted to enter NATO,33
and that decision cemented the division of Germany, which would last as long as
the division of Europe.34 Ten years after the end of World War II, the reversal of
alliances was complete and institutionalized in both NATO and the European
Coal and Steel Community (ECSC). The postwar period of turbulence ended
and Europe returned to normal.35
Enemy Brothers
In 1955, after a brief period as a member of the Rassemblement du Peuple
Français (RPF) party, Aron returned to the university and, between courses at
the Sorbonne and during a sabbatical at Harvard in 1960, found time for traveling
and writing his treatise on international relations, Paix et guerre entre les nations.36
After the perfect ending to the EDC crisis, Aron reformulated his analysis
about “the unity and plurality of the diplomatic field,” the main characteristics
of which were dominated by the cleavages of the Cold War: the supremacy of
two states, their presence all over the planet, the mutual hostility of their ideolo-
gies, and, of course, their possession of weapons of mass destruction, including
atomic weapons: “none of these traits was unprecedented, except for the last one,
but their combination was original.”37 For the fi rst time, bipolarity was treated
in a systematic way, with the identification of four possible configurations: in
the new system, the two states could rule together the civilization of which both
were part, draw a demarcation line between the areas in which each one of them
constituted an empire, wage a fight to the death, or co-exist in opposition. The
most likely scenario, however, was a mixed one: “Total agreement and the fight
to the death being excluded, reality pointed to a combination between dividing
the world into spheres of influence and a rivalry for the defi nition of borders and
the allegiance of neutral states.”38
In this framework, in which the two superpowers were determined not to
make war between themselves but were also unable to come to terms with each
other, relations between the United States and the Soviet Union alternated
between a “Cold War” and “Peaceful Coexistence.”39 The main virtue of bipo-
larity was the mutual neutralization of the two great powers, which returned
some degree of independence to other states. This mechanism explained the
survival of the Tito heresy in Eastern Europe, despite the fact that Yugoslav dissi-
dents challenged the constitutive principle of the Soviet empire itself by defying
the authority of the Moscow center: in Europe, “none of the great powers will
dare to employ its armies against a reluctant small state, for there exists another
great power.”40
In the new context, the power of the United States and the Soviet Union
had not only decreased, it had also reached its limits. First, the Soviet-Russian
empire was no longer invulnerable to “ideas of the century.” On the other
hand, the rise of new peripheral powers such as China and India was going to
52 C A R L O S G A S PA R
change the strategic balance and reinforce the reasons for the two superpowers’
mutual containment: a total war between them could only make them more
vulnerable with respect to the poor and non-aligned states.41 Finally, and most
importantly, neither of the ideological rivals was able to unite humanity in a
universal empire.42
By defi nition, the risk of war remained: “States are cold monsters whose law
is always to suspect one another, to fight one another often and to sometimes
destroy one another. Science helps men to kill one another, it does not entrust
them with wisdom.”43 However, the nuclear revolution was the proof of the
thesis of the “powerlessness of victory:” the political and strategic survival of the
United States and the Soviet Union ensured their joint commitment to prevent-
ing a suicidal war. Under these conditions, total war, rather than an “improbable
war,” was a guerre introuvable.44 The wars of the Cold War, as it became clear fol-
lowing the Korean War, were limited wars as far as the number of belligerents,
their theater, the weapons used, and the objectives were concerned.45 The armed
forces of the United States were present, but there was no military intervention
by the Soviet Union, despite its responsibility for the decision to invade South
Korea; the fighting never went beyond the Korean border, despite the tempta-
tion to cross the Yalu; no weapons of mass destruction were used, despite threats
of nuclear retaliation against the People’s Republic of China; and the issue was
restricted to the Korean question.
The dual crisis of Suez and Hungary challenged the rules of the Cold War.
Aron followed the two events, step by step, in his articles in Le Figaro, and often
returned to the question during the following years.
In July 1956, the surprise of the nationalization of the Suez Canal by the
Egyptian Rais was received as an unbearable humiliation by France and Britain,
a humiliation due to the indifference of the United States, which chose to dis-
tance itself from its allies in a dispute that pitted the old colonial powers against
their former protectorates. Aron began by defending the mainstream opinion,
both when he defended the use of force—essential for Paris and London not to
lose face, as the only alternative to capitulation—and when he considered the
issue decisive for the Western alliance and criticized Washington’s passivity.46
The upheaval in Eastern Europe, however, created a new situation. Gomulka’s
success in the Polish crisis marked a fi rst turning point, which it seemed possible
to repeat in the Hungarian Revolution: “In the long run men and their desire for
freedom prevail over the tanks.”47 Then Khrushchev decided to invade Hungary
while the Anglo-French expedition was landing at Suez.
In this extraordinary situation, Aron noted the general immobility in the face
of Hungary’s agony and expressed his skepticism regarding the circumstances
of the belated intervention of France and Britain. Recognizing how this deci-
sion caused “violent and confl icting emotions,” he warned that in Suez no one
could expect to fi nd the answer to the Algerian problems and he stressed the
emotional context of the intervention: “The French and the British were driven
less by political calculation and more by their revolt against their humiliation
and their wish to remind the world that they were not in decay.”48 At the same
time, he deplored the two military actions taking place concurrently, although
A R O N A N D T H E C O L D WA R 53
he did not accept any comparison between the Franco-British expedition and
the Soviet invasion, and he criticized the position of the United States: “fearing
war, American diplomacy implicitly condoned the Soviet empire as a permanent
feature. The two great powers agreed to respect each other’s possessions.”49 The
Soviet Union had become a nuclear power, and the United States would do
nothing that could precipitate a confrontation: “The Soviet-American alliance
against war was stronger than the Western alliance against the Soviet bloc.”50
The dual crisis confirmed that “the supreme interest of the two great powers
(coinciding with that of humanity) is not to engage in a total war.”51 But the
Franco-British intervention also revealed that the assumption of mutual neu-
tralization between the two superpowers was wrong,52 while the invasion of
Hungary showed not only that the Soviet Union was determined to preserve the
integrity of its empire, but also that it was authorized to do anything it wished
within its own area.53 The recognition of this fact required an amendment of the
rule that did not allow regular armies to cross national borders: in its new ver-
sion, this prohibition applied only to “contested areas.”54
In the absence of war, the crises of the Cold War were decisive for defi n-
ing the main trends and the rules of the game. In this context, the dual crisis
was important in the triple sense that the Hungarian anti-totalitarian revolution
destroyed the credibility of Soviet communism for the coming generations,55 the
European revolt against the two great powers confi rmed the limits to their polit-
ical hegemony, and the Soviet-American convergence revealed the complicity, if
not collusion, of the two “enemy brothers.”56 The Suez crisis and the Hungarian
revolution marked the end of illusions.57, 58 By then, Aron was focused on the
global problématique determined by the systemic competition between the two
political, economic, and social models of industrial society, which were the sub-
ject of his fi rst courses on his return to the Sorbonne in 1955.59
In his view, Comte’s industrial society,60 more than Tocqueville’s democratic
society or Marx’s capitalist society, was the paradigm of modernity, “the avant-
garde of humanity,” the universal vocation which might ensure a dynamic of
world unification contrary to the inertia of the past, represented by the empires,
nationalisms, and ideologies responsible for the wars of the twentieth century.
These catastrophes, in turn, had accelerated the “unification of the diplomatic
field” and the diff usion of the model of industrial society on a global scale that
characterized the international system, where three orders converged: the anar-
chy of the powers, the uneven development of economies, and the heterogeneity
of values.61
In this situation, the issue of the opposing models of organization of indus-
trial society, represented respectively by the pluralist democratic regimes and
the market economies of the Western camp, on the one hand, and the Leninist
single-party regimes and planned economies typical of the Soviet bloc, on the
other, constituted a crucial dimension of the competition between the super-
powers. The bipolar balance was dependent on economic growth, scientific and
technical innovation, increases in living standards, and the quality of political
institutions. Moreover, the demonstration of the relative merits of the two com-
peting models was decisive for the competition between the two superpowers,
54 C A R L O S G A S PA R
as the choice of one of the systems entailed an alignment with one of the fields
of the bipolar divide.62
At the same time, the globalization of “industrial civilization” was creating a
new divide between advanced societies and developing countries such as China
and India, which would become great powers in the future.63 The “law of num-
bers” would impose a new hierarchy: “As the technical equipment gaps between
countries diminish, God takes the side of the largest battalions.”64 In the compar-
ison between the United States and the Soviet Union on the one hand and China
and India on the other, the structural convergence between the two models of an
advanced industrial society was stronger than the divergence between them and
the developing countries. This bipolar convergence was enhanced by a common
interest in containing the emergence of future major powers.
Nevertheless, the differences between the political and ideological “super-
structures” of the two models persisted, since it was not possible to separate forms
of organization of production from cultures and political regimes: it was not the
aim of communism “to achieve total tyranny in the name of abundance and of
liberation.”65 In a sense, the homogenization imposed by industrial globaliza-
tion made it more important to appreciate the value of political, ideological, and
cultural heterogeneity in order to ensure the independence of states and political
plurality in the international system.
For Aron, the duality of the history of the twentieth century set the banality
of hegemonic wars—“history as usual,” to use Arnold Toynbee’s formulation—
against the originality of industrial society, “an intellectual, technical, and eco-
nomic revolution which pushes humanity towards an unknown future like a
cosmic force.”66 In the past, the dialectic between the inertia of empires and the
dynamics of industrial society had caused a tragic succession of wars and revo-
lutions.67 After World War II, the tension between international unity and the
bipolar division confi rmed the persistence of this duality, but the convergence
of the expansion of the international system and the globalization of industrial
society announced “the dawn of universal history.”68
Notes
1. Raymond Aron, “L’âge des empires,” in Chroniques de guerre: La France libre
(1940–1945), Paris, Gallimard, 1990, 976.
2. Raymond Aron, “Pour l’alliance de l’Occident,” in Chroniques de guerre: La France
libre (1940–1945), Paris, Gallimard, 1990, 950.
3. In his own words: “une poussière d’États nationaux,” in Chroniques de guerre: La
France libre (1940–1945), Paris, Gallimard, 1990, 978.
4. Aron, “L’âge des empires,” 984.
5. Raymond Aron, “De la violence à la loi,” in Chroniques de guerre: La France libre
(1940–1945), Paris, Gallimard, 1990, 672.
6. Aron, “Pour l’alliance de l’Occident,” 958.
7. Raymond Aron, Le Grand Schisme, Paris, Gallimard, 1948, 17.
8. Ibid., 19.
9. Ibid., 30.
10. Ibid., 23.
A R O N A N D T H E C O L D WA R 55
33. Raymond Aron, “L’accord de Londres,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro,
Tome 1: La Guerre Froide (1945–1955), vol. 1, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1990,
1289–1293 and Raymond Aron, “Les accords de Paris,” Raymond Aron, Les
Articles du Figaro, Tome 1: La Guerre Froide (1945–1955), vol. 1, Paris, Editions de
Fallois, 1990, 1300–1305.
34. Aron always stood by this analysis and criticized Kennan for his defense of
German unity in the 1957 Reith Lectures. George Kennan, Memoirs 1950–1963,
New York, Pantheon, 1972, 229–266 and Raymond Aron, Mémoires. 50 ans de
réflexion politique, Paris, Julliard, 1983, 279–283, Aron, Le Spectateur engagé, 142.
35. Raymond Aron, “Le règlement européen” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du
Figaro, Tome 1: La Guerre Froide (1945–1955), vol. 1, Paris, Editions de Fallois,
1990, 1312.
36. Aron, Mémoires, 455–467.
37. Raymond Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle. Essais non partisans, Paris, Calmann-Lévy,
1957, 273.
38. Ibid., 274.
39. François Houtisse, La Coexistence pacifique, Paris, Monde Nouveau, 1953.
40. Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle, 276.
41. Raymond Aron, “Nations et empires,” in Raymond Aron, Une histoire du XXe
siècle, Paris, Plon, 1996, 6; Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle, 304.
42. Ibid., 344.
43. Ibid., 259.
44. Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle, 304.
45. Ibid., 263. Aron, Les Guerres en chaîne, 207–220.
46. Raymond Aron, “La crise continue,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro,
Tome 2: La Coexistence (1955–1965), vol. 2, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1993, 230–
231 and Raymond Aron, “L’unité atlantique enjeu de la crise de Suez,” in Les
Articles du Figaro, Tome 2: La Coexistence (1955–1965), vol. 2, Paris, Editions de
Fallois, 1993, 232–233. See also Aron, Mémoires, 357–359.
47. Raymond Aron, “La force n’est qu’un moyen,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du
Figaro, Tome 2: La Coexistence (1955–1965), vol. 2, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1993,
257.
48. Ibid., 257.
49. Raymond Aron, “Tragique faillite à New York,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles
du Figaro, Tome 2: La Coexistence (1955–1965), vol. 2, Paris, Editions de Fallois,
1993, 261.
50. Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle, 348.
51. Ibid., 349.
52. Ibid.
53. Raymond Aron, “L’Europe en quête de son unité,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles
du Figaro, Tome 2: La Coexistence (1955–1965), vol. 2, Paris, Editions de Fallois,
1993, 276.
54. Raymond Aron, “La révolution hongroise,” in Raymond Aron, Penser la liberté,
penser la démocratie, Paris, Gallimard, 2005, 408.
55. Ibid., 402.
56. Raymond Aron, Paix et guerre entre les nations, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1962, 553.
57. Raymond Aron, La République impériale, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1973, 85.
58. Aron returned to the crisis to underline that the Hungarian revolution was part
of universal history while the Suez episode was a quarrel between old enemies.
A R O N A N D T H E C O L D WA R 57
Raymond Aron, Penser la liberté, penser la démocratie, Paris, Gallimard, 2005, 387;
Aron, La République impériale, 85.
59. Raymond Aron, Dix-Huit Leçons sur la société industrielle, Paris, Gallimard, 1962;
Raymond Aron, La Lutte de classes, Paris, Gallimard, 1964; Raymond Aron,
Démocratie et totalitarisme, Paris, Gallimard, 1965. See also Raymond Aron, La
Société industrielle et la guerre, Paris, Plon, 1959; Raymond Aron, George Kennan,
Robert Oppenheimer, et al., Les Colloques de Rheinfelden, Paris, Calmann-Lévy,
1960; Aron, Penser la liberté, penser la démocratie, 1469–1782.
60. Aron, Kennan, Oppenheimer, et al., Les Colloques de Rheinfelden, 80–81.
61. Aron, Penser la liberté, penser la démocratie, 1651–1730.
62. Aron, “Nations et empires,” 63.
63. Aron predicted that by 2007 China would have a larger industrial output than the
Soviet Union. Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle, 1957, 221, and 228. See also Abramo
Organski, World Politics, New York, Alfred Knopf, 1958.
64. Aron, “Nations et empires,” 61.
65. Aron, “La société industrielle et les dialogues politiques de l’Occident,” in
Raymond Aron, George Kennan, Robert Oppenheimer et al. (eds.), Les Colloques
de Rheinfelden, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1960, 22.
66. Raymond Aron, “L’aube de l’histoire universelle,” in Raymond Aron, Une his-
toire du XXe siècle, Paris, Plon, 1996, 1792.
67. Aron, Les Guerres en chaîne, 203.
68. Aron, “L’aube de l’histoire universelle,” 1803.
CHAPTER 5
Bryan-Paul Frost
that Aron himself did not want his analysis of a specific historical constellation
to detract from the theoretical framework elaborated in the book as a whole.8
But it is undeniable that Aron must have ruminated for a very long time upon
the new emerging international order if only to determine whether the basic
Clausewitzian framework elaborated in Part One was applicable in the Cold
War era: if not, then his book would simply have been a history of international
relations up until the end of World War II. Moreover, by starting with Part
Three, we can also begin to address concerns as to whether Aron’s “realism” is
relevant and applicable in the twenty-fi rst century. There is a tendency of every
generation (and especially of the “intellectuals” of that generation) to claim that
their epoch is unique from all that came before it—that utterly new concepts,
ideas, paradigms, and theories are needed to understand it fully. It is no surprise,
therefore, to hear a chorus of individuals proclaim that September 11 ushered in
a wholly new international order, or that the telecommunications revolution—
to say nothing of other transnational and global problems—poses challenges that
are simply different in kind from those faced in the past: new theoretical frame-
works must be created to comprehend and to confront them. But we can ask, in
response to these claims, a very commonsensical question: Were there any more
massive changes in such a short period of time than those that Aron experienced
during his lifetime? Born into a secularized Jewish, bourgeois family, Aron lived
through World War I as a child and watched his father lose much of his fortune
during the Great Depression; Aron taught in Germany during the early 1930s,
saw and accurately assessed the meaning of the rise of Hitler and Nazism, and
fled to London when France fell in the summer of 1940; and after the war,
Aron became an influential editorialist, writer, and later university professor,
and he was always in the very thick of the heated debates surrounding the his-
toric choices facing France, in particular, and Europe, in general, in respect to
such issues as communism, NATO, German rearmament, the Common Market,
Gaullism, Algerian independence, and the events of May 1968. And yet what
is most shocking is that after analyzing these momentous changes—from the
Holocaust to Hiroshima—he did not argue that the fundamentals of human
nature or international relations had changed: while there were significant—and
very significant—differences between the beginning and aftermath of World
War II, these difference were quantitative rather than qualitative, and politics
between nations could still be grasped through Clausewitz and others. Aron’s
moderation, therefore, is on full display in Peace and War, and that example may
help to instill in us a healthy dose of the same in order that we might be able to
analyze accurately our own historical epoch and to determine what is genuinely
new and original (if anything) and what is not. Indeed, we might come to see
that moderation is often the hallmark of a sound theory in the social sciences.9
power of their alliance structure and/or of creating a more “just” and “caring”
image internationally.15 Smaller states, whose power is exponentially eclipsed by
the two superpowers, are thus able to enjoy and even to flaunt in various forms
of neutrality, neutralism, and/or non-alignment an unreal or virtual indepen-
dence, using their newfound juridical homogeneity to bolster their importance
and influence in a starkly heterogeneous political environment.16 There would
now seem to be three kinds of aid and assistance in the world: genuine, cynical,
and that by extortion.
However, as unprecedented as the world’s new productive capacity is, as
well as the worldwide extension of the diplomatic field, Aron considers that the
“most truly revolutionary” feature of the twentieth century is thermonuclear
weapons: “For the fi rst time, men are preparing a war they do not want, a war
they hope not to wage.”17 Indeed, for the fi rst time in human history, a tradi-
tional notion of defense has been rendered obsolete: there exists the ability to
annihilate opponents without fi rst disarming them.18 Now it is simply impossible
to do justice to Aron’s description of nuclear strategy in Part Three as it would
require us merely to repeat the multiple scenarios and complicated layers that
he can envision in the heterogeneous, bipolar world of the superpowers. What
is therefore essential to emphasize are two underlying principles that animate
his analysis. First, despite the unprecedented destructive capacity of nuclear
weapons, Aron never rules out their use in extreme circumstances (e.g., a Soviet
invasion of Western Europe); and second, he does not believe that the fi rst- (or
second-) strike use of these weapons would necessarily lead to an all-out con-
fl ict. While thermonuclear bombs seem to be weapons unlike any other in his-
tory, they are still weapons: Aron can consequently imagine (and he believes the
superpowers can as well, under extreme circumstances) the possibility of a lim-
ited nuclear war.19 It should go without saying that Aron repeatedly deplores (and
is indeed sickened by) such a thought; nevertheless, he never lets his emotions
get in the way of his reason. He famously observed as early as 1948 in Le Grand
Schisme that the emerging diplomatic constellation between the superpowers
was a “bellicose peace,” and that while peace between the blocs was impos-
sible, war was highly improbable—but it was improbable and not impossible.20
In other words, the improbability (or unattractiveness) of nuclear war had the
effect of making the Soviets and Americans les frères ennemis, and their collective
interest in avoiding nuclear war overrode and to some extent moderated their
ideological antagonism.21 Of course, this dynamic tension between the blocs
also had repercussions within the blocs (as well as outside of them): les frères
ennemis then became les grands frères within their respective alliance structures,
the particular internal diplomatic relations of which were strongly influenced
by the different internal regimes of the Soviets, Americans, and their various
allies.22 Nevertheless, despite these complicated, worldwide dynamics, Aron
maintains that the strategy of deterrence has not been rendered obsolete with
the introduction of nuclear weapons, and a diplomat’s decision-making process
in the nuclear age remains “formally” the same as in any other age.23 As Aron
sees it, the global extension (and juridical homogeneity) of the diplomatic field
in the post-world war era has not eclipsed the necessarily “oligopolistic” nature
64 B RYA N - PAU L F RO S T
of the international system and its various sub-systems.24 Indeed, it has only
accentuated it.
The conclusion of this massive case study is announced in the opening pages
of Part Three and demonstrated throughout: “What are called weapons of mass
destruction have changed something in the course of relations between what are
called sovereign states. They have changed neither the nature of men nor that of
political units.”25 In fact, Aron goes even further in restricting the revolutionary
character of these weapons: “The formation of blocs owes little or nothing to the
introduction of atomic weapons. It has been a mechanical effect of the situation
created by the Second World War. Two states had emerged reinforced from the
turmoil.” Despite the horrendous devastation incurred by the Soviet Union, it
alone possessed a massive army in the heart of central Europe, while the United
States, having been spared a destructive invasion on its mainland, possessed great
industrial capacity as well as (at least for a short time) the sole possession of
nuclear weapons. Therefore, the “constitution of a Soviet zone of influence in
Eastern Europe provoked a regrouping in the West which, in its turn, provoked
a reply in the form of a tightening of the links between the People’s Democracies
and the Soviet Union.”26 Aron concludes: “The dialectic of the blocs is, as such,
classical, in accord with the predictable logic of a bipolar equilibrium.”27 What
we now see is a “permanent combination of deterrence, persuasion and subversion,”
which, while new, does not change the essentially Clausewitzian character of
international politics: “war is the continuation of policy by other means.”28 The
twentieth century is certainly novel, but it is not fundamentally unique.
be concerned with the balance of forces and the survival of the state. As such, a
diplomat must renounce all “Christian virtues” that condemn or are in tension
with the actions required to prepare for the sometimes-bellicose rivalry between
states.33 According to Aron, the particular virtue of a diplomat is to act in accor-
dance with the precepts of prudence: “To be prudent is to act in accordance
with the particular situation and the concrete data, and not in accordance with
some system or out of passive obedience to a norm or pseudo-norm; it is to pre-
fer the limitation of violence to the punishment of the presumably guilty party
or to a so-called absolute justice; it is to establish concrete accessible objectives
conforming to the secular law of international relations.” Aron therefore rejects
what he describes as “limitless” and therefore “perhaps meaningless objectives,
such as ‘a world safe for democracy’ or ‘a world from which power politics will
have disappeared.’ ”34 The morality of prudence is a morality of responsibility,
and prudent diplomats, unlike those acting from conviction alone, always take
into consideration the likely consequences of their decisions and act accord-
ingly.35 As Aron is able to envisage circumstances that would require and justify
the launching of nuclear missiles, he rejects the arguments of those who categori-
cally refuse to consider their use. Rather than being the only moral alternative,
the idealist’s or pacifist’s renunciation of nuclear weapons risks turning into its
opposite. The existence of nuclear weapons, then, has not changed “the nature
of the morality of diplomatic-strategic action.”36
In chapters 21 and 22, Aron developed a military and political strategy that
would help the West achieve its aims in the Cold War. Those aims, as Aron saw
them, were the physical survival of the West by avoiding nuclear war and the
moral survival of its liberal civilization by forcing the Soviet bloc to accept its
right to exist. Forcing the Soviets to live in peaceful coexistence with the capi-
talist West would translate into a victory for the West because the Soviets would
have to renounce their universalist Marxist-Leninist ideology. Aron counseled,
on the one hand, the maintenance of a military equilibrium in both conven-
tional and nuclear weapons, and, on the other hand, the continued solidarity
and strengthening of the Atlantic Alliance. Although Aron encouraged Western
leaders to confront the Soviets in the Third World, he emphasized that the pri-
mary stake in the confl ict was Europe.37
In the fi nal two chapters, Aron more or less reexamines his entire theoreti-
cal approach by asking what the conditions for and prospects of peace through
law and peace through empire are. Aron does not believe that universal peace
depends upon the progressive development and articulation of a body of inter-
national law but rather upon the universality of republican regimes, the rigor-
ous homogeneity of the international community, and the renunciation of the
recourse to arms. These same conditions would also be necessary in order to
achieve peace through empire. Aron is highly skeptical that these conditions
could be realized in the near or distant future. Indeed, he wonders whether a
universal empire would not require the transformation of human nature.38
The sober manner in which Aron analyzes foreign policy decisions strikes a
balance between the immoderate hopes of idealists and the gloomy pessimism of
realists. Aron’s morality of prudence or responsibility emerges from what he sees
66 B RYA N - PAU L F RO S T
always as robust as one would hope, and are often mixed with other, less “noble”
motives. Nonetheless, the distinctive arena of international relations can never
be severed irrevocably from considerations of justice and morality: wars between
political units cannot be explained by or reduced to mere self-interest or the
accumulation of power because the human beings who represent their political
units do not always act in this fashion. In the second place, Aron is continually
reformulating his own assumptions in manifold ways, as if to remind his read-
ers that there is not—and cannot be—a single, privileged historical perspective.
For example, when Aron discusses the goals or ends states seek (chapter 3), he
argues that at the most general level of abstraction or conceptualization, they
have sought three objectives: security (either by increasing their own force or
weakening a rival’s), power (the ability of imposing one’s will on another), and
glory (to be recognized by others in a certain way or for a certain quality). Aron
nicely distinguishes these three goals from one another (the first of which he calls
a “material” objective, the latter two “moral” ones) by contrasting three famous
French leaders: “Clemenceau sought the security, Napoleon the power, Louis XIV
the glory of France.”45 As the chapter proceeds, Aron reconceptualizes these objec-
tives as he deepens his analysis of them. The ternary series security, power, and glory
could also be reformulated as space (to conquer more territory), men (to conquer
more subjects), and souls (to convert others to a political, social, or religious idea),
or again as body (to accumulate material objectives such as space or resources
or force), heart (to satisfy a state’s amour-propre by prevailing over its rivals), and
mind (to spread an idea of which the state represents a unique incarnation).46 And
finally, in the third place, Aron centers much of his attention on the unit (and
individual) level of analysis. More specifically, he argues that it is imperative for a
theorist to be cognizant of a state’s regime, for it is only here that one will discover
its conception of justice and its over-arching political objectives. Certainly, Aron
is attuned to whether any particular international system is bipolar or multipolar,
and he is aware of the dynamics that often prevail in such systems. Nonetheless,
it is the compatibility or confl ict among the regimes of the major powers in any
given international system (or sub-system) that is most decisive in influencing the
character of that system. As Aron observes (perhaps thinking of Germany in the
1930s), “A change of regime within one of the chief powers suffices to change the
style and sometimes the course of international relations.”47 This makes Aron’s
theorizing much more akin to classical philosophers such as Thucydides and
Aristotle than it does to many a contemporary theorist, where the separation
between international and comparative politics is much more stark. At the end of
the day, all three of these examples punctuate the fact that Aron does not believe
in a “theory of undetermined behavior,” one that divorces the political unit’s
intentions from the forces it possesses. Aron thus rejects any “science that gives to
the forms of behavior it studies explanations contrary to or divorced from the mean-
ing understood by the participants” themselves.48
Although much more could be said about what we might call Aron’s posi-
tive theoretical originality, his negative or cautionary originality is equally sig-
nificant. In other words, Peace and War is as distinctive in revealing what Aron
stood for as in what he stood against. Aron sounds one of his massive warnings
F O RWA R D T O T H E P A S T 69
about international relations theory from the opening pages: “the limits of our
knowledge.”49 The “limits” to which he is referring are not so much a lack of
historical evidence or information (although he certainly means this as well)
but rather the inherent limits of theoretical knowledge itself. Aron argues that
there is no single goal or objective which all states pursue, and attempts to claim
that there is some such overarching end (e.g., “national interest” or “power and
security”) are either hopelessly vague or distorting simplifications. This is not
to say that efforts at conceptualizing international relations are fruitless—on the
contrary, Aron is at pains to point out that all political units must be mindful
of the alternatives of war and peace, and that “the risk of war obliges [states] to
calculate forces or means.”50 Nevertheless, the alternatives of war and peace do
not and cannot tell the theorist what specific goals political units will pursue, and
absent this, theorists are relatively constrained in what they can say or predict:
“[L]acking a single goal of diplomatic behavior, the rational analysis of interna-
tional relations cannot be developed into an inclusive theory.”51
These early cautionary remarks reach a crescendo at the end of chapter 3 (the
last of the three chapters that articulate his fundamental theoretical concepts
before he turns to the development of typical diplomatic systems in chapters
4–6). Here, Aron most fully develops the difference between economic behav-
ior and diplomatic-strategic behavior, and in so doing he clarifies why the for-
mer has had (and will continue to have) far more “success” when it comes to
theory. Although Aron admits that “homo economicus exists only in our ratio-
nalizing reconstruction,” that reconstruction resembles a “concrete economic
subject” far more accurately than any imagined or postulated homo diplomaticus
resembles any historical diplomat: the concrete economic subject more often
than not does seek a single objective (the “maximization” of some quantity,
whether it be income, profit, or production) while diplomats have not. In other
words, there is no comparable variable in international relations that serves the
same function as “utility” does in economics, and to claim that there is would be
to create a “caricatured simplification of certain diplomatic personages at certain
periods” and not the much sought-after “idealized portrait of the diplomats of all
ages.”52 Aron’s humble—and to some, disappointing—conclusion is that “there is
no general theory of international relations comparable to the general theory of economics.”
While the necessity of calculating forces or means makes it possible to elabo-
rate a conceptual framework, the multiplicity of goals (or the indeterminacy
of diplomatic-strategic behavior) prevents the articulation of theories similar to
those in economics.53
Given these inherent limitations, Aron repeatedly cautions theorists against
the attempt of transforming international relations into an operational or predict-
able science. Despite the best of intentions, international relations scholars will
never discover a “grand theory” that enables them to predict diplomatic-strategic
behavior, and the effort to do so is itself potentially irresponsible: it is not a lack of
historical knowledge that thwarts scholars but the inherent limitations of theory
itself. Aron stood squarely against the dominant trends in international relations,
and this, in part, helps to explain why he had such a limited impact on Anglo-
American social science.
70 B RYA N - PAU L F RO S T
at various times and places, has captured a portion of the truth without being
true tout court. Aron then offers a trenchant critique of the Marxist-Leninist
theory of imperialism and colonialism, concluding that no economic system,
“whether capitalist or socialist, makes war inevitable; none suppresses all occa-
sions for it.”58
In contradistinction to material or physical causes, the moral or social deter-
minants refer to political units’ “styles of being and behaving.”59 Here, Aron
wants to see if he can discover a recognizable pattern of action or change. Not
surprisingly, his conclusions are negative. While not denying the tremendous
impact of a political unit’s regime on the conduct of foreign policy, Aron does
not believe that certain regimes, national characters, military organizations, or
even the nation itself are inherently “bellicose or peaceful.”60 At a higher level
of abstraction, Aron also fails to discern a pattern of change or development in
the succession of nations and civilizations, or in the so-called historical process
itself.61 As for the biological, psychological, and sociological roots of war, Aron
cautiously surmises: “The human animal is aggressive, but does not fight by
instinct, and [while] war is an expression, it is not a necessary expression of human
combativity . . . It is contrary to the nature of individuals and groups that the con-
fl icts between individuals or among groups disappear. But it is not proved that
these confl icts must be manifested in the phenomenon of war.”62
Notes
1. See, respectively, Raymond Aron, Introduction to the Philosophy of History: An Essay
on the Limits of Historical Objectivity, trans. George J. Irwin, Boston, MA, Beacon
Press, 1961, and Raymond Aron, “Introduction,” in Miriam Bernheim Conant
(ed. and trans.), Politics and History: Selected Essays by Raymond Aron, New York,
The Free Press, 1978, xix; Raymond Aron, The Century of Total War, Boston,
MA, Beacon Press, 1954, as well as Pierre Hassner, “Raymond Aron and the
History of the Twentieth Century,” International Studies Quarterly, vol. 29, no.
4, 1985, 29–37; Raymond Aron, Clausewitz: Philosopher of War, trans. Christine
Booker and Norman Stone, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983, and
Raymond Aron, Memoirs: Fifty Years of Political Reflection, trans. George Holoch,
New York, Holmes & Meier, 1990, 407–411; and Raymond Aron, The Opium of
the Intellectuals, trans. Terence Kilmartin, New York, W. W. Norton, 1962.
2. Raymond Aron, Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, trans. Richard
Howard and Annette Baker Fox, Garden City, Doubleday, 1966, reissued (with
a new introduction by Daniel J. Mahoney and Brian C. Anderson) by New
Brunswick, NJ, Transaction Publishers, 2003. All emphasized words in quota-
tions are contained in the original.
3. Aron, Memoirs, 302. For a discussion of the critical reception of the book in
Europe (where it received widespread praise) and America (where its reception
was more reserved and sometimes downright chilly), see Robert Colquhoun,
Raymond Aron: The Sociologist in Society, 1955–1983, vol. 2, London, Sage, 1986,
191–197. Ibid., 166–169, also has a very useful set of schematic tables that shows
how Peace and War is organized.
F O RWA R D T O T H E P A S T 73
4. John Hall, Diagnoses of Our Time: Six Views on Our Social Condition, London,
Heinemann Educational Books, 1981, 164, conjectured the following more than
30 years ago, and it reads as true today as it did then: “one suspects that [Peace and
War] is more quoted than read.”
5. Stanley Hoffmann, “An American Social Science: International Relations,”
Daedalus, vol. 106, no. 3, 1977, 45.
6. David Thomson, “The Three Worlds of Raymond Aron,” International Affairs,
vol. 39, no. 1, 1963, 53–55.
7. Henry Kissinger, “Fuller Explanation,” New York Times Book Review, February
12, 1967, 3.
8. Raymond Aron, Mémoires: 50 ans de réflexion politique, Paris, Julliard, 1983, 453.
9. The unorthodox method we propose here is in many ways endorsed by Stanley
Hoffmann, “Minerva and Janus,” in his The State of War: Essays on the Theory
and Practice of International Politics, New York, Frederick A. Praeger, 1965, 32–33,
whose compressed summary of Peace and War accurately captures the importance
of history throughout the book. “[E]ach aspect of research depends on the results
achieved at the previous level; they are parts of the same undertaking and the
same conception. But each one activates different qualities of the mind, requires
different forms of reasoning or methods of verification. At every level [of con-
ceptualization], the research is inseparable from history, but the role of history is
not the same in all four cases. At the level of theory in the narrow sense, it is the
primary raw material, and the concepts and types defined by theory are drawn
from the systematic comparative study of concrete data. At the second level [soci-
ology], where hypotheses about material and moral causes are filtered through
historical analysis, history is the touchstone. At the third level [history], it is an
object of direct investigation. At the level of philosophy [or praxeology], history
is being judged.”
10. Aron, Peace and War, 371.
11. Raymond Aron, 18 Lectures on Industrial Society, trans. Mary K. Bottomore,
London, Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1967; Raymond Aron, La Lutte de classes:
Nouvelles leçons sur les sociétés industrielles, Paris, Gallimard, 1964; Raymond Aron,
Democracy and Totalitarianism, trans. Valence Ionescu, New York, Praeger, 1969.
12. Aron, Peace and War, 506–535.
13. See Ibid., 373–381.
14. Ibid., 506–507, 513.
15. Ibid., 513–522.
16. Ibid., 507–513.
17. Ibid., 371.
18. Ibid., 396, 435.
19. Ibid., 404–440, 476ff, 494, 641.
20. Raymond Aron, Le Grand Schisme, Paris, Gallimard, 1948, 1–31. Although Aron
does not say so specifically, clearly weapons of mass destruction in the hands of
religious fanatics will have a different dynamic from such weapons in the hands
of ideological extremists (especially extremists who ostensibly maintain that reli-
gion is the opium of the people).
21. Aron, Peace and War, 389, 407, 428, 536ff, 546, 564.
22. Ibid., 441–475.
23. Ibid., 404–408, 435–436, 636.
24. Ibid., 95; cf. 389–394.
25. Ibid., 371.
74 B RYA N - PAU L F RO S T
48. See Hoffmann, “An American Social Science,” 52, as well as Hoffmann, “Minerva
and Janus,” 25.
49. Aron, Peace and War, 4.
50. Ibid., 16.
51. Ibid., 17.
52. Ibid., 91.
53. Ibid., 93; cf. 285.
54. Ibid., 178–180, 279.
55. Ibid., 181–209, 757–766.
56. Ibid., 213.
57. Ibid., 215–242.
58. Ibid., 278.
59. Ibid., 279.
60. Ibid., 306.
61. Ibid., 308–309, 316–317, 320, 324–325, 333.
62. Ibid., 365–366.
63. Raymond Aron, “Conf lict and War from the Viewpoint of Historical Sociology,”
in The Nature of Conflict: Studies on the Sociological Aspects of International Relations,
Paris, UNESCO, 1957, 190–198. Of course, Aron notes that theorists who focus
primarily on sociological factors to the exclusion of historical ones are likely to
commit two related errors: “they tend to establish ‘causes’ where, at most, there
are trends, and they do not take account of all the factors involved but exaggerate
the inf luence of those that are considered.” One might say that one of the great
virtues of historical sociology is that it compels a theorist to give due consider-
ation and weight to the authentic political perspective of those actors whose deci-
sions are the object of theoretical or scientific investigation.
CHAPTER 6
“CITIZEN CLAUSEWITZ”:
ARON’S CLAUSEWITZ IN DEFENSE OF
POLITICAL FREEDOM
Joël Mouric
Germany until his first systematic reading of his work in 1955.9 Then comes the
central question: that of the Aronian interpretation of Clausewitz, developed from
1955 to 1976 in the context of the Cold War and then culminating in Penser la guerre.
Finally, we will question the scope of this interpretation, separating the political
issues from the criticism, sometimes very harsh, to which it has given rise.
the local level a decisive victory, which might escalate the confl ict and make it
worldwide. Having made that decision, Harry Truman relieved MacArthur of
his duties. Hence, the article “Peace without Victory,”32 in which Aron, draw-
ing upon the idea of the primacy of politics in Clausewitz—“war may have
its own grammar, but not its own logic”33 —called attention to the analogies
between Clausewitz’s concept of absolute war and the ideal type of Max Weber.
Aron recalled the criticism of Ludendorff by Delbrück, based on the distinction
between a strategy of overthrow (Niederwerfungsstrategie) and a strategy of harass-
ment 34 (Ermattungsstrategie), and stated that, as war is a trial of will, “the strategy
of harassment tends to wear down the will of the enemy.” The Cold War then
appeared as “a limited war . . . where one side seeks total victory and the other just
a partial victory.” The resistance of the West would force Stalin to adopt a strat-
egy of harassment to move toward his goal, but “in that case, the coincidence of
two strategies of harassment, with limited means, can lead to an extended trial of
strength over a generation.”35
issue of the Cold War. Aron then observed that it was “exclusively in relation to
Europe that the problem of the scale of retaliation and action [was] raised.”48
Thus, Aron naturally placed Clausewitz at the heart of his own theory of
international relations articulated in Peace and War: A Theory of International
Relations. Out of realism, one must acknowledge war: “War is present in all his-
torical ages and in all civilizations.”49 But Aron maintains Clausewitz’s praise of
prudence, a virtue as essential to the war leader as to the statesman, as evidenced
by the quote highlighted in his essay On War: “The art of war will shrivel into
prudence, and its main concern will be to make sure the delicate balance is not
suddenly upset in the enemy’s favor and the half-hearted war does not become a
real war after all.”50 Based on a grasp of the concrete and on a sense of responsi-
bility, caution should not be confused with moderation,51 much less with pusil-
lanimity. It consists in “preferring the limitation of violence to the punishment
of the alleged culprit or to a justice called absolute,” in “aiming at goals that are
concrete, accessible, consistent with the millennial law of international relations
and giving up unlimited objectives.”52
In Peace and War, published in 1962, Aron offered to the Europeans, in con-
tinuity with the interpretation of Clausewitz by Delbrück, a strategy to wear
down Soviet expansionism through the American alliance and a clearly stated
spirit of defense. He summed it up in the phrase “to survive is to win,”53 which
extends the intuition of “De la paix sans victoire”: the ideological confl ict, since
it would be impossible to end it by force due to the fact of nuclear weapons,
would in the long run be a test of will.
Aron meant neither to accept the factual situation in Europe nor to endorse
the idea, so fashionable then, of the convergence54 between East and West. He
meant to deter “the men in the Kremlin” by an appropriate defense effort, and
to challenge their ideological ambitions by engaging in “the competition of
ideas.”55 Aron emphasized that the Soviets, also disciples of Clausewitz,56 did
not intend to resolve the confl ict militarily, but did continue to aim for the total
victory prescribed by their ideology.
Clausewitz compared decision by arms to payment in cash.57 On the issue of
the Traites de la dissuasion (“the bills of deterrence”)—“If the threat, according to
the theory, has no other purpose than to prevent its own enforcement, does there
not follow a kind contradiction: can we live indefi nitely on credit?”58 —Aron
responds with “betting on reason,”59 a gamble on the prudence and fi rmness of
leaders capable of managing arms control and, in emergencies, to preserve the
essential. In his inaugural lecture at the Collège de France,60 Raymond Aron had
insisted on what he owed to Clausewitz and Delbrück of his vocation as a soci-
ologist and theorist of international relations—hence his return to Clausewitz in
the Collège de France lectures,61 followed by Penser la guerre, in 1976. Aron felt a
strong empathy for the Prussian theorist, to the point of overlooking Clausewitz’s
anti-Semitism.62 He insisted instead on what unites their fates: “To understand
the mindset of Clausewitz between 1806 and 1813, it is probably necessary to suf-
fer a trauma comparable to the one that Clausewitz suffered at the collapse of the
state and the loss of his homeland. Clausewitz wrote that, from then on, being no
longer the Bürger of a respected state, he would owe respect to the compassion of
82 JOËL MOU RIC
strangers abroad, but would not enjoy it as a right; I just had to recall my experi-
ences of 1940, when I arrived in England with nothing more than the uniform
I wore, to sympathize with the contradictory feelings that stir the prisoner in
France, and later on with the reformer returned to Prussia, where there was a
party that, in the twentieth century, we would call the collaborationists.”63
The elective affinity between Aron and Clausewitz was primarily intellec-
tual—the ambition of outlining a theory of war that would be neither an irrel-
evant manual nor a false science, such as that of Heinrich von Bülow,64 whom
Clausewitz criticized for his obsession with mathematical formalism: “The the-
ory of war,” Aron writes about Clausewitz, “will be the theory of an art or prac-
tice (in modern terms a praxeology).”65 Aron points out the similarities between
the approaches of Clausewitz and Montesquieu.66 The theoretical requirements
indeed distinguish the Treatise of Clausewitz, whose first two books are devoted
to the defi nition and theory of war, from the views of Ludendorff, who, in Total
War, began by proclaiming himself “the enemy of all theories,”67 an utterly anti-
Clausewitzian approach. Clausewitz, like Aron in the Introduction to the Philosophy
of History,68 focused on the understanding (Verstehen) of historical situations—
through analysis of available data, an estimate of the likely intentions of the
various players—rather than their explanation (Erklärung).69 Theory is observa-
tion, not doctrine, “Betrachtung, nicht Lehre,” Aron concluded in his Leçons sur
l’histoire.70
But the Aronian interpretation of Clausewitz in the direction of moderation
depends ultimately on chapter 1 of Book I of the Treatise, in which Clausewitz
described war as absolute war in accordance with his concept; in other words, in
the language of Aron, as an ideal type. This is the same text where Clausewitz
describes war as a “strange trinity”: “natural blind passion,” “free action of the
soul,” or “pure understanding,” 71 depending on whether it relates to the people,
the war-leader, or the statesman. This distinction corresponds to the two types
of war, as outlined in the Foreword of 1827 and in the eleventh paragraph of
Chapter 1 in Book I: “These two kinds of war are as follows: one has as an end to
defeat the opponent, either to destroy him politically or to disarm him by forcing
him to accept peace at any price; the other kind consists of just a few conquests
at the country’s borders, either to keep them or to use them as a bargaining chip
at the moment of peace. It will of course be necessary to take into account the
intermediate types, but their entirely different nature should be apparent every-
where and mark the separation between the irreconcilable elements.” 72
The political goal “returns” after being “somehow swallowed up by the law of
extremes.” 73 Aron points out that Clausewitz warned against a false interpreta-
tion of his system, which would be the confusion between absolute war and real
war.74 But Clausewitz, who died of cholera in 1831, had not the time to reor-
ganize the Treatise according to this fi nal conception of his subject. Aron notes
that “Clausewitz laid the foundation for his conceptual cathedral, namely the
absolute unreality of absolute war, only in the last two years of his life, between
1827 and 1830 . . . In order to establish the status-equality of the two kinds of war,
he had to recognize the unreality of absolute war, which he presented, in many
texts, as the only one consistent with the concept.” 75
“C I T I Z E N C L AU S E W I T Z” 83
Hence Aron’s use of Delbrück, like him “a teacher, a civilian, who indulged,
and in what a tone, in criticizing the military.” 76 Delbrück launched in 1878 the
“strategic debate,” 77 distinguishing the strategy of annihilation (Vernichtung) or
of overthrow (Niederwerfung) on the one hand from the strategy of harassment
(Ermattung) on the other. This approach was challenged, not only because the
term Ermattung was absent from Clausewitz’s Treatise, but also because it contra-
dicted the prevailing doctrine in the Prussian army, which only knew the fi rst
kind of war. 1870 had been a triumph of the Niederwerfungsstrategie. However,
in a parody article, Delbrück demonstrated that Frederick would have been a
coward if one were to judge his conduct in the Seven Years War in terms of
Napoleonic strategy. Moreover, Delbrück then presented the strategy of Pericles
as a great example of a strategy of harassment:78 “the comparison between
Pericles and Frederick the Great led to a comparison of Athens on the eve of
the Peloponnesian War and Germany at the end of the nineteenth century. In
advance, H. Delbrück criticized the strategy of annihilation or decisive victory
that the Hindenburg-Ludendorff team would choose until the summer of 1918
and up to the fi nal catastrophe.” 79 Faced with a united coalition opposed to its
rise, Germany should have led a defensive policy, intended to wear down the will
of the Entente. Yet Delbrück was not listened to, instead, “mistaken for Verdun,
with mutual slaughter, without ideas and without maneuver, Delbrück’s harass-
ment strategy fell into total and unjust disrepute.”80
Raymond Aron criticized Delbrück for remaining a historian and not having
“cleared the joints of the conceptual system”81 of Clausewitz, but he approved
of the Prussian historian for his rehabilitation of the second kind of war and his
understanding of Clausewitz in the direction of moderation, distinguishing the
end in the war (military goals or Ziel) and the end of the war (political aims or
Zweck 82).
achieve his political goal, but examples abound of war leaders, from Napoleon to
Hitler, who accumulated tactical victories only to achieve a strategic failure.
The refusal to reverse Clausewitz’s formula is fundamental in what concerns
the very possibility of a liberal policy. Indeed, the autonomy of the political and
the distinction between war and peace depend on it. The philosophy of Raymond
Aron teaches us, in fact, contrary to the illiberal ideologies he criticized, fascism
and Marxism, that politics is not a war. As Bernhard Schlink wrote in criticism
of Carl Schmitt “there are situations that call for action, but there are also cer-
tainly some situations that cannot be overcome, unless the underlying tension
can be undone, not by a decision, but by endurance.”101
These anti-liberal attacks were the price to pay for Raymond Aron’s support
of the Federal Republic of Germany. Aron had always considered the Franco-
German reconciliation essential and indispensable to the possibility of a defense
of Western Europe.102 Rehabilitating a Prussian liberal tradition, albeit a more
conservative one, Aron supported the regime of the FRG, which since 1956 he
had described as a “peaceful democracy.”103 However, at the time of publication
of Clausewitz, West Germany was suffering terrorist attacks at the hands of the
Red Army Faction of Baader. Aron’s intellectual and political support for the
democracy of Bonn was rewarded with the Goethe Prize in 1979.
After the end of the Cold War, the work of Aron was partly forgotten or
neglected as it was presumed outdated. In Achever Clausewitz,104 René Girard criti-
cizes Aron for his rationalist optimism, “one of the last fi res of Enlightenment.”105
Penser la guerre, “a very brilliant essay,” “is marked by its time . . . let us say, by
the time of the Cold War, when nuclear deterrence still carried credibility, and
politics still meant much. It no longer makes sense today.”106 René Girard chal-
lenges Aron’s moderate interpretation according to which “absolute war is only
a concept.”107 He thus restores the perspective of the rise to the extremes, of
which Clausewitz had an “apocalyptic insight.” Girard, like Aron, resumes the
unfi nished work of Clausewitz, but is in a sense diametrically opposite, since he
in turn reverses Clausewitz’s formula.108 Finding in Wechselwirkung and the rise
to the extremes his own conception of mimetic rivalry, he abandons the paths of
political philosophy for those of anthropology and Christian eschatology.
Very different was the reaction of the military. Since Raymond Aron had a
strained relationship with some generals and theorists of national atomic force,
including Pierre Marie Gallois, because they wished to think about deterrence
in exclusively technical or mechanical terms, regardless of the diversity of con-
crete political situations, contemporary military authors have reassessed the
value of the Aronian interpretation of Clausewitz. This is particularly the case
with General Durieux, who qualifies it as “enlightening.”109 When considering
Clausewitz as “a strategist for Europe,”110 he took into his account the basic idea
of Raymond Aron.
* * *
“What I reject,” Aron wrote in his Mémoires, “is the accusation of having belittled
Clausewitz, to having reduced him to a harmless thinker, unaware of historical
86 JOËL MOU RIC
tragedy. Tragedy, I have seen it, I have felt it, and I have tried until the last page
to make its presence felt. Israel was born through violence, lasts only through
violence, and risks dying tomorrow through violence.”111 And, in fact, Penser
la guerre ends with a reminder to Europeans tempted to say “farewell to arms”
not to give up their civic duty, that is to say, their duty to defend themselves.
“French, Jewish by birth, how could I forget that France owes its liberation to
the strength of its allies, Israel its existence to its arms, a chance of survival to its
resolution and to the American determination to fight if necessary?”112 Aron’s
Clausewitz is a European citizen, committed to defending political freedom.
Notes
1. Raymond Aron, Les Guerres en chaîne, Paris, Gallimard, 1951, 502; English trans-
lation: Raymond Aron, The Century of Total War, New York, Doubleday, 1954.
2. See Fabrice Bouthillon, Et le Bunker était vide. Lecture du testament politique d’Adolf
Hitler, précédé de la traduction inédite des testaments d’Adolf Hitler, Paris, Hermann,
2007.
3. Clausewitz, De la guerre, I, 1, 3. We refer to the French translation by Denise
Naville, Paris, Les éditions de Minuit, 1955. This edition is the one that was used
by Aron. See 52. Carl von Clausewitz, On War, ed. Michael Howard and Peter
Paret, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1976.
4. Ibid., I, 2, 70: “The fighting forces must be destroyed: that is, they must be put in
such a condition that they can no longer carry on the fight. Whenever we use the phrase
‘destruction of the enemy’s forces’ this alone is what we mean.”
5. Isabel V. Hull, Absolute Destruction: Military Culture and the Practices of War in
Imperial Germany, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press, 2005, 400.
6. Basil Liddell Hart, The Ghost of Napoleon, London, Faber, 1933, 118–122.
7. Raymond Aron, Penser la guerre, Clausewitz, Tome I, L’Âge européen, Tome II, L’Âge
planétaire, Paris, Gallimard, 1976. English translation: Clausewitz: Philosopher of
War, New York, Simon and Schuster, 198.
8. Raymond Aron, Mémoires, Paris, Robert Laffont, 2003 [1st ed. Julliard 1983],
645.
9. Ibid., 10.
10. Clausewitz, Vom Kriege. Hinterlassenes Werk des Generals Carl von Clausewitz, her-
ausgegeben von Werner Hahlweg, Dümmler, Bonn 1952, 1165.
11. Aron, Penser la guerre, 9.
12. NAF 28060, boîte 209, letter from H. Rosinski to Raymond Aron from June 11,
1938.
13. Herbert Rosinski, “Die Entwicklung von Clausewitz’ Werk Vom Kriege im
Lichte seiner ‘Vorreden’ und ‘Nachrichten,’ ” Historische Zeitschrift, no. 151, 1935,
278–293.
14. Aron, Mémoires, 72.
15. Christian Malis, Raymond Aron et le débat stratégique français, 1930–1966, Paris,
Economica, 2005, 27.
16. Aron, Mémoires, 171–173.
17. L’Année cruciale, par le critique militaire de la revue La France libre, London,
Hamish Hamilton, 1944, 100.
18. Aron, Mémoires, 171.
19. Erich Ludendorff, Der totale Krieg, Munich, Ludendorff, 1935.
“C I T I Z E N C L AU S E W I T Z” 87
20. The formula appears twice in On War: I, 1, 24 (67): “war is merely the continuation
of policy by other means,” and VIII, 6B (703): “war is simply a continuation of political
intercourse, with the addition of other means. We deliberately use the phrase ‘with the
addition of other means’ because we also want to make it clear that war in itself
does not suspend political intercourse or change it into something entirely differ-
ent.” Aron preferred the latter version, because it suggests, with more emphasis
than the former, the permanence of policy during the war and the subordination
of warfare to political aims.
21. Raymond Aron, “La stratégie totalitaire et l’avenir des démocraties” (May 1942),
reprinted in Chroniques de guerre: La France libre 1940–1945, Paris, Gallimard,
1990, 561.
22. Raymond Aron, “La menace des Césars,” La France libre, vol. V, no. 25, November
1942, 24–31.
23. Hans Delbrück, Geschichte der Kriegskunst im Rahmen der politischen Geschichte,
Berlin, Stilke, 1900–1920 (4 vols.); new edition: Hamburg, Nikol, 2003.
24. Ibid., 396.
25. Hull, Absolute Destruction, Chapter 9: “Waging War, 1914–1916: Risk, Extremes,
and Limits, Strategic Vacuum.”
26. Raymond Aron, “Discours à des étudiants allemands sur l’avenir de l’Europe,” La
Table ronde, no. 1, January 1948, 63–86.
27. Hanson W. Baldwin, Great Mistakes of the War, London, Alvin Redman, 1950,
105. See also Aron, Penser la guerre, II, n. xviii, 332–334.
28. Raymond Aron, Le Grand Schisme, Paris, Gallimard, 1948, 13.
29. Raymond Aron, “Bataille des propagandes,” La France libre, vol. IV, no. 23, 372–
379. Reprinted in Chroniques de guerre: La France libre 1940–1945, Paris, Gallimard,
1990, 583.
30. Aron, Le Grand Schisme, 30.
31. Raymond Aron, “Zwischen dem begrenzten und dem totalen Krieg,” Der Monat,
vol. 22–23, July–August 1950, 455 sqq.
32. Raymond Aron, “De la paix sans victoire. Note sur les relations de la stratégie et
de la politique,” Revue française de science politique, vol. 1, no. 3, 1951, 241–255.
33. Clausewitz, De la guerre, 703.
34. While the Niederwerfungsstrategie focuses on battle alone to destroy enemy forces,
the Ermattungsstrategie (a term coined by Delbrück) combines maneuvers and
small-scale fighting when will or resources are limited. “Strategy of attrition,”
a designation that is being used for Verdun, does not match the type of limited
war envisioned by Clausewitz as “war of the second kind” and by Delbrück as
Ermattungsstrategie. By the same token, we prefer to translate Niederwerfungsstrategie
by “strategy of overthrow” instead of “strategy of annihilation” (a choice made in
many publications), because, as we have seen, Clausewitz insists that by “destruc-
tion of enemy forces,” he means to disarm them, not to destroy them physically.
Physical destruction may be the outcome, it should not be the aim of warfare.
35. Aron, “De la paix sans victoire,” 253.
36. So did Admiral Sanguinetti. Alexandre Sanguinetti, La France et l’arme atomique,
Paris, Juillard, 1964, 21.
37. NAF 28060, boîte 88, letter from Raymond Aron to Bernard Brodie, November
23, 1965. Quoted in Malis, Raymond Aron et le débat stratégique français, 1930–1966,
729.
38. Raymond Aron, Paix et guerre entre les nations, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1962, 409.
88 JOËL MOU RIC
39. Raymond Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle. Essais non partisans, Paris, Calmann-Lévy,
1957, 367.
40. Ibid., 241.
41. Ibid., 270. See also “La course à l’arme absolue,” Le Figaro, December 2, 1955.
42. Robert E. Osgood, Limited War: The Challenge to American Strategy, Chicago,
University of Chicago Press, 1957, 315.
43. Henry A. Kissinger, Nuclear Weapons and Foreign Policy, New York, Harper, 1957,
463.
44. Clausewitz, De la guerre, I, 1, 28.
45. Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle, 292.
46. Raymond Aron, La Société industrielle et la guerre, Paris, Plon, 1959, 300: “The
strategy of deterrence divides the diplomatic field which communications and
production technologies tend to unify.”
47. Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle, 300.
48. Ibid., 310.
49. Aron, Paix et guerre entre les nations, 794. See 157.
50. Clausewitz, De la guerre, 703.
51. Aron, Paix et guerre entre les nations, 586–587.
52. Ibid., 572.
53. Ibid., Chapter XXII: En quête d’une stratégie, II: Survivre, c’est vaincre. Aron’s
formula was later challenged by Richard Pipes in Survival Is Not Enough, New
York, Simon and Schuster, 1984, 302.
54. Aron, Paix et guerre entre les nations, 557–558.
55. Conferences at the Institute for European studies at the Université libre de
Bruxelles, April 28–30, 1975, in L’Europe des crises, Bibliothèque de la fondation
Paul-Henri Spaak, Bruxelles, Bruylant, 1976, 105.
56. Berthold C. Friedl, Les Fondements théoriques de la guerre et de la paix en URSS, suivi
du Cahier de Lénine sur Clausewitz, Paris, Médicis, 1945, 205.
57. Clausewitz, De la guerre, 70.
58. Aron, Penser la guerre, II, 139–140.
59. Ibid., II, 174. Aron nevertheless liked the idea of an unlimited line of credit. See
I, 296: “Besides, the English f leet in the last century only maintained its rule on
credit: no enemy ever challenged it, nor forced it to honor its bills through a pay-
ment in cash.”
60. Raymond Aron, De la condition historique du sociologue, Paris, Gallimard, 1971,
58.
61. Carl von Clausewitz en son temps et aujourd’hui (1971–1972). NAF 28060, boxes
23– 26. The lectures of 1972–1973 and 1973–1974 were published as Leçons sur
l’histoire, Paris, de Fallois, 1989, 455.
62. Aron, Penser la guerre, I, 13.
63. Raymond Aron, “Clausewitz et l’État,” Annales. Histoire, Sciences Sociales, vol. 32,
no. 6, 1977, 1262.
64. Heinrich Dietrich von Bülow, Théorèmes de la guerre moderne ou stratégie pure et
appliquée, taken from l’Esprit du système de la guerre moderne, Berlin, Fröhlich,
1805.
65. Aron, Penser la guerre, I, 82.
66. Ibid., especially 343–346 and 371–374.
67. Ludendorff, Der totale Krieg, 3.
68. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire: Essai sur les limites de
l’objectivité historique, Paris, Gallimard, 1938.
“C I T I Z E N C L AU S E W I T Z” 89
FIN DE SIÈCLE:
ARON AND THE END OF THE BIPOLAR SYSTEM
Carlos Gaspar
Fin de siècle
According to Kissinger, the consolidation of the bipolar system made possible the
creation of a “peace structure.” The new diplomatic configuration was based, on
the one hand, on the equality between the two superpowers and on a “peaceful
competition”—almost an alliance—between the two great powers and, on the
other, on the growing European and Asian autonomy, marked by the emergence
for the fi rst time in history of a “world concert,” including a système à quatre (sys-
tem of four) formed by the United States, the Soviet Union, China, and Japan.4
The détente summits signaled not only the end of the Cold War, but also the end
of the postwar era.5
92 C A R L O S G A S PA R
This system began to crumble with the Yom Kippur War in October 1973,
the most serious confrontation between the United States and the Soviet Union
since the Cuban missile crisis. Contrary to theories about a Soviet-American
condominium, the confl ict in the Middle East confi rmed the divergences in the
superpowers’ interests and purposes. At the crucial moment, no one remembered
the rules of détente that were part of the code of conduct solemnly adopted by
the United States and the Soviet Union at their last summit before the confl ict.6
The limits to détente were confi rmed during the following months. After
Nixon’s resignation, the United States accumulated defeats, both in Europe,
with the prospect of “Portugal sliding towards a pro-communist authoritarian
regime,” and in Asia, when Congress refused to approve the funds necessary for
supporting its allies in Saigon.7 At the same time, there was a succession of crises
in the bilateral relations between the two superpowers, fi rst at the Vladivostok
summit and later when the Soviet Union was refused the status of “most favored
nation.” Bipolar tension took the place of Soviet-American détente, without
any substantial change: “None of the two great powers has a serious chance of
obtaining a decisive superiority.”8
The fall of Saigon, the Portuguese Revolution, and the Soviet-Cuban inter-
vention in Angola confi rmed this turning point. The decline of the United States
and Western Europe, the economic crisis, and the internal divisions among the
Western democracies were creating “a fi n de siècle climate.”9
The crisis in Portugal proved decisive. Right from the start, the Portuguese
revolution had the ability to affect the transition in Spain and how things evolved
in France: in Portugal and Spain, “Communists may advance without violating
the unwritten rules of the division of Europe. France will be next.”10 Italy was
also at stake, with the Communists’ increasing electoral strength. The strategy of
the Portuguese Communist Party for gaining political power had the fi rm sup-
port of the Kremlin, in spite of the détente, Kissinger’s warnings, and opposition
from the Italian and Spanish Communists: “The action taken by the Portuguese
Communist Party, under Moscow’s influence, bothers the Italians, who reject
it, and the French, who claim their solidarity. Cunhal and his party have osten-
sibly applied Lenin’s 1917 tactics and this should awaken the fear of Soviet
Communism both in France and in Italy.”11 European Communists achieved a
position unprecedented since the end of World War II, and their advances could
undermine both democracy and the regional balance: “the fate of Europe is
being decided in Portugal, Spain, and Italy.”12
The Soviet-Cuban military intervention in Angola ensured the victory of
the MPLA and completed the change in Moscow’s strategy. Apparently, in the
autumn of 1974, after the Soviet Union had reached “global parity” with the
United States, the Kremlin leaders decided that the “correlation of forces” was
favorable for consolidating their European sphere of influence with the Helsinki
accords and simultaneously taking the offensive in Vietnam, Portugal, and
Angola, while restoring ideological discipline against the Eurocommunists’
democratic delusions: “The party of Alvaro Cunhal in Portugal and the soldiers
of Fidel Castro in Angola behave in accordance with the rules of that strategy,
FIN DE SIÈCLE 93
the answer is obvious. But if one rejects such a confusion, the future remains
open.”24
In 1975, pessimism prevailed once more, but without the confidence of the
early years of the Cold War. Aron felt, as he did in 1930 on his fi rst trip to
Germany, that “history is again on the move.”25 The distinction between decline
and decadence remained valid and, in this sense, it was still possible for him to
make a fi nal defense of decadent Europe:26 the decline of Europe on the interna-
tional balance was undeniable, but the destiny of the West, as Arnold Toynbee
upheld against Oswald Spengler, was not yet decided. The main problem in the
crisis was the Europeans’ loss of confidence in themselves, which was in turn
inseparable from the triple economic, political, and social crisis undermining the
political legitimacy of the democracies. In 1973, the energy crisis precipitated the
fi rst Western economic recession since the war, ending nearly three decades of
continuous growth. In the years that followed the rise of the Communist parties,
the radicalization of the Socialist left, and the polarization of the political system,
particularly in Italy and in France, seemed to justify the reference to a “Weimar
syndrome”: “a distribution of votes which forces upon democracy the choice
between two forms of suicide, either by giving power to those that will destroy
it, or by violating its own principle of legitimacy.”27 At the same time, there was
a growing social crisis, where the excesses of freedom and the idols of moder-
nity were diluting the traditional values sustaining authority and order, as in the
“civilization crises” described by Vilfredo Pareto: “Liberty dissolves beliefs and
prejudices, accelerates the downfall of the existing order, and makes for the rise
of a new, less skeptical, and more brutal ruling minority.”28
The three crises converged in a crisis of legitimacy for European democra-
cies, exposed to “Tocqueville’s Law” of “failed liberalizations” and therefore
threatened by the risk of political revolution.29 The Portuguese revolution was
yet another demonstration of the perils of late liberalization, but the democratic
outcome of the post-authoritarian transition demonstrated the greater strength
of liberalization in advanced industrial societies, also confi rmed by the success of
the regime-changes in Greece and Spain.30 In a sense, liberalization in Southern
Europe, as well as parallel trends in Eastern Europe, marked the end of the his-
torical period of revolutions. For the more optimistic, such as Ernest Gellner,
the functional elites in the modern societies of Eastern Europe, like their peers
in Western Europe, had no use for communist ideology, while growing eco-
nomic affluence made repressive Leninist regimes superfluous: between indus-
trial modernity and ideological boredom, communist regimes would eventually
yield to the spirit of the time.31
These arguments paid homage to his thesis on industrial society, but Aron,
without denying the trends toward liberalization in Poland, Hungary, or
Czechoslovakia, doubted that the time had come for political change in the
Soviet Union.32 On the contrary, for him the Soviet regime was as much stable
and durable as it appeared original: “A regime which is the outgrowth of Asiatic
despotism or, rather, a military empire under a centralized bureaucracy, is histor-
ically one of the most lasting and stable political forms, as long as its ruling class
retains its coherence.”33 At this juncture, dominated by the decline of the United
FIN DE SIÈCLE 95
States and the rise of the Soviet Union, it was not possible to exclude the pos-
sibility of a European suicide—“L’Europe éclatante peut être l’Europe condamnée”34 (a
flourishing Europe may become a condemned Europe).
Realism and moderation tempered his pessimism. It was unlikely that the
prolonged impasse between the incomplete decadence of the declining European
democracies and the imperfect stability of the expanding Soviet empire would
give rise to some catastrophic decision: “It does not seem to me that the next
years will present an exceptional opportunity” that the Soviets could not miss if
they wanted to “conquer Western Europe without destroying it.”35
The “geopolitical map” of the world had not changed fundamentally: the
system continued to embrace all five continents and to be divided into two
sub-systems with different rules; the dominant ideology was still a national
one, in contrast with the empires’ transnational ideologies; most states, unlike
the European nations, did not rule over a homogenous people; and the same
contrast continued to set “the apparent stability of the abnormal status quo in
Europe against the multiple changes in the rest of the world.”36 Soviet hege-
mony, denounced before and after the invasion of Afghanistan,37 was but a result
of the short-term superiority of their weapons on the European theater and the
ability to project military force anywhere in the world: “The Soviets have not
replaced the Americans in their imperial function.”38 Continuity still prevailed
over change: “From here to the end of the century, the United States and the
Soviet Union will keep their position as the two major powers.”39
Envoi
The cunning of reason decided otherwise. Raymond Aron did not foresee, just
as almost no one else did, the end of the Cold War,40 but he never stopped
thinking about this question.41 In the early years, the settling of the bipolar dis-
pute was expected to be short-term: “It would be absurd to consider the acci-
dental constellation which came out of World War II as more lasting than the
one existing at the beginning of the century.”42 The alternative scenarios of a
Soviet or a Western victory formed the totalitarian nightmare, anticipating “the
wars among the irreconcilable disciples of the prophet” against a comparatively
benign American hegemony: “a semi-pacification imposed by the domination of
an industrial republic has nothing in common with the end of history.”43
The end of Stalinism made possible an end to the international divide in the
best possible way, through an internal change of the Soviet regime. The dif-
ficult choice between the stability of the “new class” and the totalitarian move-
ment was evident: “The Soviet bourgeoisie wants the end of revolution but the
regime is condemned to a perpetual fuite en avant [headlong rush].”44 At the same
time, the Hungarian revolution marked “the defeat of Russian communism in
Europe—a defeat which is, in my view, a defi nitive defeat.”45 Soviet commu-
nism lost its international prestige and the Leninist regime its ideological élan:
“The regime may survive without faith,” but it could no longer deny the Soviet
elites’ desire for openness, which could cause a fatal “ideological indiscipline.”46
Similarly, the structural tensions between the modern production system and
96 C A R L O S G A S PA R
the Asian political regime would become more pronounced if the Soviet Union
resisted liberalization: “A regime which is an extension of Oriental despotism is
hostage to a permanent contradiction as long as it pretends to be the achieve-
ment of Western rationalism . . . Does industrial society fit into the framework
of Oriental despotism?”47 But the dual crisis of Suez and Hungary also demon-
strated the complicity of the “enemy brothers” and the Soviet determination to
protect its empire: the Cold War would last.
The debates about Soviet liberalization and international détente went on for
a decade. Against Kennan or Kissinger, Aron emphasized the “ideocratic” nature
of the communist regime,48 which not only limited the conditions for internal
liberalization49 but also prevented the Soviet Union from being a country like all
the others and becoming a partner in a world order: the Cold War could only end
by the transformation of its political system. In any case, his original defi nition—
“Communism is at once an army and a church”50 —gained new meaning with
the transformation of the secular Leninist religion into a theocratic bureaucracy
and the metamorphosis of the Soviet Union into a military empire.
For Aron, it was obvious that Soviet communism had failed, and it was
unlikely that an empire could extend its domination without an underlying
political legitimacy: “Empires live and die. If the one in Moscow relies solely
on brute force, is it destined to last for very long?”51 The stability of the Soviet
Union depended on the cohesion of its elites, and succession could lead to a crisis:
“When a new generation assumes the supreme responsibilities, they will perhaps
ask two questions: Why so many weapons? Why should we be denied the means
of prosperity? The destiny of the Soviet Union, as well as our own, depends on
their answer to those questions.”52
Eventually, Mikhail Gorbachev would answer those questions and pave the
way for the peaceful end of the Cold War, but Aron was aware of the shortcom-
ings of his reflections on the subject and at his last meeting with Hedley Bull told
the latter: “It is my view that the most important and indeed the most neglected
question in contemporary International Relations scholarship is: what will the
West do when and if the Soviets decline? How we answer this question will per-
haps determine whether there will be war or peace in our time.”53
Raymond Aron was the greatest chronicler of the Cold War; he devised a
formula summarizing its strategic dilemma and developed complex models for
analyzing the “diplomatic constellations,” where he combined three dimen-
sions—the unity of the international system and the bipolar structure, the uni-
versal diff usion of the secular religion of the Soviet empire, and the nuclear
revolution and total war54 —while never failing to place the age dominated by
the competition between the United States and the Soviet Union within twenti-
eth-century history, the fi nal direction of which he anticipated in a rare moment
of enthusiasm: “History is moving towards liberty.”55
Notes
1. Raymond Aron, “Les chances d’un règlement européen,” Politique étrangère, vol.
14, no. 6, 1949, 255.
FIN DE SIÈCLE 97
2. Raymond Aron, Paix et guerre entre les nations, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1962, 147.
3. Georges-Henri Soutou, “Raymond Aron et la crise de Cuba,” in Maurice Vaïsse
(coord.), L’Europe et la crise de Cuba, Paris, Fayard, 1993.
4. Raymond Aron, “La fin du système bipolaire,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles
du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997,
970; Raymond Aron, “Après l’après-guerre” in Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les
Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997.
5. Raymond Aron, République impériale: Les États-Unis dans le monde 1945–1972,
Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1973, 325.
6. Raymond Aron, “Détente et condominium,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du
Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997, 1318.
See also Raymond Aron, “De Yalta à Moscou,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du
Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997.
7. Raymond Aron, “Défaite au Vietnam,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro,
Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997, 1501.
8. Raymond Aron, “Le ciel ne va pas tomber sur nos têtes,” in Raymond Aron,
Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de
Fallois, 1997, 1469. See also Raymond Aron, “La mystification de Vladivostok,”
in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3,
Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997, 1433.
9. Aron dialogue avec Alexandre Soljénitsyne, “La IIIe guerre mondiale n’aura pas
lieu,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977),
vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997, 1543.
10. Raymond Aron, “Décrispation tous azimuts,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles
du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997,
1552.
11. Raymond Aron, “Conférence introuvable,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du
Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997,
1604. See also Pierre Hassner, “Détente and the Politics of Instability in Southern
Europe,” in Johan Holst and Uwe Nehrlich (eds.), Beyond Nuclear Deterrence: New
Aims, New Arms, New York, Crane, Russak, 1977, 41–59 and Pierre Hassner,
“The Communist Parties of Southern Europe: The International Dimension,”
Lo Spettatore Internazionale, vol. 13, no. 3, 237–266.
12. Raymond Aron, “Limites de la coopération franco-soviétique” in Raymond
Aron, Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions
de Fallois, 1997, 1580–1581.
13. Raymond Aron, “Les communistes français et Moscou I. Les deux volets du dyp-
tique,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les crises (1965–1977),
vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997, 1658.
14. Raymond Aron, “Directoire européen?” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro,
Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997, 1650.
15. Raymond Aron, “Contre la psychose de guerre,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles
du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997,
1625.
16. Raymond Aron, “Diplomatie française en crise,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles
du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997,
1664.
17. Raymond Aron, “La France en première ligne,” in Raymond Aron, De Giscard
à Mitterrand (1977–1983), Paris, Editions de Fallois, 2005, 167. See also Odd
Arne Westad, “Moscow and the Angolan Crisis, 1974–1976: A New Pattern
98 C A R L O S G A S PA R
of Intervention,” Cold War International History Project Bulletin, no. 8–9, 1996,
21–37.
18. Raymond Aron, “La détente après Helsinki,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du
Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997,
1625.
19. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire: Essai sur les limites de
l’objectivité historique, Paris, Gallimard, 1938; Raymond Aron, Essai sur la théorie
de l’histoire dans l’Allemagne contemporaine. La philosophie critique de l’histoire, Paris,
Gallimard, 1938.
20. Raymond Aron, Mémoires, Paris, Julliard, 1983, 666–680.
21. Raymond Aron, Plaidoyer pour l’Europe décadente, Paris, Laffont, 1977, 26.
22. Raymond Aron, Le Grand Schisme, Paris, Gallimard, 1948, 337.
23. Raymond Aron, Espoir et peur du siècle. Essais non partisans, Paris, Calmann-Lévy,
1957, 228.
24. Ibid., 229.
25. Raymond Aron, “La crise et les successions. Les incertitudes du Kremlin,” in
Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3,
Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997, 1589.
26. Aron explains in his Memoirs the ambiguity and the irony of the title he chose
against the best wishes of his publisher. Aron, Mémoires, 675. Raymond Aron,
“My Defense of Our Decadent Europe,” Encounter, vol. 49, no. 3, 1977, 11–32.
27. Aron, Plaidoyer pour l’Europe décadente, 27. See also Raymond Aron, “Démocraties
en crise le syndrome de Weimar,” in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro, Tome
3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997, 1721–1725.
28. Aron, Plaidoyer pour l’Europe décadente, 28, 420–421.
29. Raymond Aron makes a clear distinction between the European and the American
crises. In the United States democracy is not on the verge of breakdown: “The
United States are a young country capable of recovery. At a given moment they
seem crushed and, a few years later, they will be in a state of delirious opti-
mism. They are a historically young people and they are able to forget.” Aron,
Plaidoyer pour l’Europe décadente, 438. Cfr. Raymond Aron, Le Spectateur engagé,
Paris, Julliard, 1981, 280.
30. Raymond Aron, “La victoire de Caramanlis de l’exil à l’investiture,” in Raymond
Aron, Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions
de Fallois, 1997; Raymond Aron, “Après Franco les équivoques de la transition,”
in Raymond Aron, Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3,
Paris, Editions de Fallois, 1997. Raymond Aron, “Rien de nouveau à Madrid,”
in Les Articles du Figaro, Tome 3: Les Crises (1965–1977), vol. 3, Paris, Editions de
Fallois, 1997.
31. Ernest Gellner, “Plaidoyer pour une libéralisation manquée,” in Ernest Gellner,
Spectacles and Predicaments, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1979, 339–
340. See also John Hall, Power and Liberties, Harmondsworth, Pelican, 1986,
203–210.
32. Aron, Plaidoyer pour l’Europe décadente, 469, 474. On the exchange between Aron
and Gellner, see Ernest Gellner, “From Revolution to Liberalisation,” Government
and Opposition, vol. 11, no. 3, 1976, 252–272; Aron, Plaidoyer pour l’Europe déca-
dente, 457–474. Raymond Aron, “On Liberalization,” Government and Opposition,
vol. 14, no. 1, 1979, 37–57. Ernest Gellner, “Plaidoyer pour une libéralisation
manquée,” Government and Opposition, vol. 14, no. 1, 1979, 58–65.
FIN DE SIÈCLE 99
R aymond Aron spent his life defending “liberal democracy.” What is the
status of liberal democracy and the study of it today? Any “casual look”
shows a close relationship between authoritarian and poor countries, on the one
hand, and democratic regimes and rich countries, on the other. This question has
been part of the research agenda since at least 1960, when Lipset1 questioned the
relationship between democracy and development. Empirical research distin-
guishes two “causal mechanisms” in order to explain the correlation: democra-
cies emerge in economically developing dictatorships either by an “endogenous”
process or for other “exogenous” reasons, but they survive longer in developed
countries and so there is an accumulation of democratic regimes in these coun-
tries. The first mechanism assumes that dictatorships die when countries ruled
by them develop because such countries can no longer be governed effectively
by command or because—more crudely stated—the political systems there are
determined by economic factors. This is a mechanism consistent with modern-
ization theory: there is one general process, which begins with industrialization
and urbanization, goes through education and mass communication, and culmi-
nates in social and political mobilization and democratization. Adam Przeworski
summarizes thus: GDP per capita is the most suitable indicator predicting the
type of regime.2 If so, China will be democratic when it develops. A second
type of mechanism was also ambiguously suggested by Lipset,3 but has only
recently been explored. It is based on the assumption that if democracies emerge
randomly during the development stage, they are more likely to survive in a
rich country, and there is also a cumulative effect of monotonic convergence,4
which is also consistent with the correlation between the two factors. This sec-
ond hypothesis is consistent with the role of human freedom in history. Men
make democracies emerge and the environment is responsible only for allowing
102 JOSÉ COLEN A N D SCOTT N ELSON
Notes
1. Seymour Martin Lipset, Political Man: The Social Bases of Politics, New York,
Doubleday, 1960, 27–65.
2. Adam Przeworski, Michel Alvarez, José António Cheibub, and Fernando
Limogi, Democracy and Development: Political Institutions and Well Being in the World,
1950–1999, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2000, 78, 111; 87–89, on
the indicators 79 and 88; David L. Epstein, Robert Bates, Jack Goldstone, Ida
Kristiensen, and Sharyn O’Halloran, “Democratic Transitions,” American Journal
of Political Science, vol. 50, no. 3, July 2006, Appendix, 26–27. Cf. also Samuel
Huntington, “Vinte anos depois: o futuro da terceira vaga,” in AAVV, A invenção
da democracia, Lisboa, Fundação Mário Soares—ICS, 2000, 20.
3. Lipset, Political Man, 29 and 61, also suggests that democracy can be a cause (facili-
tator) of economic development.
4. Przeworski, Alvarez, Cheibub, and Limogi, Democracy and Development, 90.
5. Not only life expectancy arises from 8 to 18 years with a GDP per capita greater
than $1,000, but if it is greater than $6,000 then we have a miracle: no democ-
racy ever returns to a dictatorship. Robert Dahl, while denying that there was a
linear tendency, nevertheless established one at a GDP per capita of $800 in 1957.
Robert A. Dahl, Polyarchy. Participation and Opposition, New Haven and London,
Yale University Press, 1971, 67–68.
CHAPTER 8
Perrine Simon-Nahum
“To achieve one’s secular salvation.” As he neared the end of his life, it was
with these words that Raymond Aron summarized his intellectual journey in
his Mémoires. History was at his life’s center. Above all else, the notion of history
provided a framework for a philosophy that turned its back on the idealism of the
preceding philosophical generation. Instead, it sought to rethink the inscription
of the individual in the historical world in light of the tension between freedom
and determinism. In both Raymond Aron’s World War II participation in the
Resistance in London and his ideological positioning during Cold War clashes
between supporters of the Soviet Union and defenders of Western democracies,
history was one of his works’ central themes. In France, he pioneered histori-
cal analysis of both international relations and modern societies threatened by
nuclear extinction. This critical research continued all the way through the 1970s
right up to his 1984 posthumous book Les Dernières Années du siècle. Furthermore,
his dialogue with sociology helped him redefi ne a notion of history that was able
to meet the demands of a critical philosophy.
been leveled against him at the time of his thesis. However, it also follows from
his view of the dangers posed by theories that identify history with quasi-bi-
ological cycles of civilization, thus subjecting each civilization’s existence to a
unique ideal and rendering the fate of one irreducible to that of all the others.
The plurality of the historical objects we call events, like the plurality of inter-
pretations historians offer to account for them, does not, according to Aron,
under any circumstances signify that the search for historical truths must be
abandoned. In a 1958 colloquium at Cerisy, Aron engaged in a dialogue with the
philosopher Arnold Toynbee on the danger that plurality poses for truth. Aron
sought to refute the idea championed by Toynbee (and Spengler before him)
that the diversity of civilizations would prohibit the conceptualization of a unity
of human spirit. If all civilizations are equal, each is accountable only to itself,
expressing nothing but its singular nature. Consequently, in Toynbee’s theory,
history oscillates between each culture’s specific destiny and that of humanity
taken as a whole, thereby preventing all intermediate distinctions and compari-
sons. Therefore, the essential question raised for the philosopher hinges on the
formation of historic ensembles and the reality of history’s objects. The notions
of causality and coherence that Aron invokes as the basis of the historian’s work
are thus diametrically opposed to Spenglerian relativism, which rules out com-
parisons of one civilization with another. In a similar way, these two notions
undermine the empirical schema advanced by Toynbee, which can only explain
cultures as expressions of an abstract humanity, thus depriving the historian lost
in the universality of viewpoints of any explanatory power. In the absence of
a reflexive principle, historical construction becomes impossible. Instead, it is
actually driven by external principles based on implicit value judgments.
There must be a response other than metaphysics (Spengler) or theology
(Toynbee) to the constituent tension that Aron sees at work in the postwar
twentieth century, a tension that forged the consciousness of an unprecedent-
edly unified destiny of peoples. Potential nuclear destruction and rapid technical
progress had made it possible, but different peoples still had the distinct feeling
that their ways of life remained singular. This tension provides the starting point
for Aron’s critique of historical reason, a critique that legitimized itself through
recourse to a reflective causality that structures the field of historical experience
and its possible interpretations. The historian constructs his object, following a
logic at least partly dictated by the reality of the events he intends to study. This
logic is at the same time immanent and counterfactual. Philosophy operates in
this tension between the reality it seeks to explain and the constructions it uses
to conceptually create this reality in the first place. The Aron of the 1960s was
thus no less a philosopher in his reflections than the young doctoral student of
the 1930s. Philosophy is vital to remind the historian that he always works with
historical objects he himself has constructed, but also, in the same way, to recall
the arbitrary nature of that construction. This arbitrariness is twofold. If Aron
insists on the historical situation of the historian himself, but only to a certain
extent, contingence is also at work in the application of epistemological concepts
to objects. It is at this level of analysis that Aron will later situate sociology.
Plurality is not just derived from the empirical observation of contemporary
events, even if one of the characteristics of the modern predicament consists
110 PER RIN E SIMON-NA HUM
provided him with a way to enter into a dialogue with Marxism and to combat
its disciples’ messianic interpretations of history. By elaborating the notion of
secular religions and on the belief implied by adherence to the Soviet model,
Aron continuously challenged the teleological reading of history propagated by
Soviet Communism’s fellow travelers. Key French intellectuals, such as Sartre
and Merleau-Ponty, figured prominently among them. This argument was at the
center of a series of articles that Aron published in the revue Preuves, the publica-
tion of the Congress for Cultural Freedom, as well as in the 1955 book L’Opium
des intellectuels, published contemporaneously with Merleau-Ponty’s Aventures de
la Dialectique17. It also surfaced in a large number of the articles in Dimensions de la
conscience historique, continuing well into the 1970s in his lectures at the Collège
de France, Marxismes imaginaires, and D’une Sainte Famille à l’autre. Too often, the
violence of these debates concealed the philosophical depth of what was at stake.
Like others in the generation of the 1930s, Aron wanted to rethink the articula-
tion of freedom and determinism without recourse to any transcendent prin-
ciple. For a long while, Aron remained Sartre’s preferred sparring partner, even
if the latter sought to conceal it. Thus Sartre’s Les Carnets de la drôle de guerre18 and
his 1943 thesis L’Etre et le Néant 19claimed to be a response to the Introduction à la
philosophie de l’histoire. L’Opium des intellectuels, which subjected Aron to scandal
and anathema from the bien-pensante French left, should be read as a continuation
of his 1938 thesis. The three parts that compose it—Mythes politiques, Idolâtrie de
l’histoire et Aliénation des intellectuels—seek to probe the principal characteristics
of the European left and to submit them to a historical critique. Aron analyzes
Stalinism as an ideology that remains indebted to a kind of historicist gnosis. His
critique unfolds in two parts. In the fi rst, Aron takes the fellow travelers to task
for their philosophical thoughtlessness, taking Merleau-Ponty and later Sartre as
his main targets. Aron condemns the idea of a philosophy of existence in which
the individual’s absolute freedom is at the same time inscribed in the temporality
of a collective history over which he has no control and to which he must submit
if he wishes to fulfi ll his own essence. In the second, Aron rebukes interpreta-
tions of Marxism that pass political reality through the prism of a history whose
meaning is already predefi ned as the realization of humanity’s flourishing by the
Communist regime. His criticism is incontrovertible. In the Marxist concep-
tion of history, individual actors have no place. A classless society, communism’s
objective, “comes about spontaneously, necessarily, as a result of the actions and
reactions between individuals and groups,”20 without the intervention of some
kind of Providence. At the end of time man will see his own mystery revealed at
the same time as history’s. “But why,” asks Aron, “must the adventure draw to a
close?”21 and by virtue of what should it come to an end? Aron sees no explana-
tion other than faith and messianic conviction. For Christians, messianism desig-
nates a divine transcendence, but for the man of communist faith, it refers to the
transcendence of history. Aron condemns the deformation of history infl icted by
philosophies of history. From the point of view of the critic of historical reason,
nothing can guarantee our predictions of the future, nor even that there is such
a thing as the meaning of history. If we consider the situation of industrial soci-
eties that he investigates at the beginning of the 1960s, judging by the available
R AY M O N D A RO N A N D T H E N O T I O N O F H I S T O RY 113
information, nothing can assure the triumph of one model over another in the
competition between the centralized authoritarian socialist economy and a plu-
ralist constitutional regime espousing capitalist values. Adhering to the idea of
a meaning of history amounts to a disavowal of philosophical distance and the
adoption of a theological position. This is true not just of Sartre and Merleau-
Ponty but also of Toynbee. The political consequences are immediately visible. A
reign of terror is necessary if one is to uphold an ideological regime enamored of
its faith in historical eschatology. In the same way, thinkers espousing a form of
these teleologies are often led to justify violence. Aron’s critique of philosophies
of history, which broadened his pre-war analysis of totalitarianism, contained
the seeds of his 1950s critique of Third-Worldist thinkers. Aron’s appraisal of
the historical event thus allows us to comprehend the specificity of his political
position in the postwar period. His ability to articulate the different levels of cau-
sality, while remaining attentive to the role of uncertainty in individual actions,
explains why he did not cease to condemn the Soviet Union’s stranglehold on its
satellite states. This was true both for his endorsement of the decolonization of
French territories after 1956, notably in Algeria, where he had long anticipated
independence, and for the warnings he sounded from the 1960s onward about
policies that presupposed exponential and continuous economic progress.
of the international crises that were to follow: the bipolar schism, the shared des-
tiny of a humanity in the shadow of technological and economic progress, and
the spread of communist messianism. Certain variations notwithstanding, the
diagnosis fi rst outlined in 1951 in Guerres en chaîne remained valid throughout
the next half century because it allowed Aron to simultaneously shed light on the
motives of individual actors as well as on the equilibrium—or rather, disequilib-
rium—between productive, economic, political, cultural, and military-strategic
factors. He deployed a logic that combined the various levels of analysis, while
acknowledging not only the rational implementation of policies but also the role
of chance and accidents. Aron’s reflections on strategy ultimately lead back to his
interpretive conception of history and the idea of humanity’s uncertain future.
The most that could be expected from the latter is that it remains within the
horizon of a regulative ideal of reason. All of Aron’s work on international rela-
tions, from Paix et guerre entre les nations—considered by Aron himself to be his
third thesis, not least because it follows a similar structure as the Introduction à la
philosophie de l’histoire—to La République impériale, an analysis of US policy from
1945 to 1972, and the late works Penser la guerre, Clausewitz, and Dernières Années
du siècle, are based on a conception of history as “drama and process.”
History or Sociology?
The 1965 Gifford Lectures and a series of 1967 talks published as La Conscience
historique dans la pensée et dans l’action presented Aron with an occasion to revisit
his theory of history and to continue his engagement with Thucydides’ analysis
of political action and warfare. The debate over history came to hinge on the
issue of a possible space for critical thought. Does this mean that Aron’s thought
underwent a “sociological turn”? Numerous scholars have argued that, toward
the end of the 1960s, a sociological point of view seemed to have supplanted
Aron’s earlier historical approach to describe modern societies. But Aron, in fact,
indirectly reaffirmed history’s superiority by insisting on the primacy of politics
in contemporary societies. In the early 1970s, Aron sought to establish a research
methodology that was more interested in practical applicability even as it refused
to renounce its quest for objectivity. This ambition came to the fore in his lec-
tures at the Collège de France where Aron confronted the legacy of German
phenomenology with contributions from Anglophone analytic philosophy.
During those years, regardless of whether he worked on international relations
or the operations of different political regimes, Aron maintained a keen interest
in the epistemological issues raised by the interpretation of these phenomena. He
registered the rise of political science and sociology and attempted to critically
integrate the results of these two flourishing disciplines into his own analysis
of society. Yet, according to Aron, at no point did this disciplinary enrichment
call into question a notion of history that is uniquely capable of satisfying the
demands of critical reason. The comparative study of the advantages of these var-
ious disciplines constituted, fi rst and foremost, a reflection on the forms of con-
ceptualization they rely on. This was also a time when Aron engaged with the
uses of the concept of the model that became widespread throughout the social
R AY M O N D A RO N A N D T H E N O T I O N O F H I S T O RY 115
its pretentions. The philosopher casts doubt on the idea of a historical totality.
However, he also faces up to his political responsibilities. Between philosophy
and action, Aron carved out a space that he surveyed as an engaged spectator.
Notes
1. [Translator’s note]: Up until 1968 French doctoral dissertations involved both a
thèse and a thèse complémentaire, that is a main thesis and a secondary thesis.
2. Raymond Aron, Mémoires. 50 ans de réflexion politique, Paris, Editions Julliard,
1983, 53.
3. Ibid.
4. Georges Canguilhem, “La problématique de la philosophie de l’histoire au début
des années trente,” in Alain Boyer, et al. (eds.), Raymond Aron, la philosophie de
l’histoire et les sciences sociales, Paris, Éditions de la rue d’Ulm, 2005, 19–32.
5. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire: Essai sur les limites de
l’objectivité historique, Paris, Gallimard, “Bibliothèque des Idées,” 1938, 205.
6. These courses have been collected and edited by Sylvie Mesure in the volume
titled Leçons sur l’histoire, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 1989.
7. Thucydide, Histoire de la guerre du Péloponnèse, Paris, Gallimard, “Folio Classique,”
2000.
8. Correspondence of Alain with Florence and Élie Halévy, cited in Raymond Aron
(1905–1983). Histoire et politique, Commentaire, 1985, 344.
9. Raymond Aron, Dimensions de la conscience historique, Paris, Editions Plon, 1985
[originally 1961], preface.
10. Ibid., 87.
11. L’Histoire et ses représentations. Entretiens autour de Arnold Toynbee, sous la direction
de R. Aron, Paris, Mouton, 1961, 37–46.
12. Aron, Dimensions de la conscience historique, 70.
13. Ibid., 121.
14. Ibid., 126.
15. Raymond Aron, “Comment l’historien écrit l’épistémologie: à propos du livre de
Paul Veyne,” Annales E.S.C., vol. 26, 6, 1971, 1319–1354.
16. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, “La guerre a eu lieu,” Œuvres, Paris, Gallimard,
“Quarto,” 2010.
17. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Les Aventures de la dialectique, Paris, Gallimard, “Folio,”
2000.
18. Jean-Paul Sartre, Les Carnets de la drôle de guerre, Paris, Gallimard, 1995.
19. Jean-Paul Sartre, L’Etre et le Néant, Paris, Gallimard, “Tel,” 1976.
20. Raymond Aron, “La notion de sens de l’histoire,” in Raymond Aron, Dimensions
de la conscience historique, Paris, Plon, 1961, 32–45, 35.
21. Ibid.
22. Pierre Hassner, “L’histoire au XXème siècle,” Commentaire, Op. cit., 226–233,
228.
23. Aron, Leçons sur l’histoire, 442.
24. Raymond Aron, Penser la guerre, Clausewitz, vol. 1, Paris, Gallimard, 2009 [orig.
1976], 23–24.
CHAPTER 9
Giulio De Ligio
the political from a perspective defi ned by the decisive and unstable meeting point
between sociology and political philosophy.
most clearly the theoretical proposition, clarifying judgment and action, of “the
primacy of the political.” In the introduction to Démocratie et totalitarisme Aron
begins by recalling the ambiguity, or rather three ambiguities, of the concept. He
introduces the issue in an Aristotelian fashion: the term politics is used in many
ways. First, he distinguishes between two meanings of the word by referring to
two English terms: policy—a program of action—and politics—the domain where
programs of action are in opposition to one another. Then the term indicates
both the reality and our consciousness of reality, where the latter is integral to
reality itself. The third ambiguity is what we have just mentioned, and for Aron
it is the most important: the word politics, according to its present usage, desig-
nates both a particular sector as well as the social whole itself. In a certain sense
the defi nition of that partial sector, this “fragment of the whole,”16 logically links
it to the social whole since the repercussions of political decisions on the entire
collectivity defi ne the conditions and characteristics of the other sectors.
As we shall see, in this way Aron ends up reviving another sense of the term
that includes its limited sense and its encompassing sense and is expressed by the
Greek word politeia. Nevertheless, this does not mean that he is suggesting any
sort of “unilateral determinism” where one phenomenon determines everything
else, in this case politics determining all other social domains (a sort of Marxist
doctrine in reverse). As a liberal sociologist, he does not seek to establish a pri-
mary cause—or “in the last analysis”—of the whole of society and to invest
political government with a power indifferent to social conditions. If he affirms
the primacy of the political—if the liberal sociologist rediscovers the classical
philosopher through the political—it is because “the way of living of the entire
community,” which distinguishes between collectivities belonging to the same
“type of society,” is defi ned by their type of partial political system, their form of
government. Aron goes one step further, or back, by asserting that the primacy
of the political maintains in his era above all “a human meaning.” The political
is more important than, for example, the economy “in regards to man,” because
it most directly concerns “the meaning of existence itself ” and the “relations of
men with each other.” It does not “determine” the relations within the family or
the church or the workplace, but the political organization of authority and the
form of government contribute toward fashioning all the relations between men
and their consciousness thereof. The primacy of which Aron speaks is then not
“causal” but it concerns nevertheless the “human or non-human character of the
entire collectivity.”17
However one interprets the dialectic at work in the Aronian understanding of
the limited sense and the encompassing sense, the political order proves to be one
of the “eternal problems” resulting from the human condition and which have
seen “changing and forever imperfect solutions through the ages,”18 “solutions”
by which men actualize their humanity. For Aron this is what the twentieth
century confi rmed in spite of, or even within, the great social, economic, and
technological transformations that marked it and brought it about. Just as drama
remains possible in the industrial age and war must therefore be understood and
governed, modern society does not resolve, by its own “process,” the question
of the best regime.
TH E QU ESTION OF POLITICA L R EGIM E 125
also changes when one subordinates the political regime to the economic orga-
nization or to a historical stage of the collectivity. Aron sees the conceptions
affirming this transformation as subject to a double danger: total relativism and
dogmatism. In the two cases, the question of the ends of man or of the best regime
is not posed, because its response is given by history or because the question is
simply asked in vain.
As we have seen, Aron’s reaffi rmation of the question of the best regime does
not boil down to a simple return to classical philosophy. The work itself where
this theoretical proposition appears shows it clearly, although this is certainly not
Aron’s last word on the subject. Démocratie et totalitarisme was in effect intended to
serve as a sociological analysis of the political regimes of the twentieth century.
Originally, a set of lectures given at the Sorbonne in 1957–58, the work is note-
worthy in many respects. As the fi nale of a trilogy including Dix-Huit Leçons sur
la société industrielle and La Lutte de classes, it was meant to conclude a comparative
analysis of all the sectors of the two regimes that defi ned the twentieth century,
thereby completing the “true sense” of the investigation. Its original title, which
Aron thought was more accurate, encapsulated all the elements of the problem:
Sociologie des sociétés industrielles. Esquisse d’une théorie des régimes politiques. The
chapters introducing the analysis, whose importance we have already alluded to,
incorporate the terms of the dialectic that the title sums up. Aron reaffi rms the
primacy of the political regime and thus the persistence of that eminent question
in the twentieth century, all the while calling for a sociological investigation in
which Western democracy and Soviet totalitarianism are subsumed under the
same type of “industrial society.”
Without being able to enter into the details of Aron’s presentation, which
at times seem aporetic (although one should not forget Aron’s pedagogical or
“moderating” aim), one can underline the possible key, that is, the point at which
Aron’s approach is situated between philosophy and sociology. Aron justifies his
move from philosophical research to sociological study by the wish or neces-
sity to analyze how political institutions translate moral principles, on the one
hand, in a given social organization (in this case, industrial society) and, on the
other, taking into account the plurality of objectives pursued by the political
order. When he mentions the reasons that led him to “discard” the philosophical
search, a search whose sense he wishes on the other hand to extend, Aron means
to say that he has discarded the search for the best regime “in the abstract.”22
He does not reject the question “sociologically” because it “is part of the real-
ity itself.”23 Thus, in order to describe and judge the regimes of his time, Aron
does not reject classical philosophies (as does Hannah Arendt) but takes the cri-
terion of number, employed in that “venerable book” of Aristotle, and applies it
to an organization based on party representation (one or many).24 Furthermore,
he draws on Montesquieu’s notion of “principle” to bolster his explanation. It
would be necessary to see how this political analysis of the social dimension is
enlarged and complicated by taking into account the relation between spiritual
power and temporal power, the ideology, or the “metaphysical intention” at the
origin of the “secular religions.”25 In any case, it will suffice here to summa-
rize the two conclusions at which the entire Aronian reflection arrives without
TH E QU ESTION OF POLITICA L R EGIM E 127
character of “political change.” This science leads Aron to pose the problem
and analyze the types of corruption, which is always possible and ever fatal, for
political regimes.32 It culminates in an attempt to classify political regimes that
Aron outlines and systematizes for the societies of his time. His Remarques sur la
classifi cation des régimes politiques (1965) applies “a method conforming more to
the tradition of Aristotle or Montesquieu” than to that of Weber.33 However, if
typology of principles of legitimacy elaborated by the German emperor of soci-
ology proves for Aron to be too formal to contribute to the historical discern-
ment of the essential characteristics of regimes, the Aristotelian classification itself
presupposes the infrastructure of a certain type of society, the Greek city. Once
again, one fi nds here the conclusions of the French political school. Aron again
reminds us that it is necessary to attempt an analytical combination: a classifica-
tion capable of rendering intelligible the realities of the twentieth century should
combine—following Montesquieu’s approach, although avoiding the difficulties
raised by some of his arguments that suggest an “inexorable determinism”—the
classification of social types and that of political regimes.34
We can now better understand “the lesson of the century,” which, for Aron,
should drive the sociologists to overcome their “simplistic conception of the
social totality,” to discard “the utopia of a unified and homogeneous soci-
ety,” therefore to come to recognize politics as “an eternal category of human
existence, a permanent sector of every society.” It was the old lesson given by
Tocqueville: “The political regime determines, for the most part, the form of the
collectivity . . . The sociologists of the West take up the alternative of Alexis de
Tocqueville. Certainly, modern societies are inevitably industrial, commercial,
democratic; but are they liberal or despotic? The choice depends on the political
regime.”35 The “lesson of Tocqueville” seems to reveal the core of the Aronian
approach. It is this manner of political thinking that helps one recognize the
essential alternatives, even if the social phenomena of an era are not reducible to
them. It is this analytical practice that preserves, within more or less providential
transformations, the question of the justice of the city, of the grandeur of man,
and of the ultimate meaning of the evolution of the world. It is this classical per-
spective that helps one see “further than the parties.” It is the voice that Aron
proclaims at the end of his inaugural lecture at the Collège de France because it
gives encouragement to those who bow neither before the modern Prometheus
nor before the despondent expectation of the last man. It is the “new political
science” that illuminates the thinker who is always interested in political choices
because he accepts the path of modern civilization, all the while knowing that
humanity has followed it “for good or for ill.” It is the “salutary fear” or the
“limpid and sad prose” that nourishes the philosophical concern of the sociolo-
gist, who, analyzing the course of history and its societies, tries to discern “what
is important” and asks himself: “by what right can one affirm that men will
lose or save their souls in the cathedrals of cement, glass, or metal, which they
build for themselves and their descendants?”36 By reading him politically, Aron
rediscovers in the thinker of the “two distinct humanities” a sociologist who is at
the same time a philosopher, a voice that echoes through the ages, and a classical
educator of modern democracy.
TH E QU ESTION OF POLITICA L R EGIM E 129
philosopher continues to fulfi ll his role in the middle of the war. Even when he
supports the democratic cause, Aron does not refrain from examining its nature
and its weaknesses. In his eyes, what is crucial is showing on the one hand that
democracy is the regime whose essence requires the enduring support of political
consciousness, and on the other, that, without responding fatally to a historical
necessity, “the progression of constitutions is not coincidental, it does not result
from pure accidents.”45 An article from June 1941, Naissance des tyrannies, unveils
something more of the classic approach that Aron resurrects in his attempt to
understand the singular phenomena of the twentieth century. It is revealing
that, while other eminent thinkers of the time had revisited the Greek politi-
cal philosophers to look for the most profound roots of modern totalitarianism,
Aron had consulted Plato and Aristotle in order to understand the “decomposi-
tion of democracy into tyranny” that he had observed in Germany. The affinity
between the corruption of ancient and modern democracies is justified for Aron
by a certain continuity of psychological and political phenomena. As different as the
economic, technological, or social circumstances might be, there are still anal-
ogous dynamics in human souls and in the relations between men. Aron thus
outlines “the translation in modern terms” of certain arguments of Greek politi-
cal philosophy that would continue to inspire his analyses and commentaries. Let
us cite the most important of them.
Aron derives first from Plato a hermeneutical principle of political life: polit-
ical regimes are what the men are who give them life. This also raises an argu-
ment about the dynamic of the soul and the city that Aron presents as ever fatal
but always possible: despotism can arise from license. The sign of the corrup-
tion of a democracy is par excellence the situation where “the rulers seem to be
ruled and the ruled seem to be rulers.”46 Aron draws attention to the poten-
tial for tyrannical mores, words, or practices to enter progressively into liberal
regimes—he discerns their moral and material causes as well as their social and
intellectual roots. He illustrates the effects of demagogy on the conception of
liberty or the experience of the law and the “immoderate” disequilibria that are
produced in the relations between poor and rich and which weaken the unity of
the city. This is why Aristotle offers him the political principle that, combined
with the “principle” and “politics” of Montesquieu, doubtlessly defines the core
of his perspective: “One must not push too far the application of the principle
inherent to each regime.”47
Aron developed the perspective outlined and practiced at the onset of the war
in the great courses that we have explored in this text as well as in other works
such as La Révolution introuvable and Plaidoyer pour l’Europe décadente. The words
addressed to public opinion illustrate the same concern to have others appre-
ciate the fragility of modern societies and to put others on guard against the
persistent risk of the “self-destruction of democracy.” Therefore, one must not
interpret these words as the jeremiads of an old thinker turned “pessimist” or as
the repetitive refrain of an “ancient” philosopher criticizing democracy. These
public speeches are motivated by the concern of the citizen; they are also held
up by the eternal problems that always question the minds of men. Their argu-
ments lay out a “way of political thinking” that “still has something to say to us.”
132 GIU LIO DE LIGIO
Since the appearance of these books, liberal democracy has neither reverted to an
opposed regime nor has it self-destructed, but, for example, one must still con-
sider the capacity for collective action that it preserves in Europe by pursuing the
movement that worried Aron. If one reads the lectures where he most rigorously
develops his arguments, one sees in any case that Aron invites the reader to con-
sider and judge democracy in light of a dialectic that characterizes every political
regime. If he holds liberal democracy to be the best of imperfect regimes, it is
that its institutions are at the service of personal liberties, that competition for
the exercise of power is peaceful, and that it is a moderate political order that can
integrate the matter of modern society. In other words, to take up the defi nition
established and developed in Démocratie et totalitarisme, Aron illustrates the merits
of Western democracy as a constitutional-pluralist regime. For Aron, it is this lib-
eral character of its institutions—and of its public spirit—that most adequately
defi nes the democratic “idea” in modern society. A descendant of Aristotle and
the school of Montesquieu and Tocqueville, Aron nevertheless does not hold to
this liberal formulation. We better understand the sense and the implications
of his “conclusions”: the experience of modern democracy remains political. It
must therefore preserve a political consciousness or science of itself.
The analytical developments of the Introduction à la philosophie politique and of
Démocratie et totalitarisme should also be read in terms of how they explain the
dialectics that defi ne political life and modern society. First of all it is necessary
that the regime be considered legitimate but that it also be effective, and that it man-
ages to respond to the fundamental problems posed by history to every political
community: for Aron the good of a regime must integrate what can safeguard it,
in the same way that virtue is distinct and inseparable from political virtue. We have
seen that Aron does not draw on the classical philosophers just for a critique of
tyranny. He is also attentive to their teachings on the education that common life
demands and brings with it. The political thinker thus alerts the theoretician of
liberalism: “before society can be free, it is necessary that it be.”48 Every political
community is in effect defi ned by a certain articulation between multiplicity and
unity.49 Every political community must be composed in a certain political way.
Reformulating the conclusions of Greek political science and of the French polit-
ical school, Aron thus summarizes the lesson concerning the democratic regime:
“Democracies are corrupted either by the exaggeration or by the negation of
their principles.”50 They are always exposed either to the default or to the exag-
geration of the sense of compromise,51 to an excess of oligarchy or demagogy, or
to a disequilibrium between political power and social power. They allow and
arouse a manifest and confl ictual plurality, but they rest on a certain collective
understanding and live only through a shared experience.52 This Aronian per-
spective implies a political explication that accompanies or contains the question
of the regime in an era characterized in Europe by the “contestation of the very
principle of political units,” the nation, and, outside of the old continent, by the
extension of democratic legitimacy to collectivities “without traditions of com-
mon political life,” that is to “still fragile political bodies.”53 Democracy implies,
to be sure, a social and human wager, but a wager whose terms can and must be
understood: the desire to create a common life and effective action from confl ict
TH E QU ESTION OF POLITICA L R EGIM E 133
and plurality could never entirely disregard the demand for a certain “coherence
of the political body” capable of moderating and educating rivalries.
Whether it comes to its preconditions, causes of corruption or virtues, Aron
endeavors to bring liberal democracy back “to earth,” back to the opacity inher-
ent in human history. It is by taking account of the problems that character-
ize it that liberal democracy can be preserved in this sublunar world as the
best of the imperfect regimes. One could say that liberal democracy for Aron
always risks posing itself as a solution and lacking awareness of itself as a politi-
cal regime. In effect, it tends to consign the justice of the collective order to the
historical or economic ruse of reason, or to reduce internal and external action
to the spreading of human rights, even when this tendency makes it politically
impotent. Nonetheless, “recognition” is an operating principle of common life
only within a political order that makes clear its content.54 Similarly, the prin-
ciple of consent or liberty cannot be established as the “unique principle of the
political order”55 because men and regimes pursue a plurality of objectives.
Aron reformulates or completes these democratic or liberal questions by asking:
which equalities and inequalities must a community recognize in the “relations
between men”? Within which community can a private sphere be protected?56
External relations confi rm and accentuate the need to think the opacity in
which democratic man must also live. For Aron, the “doubtful combats” inher-
ent in foreign policy in effect could not be understood or conducted according
to the sole criterion of respect for rights: the fact that there is no country in
which all rights are always respected means that men are necessarily called to the
comparison of regimes (or of allies) and to a contingent deliberation.57 At times
believing itself to be a religion or the only regime “whose principles impose that
it does not have to defend itself against its enemies,”58 liberal democracy forgets
that no human association in history can be defined by the fact of not defending
its own principle, or its own existence. It also forgets that it continues to be the
object of more or less extreme criticism, which Aron shows as more or less just
or unjust, thereby fulfi lling his responsibility in regards to the city by searching
for its truth or the truth.59
Philosophy or sociology, philosophy and sociology, the political science that
allowed Aron to understand the “lesson of the century” endeavors to extend a
teaching whose pertinence and importance, in different forms, has been con-
fi rmed by the modern world. Man continues to “defi ne himself ” through politi-
cal action and historical judgment, even if “the quarrels of the Forum” do not
exhaust “the secret of man’s destiny.”60 This is why the liberal sociologist, in
order to understand and instruct democracy, questions it philosophically and
thinks it politically.
Notes
1. Cf. “La société industrielle et les dialogues politiques de l’Occident,” in Colloques
de Rheinfelden, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1960, 37–38.
2. “De la condition historique du sociologue” (1971), in Raymond Aron, Les Sociétés
modernes, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2006, 1073.
134 GIU LIO DE LIGIO
Daniel J. Mahoney
R aymond Aron’s life and political ref lection was coextensive with the totali-
tarian epoch that emerged with the Bolshevik revolution of 1917 and came
to an end with the implosion of the Soviet Union in the years immediately fol-
lowing his death in 1983. He did a great deal to educate western public opinion
about the nature of totalitarianism, but he did not live to see the final defeat of
the regime based upon the ideological Lie. His was a posthumous victory.
It was the rise of National Socialism in pre-Hitler Germany that cured Aron
of progressivist illusions and awakened him to the deadly threat that totalitarian-
ism posed to western civilization. Studying and teaching in Cologne and Berlin
between 1930 and 1933, Aron “felt, almost physically, the approach of historical
storms,”1 as he so suggestively put it in his Inaugural Address to the Collège de
France in 1970. As a result of that experience, he “ceased to believe that history
automatically obeys the dictates of reason or the desires of men of good will.”2 He
“lost faith and held on, not without effort, to hope.”3 He “discovered the enemy”
that he would relentlessly pursue all his adult life—“totalitarianism.”4 “In any
form of fanaticism, even one inspired by idealism, I suspect a new incarnation
of the monster,”5 he writes—a formulation that can serve as his mature politi-
cal credo. If National Socialism revealed the “diabolical essence”6 of a politics
bereft of all decency and any respect for common humanity, the Soviet Union
showed the monstrous consequences of all efforts to build heaven on earth. In the
years before 1945, Aron concentrated on analyzing and exposing the National
Socialist subversion of humanity. In the post-1945 years, he turned his attention
to a critique of Communist totalitarianism, while never forgetting its kinship
with, and differences from, its frère-ennemi (brother-enemy), National Socialism.
Aron’s critique of National Socialism as an essentially revolutionary and total-
itarian state and movement is expressed with rare eloquence and authority in his
138 DA N I E L J. M A HON E Y
June 17, 1939 address to the French Philosophical Society on “Democratic and
Totalitarian States.” 7 The 34-year-old Aron spoke as a self-declared adherent
of “democratic conservatism.”8 Drawing on intellectual categories provided by
Max Weber and Vilfredo Pareto, he drew a portrait of the new revolutionary
“elites” who set the tone for totalitarianism in Hitler’s Germany. These elites
had a debased “taste for violence.”9 National Socialist and fascist elites had mas-
tered techniques for moving men, a capacity for manipulation that was indis-
tinguishable from “scorn”10 for the masses. They reduced individuals to “means
of production”11 or “objects of propaganda”12 and mocked the traditional moral
categories of Western civilization. In the moral realm, they pursued a compre-
hensive transvaluation of values: all the “old forms of family life, of university
and intellectual life”13 were under assault. Totalitarian states repudiated the “old
virtues” held dear by bourgeois civilization: “respect for the person, respect for
the mind, . . . personal autonomy.”14 In their place, they cultivated harsh military
virtues, “virtues of action, of asceticism, of devotion.”15 In principle, they rec-
ognized no limit to the interventions and coercion of the State. They assaulted
political and economic liberty and “showed unmistakably . . . that when one
wants to administer everything, one is obliged to govern everything as well.”16
Writing on the eve of the Second World War, Aron feared that democratic
states were “hard to sustain” and that the future may lie with that “peculiar mix-
ture of demagogy, technique, irrational faith and police force”17 that character-
istically defined totalitarian states. This was all the more reason for saving what
was worth saving in the democratic idea. Those who cared for the future of
democracy needed to free themselves from what Aron would later call, in The
Opium of the Intellectuals, the “myth of revolution.”18 They needed to conserve a
liberal civilization worth conserving. This would demand discipline, respect for
authority, and technical competence. But above all, it demanded the “intellectual
courage” to face the totalitarian threat and the problems that threatened “the very
existence of a country like France.”19 Democratic regimes necessarily have to
remain faithful to the rule of law (the appeal to “popular sovereignty” could be
too easily abused by the totalitarians) while rejecting the notion that power could
ever be exercised without limits. Democratic regimes are defi ned by “a decent
respect for persons,”20 persons whom they refuse to treat as fodder for an omni-
competent state. Much of Aron’s analysis in the 1939 address also holds true for
Leninist-Stalinist totalitarianism. But he would not make an explicit comparison
of the two totalitarianisms until his two-part 1944 essay on “The Future of the
Secular Religions.” We will return to that essay in the course of our discussion.
The 1939 address on “Democratic and Totalitarian States” paved the way for
Aron’s fuller critical engagement with the nihilism and fanaticism of National
Socialism in the series of essays he wrote for La France libre between 1940 and
1945. For our purposes, the most relevant essays are those collected in the 1944
volume L’Homme contre les tyrans. These essays are among the most thoughtful
and moving that Aron ever composed. They are forthright about the weaknesses
of the democracies, even as they defend liberty and human dignity against the
menace of a tyranny devoted to total war, ideological fanaticism, and scorn for
ordinary humanity. Aron locates the roots of the new tyranny in an unabashed
T H E TOTA LI TA R I A N N EGAT ION OF M A N 139
and evil.”31 Against the subversion of ordinary moral judgment proffered by the
ideologists of Left and Right, Aron appealed to the power of conscience, that
reminder of the moral law within each human being.
If Aron fl irted with existentialism in his writings on the philosophy of history
in the 1930s, his essays in La France libre suggested that the totalitarian negation
of universal ethics had led him back to more traditional affirmations. The pathos
and beauty of these essays arises in no small part from Aron’s recognition of
precisely what was at stake in the struggle between National Socialism and the
remnant of western civilization. It should be added that Aron later turned away
from using the idiom of “secular religion” to describe twentieth century totali-
tarianism. He did so in no small part because of his respect for transcendental
religions whose faith he could not affirm, but whose ideals and affi rmations still
spoke to his soul. As he put it in his Mémoires at the end of his life, “I often sym-
pathize with the Catholics, loyal to their faith, who demonstrate a total freedom
of thought in all profane matters. The horror of secular religions makes me feel
some sympathy for transcendent religions.”32 He did not wish to disparage the
word religion by using it to describe those movements and regimes that repudiated
the best traditions of the West and that had nothing but contempt for conscience
and the age-old distinction between good and evil.
With the defeat of the Third Reich, Aron turned his attention to the surviv-
ing totalitarianism of the twentieth century. In an eloquent and discerning chap-
ter of Les Guerres en chaîne (1951), titled “Totalitarianism,” he made clear that the
struggle against Stalinism must continue unabated because the universal diff u-
sion of Communism demanded “the physical elimination of millions of men and
the moral elimination of ideas and secular traditions.”33 He did not hesitate to
call totalitarianism the “enemy” that must be resisted, since the totalitarian state
alone was capable of conducting such monstrous enterprises and its “philosophy”
or ideology was alone capable of inspiring them.34 Writing in 1951, Aron was
astonished by the persistence of revolutionary phenomena so late in the history of
the Soviet regime. The secret police and terror had lost none of their significance
30 years after Lenin’s victory in the Civil War.
Aron was one of the fi rst to acknowledge the Leninist roots of Stalinist totali-
tarianism. The Lenin of State and Revolution (1918) may have dreamed of a post-
revolutionary withering away of the State. “But in assimilating the power of the
Bolshevik party with that of the proletariat,” and by giving the party a dictato-
rial role during the “transition” to Communism, Lenin condemned the Soviet
Union to “enter into an infernal cycle of violence.”35 Aron was also sensitive
to the ideological Manicheanism that led to the creation of forced labor camps
and to the stigmatization of a bourgeoisie and nobility who were guilty not
because of anything they had done but because of who they were. The col-
lectivization of agriculture extended such ideological culpability to millions of
peasants (so-called “kulaks”), who were deemed class enemies and adversaries of
the Bolshevik state. Collectivization unleashed mass violence, a deadly famine
that took the lives of millions, and the destruction of an independent peasantry
in the Soviet Union. After 1930, the Soviet regime was totalitarian not only in
aspiration but in reality.
T H E TOTA LI TA R I A N N EGAT ION OF M A N 141
sociological claim is that the number of parties provides the single most impor-
tant variable for analyzing political regimes in the contemporary world. However,
Aron’s analysis and critique of what he freely calls an ideocracy goes far beyond
sociological analysis to include fi rst-rate political philosophizing and acute spiri-
tual judgment.
Still, in his Mémoires, published months before his death in 1983, Aron defended
“the opposition between a single party and a plurality of parties as a criterion of
classification.”41 He admitted that this distinction was “open to question.”42 Yet,
democracy demands “legally organized competition for the exercise of power”
and the winning party’s acceptance in advance of “the possibility of its defeat at
the next election.”43 The party exercising power must do so in accordance “with
constitutional law and ordinary law.”44 Thus, well-constituted democracies are
by defi nition “constitutional-pluralistic regimes.”45 Where Aron’s claim of pur-
suing a sociological analysis of regimes breaks down is in his discussion of the
Soviet regime. Is a one-party system inevitably totalitarian, exercising supreme
secular, spiritual, and ideological authority? Doesn’t one need a philosophical
analysis of totalitarianism of precisely the kind Aron provides in Democracy and
Totalitarianism without fully acknowledging what he is doing?
Whatever Aron’s own “official” claim, in Democracy and Totalitarianism the
single party is never the sole variable for explaining totalitarianism. The party
is inseparable from an ideocratic state that has a “monopoly of the means of
coercion, and of the information and propaganda media.”46 Ideology is “neither
the sole end nor the exclusive means; there is a perpetual interaction or indeed
dialectic.”47 At times, ideology is a means to an end, at other times “force is used
to change society so that it will conform to ideology.”48 One party not only has
a monopoly of political activity, but it is also animated (or armed) by an ideol-
ogy “on which it confers absolute authority and which consequently becomes
the official truth of the state.”49 In the Aronian framework, ideology is at least as
important as the existence of a monopolistic party. Since the state is inseparable
from its ideology, “most economic and professional activities are colored by the
official truth.”50 Since all activity is state activity and subject to the reigning
ideology, any error or mishap becomes an ideological crime. The totalitarian or
ideological regime thus leads inexorably to “police and ideological terrorism.”51
Aron’s defi nition of totalitarianism depends not only on a monopolistic party,
but also on state control of economic life and on ideological terror. “The phe-
nomenon is complete when all these elements are united and fully achieved.”52
Aron was also as sensitive to the grotesque mendacity at the heart of the
totalitarian enterprise. Democracy and Totalitarianism contains some moving pas-
sages about the “world of macabre fiction”53 that accompanied the Great Terror
and show trials of the 1930s and that made ideological despotism so surreal. As we
shall see, under the impact of the writings of Solzhenitsyn and the French philo-
sophical historian Alain Besançon, the Aron of the 1970s and 1980s would come
to see the Ideological Lie to be at least as important as terror as a defi ning feature
of an ideocracy. One might say that violence and lies were the twin pillars of
the monopolistic party state—its “principle,” to use the idiom of Montesquieu’s
T H E TOTA LI TA R I A N N EGAT ION OF M A N 143
political philosophy. Here, we are a long way from positivistic social science with
its concern for variables and its undue preoccupation with scientificity.
Some of the most striking pages in Democracy and Totalitarianism deal with the
comparison of the Soviet and Nazi undertakings. These pages have been sub-
jected to sustained criticism from sympathetic observers such as Alain Besançon
and Martin Malia. And as we shall see, Aron would later qualify his views on
this matter in very significant ways. What Besançon and Malia object to is Aron’s
identification of the Soviet enterprise with a “revolutionary will inspired by a
humanitarian ideal.”54 Aron does not endorse this “humanitarian ideal,” which
arguably is coextensive with rank utopianism. However, he seems to give the
Soviet leaders credit for good intentions. Soviet Communism is said to aim for a
universal, homogenous state where all men “could be treated as human beings,
in which classes would have disappeared or in which the homogeneity of society
would allow of mutual respect between people.”55 This “absolute goal,” this
desire to create a “completely good society,” can only be brought about by a
“merciless war”56 with capitalism. Aron remarks that the “different phases in the
Soviet regime sprang from a combination between a sublime goal and a ruthless
technique.”57 Political terror inevitably flowed from this effort to create human
perfection through class warfare and a dictatorship of the party in the name of a
historically privileged proletariat.
Alain Besançon has best expressed the limits of the Aronian analysis of the
Soviet regime in Democracy and Totalitarianism. As Besançon pointedly observes in
his classic 1976 article titled “On the Difficulty of Defi ning the Soviet Regime,”
“the ideological project is not humanitarian, precisely because it is ideological.”58 Contrary
to Aron’s analysis, “a part of humanity fi nds itself ontologically excluded”59 in
the new revolutionary state and society. The nobility, clergy, ordinary religious
believers, the bourgeoisie, so-called kulaks, and anyone who exercises indepen-
dence of thought is relegated to the category of “enemy of the people.” We have
seen that Aron had already highlighted that ontologically exclusionary fact in his
superb 1951 critique of totalitarianism in Les Guerres en chaîne. Besançon objects
to Aron’s failure to appreciate that the “universal and humanitarian ideals of reli-
gion and morality”60 are mutilated beyond recognition when the Soviets appro-
priate them at the service of a project of revolutionary negation. Aron appears to
be torn between a recognition of moral nihilism as the heart of the totalitarian
enterprise and his willingness in Democracy and Totalitarianism to conflate ideol-
ogy with a “humanitarian ideal,” albeit an ideal that is distorted in profoundly
important ways by “ruthless techniques.”
Aron continues to sharpen the contrast between Nazi and Communist totali-
tarianism. He insists that “the aim of Soviet terror is to create a society which
conforms completely to an ideal, while in the Nazi case, the aim was pure
and simple extermination.”61 He understates the eliminationist dimensions of
the Leninist-Stalinist project (the goal of “purging Russia of all the harmful
insects,”62 as Lenin wrote in 1918) and fails to appreciate that National Socialists
also upheld “ideals,” however perverse and inhumane. He sharply differentiates
the Soviet labor camp from the Nazi gas chamber and contrasts the construction
144 DA N I E L J. M A HON E Y
of a new regime “and perhaps a new man, regardless of means” from “the truly
daemonic will to destruction of a pseudo-race.”63
Aron’s fi nal summing-up of the totalitarian undertakings is more balanced
and persuasive. The Soviet regime reveals that efforts to “create an angel cre-
ate a beast.”64 Similarly, the Nazi undertaking shows that “man should not try
to resemble a beast of prey because, when he does so, he is only too success-
ful.”65 Without disagreeing with these admirable formulations and conclusions,
Besançon suggests that Soviet totalitarianism poses a diabolically enticing temp-
tation to those who accept humanitarian ideals and enlightenment principles.
Its “falsification of the good”66 is demonic because it destroys one’s sense of
justice and natural morality. Pseudo-humanitarian ideals are used at the ser-
vice of the subversion of the moral life and of any deference to civilized values.
“The creation of a new man and the expectation of the end of prehistory”67 are
superstitions—ideological fictions—that give rise to a regime built on limitless
violence and lies.
Aron later had serious reservations about the way he posed the contrast
between Nazi and Communist totalitarianism. It is fair to say that in the 1970s
his position grew closer to Besançon’s. Besançon was a faithful attendee of Aron’s
famous seminar. The two men would debate these matters over the course of a
decade and a half. Of course, Aron was a life-long anti-Communist who saw
in Leninist-Stalinism “a new incarnation of the monster.” Nevertheless, under
the influence of the writings of both Besançon and Solzhenitsyn, Aron came
to appreciate that Marxist-Leninism “as an ideology is the root of all ill (in the
Soviet regime), the source of falsehood, the principle of evil.”68 He endorsed and
summarized the message of Solzhenitsyn’s The Gulag Archipelago in two funda-
mental sentences: “there is something worse than poverty and repression—and
that something is the Lie, the lesson this century teaches us is to recognize the
deadly snare of ideology, the illusion that men and social organizations can be
transformed at a stroke.”69 Solzhenitsyn’s and Besançon’s influences are particu-
larly evident in 1977s Plaidoyer pour l’Europe décadente, where Aron holds Marx’s
“prophetism” partly responsible for the tragedies of the twentieth century.70
The effort to remake la condition humaine is indeed an exercise in nihilism, an
assault on human nature, and an “order of things” that fundamentally cannot
be changed. Aron acknowledged that Marx’s writings are often rich, subtle, and
worthy of serious engagement. But his fi nal conclusion was damning: “As an
economist-prophet, as a putative ancestor of Marxism-Leninism, [Marx] is an
accursed sophist who bears some responsibility for the horrors of the twentieth
century.” 71
Democracy and Totalitarianism is a book that is still worthy of reflection.
However, it should not be considered Aron’s fi rst or fi nal word on the subject.
Few books combine political sociology and political philosophizing in as sug-
gestive and fruitful manner. At the same time, its tone is somewhat skewed. One
suspects that Aron was trying to get a hearing for anti-totalitarianism from a Left
that was still blind to fundamental realities, hence his bending over backward
to give the Soviet undertaking an equitable hearing, even as he condemned its
“essential imperfection.” In his Mémoires, he concedes that the book, influenced
T H E TOTA LI TA R I A N N EGAT ION OF M A N 145
by the Soviet thaw of the mid-1950s, was too optimistic about a reform of the
Soviet system short of the breakdown of the regime and ideology.72 He later came
to realize that the Soviet regime could only liberalize by ceasing to be itself.
Near the end of his Mémoires, Aron clearly states that “the argument that I
used more than once to distinguish class messianism from race messianism no
longer impresses me very much.” 73 “The apparent universality of the former
has become, in the last analysis, an illusion.” 74 Once a class-based organization
has come to power, it sanctifies confl icts and wars and becomes “involved with
a national or imperial messianism.” 75 In theory and practice, Communism is
an aff ront to the “fragile links of a common faith.” 76 Aron’s mature position is
indistinguishable from Besançon’s: ideology appropriates and mutilates authentic
“universality.” Aron forthrightly stated in 1983 that “Communism is no less
hateful to me than Nazism was.” 77 He professes “the systematic anticommunism
that has been attributed” to him “with a clear conscience.” 78
If Democracy and Totalitarianism was Aron’s fi rst and last word on totalitarianism,
he would indeed be vulnerable to the criticism of a friendly critic, Peter Baehr,
who writes that Aron’s “chief variable”—the nature of the political party—“falls
short of explaining the grotesque texture of the totalitarian world.” 79 But as we
have already suggested, the Aronian analysis of democracy and totalitarianism is
much more than a sociological account of political parties, “constitutional-plu-
ralistic” and ideocratic. Read in the context of Aron’s work as a whole, Democracy
and Totalitarianism makes a substantial contribution to understanding the totalitar-
ian mutilation of human and political liberty. Perhaps Baehr is right. One needs
to turn to earlier and later writings of Aron to experience the full “texture” of
totalitarianism, including the soul-wrenching experiences of Auschwitz and the
gulag archipelago. Thankfully, Aron’s work from the 1930s to the 1980s was
inseparable from a sustained, morally serious reflection on totalitarianism and all
its works. As The Opium of the Intellectuals (1955) particularly evidences, he was
an indefatigable critic of the indulgence that French intellectuals showed toward
Communist totalitarianism. He patiently exposed the myths of Revolution,
the Left, and the Proletariat.80 His long witness was vindicated in the 1970s by
Solzhenitsyn and the Soviet dissidents. As Pierre Manent has observed, Aron the
scholar was above all a public educator, a defender of the city and a defender of
man.81 If totalitarianism poses a permanent threat to civility and common life, to
the integrity of human bodies and souls, Aron’s engagement with this “monster”
remains as relevant as it was in “the age of ideology.” His is a rich and enduring
trove of anti-totalitarian wisdom that we ignore at our own peril.
Notes
1. Raymond Aron, “On the Historical Condition of the Sociologist,” in Raymond
Aron, Politics and History, ed. Myriam Bernheim Conant, New Brunswick, NJ,
Transaction, 1984, 65.
2. Ibid., 65.
3. Ibid.
4. Ibid.
146 DA N I E L J. M A HON E Y
5. Ibid.
6. Ibid.
7. Raymond Aron, “États Démocratiques et États Totalitaires,” in Raymond
Aron, Penser la liberté, penser la démocratie, Paris, Gallimard, 2005, 55–106. I will
cite the English-language translation by Anthony M. Nazzaro in Raymond
Aron, Thinking Politically: A Liberal in the Age of Ideology, New Brunswick, NJ,
Transaction, 1997, 325–347.
8. Aron, Thinking Politically, 336–337.
9. Ibid., 327.
10. Ibid.
11. Ibid., 336.
12. Ibid.
13. Ibid., 329.
14. Ibid.
15. Ibid.
16. Ibid., 336.
17. Ibid.
18. Raymond Aron, The Opium of the Intellectuals, with a new Introduction by Harvey
C. Mansfield, Foreword by Daniel J. Mahoney and Brian C. Anderson, New
Brunswick, NJ, Transaction, 2001.
19. Aron, Thinking Politically, 337.
20. Ibid., 336.
21. Raymond Aron, “Le romantisme de la violence,” in Raymond Aron, Chroniques
de Guerre: La France libre, 1940–1945, Paris, Gallimard,1990, 438.
22. Ibid.
23. Winston Churchill, Blood, Toil, Tears and Sweat: The Great Speeches, ed. David
Cannandine, London, Penguin, 2007, 177–178.
24. Raymond Aron, “Tyrannie et mépris des hommes,” in Raymond Aron, Chroniques
de guerre: La France libre, 1940–1945, Paris, Gallimard,1990, 466–478.
25. Ibid., 478.
26. Ibid.
27. See Raymond Aron, Chroniques de guerre: La France libre 1940–1945, Paris,
Gallimard, 1990, 925–948. I have cited the English-language edition, “The
Future of Secular Religions,” in F. Flagg Taylor IV (ed.), The Great Lie: Classic
and Recent Appraisals of Ideology and Totalitarianism, Wilmington, DE, ISI Books,
2011, 97–123.
28. Taylor, The Great Lie, 122.
29. Ibid.
30. Ibid.
31. Ibid.
32. Raymond Aron, Memoirs: Fifty Years of Political Reflection, trans. George Holoch,
Foreword by Henry A. Kissinger, New York, Holmes & Meier, 1990, 477.
33. Raymond Aron, “Le totalitarisme,” in Raymond Aron, Les Guerres en chaîne,
Paris, Gallimard, 1951, 457.
34. Ibid.
35. Ibid., 471.
36. Ibid., 474.
37. Ibid.
38. Ibid., 481.
39. Ibid.
T H E TOTA LI TA R I A N N EGAT ION OF M A N 147
40. Raymond Aron, Democracy and Totalitarianism, ed. and with an Introduction by
Roy Pierce, trans. Valence Ionescu, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press,
1990, 245.
41. Aron, Memoirs, 273.
42. Ibid.
43. Ibid.
44. Ibid.
45. Ibid.
46. Aron, Democracy and Totalitarianism, 185.
47. Ibid.
48. Ibid.
49. Ibid., 193.
50. Ibid.
51. Ibid.
52. Ibid.
53. Ibid., 191.
54. Ibid., 198.
55. Ibid., 199.
56. Ibid.
57. Ibid.
58. Alain Besançon, “On the Difficulty of Defending the Soviet Regime,” in F.
Flagg Taylor IV (ed.), The Great Lie: Classic and Recent Appraisals of Ideology and
Totalitarianism, Wilmington, DE, ISI Books, 2011, 31–50. The quotation is from
44.
59. Ibid.
60. Ibid.
61. Aron, Democracy and Totalitarianism, 203.
62. Lenin wrote that revealing phrase in his incendiary 1918 essay “How to Organize
the Competition.”
63. Aron, Democracy and Totalitarianism, 204.
64. Ibid.
65. Ibid.
66. See the use of this evocative phrase in Alain Besançon, A Century of Horrors:
Communism, Nazism, and the Uniqueness of the Shoah, trans. Ralph C. Hancock and
Nathaniel H. Hancock, Wilmington, DE, ISI Books, 2007.
67. Aron, Democracy and Totalitarianism, 216.
68. Raymond Aron, “Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn and European ‘Leftism’,” in F.
Flagg Taylor IV (ed.), The Great Lie: Classic and Recent Appraisals of Ideology and
Totalitarianism, Wilmington, DE, ISI Books, 2011, 369.
69. Ibid., 376.
70. Raymond Aron, In Defense of Decadent Europe, with a new Introduction by Daniel
J. Mahoney and Brian C. Anderson, New Brunswick, NJ, Transaction, 1996.
71. Aron, Memoirs, 468–469.
72. Ibid., 277.
73. Ibid., 471.
74. Ibid.
75. Ibid.
76. Ibid.
77. Ibid.
78. Ibid.
148 DA N I E L J. M A HON E Y
79. Peter Baehr, Hannah Arendt, Totalitarianism and the Social Sciences, Palo Alto, CA,
Stanford University Press, 2010, 87.
80. See Aron, The Opium of the Intellectuals, 3–93.
81. See Pierre Manent, “Raymond Aron éducateur,” Commentaire, no. 28–29, Février
1985, 155–168. For an unusually thoughtful and detailed account of Aron’s “phil-
osophical” engagement with modern tyranny, see Giulio De Ligio, “Tirannia,
totalitarismo e saggezza: Raymond Aron e il male della vita politica,” in G.
Chivilò, M. Mennon (eds.), Tirannide e filosofia, Venezia, Ca’ Foscari University
Press, 2014.
CHAPTER 11
Serge Audier
B etween the late 1970s and early 1980s, the French intellectual landscape
changed noticeably. It was a time when totalitarianism was being criti-
cized, liberal democracy rediscovered, and human rights rehabilitated. In this
context, the figure of Raymond Aron, long marginalized and in many ways
against the current, was the subject of a kind of retrospective recognition in
France—did he not, before many others, clearly distinguish liberal democracies
from “secular religions” and “totalitarianism?” However this may be, it is clear
that this belated recognition went hand in hand with a certain banalization of the
Aronian approach. Praised, to be sure, for his “lucidity,” Aron was considered a
rather unoriginal political thinker, since his conception of democracy basically
consisted in a prosaic defense of the rule of law and pluralism. It is striking that,
in contemporary French political philosophy, the references to Aron, outside the
small circle of his admirers, are few, or rather, almost nonexistent, while his pres-
ence in the Anglophone academic debate remains barely more than marginal. It
is especially in some areas of political sociology that the Aronian conception of
democracy is sometimes mobilized in a nebula that goes from a small group of
theorists concerned with the role of “elites”—Gaetano Mosca, Vilfredo Pareto,
and Robert Michels—to Joseph Schumpeter, whose conception of democracy
is presented primarily in terms of a competitive elitism. Moreover, Aron’s view
of democracy, when it is not presented as similar to that of other political sci-
entists such as Robert Dahl or Giovanni Sartori, is often placed in a specifically
French tradition of liberalism, which, from Montesquieu to Élie Halévy, via
Tocqueville, favors pluralism, countervailing powers, and moderation.
These perspectives, of course, each contain some truth, but they do not exhaust
the originality of the Aronian approach. This chapter will try to show that in
Aron we can fi nd some features of a Machiavellian conception of democracy
that perhaps still today merits consideration as regards two different aspects. The
150 S E RG E AU DI E R
The view that Aron initially presented of Machiavelli, however, was not so far
from those of the Florentine’s greatest critics, such as Strauss himself, or the neo-
Thomist philosopher Jacques Maritain. First formulated in the context of the late
1930s and early 1940s, Aron’s reading—in an unfi nished book he planned to title
Essais sur le machiavélisme moderne (Essays on Modern Machiavellianism), pub-
lished in 1993 under the title Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, and also adum-
brated in his columns in La France libre—at fi rst unfurled to a great extent under
the banner of anti-Machiavellianism, or rather of the political literature of the
time, which considered Machiavelli more or less directly “responsible,” intellec-
tually, for Nazism and fascism. This happened in part because Mussolini himself
had claimed his debt to and admiration for the author of The Prince.
More specifically, one can only understand the importance attached by
Aron to the idea of Machiavellianism by considering the arguments previously
developed by Halévy in his famous lecture titled L’ère des tyrannies1 (The Age
of Tyranny). It is as though Aron had tried in Essays on Modern Machiavellianism
at once to continue and to alter Halévy’s analyses. Aron takes up the notion
of tyranny proposed by Halévy in order to describe the totalitarian regimes
then emerging, but he moves toward another interpretation, placing the idea of
“modern Machiavellianism” at the center of his reflections. By insisting on the
importance of a doctrine in the genesis of the tyrannical regimes of his time,
he was certainly aware that he was developing a bold and daring interpretation:
“Theory: the word may surprise us, and yet it is essential. National Socialism
and Communism do not appear Machiavellian to us only because they trick,
deceive, lie, violate their words, and murder. If Hitler’s Machiavellianism con-
sisted merely in the use of such methods, it would not be worth wasting much
time studying it. In reality, the use of such visibly Machiavellian means interests
us only as a symptom of a more profound Machiavellianism: namely, a certain
conception of man and politics.”2 Besides, the question is therefore not so much
one of describing this or that technique of lying as of analyzing the “rational-
ized systems,” the model on which modern Machiavellians conceive and build
the government of peoples.3 It is in from this point of view that, without mak-
ing Machiavelli directly responsible for the disaster of “modern tyrannies,” the
young Aron considers them to have emerged in the wake of the Machiavellian
rupture. In this sense, the Machiavellian Machiavelli cannot be considered a mere
legend. On the contrary, Aron says that the Florentine secretary can legitimately
be considered a Machiavellian thinker. He undoubtedly feels no sympathy for
tyranny, which he always analyzes with a theoretician’s coldness, but it is pre-
cisely in this neutrality that his Machiavellianism lies. Moreover, Machiavelli’s
preferences for republican liberty should not mislead us, Aron warns, since he
could, just as objectively as in The Prince, have developed a theory of monarchies
or republics. Certainly, such a detachment cannot make us doubt Machiavelli’s
sincere admiration for Republican Rome, and Rousseau was probably right, in
this sense, to ascribe a republican ideal to the Florentine—provided, however,
that we add that Machiavelli was too sensible to offer men an unattainable ideal
in most circumstances.4 Even if he prefers the life of republics to the actions of
an illegitimate prince, though, it is clear that these new princes are most often
152 S E RG E AU DI E R
on Machiavelli. Aron was familiar with this book, which has by now fallen into
total oblivion, and was not unaware of the author, whom he met personally, since
it was under his aegis that the book was translated and published in France. This
book, with its obviously provocative title, was much less successful in its time
than The Managerial Revolution, but it contributed greatly to the reconsideration
of Machiavelli as well as of Mosca, Pareto, and Michels, who until then had been
widely seen as harbingers of fascism. Burnham’s main thesis is that these think-
ers, like Machiavelli, were “defenders of freedom” inasmuch as they thought,
basing themselves on the observation that in all political societies there are rela-
tions of power and ruling elites, that the most important thing is for pluralism,
division, and confl icting forces to make possible the emergence of freedom.
Machiavelli was a theorist of the balance of confl icting social forces. The author
of The Machiavellians showed that the Florentine’s preference for a republic is not
inconsistent with his calling the prince to action to unify Italy. If a republic is the
best form of government in his eyes, it does not follow that the establishment of a
republican regime is possible in all situations. In addition, the republic portrayed
in the Discourses is not a utopia: Machiavelli shows both the defects and the vir-
tues of his ideal, and, unlike the utopian thinkers, does not attach any ultimate
importance to the form of government. Machiavelli’s concern is indeed free-
dom, understood as the independence of a city, itself based on the freedom of its
citizens. Only the government of the law curbing private interests can guarantee
this. For Machiavelli does not trust individuals as such to establish freedom. The
picture he draws is very pessimistic: driven by ambition and liars, men are always
corrupted by power. Nevertheless, the Florentine believes that the establishment
of freedom is not impossible. By the introduction of appropriate legislation, we
can, in fact, at least to some extent and for some time, discipline individual pas-
sions. Hence the insistence that no person or magistrate be above the law, that
there must be legal means for every citizen to prosecute, that punishments should
be impartial, and fi nally, that private ambitions must be channeled through pub-
lic institutions.
In short, if the author of the Discourses does not believe that individuals possess
a natural virtue—and, for Burnham, nothing is further away from Machiavellian
thought than the Aristotelian model of the “political animal,” the zoon poli-
tikon—he does believe, however, that a set of ingeniously developed laws can
contribute to political freedom. From this point of view, the critical importance
he ascribes to the balance of power becomes clear: “Machiavelli is not so naive
as to imagine that the law needs no other enforcement than itself. The law is
based on force, but force, in turn, destroys law, unless it is restrained; and force
cannot be restrained except by an opposing force. Sociologically, therefore, the
foundation of freedom consists in a balance of different powers and that is what
Machiavelli called “ ‘mixed’ ” government.”8 In support of this thesis, which
Aron foresaw in the 1930s, Burnham cites the famous passage from Chapter 4 of
Book I of the Discourses praising the confl ict between the plebeians and nobles as
decisive for the freedom of republican Rome. Anxious to promote not a utopian
freedom but a concrete one, Machiavelli shows how hypocritical the calls for
“unity” are, which are often no more than a lie aimed at suppressing opposition;
and how fallacious the idea is that freedom is a natural attribute, as it were, of an
individual or a particular group.
Among the Machiavellians, Mosca, according to Burnham, is the man in
the twentieth century who best remembered the Florentine Secretary’s lesson
on the role of balance in the confl ict between opposing forces. We must pause
again now for a moment because Burnham’s interpretation clearly led Aron to
enrich his own conception of democracy as a system based on the recognition
of confl ict. Contrary to the impression given by an overview of Elementi di sci-
enza politica, Burnham recognized the Italian sociologist’s normative options:
“Mosca, like Machiavelli, does not stop at a descriptive analysis of politics. He
clearly shows his own preferences and opinions about the best and worst forms of
A M A C H I AV E L L I A N C O N C E P T I O N O F D E M O C R A C Y ? 155
It is also true that, due to the influence of Burnham and the elite theorists,
Aron probably has a far too liberal and traditional view of Machiavelli, which
does not adequately scrutinize the destabilizing force of the desire of the peo-
ple for freedom in Machiavellian thought. As free and philologically question-
able as it is, however, this reading has the merit of paradoxically pointing out
some important features of Machiavellian thought that have sometimes escaped
the best-known scholars, including contemporary scholars. In the wake of
Burnham—and, as we have said, even before him, in the 1930s—Aron’s analysis
was in fact able to identify an innovative political approach in Machiavelli, which
is marked by a profound realism and which assigns a key role in the lives of free
societies, and particularly in democracies, to social and political confl icts. This
realism, difficult to contest, must lead to deeply profound reconsideration of
Pocock’s thesis about the “Machiavellian moment,” which placed Machiavelli’s
republicanism in the tradition of the Aristotelian conception of the citizen as a
“political animal.” Moreover, if there is an element for which Machiavelli stands
out in the history of republicanism from antiquity to the Italian Renaissance, it
is precisely his praise of “disunity” as an important factor in the freedom of the
Roman Republic. This view was shared neither by Aristotle nor by Cicero in
their presentations of republicanism, nor even by most theorists of civic human-
ism and Renaissance republicanism; and it deeply shocked Machiavelli’s con-
temporaries, such as Francesco Guicciardini. Moreover, this theory about the
fertility of “disunity” and “turmoil” is not found frequently outside of a small
portion of the modern republican tradition (it can be found, e.g., in seventeenth-
century England, in Algernon Sidney but not in James Harrington). It is there-
fore a very important point that identifies Machiavelli’s originality. Certainly,
neither Burnham nor Aron sufficiently emphasizes how Machiavelli describes
the confl ict between the people’s desire not to be oppressed and the desire of
the “great,” driven by their ambition to increase their power continuously and
to dominate the people. Their liberal and “elitist” reading of Machiavelli does
not adequately reflect all the links in his thought or his dynamic conception of
politics. In addition, because this is not what they are looking for in Machiavelli,
they quickly pass over the horizon of war that is at the heart of both The Prince
and the Discourses. (It should be noted, however, that, starting in the 1930s, when
he still saw Machiavelli as the forerunner of “modern tyrannies,” Aron was more
attentive than Burnham to this dimension.)
The reaffirmation of the centrality of confl ict in Machiavelli’s work is a key
to the reading of it that is still relevant today, especially vis-à-vis the “neo-
republican” interpretations that tend, more or less clearly, to erase it by placing
the author of the Discourses on the First Decade of Livy in a larger nebula—that
of “civic humanism,” “republicanism,” or “neo-Roman” freedom.32 However,
there are other interpreters who, against the grain in terms of the readings domi-
nant today, emphasize the centrality of social divisions. Whether they know it
or not, these interpreters follow at least partly in Burnham and Aron’s footsteps.
Furthermore, every argument that underscores the famous division between
“republicanism” and “liberalism,” advanced by Pocock and the Cambridge
school, is superficial—or debatable in any case—and fails to take into account
A M A C H I AV E L L I A N C O N C E P T I O N O F D E M O C R A C Y ? 161
Machiavelli’s republican and liberal legacy.33 One need only think, for example,
of Thomas Gordon and John Trenchard’s Cato’s Letters (1720–1723), historically
an influential text, that combined unashamedly “Machiavellian” and “liberal”
elements from Locke; or one could think of Montesquieu’s writings, such as
Considerations on the Causes of the Greatness of the Romans and their Decline (1734),
which praises the tumults that went hand-in-hand with the greatness of republi-
can Rome. Machiavelli’s Discourses was in all likelihood the source of the praise
for republican Rome found in Montesquieu’s own work, and although he does
not indicate it, Aron himself knew and admired the work of the French aristo-
crat. In this sense, one could moreover say that in the wake of totalitarianism—a
regime built on the double refusal of civil discord and political liberty—Aron
had reawakened in his century a political thought that was at the crossroads of
apparent antagonists: a political thought that laid to rest the overly simplistic
division between liberalism and republicanism.
Rediscovering a Machiavellian philosophy of confl ict is noteworthy today not
only for historical reasons, but also for political and philosophical reasons. Many
contemporary theories of democracy, notably those of a contractarian variety, in
effect lay a great deal of stress on the idea of consensus. The collapse of Marxism
and of analyses in terms of “class struggle” has promoted a vision of democratic
societies that largely neglects any “antagonistic” paradigm, as if confl ict or dis-
cord were signs of regress. Democracy is undoubtedly represented as a type of
regime and society that is not monolithic, in which pluralism and fragmentation
constitute the fundamental traits, whether this be cause for concern or joy. But
it is rare to see today the emphasis placed on a trait that nevertheless remains
essential, even after the end of totalitarianism: democracy is a regime whose very
essence welcomes division and confl ict of opinions, philosophies, and interests.
Thinking the “common good” cannot exclude reflecting on this more or less
visible discord which remains fundamental in the life of democracies.
Notes
1. Élie Halévy, “L’ère des tyrannies,” communication à la Société Française de
Philosophie, [1936], in L’Ere des tyrannies, Paris, Gallimard, 1938, 213–249.
2. Raymond Aron, “Essais sur le machiavélisme moderne [1938–1940],” in
Raymond Aron, Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, établi, présenté et annoté par
R. Freymond, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 1993, 119.
3. Ibid., 120.
4. Ibid., 73.
5. Ibid., 61.
6. James Burnham, The Machiavellians: Defenders of Freedom. A Defense of Political Truth
against Wishful Thinkings, London, 1943, new ed. pref. S. Hook, Washington, DC,
Gateway Edition, 1963.
7. Aron, Essais sur le machiavélisme moderne, op.cit., pp. 72–73 (my italics).
8. James Burnham, The Machiavellians, 80.
9. Ibid., 119.
10. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie politique: démocratie et révolution, préf.
J.-C. Casanova, Paris, Le Livre de Poche, 1997, 72.
162 S E RG E AU DI E R
11. Ibid.
12. Gaetano Mosca, Elementi di scienza politica, in Ibid., Scritti politici, t.II, ed. G. Sola,
Torino, Unione Tipografico-Editrice Torinese, 1982, 681.
13. Aron, Introduction à la philosophie politique, 77.
14. Ibid., 79.
15. Ibid.
16. Ibid., 80.
17. Mosca, Elementi di scienza politica, 692. On the importance of the theory of the
“mixed constitution” in Mosca, cf. N. Bobbio, “Mosca e il governo misto,” in
Ibid., Saggi sulla scienza politica in Italia, Rome and Bari, Laterza, 1996, 201–219.
18. Burnham, The Machiavellians, 126.
19. Aron, Introduction à la philosophie politique, 121.
20. Ibid.
21. Ibid., 132.
22. Ibid., 133.
23. Ibid., 135.
24. Ibid., 136
25. Ibid.
26. Ibid., 137.
27. Raymond Aron, Démocratie et totalitarisme [1965], Paris, Gallimard, 1992, 166.
28. Ibid.
29. Ibid., 167.
30. Ibid., 191.
31. Ibid., 342–343.
32. It is true that certain authors of the Cambridge school, like Skinner himself,
underscore the importance of “conf lict” in Machiavelli, but they do not derive
from this all of the possible—and in my mind, necessary—conclusions as to the
rupture effected by Machiavelli, and similarly concerning his different legacies.
33. Cf. Serge Audier, “Machiavel, héritier du républicanisme classique?” in A. Boyer
and S. Chauvier (eds.), Cahiers de philosophie de l’Université de Caen, no. 34, 2000,
9–35; Ibid., Machiavel, conflit et liberté, Paris, Vrin/EHESS, 2004; Ibid., Les Théories
de la République, Paris, La Découverte, 2004. See also V. Sullivan, Machiavelli,
Hobbes, and the Formation of Liberal Republicanism in England, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 2004.
CHAPTER 12
Serge Paugam
considers necessary to examine further. The fi rst issue concerns the increasing
heterogeneity of the working class, the second relates to the transformation of
social confl icts, and the third stresses the problem of sustained poverty in wealthy
societies. This article revisits these three issues and illustrates them with the help
of empirical materials drawn from contemporary research, which I hope allows
for a dialogue with Aron’s thought.
In effect, it comprises wage-earners and factory workers who, with few excep-
tions, do not possess any property; they work and they live off of their salary, i.e.
the cost of their efforts to the owner of the means of production. Their incomes,
at least in Western societies, do not vary substantially. Therefore, you can see in
this unique case all of the defining criteria come together: the same situation in
regards to property and the same type of work and income. The workers are for
the most part assembled in their workplaces and, at least in the nineteenth century,
they also usually lived together or next to each other. And this is how a sort of
society is created, distinct from global society, with its way of living and thinking,
its level of income, and its situation in regards to property. The similarity of the
socio-economic conditions is such that almost inevitably a conscience of commu-
nity forms and, with it, the opposition to other social groups. 5
166 S E RG E PAU G A M
Aron notes, however, that the conjunction of criteria characterizing the working
class does not apply to any other class; this he proves by successively examining
the cases of the bourgeoisie, the middle classes, and the rural classes.
Notwithstanding the homogeneity of the working class, the notion of class
consciousness needs to be carefully examined. Aron submits the notion to trial
by testing it with studies available in his time. This brings him to the following
conclusion: “In a country like France the workers think about certain things
differently than other groups in the collective. But they are also French and they
have characteristics that classify them as members of the French collective, while
at the same time having characteristics that classify them as members of a class. It
is always important to determine the strength of the elements that defi ne them as
a class compared to those that defi ne them as part of the global collective. Finally,
their class consciousness cannot be total. Is the working class aware of itself?
Indeed, class consciousness is never present in the totality of French workers; it
is incited by a minority.”6
Without explicitly referring to social bonds, Aron invokes the plurality of
forms of attachment in modern societies. Although an individual’s relation to
his or her professional activity fi rst of all links the individual intimately to a
group defi ned by its economic function, and secondly constitutes a social iden-
tity with the potential to envelope several overlapping dimensions of belonging,
it is necessary to observe that not all social circles intertwine with as much ease,
even within the working class. The worker, however integrated in occupational
terms, does not belong solely to a world of workers. He can be a member of a
religious community, or feel deeply enmeshed in the community of citizens. In
other words, forms of diversification of practices and representations are quite
possible.
In reality, Aron’s analysis foregrounded, with striking accuracy, the research
fi ndings of the decade that was to follow. In the beginning of the 1960s, the
embourgeoisement of the working class was debated. During this period, substan-
tial research on the affluent worker was done among the manual workers of Luton
in the region of Bedfordshire, which at that time was a significant and expand-
ing industrial hub.7 The theory of embourgeoisement postulates the adoption by
the manual workers and their families of a way of life that aligns them with the
middle class, before progressively integrating with it as their income level and
living conditions rise. The choice of Luton as the research site was influenced
by a conscious search for an environment enabling embourgeoisement: indeed,
many of the local workers were geographically mobile and had opted for this
region in the hope of better living conditions. Many of them lived in residential
neighborhoods made up of private homes. Finally, the local companies had a
reputation of embracing a wage policy favorable to the professional promotion
and social mobility of their workers.
The affluent worker maintains an instrumental relationship to his work inso-
far as his behavior within the professional sphere is informed by ends exter-
nal to it. It is the remuneration, and not the intrinsic value of work itself, that
counts. Individual fulfi llment is mediated by the possibility of improved living
conditions by means of a rise in income. Work, then, merely corresponds to
R E V I S I T I NG A RON ’ S T H E C L A S S S T RUG G L E 167
working class is hence fully validated by the developments of the past 50 years.
More generally, and not pertaining solely to the working class, the traditional
differentiations between employees are likely to remain in place as long as the
different categories of employment continue to collectively claim their profes-
sional identity; these categories are distinguished from one another in companies
and in the overall society; and, fi nally, there remains a need for classifying com-
petencies and responsibilities. It is, however, clear that the developments in the
organization of work and the labor market lead to new forms of differentiation
springing not only from various hierarchies but also from the very principles of
professional integration. New forms of inequalities based on both self-fulfi llment
at work and professional status are being placed on top of the traditional forms
of inequalities today.
for approaching this question, in dialogue with Aron’s projection concerning the
weakening of revolutionary movements and their propensity for violence.
We know that consciousness of oppression is a necessary condition for the
emergence of a social confl ict or struggle. We have confi rmed the thesis accord-
ing to which a penchant for radicalism gains impetus in the face of professional
precariousness. We are dealing with neither a spontaneous discontentment nor
an uncontrolled revolt. My in-depth interviews prove that precarious workers
possess a sense of social criticism and an inclination toward struggle. When their
jobs come under threat, they understand perfectly clearly that their future is
in the hands of large fi nancial corporations interested mainly in protecting the
profits of their shareholders. They also evaluate negatively the labor policies of
the successive governments and remain skeptical about the schemes of profes-
sional (re)integration, the latter being suspected as an additional element of their
being placed at risk. They see clearly into the causes of the difficulties they face
in their working life. In other words, it would be erroneous to take the current
weakness of protestations of precariousness for an incapacity of the workers to
form clear judgments about the objectives of a possible revolt. The research does
not provide support for the existence of a gap between the workers’ objective
situation and their consciousness of it.
However, concrete obstacles stand in the way of new social struggles—some
of which can certainly be overcome. Raymond Aron identified two conditions
for entering the phase of revolution: “Two contradictory feelings are necessary
and they go together: hope and despair. It is necessary that men fi nd themselves
in a situation that they judge essentially unacceptable and is necessary that men
conceive a different reality.”15 My research indicates high levels of despair among
the precarious workers—which may, at least partly, explain their radicalism—
while hope of change remains low or almost nonexistent.
The disillusionment of the workers can partly be explained by the nature of
power relations. In his acclaimed book on the conditions of the English working
class, Engels voiced a call for the class struggle with the following words: “Once
more the worker must choose, must either surrender himself to his fate, become
a ‘good’ workman, heed ‘faithfully’ the interest of the bourgeoisie, in which case
he most certainly becomes a brute, or else he must rebel, fight for his manhood to
the last, and this he can only do in the fight against the bourgeoisie.”16 A century
and a half have since passed, and the call sounds obsolete. This type of wording is
no longer expected from the parties of the left, including the Communist Party.
Just like the once-common claims made by the workers, the class struggle itself
has weakened. However, even if the style of Engels’ claims appears dated at the
beginning of the twenty-fi rst century, how can we judge the struggle of the pre-
carious workers itself as dated? Today, many wage-earning workers believe the
economic evolution to be scandalous. At the same time, they perceive themselves
as entangled in unequal power relations, at a time when even political parties and
trade unions have not kept in pace with the recent evolution. How do we launch
an attack against the bosses when we do not even know who they are in the
majority of cases? How do we face up to arguments infused by the logic of the
markets? Economic globalization often endows the heads of companies with an
170 S E RG E PAU G A M
elusive quality, as they steer fi nancial groups according to interests that transcend
national boundaries. The precarious workers are hence deprived of a point of
application for their discontent.
Nevertheless, it would be inaccurate to propose that no leeway exists for eco-
nomic processes that are not entirely determined by the autonomous forces of the
market. These processes are also shaped by the nature of the welfare state capable
of setting limits to capitalist development, particularly as the national popula-
tions express strong expectations regarding social protection. Social struggles
can hence target the public powers in general and call for fi rm policies in the face
of precariousness and unemployment. Precarious workers cannot, for instance,
accept the State’s lack of opposition to extensive lay-off s demanded by commer-
cial enterprises generating considerable profits. As it is, is there not an aberration
in a process with such a costly outcome for the workers and the collectivity alike?
Social struggles can thus locate a point of application in taking the welfare state as
their target, forcing its regulatory function on the economic and social system.
Bringing about a new configuration of power relations is not the only prereq-
uisite for the precarious workers to successfully see through new social struggles.
In order to make collective claims, the group formulating them needs to access
a certain level of consciousness of itself. If the group is split up into numer-
ous subgroups with diverging interests, chances are low that its activity will
be conducted in an organized manner. Given that professional precariousness
comes in many forms and concerns different levels of social hierarchy, and that
the subjective experiences of precariousness evolve over time, it is also unlikely
that the entire body of workers facing difficulties at work naturally possesses the
consciousness needed for forming a unified group.
Finally, a social movement of precarious workers implies the necessity of
means, fi nancial and symbolic alike. The self-identity of these workers is often
negative: they feel disqualified both at work and in the society at large. Social
movements are more likely to take shape when people consider their identity to
be unjustly tainted. We need to see whether the precarious workers are in a posi-
tion to perform a reversion of meaning—that is to say, to turn their discredit into
a collective force. If they feel that individual solutions are needed to address the
difficulties they face, collective action is also made void. Such a process is com-
monplace, as disadvantaged groups are in the majority of cases unable to defend
themselves. Nonetheless, the accumulated frustrations may eventually fi nd an
expression in sporadic revolts and radicalized movements.
Thus, 50 years after the publication of The Class Struggle, it is striking to assess
a radically transformed context of social confl icts. Even though expressions of
contentious satisfaction may not have disappeared altogether, it appears to have
been called into question by the conditions of the crisis of the society made up of
wage-earning workers. Nor can we say with certainty that future confl icts will
be non-violent.
In order to fi nd an explanation for this paradox, Aron looked into the case of
the United States and took up his thesis grounding the persistence of an under-
class in the extreme national and racial diversity of the US population. He would
revisit this theme in 1963 in the lectures given at the University of California at
Berkeley (leading to the publication of Essai sur les libertés in 1965). He recalled
the relative character of wealth in the United States. According to Aron, a large
gap exists in most families between actual purchasing power and the purchas-
ing power necessary to satisfy the desires now considered as normal. Aron also
reflected on the sense of poverty at a time of strong economic growth. He under-
lined the fact that in each society a minimum threshold is determined to defi ne
someone as poor or not, and this is fashioned by collective opinion, a spontane-
ous but powerful judgment. It is probable that in no society is the minimal level
of subsistence guaranteed to everyone. Aron insisted:
But what is significant is that even in the richest country in the world, a com-
paratively large fraction of the population continues to fall below this collectively
determined minimum, a fraction representing between one-fifth and one-fourth
of the American population, between 36 and 50 million human beings. Moreover,
poverty is defined less in quantitative terms than in qualitative terms. The ques-
tion is whether the poverty which statisticians define arbitrarily when they decree
that it begins below a certain income actually involves misery in Péguy’s sense of
the word. Are the poor excluded from the community and robbed of their dignity,
as it were, by their condition? And it would seem, according to the investigations,
that this actually is the case, not for all, but for a fraction of the poor. 22
Upon the publication of The Class Struggle, Aron also included in his analyses
a series of concrete examples, some of which stem from Michael Harrington’s
The Other America, fi rst published in 1964.23 Harrington’s book had a major
impact in the United States, to the extent that some consider it as one of the
main factors influencing the commencement of the war on poverty in the 1960s. In
any case, it marked a clear turning point in the dominant representations of the
affluent society. Harrington strove to show that the poor—counted in millions
in the United States—tend to become invisible unless one makes a conscious
effort to see them. Contrary to Galbraith, the author insisted on the problem of
segregation, and in particular, its racialized dimension. The middle class com-
fortably living in suburban neighborhoods and aligning its way of life with the
bourgeoisie is easily convinced of the disappearance of poverty. Harrington,
however, stressed the fact that the poor who often feel ashamed of their lot come
to internalize their inferiority and hence accept poverty as their destiny. This is
precisely what Harrington referred to as “the other America,” the fl ipside of the
apparent affluence.
Aron was receptive to this analysis. He noted that unemployment persisted in
the United States (at a rate of 4–5%) despite strong economic growth. He even
spoke about it as a “poverty reserve” comparable to Marx’s “industrial reserve
army.”24 He also pointed out that in the developed countries inequalities are
likely to appear and be accentuated between people who hold the educational
R E V I S I T I NG A RON ’ S T H E C L A S S S T RUG G L E 173
What does the picture look like in France at the time of Aron’s lecture on
The Class Struggle? According to the author, the French case is an intermediate
one between the United States and Great Britain. In the 1950s, France was faced
with a serious housing crisis, and, furthermore, many of its economic sectors
remained unmodernized. A large part of the rural population still lived in con-
ditions of extreme poverty. However, Aron drew attention to the existence of a
system of family allocation that progressively acted toward eliminating extreme
destitution.26
At the time of Aron’s analysis of these problems, destitution had thus not
entirely disappeared, and educational and cultural inequalities remained strong
in most countries. Moreover, even though Aron observed a reduction in eco-
nomic inequalities, coinciding with the quasi-universal acceptance of progres-
sive income taxation, two aspects of inequality struck him as being in total
contradiction to the ideals of modern societies. Firstly, he remarked upon “the
destitution of some at a time when the wealth of the community makes it pos-
sible to provide everyone with the minimum income required for what society
regards as a decent standard of living,” and secondly, upon “the transmission of
privileges, whether through the inheritance of wealth or through those advan-
tages that children of the upper strata enjoy from the beginning.”27 In a period of
strong growth, Raymond Aron was thus sensitive to the progressive diminution
of economic and social inequalities, but, unlike many others, was wary of con-
cluding that differences had been eradicated altogether: “The operation of the
tendential laws weakens the reality of classes in many ways, but so long as social
stratification exists (and it appears to be inseparable from industrial society), an
interpretation in terms of classes will always be possible.”28
The job crisis marking the fi nal decades of the twentieth century contrib-
uted to the renewed visibility of poverty to such an extent that, in the mid-
1980s, the term “new poverty”29 was coined. During the 1980s, welfare agencies
saw a growth in the number of applications for fi nancial assistance. While the
social workers had become accustomed to intervening in families that had accu-
mulated different disadvantages, often labeled as “social misfits,” they now saw
174 S E RG E PAU G A M
applications made by deprived young adults coming from families with no pre-
vious experience of hardship, and by individuals excluded from the labor mar-
ket and, thus, in the process of being placed at risk. In other words, the “new
poverty” largely resulted from the erosion of the system of social protection that
left out increasingly large parts of the population. Also, one should note that
this poverty was not only fi nancial in nature. It touched upon the epicenter of
social integration—that is to say, job stability. It was therefore often expressed by
relational—as opposed to fi nancial—poverty, bringing, for instance, health or
housing problems. It is for this reason that the new poverty aroused and contin-
ues to arouse anxiety in modern societies.
Generally speaking, the developments following this period confi rm that the
process of social disqualification is not merely limited to a context of an excep-
tional economic conjuncture. On the contrary, it has been amplified and now
concerns ever-larger portions of the population. Once limited to the unemployed
and the more permanently dependent, social disqualification now looms over
precarious workers and especially the working poor, a population characteristic
of our times. In sum, the phenomenon does not touch only the most precarious
among us, but casts a shadow of collective anxiety over the entire society.
Based on research comparing several European countries,30 I have been able
to verify that disqualifying poverty (pauvreté disqualifiante) is one of the elemen-
tary forms of poverty, and that this analytic notion needs to be elaborated upon
in order to better understand the variability of poverty in time and space. Social
disqualification is more likely to operate in post-industrial societies, namely in
those confronted by a sharp rise in unemployment and a precarious labor mar-
ket. However, it appears necessary to come into dialogue with other concepts
in order to analyze the different social configurations. Receiving an equally low
income, it is one thing to live in Italy’s southern Mezzogiorno, and another to
make it in Paris. Being poor in the northern parts of France in the 1960s did not
mean the same thing as being poor in the same place today. The poor can obvi-
ously be defi ned by referring to a common objective measure that might just
appear as universally acceptable and applicable. However, what is the sense of this
measure if we do not take into account, at the same time, the social representa-
tions and the lived experiences of people living in poverty?
What I would like to insist upon is that an elementary form of poverty cor-
responds to a type of interdependent relation that is stable enough to persist in
time and to impose itself sui generis, and despite the individual elements that
may characterize it in a given place and at a given time. Such a form expresses a
relatively crystallized state of equilibrium of relation between unequal individu-
als (the poor and the nonpoor) within a social system forming a coherent entity.
Disqualifying poverty now appears as a durable social configuration in France
and in other European countries. This will not be cast aside unless significant
collective efforts are mobilized in order to rethink social integration, and pro-
found reforms securing the integration of not only the poor and the dependent,
but all members of a given society, are designed. This contemporary perspective
differs dramatically from the one imagined by Aron when he lectured on The
Class Struggle.
R E V I S I T I NG A RON ’ S T H E C L A S S S T RUG G L E 175
Notes
1. Raymond Aron, Mémoires. 50 ans de réflexion politique, Paris, Julliard, 1983, 393;
Raymond Aron, Memoirs. Fifty Years of Political Reflection, New York and London,
Holmes & Meier, 1990, 266.
2. Raymond Aron, La Lutte de classes: Nouvelles Leçons sur les sociétés industrielles, Paris,
Gallimard, “Idées,” 1964.
3. Ibid., 92.
4. Aron, Mémoires, 398; Aron, Memoirs, 271.
5. Ibid., 98–99.
6. Ibid., 90.
7. J. H. Goldthorpe, D. Lockwood, F. Bechhofer, and J. Platt, The Affluent Worker,
vol. I: Industrial Attitudes and Behaviour, vol. II: Political Attitudes and Behaviour, vol.
III: The Affluent Worker in the Class Structure, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1968–69.
8. For a review of research on these issues, see Christian Thuderoz, “Du lien social
dans l’entreprise. Travail et individualisme coopératif,” Revue française de sociologie,
vol. XXXVI, no. 2, 1995, 325–354.
9. Notably Stéphane Beaux et Michel Pialoux, Retour sur la condition ouvrière. Enquête
aux usines Peugeot de Sochaux-Montbéliard, Paris, Fayard, 1999.
10. Serge Paugam, Le Salarié de la précarité. Les nouvelles formes de l’intégration profession-
nelle, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, “le lien social,” 2000.
11. Serge Paugam, “La condition ouvrière: de l’intégration laborieuse à l’intégration
disqualifiante,” Cités, vol. 35, 2008, 13–32.
12. Aron, La Lutte de classes, 226 et sqq.
13. Ibid., 226.
14. Ibid., 227.
15. Ibid., 229.
16. Friedrich Engels, La Situation de la classe laborieuse en Angleterre, 1st edition in
German, 1845, Paris, Editions sociales, 1975, 166. NB. The English citation is
informed by the several versions of the book accessible online.
17. Jean Fourastié, Les Trente Glorieuses ou la révolution invisible, Paris, Fayard, 1979.
18. J. K. Galbraith, L’Ere de l’opulence, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1961.
19. Ibid., 13.
20. In his memoirs, Aron points out that the rate of economic growth in Europe
(5–6% of the GDP) is likely to slow down as the productivity of the old continent
176 S E RG E PAU G A M
catches up with that of the new world. The high rate did not appear sustainable
to the author in the long term. See Aron, Mémoires, 408 and Aron, Memoirs, 279.
21. Aron, La Lutte de classes, 235.
22. Raymond Aron, Essais sur les libertés, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1965, 116. An Essay of
Freedom, New York, World Publishing, 1970, 79.
23. The French edition appears in 1967 with the title L’Autre Amérique. La pauvreté aux
Etats-Unis, Paris, Gallimard.
24. Essai sur les Libertés, 118; An Essay on Freedom, 80.
25. Raymond Aron, Les Désillusions du progrès. Essai sur la dialectique de la modernité,
Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1969, 35; Raymond Aron, Progress and Disillusion: The
Dialectics of Modern Society, New York, Praeger, 1968, 12–13.
26. Aron, La Lutte de classes, 238.
27. Aron, Les Désillusions du progrès, 34; Aron, Progress and Disillusion, 12.
28. Aron, Les Désillusions du progrès, 32; Aron, Progress and Disillusion, 10.
29. See about this question Serge Paugam, La Disqualification sociale. Essai sur la nouvelle
pauvreté, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 1991.
30. Serge Paugam, Les Formes élémentaires de la pauvreté, Paris, Presses universitaires de
France, “Le lien social,” 2005.
31. Serge Paugam (dir), L’Intégration inégale. Force, fragilité et rupture des liens sociaux,
Paris, Presses universitaires de France, “Le lien social,” 2014.
CHAPTER 13
Iain Stewart
F rom the mid-1950s to the 1960s, Raymond Aron played an important role in
popularizing the notion that the postwar achievements of Europe’s partially
managed, mixed economies held out the possibility of an end to the “ideologi-
cal” politics of class conf lict and polarization between left and right. This “end
of ideology” argument has been identified as a distinguishing feature of “cold
war liberalism,” a rhetorical shift in the language of anti-communism marking
the dawn of a “golden age of capitalism.”1 Yet, in Aron’s writings, the origin of
this argument is to be found not in capitalism’s golden age but in its moment of
ultimate crisis during the Depression. This problematizes the notion of a clear
divide between Aron’s pre-war socialism and cold war liberalism, highlighting
the importance of reaching a more detailed knowledge of the former if we are to
reach a better understanding of the latter.
Toward the end of his life, Aron described his political orientation in the
1920s and 1930s as “vaguely socialist.”2 Most of his subsequent commentators
have been equally vague on this subject, emphasizing the strength of Aron’s
socialist convictions before the Cold War without analyzing their content.3 Yet
interwar French socialism was so heterogeneous that simply to assert Aron’s pas-
sionate commitment to socialism in this period does not tell us a great deal.
What, for instance, are we to make of the fact that from 1938, a year in which
Aron publicly reasserted his socialist convictions,4 he was also involved in some
of the earliest attempts to formulate a “neo-liberal” economic program? To
answer this question we must begin by reconsidering Aron’s peripheral involve-
ment in student socialist politics at the École normale supérieure between 1924
and 1928. From this starting point, it is possible to reach a clearer understanding
of the “mature” Aron’s relationship with his socialist past and his place in the
intellectual history of economic liberalism.
178 I A I N S T E WA R T
since leaving for Germany in 1930. Aron had become personally acquainted with
Hendrik de Man in Germany and had praised his work for its attempt to escape
the doctrinal cul-de-sacs of reformism and revolution.6 His concern with this
issue and attraction to de Man’s ideas were typical of the student socialist milieu
to which Aron had belonged as a member of the Groupe d’étudiants socialistes.
Aron’s fi rst published article had called on the Socialist Party to reject “the cult
of outdated formulas” and develop “an acute vision of current possibilities.” 7
As a student, he had also been an admirer of Marcel Déat, and now he was
returning to the École normale to follow in Déat’s footsteps as secretary-archivist
of its Centre de documentation sociale (CDS).8 It was here that Aron would
befriend the young economist Robert Marjolin, a member of the heterodox
socialist group Révolution constructive. This group was an outgrowth from the
GESENS and Déat’s Bureau d’Études, and it had belonged to the avant-garde
of French planism since the early 1930s. Yet soon Marjolin began to distance
himself from socialist planism, withdrawing his support from Jules Romain’s
famous Plan du 9 juillet in 1934 and resigning from Révolution constructive the
following year.
Robert Marjolin later attributed his increasing skepticism about socialist eco-
nomic planning in these years to the influence of Aron.9 From 1934 up to the war
the two men co-taught a course on political economy at the CDS and became so
close that, according to Marjolin, “our moral and intellectual universes and our
value systems were the same, not just in general but in detail.”10 In 1936, they
were united in opposition to the economic policies of the Popular Front gov-
ernment elected the same year. Marjolin was an advisor on the Popular Front’s
National Economic Council but was unable substantially to influence its poli-
cies. He vented his frustration by criticizing the government’s economic policy
in the pages of Le Populaire, the Socialist Party’s newspaper. In the summer of
1937, Aron published his own critique of the Popular Front in the Revue de
métaphysique et de morale.11
This article focused on two things that Aron regarded as having condemned
the Popular Front’s economic policy to failure: the refusal of currency devalua-
tion before September 1936 and the implementation of the 40-hour week in the
same month. It also attacked the redistributionist logic underlying the Blum gov-
ernment’s economic program. In conceding large wage rises and working-hour
reductions during the industrial unrest of the summer of 1936, the government
had failed to recognize that such reforms, however desirable, were ultimately
dependent upon long-term improvements in the productivity of the French
economy. Yet Aron was also skeptical of structural reforms promoted by the
planist left as an alternative. It was not clear, he argued, that nationalizing credit
would be an effective mechanism for managing the economy, and French civil
servants and politicians lacked the expertise for this task anyway.
Aron and Marjolin’s critiques of the Popular Front scandalized their friends
on the left but were warmly received within the economic think tank X-Crise.12
Founded at the École Polytechnique in 1931, X-Crise was committed to rethink-
ing liberal economics in response to the Depression. Its membership ranged from
more or less orthodox economic liberals like Jacques Rueff on the right through
180 I A I N S T E WA R T
to the heterodox socialist Jules Moch on the left. X-Crise was an inter-profes-
sional body and economists mixed with reformist industrialists and trade union-
ists at its meetings. Aron and Marjolin entered its orbit via Marjolin’s working
relationships with the economist Charles Rist and the statistician Alfred Sauvy.
Like Marjolin, Sauvy was a frustrated advisor to the Popular Front who belonged
to that section of X-Crise that was sympathetic to the Blum experiment but
dismayed by its economic policy. Jules Moch, like Marjolin, had a background
on the planist wing of the Socialist Party, and X-Crise, as a whole, had been
preoccupied with the issue of economic planning since its inception. However,
the “neo-liberal” planning vision that developed at X-Crise was more centrist
and technocratic than its revisionist socialist counterpart, articulated in “a lan-
guage not of statist command but of initiative, coordination, and productivity.”13
Although Aron became increasingly critical of socialist planism in the 1930s, he
was much more sympathetic toward the planning model developed at X-Crise,
as his wartime writings would later demonstrate.
As well as drawing him closer to the X-Crise group, it is likely that Aron’s
critique of the Popular Front also facilitated his invitation to the Colloque Walter
Lippmann in August 1938. This was the fi rst international attempt explicitly
to formulate a “neo-liberal” economic program.14 The event attracted partici-
pants from a range of opinions and professional backgrounds roughly comparable
to that which characterized X-Crise. No consensus as to what “neo-liberal-
ism” might mean in practice was reached at the conference, which was divided
between defenders of radical laissez-faire economics such as Ludwig von Mises,
more centrist German economists who would go on to found the school of
Ordoliberalism, and Keynesians from revisionist socialist backgrounds such as
Aron and Marjolin. There is no record of any intervention by Aron in the dis-
cussions at this gathering, but in 1939 he did give a speech at the opening of the
Centre d’études pour la rénovation du libéralisme, the short-lived precursor of
the Mont Pèlerin Society founded in the wake of the Lippmann event.15
Although the text of this speech appears to have been lost, the record of its
occurrence suggests that Aron’s involvement in early neo-liberal initiatives was
ideologically significant and not purely circumstantial. But how does this square
with his then on-going commitment to socialism? This is in fact less paradoxical
than it at fi rst appears. Raymond Aron’s early intellectual itinerary shows that
during a period of profound crisis when traditional ideological categories such
as left and right or liberal and socialist were being extensively rethought, the
boundaries between the right wing of neo-socialism (broadly defi ned) and the
left of the emergent neo-liberal movement partially overlapped. It was from this
starting point on the overlapping peripheries of the liberal and socialist revision-
ist movements that Aron’s “post-ideological” economic thought would emerge
in more detail during the war years.
During the winter of 1943–1944, Aron’s writing on these themes became more
detailed and specific in its recommendations. In an article dated November–
December 1943, he wrote that “it is an indisputable fact that the prosperity and
grandeur of a nation depends to a large extent on the minority which holds the
positions of command,” but warned against the technocratic illusion that the
administration of things would replace the government of people in a postwar
French democracy.26 It would, he argued, be essential to reanimate the faith of
the masses in the democratic system, but the organization of mass democratic
enthusiasm must be steered along non-partisan lines.27 The only way to avoid a
return to the radical polarization of the 1930s would be to learn the lesson of that
decade’s failed economic policies:
Returning to this theme in the spring of 1944, Aron attributed the failure
of French economic policy in the 1930s to a disconnect between technical
expertise and government.29 After the war, this would need to be addressed
by linking public administration and independent think tanks, and by over-
hauling civil service training to instill a culture that was “less bookish, more
international.”30 It was, he argued, “inadmissible that an inspector of fi nances
should not have completed sufficient work experience in a bank or large enter-
prise, that he should not have direct experience of English and American
markets.”31 Economic planning would thus be fundamental to stimulating the
French economy into the growth upon which postwar social stability depended,
but it should be based upon a consultative, cooperative relationship with private
enterprise. Favoring a targeted, indicative form of planning over more com-
prehensive socialist approaches, Aron also suggested that the extent of state-
led economic planning would reduce once the immediate demands of postwar
reconstruction had been met, allowing for a relative expansion of the private
sector within the mixed economy. 32
Written between March and April 1944, this article shows Aron diverging
somewhat from the social democratic mainstream of planning debate as rep-
resented in the then recently published program of the Conseil national de la
Résistance (CNR). This was also apparent in a later piece in which he discussed
the question of nationalization. Acknowledging the strength of public opinion
on this issue, Aron recognized the political case for nationalization, even if the
economic argument was sometimes unconvincing. He thus accepted in principle
the nationalization of the mining, insurance, transport, chemical, and electric-
ity industries, but emphasized that public ownership should not be viewed as a
panacea.33 Elsewhere, his favorable attitude toward comprehensive social insur-
ance was balanced with a similarly pragmatic warning that its long-term feasi-
bility would depend upon tackling France’s historically low birth rate. 34 Aron’s
TH E ORIGINS OF TH E “EN D OF IDEOLOGY?” 183
moderation regarding such issues was not only rooted in an awareness of practi-
cal limitations; it was equally motivated by a political concern that any postwar
settlement should have a broad-based appeal and refrain from the kind of divisive
economic demagogy that he considered to have marred the experience of the
Popular Front. Later that year, he suggested that postwar economic planning
should be Saint-Simonian in inspiration rather than socialist because whereas
the socialist ideal would arouse confrontation, its Saint-Simonian counterpart
offered an opportunity for collaboration in good faith between social classes. 35
What this meant in practical terms, he later wrote, was that
While the CNR’s planning agenda was oriented toward the establishment of
an extensive social and economic democracy, with substantial worker control
at all levels and generous minimum wage guarantees, the vision promoted by
Aron stressed the need to subordinate the demands of both wages and prof-
itability to those of productivity: “Such a plan,” he wrote, “would transcend
partisan quarrels, offer the French people an opportunity to work together, and
create a space for reconciliation between political parties.”37 For Aron, then,
postwar economic planning would perform a socially didactic role in addition
to its immediate technical function: a broad-based, collaborative approach, cen-
tered on modernization and efficiency rather than socialization and redistribu-
tion, would ultimately serve to teach a lesson of civic virtue.38 Thus conceived,
planning offered an opportunity to break the cycle of moral and political crises
fueled by the historical recurrence of Manichean polarization in national politi-
cal debate since the French Revolution.39
While this vision stood in contrast to the socialist mainstream of wartime
planning debate, it would prove to be closely aligned with the planning model
that was eventually established by Jean Monnet, Robert Marjolin, and Étienne
Hirsch at the Commissariat-général au Plan in 1946.40 This is not to suggest that
men whose combined economic expertise greatly surpassed Aron’s were sub-
stantially influenced by his wartime writings. But the basic similarities between
their respective visions do point to a common historical origin that lay partly
in the heterodox economic theory developed in pre-war think tanks such as
X-Crise. This kind of economic thought, which had been relatively marginal
in the 1930s, became much less so after the war when it achieved hegemony
within France’s elite administrative training schools.41 Between 1946 and 1955
Aron participated in this ideological reorientation of French institutions, teach-
ing Keynesian economics at the new École nationale d’administration and at the
reformed Institut d’études politiques de Paris, previously a bastion of classical
economic liberalism.42
184 I A I N S T E WA R T
Ten years after the end of the war, Europe has achieved a level of prosperity which
surpasses the most optimistic predictions formulated at the launch of the Marshall
Plan . . . [A] semi-dirigiste, semi-liberal commercial policy has brought the same
results which, theoretically, would have been induced through liberal mechanisms.
Impassioned controversies between the doctrinaires of liberty and the doctrinaires
of administrative control today take on an outdated and almost trivial character.43
capitalist industrial society appeared to show that the fears expressed in Hayek’s
The Road to Serfdom were unfounded. Aron had been the chief architect of this
empirical critique, but the end of ideology was only one element of his critical
appraisal of radical laissez-faire economics. In an article written around the time
of his involvement in the Lippmann conference, Aron had criticized economic
liberalism on epistemological grounds.53 Using economics as an example to dem-
onstrate the limitations of objectivity in the social sciences, he criticized neo-
classical economic liberalism for transgressing the boundary between economic
theory and doctrine. What separated these domains, he argued, was the ability
to distinguish between two forms of truth, a “vérité logique” (logical truth) and
a “vérité de fait,” (factual truth) arising from the unavoidable interval separating
schema and reality. As Aron explained,
these uncertainties . . . do not result from the shortcomings of economists, but from
the complexity of economic reality. Economic subjects are men, their decisions are
only intelligible if they are rational: but they are not always rational. The economy
only exists as an abstraction of the economist, it unfolds in a complex of social insti-
tutions and is subject to the effects of political and social events . . . All parts of the
complex are interdependent, hence the multiplicity of possible actions and reactions
between these parts. In short, the situations analyzed by theoretical schemas are
precisely defined [whereas] concrete situations are always imperfectly known.54
This article anticipates the philosophical critique of Hayek that Aron would
develop following the publication of Hayek’s The Constitution of Liberty in 1960.
The defense of economic liberalism in this book was based on a narrow defi ni-
tion of liberty as non-coercion. Although impressed by the logical coherence of
the liberal philosophy which Hayek constructed from this starting point, Aron
regarded it as an abstract model that ignored how feelings of liberty and coer-
cion were actually experienced in the real world.55 While Hayek considered
that liberty was a concept that could be applied only in relation to individuals,
Aron, writing as the Algerian War approached its bloody denouement, noted
the capacity of individuals willingly to sacrifice personal freedoms in the cause
of national liberation. That Hayek’s liberalism rested on an unsophisticated psy-
chological model coupled to a naively individualist social ontology was a theme
that Aron would develop when he reworked his critique of Hayek during his
lectures at the Collège de France in 1973–1974.56 By this point, however, an oil
crisis sparked by the Yom Kippur War was bringing about a shift in the global
economy, which would soon put into question some of the fundamental assump-
tions of the economic model that Aron had defended since the war. By the end
of the decade, Hayekian neo-liberalism, marginalized for much of the postwar
period, was on the ascendency.
* * *
Notes
1. Anthony Arblaster, The Rise and Decline of Western Liberalism, Oxford, Blackwell,
1984, 322–326; Giles Scott-Smith, “The Congress for Cultural Freedom, the
End of Ideology and the 1955 Milan Conference ‘Defining the Parameters of
Discourse,’ ” Journal of Contemporary History, vol. 37, July 2002, 437–455; Donald
Sassoon, One Hundred Years of Socialism: The West European Left in the Twentieth
Century, London, Fontana, 1997, 189–208.
2. Raymond Aron, Le Spectateur engagé. Entretiens avec Jean-Louis Missika et Dominique
Wolton, Paris, Julliard, 1981, 25–26.
3. Robert Colquhoun, Raymond Aron: The Philosopher in History, 1905–1955, vol. 1,
Beverly Hills, Sage, 1986, 32–33; Nicolas Baverez, Raymond Aron: un moraliste au
temps des idéologies, Paris, Flammarion, 1993, 53–56.
4. Colquhoun, Raymond Aron: The Philosopher in History, 1905–1955, 143.
5. The following discussion of French socialist revisionism draws upon Jean-François
Sirinelli, Génération intellectuelle: khâgneux et normaliens dans l’entre-deux-guerres,
Paris, Fayard, 1988; Georges Lefranc, Le Mouvement socialiste sous la troisième répub-
lique, Paris, PBP, 1977; Marcel Déat, Mémoires politiques, Paris, Éditions Denoël,
1989; Christophe Prochasson, Les Intellectuels, le socialisme et la guerre, 1900–1938,
Paris, Éditions du Seuil, 1993; Jean Touchard, La Gauche en France depuis 1930,
188 I A I N S T E WA R T
Paris, Seuil, 1977; Olivier Dard, Le Rendez-vous manqué des relèves des années 30,
Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2002.
6. Raymond Aron, De Giscard à Mitterrand, 1977–1983, Paris, Éditions de Fallois,
2005, 655; Raymond Aron, “Henri de Man: Au delà du marxisme,” Libres Propos,
January 1931, 43–47.
7. Raymond Aron, “Ce que pense la jeunesse universitaire d’Europe,” Revue de
Genève, December 1926, 789–794, 791–792.
8. Raymond Aron, Mémoires. 50 ans de réflexion politique, Paris, Julliard, 1983, 47–48,
69.
9. Robert Marjolin, “Les années 30,” Commentaire, vol. 8, February 1985, 19.
10. “nos univers moraux et intellectuels, nos systèmes de valeurs étaient les mêmes, non seule-
ment dans l’ensemble mais même dans le détail,” Robert Marjolin, Le Travail d’une vie:
mémoires 1911–1986, Paris, Robert Laffont, 1986, 56.
11. Raymond Aron, “Réf lexions sur les problèmes économiques français,” Revue de
métaphysique et de morale, vol. XLIV, 1937, 793–822.
12. Aron, Mémoires, 143.
13. Richard Kuisel, Capitalism and the State in Modern France, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1981, 105–108; Philip Nord, France’s New Deal
from the Thirties to the Postwar Era, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press,
2010, 42.
14. Serge Audier, Le Colloque Lippmann: aux origines du néo-libéralisme, Paris, Bord de
l’Eau, 2008.
15. François Denord, Néolibéralisme version française: histoire d’une idéologie politique,
Paris, Demopolis, 2007, 156.
16. Raymond Aron, Penser la liberté, penser la démocratie, Paris, Gallimard, 2005,
57–106.
17. Ibid., 69.
18. Ibid., 57–61.
19. Ibid., 68–69, 89–90.
20. Ibid., 70.
21. “Ce qui est essentiel dans l’idée d’un régime démocratique, c’est d’abord la légal-
ité: régime où il y a des lois et où le pouvoir n’est pas arbitraire et sans limites.
Je pense que les régimes sont ceux qui ont un minimum de respect pour les
personnes et ne considèrent pas les individus uniquement comme des moyens de
production ou des objets de propagande.” Ibid., 70.
22. “ . . . si l’on peut gagner la guerre sans croire en la démocratie, on ne gagnera pas la
paix si l’on ne croit pas en elle,” Raymond Aron, L’Homme contre les tyrans, New
York, Éditions de la Maison Française, 1944, 247. See also 365–382.
23. “Enfin, libérés des Allemands, libérés de la tyrannie, les hommes doivent être
libérés aussi ‘du besoin et de la peur’, peur que répand la guerre, misère que
répand le chômage.” Ibid., 261–262.
24. “ . . . les collaborations élargies qu’exige la technique économique . . . de notre
époque,” Ibid., 284.
25. Ibid., 334–342.
26. “c’est une fait irrécusable que la prospérité et la grandeur d’une nation dépendent
en une large mesure de la minorité qui tient les postes de commande.” Raymond
Aron, L’Âge des empires et l’avenir de la France, Paris, Défense de la France, 1945,
92–93, 103.
27. Ibid., 99.
28. “ . . . il n’y avait pas d’équilibre économique, social, politique possible, aussi
longtemps que la stagnation de l’activité obligeait à partager, entre des appétits
TH E ORIGINS OF TH E “EN D OF IDEOLOGY?” 189
the political does not entail replacing a unilateral economic determinism, say,
with an equally dogmatic and uninstructive political determinism; it does not
refer to causal primacy. Nor does it suggest that our interest should be directed
solely to political phenomena. What it suggests, rather, is that, in a world that
is increasingly living the same history and speaking the same language of tech-
nology and economics, it is in the political realm that international actors’ dif-
ferences are most clearly displayed. More to the point, politics is a question of
human existence and human ends, to which there is no single answer—perhaps
save for on the horizon, as a regulatory idea. Behind every sociological analysis
or sober piece of journalism stands Aron the philosopher.
Some of the thinkers discussed in this section had a more difficult time than
others did in dealing with this uncomfortable uncertainty about man’s destiny.
At some point, though, they all confronted the fundamental questions about
man’s nature and the society in which he acts in their own way. The thinker
in whom changes in society had probably produced the most outrageous moral
indignation was Karl Marx, Aron’s most important and influential “interlocutor.”
Sylvie Mesure’s chapter examines Aron’s interpretation of Marx and Marxism.
She draws on Aron’s writings about Marx, especially the lectures about Marx
that Aron gave at the Sorbonne in the 1960s and at the Collège de France in
the 1970s. Published in 2002 as Le Marxisme de Marx, these lectures illustrate
Aron’s understanding of Marx and the various forms of Marxism that sprouted
up in twentieth-century France. One of the major questions in Mesure’s chapter
is how one should interpret an author. This becomes particularly troublesome
with a writer such as Marx, who posed alternately as a prophet and as a scien-
tist, preaching revolution and then illustrating the inevitable course of history.
Mesure shows us that Aron’s interpretation was in this regard far more hon-
est than the one-sided and diametrically opposed interpretations of Sartre and
Althusser. Ignoring the importance Marx attributed to his economic analyses
is just as egregious a disservice to the German thinker as postulating an epis-
temological break that negates all of his early works. In any case, regardless of
the interpretation, there are certain problems with Marx’s economics, sociology,
and philosophy of history, not the least of them being his historical determinism,
buffered by the primacy given to economic factors.
This is a mistake Montesquieu did not make, and if Aron has no problem
thinking of himself as an intellectual descendant of this French liberal, it is
because he found the latter’s respect for the plurality of causes deeply congenial
to his own interests. Indeed, Aron declared Montesquieu the founder of soci-
ology—more specifically, of political sociology, as Miguel Morgado points out
in his contribution. Morgado explores the similarities and differences between
Aron’s and Montesquieu’s approaches to political and social regimes and how
these regimes are unique in their respective time-periods. Montesquieu’s notion
of “principle” is reflected in Aron’s own analysis of political regimes as a method
of elucidating the struggle between democratic virtue and the sense of compro-
mise that is at the heart of democratic politics. If a polity leans too far in either
direction, it is prone to fall into corruption. Morgado concludes his chapter with
a discussion of the prosaic nature of democracy.
VO I C E S O F T H E G R E AT M E N O F T H E PA S T 193
political action. They historically contextualize Weber’s ideas and make use of
Aron’s numerous writings on Weber, especially two unpublished courses of his
from the 1970s, Théorie de l’action politique and Jeux et enjeux de la politique, in
which Aron reevaluates Weber’s two ethics. In the authors’ view Aron proves
to have a more coherent understanding of political ethics because he is more
attuned to the irreducible variety of political ends and the statesman’s need to
fulfi ll faithfully both his obligations and the demands of his conscience.
* * *
The analysis of history is the key to addressing the central political question.
Aron does so in the context of the confl icts that would be fought, as Nietzsche
foresaw and as Nicolas Baverez has recalled, in the name of man’s philosophies
and ideas. He has been justly called the “Thucydides of the twentieth century.”
Nevertheless, the philosophical world of Plato and Aristotle is different from
that of Thucydides. When we open the latter’s history of the Peloponnesian
War, the city is caught in a bloody war and we fi nd ourselves amid statesmen,
military commanders and armies, citizens, and demagogues. Aron’s city—like
Thucydides’ city—is in “motion.”2 One might think, however, that the Platonic
approach was theoretical or philosophical, and Thucydides’ merely historical or
descriptive. This would be unfair to Thucydides. As with Thucydides, Aron’s
theory is based on a philosophy of history—it is a theory and sometimes even
a philosophical theory, offering models, both static and dynamic, with deep
insights into the human condition and the ways of examining it. We can recall
some of them briefly: the “comparative method” which he used is capable of
close phenomenological analysis and fi ne-grained distinctions, vividly bringing
to light societies and political systems in their unity and diversity. He avoided the
idealization of any actual or potential society as wholly just, free, and equal. He
also never forgot values, goods, and the improvements that society and political
institutions can pursue.
“Values” or goods we cherish—truth, justice, liberty, equality—are neither
transcendental nor found in institutions, which are but imperfect arrangements.
There is no perfectly just society: not even democracy is the natural system
of the human species, but only one “perfectible artifact” or an “invention.”
Aron could not describe the best regime in the abstract, ignoring social mech-
anisms and their results. One consequence of this approach is that he shared
with Tocqueville the view that the best friend of democracy is not its flatterer.
Aron did not ignore the international scene—the modern nation is not isolated;
there are people and groups affected here and now, sometimes tragically, by
decisions made somewhere. His method leaves room for something beyond the
rational method. People may not behave reasonably despite hypothetical social
contracts, and all institutions represent choices related to a particular time and
place. But Aron’s attention to practical particularities is never merely pragmatic
or Machiavellian Realpolitik. There are many human activities that we do not
understand without the use of standards (truth in science, beauty in art, the good
VO I C E S O F T H E G R E AT M E N O F T H E PA S T 195
in ethics). Aron was aware that, even in a fictitious original state, people can have
different principles because values and norms are the application of “reason” to
particular circumstances that we know empirically and must adapt to different
types of society; and, in the public sphere, the references are necessarily multiple,
but not unrelated to a reasonable choice. Finally, not being himself a politician,
he never ignored the role of the statesman, the recognition of which tends to be
absent in current political theory.
Less than clear-cut theories may disappoint. But it is worth remembering that
this is an old problem and that necessary simplifications do not always produce
even good theories. Someone once said that Plato wrote the Republic, a city in
the sky, to achieve a better city, and that Aristotle wrote the Politics just to make
a better theory. However, it is certainly easier to live in the city of Aristotle than
in the regime “according to prayer” of Plato. To Aron only possible political
regimes can be compared among themselves, and the city in motion was what
interested him above all. Only there can we fi nd the political speeches, propa-
ganda, confl ict, armies, voting, parties, and all the other elements that populate
his theories. Can we have a comprehensive theory about the city in motion? Aron
was attracted to those who had tried to discover one—Montesquieu, Clausewitz,
and even Marx. But if the power and fertility of this “praxeological” vision can
be shown, this can only be done through the study of Aron’s insights, hypoth-
eses, and innumerable concrete proposals when seen in light of his explicit or
implicit theoretical framework. His own political judgments are in debt to his
never-completely-fi nished-or-articulated theory. As Leo Strauss, who regarded
Aron’s Peace and War as “the best book on the subject in existence,”3 said, “it is
impossible to understand the biggest movement without understanding simulta-
neously the biggest rest,” and “one cannot understand the biggest war without
understanding the biggest peace, the peace which, as it were, culminates in the
biggest war.”4 That Aron’s reflections on “the biggest rest” are necessarily incom-
plete may, in a sense, be a misfortune, but it is also a challenge that the present
volume has attempted to address.
Notes
1. Raymond Aron, Mémoires. 50 ans de réflexion politique, Paris, Julliard, 1983, 746.
2. If we are allowed to borrow Leo Strauss’s words about Thucydides in The City and
Man, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1978.
3. Letter of June 11, 1963, Aron Archives.
4. Leo Strauss, The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism, Chicago, University of
Chicago Press, 1988, 83.
CHAPTER 14
Pierre Hassner
Parodying Irving Kristol, who once said that the “neo-conservative is a lib-
eral who was mugged by reality,” one could say that Aron was a Kantian who
had been mugged by history, especially by the rise of totalitarianism in the twen-
tieth century.
The difference is that the neoconservatives abandoned their prior liberalism
or leftism, while, for Aron, the discovery of tragedy converged with his episte-
mological position that begins from the subject involved in history rather than
from a panoramic or teleological vision of history, but he never gave up his
commitment to Kant or the Enlightenment. What he abandoned was the idea
of the “cunning of nature” or Providence (according to Kant), or the “cunning
of reason” (according to Hegel), leading to a happy ending for history. Aron’s
philosophy of history always starts from the committed subject who is ignorant
of the future.
Let me try to enumerate the similarities and differences between Aron and
Kant.
A key meeting point, it seems to me, is their common attitude toward the
diversity and possible contradictions between the different dimensions of anthro-
pological and historical experience. For those thinkers who want to fi nd an intel-
ligible order in such multiplicity, there are three possible attitudes.
The fi rst attitude belongs to those for whom diversity is ordered hierarchically
and harmoniously. This is the case for Plato and Aristotle, to whom the hierar-
chies of the soul and of the city run in parallel, whether the individual or society
are at stake. The passions of the people, slaves, workers or merchants; the thumos,
seat of honor and anger, characteristic of the guardians; and the theoretical or
contemplative reason characteristic of the philosophers; all of these are presented
in ascending order. Secondly, there are thinkers for whom dialectics allows either
the reversal of hierarchies or the combination of opposites, and who think that
they have arrived at the synthesis of the individual and the universal without sac-
rificing either the particular or the general. This is the case with the Hegelians.
And there are those, like Kant and Aron, who start by strictly separating differ-
ent dimensions according to their respective essence, and then strive to diminish
the gap, going to great lengths to construct bridges between them. Thus, for
Kant, the separation of noumenon and phenomenon, of the transcendental and the
empirical, of theoretical reason and practical reason, of education and the moral
leap that only will lead to peace (“an agreement pathologically extorted may, he
says, turn into a moral whole,”)4 the search for concepts (“which without intu-
itions are empty”) and intuitions (“which without concepts are blind”)5 which
are as indispensable as they are problematic. The indefi nite progress in the way
of morality as well as peace provokes an ironic smile from those who, like Hegel,
think that Kant’s “indefi nite” is the “bad infi nity,”6 or, like Leo Strauss, believe
that “a perpetual progress towards perpetual peace means perpetual war.” 7 This
objection plays on the fact that Kant is not clear as to whether it is through an
asymptotic progress that mankind would gradually attain peace by decreasing
the frequency and intensity of wars or, on the contrary, it is their frequency and
intensity, and, therefore, their cost, that are expected to produce a reversal whose
crowning would be moral conversion.
R AY M O N D A RO N A N D I M M A N U E L K A N T 199
Aron goes in the same direction, but harbors more doubts about the fi nal out-
come. In his most unambiguous text, “L’Aube de l’histoire universelle,” gathered
in Dimensions de la conscience historique,8 Aron notes, as Kant did, that humanity
is in a “cosmopolitan situation,”9 where events spread from one country to the
other (the “process” driven by advances in science, technology, education, objec-
tive factors that demonstrate that nations no longer need to kill to survive) but,
at the same time, there is the drama of “the clash of passions and desires that
for the moment remain alive.” The peaceful outcome depends on the taming
(which is in no way assured) of social and political passions following the taming
of nature. He therefore expressed the same wishes as Kant, as he also believes
in the progress of reason. In a long article, “Pour le progrès, après la chute des
idoles,”10 he even defends modern society, not only against the absolute pessi-
mism of the “new philosophers” of the seventies (mainly Bernard-Henri Lévy
and André Glucksmann), but also against authors he revered, such as Tocqueville,
or admired, like Solzhenitsyn. His Kantian conclusions always contain, however,
a protestation of ignorance and a question mark following the profession of moral
faith.
Paix et guerre entre les nations ends with the following statement:
Nothing can prevent us from having two duties, duties that are not always compat-
ible, toward our people and toward all peoples: one is to participate in the conf licts
that constitute the web of history, and the other is to work for peace . . . Will we
be obliged to choose between a return to the pre-industrial age and the advent of
the post-belligerent age? . . . Will the age of wars end in an orgy of violence or in a
gradual pacification? We know that the answers to these questions remain uncer-
tain, but we do know that man will have surmounted the antinomies of action
only when he has finished with violence, or with hope. Let us leave to others
with more talent for illusions the privilege of speculating on the conclusion of the
adventure, and let us try not to fail in either of the obligations ordained for each of
us: not to run away from a belligerent history, not to betray the ideal; to think and
to act with the firm intention that the absence of war will be prolonged until the
day when peace has become possible—supposing it ever will.11
On the previous page, after reporting two new features, (the ability to manip-
ulate natural forces and the emergence of a universal consciousness at once moral
and pragmatic), he wonders: “Are these two new factors proof of a new phase
of the human enterprise?” His response is modeled on the three classic Kantian
questions (“What do I know? What should I do? What can I expect?”): “We can-
not know, we must desire, we are entitled to hope that it is so . . . To use Kantian
language, there is a regulatory use of the ideas of reason.”
In the text titled “L’Aube de l’histoire universelle,” he makes it clear that
mankind has entered what Kant called “the cosmopolitan situation,” which is
characterized, as we have seen, by the coexistence on the one hand of what Aron
calls the “process,” technical progress and material change of societies with, on
the other hand, the “drama,” the interaction and often the struggle of peoples and
social passions. Will the process eventually absorb the drama, or will the drama
put an abrupt end to the process? “It may be,” replied Aron, “that universal
200 PIER R E H ASSN ER
history will differ in this respect from the provincial histories of past ages. But it
is only a hope based on faith.”12
Kant is much more assertive, for two reasons that lead us to the center of the
difference between the two thinkers. First, his pamphlets on history attribute a
fundamental role to what he sometimes calls the “cunning of nature” and some-
times simply “Providence.”
Practical reason issues a clear verdict that has no exceptions: “there ought to
be no war, neither between me and you in the condition of Nature, nor between
us as members of States.”13 Both men and states must leave behind the state of
nature, a state of war, to enter a state of institutionalized peace. In his Idea for
a Universal History from a Cosmopolitan Point of View 14 Kant explains that “the
hidden plan of nature” should lead to the following result: “One day, in part
by the establishment of the most appropriate civil constitution domestically (a
republican government) and partly on the external side by a common conven-
tion and law, a state of things will emerge as a universal civil community that
can maintain itself as an automaton” (seventh proposal). In Perpetual Peace15 it
should be noted that, for Kant, this result is due to the “hidden plan of nature
for mankind,” a plan that men could have devised consciously but have not, yet
one that will be realized by them, in part, in spite of themselves: Volentem fata
ducunt, nolentem trahunt (The fates lead those who go willingly, and those who are
unwilling they drag). Moreover, it is precisely the passions and wars that are the
instruments of Providence.
Hence the paradox—a morality without concessions, but whose violations
apparently drive history, which should eventually allow the victory of moral
progress.
However, two surprises await the reader of Perpetual Peace: Kant says that this
universal civil community can only be achieved by a single move, the states
entering into a legal situation by submitting to a higher authority; and this legal
situation must be achieved through the second best (“surrogate”),16 that is to say,
“a free federalism which must necessarily relate to the concept of law.” Instead of
a universal republic, it would be the negative surrogate of a permanent alliance
extending further and further (Second Defi nitive Article).
If the defi nition of institutions destined to “move gradually towards perpetual
peace” admits some empirical flexibility, it is not the same for the relationship
between morality, law, and politics. There cannot, according to Kant, be a con-
fl ict between them. Politics is “the doctrine of legal practice,” morality is its
foundation, and there cannot be a confl ict between theory and practice, which
Kant devoted an entire pamphlet to proving: “Politics must bend the knee before
morality.” On the other hand, Kant criticizes the “political moralist” who takes
liberties with morality in the name of politics, and he praises the “moral politi-
cian,” who recognizes that “morality is the best policy.”
The political philosophy of Kant is not, strictly speaking, ultimately political.
It is a legal philosophy based on a moral philosophy and guaranteed by a philoso-
phy of history.
All these terms exist in Aron, but with a very different hierarchy of priorities.
R AY M O N D A RO N A N D I M M A N U E L K A N T 201
The moral inspiration, and above all Kantian morality, is always present with
Aron, but in the background. He says in his Mémoires that he never forgot the
categorical imperative or the “Religion within the Limits of Reason,” and it is
true that some expressions he used, such as “I am not a believer in the ordinary
sense of the word” and “to achieve one’s secular salvation,” may be their echo. In
Chapter 19 of Peace and War between Nations, titled “In Search of a Morality,” he
arrives at a “morality of wisdom” which, if it is the “best in terms of both facts
and values, does not resolve the contradictions of the strategic-diplomatic behav-
ior, but tries to fi nd for each case the most acceptable compromise.” Between
“idealism and realism” and “conviction and responsibility” (the titles of two
sub-chapters), compromises are possible and desirable.
But Aron, who had engraved on his academician’s sword the (unfortunately
very optimistic!) phrase of Herodotus, “No man is so devoid of reason as to
prefer war to peace,” also chose for the epigraph to Peace and War a passage from
Montesquieu, “International law is based by nature upon this principle: that
the various nations ought to do, in peace, the most good to each other, and, in
war, the least harm possible, without detriment to their genuine interests.”17 He
continues to say that peace is in itself preferable to war from all points of view,
including the moral one, but not to unilateral disarmament. A posture of “all or
nothing,” even from a nuclear perspective, risks leading to war or oppression.
“The cost of bondage, for a people and a culture, may be more than the cost of
war, even nuclear war.” The center of his thinking and his positions is political
(even if the inspiration is often moral). He does not share the contempt of Kant
(and of Rousseau and Hegel) for theorists of war legislation, treated by Kant as
“miserable comforters,” but he shares even less than his masters the faith in inter-
national organizations like the United Nations and international courts like the
International Criminal Court. The idea of reason, “that of human reconciliation
and peace,” remains with him, albeit somewhat disembodied. In any case, it is
not defi ned in institutional terms.
And perhaps yet another surprise awaits us.
In Perpetual Peace, Kant says that humanity is in a cosmopolitan situation where
states depend on each other, and where a breach of human rights can be known
and its consequences felt on the other side of the earth. He concludes that these
neighboring states are entitled to intervene by offering mediation, or by their
disapproval, but not by force. Two years later, in paragraph 60 of the Doctrine of
Right (the fi rst part of the Metaphysics of Morals), Kant wrote:
The Right of a State against an unjust Enemy has no limits, at least in respect
of quality as distinguished from quantity or degree. In other words, the injured
State may use—not, indeed, any means, but yet—all those means that are per-
missible and in reasonable measure in so far as they are in its power, in order to
assert its Right to what is its own. But what then is an unjust enemy according to
the conceptions of the Right of Nations, when, as holds generally of the state of
Nature, every State is judge in its own cause? It is one whose publicly expressed
Will, whether in word or deed, betrays a maxim which, if it were taken as a
universal rule, would make a state of Peace among the nations impossible, and
202 PIER R E H ASSN ER
would necessarily perpetuate the state of Nature. Such is the violation of public
Treaties, with regard to which it may be assumed that any such violation concerns
all nations by threatening their freedom, and that they are thus summoned to
unite against such a wrong, and to take away the power of committing it. But
this does not include the Right to partition and appropriate the country, so as to
make a State as it were disappear from the earth; for this would be an injustice
to the people of that State, who cannot lose their original Right to unite into a
Commonwealth, and to adopt such a new Constitution as by its nature would be
unfavorable to the inclination for war.
Carl Schmitt violently attacked this text in an appendix to Nomos of the Earth,
arguing that considering a state as an enemy of humanity allows it to be treated
inhumanely. But does this text of Kant not make one think of Aron’s discovery
of Nazi totalitarianism, which made him abandon the pacifist temptations of his
youth?
On the other hand, in the conclusion of the section in this book dedicated to
cosmopolitan law, Kant writes:
Now, as a matter of fact, the morally practical reason utters within us its irrevo-
cable veto: There shall be no war. So there ought to be no war, neither between
me and you in the condition of nature, nor between us as members of states which,
although internally in a condition of law, are still externally in their relation to
each other in a condition of lawlessness; for this is not the way by which any one
should prosecute his right. Hence the question no longer is as to whether perpetual
peace is a real thing or not a real thing, or as to whether we may not be deceiving
ourselves when we adopt the former alternative, but we must act on the supposi-
tion of its being real. We must work for what may perhaps not be realized, and
establish that constitution which yet seems best adapted to bring it about (mayhap
republicanism in all states, together and separately). And thus we may put an end to
the evil of wars, which have been the chief interest of the internal arrangements of
all the states without exception. And although the realization of this purpose may
always remain but a pious wish, yet we do certainly not deceive ourselves in adopt-
ing the maxim of action that will guide us in working incessantly for it; for it is a
duty to do this. To suppose that the moral law within us is itself deceptive, would
be sufficient to excite the horrible wish rather to be deprived of all reason than to
live under such deception, and even to see oneself, according to such principles,
degraded like the lower animals to the level of the mechanical play of nature.18
Facing, on the one hand, this doubt about the fi nal outcome and, on the
other, the call to duty and reason, is it not tempting to think that at the end of
his life, it was Kant who was getting closer to Aron?
Notes
1. Sylvie Mesure, Raymond Aron et la raison historique, Paris, Vrin, 1984.
2. Pierre Manent, “La politique comme science et comme souci,” in Raymond
Aron, Liberté et égalité: cours au Collège de France, Édition établie et présentée par
R AY M O N D A RO N A N D I M M A N U E L K A N T 203
Pierre Manent, Paris, Editions de l’École des hautes études en sciences sociales,
2013.
3. Georges Canguilhem, “La problématique de la philosophie de l’histoire au début
des années 30,” in Jean-Claude Chamboredon (ed.), Raymond Aron, la philosophie
de l’histoire et les sciences sociales, Paris, Editions rue d’Ulm, 1999, 9–23.
4. Raymond Aron, Intemporality in Kant, ms of master’s thesis (unpublished).
Bibliothèque Nationale de France, Paris, Manuscripts, Fonds Aron.
5. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp Smith, New York, St.
Martin’s Press, 1929, 93.
6. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Hegel’s Science of Logic, trans. A. V. Miller,
London, Allen and Unwin, 1969.
7. Leo Strauss, Seminar on Kant, Chicago, University of Chicago Library, 1956–
1957, Special Collections.
8. Raymond Aron, “L’Aube de l’histoire universelle,” in Raymond Aron, Dimensions
de la conscience historique, Paris, Plon, “Recherches en sciences humaines,” 1961; new
edition Paris, Les Belles Lettres, “Le goût des idées,” 2011, 229–255. Raymond
Aron, The Dawn of Universal History, Londres, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1961;
reproduced in Politics and History, New York, Free Press, 1978, 212–233.
9. Kant’s expression is “Perpetual Peace.”
10. Raymond Aron, “Pour le progrès, après la chute des idoles,” Commentaire, no. 3,
1978, 233–245.
11. Raymond Aron, Paix et guerre entre les nations, Paris, Calmann-Lévy, 1962, 770;
Raymond Aron, Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, New Brunswick,
NJ, Transaction, 2003, 787.
12. Raymond Aron, Dimensions de la conscience historique, Paris, Les Belles Lettres,
2011, 254; Politics and History, 232.
13. Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, “The Universal Rights of Mankind,”
Part III of “Public Right,” conclusion. In The Philosophy of Law: An Exposition of
the Fundamental Principles of Jurisprudence as the Science of Right, trans. W. Hastie,
Edinburgh, Clark, 1887.
14. Immanuel Kant, “Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltbürgerlicher
Absicht,” Berlinische Monatsschrift, no. 4, 1784, 385–480.
15. Immanuel Kant, Zum ewigen Frieden. Ein philosophischer Entwurf, Königsberg, F.
Nicolovius, 1795.
16. Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace, Second Definitive Article: “The Right of
Nations Shall Be Founded on a Federation of Free States,” in Kant’s Principles
of Politics, Including His Essay on Perpetual Peace: A Contribution to Political Science,
trans. W. Hastie, Edinburgh, Clark, 1891.
17. Aron, Peace and War, 5.
18. Immanuel Kant, The Science of Right, conclusion, in Philosophy of Law: An Exposition
of the Fundamental Principles of Jurisprudence as the Science of Right, trans. W. Hastie,
Edinburgh, Clark, 1887.
CHAPTER 15
R aymond Aron discovered Max Weber around the same time that he discov-
ered Karl Marx—in the early 1930s, during his sojourn in Germany. These
thinkers represented a fraction of the total number of German authors he delved
into at the time, including Husserl, Heidegger, and the Southwest School of neo-
Kantians (Heinrich Rickert and Wilhelm Windelband).1 It was in Max Weber’s
writings that Aron eventually found the resources and the words to express the
relationship between politics and morality.2 Moreover, Aron also found in Weber
an exposition of the tension between knowledge (science) and action (politics).
There are genuine trade-offs between a profession that demands the absolute pur-
suit of truth and one that demands the willingness to compromise not only one’s
own morals (anathema to the moralist) but even the truth itself (anathema to the
scientist). This variance at the root of science and politics is probably why Aron
was so fond of “failed” statesmen: Thucydides, Machiavelli, Clausewitz, and
Weber himself. All of them partook to some extent in politics or war, and they
were incredibly gifted thinkers who ref lected on the nature of politics or war.
The 1930s were rife with political agitation and a looming war, and thus
Weber confi rmed Aron’s intuition that history was once again on the move.
Compared to Émile Durkheim, who dominated Aron’s sociological education
at the École normale supérieure, Weber seemed to have caught on to the spirit
of the time in a most stimulating way.3 Weber’s methodology was also more
congenial to Aron’s approach because it takes individuals and their intentions as
the starting point. Hence, both thinkers can preserve some degree of freedom
for their actors. This freedom is crucial, for if they want to cross the bridge from
knowledge to action, then they must believe that actors have at least some role to
play in forming the future.
The young French student paid his respects to the imposing German thinker
by showering him with unabashed admiration and giving him pride of place in
206 SCOTT N ELSON A N D JOSÉ COLEN
his fi rst published work on German sociology.4 Thirty years later, he could not
help but continue to evince a profound, albeit mitigated, respect for Weber, even
when he disagreed with him.5 One of the most important influences of Weber
on Aron (and one of the explanations for the former’s methodology) was the rec-
ognition of the relation between knowledge and action, or science and politics.6
Both Raymond Aron and Max Weber were social scientists who commented on
the politics of their day and yet never managed to adapt to the conditions neces-
sary to partake fully of political life. We will now turn to Weber to investigate
those conditions.
On January 28, 1919, against the backdrop of the November Revolution
of 1918, Weber gave his famous Politik als Beruf lecture before the Münchner
Freistudentischer Bund. One could even say that politics surrounded the origins
of the lecture itself: Weber initially did not want to give the talk and recom-
mended Friedrich Naumann in his stead. Naumann was ill at the time and it
seemed like the opportunity might be passed to Kurt Eisner, whereupon Weber,
who cared deeply about the success of the new German democracy, rose to the
occasion in order to prevent Eisner from adding any more to the revolutionary
fervor of the students.7 Weber defi nes politics early on in this lecture as “striv-
ing for a share of power or influence over the division of power, be it between
states or between groups of people within states.”8 It is here that Weber also sets
forth the three qualities that are prerequisites to embarking on a political career:
passion (Leidenschaft), feeling of responsibility (Verantwortungsgefühl), and sense of
proportion (Augenmaß).
As far as Aron’s engagement with this particular teaching is concerned, he
focuses primarily on the dichotomy and implications of Weber’s ethic of convic-
tion (Gesinnungsethik) and ethic of responsibility (Verantwortungsethik). These two
ethics follow on Weber’s discussion of the relation between ethics and politics.
That the ethic required for effective statesmanship might be different from the
personal ethic necessary to be a good Christian, say, is an idea that goes as far
back as Machiavelli. Unlike his Florentine predecessor, the fulcrum of political
morality in Weber’s construct is not only about having the fortitude to choose
potentially disagreeable means in order to achieve desired ends, but also having
the fortitude to take responsibility for the consequences, intended and unin-
tended, of political action.
Aron thought that Weber had in mind two different types of people when he
elaborated on his ethic of conviction: the pacifists of Christian inspiration and the
revolutionaries. Weber’s contention with respect to the former was that if their
moral position were entirely swept away, accepting the status of the defeated
party, they would be inviting the victors, now in complete control of the moral
high ground, to force them into a treaty so unfair that it would sow the seeds of
discontent and, in effect, undermine the very pacifism that was their creed. As
for the latter, the revolutionaries were guilty of positing their goal as an abso-
lute value whose price of attainment could never be too high.9 Aron knew that
whereof Weber spoke: he, too, had to stand up for reason and responsibility in
the carnival of French public life.
We cannot separate these two ethics so easily, for conceptual problems seem
to abound. On the one hand, how can there be an ethic of responsibility without
a reference point toward which responsibility is directed? Conviction is there-
fore a precondition for responsibility.10 On the other hand, to the extent that
the ethic of conviction also means satisfying one’s conscience, and not just the
exigencies of one’s faith, how can we be so certain that one’s conscience would
not be adversely affected by the failure to achieve an outcome consonant with
one’s convictions? In this sense, conviction could potentially presuppose respon-
sibility, that is, a concern for consequences. For Aron these two ethics might
not only be conceptually flawed, but even destructive, since they offer a sort of
justification to the false realists and false idealists: the former can disregard moral
injunctions with impunity, while the latter can wantonly blind themselves to the
critical role they are playing in contributing to the collapse of the existing order,
thereby paving the way for revolutionaries or tyrants to rule. There is an addi-
tional problem worth highlighting: if the dividing line between the two ethics
is characterized more or less by concern (or lack thereof ) for the consequences of
any given action, then it must be assumed that the actor in question has had the
opportunity to consider (or refuse to consider) the potential consequences of his
actions. This assumption prompts Aron to observe that Weber has conflated two
different antinomies: political action vs. Christian action and considered decision
vs. immediate choice.11
Max Weber himself seems to have an ambiguous view of the reconcilability of
the two ethics. At fi rst, he states that the decisive point is that there are two “fun-
damentally different, irrevocably opposed maxims,” which are the two ethics.
He is, however, also quick to add that neither ethic implies the absolute absence
of the other; that is, the ethic of conviction is not equivalent to a lack of respon-
sibility, and the ethic of responsibility is not equivalent to a lack of conviction. In
this sense they are ideal types and therefore function as heuristic tools to acquire
a keener understanding of the inevitable trade-offs that characterize politics as a
vocation. Toward the end of the lecture, though, Weber declares that politics is
not conducted with the head alone; and at that point, it would seem that it is not
enough, as one might earlier have thought, for a politician to act according to
the ethic of responsibility, but that the true politician must combine both ethics.
More pointedly, the politician’s conviction must be not just sterile excitement
208 SCOTT N ELSON A N D JOSÉ COLEN
(sterile Aufgeregtheit), but real passion (echte Leidenschaft) for the responsibility that
defi nes political life. For Weber it is a stirring sight to behold a politically mature
man, “who feels with his whole soul the responsibility he bears for the real con-
sequences of his actions, and who acts on the basis of an ethics of responsibility,
[and] says at some point, ‘Here I stand, I can do no other.’ ”12
One scholar, Hans Henrik Bruun, believes that Weber was hereby indicat-
ing a third ethic that he has termed the “responsible ethic of conviction.”13 The
politician must act with a feeling of responsibility, but also with awareness of the
values he is preserving or destroying in acting thus. Lastly, he must acknowledge
two other inconvenient facts: once he has initiated the causal chain, he may bring
about consequences contrary to his intentions, and the causal chain cannot necessar-
ily be stopped at will once it has been set in motion. This all amounts to a very
heavy moral burden for the politician.
Politics presents aspiring officeholders with certain pitfalls. It can be all too
easy to enjoy the feeling of empowerment and let oneself be swept away by proj-
ects of self-aggrandizement as opposed to dedicating oneself fully to the task at
hand. Like the revolutionary syndicalist and the Christian pacifist, Weber feels
that the man who works in politics only to serve his own vanity is weak and unfit
for the role. What, then, should be the goal of the politician’s constant struggle?
Weber lays out a platter of viable political ends with the only stipulation being
that “some kind of belief must always be present,” but in his case at least, it is quite
clear that devotion to Germany and its national interest is supreme.14 He goes as
far as to open one of his political writings by plainly declaring that he has always
viewed all politics from the national perspective.15 Raymond Aron saw a pattern
in his political writings, in which there is a theoretical component with an analy-
sis of the eternal, current, and personal conditions of political action (this section
is full of antinomies such as means-ends, responsibility-conviction, etc.) and a
historical component that consists of judgments of the concrete historical data.
We can detect two major areas of concern that pervade Weber’s political
writings with respect to Germany’s national interest: the preparation of the rul-
ing elite and the civilizing role of German culture. The fi rst area is in domestic
politics and is related to the problem of the power vacuum caused by Bismarck’s
dismissal from politics in 1890 by Emperor Wilhelm II. Weber’s chief concern
was that Bismarck, in pursuing policies of economic development and the fi rst
modern welfare state, had also inadvertently spared his citizens from having to
worry about public affairs by hindering the power of the German parliament and
creating a stifl ing bureaucracy that was the only force that could step in to gov-
ern after Bismarck’s departure.16 In effect, Bismarck had left behind a politically
immature ruling class. In response, Weber called for a constitutional democ-
racy that would allow men with the aforementioned prerequisite characteristics
for political leadership to compete for office and use the bureaucratic entity as
a means to govern (where hitherto it had been in the driver’s seat of policy-
making). Nationalism was a force that could support a mass political party and
transcend the useless parliamentary squabbling of the time. The fatherland was
not just any old value among others, but rather one of the few serious (unlike the
vain pursuit of power), non-illusory, this-worldly (unlike Christianity) political
STAT E SM A N SH I P A N D ET H IC S 209
goals to which one could devote oneself.17 In his impassioned fury, Weber sought
out that charismatic Übermensch who would rescue Germany from Christian ser-
vility, revolutionary stupidity, and bureaucratic sterility.18
The second area concerns Germany’s prestige in Europe. Max Weber seems
to take it for granted that the international order is anarchic by nature and that
relations between nations are a function of the nations’ power. Indeed, as Aron
remarks, the closest Weber ever comes to a sociology of international relations is
in a few unfi nished pages of Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft.19 That the international
order is characterized by power relations between nation-states is hardly a sur-
prising conclusion for those of the realist school of international-relations theory.
One might fancy Weber’s pessimistic worldview as a type of realism; but Aron
is right in reminding us that it is unrealistic to see the world not as it is but as
one wants it to be, and therefore Weber’s conception of a world shaped solely by
savage power politics is just as far removed from reality as is the extreme idealist’s
view of the world.20
Where Weber’s conception of world politics sounds much more dated and
indubitably German is in his emphasis on the uniqueness of German culture.
The link between German grandeur and power and culture never seems very
rigorously defi ned—we do not suspect that it would have demanded a thorough,
theoretical treatment at the time. Power appears to be the means to German
grandeur, which has less to do with the triumph of force than with the spreading
of German culture. This propagation of German culture is made to be a moral
imperative that the German nation must shoulder in its capacity as a Machtstaat.
Germany is in turn a Machtstaat because it has 70 million people,21 and therefore
it is saddled with the inescapable obligation to throw its weight into the balance
(on behalf of its own people as well as the Danes, the Swiss, the Dutch, and the
Norwegians) and prevent world power from being divided “between the regula-
tions of Russian officials on the one hand and the conventions of English-speaking
‘society’ on the other, with perhaps a dash of Latin raison thrown in.”22
Max Weber’s political thought centers on nationalism, albeit a nationalism
that transcends state borders and encompasses greater cultural or ethnic wholes.
Aron also points out the liberal and imperialist currents in Weber’s thinking.23
As for the latter, he was not of the mission civilisatrice stripe, nor did he advo-
cate geopolitical speculation or the plunder of far-off lands for the sole purpose
of economic exploitation,24 but he did have certain imperialist ambitions, such
as maintaining military bases in locations as distant as Warsaw and having the
German army occupy Liège and Namur for some twenty years. 25 As for the for-
mer, a brief look at Weber’s liberal side might shed some light on the peculiarities
of the German situation at the time.26
Unlike liberalism elsewhere, in Germany, the liberal tradition was not rooted
in metaphysics or natural law. Weber was a liberal in that he valued the individual
as an autonomous cultural being, but he did not indulge the conceit of elevating
this preference to the level of a universal principle. The rationalistic liberalism of
the French Enlightenment and Revolution, bestowed upon all of humanity, was
quite foreign to German sentiments. Similarly, English utilitarianism confl icted
with Germany’s conception of the role of the state, and so it should come as no
210 SCOTT N ELSON A N D JOSÉ COLEN
surprise that the latter rejected the negative liberty of the former in favor of posi-
tive liberty. Because principles in general were something of an embarrassment,
German liberalism accepted the primacy of the pragmatism of power as a matter
of fact and consequently admitted only a liberalism of results. Weber would not
live long enough to see the destructive and nihilistic implications such a political
position could have; Aron, by contrast, had direct experience of the outcome.
Whether it concerned Weber’s stance on German domestic politics or his
feelings with regard to Germany’s position in Europe, he was steadfast in his
loyalty to the German national interest alone, with everything else serving an
instrumental purpose. It is for this reason that there is a conspicuous lack of
ideological justification in Weber’s political arguments.27 Any ideological jus-
tification would have to rely on the unstable foundation of an arbitrary value
whose very bias would diminish its scientific worth.28 The problem with using
German power and grandeur alone as the justification is interpreted brilliantly
by Aron when he asks, “if the nation’s power is the supreme value, regardless of
the nation’s culture, regardless of its leaders, regardless of the means employed,
then on what grounds can one say no to what Max Weber would have rejected
with horror?”29
And this is perhaps the great tragic irony in Weber’s position on world poli-
tics: he expected that Germany’s acquisition of power would promote German
culture and grandeur, though he never conceived of power in terms of national
prosperity, for instance, instead of force of arms, and therefore he never thought
that the naked pursuit of power could destroy the culture he desperately wished
to defend.30 This oversight is a consequence of a metaphysics rooted in struggle
and confl ict, at times Darwinian, at times Nietzschean.31
This vision of struggle penetrating every sphere of human activity pervades
Weber’s work, both political and scientific. Aron noticed that it was one of the
great faults of the German thinker’s impossible philosophy—whose foundation
lay in his irrefutable methodology—that he never considered that one could
reconcile one’s confl icting values.32 Indeed, for all of his pontificating against the
pacifists, there remains something curiously Christian about Weber’s insistence
that one must choose one’s god (or demon, for that matter), and not one’s gods.33
Once a man has chosen his value, he must never waver in his devotion. This
unwillingness to compromise is fitting for the seeker of truth, but not for the
politician.
This would not be the last time that Aron would engage with Weber’s mind
on the ethics of conviction and responsibility. In two unpublished courses he
gave at the Collège de France, Aron would explore the theory of political action;
and this would lead him to reexamine the antinomies of conviction and respon-
sibility, means and ends. It is to Aron’s later meditation on Weber’s work that we
now turn.
texts on political theory in spite of their being unfi nished, Raymond Aron
returns to Weber’s ideas and proceeds to a reinterpretation of the problem of
political morality.34 He begins by contrasting the approach of what a political
theory of action might be, with an analysis from an aerial perspective of inter-
state relations or political regimes. The latter describe systems or constitutions,
although not precisely in the legal but rather the sociological sense, as “sets of
rules under which a certain state functions” both domestically and international-
ly.35 But there is another approach to the political, which roughly corresponds to
what we would call policy, which seeks to examine the action of individuals, or
parties, or states, within those systems. Of this analysis of political behavior in a
strategic sense, “employing a range of means in accordance with a certain plan,”
or to achieve certain ends, we can fi nd models in Thucydides, Machiavelli or
Clausewitz. It is this analysis that often appears in the form of advice to princes—
how to win and how to succeed—and Aron calls it “praxeology” from Paix et
guerre onward. Political action has restrictions of its own, and its own efficacy
and internal logic.
In the fi rst of these courses, Aron comments on the arguments found in
Raymond Polin’s book, Ethique et politique. In this work, his colleague at the
Sorbonne argued that it was impossible to make separate judgments about means
and ends, since all techniques—including political technique—do not in them-
selves have an intrinsic moral significance, and are a mere assemblage of methods
to obtain a certain effect. A technique, as such, would be radically amoral if it
were not part of a human action. A human action is always performed in view
of certain ends, with which it forms a whole: “The use of a knife to cut meat is
a technique; it acquires a moral significance only when the knife is handled by a
butcher, a dinner-guest, a surgeon or a murderer.” According to Aron, Polin errs
in assuming that means cannot be evaluated both for their effectiveness and for
their ethical significance.
Polin’s approach is typical of moral consequentialism: human acts are not,
intrinsically, good or bad; they acquire a moral value depending on the results
and purposes sought. The author of the work further adds “the idea that there
may be a moral opposition between means and ends comes from the same con-
fusion; it is considered that a certain conduct may bring into play a purpose, or
means, which is not in agreement with them.” However, Polin does not help his
case any by concluding that “there is no confl ict between means and ends; there
is just an opposition between two conceptions of moral education, two global
conceptions of war,” in the end, two Weltanschauungen.
Raymond Aron presents and criticizes this position. He defends the legiti-
macy of evaluating means in themselves, an evaluation very distinct from that
of the legitimacy of the ends. It is true that the teleological calculation used
implicitly in the political technique of men endowed with free will implies the
assessment of possible effects. Aron gives an example, following the same line of
reasoning as Polin: “Does the knife, or the use of a knife, have a moral meaning,
an intrinsic moral value, when it is wielded by a soldier in the trenches? In other
words: what order of violence is it morally legitimate to use in war?” In war, we
are not just soldiers with a duty to overthrow the enemy; we also remain human
212 SCOTT N ELSON A N D JOSÉ COLEN
beings endowed with a sense of dignity and respect for others. Therefore, “even
in war there is the question of judging what is non-human, inhuman, what we
morally condemn, and what we do not morally condemn.” This is an issue that
the political philosopher cannot ignore. Is it indeed the case that the ends justify
the means? Even if the end is sublime, is it not the case that there might be a
“fundamental contradiction between what we ultimately want to achieve and
the means that we employ”?
Aron rejects two doctrines that he considers extreme. The fi rst is that “of cer-
tain moralists—and Maritain at times seemed to think along these lines—who
want to convince us that nothing good can ever come out of evil and that certain
means, obnoxious in themselves, always corrupt action and are not conducive to
achieving a valid end.”36 The other extreme is “the cynicism which suggests that
it is always the crueler or more radical means which are the most effective,” and
this also seems misplaced to him. In the end, Raymond Aron departs decisively
from Max Weber’s theory, explaining his previous hesitations and reservations.
The distinction between the ethic of responsibility and the ethic of conviction
led to numerous comments and had disturbed Aron for a long time because the
distinction had never given him complete satisfaction. He came to feel the flaw
was that Weber did not acknowledge that the ethic of conviction might incor-
porate both the absolute wish for certain ends, but also the absolute refusal to use
certain means.
The starting point for Aron’s own examination of the relationship between
morality and politics is instrumental thought. This instrumental thought is char-
acteristic of transitive action: “what we use, even without thinking, when it is a
question of achieving an end external to the action itself.”37 What he is investi-
gating is how a man of action evaluates his action, a man who wants to achieve
certain ends and employs certain means. The question is twofold: on the one
hand, how to defi ne the purpose, and, on the other, which means one has the
right to use.
According to Aron, the starting point for Max Weber is not the same, because
for him the ends are immediately given in world history. In his second course,
Aron explains his reinterpretation of Weber’s argument. This argument distin-
guishes between two types of ethics. The fi rst is an “ethic of personal perfec-
tion,” with a universal and timeless meaning, “subject as little as possible to
specific social institutions.” The second is an ethic “connected to the plurality of
values,” the roots of which are “the problems of action in this world,” not any
difficulty in determining the ends. The ends are written in activities themselves:
the wise man seeks the truth, the artist beauty. Only in the political field is there
a serious problem regarding the knowledge of values, or purposes, due to the
“historical condition of man.” Can the ends be easily determined in politics?
Even if they can, are the means that we employ in axiological agreement with
these ends?
It is true that, apart from these intrinsic difficulties of the political order, Max
Weber introduces a radical incompatibility between certain values, the contra-
diction between values, in which Aron does not believe and which does not
seem essential to him. This opposition between the ethic of personal perfection
STAT E SM A N SH I P A N D ET H IC S 213
and the difficulties of political action “is a truism that we must often repeat,
for the essence of the intellectual, humanist, and utopian is to refuse it,” and to
build models in which an ideal society and the moral and political conduct of a
person are in harmony. For Aron, there is no “pre-established harmony between
the determinism of world history and desires for value”; that is, progress does
not have to coincide with the good, and the trends of history do not imply the
creation of a human ideal. Nevertheless, he strives to reconcile the ethic of con-
viction and the ethic of responsibility, as the opposition between them does not
need to be radical. Thus, it is conviction that determines the choice of ends to
which one is responsible.
Secondly, the ethic of conviction also implies the “unconditional refusal
to employ certain means.” Since Weber often uses the aphorism “each person
chooses his own god or demon,” he authorizes or at least suggests an interpreta-
tion of his philosophy as being a “decisionist or, to be strict, nihilistic” philoso-
phy, in which “determining the purposes completely escapes rational argument,”
and so the ends become a mere arbitrary choice. Raymond Aron chooses not
to interpret Weber in this way. For him, above or beyond the political decision
in terms of consequences, the German sociologist strives to preserve an ethical
sphere, which in itself has its own reward and motivation.
Instead, in the lectures of these courses, Aron reviews the distinction between
the two meanings of Weber’s ethics, a distinction rendered very mild and very
different from the traditional distinction: on the one hand, “a morality that is
simply defi ned by the Sermon on the Mount or Kantian morality,” to “obey the
unconditional imperative of Christianity not to resort to violence,” to “obey
the law out of respect for the law, without worrying about one’s own interest or
worrying about the consequences”; and, on the other hand, a worldly examina-
tion of the consequences of action in the political realm: “If we want to, we can
translate a morality of personal perfection into the language of means and ends,
but I think that this would be a falsification of the psycho-moral meaning of
ethical behavior; ethical conduct so conceived has no other purpose than to obey
a divine imperative or a human law.”
always go hand-in-hand, and justice and the common good have many meanings
in a society divided into rival groups. Perhaps this idea can be translated into
what Isaiah Berlin calls the “uncombinability” or complexity of moral goods,
transposed into the public domain. Finally, human ends are not always incom-
patible, nor are they a mere matter of preference, even if the idea of humanity
underlying the “reconciliation of all the political ends that can be proposed in an
ideal regime” is nothing but a regulatory idea, an idea of Reason in the Kantian
sense.
The essence of politics thus consists of the tensions between the exigencies
of the moment, the political morality that seeks to accommodate the citizens’
private moralities, and the statesman’s own private moralities (some of which
are reconcilable with each other, some of which are not), that exist both within
and between human beings. The great statesman is he who can navigate his way
through this stormy sea of uncertainty—knowing full well that many of his
decisions will leave him little-to-no time for reflection and therefore be based
entirely on political knack—and arrive at the action that is, given the circum-
stances, the least detestable both for himself and for the collectivity.
In any case, both Raymond Aron and Max Weber were more spectateurs enga-
gés than they were statesmen, even if they did possess Weber’s three aforemen-
tioned necessary qualities for politicians: passion, feeling of responsibility, and
sense of proportion. Aron nevertheless doubted that his character was resilient
enough to carry out some of the unpleasant but nevertheless necessary tasks that
politicians must sometimes perform. 38 Weber knew that his inability to com-
promise made him a poor match for the political life.39 He could never commit
himself fully to his views grounded in power politics because he had a feeling
of responsibility to values even greater than German grandeur. Aron, too, saw
beyond the nation and was an early and ardent supporter of Franco-German
reconciliation right after the war, when that was the last thing to be expected
from a French Jew. In the war of the gods, and in spite of it all, they sided with
liberty, nobility, and truth.
Notes
1. See Raymond Aron, Mémoires: Edition intégrale inédite, Paris, Editions Robert
Laffont, 2010 [1983], 102.
2. See Franciszek Draus, “La philosophie sociale de Raymond Aron,” PhD diss.,
École des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales, 1981, 9.
3. Aron, Mémoires, 105–106.
4. See Raymond Aron, La Sociologie allemande contemporaine, Paris, Quadrige, 2007
[1935], 81. The relevant pages from this work are 82 and 102–110.
5. See Raymond Aron, Les Étapes de la pensée sociologique, Paris, Gallimard, 2011
[1967]), 21.
6. See Ibid., 315; Raymond Aron, “Max Weber and Modern Social Science,” trans.
Charles Krance, in Franciszek Draus (ed.), History, Truth, Liberty: Selected Writings
of Raymond Aron, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1985, 336.
7. See Ralf Dahrendorf, afterword to Politik als Beruf, by Max Weber, Stuttgart,
Reclam, 1992, 85–86, 89, 92–93.
STAT E SM A N SH I P A N D ET H IC S 215
8. Max Weber, “Politik als Beruf,” in Johannes Winckelmann (ed.), Gesammelte poli-
tische Schriften, Tübingen, J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) Verlag, 1988 [1919], 506.
The relevant pages from this work are 545–552 and 558–559.
9. See Aron, “Max Weber and Modern Social Science,” 349–350.
10. See Aron, Les Étapes, 528.
11. See Raymond Aron, “Max Weber et la politique de puissance,” in Raymond
Aron, Les Étapes de la pensée sociologique, Paris, Gallimard, 654.
12. Max Weber, “The Profession and Vocation of Politics,” in Peter Lassman and
Ronald Speirs (eds.), Weber: Political Writings, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 2000 [1994], 367.
13. See Hans Henrik Bruun, Science, Values and Politics in Max Weber’s Methodology,
Hampshire, Ashgate, 2007 [1972], Loc. 7956, 7978, and 1407, Kindle.
14. Weber, “The Profession and Vocation of Politics,” 355.
15. See Max Weber, “Deutschland unter den europäischen Weltmächten,” in
Johannes Winckelmann (ed.), Gesammelte Politische Schriften, Tübingen, J.C.B.
Mohr (Paul Siebeck) Verlag, 1988 [1919], 157.
16. See Sven Eliaeson, “Constitutional Caesarism: Weber’s politics in their German
context,” in Stephen Turner (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Weber, New York,
Cambridge University Press, 2000, 134–135; Tracy B. Strong, Politics without
Vision, London, University of Chicago Press, 2012, 115; Max Weber, “Parlament
und Regierung im neugeordneten Deutschland,” in Johannes Wicnkelmann
(ed.), Gesammelte politische Schriften, Tübingen, J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) Verlag,
1988 [1919], 311–320.
17. See Stephen Turner, introduction to The Cambridge Companion to Weber, 17.
18. See H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills, introduction to From Max Weber, by Max
Weber, Oxon, Routledge, 2009 [1948], 43.
19. See Aron, “Max Weber et la politique de puissance,” 645; Max Weber, Wirtschaft
und Gesellschaft: Grundriß der verstehenden Soziologie, ed. Johannes Winckelmann,
Tübingen, J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), 2009 [1921], 520–530.
20. See Aron, “Max Weber et la politique de puissance,” 643.
21. See Weber, “Deutschland unter den europäischen Weltmächten,” 176.
22. Max Weber, “Between Two Laws,” in Peter Lassman and Ronald Speirs (eds.),
Weber: Political Writings, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2000 [1994],
76.
23. See Aron, “Max Weber et la politique de puissance,” 644.
24. See Paolo Armellini, “Max Weber: scienza e realismo politico,” in Giovanni
Dessì and Maria Pia Paternò (eds.), Il realismo politico e la modernità, Rome, Edizioni
Nuova Cultura, 2012 [2005], 71.
25. See Gerth and Mills, From Max Weber, 39.
26. See Eliaeson, “Constitutional Caesarism,” 136–139.
27. See Aron, “Max Weber et la politique de puissance,” 647.
28. See Max Weber, Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, ed. Johannes
Winckelmann, Tübingen, J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) Verlag, 1988 [1922].
29. Aron, “Max Weber et la politique de puissance,” 655.
30. See Ibid., 656. For a contrasting view see Bruun, Science, Values and Politics in Max
Weber’s Methodology, Loc. 1316.
31. See Aron, “Max Weber et la politique de puissance,” 650; Max Weber, “Der
Nationalstaat und die Volkswirtschaftspolitik,” in Johannes Winckelmann (ed.),
Gesammelte politische Schriften, Tübingen, J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) Verlag, 1988
[1919], 14.
216 SCOTT N ELSON A N D JOSÉ COLEN
32. See Aron, “Max Weber and Modern Social Science,” 371–372.
33. See Max Weber, “Wissenschaft als Beruf,” in Johannes Winckelmann (ed.),
Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, Tübingen, J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck)
Verlag, 1988 [1919] 609; Carlo Antoni, Dallo storicismo alla sociologia, Firenze, G.
C. Sansoni, 1940, 142–143.
34. Both texts are posthumous and only summaries by Aron, which were published
in the Collège de France Annuaries, but the texts are at BNF, Manuscrits, NAF 28060
(024) and NAF 28060 (027).
35. See Raymond Aron, Théorie de l´action politique, Bibliothèque Nationale de France,
Manuscrits, NAF 28060 (024), Leçon 1, f l. 2. The relevant sections of this course
for the following discussion on Raymond Polin, Ethique et politique, Paris, Sirey,
1968, are Leçon 1, f ls. 3–4, 12, Leçon 6, f ls. 5–7, 10–11, 21–24, and Leçon 7, f l.
3.
36. Regarding the controversy with Maritain, see Raymond Aron, Machiavel et les
tyrannies modernes, ed. Rémy Freymond, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 1993, 367–378,
405–416. See also Serge Audier, Machiavel, conflit et liberté, Paris, Editions EHESS,
2005, 73–87.
37. Raymond Aron, Jeux et enjeux de la politique, BNF, Manuscrits, NAF 28060 (027)
Leçon 2 from 15–01–1974, f l. 1. The relevant sections of this course for the
remainder of this chapter are Leçon 3, f ls. 5–9, 12–13, and Leçon 4, f ls. 3–5,
9–10.
38. See Raymond Aron, Le Spectateur engagé. Entretiens avec Jean-Louis Missika et
Dominique Wolton, Paris, Julliard,1981, 303.
39. See Eliaeson, “Constitutional Caesarism,” 131.
CHAPTER 16
Sylvie Mesure
his Mémoires, again, Aron said that “instead of summary presentations of Marxist
thought, instead of polemics against the Parisian Marxisms,” he would have pre-
sented “a synthetic analysis, not of the Marxist thought, but of various tenden-
cies of that thought, the origin of the historical movements that call themselves
Marxist.” 7 In this respect, the volume that appeared under the title The Marxism
of Marx indeed constitutes a sketch of the missing book,8 since from the very fi rst
page Aron describes his project like a scholarly study, both philosophical and
historical, of Marx’s thought. Moreover, it is clear at the outset that this is not an
attempt to state the whole truth about Marx, but to offer a solid and well-argued
interpretation, capable of both highlighting the complexity of his thought as
well as making intelligible the plurality of levels of analysis and of interpretations
presented by others.
This was an interpretive challenge for Aron, who was aware of the difficul-
ties in undertaking a task strongly related to the ambiguities of Marx’s work.9
However, whatever makes the analysis of the work of Marx as a scholar, man of
action, and prophet a difficult task, is, at the same time, its charm. Aron never
hid that he was fascinated, as well as put off, by the thought of “one who is both
scientific and revolutionary: revolutionary in the name of science and scientific
in the name of the Revolution,”10 to the point of having dedicated a substantial
part of his life to it. In Main Currents of Sociological Thought, he also does not hesi-
tate to say that he owes nothing in his intellectual training to the influence of
Montesquieu or Tocqueville, but almost everything to Marx.
This permanent confrontation with Marx began in Introduction to the Philosophy
of History, which is largely directed against dogmatic philosophies of history,
including Marxism. Aron developed his major theses on the limits of histori-
cal knowledge. I will present the major analysis of Introduction with regard to
Marxism and will then show how, in the course of time, the Aronian interpreta-
tion of Marxism was enriched and deepened, while remaining true to its original
interpretive schema.
Aron would not reassess this critical statement formulated in 1938.18 It is con-
sequently deployed in his course at the Sorbonne with all its argumentative force.
But it is no longer a question here, as it was in 1930, of an existential quest by
a young man trying to ground his political decisions on sound knowledge and
to engage history in a certain way (when only probability is our lot). Nor it is a
question, as in the 1950s, of carrying out an ideological critique of secular reli-
gions. It is the work of a teacher, questioning texts, raising translation problems,
flushing out misinterpretations, thinking along with his audience, and delivering
his personal interpretation of an “ambiguous and inexhaustible” work.19 Thus,
the tone is set; the project is a “scholarly” analysis of Marx.
determinism repelled them, in the speculations of the young Marx they found the
secret of an ‘ultimate’ Marxism that Marx believed he had overcome at thirty.”33
In the lectures at the Sorbonne, it is also on the incomplete and uneven char-
acter of Marx’s work that Aron bases his argument.
Marx’s early texts indeed have the character of an unfi nished work because
only The Holy Family (1845), The Poverty of Philosophy (1847) and two articles, one
on the “Jewish Question,” (1843), and the other bearing the title “Introduction
to the Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right” (1844)
were published during Marx’s lifetime ; while, as Aron says, “the two books that
are perhaps today considered the most important ones from this early period,
namely the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts, written by Marx in Paris in 1844,
and German Ideology, written in 1846–1847, essential works for understanding
Marx’s intellectual itinerary, were published in full only from 1932 onwards.”34
However, Marx’s work is also unfi nished at the end of his journey because Marx
never came to grips with his critique of political economy, of which only the
fi rst book of Capital was published in 1867. In an important article, Michael R.
Krätke,35 taking stock of the various versions of Marx’s larger project, empha-
sizes that we have no less than four or five versions of the Critique of Political
Economy and that even after the publication of Book I of Capital, Marx never
stopped working on Books II and III, which remained in manuscript form and
were published posthumously by Engels.
The unfi nished nature of the work, therefore, but also the non-homogeneous
nature of the corpus, invites interpretative caution: as observed by Aron, many of
Marx’s writings remained in manuscript form, and there is a huge gap between
mere working notes for research and the publication in book form as approved by
the author. “There is a fundamental difference for all authors, including Marx,”
Aron pointedly explained, “between a fi nished and published manuscript, druck-
reif, as they say in German, and a manuscript kept among one’s papers because
one feels that it is not fully developed and worth reading. Now, Marxology and
even Marxist thought speculate indefi nitely on any fragment from Marx’s youth
which Marx himself, who was not entirely incompetent on the subject, thought
was unworthy of publication. Quasi-religious respect can sometimes go too far,
even in science.”36
We can see that Aron takes issue against any interpretation that would make
the young Marx a consistent thinker, who could be mobilized against the second
Marx or even overvalued to the point of providing new insights into the mature
Marx. This runs counter to any interpretation considering the 1844 Manuscript
the fi nal stage of Marx’s thought. The Parisian Manuscript does not constitute
one of Marx’s completed works, but the result of a posthumous compilation
(1932) of a set of texts not intended for publication: lecture notes and extracts
developed in different workbooks.37 Aron noted that, if this was an important
text—and perhaps the most important among the early works of Marx 38 because
it articulates for the fi rst time both his philosophy and economics and, therefore,
attempts a synthesis between Hegelian German philosophy and English political
economy—even so, it was no more than a step along the long road to Capital.
Analyzing Marx’s ideas in 1844, he wrote: “I would first like to repeat that no
A RON A N D M A R X I S M 223
one has the right to consider this unfi nished manuscript the fi nal stage of Marx’s
thought. It has never been published and he completely lost interest in it after
writing it.”39
However, against Althusser, Aron argues that restricting Marx’s work to Capital
is akin to betraying him. Here we only discuss the principles of the Aronian crit-
icism of Althusser because we seek mainly to highlight the interpretive principles
employed by Aron in his reading of Marx. In the same way as it is impossible
to do without reading Histoire et dialectique de la violence if we wish to understand
the subtlety of the Aronian critique of Sartre’s Marxified humanism, we can-
not dispense with reading Essai sur les marxismes imaginaires if we want to be
aware of the magnitude of the charge brought against Althusser’s “structuralist
mystification.”40 The latter, in search of a scientific Marxism, not a philosophi-
cal or ideological one, introduced an epistemological break between the young
Marx, heir to Hegel, and the Marx of Capital. Aron vigorously denounces the
relevance of such a break, which seems to go against Marx’s own intentions.41
For the Marx of Capital, the scientist, the economist, is also the same one who
used Critique of Political Economy as a subtitle to his book and did not abandon the
Promethean ambitions of his youth: Marx’s Marxism began with a critique of
religion, arrived at a critique of law and politics, and then extended this critique
to the economic field. Aron was astonished that such an obvious fact was not
perceived in full scope by others: “What I reproach almost all interpreters for
is that they do not hold the two ends of the chain and do not see that in Marx’s
thought there is an organic unity between the economic reasoning and the phil-
osophical and historical meaning of this reasoning. I repeat: the condition for this
synthesis is the notion of a critique of political economy, i.e., the simultaneous
critique of reality and of the awareness of our grasp of it.”42 Therefore, “if we
agree to think as Marx himself did,” the reconciliation between the two stages
of his work is not mysterious. Moreover, the unveiling of the synthetic unity
of Marx’s Marxism made possible by the concept of “criticism” invalidates the
symmetrical and inverse interpretations of Sartre and Althusser: it is impossible
to interpret Marxism as a humanism free of economism, and also impossible to
see it as a structuralism purified of all humanism. Returning in his Mémoires to
Althusser’s break, Aron writes, “As part of Marxology, Louis Althusser’s argu-
ment does not stand up even for a moment when compared with the reading
of the texts. The Grundrisse of 1857–1858 are steeped in Hegelianism. Marx
reread Hegel’s Logic before writing Capital. Indefensible as a historical thesis,
the notion of an epistemological break points to the ambiguity of Marx’s own
philosophy, closer, depending on the moment and on his mood, to either Hegel’s
version or Althusser’s. The strength of Marxism is, in part at least, this ambigu-
ity. The theory of profit is the basis of that of exploitation (inherent unfairness
of the exchange economy) and that of alienation (things come between people).
Marxist economics is simultaneously a moral criticism and an existential one.”43
As opposed to the unilateral readings of a Sartre or an Althusser, Aron’s inter-
pretation of Marx therefore tries to “hold together the two ends of the chain,”
as Marx conceived his own thought. This means understanding what leads him
to this fi nal stage but also what prepares what follows. It means following a
224 S Y LV I E M E S U R E
Understanding Capital
But to understand Marx is also to understand Capital. In this second part of the
course, devoted to Capital, Aron’s interpretation is enriched compared to the
analysis of Introduction to the Philosophy of History. Aron does not abandon his core
critical argument or the denunciation of the explosive synthesis of necessity and
freedom—in other words, the uncertain combination of two contradictory log-
ics, the logic of human action and the logic of capital47—but he intends not only
to understand but also to evaluate the economic thought of Marx. In his Mémoires
Aron states that he did not in the 1930s have “enough economic knowledge to
understand and judge Capital.”48
Understanding and evaluating Capital is therefore Aron’s program, and he
warned his audience that such an analysis could not be without value judgments:
“The second part of this course will be naturally uncertain, more open to criti-
cism than the fi rst one. Because for me it will be much more difficult, in this
section, to distinguish a mere exposition from an effort to interpret and from
a discussion that is as honest as possible. In the case of Capital, it is impossible
to provide an interpretation that does not simultaneously include a judgment
of the economic or philosophical value of the book. I’m sorry. I would have
loved to completely separate both types of consideration, as it was possible in the
A RON A N D M A R X I S M 225
fi rst part, where I was just trying to explain how Marx became Marxist based
on Hegelianism, but, when we study the economic part of Capital, it is inevi-
table that any interpretation I attempt to suggest will seem laden with judgments
about the value and the scope of Capital.”49
The professor’s analysis in this part of the course thus follows the fi rst Book
of Capital (Chapter 3), which develops the theory of value, and later focuses on
Book 3 (Chapter 12), where Marx tries to go from value to price. It demonstrates
that his program is certainly a critique of political economy, that is, a critique
of economic reality and of the consciousness that reflects it (critique of classical
political economy and critique of vulgar economics, to use Marx’s words). It also
shows how the logic of Capital is a process unveiling the essence of capitalism, the
only way to account for the phenomenal reality and its contradictions. Aron puts
forward a meticulous explanation of the key concepts of Capital: merchandise
and its value, exchange, the notion of surplus value linked to exploitation and
profit, the tendency for profit rates to fall, which must lead capitalism, in its fi nal
phase of antagonism between production forces and production relationships, to
self-destruction. We would refer the reader here to the corresponding passages
in the course for a more detailed examination of the Aronian interpretation.
What does Aron as a sociologist consider necessary to take from Capital—the
distinction between essence and phenomena? This is totally outdated for mod-
ern economists who only work on the basis of the numerical manipulation of
phenomenal reality.50 The theory of surplus value? It is false.51 The theory of the
falling rate of profit? It is not supported by the facts and does not make it possible
to demonstrate the necessary trend toward fi nal catastrophe.52 The project of
deducing the laws of historical development from a logical sequence of abstract
categories? An unachievable and unrealistic project considered doomed since
Introduction to the Philosophy of History. Understanding Marx as he understood
himself also means understanding the history of a failure: Marx failed in Capital
to fi nd a scientific basis for his theory of the collapse of capitalism.53 He failed to
theoretically explain the movement of history.54
What is left in Capital? This was the decisive question when Aron gave his
course, during the Cold War, in an era dominated by strong ideological and
political tensions between East and West—a bold question in this context! As
usual, Aron answers in a clear and nuanced manner, without the rigidity of
unambiguous positions and a sterile logic of “tout ou rien” (all or nothing). Before
discussing what he retains from Marx, we shall begin by noting what he fiercely
condemns.
Aron found in Marx, and rejects totally, the idea of a radical critique of capi-
talism, one with no leftovers, which is presented as an external criticism, since
it evaluates the capitalist system by comparing it to a social state, radically dif-
ferent in kind, where man, after a necessary evolution, will fulfi ll his vocation.
For Marxism in fact, capitalism is “condemned for its injustice” because it is
based on exploitation, just as it is “condemned to death” because of its contra-
dictions.55 Moral condemnation is coupled here with theoretical condemnation,
which explains the immense seductive power of Marxism, which the young Aron
himself had difficulty escaping, as he confesses in a lecture in 1968: “How can
226 S Y LV I E M E S U R E
one resist the seduction of such a system where science shows that necessity will
handle the execution of the verdicts of consciousness? Capitalism sentenced to
death not for but by its inherent unfairness. When I read Capital for the fi rst time,
I passionately wanted to be convinced; my wishes, alas! remained unfulfi lled.”56
However, the Aronian criticism of Marxism is not a complete demolition
since it discerns a partial truth (une part de vérité) by asking the legitimate ques-
tion of social justice.57 Noting the gap between the great principles of liberty
and equality, on which democratic systems are based, and the real inequalities
that remain, Aron was never himself tempted by political inaction and conser-
vatism. In An Essay on Freedom, published in 1966, after contrasting Tocqueville
and Marx, he does not hesitate to say in conclusion that “We are all Marxists
in the sense that we believe that men are responsible for circumstances and that
they must change circumstances when they deprive certain individuals of the
resources regarded as indispensable to a decent life.”58 Aron bases his reformism
on this legacy of Marxism.59 For him, the man who does not expect a miracu-
lous solution from a bloody revolution does not necessarily resign himself to
the unjustifiable. His reformism was as different from revolutionary activism
as it was from the quietism (and conservatism) of “laissez-faire” economics. He
upholds a liberalism that confronts and indeed opposes the neo-liberalism of
Hayek, about which he wrote in 1961 a critical and uncompromising review.
In his article “The Liberal Defi nition of Freedom,” centered on a discussion
of Hayek’s book The Constitution of Liberty (1960), Aron emphasizes the impor-
tance of the liberal defi nition of freedom understood as “negative liberty,” as
“freedom as independence” or “freedom as non-prohibition,” but he also shows
its limits and insists, in the vein of a young Marx denouncing formal freedoms
in the name of real freedoms, on the need to articulate a “positive” defi nition,
conceived as an “effective capacity for freedom.” In this search for a possible syn-
thesis between political rights and entitlements,60 which we can also fi nd in his
1968 text “Sociological Thought and Human Rights,” dedicated to the analysis
of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights of 1848, we can see how deeply
Marx impregnates Aron’s thinking.
The relation between Aron and Marx is complex, a mix of distance and close-
ness. Closeness in the attention to the element of truth in the Marxist critique
of capitalism, which throws light on the unique nature of Aronian liberalism.61
But there is also a considerable distance between Aron and Marx owing to the
former’s denial of millenarianism and the “catastrophic optimism” that goes with
it.62 If the critique of capitalist democracies is legitimate in Aron’s eyes, it can
only remain so if it renounces revolutionarism, the unrealistic and dangerous
ambition of fully achieving social justice here and now, and if it keeps the idea
of social justice as a regulatory ideal (in Kant’s sense), guiding political action
concerned with the common good.
Aron was indeed too aware of the tragedies of the twentieth century to sub-
scribe to any revolutionary romanticism, even when he was speaking for the
West under the banner of progressivism and modernity. With courage and tenac-
ity, he evaluated the distance between the ideal of brotherhood proclaimed by
Marxism and the monstrous reality it created. Understanding Marx’s Marxism is
A RON A N D M A R X I S M 227
also to understand what led to the denial and the reversal of the ideals he claimed.
It is beyond Marx, and therefore better than Marx, to understand the theoretical
and practical implications that can be drawn from his thought.
Notes
1. On Raymond Aron’s “Marxism,” see also Max Likin, “ ‘Nothing Fails Like
Success’: The Marxism of Raymond Aron,” French Politics, Culture and Society, vol.
26, no. 3, Winter 2008, 43–60, who tackles the subject from a more historic point
of view, and D. J. Mahoney, “Aron, Marx, and Marxism: An Interpretation,”
European Journal of Political Theory, vol. 2, no. 4, 2003, 415–427.
2. Raymond Aron, Le Marxisme de Marx, Préface et notes par Jean-Claude Casanova
et Christian Bachelier, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 2002, 33.
3. A summary of this course appeared in the journal Le Débat, January 1984, no. 28,
18–29.
4. Jean-Jacques Salomon, “Marx vu par Aron. A propos du marxisme de Marx,”
Futuribles, no. 293, janvier 2004.
5. See Raymond Aron, Memoirs: Fifty Years of Political Reflection, New York and
London, Holmes & Meier, 1990, 468: “I doubt that I still have the time to write
this essay, sketched in my 1976–77 lecture course at the Collège de France. It
would fill an empty space in the body of my writings. But, all things considered,
the loss does not seem to me to be serious, even for me.”
228 S Y LV I E M E S U R E
6. Ibid., 468.
7. Ibid., 435.
8. We should also mention the chapter of Main Currents of Sociological Thought dedi-
cated to Marx, which constitutes an important link in Aron’s analysis.
9. See Le Marxisme de Marx where Aron writes: “I think there is no doctrine so
grandiose in its ambiguity and ambiguous in its grandeur.”
10. Aron, Le Marxisme de Marx, 607.
11. On the young Aron see notably Jean-François Sirinelli, “Raymond Aron avant
R. Aron (1923–1933),” Vingtième Siècle. Revue d’histoire, vol. 2, no. 2, 1984, 15–30,
as well as Nicolas Baverez, Raymond Aron: un moraliste au temps des idéologies, Paris,
Flammarion, 2005.
12. Aron, Memoirs, 40–41.
13. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire: Essai sur les limites de
l’objectivité historique, nouvelle éd. revue et annotée par Sylvie Mesure, Paris,
Gallimard, 1986 [originally 1938], 448. See, also, Raymond Aron, Thinking
Politically: A Liberal in the Age of Ideology, Transaction, 1997, 41: “When I chose
my intellectual itinerary, when I decided to be both an observer of, and an actor
in, history, I began by studying Marx, in particular Das Kapital. I hoped to find
a true philosophy of history that would provide the incomparative advantage of
teaching us simultaneously that which is and that which ought to be.”
14. Ibid.
15. Aron, Memoirs, 85.
16. Ferdinand Tönnies, Karl Marx. Sa vie et son œuvre, traduction et présentation par
Sylvie Mesure, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2012 [originally 1921],
132–133.
17. Aron, Le Marxisme de Marx, 74.
18. Sylvie Mesure, Raymond Aron et la raison historique, Paris, Vrin, 1984.
19. Raymond Aron, D’une Sainte Famille à l’autre. Essai sur les marxismes imaginaires,
Paris, Gallimard, 1969, 277.
20. See also Raymond Aron, Main Currents in Sociological Thought, vol. 1, Transaction,
1998, 161: “When Marx analyzed value, exchange, exploitation, surplus value,
and profit, he wanted to be a pure economist, and he would not have dreamed
of justifying some scientifically inaccurate or questionable statement by invok-
ing a philosophical intent. Marx took science seriously, and I think we must do
likewise.”
21. Aron, Le Marxisme de Marx, 73.
22. Ibid., 20.
23. Ibid., 31.
24. Ibid., 595.
25. Ibid., 449.
26. Ibid., 23.
27. Ibid.
28. Ibid., 31.
29. On the ideological atmosphere in France at that time, see Pietro Chiodi, Sartre
and Marxism, Sussex, Harvester Press, 1976 [1965]; William S. Lewis, Louis
Althusser and the Tradition of French Marxism, Lanham, MD, Lexington Books,
2005; Emmanuel Barot (dir.), Sartre et le marxisme, Paris, La Dispute, 2011.
30. Roberto Nigro, “La question de l’anthropologie dans l’interprétation althusséri-
enne de Marx,” in Jean-Claude Bourdin (dir.), Althusser: une lecture de Marx, Paris,
Presses universitaires de France, 2008, 103–104.
31. Aron, D’une Sainte Famille à l’autre, 75.
A RON A N D M A R X I S M 229
62. Raymond Aron, Thinking Politically: A Liberal in the Age of Ideology, New Brunswick,
NJ, Transaction, 1997 [originally 1981], 157.
63. Friedrich Schleiermacher, Hermeneutics and Criticism, Berlin, G. Reimer, 1838.
64. Christian Berner, La Philosophie de Schleiermacher, Paris, Ed. du Cerf, 1995, 78.
65. Aron, Memoirs, 468–469.
66. Ibid., 414.
CHAPTER 17
“MODERATE MACHIAVELLIANISM”:
ARON, MACHIAVELLI, AND THE MODERN
MACHIAVELLIANS
R aymond Aron did not write very much on Machiavelli. Moreover, he did
not especially appreciate what he had written on that subject, as he con-
fessed, 40 years later: “when the war came, I was working on . . . a study on
Machiavelli, from which only about thirty pages survived. They are not worth
much. The knowledge I had of Machiavelli was insufficient.”1 However, beyond
a first text strictly focused on Machiavelli’s thought, the study that Aron men-
tions included three other essays, adding up to more than one hundred pages,
focusing, on the whole, on what the author calls “modern Machiavellianism.”
It would have been part of a book, as Aron says, that he intended to finish.
Unfortunately, in 1940, when Germany occupied France and he went into exile
in London, he gave up that project and published those pages, which eventually
came to light only posthumously.2
More than a hermeneutic approach to Machiavelli’s writings, in that project,
Aron aims to understand the phenomenon of Machiavellianism, which he sees
as a kind of government that resorts to any means and ignores all values, caring
about nothing but the success of political decisions. This phenomenon is usu-
ally termed tyranny. All over history, long before Machiavelli, there have been
frequent examples of such a way of ruling, and it may be seen, once again, in
the totalitarian regimes of the twentieth century. Aron reads Machiavelli “as a
contemporary of Hitler, Stalin and Mussolini,” in order “to look for the secret of
Machiavellianism.”3 According to him, whenever tyranny arises, Machiavellianism
comes into question, and far from being its creator, Machiavelli is just one more
witness of an oft-observed political practice. Machiavellianism, at least from
Aron’s perspective, is not exactly synonymous with Machiavelli’s thought.
Why is the name of the author of The Prince used to label a phenomenon appar-
ently as old as politics? The answer is easy to fi nd if one reads Machiavelli’s work.
232 DIO G O PI R E S AU R É L IO
In fact, besides the boldness of his contentions, he framed the different aspects of
Machiavellianism in a coherent theory. Boldly, he put into words a well-known
set of political techniques and simultaneously presented a method through which
some regularity can be found in the diversity of human actions, both individual
and collective, thus providing some efficient resources to whoever leads or wants
to lead a group. The method consists of several rules, explained in The Prince,
chapter 15, which are based on the observation of facts; that is, on what men
really do and are, not on speculation about what they should be or do. In essence,
it does not differ from the epistemological principles that several historians and
sociologists of the late nineteenth century would adopt in their scientific prac-
tice. Vilfredo Pareto, for instance, calls it the “logico-experimental method,”
expressly assuming Machiavelli’s heritage and largely sharing the way the lat-
ter thought about man and society. As Aron says, commenting on Pareto, “the
same themes, the same method, the same historical view, the same conception of
politics, lead us to an art of ruling which is similar to that of Machiavelli.”4 No
wonder the book that Aron intended to write attached the utmost importance
to this follower of Machiavelli, who is said to have inspired Mussolini’s fascism.
Furthermore, this makes clear both the structure of the four posthumous essays,
in which Pareto plays a main role, and the reason Aron gives for not starting
the work with a history of Machiavellianism: “That history has been written
several times . . . So it will be enough to bring Machiavelli closer to the most
Machiavellian modern theorist to describe the doctrine whose consequences in
the present situation I will try to follow.”5
This does not mean that Machiavelli himself is a minor character in Aron’s
work. On the contrary, Aron’s reading of Machiavelli, starting from the mean-
ing of Machiavellianism as it is understood by the main historians in the fi rst half
of the twentieth century, casts a new light on both The Prince and the Discourses
on Livy. First of all, it reveals the undeniable yet complicated gap between the
Machiavellian text and its current interpretation; secondly, it will enable Aron to
diverge from Pareto and to present a new theory of the democratic regime.
expensive and so not pay. As Machiavelli says, “there are two ways of fighting:
by law or by force.”16 In the abstract, it is not possible to refuse either of them,
and everything can become a useful means. Religion, for instance, is one of the
best means of maintaining power. All the leaders in history have recommended
it, not because it is true or false, but just because it is the best way to reinforce
obedience and maintain social order and power.
Power for what? To maintain power. The fi rst purpose of power is to main-
tain itself, that is, to endure. Machiavelli also values the prosperity of the city, as
is underlined by Aron. However, this prosperity is not synonymous with com-
mon welfare. A prosperous city in Machiavelli’s sense is a city strong enough to
remain independent, that is to say a powerful city, be it a republic or a principal-
ity. Power does not have any goal or any meaning beyond itself. On the contrary,
every human activity can become a means to obtain and maintain power. This
lack of a transcendent purpose to political action is the main difference between
Machiavelli and every thinker since antiquity, even in humanist culture both
before and after the Florentine. Is it a distinctive belief or a logical deduction from
the principle according to which science must refuse to incorporate transcendent
or metaphysical goals—what men should be—and restrict itself to reality? Aron,
following the common interpretation that credits Machiavelli with the founda-
tion of political science, states that it is nothing but a realistic conclusion made by
“a fanatic of abstract logic.”17 Accepting only facts and working within a logical-
deductive epistemology, Machiavelli would be obliged to put aside his personal
values. Such an epistemology, by undermining the relevance of his convictions,
made people read his work as a simple theory of means, whose aim is nothing
but power. Therefore, “there is a risk of Machiavellianism spreading when it no
longer works for public greatness, but only for individual ventures.”18
violence will always be necessary, for communism they will disappear after the
achievement of a classless society. Until then, “the prince has no doubts that he is
working for truth when he is lying, and for a happy humanity when he is impos-
ing a realm of terror.”26
Later on, Aron would appreciate Pareto’s sociological doctrine from a notice-
ably different perspective.27 But even in his fi rst essays, he already showed
Machiavelli’s influence. Aron makes two objections to Machiavellians, clearly
inspired by the Florentine himself: the fi rst is the impossibility of identifying
politics as simply a collection of techniques; the second is the ambiguous char-
acter of modern tyranny, which on the one hand seems to be a regime, that is,
a juridical order and a system of government with a stabilized set of procedures,
but whose head, on the other hand, rules in a discretionary way, beyond any rule
or rational ground.
Pareto differs from Machiavelli as a forerunner of “scientific politics” in
despising any aim grounded on ideology or myths, like progress, humanitar-
ian values, universal peace or justice, collective interests, and so on. The way to
achieve such aims cannot be drawn from facts, so they are undetermined and
subjective. Any action oriented toward them is not rational, since their goals,
remaining subjective, make it impossible to choose the right means to achieve
them. Only the actions resorting to means whose efficiency is known through
experience can be called rational, such as “technical action, self-interested action
in the economic field, and the kind of action usually called Machiavellian.”28 Of
course, Pareto underlines the importance of utopian goals as ideological beliefs
that support the domination of an elite. In a way, politics is always the ratio-
nal use of irrational actions. The problem, Aron stresses, is that human actions
are never oriented only toward immediate goals. Commenting on Max Weber,
whom Meinecke called “the German Machiavelli,” and his notion of “political
ethic of responsibility,” Aron remarks that “such a political ethic is also grounded
on a total adhesion to a cultural or human value.”29 The same idea appears in
one of the essays on Machiavellianism: “If one wants to interpret human action,
one needs to bring out the kind of motivation which it obeys, as well as the goals
to which it tends, besides the immediate goals one can detect. However, Pareto
despises the fi nal goals, he ignores them . . . Everything that science does not fi nd
in reality is non-existent for science. However, without its orientation to the
future, human existence is no longer humanity, but only nature.”30
Regardless of Pareto’s personal beliefs, his idea of society and politics, as Aron
often notes, leads to Machiavellianism. Refusing, as a scientist, to attend to
notions like human values, he reduces politics to technique. And since violence
and cunning have always proved to be the most efficient techniques, Pareto’s
work can be read as an apology for tyranny. The problem with tyranny is that it
arises from a revolution or some other break in the established order and wants
to become a new order without sacrificing its original exceptional character:
“Legalization of tyranny is nothing but an effort to translate into institutions the
customs of revolutionary practice, in order to make plebiscites the norm, but this
legalization is just a matter of form and appearance.”31
240 DIO G O PI R E S AU R É L IO
institutions to restrain arbitrariness: “Once rulers are elected, they care perma-
nently about their popularity as well as the consent of their ruled people.”42 Both
totalitarian and democratic powers are imperfect. However, the latter assumes its
imperfection as a consequence of confl icts, and organizes itself to resist them; the
former, on the contrary, is organized over a denial of confl icts and, anticipating a
utopian homogeneous community, attempts to destroy the institutions in which
difference of interests and opinions could survive peacefully. Such a distinction,
it is true, may be thought insufficient. As Claude Lefort remarks,43 democracy
is more than a set of juridico-political institutions; it is also a rejection of all
kinds of absolutism, whoever the possessor of absolute power is—state, market,
technology, media, and so on. Furthermore, it is the submission of power to the
multiplicity of demands from the mass of citizens, not to an abstract noun like
the state, the people, or the nation. It might be the case that Aron’s defi nition
of democracy risks seeming too formal. But Lefort’s remark does not deny its
main insight. On the contrary, it can be read as a deepening of Aron’s moderate
Machiavellianism.
Notes
1. Raymond Aron, Mémoires. 50 ans de réflexion politique, Paris, Robert Laffont, 2003
[1983], 152.
2. Raymond Aron, Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, ed. Rémy Freymond, Paris,
Éditions de Fallois, 1993.
3. Ibid., 59.
4. Ibid., 84.
5. “Le machiavélisme de Machiavel,” in Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, 60,
footnote.
6. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie politique: démocratie et révolution, Paris,
Éditions de Fallois, 1997, 131.
7. Aron, Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, 83.
8. See Serge Audier, Raymond Aron: la démocratie conflictuelle, Paris, Michalon, 2004,
44; Serge Audier, Machiavel, conflit et liberté, Paris, Vrin, 2005, 66.
9. Aron, Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, 62.
10. Ibid., 65.
11. Ibid., 70.
12. Ibid., 76.
13. Ibid., 77.
14. Ibid.
15. Ibid., 79.
16. Machiavelli, The Prince, 18, London, Penguin, 1981, 99.
17. Aron, Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, 75.
18. Ibid., 74.
19. Ibid., 119.
20. Ibid.
21. Ibid., 93.
22. Ibid., 92.
23. Ibid., 105.
“ M O D E R A T E M A C H I AV E L L I A N I S M ” 243
Miguel Morgado
would be for Aron. It goes without saying that for generations of Montesquieu’s
readers this interpretation of the great French political philosopher’s thought
was not obvious. Many would not agree without the greatest resistance that
Montesquieu accepted this priority of natural right over “society’s laws,” or that
he made it a pillar of a so-called theory of obligation.2
It is not the purpose of this chapter to deal with this important question. Nor
will we try to discuss whether Montesquieu even held a coherent structure of
natural right as a basis for his political philosophy. But it is important to stress that
Aron also left many disappointed with his openness to historical contingency,
or with his unwillingness to use “thick” (or strong) natural-rights language to
condemn regrettable political choices or outcomes. Many are still unsatisfied by
Aron’s simultaneous acknowledgment of historical necessity and affi rmation of
free human action. This apparent ambiguity in his interpretation of the human
adventure was not without its detractors among the readers of Montesquieu as
well. Rousseau was among the fi rst to protest.3 Destutt de Tracy, whom Thomas
Jefferson was counting on to rid America of Montesquieu’s hegemonic influ-
ence, denounced Montesquieu’s “plan,” which was “to speak always about fact,
and never discuss right.”4 On the opposite side of the political argument, Louis de
Bonald was also very disappointed with Montesquieu because of the primacy he
had given to “what is,” leaving “what ought to be” far behind.5
Regarding the relationship between Aron and Montesquieu, perhaps the fi rst
thing to do is to recall the former’s remark that he was not influenced by the
latter (nor by Tocqueville). He explicitly says that he arrived at Montesquieu’s
thought late in his intellectual life. His philosophical mind had already been
formed by then, as it were, by German philosophy. However, he concedes that
his “conclusions” have obvious affinities with the “English school” of French
sociologists, although his intellectual education had been mainly “German.”6
In The Spirit of Laws, Montesquieu famously remarked that “Many things
determine man: climate, religion, laws, the maxims of the government, exam-
ples of past things, mores and manners.” 7 He was presenting, of course, his con-
cept of “the general spirit of the nation.” In this passage, some have detected the
precise moment of the birth of the sociological perspective. It seemed that with
Montesquieu the primacy of the political regime, distinctive of classical politi-
cal philosophy and abandoned by early modern political philosophy, was being
rejected in the name of an altogether different approach. Aron singles out this
particular passage in The Spirit of Laws for elaborating the “principle of unifica-
tion of the social whole.”8 For him, the concept of the general spirit of the nation
is “the true apex of Montesquieu’s sociology.”9 The general spirit of the nation is
the “way of being, acting, thinking, and feeling of a particular collectivity, such
as it was made by geography and history.”10 The totality of human national real-
ity was now being determined, not by the political regime, nor by a particular
physical or moral cause, but by a host of determining factors. Human existence is
determined by the synthesis of several causes—political, moral, religious, physi-
cal. In some cases, one category of causes might be stronger as a determining
force of human existence, while in other historical experiences an altogether
different category of causes would be paramount. Apparently, there was no fi xed
MON T E S QU I E U A N D A RON 247
hierarchy of determining causes, and that left the sociological point of view
ready to affirm itself. It paved the way for the foundation of a new human sci-
ence. Yet Montesquieu had already said that the “form of government” had some
kind of priority, albeit not clearly explained, over other determining factors of
human existence. And this is the explicit reason why he began his examination
of human reality by analyzing forms of government before everything else.11
According to Aron, Montesquieu’s text does not allow for a defi nitive removal
of this ambiguity.12
Although Aron reaffirms Montesquieu’s place as the founder of sociology,
perhaps one should consider that for him Montesquieu is the founder of political
sociology, precisely the kind of sociology that Aron claims to profess.13 More
notably in Main Currents of Sociological Thought, Aron presents Montesquieu as a
sociologist and as a political philosopher. He was a sociologist because he exam-
ined all realms of social activity, the parts of the social as such, and tried to
establish the relationships between all of those parts. He was a sociologist because
his work is “defi ned by a specific intention, to know scientifically the social as
such.”14 There are deep explanatory “causes” behind the almost infi nite human
diversity in mores, religions, and political arrangements, and also behind the
historical succession of events. To use Montesquieu’s succinct formulation, “it is
not Fortune who dominates the world.”15
The second aspect that qualifies Montesquieu as the founder of sociology is
his organization of human diversity into a small number of “types or concepts.”16
Both static diversity and historical change become intelligible through socio-
logical reasoning. Nevertheless, Montesquieu was also a political philosopher,
because he continued to formulate a typology of political regimes in the spirit of
classical philosophy. For Aron, this means the more or less explicit postulation of
the primacy of the political.17
His dedication to sociology notwithstanding, it is fair to say that Aron shares
Montesquieu’s general approach, though not without qualifications. In other
words, from this Aronian(-Montesquieuan) perspective, one still concedes a sort
of political primacy over other nonpolitical factors but, at the same time, deep-
ens the study of political units by linking the political form to a certain “social
type.” Indeed, each political regime is “characterized by a social type.”18 Political
form is not independent of certain economic or social forms—not to mention
demographical and spatial realities.19
But when confronting the question of the primacy of either politics or econom-
ics, that is to say, the idea that a certain social dimension of reality (the political or
the economic) unilaterally determines the whole of social reality, Aron fi nds such
dogmatism “arbitrary.” Moreover, “it can be shown quite easily that every theory
of the unilateral determinism of the community as a whole by one single element
of collective reality is false.”20 In other words, it is demonstrably false that starting
from one political (or economic) form a specific type of economy (or politics) will
ensue. He goes on raising the stakes of skepticism: the notion that “one particular
order of things is more important than any other order is a misleading idea.” It
may be argued that here Aron is breaking with Montesquieu, who claimed that
the political was, in a certain way, the most important element among several
248 M IG U E L MORG A D O
Ideal Types?
On the question of whether or not Montesquieu’s forms of government are
identical to Max Weber’s “ideal types,” Aron argues that a peremptory answer
250 M IG U E L MORG A D O
one way or the other would be a gross simplification of the French nobleman’s
thought. When all perspectives of analysis are taken into account, it is indeed
risky to say otherwise. It is easy to fi nd Montesquieu scholars on both sides of
the divide.27 For example, Carcassonne rejected the notion that the regimes pre-
sented in The Spirit of Laws are abstractions from historical experience. Focusing
on the case of monarchy, he claimed that Montesquieu’s forms of government
were in fact specific moral and social conditions of human experience.28 Hegel
argued that Montesquieu had avoided the partiality of both idealism and empiri-
cism because he “did not merely deduce individual institutions and laws from so-
called reason, nor merely abstract them from experience to raise them thereafter
to some universal”; Montesquieu “comprehended both the higher relationships
of constitutional law and the lower specifications of civil relationships,” and did
so “entirely from the [national] whole and its individuality.”29
Montesquieu himself left us with one or two reflections that remove almost all
our doubts. There we can see Montesquieu avoiding the partiality both of ideal-
ism and empiricism, confi rming Hegel’s reading. On the one hand, the analysis
of the English regime is closer to an “ideal type” approach. The typological
content of The Spirit of Laws (XI.6 and XIX.27) seems to indicate the probable
result of the development of previously defi ned constitutional principles. Perhaps
that can explain the use of the conditional tense in The Spirit of Laws (XIX.27);
that is to say, Montesquieu chose to use an “if-then” formulation because he
was positing an “ideal” form of government less connected to concrete political
experience.30 However, on the other hand, Montesquieu considered the other
forms of government as corresponding to representations, as reliable as possible,
of actual political experience. A case in point in The Spirit of Laws is China. At
a certain stage, Montesquieu believed that he had to reply to some of the travel
literature—a privileged source of knowledge of politics and society in faraway
lands in the eighteenth-century—that allegedly put the Chinese empire outside
the typological orbit presented in The Spirit of Laws. Although he was ready to
acknowledge the problems posed by China’s heterogeneity of social and political
structure, he strove to demonstrate that China was indeed a despotic state. By
implication, he was making the claim that the empirical (not “ideal”) reliability
of his typology becomes irrefutable after being tested—on the basis, of course,
of empirical elements.
Another point at which Montesquieu seems to follow a similar orientation is
in his critique of Aristotle’s conception of monarchy. According to Montesquieu,
Aristotle’s views on monarchy became so confusing because the historical age of
real (gothic) monarchies had yet to emerge in classical antiquity; Aristotle could
not analyze monarchies properly due to the simple fact that they did not yet have
historical existence. For example, the nobility as a social and political part of the
regime is a central element of monarchies; therefore, it did not exist in ancient
times either.31 This allows the conclusion to be drawn that for Montesquieu
regimes must fi rst become historically manifest before they can be categorized.
Was England an exception to this rule, then? Perhaps not, since England—with
its proclaimed political and constitutional basis—was already “ideally” real.
MON T E S QU I E U A N D A RON 251
To Aron, things are somewhat more complex, albeit not dramatically dif-
ferent. In Aron’s own approach the political regime has to be examined in the
light of its “historical environment,” for it is “influenced, if not determined” by
a whole array of nonpolitical factors such as traditions, values, ways of thought
and of action, peculiar to each country. This may be seen as just an update to
Montesquieu’s insight concerning the general spirit of the nation. Additionally,
all regimes share one basic “function”—the maintenance of internal peace and
protection from external aggression. It must be added that they all strive to ful-
fi ll another basic condition—the obedience of their citizens, or a more-or-less
universal acceptance of their legitimacy. Lastly, every regime advances ethical or
existential goals which deserve the loyalty of the governed and, at the same time,
binds the regime’s self-interpretation, or the representation of its “own picture of
itself.”32 Regardless of how far the regime’s actual conduct may be from its self-
interpretation, this last aspect retains a great deal of flexibility. Explicit coher-
ence, even if at a general level, becomes decisive for the regime’s integrity and
even survival. This insight also reveals the rather narrow limits of “cynical politi-
cal philosophy,” or the notion that politics is simply the realm of the struggle for
power and that outright institutionalized hypocrisy is not a political liability.
Still, and with all these caveats in mind, Aron does argue in favor of a limited
primacy of the political. This can be justified by historical comparisons as well
as on anthropological grounds. First, given that industrial society is the modern
social type par excellence, the dissimilarities between historically concrete indus-
trial societies fi nd their reasons in political differences. In a word, “it is politics
which determines the different variations.” Second, since society is essentially
the organization of human relationships, and because living with other people is
an essential aspect of being human, it is politics that is “concerned more directly
with the very meaning of existence.” Science, and sociology in particular, can-
not be abstracted from men’s own interpretation of politics and its place in the
world.33 As a matter of fact, Aron perceived in Montesquieu a similar under-
standing when he described Montesquieu’s primacy of the political as being in
an anthropological sense, rather than a strictly causal one.34 “Cynical political
philosophy,” rooted in Machiavelli’s conception that politics is the mere struggle
for power, evades this fundamental question with a false realism. It is nihil-
ism disguised as pseudo-social science, and is conducive to swinging between
skepticism and fanaticism. This leads to the sociological conclusion that “the
constitution of authority affects ways of life more directly than any other aspect
of society.”35 We should say “more directly,” but not absolutely. Again, this does
not allow for the ancient postulation of a primacy of politics in which all human
relationships in society are determined by it—at least according to the particu-
lar concept of politics which only encompasses the domain in which rulers are
selected and then act. Interestingly, Aron thought that the claim of the abso-
lute primacy of politics was characteristic of “Greek” political philosophers—
presumably, classical political philosophers. It goes without saying that Marxists
were on the exact opposite side of the argument—the absolute primacy of the
economic factors in determining the whole of society. But it has to be said that
252 M IG U E L MORG A D O
protect the rights of man and improve social conditions, for the simple reason
that not every nation is capable of ruling itself this way. Following Montesquieu,
Aron, like Rousseau before him, could have said then that “freedom, not being a
fruit of all climates, is not within the reach of all peoples”47—as long as “climate”
is understood very broadly.
Let us make one fi nal remark about moderation. Aron indicates that
Montesquieu combined a political typology of three different forms of govern-
ment (republics, monarchies, despotic states) with another implicit classification
distinguishing moderate from immoderate regimes.48 This simple observa-
tion has important consequences. For Aron reads Montesquieu as saying that
“social life” will be different depending on whether the political community is
ruled moderately (according to law and rules) or immoderately (arbitrarily and
with violence). No present-day sociology of political analysis should forget this
insight and fundamental division.49 Moreover, even though Aron commented
that Montesquieu was a “representative of the aristocracy” and therefore had
elaborated a notion of social balance typical of the “model of an aristocratic soci-
ety,” he suggested that Montesquieu’s general idea of social and political balance
preserves its relevance in present-day conditions. Social and political balance
resulting from a diversity of powers, social orders, and categories is a condition
for moderation and freedom. A free and moderate democratic society in the pres-
ent world cannot be simply built on the spurious notion of the sovereignty of the
people. The Montesquieuan distinction between the power of the people and
the liberty of citizens is undoubtedly relevant to present-day political sociology,
not to mention his doctrine of the need to limit power in order to bring about a
moderate regime.50
Corruption
No regime is immune to corruption. Montesquieu warned that “the corruption
of each government almost always begins with that of its principles.”51 The cor-
ruption of a regime’s political principle was for Montesquieu the main reason for
its eventual fall—and possible transformation into another historically available
regime. Corruption, we might say, is a matter of principle.
Aron was also concerned with the problem of “corruption” as understood in
a classical and Montesquieuan sense. Let us recall again that, according to Aron,
the democratic political principles are respect for the law and a “sense of compro-
mise.” And let us recall that for Montesquieu the democratic republican principle
is “virtue.” In Aron’s thought, democracy has “negative virtues” and “positive
virtues.” “Negative virtues” are those related to the limitation of the authority
of groups and their opinions in public discussion and party competition, includ-
ing the limitation of political power. “Positive virtues,” in turn, are respect for
the law and basic political rules and respect for individual liberties. These virtues
are more responsible for the avoidance of evils than for the performance of great
heroic achievements. In its modesty, constitutional-pluralist democracy is able
to protect society and individuals from evils that other regimes cannot.52 This
MON T E S QU I E U A N D A RON 255
is nothing that will inspire men to poetic greatness, to be sure; but, like one’s
health, one only appreciates it fully once it is already lost.
Aron argues that the loss of “public spirit” is definitely a manifestation of the
corruption of the principle of modern democracies. In Montesquieu’s thought,
the corruption of republican “virtue” may be expressed in these terms. However,
Montesquieu thought that insofar as “virtue” is patriotism, its corruption would
mean, for instance, the return of the individual to his own private concerns and
desires, deserting communal action for the sake of the fatherland. Insofar as “vir-
tue” is love of equality, its corruption would mean either the toleration of great
inequalities or a fanatical view of equality that wants to abolish every source
of inequality or distinction, regardless of how temporary or how respectful of
republican government it may be, thereby compromising the very structure of
republican political power and the justification of obedience. Insofar as “virtue”
consists of willingly obeying the laws, its corruption would mean contempt for
the discipline introduced by legality and disregard for obeying common rules—ev-
ery man thinks of himself as an exception. Finally, insofar as “virtue” is the love of
“frugality,” its corruption would be the openness of men and women to indulge
in their subjective private pleasures and promote their unrestrained growth, and
the loosening of restraints on the desire of leading an ever-more-comfortable
prosperous existence, even at the price of detachment from the bonds that tie the
republican citizen to his duties.
All this is reasoned against the backdrop of the small ancient city, whereas
Aron has in mind modern industrial societies. Industrial societies are mobilized
to produce more—in fact, to produce as much as possible. The quest for affluence is
inimical to frugality.53 So what is the meaning of “public spirit” in these modern
conditions? Interestingly, it means two extreme behaviors: either party sectari-
anism to the point at which people lose sight of the most tenuous notion of the
common good (which, one may add, is a classic republican remark against the
“spirit of faction”) or a hyperbolic “sense of compromise” that paralyses decision-
making and undermines the possibility of pursuing a coherent and stable political
strategy. Compromise, as Aron acknowledges, is not always a good thing. Not
only may compromise be a euphemism for inaction and paralysis but, very often,
political choices themselves are not open to compromise. Sometimes it simply
must be one way or another. Combinations of alternate choices are occasionally
impossible. In these cases, a desperate search for compromise will bring about
an unequivocally bad solution to the national problem at hand. There can be
indeed an “excess use of compromise,” which is another aspect of political cor-
ruption.54 In other words, corruption of “public spirit” can be either too much
“sense of compromise” or too little. There is, then, a golden mean of the “sense
of compromise” which can only be determined in the context of actual concrete
circumstances and appeals to prudent political judgment. Vitality in a democ-
racy, then, presupposes and points to a proper, but difficult to ascertain, balance
between, on the one hand, the forces that divide—decision-making, pluralism
of opinion, and diversity of interests—and, on the other hand, the need for com-
monality and general consensus regarding basic rules and behavior.
256 M IG U E L MORG A D O
Notes
1. Émile Durkheim, “Contribution de Montesquieu à la constitution de la science
sociale,” in Émile Durkheim, Montesquieu et Rousseau. Précurseurs de la sociologie,
Paris, Librairie Marcel Rivière et Cie, 1966, 54, 50.
2. In his widely quoted biography of Montesquieu, Robert Shackleton held a rela-
tivistic reading of his work. Robert Shackleton, Montesquieu: A Critical Biography
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1961, 45.
3. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Émile, Œuvres complètes, vol. IV, Paris, Gallimard, 1959–
1969, 836.
4. Destutt de Tracy, Commentaire sur l’Esprit des Lois de Montesquieu in Œuvres de
Montesquieu, vol. VIII, Paris, Dalibon, 1827, 82.
5. Louis de Bonald, Théorie du pouvoir politique et religieux dans la société civile, vol. I,
Paris, A. Le Clere, 1843, 12.
6. Raymond Aron, Les Etapes de la pensée sociologique, vol. I, Paris, Gallimard, 1967,
21.
7. Charles de Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, eds. Anne M. Cohler, Basia
Carolyn Miller, and Harold Samuel, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1989, XIX.4.
8. Aron, Les Étapes de la pensée sociologique, 30.
9. Ibid., 46. See Raymond Aron, Dix-Huit Leçons sur la société industrielle, Paris,
Gallimard, 1962, 70.
10. Aron, Les Étapes de la pensée sociologique, 52.
MON T E S QU I E U A N D A RON 259
Aurelian Craiutu
I n the French school of political sociology, whose origins can be traced back to
Montesquieu and which also includes Alexis de Tocqueville, Raymond Aron
(1905–1983) occupies a prominent place. He felt close to those political sociolo-
gists who displayed an unfailing commitment to political liberty, emphasized the
importance of civil society and intermediary bodies, underscored the autonomy
of the political sphere, and defended political moderation.2 Although he lived
in an age of extremes, Aron retained his moderate voice up to the end of his
life. He wrote against the arguments of those with whom he disagreed (first and
foremost, Jean-Paul Sartre), but never against them personally, distinguishing
sharply between ideas and persons. As Edward Shils once remarked, Aron “was
never abusive even when he was abused; he wrote polemics, but they were fac-
tual and logical, and he never insulted his adversaries as they insulted him.”3 He
was, to use a memorable phrase of Claude Lévi-Strauss, “notre dernier professeur
d’hygiène intellectuelle.”4
Since Aron lived in a country with a revolutionary soul, he often found him-
self in the minority, but he was in good company in this regard. A century before
him, Tocqueville, too, had found himself marginalized in the middle, between
the prophets of the past, the apostles of the new bourgeoisie, and the enthusiast
advocates of a radiant (socialist) future. “Politically,” Aron noted, “Tocqueville
belonged to that liberal party which probably had little chance of fi nding even a
disputatious satisfaction in the course of French politics.”5 Tocqueville was well
aware of his solitary situation and in a letter to his mentor, Pierre Royer-Collard,
he admitted that “the liberal but not revolutionary party, which alone suits me,
does not exist.”6 Tocqueville’s words can also be applied, mutatis mutandis, to
Aron who was and remained to the very end a lonely friend of constitutional
262 AU R E L I A N C R A I U T U
ignored each other and never engaged with each other’s ideas, even if, as Aron
noted, they had many things in common, from their “disgust for opportunism”
to their “total fidelity to themselves and their ideas.”14
To be sure, the differences between them were insurmountable. One placed
above everything else the safeguarding of personal and political freedoms in
modern democratic societies, while the other gave priority to achieving eco-
nomic justice and eliminating the exploitation of man by man. One believed
in the possibility of gradual reforms and the improvement of living conditions,
while the other flatly rejected this approach in favor of a total revolution meant to
reshape the very foundations of society and the state.15 Aron remarked that both
Tocqueville and Marx believed in freedom, but they did it in significantly dif-
ferent ways, with major implications for their political agendas. For Tocqueville,
the essential condition of freedom was representative government and self-gov-
ernment, while for Marx it was the communist (economic and political) revolu-
tion that was supposed to be brought about by the dictatorship of the proletariat
and the elimination of private property. In Tocqueville’s eyes, the personal and
civil freedoms enjoyed by the citizens of liberal democracies were real and mean-
ingful, even if not all individuals fully enjoyed the freedom to actualize their
potential as human beings and forge their total liberation from domination.
Marx believed the contrary.
In the end, Aron claimed, Tocqueville’s long-term vision emphasizing the
gradual but unstoppable equalization of conditions and stressing the importance
of formal freedoms proved to be more “accurate,” while Marx, who predicted
the impoverishment of the masses and argued that formal freedoms were mere
veils hiding the truth of capitalist societies from the eyes of the public, offered
a “distorted”16 view of modern society. There was a paradox in all that, since
Tocqueville was certainly not as well read in economics as Marx who had stud-
ied with greater attention and interest the dynamics of modern capitalist econo-
mies. Yet, as Aron argued, the Frenchman managed to see “better” and farther
than the author of Das Kapital. He foresaw that modern society would evolve
toward a middle-class society with functional intermediary bodies that would
make revolutions less frequent in the future, as the desire for gain and the pos-
sibilities of acquiring wealth become more widespread. In turn, Marx assumed
that society would be disturbed by constant confl icts of interest between the
rich and the poor and would usher in a global communist revolution that would
profoundly transform the face of the earth. Marx’s prediction that the condition
of the masses would worsen with the development of capitalism (accompanied
by more frequent economic crises) was falsified by subsequent developments,
and he misread the conditions of economic growth in modern society. Socialism
(communism) or barbarism, as Marx put it, was not exactly the choice that the
twentieth-century faced.
Aron followed in Tocqueville’s footsteps in this regard. He remarked that
while liberal democratic societies are stratified and allow for significant eco-
nomic inequalities, they are not divided as sharply into antagonist classes as Marx
thought. Aron also shared Tocqueville’s sociological approach to democracy as
opposed to Marx’s economistic and deterministic methodology. As Tocqueville
R AY M O N D A RO N A N D A L E X I S D E T O C Q U E V I L L E 265
citizens living in modern liberal democracies. In his last lecture, Aron referred to
the “moral crisis” affecting our liberal democracies today. We may be freer than
before in negative terms, Aron claimed, but we no longer know for sure where to
locate virtue and how to think of it in our societies. If we are to remain free, he
concluded in a Tocquevillian vein, our efforts at protecting our individual rights
must be accompanied by a thorough reconsideration of our civic duties.27
In the end, Aron argued, the author of Democracy in America was a good analyst
and prophet. “The federation has endured . . . The institutions which he saw as the
expression and the guarantee of freedom—the role of citizens in the local admin-
istration, voluntary associations, reciprocal support of the democratic spirit, and
the religious spirit—have survived.”28 The society in which we live today, Aron
remarked, is basically democratic in the sense that there are no civil inequalities
anymore; it guarantees individual rights, personal freedoms, and constitutional
procedures, even if it also gives birth to significant economic inequalities. It was
one of Tocqueville’s greatest merits that he was not oblivious to the existence
of economic inequalities in the modern world. If, at times, he referred to the
“surprising equality” in fortunes that reigned in the New World, he noticed
the potential for the appearance of what he called an “industrial aristocracy” in
America. All things considered, Tocqueville did not believe, however, that the
existence of this type of aristocracy was enough to call into question the future
of the American democracy as long as social mobility and what he referred to as
“the sentiment of equality” continued to exist in the New World.29 Aron agreed
with him on this essential point.
point to a free and open society that leaves to individuals a margin of operation
as large as possible and would protect their rights from undue interference and
discrimination.36
We can examine further the similarities and differences between Aron and
Tocqueville’s views on liberty by taking into account their views on the rela-
tionship between the political and social spheres. Both were “probabilists” who
shied away from endorsing a purely deterministic view of history, society, and
politics. Instead, they emphasized the important role played by a wide array of
fortuitous circumstances and non-economic factors in determining the nature of
political regimes. On Aron’s interpretation, one of the reasons for the superior-
ity of Tocqueville’s vision compared to Marx lies in the fact that he refused to
subordinate politics to economics and did not believe that the administration of
things would ever replace the rule of men. In other words, for Tocqueville, the
political remained an autonomous sphere in modern society, one that is never fully
determined only by the economic sphere. Aron was sympathetic to this argu-
ment and believed that all notions of absolute determination are excessive and
ultimately devoid of meaning. He went further than Tocqueville in highlighting
the importance of the nature of political regimes, emphasizing “la primauté de la
politique”37 vis-à-vis the economic sphere, and thus reaffirming the importance
of individual liberty and political choice.
While making a seminal distinction between social and political order, both
Tocqueville and Aron underscored the complex and unique nature of the politi-
cal sphere as a distinctive dimension of human life that cannot be reduced to
a mere epiphenomenon of economics or administration, as Marx and Comte
claimed. Neither Tocqueville nor Aron accepted at face value the claims made by
Marx and Comte, who pretended to eliminate from politics allegedly vague and
ill-defi ned notions and attempted to discover apodictic laws by using methods
similar to those to be found in natural sciences. Such goals were never achieved
in practice, and one good example was the Soviet economy. As Aron remarked,
we can understand neither the mode of allocation of resources nor the strategy
of economic growth if we ignore the peculiarities of the Soviet political regime
and its ideology.38 The latter explains how and why the scarce resources were
allocated in a certain way that privileged certain economic sectors and social
categories over others. In Aron’s view, it would be a simplification (and error)
to regard power as nothing other than the organized power of one class for the
oppression of another; political superstructure is always much more than a mere
reflection of social and economic forces. “The political order,” Aron claimed,
“is as essential and autonomous as the economic order,”39 and the idea of the
state’s disappearance announced by Marxists is nothing but a myth. In reality,
the power of the state “does not and cannot disappear in a planned society, even
when private ownership of the instruments of production has disappeared.”40
As history demonstrated, a centrally planned economy required an even stron-
ger state than a market-based one, and the economic allocation of resources in
Soviet-type economies always followed important political decisions and priori-
ties made by political elites.
270 AU R E L I A N C R A I U T U
the limitations of industrial civilization, the power of money, and the price of
economic success tend to offend the susceptibilities of intellectuals, who become
over-emotional in preaching a strange form of intellectual and political evange-
lism while claiming at the same time to be more competent than ordinary citi-
zens at judging the flaws of society.44 Moreover, the obscurity and compromise
inherent in political life tend to offend their aesthetic sensibilities, which can
hardly accept that the best is often the enemy of the better. Thus, many intellec-
tuals often refuse to think politically, and “prefer ideology that is a rather liter-
ary image of a desirable society, rather than to study the functioning of a given
economy, of a parliamentary system, and so forth.”45 As a result, intellectuals
tend to form opinions based on emotions and moral imperatives rather than a
careful analysis of each particular situation, and often come to conceive of their
political engagement only (or primarily) as a pretext for self-aggrandizement.
Aron’s conclusion was a restatement of Tocqueville’s analysis.
A comparison between their views on the revolutions of 1848 and 1968 might
shed additional light on this issue. In February and June 1848, as member of the
Chamber of Deputies, Tocqueville witnessed fi rst-hand the attempts at building
a republican regime in France. More than a century later, in May–June 1968,
Raymond Aron almost became a political actor against his will, writing a num-
ber of important articles in Le Figaro and later devoting an entire book to this
issue, La Révolution introuvable.46 As Hoff mann pointed out, in both its tone and
content Aron’s book is to some extent reminiscent of Tocqueville’s Souvenirs.47
Both books put forward trenchant critiques of French politics and suggested that
the deeper and enduring cause of the French problem lay not so much with the
incompetence of the central government and its leaders (Louis-Philippe, General
de Gaulle) as with the weakness of intermediary bodies in French society and
the absence of administrative decentralization. It is no accident that Aron himself
compared his skepticism toward the claims advanced by the revolutionaries of
1968 with Tocqueville’s critique of the revolution of 1848 in France. In his view,
the crisis of May 1968 unfolded much like the revolution of 1848, yet the two
revolutions left different legacies in their wake. Neither Aron nor Tocqueville
gave one-dimensional explanations of 1848 or 1968, and both believed that,
most of the time, individuals do not determine events as much as they are deter-
mined by them. In their accounts of the failure of 1848 and 1968, Tocqueville
and Aron bemoaned the fact that the French nation had not been cured yet of its
old “revolutionary virus”48 that had delayed much-needed political reforms and
made it possible for demonstrators in the streets to make and unmake govern-
ments at will.
Like Tocqueville in 1848, Aron could not take the political actors of 1968
seriously, and argued that the events of May–June of that year seemed a mediocre
drama played by immature actors. Aron had little patience for the intellectuals’
nostalgia for direct and authentic political action as illustrated by their idealiza-
tion of “action committees” and disregard for concrete political institutions. In
his view, the spirit of revolt undergirding the participatory practices proposed
by the famous comités d’action could hardly be reconciled in practice with the
principles of democratic legitimacy and liberal democracy. This was not only
272 AU R E L I A N C R A I U T U
because the leaders of the students and workers had a low regard for legality and
compromise, but also because their idea of a revolution opposed to any form of
domination was, in reality, an untenable concoction of pre-Marxist socialism,
anarcho-syndicalism, and Proudhonism that lacked an adequate understanding
of the constraints governing the political and economic spheres of modern soci-
ety. Without being a dogmatic partisan of the status quo, Aron argued that the
unconditional contestation of hierarchies was unlikely to usher in the discov-
ery of an original third way between—or beyond—communism and capitalism.
With the benefit of hindsight, he was right to make this claim.
Conclusion
“Libéral et démocrate, j’avais en politique deux passions: la France et la liberté.” These
words, serving as an epigraph for this essay, could have also been used to
describe Tocqueville’s political agenda. Both were probabilists who believed
that the progressive equalization of conditions could lead to liberty or despo-
tism, depending on the actual choices made by individuals. Both refused to hold
any of the given facts of social order as entirely eluding human control. This also
applies to democracy, which, they believed, could be moderated and educated
while being purified of its revolutionary excesses. Aron spent his entire career
defending the principles of liberal democracy in dark times. He once described
himself as “a man without party, who is all the more unbearable because he
takes his moderation to excess and hides his passions under his arguments.”49
In this regard, too, he shared important affi nities with Tocqueville. Their con-
servative liberalism was fundamentally a doctrine of political moderation seeking
to avoid the evils of the past and keeping the memory of past tragedies alive
as a source of instruction and a justification of the need for moderation.50 The
society for which they fought was based on a constitutional framework whose
main purpose was to prevent abuses of power and to create and sustain a vibrant
social and political pluralism. Their open-ended philosophy of history reflected
their trust in human freedom and their respect for human dignity, two values
which continue to inspire us today, as we are continuing our journey into the
twenty-fi rst century.
Notes
1. The author would like to acknowledge the support received from the James
Madison Program at Princeton University which provided an ideal research set-
ting for completing this chapter.
2. See Raymond Aron, “Élie Halévy et l’ère des tyrannies,” in Raymond Aron
(1905–1983): Histoire et politique, special issue of Commentaire, vol. 8, 28–29,
1985, 327–350. I have commented on this topic in Aurelian Craiutu, “Raymond
Aron and the French Tradition of Political Moderation” in Raf Geenens and
Helena Rosenblatt (eds.), French Liberalism: From Montesquieu to the Present Day,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012, 271–290.
R AY M O N D A RO N A N D A L E X I S D E T O C Q U E V I L L E 273
Christian Bachelier
“. . . History is again on the move,” this famous remark of Toynbee was quoted
by Raymond Aron remembering his own mood in Cologne and Berlin at the
beginning of the 1930s . This moment was also the revelation of his “existential
project”: “On a beautiful day, walking along the Rhine, I thought I wanted to
be both spectator and engaged. A spectator of history being made and engaged
in this history in the making.”1
Aron’s relationship with history in the making rules the evolution of his
thought on peace and war among nations, from a belief in “integral pacifism” to
the analysis of a “warlike peace.”
Linked with history in the making, such evolution singled him out from his
generation,2 which can be seen by comparing his evolution to the paths of some
of his contemporaries. His generation was composed of such promising intel-
lectuals as Sartre, Nizan, Friedmann, Canguilhem, Cavaillès; and this genera-
tion early on was historically conscious of itself. In 1928, Bertrand de Jouvenel
wrote L’économie dirigée. Le programme de la nouvelle génération; and, in 1929, Jean
Luchaire, Une génération réaliste. The latter focuses on Franco-German relations.
Indeed, the slaughter of elders mowed down by the First World War marked
this generation. A very close friend of Aron, Georges Canguilhem, testified: “It
is not surprising that Aron and I, like all of our classmates, perceived in our elders
a spirit of pacifism not free of antimilitarism.”3 In his Mémoires, Aron empha-
sized that this loathing for war could lead to three kinds of positions: revolution
epitomized by communism, as in the case of his friend Paul Nizan; Franco-
German reconciliation or Briandism, as in the case of Jean Luchaire; or, fi nally,
the avoidance of military service in the form either of conscientious objection
or distrust of all authority, as in the case of Alain. An “integral pacifi st” and
professor occupying the prestigious and strategic position of chair of philosophy
for the senior class at the Lycée Henri-IV, Alain had a considerable influence on
this intellectual youth, as evidenced by the novel Dix-huitième année, written by
his former student Jean Prévost and published in 1929. This Alainian influence
was also exerted over Aron, who in the very words of his Mémoires described
276 CH R I ST I A N BACH E LI E R
himself as a “passionate pacifist.” But though Aron wrote for Alain’s periodical,
he rightly claimed, in his Mémoires, to have adhered to the Briandist position.
Indeed, Aron was then advocating the policy of Franco-German reconciliation
connected with the principle of pacifism, the possible with the desirable.
From the post-First World War period to the drôle de guerre (phony war),
his “political education,” according his own words, takes place. This educa-
tion took the form of a conversion to political realism, triggered fi rst by his
years in Germany and then ratified by his pre-World War II writings. Later, he
remembers this intellectual evolution, whose mover can be linked to the ethics
of responsibility that Weber applied to political thought: “It is not very reason-
able for a man of thought to have political opinions without thinking, without
knowing what can be said about them from the point of view of social sciences,
even if these are imperfect.”4
The German experience of Aron, especially his relation to “history in the
making,” indeed caused a “conversion.”5 Although most French students in
Berlin were then attempting to analyze the Nazi phenomenon, this stay was not
in itself decisive, as one could see when, for the next academic year of 1933–
1934, Sartre succeeded his friend Aron to the Berlin Französisches Akademiker
Haus. Despite German events such as the Gleichschaltung (the coercive reorga-
nization of politics and society), the impact of these circumstances did not have
a significant effect upon Sartre’s mood. A few years later, in his Carnets de la
drôle de guerre, Sartre wrote: “I spent holidays in Berlin; there I rediscovered the
irresponsibility of youth.”6 And once more, he corroborates upon this way of
thinking thirty years later: “Yes, Hitler was in power . . . I saw Nazism, and I also
saw a quasi-dictatorship in France with the Doumergue’s policy.” 7 Regarding
the intellectual side of his stay in Berlin, Sartre studied Heidegger and Husserl,
wrote La Transcendance de l’ego, and began working on La Nausée. Therefore,
some of the major characteristics of Aron’s intellectual evolution during his years
in Germany must be specified.
First of all, this was the moment when Aron confronted politics. This time
period in Germany saw the rise of Nazism and the seizure of power by Hitler:
“I was no longer colliding with the mysteries of intemporality in the thought
of Immanuel Kant but with Germans, students, teachers, and ordinary bour-
geois who cursed the Treaty of Versailles, the French, and the economic crisis
altogether.”8 Therefore, he transferred this confrontation into the knowledge of
the self and of the other: “Lévi-Strauss discovered the other in archaic societies;
I, myself, discovered the other in modern society embodied by Hitler and his
followers.”9
In his Mémoires, Aron wrote about this period of his life: “I left a postwar
world to enter the prewar world.” Therefore, in this moment, he discovered the
concrete conditions of politics and the reality of power interests.
These troubling times inspired his fi rst observations that he would share in
Alain’s Libres Propos and Romain Rolland’s Europe. In his Mémoires, he criticizes
his correspondence from Germany without indulgence: “To become a commen-
tator on history in the making, I had a lot to learn.”10 In addition, these reviews
had little weight: “A spectator of the success of the Third Reich, voiceless and
EPILOGU E 277
without tribune, I could not, like others, ignore the question of the gigantic
struggle that I foresaw. This question concerned all of mankind, but also my
own being.”11 Therefore, focusing on peace and on the totalitarian regime, the
subjects of these writings belonged to universal history.
His “Réflexions de politique réaliste,” in Libres Propos, April 1932, dwell upon,
first, the permanent rivalry between States; then, the principle of the balance of
power; and, fi nally, the need for a common will to avoid confl icts. Furthermore,
Aron emphasizes the principle of reality by stating in his “Lettre ouverte d’un
jeune Français en Allemagne,” in Esprit, February 1933, that “good politics is
specified by effectiveness, not by virtue.” In addition, he links domestic politics
and foreign policy in his article “Hitler et le désarmement,” published in Europe,
the periodical of another proponent of French pacifism, Romain Rolland, in
July 1933. Indeed, after noticing that the leaders of the German left had found
the Nazi program “reactionary and utopian” and were consequently unable to
understand the “driving force” of Nazism, Aron sent a warning: “this same dan-
ger can be replicated at the level of world politics.”
First, seeking reasonable thought applied to social reality, Raymond Aron
began reading Marx in 1931 and would be one of the fi rst French readers of
the famous Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, published at Berlin in
1932. Also, later, he describes relevantly the link between Marxism and history
in the chapter “L’homme dans l’histoire: choix et action” of his thesis disserta-
tion, Introduction à la philosophie de l’Histoire, where he exposes the fundamental
antinomy between two ideal types, the politician of reason and the politician of
understanding, this antinomy being based on the criterion of the relationship
to history in the making. The politician of reason, that is, the Marxist claiming
to be the confidant of Providence, “is certain of the inevitable disappearance of
capitalism” and foresees “the next stage of evolution.”12
As for the politician of understanding—or “politician of compromise”—fac-
ing history, “he is like a pilot navigating without knowledge of the port. There is
dualism of means and ends, of the reality and values; there is no current totality or
predestinated future; every moment is new to him.” This is the Weberian politi-
cal ideal that Aron maintains: “To take in situations, to discern the complexity
of determinism, and to fit into reality the new fact which gives the greatest
chance of attaining the goal which has been set.”13 Indeed, the other discovery
of the moment was German sociology, notably the sociology of Max Weber:
“What struck me in Max Weber was his vision of world history, his enlightening
perspective on the originality of modern science, and his reflection on the his-
torical and political condition of mankind.”14 Therefore, Weberian concepts—
understanding, value judgment, ideal type, ethics of responsibility and ethics of
conviction, forms of domination, universality and singularity, search for truth
and plurality of interpretations—would structure the Aronian relationship with
history in the making.15 Nonetheless, in his presentation of German sociology,
Aron notes the limitations of Weber’s thought;16 and, in particular, by regarding
Weber’s plurality of interpretations, he objects to Weber’s theory of hypothetical
objectivity: “Furthermore, relativism is itself transcended as soon as the historian
ceases to claim a detachment that is impossible, identifies his point of view, and
278 CH R I ST I A N BACH E LI E R
and prepared his Leibniz et Spinoza, which would be published after the war.
Raymond Aron suffered the German attacks in May 1940 in Ardennes, was in
Bordeaux on June 20, then in Toulouse, decided to go to England, and finally
enlisted with Free French Forces.
For Aron, the shock of war brought the necessity to think about war and to
develop strategic concepts to extend and develop his pre-war thought: “The
catastrophe that, in a few days, struck down the army and the French nation
made me swell with indignation,” Aron resumed, “less against ‘the responsible’
than against ourselves, all of us who, men of thought, never devoted time and
our attention to studying this endemic disease of human societies: war.”28
The inability to think about the war in advance was regretted by Aron. He
saw this, among others, as one of the baneful effects of Alain’s pacifi stic influ-
ence. He therefore wrote an article titled “Philosophie du pacifisme” published
in the fi rst issue of the monthly La France libre, November 1940. He cited the
military historian Hans Delbrück, who described pacifism as a weapon at the
service of the enemy, and he highlighted the harmful combination of pacifism
with Hitler’s “peace offensive” during the drôle de guerre. Alainism showed itself
to be nothing but a fallacy.
Indeed, the more doctrinaire Alainian pacifi sts became, precisely in the name
of integral pacifi sm, supporters—explicitly or implicitly—of Franco-German
collaboration. To these can be added the path followed by Jean Luchaire, who
transited from Briandism to collaboration via the Franco-German reconcilia-
tion, which led him before the fi ring squad after the war. Therefore, the dif-
ferent destinies of Aron’s contemporaries under the Occupation offer a mixed
picture. The resistance activity of Sartre is often questioned. After a brief
moment of reflecting on resistance in informal intellectual circles on his return
from the Stalag, he devoted himself to his works: L’Être et le Néant, published in
1943, the year of the fi rst performance of Les Mouches, which was followed by
Huis-Clos, before an audience made up partly of Germans—all this while he was
visiting the underground National Committee of Writers, founded by com-
munist intellectuals. A member of this Committee, awarded by the Académie
française in 1943 for his dissertation, La Création chez Stendhal, Jean Prévost was
killed by Germans during the uprising of the Maquis du Vercors. Canguilhem,
this prewar Alainian pacifi st, became a very resolute and active member of the
resistance. The same occurred with Jean Cavaillès, although the latter would
meet a tragic fate. When, in July 1945, his body was found in the moat of Arras’
citadel, Aron, in a moving tribute to his dear friend, wrote that “the warrior
remained a philosopher.”29
Indeed, the art of politics and the art of war are objects of knowledge. And
Aron attended to his shortcomings in these areas during the war.
The learning phase from 1940 to 194230 was facilitated by his encounter with
Stanislas Szymonzyk, a former officer and a great connoisseur of Clausewitz’s
work. It was Clausewitzian science that had passed through operating experi-
ence. Aron also submitted to General De Gaulle the article “La bataille de
France,” that would be published in January 1941 under the signature of the
“War Chronicler of La France libre,” that is, Szymonzyk’s remarks rethought
282 CH R I ST I A N BACH E LI E R
and reformulated by Aron and connected with Aron’s thinking on history and
politics.
In a long article, “La capitulation,” published in the fi rst issue of La France
libre, November 1940, Aron offered a light and shade analysis of the armistice.
This understanding of the confl ict did not prevent him from being unequivocally
enlisted in the camp of those continuing the struggle. This critical conscience at
work was an Aronian constant—and distanced Aron from orthodox Gaullism, as
any orthodoxy. For instance, when war was coming and extended to the world,
geostrategic thinking was revived. But, and even if German geopolitics frequently
ended up justifying Nazi and expansionist propaganda, Anglo-Saxon geopoli-
tics, for instance, Mackinder, was not exempt from Aron’s critical analysis either,
peculiarly against deterministic “geographical causation in universal history.”31
In this history in the making taking place under the dominion of war, there
appeared notably, as part of the strategic thought undertaken by Aron, his key-
article: “La stratégie totalitaire et l’avenir des démocraties,” May 1942. The
article deserves to be analyzed because it shows the junction of Aron’s political
thought and his strategic thinking.
Here, Aron develops the concepts of “military revolution” and “early mobi-
lization,” two concepts already discussed in “La bataille de France,” January
1941. He connects these concepts to the revolutionary dynamism he had previ-
ously identified as an essential datum of totalitarian states. This connection con-
tinues and develops Delbrück’s sociology of war. Thus, between total war and
total State, between which Halévy had observed the affinity or even connection,
the missing link of “early mobilization” is inserted. Moreover, Aron resumes
Guglielmo Ferrero’s notion of “hyperbolic war” and Ludendorff ’s “total war.”
Indeed, the total State is able to engage in a total war through the anticipated
mobilization enabled by its political structures. All of this is done in such a way
that it is able to avoid a hyperbolic war, which is a war of annihilation.
In this article of May 1942, Aron also emphasizes the development of his
thinking on modern Machiavellianism. He had already dealt with Machiavellian
Machiavellianism in his article “Le machiavélisme, doctrine des tyrannies mod-
ernes,” published in the fi rst issue of La France libre, November 1940. Later,
September 1943, the fall of il duce gave Aron an opportunity to illustrate vulgar
Machiavellianism: the cynicism of the “master of Mussolini” comes to punish
the clumsy disciple. With “La stratégie totalitaire et l’avenir des démocraties,”
Aron considers a moderate Machiavellianism, which includes elements inspired
by the “German Machiavelli,” Max Weber.
During the war, Aron frequently consulted the analysis of totalitarianism by
Élie Halévy. Aron introduced a new concept, “secular religions”: “doctrines
that, in the souls of our contemporaries, take the place of the faith that is no
more, placing the salvation of mankind in this world, in the more or less distant
future, and in the form of a social order yet to be invented.” He goes on to ethical
consequences: “The followers of these religions of collective salvation know of
nothing—not even the Ten Commandments, not even the rules of the catechism
or of any formal ethic—that is superior in dignity or authority to the aims of
their own movement.”32
EPILOGU E 283
With war ending, Aron questioned the power of France and the future of
Germany, and then he turned to the analysis of the incipient warlike peace.
Back in Paris at the end of September 1944, Aron wrote his fi rst article for
Combat published on October 25. In the postwar period, Aron opted for journal-
ism in order to be a “commentator on history in the making.” He fulfi lled this
role by working at the daily Combat, then Le Figaro for three decades, and fi nally
at the weekly L’Express, but also by publishing some important books.
His fi rst article for Combat, “Les conditions de la grandeur,” analyzed the
power of France, which seemed weakened by “poverty.” Aron witnessed France’s
relegation to second-rate status. In particular, he considered how demographic
and economic factors outweighed France’s geographical assets. Indeed, from the
fall of 1944 until May 1945, it was the time of the “disillusions of liberty.”
As Hitler’s defeat grew nearer, so too did the question of Germany’s fate. In
September 1944, Henry Morgenthau, the American Secretary of the Treasury,
proposed a pastoralization plan for Germany, consisting of deindustrialization and
dismembering of the country, most of the Western part of which was to go
to France. At the end of October 1944, Roosevelt completely renounced this
bucolic project.
The German question remained—especially in France, where numerous
lively debates took place in the form of press controversies, public conferences,
and political meetings. In an article in the weekly Point de Vue, July 5, 1945,
titled “Deux Allemagnes,” Aron took a position against dismemberment but in
favor of the economic integration of the Saar and industrial cooperation between
the Ruhr and Lorraine. Nonetheless, he concluded that it was probably neces-
sary to convince the Germans that “their defeat was irreversible,” to offer them
an “acceptable peace.” He defended a similar position in most of his articles in
another weekly Terre des Hommes in October and November 1945.
However, parallel to the evolution of his strategic thinking on the postwar
world, he abandoned his 1945 positions about Germany and thus wrote at the
beginning of 1947: “Two years ago the separation of the Ruhr and the Rhine
seemed the best solution. Today everyone knows that this position, rejected by
the three great powers, has no chance of success.”33
Germany was, indeed, the central stake for the great powers. Early on, Aron
evoked the “iron curtain,” for example in his article “Le partage de l’Europe”
in Point de Vue, July 26, 1945. The French position on the German question
was under the sway of the global rivalry and, consequently, under the risk “that
Germany was being used by Russia against the Anglo-Saxon powers,” or vice
versa. Furthermore, it was then acknowledged that the great powers wished
to rebuild Germany. In a series of articles published in Combat in January and
February 1947, Aron developed a new position: it was necessary to avoid, in De
Gaulle’s terms, a “new Rapallo,” that is, the German-Soviet collusion. However,
while rejecting the dismemberment of Germany desired by the Bainvillian
Gaullists, Aron nevertheless did consider the risks posed by a united Germany in
the future. This, coupled with the necessity of a balance of power in Europe, led
him to favor the rapprochement between France and the three Western occupa-
tion zones of Germany: “Nothing therefore opposed the assertion of a French
284 CH R I ST I A N BACH E LI E R
between the causes and the results of events, between human passions and the
effects of the acts they inspire, between confl icts of ideology and power and the
real issue of wars, fascinates the observer, who is tempted at one moment to
denounce the absurdity of history and at another its broad rationality. The only
truth accessible to positive cognition is the recognition of these contradictions.”
And the ignorance of these contradictions leads to mythology: “Mythologies
consist of the substitution of a single factor for the plurality of causes, of lending
unconditional value to a desired objective, and of failure to realize the distance
between the dreams of men and the destiny of societies.”43
This inclination to a facile Manicheanism that diverts oneself from interpret-
ing history in the making gave cause for Aron’s 1955 analysis of “the attitude of
the intellectuals, merciless toward the failings of the democracies but ready to
tolerate the worst crimes as long as they are committed in the name of proper
doctrines.”44 In this sense, L’Opium des intellectuels was also a work on history.
In the fi rst part, “Mythes politiques,” he analyzed the myths of the Left, of the
Revolution, and of the Proletariat: “These notions cease to be reasonable and
become mythical in consequence of an intellectual error . . . The common source
of these errors is a kind of visionary optimism combined with a pessimistic view
of reality.”45 Therefore, in the second part, “Idolâtrie de l’histoire,” he empha-
sizes that “neither the wars nor the revolutions of the twentieth century fit into
the theory which Marx adumbrated.”46 Aron thus proceeds to write a critique of
“the revolutionary idealism” contained in Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s Humanisme
et Terreur. Regarding “the alienation of the intellectuals,” Aron indicates the
effects on the intelligentsia of secular religion, and concludes interrogatively
with “Fin de l’âge idéologique?” and a wish: “If they alone can abolish fanati-
cism, let us pray for the advent of the skeptics.”47
The euphoric dreams of some of these intellectual fellow travelers vanished
the following year with the Hungarian uprising. Aron then thoroughly analyzed
this anti-totalitarian revolution.48 On the tenth anniversary of the Hungarian
revolution, he reiterated the essential and well-founded points of his past inter-
pretations and made some remarks about this history: “Thanks to the sacrifice of
the Hungarian people, other peoples in Eastern Europe have learned that their
hope for a ‘liberation from the outside’ is vain, and they are currently trying to
fi nd other ways less dramatic but perhaps not any less effective for ensuring their
own ‘inner’ liberation.” With emotion, Aron concluded on the moral signifi-
cance: “Historical tragedy, triumph in defeat, the Hungarian revolution will for-
ever remain one of those rare events that give men back some faith in themselves
and remind them, through their destiny, of the meaning of their destination: the
truth.”49
“Be true in everything, even on the subject of one’s Country. Every citizen
is obliged to die for his Country; no one is obliged to lie for it.” This quotation
of Montesquieu introduced Aron’s pamphlet, La Tragédie algérienne, comprised of
two memos (April 1956 and May 1957), and alluded to the duplicity of French
politicians about the Algerian question and Aron concluded his second memo by
asking: “What can an ordinary citizen do but express the anguish he feels and
appeal to everyone to have the courage to face the truth?” Here as well there is
EPILOGU E 287
the difficulty of judging the history that we experience. History in the making is
tragic, for it forces us to choose, and yet the rulers procrastinate in doing so: “No
miraculous solution will spare us the effort and pain of adapting to a changed
world.”50
Aron had more to say on the relations between events and will, history and
myth, in 1959 on the occasion of the publishing of the French translation of Politik
als Beruf, Weber’s famous lecture held in 1919: “History encourages mythologiz-
ing by its very structure, by the contrast between partial intelligibility and the
mystery of the whole, between the apparent role of human wills and the no less
apparent refutations which events infl ict on them by the hesitation of the spec-
tator between indignation, as if we were all responsible for what happens, and
passive horror, as if we were in the presence of a human inevitability.”51
His study of totalitarianisms was continued in one of his three courses at the
Sorbonne dedicated to industrial societies. This 1957–1958 course, Démocratie
et totalitarisme, was given in an atmosphere characterized by the events of 1958
and the relative liberalization of the Soviet regime. In his presentation of the
“concepts and variables,” he summed up that “the fundamental characteristic
of collectivities is the organization of powers” and established two categories
of industrial societies: constitutional-pluralistic regimes and monopolistic party
regimes.
A quarter of a century after his dissertation Introduction à la philosophie de
l’histoire, Aron appended to it a compilation of his articles published between
1946 and 1961. These articles could “enlighten, from different points of view,
one and the same problem, that of the history that we live through and try to
think.”52 This collection was published under the title Dimensions de la conscience
historique. This work, his thesis dissertation, and his Mémoires, constitute the trip-
tych of his thoughts on history.53 In Dimensions, Aron asks himself, on the one
hand, about the difficulty of judging one’s own epoch, and on the other hand,
about the relation between historical knowledge and human action. Regarding
the former, Aron reaffirmed the historian’s liberty, in particular with the present
that is both plural and restrictive. This is reflected to a certain extent in the latter
aspect: the uncertainty, unpredictability, and element of surprise that restores the
politician’s freedom to act. Nevertheless, this was a cause of regret for Aron and
he would express it in his Mémoires: “Are we prisoners of a system of beliefs that
we internalize since a very early age and that governs our distinction between
good and evil?”54
The last chapter of Dimensions, “L’Aube de l’histoire universelle,” the Third
Herbert Samuel Lecture delivered on February 18, 1960, announced a proj-
ect never realized: a History of the World since 1914, in which Aron wanted
“to convey to the reader the twofold feeling of human action and necessity, of
drama and process, of history as usual and the originality of industrial society.”55
The movement toward the unification of the world, “based solely on material,
technical, or economic factors,”56 led him to contemplate the divisions, “schism
between the communist world and the free world,” “rivalry for power and ideo-
logical competition,” “inequality of development,” and “diversity of customs
and beliefs,” this last type of division appearing more problematic to resolve: “we
288 CH R I ST I A N BACH E LI E R
Notes
1. Raymond Aron au Collège de France, documentary film directed by Alexandre
Astruc, FR3 (3rd French TV channel), October 30, 1977, transcription in
Raymond Aron, “Autoportrait,” Commentaire, no. 116, Winter 2006–2007, 904.
2. See Jean-François Sirinelli, Génération intellectuelle. Khâgneux et normaliens dans
l’entre-deux-guerres, Paris, Fayard, 1988.
3. Georges Canguilhem, “La problématique de la philosophie de l’histoire au début
des années 30,” in Alain Boyer, et al., Raymond Aron, La Philosophie de l’histoire et
les sciences sociales, Paris, Éditions de la Rue d’Ulm, 1999.
4. Raymond Aron au Collège de France, 904.
5. See Christian Malis, Raymond Aron et le débat stratégique 1930–1966, Paris,
Economica, 2005, 36ff.
6. Jean-Paul Sartre, Carnets de la drôle de guerre, augmented edition, Paris, Gallimard,
1995, 273.
7. Sartre, un film réalisé par Alexandre Astruc et Michel Contat, Paris, Gallimard, 1977,
44–45.
8. Raymond Aron, “De l’existence historique” (1979), manuscript published in
Cahiers de philosophie politique et juridique, no. 15, La politique historique de Raymond
Aron, 1989, 147.
9. Raymond Aron au Collège de France, loc. cit., 904.
10. Raymond Aron, Mémoires. 50 ans de réflexion politique, Paris, Julliard, 1983, com-
plete edition, Robert Laffont, 2010, 86.
11. Aron, “De l’existence historique,” 148.
12. Raymond Aron, Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire: Essai sur les limites de
l’objectivité historique, Paris, Gallimard, 1938, 331.
13. Ibid.
14. Aron, Mémoires, 105.
15. See Nicolas Baverez, Raymond Aron: un moraliste au temps des idéologies, Paris,
Flammarion, 1993, revised edition, 2005, 80; Philippe Raynaud, “Raymond
Aron et Max Weber. Épistémologie des sciences sociales et rationalisme critique,”
Commentaire, no. 28–29, Winter 1984–1985, 213–221.
16. See Raymond Aron, La Sociologie allemande contemporaine, Paris, Alcan, 1935,
197ff.
17. Raymond Aron, “The Philosophy of History,”Chambers’s Encyclopædia, London
and Edinburgh, 1950, 150–155.
18. Raymond Aron, Essai sur la théorie de l’histoire dans l’Allemagne contemporaine. La
philosophie critique de l’histoire, Paris, Vrin, 1938, new edition, Le Seuil, 1991,
290–291.
19. Bernard Groethuysen, “Une philosophie critique de l’histoire,” La Nouvelle Revue
française, no. 313, October 1, 1939, 623–629.
20. Aron, La Sociologie allemande contemporaine, 123–133.
21. See Raymond Aron, “L’Ère des tyrannies d’Élie Halévy,” Revue de métaphysique et
de morale, May 1939, 283–307.
22. Aron, “De l’existence historique,” 148.
EPILOGU E 291
Elisabeth Dutartre-Michaut
The complete bibliography of works by and about Raymond Aron is available on the
website dedicated to Raymond Aron: http://raymond-aron.ehess.fr. So the proposed ref-
erences below are just a bibliographical guide. When there is an American translation of
a book by Raymond Aron, it appears under the original title.
Posthumous Works
* Les Dernières Années du siècle, Paris, Julliard, “Commentaire,” 1984.
* History, Truth, Liberty, Selected Writings of Raymond Aron, Chicago, University of Chicago
Press, 1985 (with a memoir of Edward Shils).
* Sur Clausewitz, Bruxelles, Complexe, “Historiques,” 1987; reissue Bruxelles, Complexe,
2005.
* Études sociologiques, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, “Sociologies,” 1988.
* Essais sur la condition juive contemporaine, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 1989.
* Leçons sur l’histoire: cours du Collège de France, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 1989; reissue
Paris, Le Livre de Poche, “Références Histoire,” 2007.
* Chroniques de guerre: La France libre 1940–1945, Paris, Gallimard, 1990.
* Les Articles du Figaro, t. I: La Guerre froide 1947–1955, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 1990.
* Les Articles du Figaro, t. II: La Coexistence 1955–1965, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 1994.
* Les Articles du Figaro, t. III: Les Crises 1965–1977, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 1997.
* Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 1993; reissue Paris, Le Livre
de Poche, “Biblio Essais,” 1995.
* Une histoire du XX e siècle, Paris, Plon, 1996; reissue Paris, Perrin, “Tempus,” 2012.
* Introduction à la philosophie politique: démocratie et révolution, Paris, Le Livre de Poche,
“Références. Inédit sciences sociales,” 1997.
* Le Marxisme de Marx, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 2002; reissue Paris, Le Livre de poche,
“Références. Histoire,” 2004.
* De Giscard à Mitterrand 1977–1983, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 2005.
* Penser la liberté, penser la démocratie, Paris, Gallimard, “Quarto,” 2005.
* Les Sociétés modernes, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, “Quadrige/Grands Textes,”
2006.
* Liberté et égalité: cours au Collège de France, Paris, Éditions de l’École des hautes études en
sciences sociales, “Audiographie,” 2013.
BI BLIOGR A PHICA L GUIDE 297
* Davis, Reed M., A Politics of Understanding: The International Thought of Raymond Aron,
Baton Rouge, LSU Press, 2009.
* De Ligio, Giulio, La Tristezza del pensatore politico: Raymond Aron e il primato del politico,
Bologna, 2007.
* De Ligio, Giulio (ed.), Raymond Aron, penseur de l’Europe et de la nation, Bruxelles, Peter
Lang, 2012.
* Dobek, Rafał, Raymond Aron: Dialog z histori ą i polityk ą, Pozna ń, Wydawnictwo
Pozna ń skie, 2005.
* Dutartre, Élisabeth, Fonds Raymond Aron: inventaire, Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de
France, École des hautes études en sciences sociales, 2007.
* Dutartre, Élisabeth (ed.), La Démocratie au XXIe siècle. Centenaire de la naissance de Raymond
Aron: colloque international de Paris tenu les 11 et 12 mars 2005 à l’École des hautes études en
sciences sociales, Paris, Éditions de Fallois, 2007.
* Fessard, Gaston, La Philosophie historique de Raymond Aron, Paris, Julliard, 1980.
* Guibernau i Berdún, Maria Montserrat, El Pensament sociològic de Raymond Aron, Moià,
Raima, 1988.
* Holeindre, Jean-Vincent (ed.), “Raymond Aron et les relations internationales. 50 ans après
Paix et guerre entre les nations,” Etudes internationales (Université Laval, Québec), vol. 43,
no. 3, September 2012, 319–457.
* Judt, Tony, The Burden of Responsibility: Blum, Camus, Aron and the French Twentieth
Century, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1998.
* Lapparent, Olivier de, Raymond Aron et l’Europe. Itinéraire d’un Européen dans le siècle,
Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, Peter Lang, 2010.
* Lassalle, José Maria (ed.), Raymond Aron: un liberal resistente, Madrid, FAES, 2005.
* Launay, Stephen, La Pensée politique de R. Aron, Paris, Presses universitaires de France,
1995.
* Mahoney, Daniel, The Liberal Political Science of Raymond Aron: A Critical Introduction,
Lanham (MD), Rowman and Littlefield, 1992.
* Mahoney, Daniel and Bryan-Paul Frost (eds.), Political Reason in the Age of Ideology:
Essays in Honor of Raymond Aron, New Brunswick (NJ), Transaction Publishers, 2007.
* Malis, Christian, Raymond Aron et le débat stratégique français 1930–1966, Paris,
Économica, 2005.
* Mesure, Sylvie, Raymond Aron et la raison historique, Paris, Vrin, 1984.
* Molina Cano, Jerónimo, Raymond Aron, realista político. Del maquiavelismo a la crítica de
las religiones seculares, Madrid, Ediciones Sequitur, 2013.
* Mouric, Joël, Raymond Aron et l’Europe, Rennes, Presses universitaires de Rennes,
2013.
* Novák, Miroslav, Mezi demokracií a totalitarismem. Aronova politická sociologie industriálních
spole čnosti 20. stoleti, Brno, Masarykova univerzita, 2007.
* Oppermann, Matthias, Raymond Aron und Deutschland. Die erteidigung der Freiheit und das
Problem des Totalitarismus, Ostfildern, J. Thorbecke, 2008.
* Piquemal, Alain, Raymond Aron et l’ordre international, Paris, Albatros, 1978.
BI BLIOGR A PHICA L GUIDE 299
* Sirinelli, Jean-François, Deux intellectuels dans le siècle: Sartre et Aron, Paris, Fayard,
1995.
* Stark, Joachim, Das unvollendete Abenteuer: Geschichte, Gesellschaft und Politik im Werk
Raymond Arons, Würzburg, Königshausen und Neumann, 1986.
* Van Velthoven, Paul, Het verantwoorde engagement: filosofie en politiek bij Raymond Aron,
Stesterberg, Uitgeverij Aspekt, 2005.
* Zuniga, Luis R., Raymond Aron y la sociedad industrial, Madrid, Instituto de la opinion
publica, 1973.
INDEX
Alain, 3, 5, 21, 32, 78, 240, 275–6, Cavaillès, Jean, 4, 275, 281
279–81 Chaliand, Gérard, 29
Alainism, 278, 281 Churchill, Winston, 50, 79, 139
Althusser, Louis, 7, 192, 220, 221, 223 Cicero, 150, 160
America. See United States Clausewitz, Carl von, 4, 9, 17, 20, 24–6,
antinomy, 64, 66, 199, 207, 208, 210, 232, 29, 46, 61, 64, 67, 77–90, 107, 115–16,
241, 257, 263, 277, 278, 284, 288 195, 205, 211, 278, 281
Arendt, Hannah, 45, 126 Clausewitzian, 25, 61, 64, 79, 80, 82, 84,
Aristotelian, 31, 41, 122, 124, 128, 154, 281
160 Cold War, 3, 4, 6, 8–10, 12, 16–17, 22–3,
Aristotle, 20, 37, 41, 68, 122–3, 126, 128, 25–6, 38, 40–1, 45–9, 51–3, 60–2,
131–2, 150, 160, 194–5, 197, 198, 250, 65–6, 74, 78–81, 85, 91, 93–6, 103,
266 105, 108, 113, 129, 177, 184–5, 187,
225, 285
Baehr, Peter, 145 communism, 4–6, 22, 28, 38–9, 45, 49,
Baldwin, Hanson W., 79 53–4, 61, 79, 92, 95–6, 112, 140–1,
Baron, Hans, 150, 159 143, 145, 151, 177, 238–9, 264–6, 272,
Bell, Daniel, 266 275, 280, 285
Berlin, Isaiah, 214 Comte, August, 53, 122, 125, 262, 265,
Bernanos, Georges, 139 269
Besançon, Alain, 142–5 Constant, Benjamin, 3, 262, 268
Bismarck, Otto von, 208 constitutional-pluralist regime, 37, 102,
Bonald, Louis de, 246 103, 127, 132, 141, 142, 145, 158, 159,
Bouglé, Célestin, 3, 106, 107 252, 254, 256, 257, 287
Bouthoul, Gaston, 70 Cunhal, Alvaro, 92
Britain, 47, 49, 51, 52, 171, 173, 186
Brossollet, Guy, 27 Dahl, Robert, 103, 149
Brunschvicg, Léon, 3, 5, 21, 106, 197, 280 de Gaulle, Charles, 3, 5, 6, 9, 22, 38, 271,
Bruun, Hans Henrik, 208 280, 281, 283
Bülow, Heinrich von, 82 de Man, Hendrik, 178–9
Burke, Edmund, 37, 41 de Staël, Germaine, 268
Burkean, 31, 37, 41 Déat, Marcel, 178–9
Burnham, James, 45, 152–5, 158–60, 193, Delbrück, Hans, 78–81, 83–4, 87, 281,
241 282, 284
Dilthey, Wilhelm, 20, 115, 278
Canguilhem, Georges, 106, 197, 275, 281 Durieux, Benoît, 85
Carcassonne, Élie, 250 Durkheim, Émile, 122, 205, 245, 259,
Castro, Fidel, 84, 92 262
302 IN DEX
Engels, Friedrich, 169, 222 Hitler, Adolf, 4, 22, 25, 32–9, 44, 48, 49,
ethic/ethics, 36, 121, 130, 139–41, 191, 61, 77, 79, 83–5, 105, 137–9, 151, 231,
193, 194–5, 206–8, 210, 212–13, 220, 241, 276, 281, 283
235, 239, 276–8, 282 Hitlerian/Hitlerism/Hitlerite/
Hitlerization, 3, 35, 38, 41, 42, 139,
Fessard, Father Gaston, 35 141
Fest, Joachim, 38 Hobbes, Thomas, 21, 150
Fourastié, Jean, 171 Hoffmann, Stanley, 60, 73, 262
France, 4–7, 9, 12, 16, 22–4, 28, 31–6, Husserl, Edmund, 5, 205, 276
38, 40, 42, 47, 49, 50–2, 61, 68, 80,
82, 86, 92, 94, 103, 105, 108, 113, international relations, 2, 7, 8, 11, 16, 17,
120, 125, 138, 149, 152–3, 166, 173–4, 19–23, 27, 35, 40, 46, 51, 59–61, 65,
178, 182–4, 186–7, 192, 221, 228, 67–70, 72, 81, 96, 105, 107–8, 110,
231, 234, 243, 262, 270–1, 276, 279, 113–14, 191, 209, 263, 268, 284–5
283–4
Frederick the Great, 83 Jew/Jewish, 5, 6, 27, 32, 61, 86, 105, 139,
Friedmann, Georges, 275, 280 214, 262
Furet, François, 4, 9 Jouvenel, Bertrand de, 7, 275
Galbraith, John Kenneth, 171–2 Kant, Immanuel, 10, 20, 21, 40, 193,
Gallois, Pierre Marie, 85 197–203, 226, 276
Gellner, Ernest, 94, 98 Kantian/Kantianism, 17, 21, 66, 121, 139,
Germany, 4–5, 16, 20–1, 31–4, 37–8, 47, 193, 197–9, 201, 205, 213, 214, 288,
49–51, 61, 68, 77–9, 83–5, 94, 131, 290
137–8, 179, 187, 197, 205, 208–10, 221, Kennan, George, 46, 49, 56, 96, 99
231, 240, 262, 276, 278, 283–4 Keynes, John Maynard, 32
Girard, René, 85 Keynesian, 11, 180, 183
Gorbachev, Mikhail, 96 Khrushchev, Nikita, 52
Gordon, Thomas, 161 Kissinger, Henry, 1, 4, 21, 46, 60, 80, 91,
Grotius, 67 92, 96
Guicciardini, Francesco, 152, 160 Kojève, Alexandre, 5, 74
Krätke, Michael R., 222
Halévy, Elie, 3, 5, 107, 121, 149, 151, 279, Kristol, Irving, 198
282
Hannibal, 78 Labarthe, André, 181
Harrington, James, 160 Lefort, Claude, 150, 242
Harrington, Michael, 172 Lefranc, Georges, 178
Hassner, Pierre, 113 Lenin, Vladimir, 25, 77, 92, 140, 143, 147,
Hayek, Friedrich, 4, 8, 103, 185–7, 226, 238, 266
249, 268 Leninist/Leninism, 39, 53, 65, 71, 84,
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 5, 20, 93–6, 138–40, 143–4, 227
21, 74, 198, 201, 219, 221–3, 235, 250 Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 4, 12, 115, 261,
Hegelian/Hegelianism, 105, 198, 221–5, 276
278 liberalism, 3, 8, 9, 12–13, 22, 31, 33–5,
Heidegger, Martin, 5, 205, 276 37–41, 70, 103, 132, 149, 156–7, 160–1,
Heideggerian, 280 177, 180, 183–7, 189, 191, 198, 209–10,
Hepp, Robert, 84 226, 272
Herodotus, 201 Lipset, Seymour Martin, 101, 187
Hirsch, Étienne, 183 Locke, John, 155–6, 161
historicism, 20, 108–9, 120, 125–6, 158, Luchaire, Jean, 275, 281
221, 258, 277 Ludendorff, Erich, 77–80, 82–4, 282
IN DEX 303