Samuel A. Chambers - The Lessons of Rancière-Oxford University Press (2012) PDF
Samuel A. Chambers - The Lessons of Rancière-Oxford University Press (2012) PDF
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam
AH rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced. stored in a retrieval system.
or transmitted. in any form or by any means. without the prior permission in writing of
Oxford University Press. or as expressly permitted by law. by license. or under terms agreed
with the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning
reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department,
Oxford University Press, at the address above.
135798642
Introduction 3
Politics 38
2 Police 65
3 Litera rity 88
4 Critique 12 3
Index 21 3
acques Rancière proc1aims that it is possible to teach what one does not
know. Applying this radical pedagogical principle to the teachings of a book
that a book can teach something the author does not know. What this
book teaches, if anything at an, is surely something other than, something
much more than, the sum of my knowledge. There is thus a profound gap
between the intelligence of a book and the will of an author. This book, in-
c1uding its errors, is "mine," then, in the sense that 1 have chosen the final
arrangement of chapters and sections and sentences and words. However, the
intelligence of the book belongs to no one, and it is shared by many. Here
1 would like to name and note my gratitude to sorne of those many.
The privilege of getting to do political theory at Johns Hopkins University
sometimes feels like cheating. Primary thanks go to my immediate faculty
colleagues in political theory: Jane Bennett, Bill Connolly, and Jennifer Cul-
bert. 1 am also grateful for the support of an my outstanding colleagues in the
political science department, inc1uding recent postdoctoral visitors. Numerous
colleagues across campus have helped to support me or to sustain this project;
in particular 1 would like to thank Amanda Anderson, Veena Das, Frances
Ferguson, Aaron Goodfellow, Siba Grovogui, Paola Marrati, and Adam Shein-
gate. Of course, the vibrancy of a graduate institution depends utterly on the
graduate students themselves; in this context, 1 am delighted to acknowledge
the vital contributions to my thinking made by seminar students over the past
four years. Nathan Gies, Jairus Grove, Chas Phillips, and Drew Walker aIl
contributed directly to this project in various, significant ways. 1 also thank the
many undergraduate students who have eagerly grappled with Rancière's writ..
ings and along the way taught me so much about them.
Perhaps most importantly, 1 want to express my deepest gratitude to the
many readers that 1 have been so lucky to have as this project has developed
over the years. Since 1 have sorne, the following is a
list of those who were kind enough to read, comment, criticize, or otherwise
respond to various portions of the manuscript at sorne point in its develop-
ment: Paul Apostolidis, Ben Arditi, Jane Bennett, Paul Bowman, Rebecca
Terrell Carver, Bill Connolly, Jennifer Culbert, Jean-Philippe Deranty,
Lisa Disch, Kim Evans, Eric Fassin, Alan Finlayson, Nathan Gies, Jairus
Grove, Stephanie Hershinow, Bonnie Honig, Adam Kennard, Patch en Markell,
Todd May, Kirstie McClure, Aletta Norval, Joel OIson, Michael O'Rourke,
Davide Panagia, Chas Phillips, Andrew Schaap, Michael Shapiro, Jon Simons,
Richard Stamp, Jeremy Valentine, Drew Walker, Liz Wingrove, Karen Zivi,
and John Zumbrunnen.
There are a few individuals whose contributions to the book constitute debts
1 could never repay but which 1 am very pleased to acknowledge here. Ran-
cière calls learning an act of translation, and 1 learned a great deal from Anne
Kantel (Gelman), Nathan Gies (Greek), and Rebecca Brown and Lisa Disch
(French). It has been an absolute joy to work with Angela Chnapko at Oxford
University Press. Her sympathetic understanding of the project and her respon-
siveness and professionalism have helped me enormously in bringing this
book to completion. 1 thank Barbara Price for her brilliant and deft editorial
work. 1 am also grateful to Tabitha Panter, who provided early and inspiring
mock-ups of the cover design. The completion of the project might never have
occuned were it not for the diligent, insightful, and always intelligent research
assistance provided by Nathan Gies. Thanks go also to the Krieger School of
Arts and Sciences and to the Department ofPolitical Science at Johns Hopkins
for providing the funds for Nathan's RA position. Stephanie Hershinow gave
the book one of its last, and thus most important, reads: 1 could not have asked
for a more learned, conscientious, and careful scrutiny of the text. Finally, 1 am
enOlmously grateful to Bonnie Honig for an untimely and invaluable reading
of the manuscript.
1 owe a special debt to Ben Arditi, who planted the seeds for this book just
over a decade ago when he invited me to give a paper on Jacques Rancière, a
thinker whose works 1 had never read, at a conference in London. 1 am deeply
grateful to participants and audience members at that 2003 Goldsmiths Col-
lege conference who helped germinate those seeds: Paul Bowman, Terrell
Carver, Mick Dillon, Alan Finlayson, Jim Martin, and Alex Thomson. Parts of,
and pieces related to, this project were given in a number of settings. 1 thank
aIl of the participants and audience members and note special thanks to the
hosts or conference organizers: Department of Government, University of
Essex, November 2006 (thanks to Aletta Norval, David Howarth, and Jason
Glynos); Department of Poli tic al Science, Johns Hopkins University, Decem-
ber 2007; Western Poli tic al Science Association annual meeting, March 2009;
American Political Science Association annual meeting, September 2009; Po-
litical and Moral Thought Seminar, Johns Hopkins University, March 20II
x 1 Acknowledgments
to John Northwestern conference on JL'.<'LlH-,'·"'"
Acknowledgments 1 xi
of teaching - to to to the world. Those 1-''-''-,,"U~V~jl'V
claims emerge out of a reading of Rancière, but the claims themselves are not
Rancière's and the reading is not simply mine. use my own words to say what
l want to say about teaching, leaming, and pedagogy, but the animating
assumptions share with Rebecca. And we share them in the sense not that
each of us possesses them (and therefore we "agree" with one another) but in
the sense that the possession itself is joint; these principles can only be held
onto by holding them together. The Rancièrean "assumption of equality" that
makes a partnership possible cannot be an assumption that one person makes
or grants to the other. The assumption is itself the condition of possibility for
the "we," and for the "1."
xii 1 Acknowledgments
1 1 n
HIS BOOK HAS A trick title. The Lessons of Rancièrel sounds undernand-
ing and painless enough, since in echoing the cornrnon cliché, "the les-
sons of history," the title rnakes it sound as though this book will tell its
readers what they need to know about Jacques Rancière in the sarne way as
historians rnight tell their readers what they need to know about a particular
tirne period or event in history. In other words, the title says to the reader: there
is this person called Rancière, who has likely written sorne books; but you do
not really need to read his books since you can read this one; and it will explain
to you "the lessons" of Rancière's writings. You rnight also expect then, know-
ing that this is a book that fits into the broadly defined field of conternporary
political theory, that it would be a book "on Rancière" as a political theorist, or
that it would systernatically construct his overall political theory. Such a book
would naturally be structured by a series of explications of Rancière's writ-
ings, places where 1 tell rny reader what Rancière is saying, what it rneans, and
ultirnately draw sorne conclusions (i.e., the lessons).
This is not such a book, because an approach like the one described above
will not work in the case of Rancière. In order to write a book deterrnined to
give a general overview of the political thought of Rancière, or to develop and
defend "Rancière's political theory," one would have to either ignore or refute
Rancière's own explicit clairns about the relationship between his writings, on
the one hand, and systernatic theories of politics, on the other. 2 In 2009,
Rancière wrote a response piece to a series of articles on his work published as
a special issue of the journal Parallax. He chose to reply not according to the
tirne-honored tradition of the response essay: narnely, by clarifying certain
points, explaining his central tenets and precepts, and refuting criticisms of
"his theory." Instead, Rancière gives the essay its own deceptive title: ''A Few
Rernarks on the Method of Jacques Rancière," by Jacques Rancière. And he
writes the entire piece in the third person. Thus, he opens the essay by writing
never intended to a
literature, cinema or anything else. He thinks that there is already a good deal
of them and he loves trees enough to avoid destroying them to add one more
to aIl those available on the market" (Rancière 2009b: l Ran-
cière confirms that he has no "theory of" anything, but certainly not of politics
2009b: l r6). The Lessons of Rancière therefore cannot be a teach-
er's guide to Rancière's political theory, since that sort of class planning would
necessarily need to disregard one of Rancière's chief lessons.
The title of this book says and does more than it might first appear to say or
do because one of the centrallessons of Rancière's work - indeed, perhaps his
most important teaching is a lesson about the "les son" (Rancière and Oliver
2008: 172). In choosing the title 1 have, 1 do not mean to suggest that my book
is a systematic account of Rancière's political theory, but rather to convey a
crucial dimension of Rancière's work: his claims about "lessons," his argu-
ments about teaching and pedagogy, prove fundamental to his project. There-
fore in this book 1 avoid systematizing Rancière's writings; 1 resist morphing
those diverse and concrete interventions into a static or comprehensive "theory
of politics"; and 1 both follow and question Rancière when he cuts against the
grain of contemporary political theory. Rather than merely explicate Rancière's
own texts, 1 mobilize them for my own polemical interventions into debates
over democratic politics. 1 thereby refuse to draw out the lessons of Rancière's
texts in the manner of a series of morals, precepts, or mIes. It is because of this
approach, and not at an despite it, that 1 am committed to thinking through the
"les sons" of Rancière in another sense. Above aIl Rancière wants to "teach"
his readers something absolutely crucial about teaching. In making this claim
1 cannot overstate the extent to which Rancière advocates an utterly radical
pedagogy, one that completely reconceives aIl the central elements of "school-
ing," including the concepts of teacher, student, intelligence, and knowledge.
Rancière thinks it possible to teach without knowing; he believes that the best
schoolmasters can operate not on the assumption of their expertise, but on the
equality of intelligence; and this means ultimately that Rancière contends that
we can "teach what we do not know." The best schoolmasters are ignorant
schoolmasters.
Below in my discussion of equality, and scattered throughout the chapters
of this book, 1 will come back to this radical pedagogy and to the resistance to
a certain fonn of epistemological and ontological mastery - a resistance that
forms the backbone of Rancière's wlitings and critical investigations. Here 1
want to make just one specific and central point about the very idea of "lessons."
The lessons of Rancière are not the so-caIled les sons of history for many rea-
sons, but chief among them must be that for Rancière even the lessons of his-
tory are not the "lessons of history," as we typically understand that phrase.
Between 1975 and 1985 Rancière played a central role in the journal Les ré-
voltes logiques, wliting numerous single- and co-authored articles, contributing
or the "new philosophers," the poor (the plebs, the proletariat) are kept in their
place to the benefit of those who would represent them. Rancière '-''V'''''HU~''''UU
contests, above aH else, this confinement of the poor to a
sphere, this creation of a pure category for the poor.
the 2011 English translation of his contributions to Les révoltes logiques, Ran-
cière describes the collective project as an effort to hold on to a of
emancipation, of revolution, of revoIt, without jettisoning or ignoring "the
issues, complexities and contradictions of two centuries of struggle" (Rancière
201 lb: 9) - without ignoring, in other words, the fact that the particular lives
and struggles of workers rarely match the categories of political philosophy,
sociology, or revolutionary the01'y. Among many other things, this effort to
maintain the possibility of emancipation and revoIt while keeping one's ears
open to the voices of definite workers (not philosophical categories) entails a
steadfast refusaI to find in history mere "lessons" for contemporary political
programs (Rancière 201 lb: 12).
Rancière's career-long refusaI of the category "the pure proletarian" always
remains tied to his understanding of history, on the one hand, and to his radical
conception of pedagogy, on the other. A quotation from the editorial collective
of Les révoltes logiques captures these connections: at most, history teaches us
to "recognize the moment of a choice, of the unforeseeable, to draw from his-
tory neither lessons, nor, exactly, explanations, but the principle of a vigilance
toward what there is that is singular in each call to order and in each confronta-
tion" (Rancière et al. 1977: 6; quoted in Ross 2009: 29; and Ross 2002: 128).
History shows us that a choice has been made, but history's real teaching lies
in demonstrating that such a choice can never be "explained" post hoc (and
sUl'ely never predicted beforehand). We learn from history a vigilance toward
the singular, a capacity to sense that "something is happening." As we shaH
see, a moment of happening might serve as another name for "politics" in
Rancière's unorthodox and polemical account. Moreover, as Kristin Ross puts
it in her own gloss on this passage, "To happen, events must be perceived and
acknowledged as such" (Ross 2009: 29). This, then, gives us sorne indication
of the lessons we might learn from Rancière: first, an emphasis on the vigi-
lance that history te aches (and concomitantly an attentiveness to history itself);
second, a capacity to perceive and acknowledge events when they happen.
1 translate this second lesson into a capacity for surprise an understanding of
politics and history that remains open to the very possibility (the constitutive
necessity, even) of surprises. For Rancière, poli tics is always a surprise (see
Arendt 1958; cf. Beltrân 2009: 601).3
INTRODUCTION 1
To stakes of this it would contrast it with better
known, tradition al approaches to polities. Take liberal political theory, on the
one hand, and social science, on the other. These two names point to distinct
disciplinary fields with their own epistemologieal and ontologieal commit-
ments and their own everyday practices of knowledge production and dissemi-
nation. Nevertheless, liberal theorists and social scientists have at least one
thing in common: they do not like surprises. 4 ln the first case, the Lockean
theory of limited government, which forms the core of liberalism's basic
tenets, 5 emerges as a response to the tumult of the seventeenth century in
England, and it aims, especially, to provide safety and security for the growing
merchant class. The hemistic deviee of a "state of nature" - in whieh aIl au-
tonomous individuals are posited as free, equal, and capable of acquüing prop-
through the natural right of exclusion (the legitimate capacity to say "this
is mine") makes it possible for Locke to argue that aIl valid governmental
authority rests implicitly upon the consent of the governed. Locke thereby cre-
ates a purpose or telos for political society: namely, the protection of individual
life, liberty, and property. Thus, a liberal theory of limited government pro-
vides a check against any power that would encroach upon individual rights or
property. This tale will prove familiar to most readers, but 1 tell it again briefly
here to emphasize the liberal commitment to order, to structure, to a certain
form of hierarchy, and ab ove aU to the idea of political stability. Much like
seventeenth-century English Parliamentarians and the rising bourgeoisie, crea-
tures in Locke's state of nature would above alllike to be secure. Locke wants
to ward off the surprise of agents of the king knocking on the door - which is
not to make the mistake of characterizing Locke as wholly opposed to king-
ship, but to indicate his fundamental opposition to what he calls "Absolute,
Arbitrary Power" (Locke 1988: 284).
ln the second case, to the extent that they approach social phenomena seek-
ing systematic explanations, twenty-first-century social scientists search for
their own form of order. The social scientific modus operandi therefore con-
sists in the attempt to measure social and political life, to quantify it, to
"operationalize" ideas, concepts, or phenomena so that they can become "vari-
ables." No practice captures the heart of the social scientific enterprise better
than that of coding. Coding is the process of translating one form of data into
discrete and often quantifiable categories. The activity of coding survey or in-
terview responses wherein a subject's answers to a range of questions are
placed into categories and usually assigned numbers - proves particularly sig-
nificant for understanding the relationship between social science and the poli-
tics of surprise. Coding creates, quite straightforwardly and plainly on the
surface, a grid of intelligibility. Answers that do not fit the code are either
made to conform somehow (for example, taking an apparent non sequitur re-
sponse to a preference question as a sign of negative preference) or rejected
entirely. In this way, coding allows social scientists to create an order to the
1NTRODUCTION 1 7
entails an of the world that renders newness,
impossible. If we could always predict, we would never be surprised. As Ran-
cière himself says, "Political science['s] ... axiom is that nothing is ever surpris-
(Ranci ère 2010a: 12). Thus, the proper social scientific response to a real
surprise will always be to seek a post hoc explanation that would have elimi-
nated such surprise if only we had developed the explanation earlier. In this way,
social science operates in this bizarre conditional perfect tense of the "would
have happened," and this means that while social scientists are surely sometimes
surprised, they always strive to eliminate the possibility of such surprise. Liber-
alism, in complementary fashion, provides a framework in which aIl problems,
issues, confticts can be resolved, sorted out, and contained. The interest-group
calculus of negotiation and compromise commits liberalism to a math without
remainder, and therefore to a vision of a world without surprises (Honig 1993).
What, then, would it mean to rethink poli tics and history as full of sur-
prises?lP How could we restore to our understanding of politics - inject into
our study of politics the very sense of wonder and shock that the world
shared while watching the events in Egypt at the beginning of 20 II? What
would it mean for the word politics to point not toward legislative decisions
and judicial decrees, but to moments of irruption like those in Egypt?
Democratie Politics
INTRODUCTION 1 9
way that is free from the stale debates over liberal and deliberative and
Ilot yoked entirely to questions of institutional systems or regime structure.
This book implicitly asks (as Rancière so frequently does) the question, "What
is democracy?" The question proves significant because it is posed in terms
that have nothing to do with voting schemes and party systems, but everything
to do with politics in a far more radical and essential sense (what Rancière
calls, simply enough, la politique). In other words, and above aU else, this is a
book on democratic politics, wherein l insist on always returning to Rancière's
radical understanding of democracy as a "miscount." The democratic miscount
is untimely; miscount names the fundamental paradox of democratic politics
as the taking part in politics of those who have no part in politics.
The chapters herein focus first and foremost on seeking a distinct, theo-
retically fecund, and politically productive conception of democracy and
democratic politics. Rancière's powerful, polemical, and unique conception
of poli tics as dissensus motivates and enables this project to just the extent
that Rancière's conception makes it possible to distinguish decisively
between a liberal politics, on the one hand, and a democratic politics, on the
other. By linking politics fundamentally with the democratic - there is no
non-democratic poli tics for Rancière; for something to be "poli tics" accord-
ing to his definition, it must somehow bring about a democratic moment -
Rancière lets us see the unique and very much distinct logics of liberalism
and democracy. Viewed through the Rancièrean lens, a liberal order is an
order of the police: a hierarchical ordering and allotment of roles (and rights)
that operates according to a logic of domination. As l discuss in detail in
Chapter Two, Rancière does not merely denigrate police orders, since police
orders are not simply bad: such orders do a lot of good things, and we can
improve them. Nor does he mean to suggest a Manichean distinction between
the police as Evil and politics as Good. Nonetheless, according to the po-
lemical framing that Rancière provides, the constitution and maintenance of
a liberal order cannot be given the name "politics" and the two phenomena
must not be confiated. Politics is that phenomenon that disrupts the police
order any police order, even a liberal one - and confronts it with the logic
of equality.
The Lessons of Rancière thereby seeks to disentangle democratic politics
from liberalism. Its goal is to wrench a thinking of democratic politics free
from its entrapment within the confines of liberalism. In formulating this claim
in severe terms, l should also emphasize that my point is not to dismiss aIl of
liberalism, to suggest we eliminate liberal institutions, or to deny the impor-
tance of those institutions to citizens. Below, and throughout th~ book, l draw
a contrast between liberal police orders, on the one hand, and democratic poli-
tics, on the other. However, just as there are better and worse police orders
and just as we cannot do away with or ever eliminate policing, so also are there
better and worse liberal orders - and one cannot do away with liberalism
1NTRODUCTION 1 11
and liberalism in order to show
ti""i"Y'lrlr"l'Clr"U however much work side
side and however much they are thought together, they are not the same
work together. In her so-called paradoxical conception of
,"',""'U, Mouffe holds on to the idea of a liberal-democratic "regime." But as
!J'V
show in the example below, this is just the notion that Rancière rejects. The
gap that Rancière's thinking of poli tics opens between democracy and liberal-
ism is therefore one that mns aIl the way across or an the way down; it is not
p;.. ..
U i "... 'y or otherwise crossed. For this reason, 1 see Rancière's thinking of
(discussed in the next section) as expressing a more radical form
of political paradox than the "constitutive tensions" on which Mouffe centers
her account 2000: 5).
This unlike Mouffe's, does not provide another critique of Rawls, of
HabermalS, or of liberal institutions. One can already find a very long and excel-
lent list of such critiques. Instead of adding another one to the pile, this book
gerlenltes its own (very much oblique, but no less fundamental) challenge to lib-
eral and deliberative approaches to political theory. It uses a Rancièrean thinking
of democratic politics as leverage against the tendency to collapse democracy into
the broader terms of liberalism. Nor do 1 see a need to elaborate a critique of
Mouffe (or Schmitt): while 1 acknowledge a set of resonances between her proj-
ect and mine, the differences also prove stark. As 1 will show, the force of Ran-
cière's thinking is never aimed at the development ofliberalism - hence the power
of his writings to help us grasp the unique logic of democracy - and ultimately his
account of democratic politics simply proves incompatible with Mouffe's.
But if my goal is not to advance liberal democracy, nor to theorize, validate,
or reform it as a regime, this raises the question of why or how the difference
between Iiberalism and democracy matters in the first place. The book itself
offers the fullest answer to that question, as it makes the broadest possible case
for a Rancièrean democratic politics. Here, let me offer a brief and simple, yet
concrete and illustrative, example. Although Americans are often said to exer-
cise "full democratic rights" at the age of eighteen, citizens are expressly prohibited
by the Constitution from holding national office until they are older (twenty-five for
the House of Representatives; thirty for the Senate; thirty-five for the presidency).
John Seery has recently published a book-length argument in favor of Iowering the
age requirements for holding national office in the USA (Seery 201 la). To launch
the book, he published a short version of the argument as an article on Salon. Even
in this brief essay, Seery makes a large number of powerful arguments against
the age requirements, showing that they are di scri mi natory, unfair, out of
touch with the times, not in line with other democracies, inflammatory of
generational tensions, not meritocratic, and particularly offensive given that
much of the burden of military service faIls on the shoulders of the same citi-
zens who are prevented from holding office (Seery 201 lb). From a Rancièrean
perspective, it is not clear that one even needs to pile up arguments in this
fashion. Democracy is not mIe by any particular class; it is the mIe of
1NTRODUCTION 1 13
age, these are never democratic The of is distinct.
redefining most of what we normally take to be poli tics under the banner
of "la police," Rancière makes space for this renewed thinking of democratic
politics. 21 He offers a much sharper sense of what it might me an to say "de-
mocracy" and not simply mean, "the given political order," because when
Rancière says "democracy" he always means moments of democratic politics.
Democracy, he insists, is not a regime (Rancière 2001: thesis 4; Rancière
2006c: 71). Rancière's approach therefore always demands we separate liber-
alism from democracy, since we can only understand liberalism as la police,
never as la politique. Thus, in their own determinate ways all the chapters in
this book conceptualize democracy and "the democratic" in ways that cannot
simply be recuperated by majoritarian representative institutions, nor relegated
to the terms of a Rawlsian (or other) liberal political theory.
Given these aims and goals, given the nature of Rancière's asystematic,
non-ontological approach to questions of politics, and given what he himself
explicitly says about systematizing an account of politics or producing a politi-
cal philosophy, it cannot be overstated that this is not a book on Jacques Ran-
cière nor on his theory of poli tics - at least not in any traditional sense of
devoting a book to a particular author. The chapters that make up the book are
themselves expressions and examples of Rancière's exemplary think.ing of
politics; this is why they eschew a systematic exegesis of Rancière's corpus
and avoid a general articulation of his political theory. There can be no grand,
unified theory of politics for Rancière, not simply (as his playful third-person
account might be taken to imply) because he has not chosen to write one (to
save the trees that he loves), but more important1y, because politics is made up
of polemical interventions. On these points, 1 take Rancière very much at his
word, but this means that 1 often work orthogonaIly to Rancière. Put differ-
ent1y, in order to take him at his word, 1 sometimes go against it. Therefore this
book demonstrates a certain fidelity to Rancière's thinking in the very refusaI
to treat him as a theorist in the "grand tradition," and specifically by appropri-
ating his writings in novel and unexpected ways - ways that often cut against
the grain of Rancière's own arguments. Throughout the book, my reading of
Rancière's texts aligns with his own remarks on his method in insisting that he
has no theOl"y of politics. This explains why these chapters on democratic poli-
tics do not simply add up to a book on Rancière's political theory. More than
this, in my approach to and reading of Rancière, 1 resist at aIl costs the idea of
articulating or constituting something like "the political thought of Rancière."
In other words, it is notjust that 1 have chosen not to write "a book on Rancière"
but that 1 refuse the very idea of producing such a text.
Of course, this refusaI to systematize Rancière should not be confused with a
hesitancy to engage with his work, a reluctance to develop certain of its themes,
or an unwillingness to make my own (sometimes polemical) daims about its
meaning and importance. In addition to pressing a series of specific arguments
Subjects
Of aIl the provocative, elliptical, polemical lines that Rancière has written
about politics, none has so transfixed me, and none has had so great an impact
INTRODUCTION 1 15
on my sense of Rancière's for than the tirst one
quoted above. The quotation is exemplary of Rancière's style. Rancière him-
self refers to his approach as "polemical," and in Chapter Four 1 discuss the
meaning of polemic for Rancière and relate it to the concept of critique. But
here it is important to be dear that for Rancière polemie does not mean lengthy
ad hominem attack. 23 And stylistically, to write polemically for Rancière
means to write provocatively by way of succinct formulations. Many of his
most crucial conceptual daims can be captured in short assertions, such as the
eleven words that make up this tirst quotation. And this line contains a number
of absolutely central elements to Rancière's thinking. First, the statement
refers to "parties," that is, the democratic subject, the subject of politics - a
category on which 1 elaborate below. These parties make a "dedaration," a
point that shows the centrality of language to Rancière's thinking. What they
dedare is "a wrong," and on the very same page Rancière says that wrong
"belongs to the original structure of aIl politics" (Rancière I999: 39). To
"dedare a wrong" is the essential work of polities itself. As 1 have identified
the elements here, one would think they combine quite easily into a simple
formula: subjects act politically. In other words, the democratic subject, in
dedaring a wrong, brings about polities; polities occurs because of this sub-
ject's actions. This formula sounds simple, but Rancière's first quotation above
completely unbalances the equation.
Rancière combines the various elements (subjects, action, and polities)
quite differently, for he brings in a temporal dimension that throws the formula
utterly off its axis. For Rancière, there can be no democratie subject to bring
about the political action - to create the politieal moment - because the daim
of the quotation above is specifically that such subjects do not exist before
politics. The "dedaration of a wrong" whieh is but another name for politics
in Rancière's framework brings about the subject ofpolitics, that is, "parties."
But how, we might immediately ask, can there be a dedaration with no subject
to do the dedaring? In Chapter Three 1 offer a detailed response to this ques-
tion, and in a certain sense 1 center my overall reading of Rancière on this
point. Here 1 want only to note the paradoxical nature of Rancière's seemingly
simple daim. With this short assertion, as in so many other places in his works,
Rancière makes a daim that simply seems impossible. 1 want to emphasize,
though, that he does not just make an impossible daim; he makes a claim for,
or of, the impossible.
And as with aimost aIl of Rancière's arguments, both the statement's "impos-
sibility" and its significance take shape against a particular context - in this
case, the context of tradition al approaches to modern political thought, in
which politics always starts with a subject. ln liberal theory, we begin by going
back to a state of nature, and we do so in order to locate a particular account of
the subject, to describe the characteristics of that subject within the state of
nature, a11 so that we may later offer an explanation for the origins of poli tics
1NTRODUCTION 1 ']
[One] cannot make any deduction from a theory of being as being to
the understanding of politics.
(Rancière 200gb: 117)
The current trend has it that you cannot think politics unless you trace
back its principles to an ontological principle .... My assumption is that
such a requirement leads to the dissolution of politics.
(Rancière 2011C: 12)
2006: 30; see White 2000; cf. Chambers and Carver 2008). Thus, when it
comes to writings in political theory, the real difference is not between onto-
political and non-ontopolitical works, but between "those who suppress the
'onto' in political interpretations" and those who engage the "onto" in distinct
ways (ConnoIly 1995: 9). This daim produces a critical perspective: anyone
who theorizes politics while eschewing ontology is really only concealing the
ontological dimension that his or her work necessarily secretes. 27 Again, ontol-
ogy is ineluctable.
Rancière is not unaware of these SOlts of arguments, as he makes clear in the
second quotation ab ove, where he suggests that the focus (by Connolly and so
many others) on the "onto" leads not to a deeper or fuller account of politics but
to just the opposite: a dissolution of politics. Rancière worries that in the hands
of political ontologists, ontology takes on the role of politics and starts to do the
latter' s work. He gives a clear example in the context of Hardt and Negri' s writ-
ings. Rancière glosses their debilitating political ontology as follows: "The
Multitudes are the real content of the empire that will explode it. Communism
will win because it is the law of being: Being is Communism." Rather than an
analysis of historical instances of political enactments, we have instead a "meta-
physical destination" (Ranci ère 201 IC: 12). Where Connolly sees the necessity
of the ontopolitical to aIl interpretations of politics, Rancière sees a thorough-
going resistance to ontology as a requirement of thinking the specificity of
actual politics. What Connolly considers an honest and indispensable articula-
tion of the ontological commitments that underwrite any politics, Rancière un-
derstands as the dissolving of politics into the ontological mixture. 28
We might even say that, for Rancière, to think politics aright, to grasp poli-
tics in history (and distinguish it from police) we must make a de-ontologizing
move - by refusing to deduce poli tics from ontology so as to take account of
politics in history. Ieven (2009) helpfully caUs this an "abstention from ont01-
ogy," since the only way to take a non-ontological position on ontology is
simply to abstain. Rancière repeats this de-ontologizing move, this abstention,
both in his polemical formulations of poli tics, where his bare, succinct, po-
lemical style resists any grounding for his concept of politics, and also in his
now very numerous meta-theoretical remarks, where he marks his distance
from an ontology in the clearest language he can muster. As the quotations
1NTRODUCTION l '19
to that is stark. on this point
the refusaI to ontologize, the rejection of an ontology - Rancière's approach to
poli tics may mark him not just as distinct, but perhaps even as unique. As
""-''-'''.1
<.CH UJ. HArditi has recently suggested, all of the various competing (and very
much conflicting) strands of post-foundational contemporary political theory
share sorne sort of commitment to (what Connolly caBs) the ontopolitical di-
mension. Here Rancière proves to be the exception; instead of accounting for,
or at least acknowledging, the ontological dimension or assumption of his
work, Rancière continually resists, refutes, or rejects the ontological, as the
occasion requires (Arditi 20I I).
ln my reading of Rancière's position on ontology, 1 emphasize not the
uniqueness of this daim as Rancière makes it rhetorically, but the centra lity of
this position to Rancière's broader body of work. In other words, the resistance
to ontology cannot be full Y grasped if we understand it as merely a resistance
on Rancière's part to have his work categorized in particular ways. Rather, the
refusaI of ontology proves essential to man y of Rancière's other arguments
(arguments that on the surface might appear to have nothing to do with daims
about ontoIogy). That is, many of Rancière's specific daims about politics,
about equality, about language, require and depend upon his refusaI of ont01-
ogy. His account of the subject, as discussed above, provides one such ex am-
pIe. For Rancière, there can be no ontological account of the subject that
grounds or conditions the activity of politics. Rather, it is the activity of poli-
tics, and only this, that indicates to us how we should come to understand the
subject. Any effort to take Rancière's statements about subjectivation29 as phil-
osophical grounds upon which to build a particular political project will stum-
ble upon his insistence that there is no ground to be found - there is no there
there. This is not to suggest that Rancière's approach to politics is groundless,
but rather to show that grounds are always political, historical, or contextual -
never ontological. Insisting on this point makes it easer to see that when
Rancière asserts that subjectivation is always and can only ever be disidentifi-
cation, his dedaration only makes sense within the context of anti-ontology
(Rancière I999: 36). Subjectivation has no grounding in being. The political
subject can never be the bearer of a politics, since the subject only emerges by
way of, through, and as articulated above, after poli tics.
ln taking his radical position against ontology, Rancière also thwarts those
efforts to appropriate his work by ontologizing particular daims that he makes.
His disavowal of ontology sets a certain bar for his readers, because Rancière
implicitly suggests that you can "ontologize" his work only by way of a poor
reading of it. In this way he seeks, intentionally or not, to foredose the possi-
bility of ontological interpretations of his work. His very intransigence on this
point means that he forces many of his readers to part ways with him. Ran-
cière's refusaI of ontology thereby expresses another dimension of his radical
pedagogy, as he makes it impossible to "follow him" except by breaking with
History
The first "history" that matters under this heading is that of the publishing and
translation of Rancière's writings - a history that follows a unique and signifi-
cant path. To give a sense of that history, 1 break it out into five separate de-
cades (1960s, 1970s, 1980s, 1990s, and 2000S) and describe it as something of
a curve function, one that follows this formula: the earlier the work was pub-
lished in French, the later it is translated into English. In other words, and
1NTRODUCTION 1
to sorne
n'VY,,,,,I',h"'Mr~ we can map the r.ll!',I,r'"h,n1"\c and transla-
tions over these five decades as follows:
Rancière's one essay from the 1960s, despite its central importance to
Rancière's oeuvre, has not been properly published in translation at all. 30
His first book, from 1974, where he makes his crucially important and
definitive break with Althusser, was only published in translation in late
2011. As noted ab ove, Rancière's numerous writings for Les révoltes
logiques are only now beginning to appear, with Volume 1 published in
2011, and Volume II forthcoming in 2012.
Rancière's works [rom the 1980s were translated, very unevenly, and
sometimes roughly, over the same decade as they first appeared in print
(while the oider writings remained untranslated during this period). La
nuit des prolétaires appeared in French in 1981 and in English in 1989
(with a new English translation just out in 2012); Le philosophe et ses
pauvres was published in French in 1983, and while an English transla-
tion was promised in the mid-1990s it did not appear until 2004; and fi-
nally Le maître ignorant appeared in French in 1987 and arrived in
English only four years later. Numerous other texts from this period, of
course, remain untranslated today.
ln the 1990s a much larger number of Rancière's numerous publications
were translated into English, aIl within five years of first appearing in
French. Other translations appeared later than this, but the main point is
that in this decade Rancière's works start to appear with frequency in
English, and the English translations that did come out in this decade
were versions of French texts published very recently. Thus, this decade
marks the first time that English translations become both common and
current.
& ln the 2000s the majority of Rancière's works were translated very quickly
into English, and a number of new texts were produced directly in English.
One can see clearly th en that as we move forward through the decades, we go
from no translations or long-delayed translations, to frequent and timely
translations. After the 1990s, an even lm'gel' number of Rancière's works
appear regularly in English soon aftel' their original publication in French.
Moreovel', as we continue to go fol'wal'd in time, there is a simultaneous
reaching backward to produce translations of Rancière's earliest writings. As
of my own writing early in 2012, we have reached far enough back in time
that Althusser's Lesson, Rancière's first book, has just now finally appeared.
1 am not in the business of prediction, but if the pattern holds, we can expect
a new translation of Rancière's contribution to Reading Capital to appear
within the decade.
Now, aIl of this matters on the one hand simply because it situates my read-
ing of Rancière in the context of his reception in the UK and North America,
into other politieal and intellectual contexts, since in these works Rancière
engages with the tradition of politieal philosophy and with contemporary poli-
tics. These writings contain what many now think of as Rancière's trademark
style of sparse, often abstract, and commonly polemical formulations, and as
such, the writings themselves are easy to quote, easy to use in provocative
ways, and easy to reappropriate for a variety of distinct contexts.
Rancière's writings from the 1970S and 1980s, in stark contrast, were in one
sense "historical" writings, and they were deeply embedded not only in their
specific historical context, but also in a partieular French context. That is to say,
Rancière's work from this time came directly out of the archive, and while it
spoke weIl beyond that archive, it often spoke to specific French political de-
bates. Thus, to grasp what Rancière has to say about history requires a bit of
historical contextualization on the part of his readers. To be dear: it should be
obvious that 1 do not intend to apply to Rancière's thought the sort ofhelmeneu-
tics often used in the history of political thought. Nonetheless, 1 contend that we
can gain a crucial perspective on Rancière's thinking of democratie politics ifwe
do more than is often done to situate him in his context. One of the limitations to
be found in so many accounts of Rancière's work - induding, at times, his own-
is that they seem to come from nowhere and to be rooted to nothing. Rancière is
a polemicist. He writes so as to provoke, and especially in his writing on democ-
racy and politics, Rancière produces radical formulations. He thus makes bold
and startling assertions that often appear as if out of the blue; their suddenness
enables these daims to strike readers with real force. However, an engagement
with Rancière's writings needs to do more than merely repeat those formula-
tions; in writing on Rancière, one cannot simply rest with Rancière's own po-
lemical force. 31 It is not my goal here to repeat what Rancière already says, but
rather to extend his arguments through my own engagements, and to stage my
engagements in such a way as to make Rancière's thought resonate more broadly
and more powerfully for the readers of this text.
It is in this sense that context matters in reading Rancière. For me, no sec-
ondary source on Rancière has brought his understanding of poli tics into focus
nearly so weIl as Kristin Ross's book May '68 and its Afterlives (2002). In
making this daim 1 do not mean to rank books on Rancière or to offer sorne
filter on the secondary literature (e.g., read this one, not those). 1 have no gen-
eral interest in such an exercise, but it surely has no place with Ross's book,
since her text is not even a book on Rancière and does not constitute part of
that literature. Ross's book operates on one level as a history of May '68, but
it does its most significant work on a second level, wherein it engages the
1NTRODUCTION 1 23
contest '68 in the I970S and
up to the turn of the century. Ross does not try merely, or even necessarily at
aIl, to "get 11ght" in the historical sense; instead she makes her own
cal and theoretical argument about ' 68 so as to contest the dominant nar-
rative that has taken root. And the sense of ' 68 that Ross wants to defend
relies upon, just as it mutually informs, a thoroughly Rancièrean account of
poli tics. The themes of ' 68 that Ross argues for almost aU prove to be
central themes of Rancière's account of politics: challenge to mastery, disrup-
tion of order, verification of equality based upon its presumption, rejection of
the expert, political subjectivation as dis identification, and above aH, a certain
happening, a certain event-ness of history (Ross 2002: 6, 15,46, sI).
More than anything else, Ross wants to contest the interpretation of May
'68 that has become dominant in France in recent decades: the daim that
"nothing happened in May," that the event was a nonevent (Ross 2002: 6,
67).32 She challenges this interpretation by invoking (sometimes explicitly, but
frequently tacitly) a Rancièrean conception of politics. As a historian, Ross
herself does not polemicize, and she allows her larger daims to unfold through
her historical narrative. However, her argument throughout the book can be
conveyed by a statement that she makes early on, an assertion that takes a more
polemical fOlm. Against those who say over and over again that nothing hap-
pened in May '68, that there was no event-ness, no emplotment of politics in
history, Ross contends: "In May, everything happened politically - provided,
of course, that we understand 'politics' as bearing little or no relation to what
was called at the time 'la politique des politiciens' (specialized, or electoral
politics)" (Ross 2002: 15, emphasis added). Ross uses Rancière's arguments
explicitly to show that the daim "nothing is happening" is a form of policing.
She quotes from Rancière's well-known reinterpretation of the Althusserian
scene of interpellation, wherein Rancière derives from the scene an utterly dif-
ferent meaning than Althusser had produced. Rancière states: "The police say
there is nothing to see, nothing happening, nothing to be done but to keep
moving, circulating; they say that the space of circulation is nothing but the
space of circulation" (Rancière 2001: par. 22; quoted in Ross 2002: 22, Ross's
translation). Ross uses Rancière's account of politics to resist a peculiar and
potent policing of May '68 that would render it a nonevent. She reopens the
dispute in order to pro duce a scene of politics. In so doing, Ross's historical
work provides one of the most powerful elaborations and illustrations of
Rancière's thinking of politics, while at the same time both illuminating and
contextualizing Rancière's thought.
Rancière's work, however, cannot be reduced to an expression of, or reflec-
tion on, a set of historical events, whether they be May '68 or any other. My
point in highlighting Ross's work and in emphasizing the importance of May '68
for Rancière's thought is much more delimited: 1 wish to indicate at times the
location from which Rancière writes, and to draw sorne tentative links between
uality
1NTRODUCTION 1 25
BMOS84732
"""JHHé'-'-"_'" Rancière's thinking from liberalism because both ap-
proaches to politics make equality central and essential. Indeed, for liberalism
'-'rl"'Cl"'''' is so important that even authors who defend non-liberal political vi-
sions if they articulate a liberal conception of equality, a role to play in
the liberal tradition. With this description l am obviously thinking of Hobbes,
who defends an authoritarian vision of politics in his writings, just as he sup-
pOlted monarchy in his life. But Hobbes plays a fundamental role in the liberal
tradition because he starts with equality. Undoubtedly Hobbes makes one of
the clearest and most direct arguments in favor of equality in the en tire history
ofpolitical thought, when he claims that in astate of nature aIl men and women
are equal because even the weakest among them still has within him- or herself
the power to kill the strongest (Hobbes I994: chapter XIII).
From Hobbes onward, equality plays a foundational but at the same time
quite curious role within liberalism. It is foundational in the most straightfor-
ward s~nse: equality, paired with liberty, is the starting point of liberalism.
Liberal subjects are, by definition, all free and equal. To consider the human
being in his or her fundamental capacities and characteristics means to con-
sider human beings as equal, and everything else follows from this starting
point. We see this most strikingly in the linear logic of Locke's argument:
Locke famously tells his readers, on just the second page of his Second Trea-
tise that "to understand political power aright, and derive it from its original,
we must consider what state aIl men are naturally in" and that is a state of
freedom and equality (Locke I988: 266). However, l caB the function of equal-
ity in liberalism curious because, especially after Hobbes's very cIever argu-
ment, there is almost no argument whatsoever given to support this assertion
of equality.34 Equality is the given, it is the starting point, it is a substantive
requirement of liberalism, but it is not, for aIl that, a principle that liberalism
spends much time defending or even articulating.
This point cornes through most starkly in the work of Rawls, who really
makes no argument for equality at aIl. A Theory of Justice, for example, simply
stipulates on its tirst page that "each person possesses an inviolability founded
on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override" (Rawls
197I: 3). Equality is caught up in this "inviolability": we are an equal to just
the extent that we are inviolable. Rawls makes it cIear- as he asserts it repeatedly
that humans must be characterized, in their very being, as free and equal, but
Rawls always moves directly and rather quickly from this assumption to the
question that matters to him. He frames the question this way on the second
page of Political Liberalism: "How is it possible for there to exist over time a
just and stable society of free and equal citizens?" (Rawls I993: 4).
For liberalism, equality is best understood as a ground in the fullest sense
of the word. That is, Iiberal political theory will start with equality, but it will
not start with an argument about equality. And this means that equality is a
ground Ilot only in the sense that it serves as the basis for the theory, but that it
1NTRODUCTION 1 27
serves as an
,:>rlll'=' 11tU equality is demon-
strated. As he does in many other places, in the second quote, above, Rancière
describes as axiomatic. Equality is an axiom that we assume and that
can be verified in practice. This assumption, however, is not a substantive
in the liberal sense, but rather a presupposition that could never take
'VU.'l'-'-Ul':;;'
the form of a "given" in a logieal proof (cf. Wittgenstein 1972). And the veri-
fication or demonstration of equality cannot be substantively grasped; we can
bear witness to equality, but we can never hold it in our hand or point precisely
to iL Equality, for Rancière, just is not that sort of thing.
If equality is anything, it is a 10gicY This explains how equality can be both
assumed and verified without ever being made substantive: both moments
occur when the logic of equality is operative. And the logic of equality never
ODlôrates on its own, in isolation, or in pure form. Rather, the logic of equality
operates in tension with the logic of inequality. Politics occurs only when these
two lügics meet, when they come into conftict. This is what Rancière means
when he says, in the tirst quote above, that equality is veritied through a pro-
cess that grabs hold of the knot that ties equality to inequality. Equality and
inequality always remain knotted together. Equality does not reside in or create
its own space; there is no sphere in which pure equality reigns. Instead equal-
ity only ever contaminates the space of inequality - what Rancière caUs an
order of the police. The police order is an order of domination and of hierar-
chy, and it operates according to its own presumption of a logic of inequality.
Polities occurs when that poliee order is interrupted by the heterogeneous
logic of equality. This makes equality a "one-off act" and it explains why
equality can never be institutionalized: "Equality tums into the opposite once
it aspires to a place in the social" (Rancière 1999: 34).
Equality in Rancière's account al ways proves to be equality of intelligence,
an equality of anybody and everybody. Here is Rancière's own description of
the presupposition of equality: "the mad presupposition that anyone is as intel-
ligent as anyone else and that at least one more thing can always be done other
than what is being done" (Rancière 20Ioa: 2, emphasis added). The emphasis
here is significant: equality is not a rational or logieal given, it is a "mad pre-
supposition." We do not start with equality as a given; we take a leap to arrive
at it as axiomatic. In this description, we see a supremely democratie form of
equality; it is not a characteristic of certain individuals under certain condi-
tions; it is an assumption that applies to anyone at aIl. Rancière's polities of
equality is always a polities of the anybody at aIl, of the anyone and everyone,
of the anyone whatsoever -- phrases that he uses interchangeably and with
great frequency across a wide range of his writings. 38
In this light we can see that liberalism gives equality a certain foundational
of place, making equality an organizing principle and a substantive goal,
whereas Rancière tums to equality as only someone who is tirst and foremost
a democrat cano For Rancière equality is not an ordering principle but instead
1NTRODUCTION 1 29
in similar fashion the of can be as the
condition for emergence of a political subject. And with equality my argu-
ments in this introduction spiral up, around, and through the broader theme of
"Rancière's lessons," since Rancière's account of equality initially emerges
most perspicaciously in his writings on pedagogy.
Rancière's critique of mainstream and dominant pedagogies from the nine-
teenth century to the present always centers on those pedagogies' presupposi-
tion and verification of the principle and logic of inequality. The work of the
teacher, traditionally understood, is to explain, to explicate, to tell the students
the lesson, to show them the meaning of the text: "Explanation, or the ordinary
routine of pedagogic practice, was above aIl a display of inequality" (Rancière
20I rb: 40). The master is the master because he or she can explain the texts
that the students are otherwise presumed not to understand on their own; thus,
teaching in this traditional sense presumes, just as it simultaneously demon-
strates, the inequality of intelligence between student and teacher (Rancière
201 lb: 40; Rancière 1991: xvi). Rancière caBs this entire framework that tra-
ditional teaching establishes "the explicative order," an order built on the
ground of the student' s inabilities. Explanation lies at the heart of the explica-
tive order. But just as he williater redefine the normal activity of politics as
police practices, Rancière had much earlier redefined explanation as stultifica-
tion. The argument pivots on a basic but powerful observation: "To explain
something to someone is first of aB to show him that he cannot understand it
by himself" (Rancière 1991: 6). Before any teacher opens his or her mouth,
the explicative order establishes the teacher as the master, as the one who will
help those to understand who cannot understand on their own.
Rancière's radical pedagogy, which he freely bOITOWS from Joseph Jacotot,
seeks the overturning of the explicative order. This new pedagogy rests on
nothing more than a reversaI of the explicative order's primary assumption.
What if the student can perfectly weIl understand for himself? What if the
student can read the text without the explanations of a master? It is the prin-
ciple of equality of intelligence - nothing more and nothing less - that unrav-
els the explicative order and founds a new, radical pedagogy. When a student
picks up a book and reads it for herself (even, as in the case of Jacotot's teach-
ing experiments, a book written in a language other than her mother tongue),
she is using the method of equality. Thiscapacity for anyone to read the book
without having someone else tell him what it means - this is the power of
equality, and this is aIl there is to equality.
What, then, does it me an to teach without stultification? How can there be
any "lessons" at aIl under the sign of a Rancièrean pedagogy? And ultimately,
what does it mean to title this work The Lessons of Rancière? Answers to these
questions begin to emerge when we note that Rancière does not give up on the
teacher or on teaching. He even, somewhat surprisingly, maintains a space for
masters and mastery. Rancière insists on the principle of equality of intelligence;
G Coordinates
1NTRODUCTION 1 31
on a lesson as an up to other - as a emancipa-
tion. While always inspired and animated in some way by Rancière's writings,
the specifie engagements with ideas, authors, arguments, and contemporary
political questions are mine, not Rancière's. Therefore the book's foundation
lies in a series of concrete engagements with the particular problematics in
which find myself. As 1 discussed above, for Rancière history means that
"you have to be located in this place." The chapters of this book remain atten-
tive to radical temporality in their reading of Rancière, but more than this, they
retain their own temporal markers. They do not speak to a comprehensive
"political theory" that 1 would attribute to another author; they speak to the
time and place in which they are located, though they almost always speak to
that historical moment through the writings of Rancière.
In Chapter One, 1 start where so many readers of Rancière have started,
with "Politics." Rancière has animated and incited numerous readers, espe-
cially political theorists, with his radical rethinking of politics and his atten-
dant redefinition of what we usually caU poli tics as "police." In this chapter
1 insist that whatever else we might wish to say about Rancière's understand-
ing of politics, we must always refuse the idea of co-opting his account under
a model that renders poli tics pure. Even some of the best readings of Ran-
cière's polemical political works have failed to take account of the consistency,
subtlety, and dedicated nature of his resistance to the idea of politics as pure.
Because he gives a unique definition of politics (in contrast to police), many
contemporary theorists have been tempted to read Rancière as something like
an Arendtian - in the sense of taking him to be carving out a unique space and
preserve for "the political" as distinct from "police," in the same way that
Arendt shelters politics from the social and the economic. This chapter thus
engages with a small portion of the vast literature on Arendt, looking specifi-
cally at a few important recent texts that read Arendt and Rancière together.
1 suggest that those thinkers who blend Rancière and Arendt usually do so by
folding Rancière's project into Arendt's, and in making this move they must
pass over or abandon some of Rancière's keenest insights about democratic
politics. Ultimately, 1 show that - despite the many ways in which their thought
is complementary - to read Rancière as an Arendtian is to miss his most fun-
damental of points about politics: that it can never be pure.
Rancière's insistence on an impure politics holds a number of important
implications, many of which 1 unravel over the course of the book. Pirst, the
notion of impure politics thwarts not only Arendtian readings of his ideas but
also dialectical renderings. In this chapter 1 engage with the most important
early interpreter of Rancière's political theory in English-Ianguage writings,
Jean-Philippe Deranty. 1 resist the tendency in Deranty's interpretation to as-
similate Rancière's conception of politics to a dialectical model. 1 insist,
with Rancière, that there is no ground for politics; in tum, 1 argue, against
Deranty, that poli tics and police do not meet on the terrain of a separate term
and the politicallogic of equality occurs in the only location it can occur: the
terrain of the police order itself. This means that contrary to to sys-
tematize or purify Rancière's account of politics, democratic politics must
always be bound up with police orders. For just this reason, Rancière's think-
ing of democratic poli tics requires of his readers far greater attention to his
concept of "the police."
Thus, Chapter Two, "Police," cornes at Rancière's well-known writings on
politics from a different tack - in this case, from the opposite direction. Most
contemporary political theorists are so taken by Rancière's novel and radical
approach to politics that they immediately move on from his fundamental dis-
tinction between politics and police, so that they can investigate more c10sely
the theOl'y of politics that this distinction makes possible. But since Rancière -
as he himself says, and as 1 have stressed above has no theOl)' of politics, it
does not make much sense to try to build a theory by piling up Ranci ère 's
statements about politics. Rancière says what he says about politics not in an
effort to ontologize politics. Instead, he uses the police/poli tics distinction
both as leverage for his polemical interventions into both contemporary and
historical political debates, and as a way to reorient our understanding of the
history of poli tic al philosophy. This chapter, then, does sorne of the basic work
to lay out the terms that prove fundamental to Rancière's broader conception
of democratic politics. However, my reading of Rancière refuses to turn any of
those temlS into established or analytic concepts that would fonn the basis of
a new model of poli tic al theory. Instead, 1 focus in this chapter on what 1 call
"the poli tics of the police," a phrase that helps me to get at not only what Rancière
means by police, but also how he mobilizes the distinction in order to make his
own set of critical interventions into politics.
This second chapter thus details three different ways of reading the phrase
"poli tics of the police." First, the "poli tics of the police" makes it possible to
analyze and unravel the meaning of the phrase that Rancière uses to describe
today's putatively "idyllic state of politics[:] consensus democracy" (Ranci ère
1999: 95)· As Rockhill helpfully puts it, consensus is "a particular way of
positing rights as a community's archë" (Rockhill 2006: 83). The victory of
what 1 would describe as a liberal consensus (rights as the principle ofpolitics)
leads to what Rancière caUs, echoing Thomas Jefferson, a loss of needed "militant
vigilance" conceming democracy (Rancière 1999: 97). Amled with the police/
politics distinction, Rancière can demonstrate that consensus democracy - which
1 show works by the same logic as US liberalism, that is, the logic of interest-
group pluralism is not poli tic al at aIl, but rather a model of policing. Consen-
sus democracy is founded upon the very elimination of politics, on the quelling
of the conflict, dissensus, and rupture that are central to Rancière's understanding
of democratic politics. Instead, consensus democracy merely implements a
new "police order" - a hierarchical regime of domination that institutes and
1NTRODUCTION 1 33
instantiates a of of the is thus a cri tic al
theOl'y, first and foremost. 1 th en offer an extensive but circumscribed engage-
ment with Todd appropriation of Rancière's thought for his anarchist
political project 2008). holds an understanding of police that would
render the phrase "polities of the police" nonsensieal. show that in
his defense of anarchism as a pure poli tics (one that would eliminate police
once and for aIl) May not only misreads Rancière on police but ends up posit-
ing an approach to politics that proves less than fully democratie (in Rancière's
sense). "The polities of the police" helps us to grasp the inadequacies of a
utopian model of pure polities. Finally, then, 1 suggest an account of "politics
of the police" that always insists on their mutuai imbrication, that definitively
refuses the ide a of a pure polities, and that points us instead toward a Ran-
cièrean theOl-Y of radical democracy.
Chapter Three, "Literarity," returns to the beginning, as 1 open this chapter
at the same place as Rancière begins his most important text on polities and
philosophy. ln his I995 book, La mésentente, translated as Disagreement
(I999), Rancière begins with Aristotle's account, in his Politics, of man as a
poli tic al animal. Aristotle can traditionally be read as grounding a theory of
politics on anthropology: anthropos (man), for Aristotle, is that creature that
possesses logos (reasoned speech), unlike animaIs that only have phonë (mere
voice). The logos makes man a politieal animal by endowing him with the
powers of deliberation and judgment, the quintessential activities of politics.
Thus, Aristotle, the so-called first politieal scientist, grounds his theory of poli-
tics on a particular theory of language a tool to be possessed and wielded by
the human being, the only properly political creature. But Rancièrean polities
begins in disagreement with Aristotle by rereading these famous passages at
the opening of the Politics. Rancière asks how we can distinguish between an
animal with mere voice and a human being with logos. Is the phonë/logos
distinction given in nature (as most readers of Aristotle would have it), or is it
precisely polities itself that allows us to draw the line between phonë and
logos, between the political and the apolitical? If it is the latter, as Rancière's
approach to politics always contends, we are led to a completely different un-
derstanding of the relationship between language and the subject. The political
subject, as 1 have shown above, cannot precede language and use it as a tool;
rather, the politieal subject only cornes to be in and through language and poli-
tics. There is no pre-given subject who uses language to declare a politieal
wrong, because before the wrong, there is no subject for us to speak of. Demo-
cratie subjectivity cornes about through democratic politics, and not the re-
verse. Language can therefore no longer be thought as an object for human
use; it must be understood instead as that medium through which the human
politieal animal emerges and in whieh it crystalizes.
In making this argument, 1 do a great deal of clarifying work concerning not
only what Rancière argues about language, but also the language in which
1NTRODUCTION 1 35
translations of the book rlrr',,,,,·,orl the contributions bS1EaOlet, and
Macherey and rearranged the order of presentation. Through this process and
the history of the reception of the text that followed, Reading Capital became
a text by a single author, Althusser. almost immediately after contrib-
uting to the volume, and in the wake of the events of '68, Rancière broke
decisively from Althusser. In rejecting quite completely the Althusserian
approach, Rancière implicitly disavowed his own contribution to Reading
Capital.
However, as l show in this chapter, Rancière never abandoned the subject
that he first broached in that lengthy (almost book-length) essay: the concept
of critique. This chapter considers three distinct contributions to a theory of
critique or critical theory that Rancière has made over the course of his career:
(I) the early essay in Reading Capital; (2) the arguments made in the later
chapters of Disagreement; and (3) a more recent essay on critical thinking
(Randère 2007c). Working sometimes with and sometimes against Rancière,
but always remaining in dialogue with him, l advance an argument against the
very notion, so well-established and commonly accepted in contemporary
theory today, of critical theory as operating by way of a logic of inversion. This
is the logic that underlies common understandings of critical theory as a prac-
tice of demystification; it rests on the classical opposition between appearance
and essence, suggesting that undemeath the false appearance lies a true es-
sence. The task of the critical theory becomes one of inversion to just the
extent that inversion can reveal the underlying truth the very truth that is
masked by outward dissimulation.
In a preliminary effort to move critical theory onto new and sustainable
coordinates, largue that we must reconsider this entire logic. More th an this,
l reject the logic of inversion (and the metaphysics of truth/appearance that
sustains it), suggesting that a new critical dispositif must function on the basis
of a different logic. Rancière points the way toward developing such a critical
dispositif when he tantalizingly hints at the ide a that the tradition of cri tic al
thinking has had it wrong an along, "that there is no hidden secret of the
machine" (Rancière 2007c: I5). l move beyond the steps Rancière has taken,
as I give the sketch of a renewed sense of critical theory, a distinct critical
dispositif that would eschew the logic of inversion. This would be a Rancièrean
critical theory (even it is not Rancière's) to the extent that it takes equality as
axiomatic and seeks its verification.
The book closes with an Afterword, which serves as a performative illustra-
tion of Rancière's concept of the "one too many." On the one hand, the After-
word threatens to be one chapter too many in the sense that it deviates mu ch
more significantly from Rancière's own arguments. On the other hand, Ran-
cière himself caUs the dëmos the "one too many," and therefore the Afterword
expresses an important dimension of democracy (Rancière I999: I88). Like
democracy, the Afterword involves a miscount. In both name and content, the
INTRODUCTION 1
Democracy is in the streets.
POLITICS 1 39
inclination to read his of of a pure, pro-
tected politieal sphere - can lead readers astray in their approach to Rancière.
1t inclines readers to see Rancière's politics as pure, despite his very direct
claim that politics can never be pure 201 lC: 3).
Rancière' s conception of politics strikes most readers as so free- floating, so
unmoored from aIl other conceptions, that many naturally seek to ground his
thinking of poli tics somewhere. An Arendtian reading of Rancière solves this
problem, but at too high a cost. Another way to moor Rancière's conception of
politics is by fixing it within a broader conceptual vocabulary. Here the strat-
egy is more German idealist than Arendtian, as if calls for the introduction of
a third term to balance and to ground the polities/police opposition. Rather
than an Arendtian pure sphere of polities, we would thus have, on this reading
of Rancière's works, either a Kantian version of Rancière (wherein the third
term serves fonnally as the condition of possibility for polities/police) or a
HegeIian version (in whieh politics and police stage a confrontation, the syn-
thesis of which determines history). A third term serves to stabilize and fix
Rancière's conception of politics by giving politics and police a space of
mediation.
In this chapter 1 will first show briefly that sorne of Rancière's best inter-
preters (and sometimes with encouragement from Rancière's own texts) have
followed one of these tempting readings and either taken Rancière's work to
support a pure theory of politics or supplemented his account with a third term
that would somehow mediate the relation between poli tics and police. How-
ever, 1 will then go on to argue that Rancière's potential contribution to politi-
cal theory lies not in Arendtian or idealist veins of thought. Rancière rejects,
perhaps above aIl else, the very idea of a pure polities. Politics is precisely that
which could never be pure (and for this very reason, politics is never some-
thing that can be measured or predicted with "precision"). Rancière's critique
of the entire tradition of political philosophy (including Arendt) centers on his
resistance to the pu rit y or purification of politics. 1 will frequently bring my
reading of Rancière into sharper relief by contrasting it with those approaches
to his work that would (explicitly or tacitly) fold his arguments into a pure
thinking of politics.
But 1 wish to state clearly from the beginning that these hermeneutic con-
flicts rai se important political stakes. The emphasis on impurity matters a great
deal because, for Rancière, politics is an act of impurity, a process that resists
purification. That is, and as 1 will explain in the text below, poli tics makes a
supplement possible in the face of a social order that says it has no supple-
ment. Polities makes visible that whieh a social order wishes to render invisi-
ble, and it does so in such a way that it does not just "add" to what is already
given. Instead, the logic of politics undermines the purity of the given. To think
politics as "impure" in this sense means, on the one hand, to reject any model
of unalloyed politics (whether it be anarchism or Hegelianism or anything
POLITICS 1 4'
cOlmnlerltm'y on Rancière's thinking with to has been so
up in his distinctive definition of poli tics as to lead to relative neglect of his
COflcelDt of la police. While in Chapter Two take up a much more detailed and
involved reading of Rancière's concept of the police, it is essential to make a
few points explicit here.
Rancière clarifies his conception of police by showing that while it is re-
lated to the idea of uniformed officers riding in patrol cars and walking the
street, it must neveliheless be analytically distinguished from "the truncheon
blows of the forces of law and order" (Rancière 1999: 28). Rancière uses
"police," "policing," and "police order" to name any order of hierarchy. And
thus he invokes this broader concept of "policing" to indicate both policy-
making - as the term in English, though not in French, already connotes - as
weIl as a wide array of economic and cultural arrangements. In order to stress
the broad nature of his concept of la police, Rancière (uncharacteristically)
emphasizes the link between his use of police and Foucault's work. Foucault
argues: first, to the extent that any police order determines hierarchical rela-
tionships between human beings, "the police includes everything"~ second, to
the extent that it sets up a relationship between "men and things," the police
order also constitutes a material order (Foucault 2002a).
These links make it clear that Rancière calls on the concept of la police to
connote the vertical organization of society:4 the dividing up and distribution
of the various parts that make up the social whole. A police order is not just an
abstract order of powers (of laws or principles), it is "an order of bodies that
defines the allocation of ways of doing, ways of being, and ways of saying, and
sees that those bodies are assigned by name to a particular place and task~ it is
an order of the visible and the sayable" (Rancière 1999: 29, emphasis added).
In this key passage Rancière elaborates on the concept of the police in terms
that will become central to his later writings, since "an order of the visible and
the sayable" glosses Rancière's vital notion of le partage du sensible - usually
translated as "the distribution/partition of the sensible" but also connoting both
sharing and division (Panagia 2010).5 Policing is a way of dividing up and
linking up, of making visible and making invisible, the various parts of the
social order.
In "Ten Theses on Poli tics" Rancière suggests that "there are two ways of
counting the parts of the community." The first way of counting he calls police,
and he describes it as follows: it "only counts empirical parts actual groups
defined by differences in birth, by different functions, locations, and interests
that constitute the social body" (Rancière 2001: par. 19). At this point, the
English translation of "Ten Theses" moves on to Rancière's next sentence (and
the next way of counting). However, in the original French, as Maria Muhle
has very helpfully pointed out, Rancière continues: "à l'exclusion de tout sup-
plément" (Ranci ère 1998a: 176~ cf. Muhle 200T 4; see also Rancière 2010b:
36). The police, then, is not just a way of counting the actual groups that make
1. Use the definition as a critical tool; leverage it for one's own argumenta-
tive purposes.
2. Ontologize the definition; make it function as an ontological ground and
build a comprehensive theory atop it.
POLITICS 1 43
1",,...,,.,.,.,,,,,,.,,1-0 the definition into an extant make it fit
within a better-known framework. There could potentially be an almost
limitless number of varieties of this strategy, but here mention only
three that prove salient in readings of Rancière:
a) Anarchist theory
b) Arendtian poli tics
c) Politics of recognition
The first overall option, to use the definition of politics as a rhetorical, argu-
mentative weapon, is one that Rancière's own texts sometimes invite, and one
that sorne of his very best readers have surely found enticing. Vnder this head-
ing one starts with Rancière's succinct daims about politics so as to put his
novel definition of politics to work, thereby using the definition the way Fou-
cault said knowledge was used, "for cutting" (Foucault 1984: 88). 1b do this is
to take Rancière's new definition of politics and make it function as a weapon
of critique. Vndoubtedly Rancière does this himself when in the latter half of
Disagreement he shows that neoliberal consensus models of politics amount to
nothing more, though surely nothing less, than "orders of the police." This ap-
proach would make Rancière's definition of politics into a tool of politico-
theoretical argument, but it remains undear how it could serve more than a
negative function. It would invite aIl those questions posed to Foucault's work:
"What are your normative grounds?" "What positive foundation for actual
politics do es this definition provide?,,6
The second option, to ontologize the definition of politics, is an aIluring
choice, particularly if one finds the "normative grounds" complaints plausible
and meaningful. To exercise this option means that rather than putting the defi-
nition to work, one instead works it up into a full-blown alternative theory of
politics. This choice provides a direct response to requests for grounds, since
it turns Rancière's daims about politics into ontological foundations. How-
ever, the limitations of this approach are obvious from my discussion of ontol-
ogy in the Introduction. From the very start this move would have to violate
what we might caB one of Rancière's primary "mIes" - the one that prohibits
recourse to ontology. As 1 have already shown, Rancière's tactic will always be
to de-ontologize, but the effort to build a full political theory on the grounds of
Rancière's definition of politics would surely be an ontologizing move. It
would found the new theory on the principles of Rancière's conception of
politics. Rancière himself does not simply eschew this move; he consistently
rejects it when he sees it in other thinkers, and he repeatedly resists it wh en he
identifies it in appropriations of his own thought. None of this prevents one
from using Rancière's conception of politics in this way. However, such a
strategy requires that one not merely part ways with Rancière's own thought,
but double back and go against it. Perhaps this choice will be taken up by
future commentators on Rancière, but 1 do not follow it here.
re Politics
In asserting that Rancière's work has frequently been incorporated into an Ar-
endtian framework, and in trying - in response to this trend to prize apart the
arguments of Arendt and Rancière, 1 am making a particular and circumscribed
POLITICS 1 45
Mm-kell's work
V<:>!'r>h,:>n me to the terms of that claim.
writes, "If there is anything like a standard reading of The Human Condition,
it is safe to say that it is built around the theme of separation. The point of the
book, we aIl know, is to div ide things that have been blurred together inappro-
priately" (Mm-kell 20II: 20; see also Holman 20II). Markell caUs this stan-
dard reading a "territorial" interpretation of Arendt's most famous book,
because it insists on "sorting" human activity into its proper categories (Markell
20 l 1: 16). 1 would add that in the effort to overcome the improper blurring of
categories and activities, this territorial interpretation of Arendt points toward
a pure conception of politics (either in Arendt herself or in the conception of
politics that the territorial interpreter tries to build). It is just this territorial ac-
count, and the conception of pure politics to which it is committed, that 1 wish
to reject. More to the point, 1 want to resist the tendency to fold Rancière's
writings on politics into this "standard" account of Arendt. In so doing, 1 am
not suggesting that the tenitorial reading of Arendt is the only one on offer.
After aIl, Markell himself clarifies the contours of this standard reading so that
he can provide an alternative (Markell 20 Il: 35), and 1 see a number of impor-
tant connections between the Rancièrean account of "impure politics" that 1
develop here and the alternative interpretation of The Human Condition that
Mm-kell advances. 7 My point is more subtle, then, since as Markell himself
shows, the territorial reading of Arendt does in fact prove to be the standard
one. For just this reason, the tendency to read Rancière alongside, or even
tacked on to, Arendt, makes it tempting to interpret Rancière's work territori-
ally. That is, the incorporation of Rancière into an Arendtian framework entices
one to read Rancière as a theorist of pure poli tics, despite his explicit rejection
of that very notion.
Perhaps the best ex ample of folding Rancière's thinking of politics into an
Arendtian structure is Cristina Beltrân's 2009 article in Political Theory. First
and foremost, this essay offers an interpretation of the widespread protests and
demonstrations by immigrants across the USA in 2006. Cutting across the
praise and condemnation of these events by commentators on the left and
right, respectively, Beltrân argues for the specifically political nature of the
protests (Beltrân 2009: 597). She uses Arendt's political theory to make this
case, as it lets her show that the demonstrators (a group that included legal and
illegal immigrants and their numerous allies) brought f01th the power of initia-
tion - a novel, creative political force. The protests, then, were "inaugural"
acts in the Arendtian sense of bringing forth something new and unexpected,
and the demonstrators were not "merely" protestors; in Beltrân's account they
emerge clearly and with sorne force as poli tic al actors.
As 1 noted at the beginning of this chapter, this Arendtian account of poli tics as
novelty (as surprise) and as the creation of something new the production of a
political stage where before there had apparently been none - resonates in various
ways with Rancière's thinking of politics. In at least this minimal sense, then,
POLITICS 1 47
make a very and - while also rich and informed quite
concrete argument about democratic politics. In this way she invokes Rancière
and a whole host of other thinkers to help her achieve that end, but she remains
very attentive to the differences among those theorists. Honig's argument
therefore provides an illustrative contrast with Beltrân. Rather than closing
down the possibilities of Rancière's thought by folding it into the frame of
another thinker, Honig's concise reading of Rancière opens up Rancière's
thought for her readers. 8
Perhaps the most complete and subtle treatment of the relation between
Arendt and Rancière comes From Andrew Schaap (2011), who makes an argu-
ment concerning Rancière's own reading of Arendt's claim about "the right to
have rights" in her Origins of Totalitarianism (Arendt 2004: 376; Rancière
2004d; see also Ingram 2008; cf. Zivi 2012).1 will not summarize or rehearse
Schaap's work here in any detail, for the simple reason that 1 myself parallel
his line of argument in what I write below. Schaap shows that Rancière at
times misinterprets Arendt in order to polemicize his own point (Schaap 2011:
33), while also indicating nicely that the question of the purity of poli tics is
just what is at stake in Rancière's rejection of Arendt (32, 43). By approaching
the relation between Arendt and Rancière through Rancière's own reading of
Arendt's work, Schaap's article achieves a number of important ends for my
own pm-poses here. First, he obviously refuses the move to collapse Rancière's
conception of politics into Arendt's. Second, he shows that the purity of poli-
tics constitutes the central issue of contention between Rancière and Arendt. I
con tend that Rancière is often misread as thinking of poli tics as pure, of con-
ceiving of politics as somehow utterly unique or special, and as privileging a
so-called political sphere over other spheres of order and action. In turn, I see
approaches to Rancière such as Beltrân's as encouraging this line of thinking.
Schaap's work therefore proves crucial because he shows that the further into
Rancière's text we go, the more clearly we see his rejection of an Arendtian
conception of the pure political sphere. In turn, I want to develop this notion of
an impure politics beyond Rancière's polemical rejections of Arendt.
These various accounts of Arendt and Rancière help to shed sorne light on
the general relationship between their work that has begun to fOlm within the
field of political theory, and it reveals something of the tendency to try to think
their thought "together." But wh ether such thinking takes the problematic form
of fitting Rancière into the Arendtian framework, or more clearly marking
their differences, it nonetheless attests to a general tendency to try to under-
stand Rancière by seeing him as at least complementary to Arendt. While 1
have emphasized the difference between Beltrân's approach, on the one hand,
and that of Honig and Schaap, on the other, even in the case of these last two
authors, it might be tempting for sorne readers to collapse the differences be-
tween Rancière and Arendt by way of the fact that Honig and Schaap also
draw from both of them for their distinct accounts of politics. That is, although
POLITICS 1
Yet as pure would the necessary
of the heterogeneous" that enacts politics (Rancière 1999: 32). politics
must be other to police, but not purely other. The to responding to this
paradox is to refuse to overcome it. Instead, Rancière's account of politics
must be understood as thinking the paradox, as capturing its fiavor and mobi-
lizing its force, rather than attempting to erase or resolve it. To defend this sort
of paradoxical argument means starting with a rejection of the idea of pure
politics a rejection that Rancière makes repeatedly and one that 1 have de-
fended in this section - but it is impossible to rest here. We must also grasp the
relation between politics and police. And while we need to understand the re-
lation as precisely as possible, we must al ways also insist that the relation
itself can never be specified with mathematical precision. On the topic of this
relation, so central to Rancière's thought, no English-language commentator
on Rancière has shed more light than Jean-Philippe Deranty - and Deranty
offers the clearest example of a third incorporationist strategy in his reading of
Rancière.
Deranty has written a number of articles (in English) that provide comprehen-
sive overviews of the political thought of Rancière. Arguing in particular that
Rancière's work can be best understood within the context of the politics of
recognition, Deranty compares Rancière's arguments directly to the work of
Axel Honneth (Deranty 2oo3a). For the most part (and in the context of my
particular work here) 1 am not overly concerned with Deranty's broader argu-
ments; however, 1 do note that Deranty's reading is doubtless inflected by his
own desire to link Rancière with the tradition of the politics of recognition.
Surely Hegel is the most prominent theorist of recognition and the most sig-
nificant figure in the tradition of dialectical thought (and, anecdotally, Hegel is
the other author upon whom Deranty has focused most of his work). More-
over, although Deranty would never reduce Rancière' s thought to the dialectic,
he still sees Rancière's conception of politics within the terrns of the dialectic.
He refers, for example, to "the dialectic between equality and inequality" that
is punctuated by Rancièrean politics (Deranty 2oo3a: 153). The context of
Deranty's reading thus suggests an "incorporation" of Rancière's thought into
the already established politics of recognition, linked to a long history of
Hegelian and dialectical thinking.
My own reading of Deranty does not try to generalize from this broader
context, but rather focuses specifically on a particular set of powerful and im-
portant claims that Deranty makes about how we should understand the rela-
tion between politics and police. 1 am somewhat surprised that Deranty's
argument on this front has not had a bigger impact on the English-Ianguage
POLITICS 1 51
terms of Marchart's own broader work (a book on
this moye makes sense, since it allows Marchart to show that while not ",r",1-rH..,"'"
with or insisting upon the distinction between politics and the (and as
would note, while not explicitly or formally using the term le politique at aIl)
Rancière, in a way, stumbles upon what Marchart caUs "political difference."
For other thinkers this is the difference between le politique and la politique,
whereas for Rancière it is the difference between la politique and la police.
And l should note that Marchart himself does not dwell on this point - Rancière
is certainly not one of the central thinkers of "political difference" -- and there-
fore Marchart may weIl be more alert to the slippery and impure thinking of
politics in Rancière that l try to track and assert here.
Neyertheless, in terms of my own argument, Marchart's key quote on Ran-
cière (from aboye) to the effect that la politique becomes "the political" for
Rancière, does seem odd, especially considering that the English translators of
Rancière's key texts on politics (the works from the early 1990s) haye seen fit
to translate, and do so rather consistently, la politique as "politics" and not as
"the political." That is, for those reading Rancière's work in English transla-
tion, "the poli tic al" makes no appearance at aIl. Thus, l would suggest that it
might make more sense to leave Rancière out of the "political difference"
model entirely, rather than trying to make him fit into it in inverted fashion.
The fact that Marchart quickly moves on from Rancière may be taken as evi-
dence that he too sees Rancière as not quite fitting the model.
In any case, things grow stranger when one turns from Marchart's brief
comments on Rancière and political difference to Marchart's reading ofZizek's
account of Rancière. In this context, Marchart tells us that Zizek finds his own
version of political difference in Rancière, which Marchart summarizes as
"the difference between 'la politique/police' and 'le politique'" (Marchmi
2007: 145). This formulation, especially in light of the earlier one, requires
sorne sorting out. Here again "the political" is distinguished from police. But
whereas in the earlier version we had the formula la politique =the political,
we now have a return to the more standard le politique =the poli tic al. At the
same time, this second formulation requires making la politique a synonym
for the police. Zizek's claim lO here strikes me as quite simply untenable since
Rancière's writings on politics consistently refer, in French, to a difference
between la politique and la police. Zizek asserts that la politique and la police
are the same for Rancière, when in fact the difference between them is the
fundamental and driving force in aU of Rancière 's writing on politics. If there
is to be any obvious "political difference" in Rancière it surely is to be found
here .- in the difference between la politique and la police that Rancière so
strongly insists upon. Again, one wonders wh ether the project of finding a
politics/the political distinction in Rancière is merely futile.
Perhaps, then, the distinction between politics and the political has no obvi-
ous place in Rancière's work. Indeed, at first glance it would seem that no
This tension between la police and la politique creates a necessary place where
they can and must be mediated. Rancière caBs this third term le politique. It
is the place where the underlying equality operating within social inequality
is verified pragmatically in struggles and demands of equality. In this place is
therefore also verified the wrongness and "wrungness" of a social order that is
otherwise presented as naturally ordered. It identifies victims of the tort and
those who perpetrate the tort. In simple words, le politique is always a demand
for justice. Le politique is in essence polemic (Deranty 2003b: par. 6, italics
original, bold added).
In a subtle yet stark departure from the standard reading, Deranty says there are
not two terms in Rancière's conceptual frame; there are three. Le politique is
the third tenn. 12 It identifies and points to that place in which the logic of domi-
nation contained by la police meets the presumption of equality mobilized
by la politique. As Deranty explains in his later note, this reading contends
that Rancière has taken on board, in a serious way, the Lacoue-Labarthe- and
Nancy-inspired distinction between le politique and la politique. However,
and utterly unsurprisingly, Rancière has mobilized the distinction for distinct,
if not opposite, ends. Whereas le politique for Nancy suggests something like
the very essence of "the political," which has been eroded or 10st within moder-
nity, Rancière, according to Deranty, uses the third term, le politique, precisely
so as to en able an anti-essentialist understanding of poli tics (Deranty 2003b:
footnote 27).
By introducing what he caUs the third tenn in Rancière's thinking of poli-
tics, Deranty offers a powerful and persuasive argument for how to interpret
the relation between la police and la politique. But we still have to ask whether
the reading is supported by the text; that is, is this difference between la poli-
tique and le politique actuaUy present in Rancière's writings? If the difference
does exist in French, it has by no means been preserved by Rancière's English
translators: neither Julie Rose, who translated La mésentente, nor Rachel
Bowlby and Davide Panagia, who translated "Dix thèses sur la politique" refer
to such a distinction; they make no effort whatsoever to calI attention to a
POLITICS 1
difference between le and la lJolltl~rue. The French texts themselves
UVI,H-HdV",-,
include very sparse references to le politique and make no mention of any ex-
plicit or meaningful distinction to be drawn between la politique and le poli~
tique. For example, aIl of the theses in the "10 Theses" use the French la
politique and never le politique (Rancière 1998a, 1995a). AIl of this evidence
leads to one central question: where, if anywhere, can we actually locate the
distinction in Rancière between la politique and le politique?
ln the case of Zizek we can safely say that the distinction is imposed upon
Rancière's writings from outside in an attempt to make his thought fit into a set
ofpremade categories (cf. Parker 200]: 71). But the answer in Deranty's case
cannot be that simple, because Deranty does not start with "political differ-
ence" and then fit Rancière to this mold; instead, his argument for the "three
terms" emerges directly from his own reading of Rancière. But if a strong
distinction between la politique and le politique cannot be found in either La
mésentente or "Dix thèses sur la politique," where did Deranty find it?
In repeatedly asking this question of myself 1 had begun to wonder, against
my better judgment, if he made it up. But, of course, he did not. The answer is
that Deranty very likely found the distinction (although he does not tell his
readers this) in Rancière's works that were originally written in English. To
reiterate for clarity's sake, the distinction that Deranty draws between la poli-
tique and le politique originates not in Rancière's better known writings on
poli tics but from a few lectures that Rancière presented in English. 13 ln I 99 I
Rancière gave the paper "Politics, Identification, Subjectivization" at a confer-
ence in the United States. The conference, as Rancière tells readers in the
preface to the second French edition of Aux bords du politique, was devoted to
"the American debate over the question of identity," and circled around issues
of nationalism and racism (Rancière I998a: I3, emphasis added).14 The con-
ference organizers posed specific questions to the paper-givers, and Rancière
chose to structure his talk directly in response to one of those. In just his second
paragraph, after clearing the ground concerning his having to give the lecture
in English, a language that is not his own, Rancière writes, "1 quote from the
third point of the list of issues we were asked to address: 'What is the politi-
cal?' " (Rancière 1995c: 63).15 Thus, the very idea of thinking about "the po-
li tic al" cornes to Rancière from outside, from what was at the time a very
American-centric debate over multiculturalism, and it is voiced in a foreign
language, English. Rancière then goes on to give his answer to the question,
"What is the political?" This answer corresponds perfectly weIl with Deran-
ty's commentary: "The political is the encounter between two heterogeneous
processes." The first process Rancière calls "policy"; the second is "equality"
(Rancière 1995c: 63). As Deranty will echo more th an a decade later, Rancière
says, "We have three terms," but at this point those terms are "policy, emanci-
pation, and the political" (Rancière I995c: 64; cf. Deranty 2003b: par. 6). Ran-
cière then suggests we name the process of emancipation "politics." Finally, if
POLITICS 1 55
la politique. The blurb reads: le itself as an of
philosophical thought, it is without doubt that this neutral adjective conve-
niently signifies a variation with the substance of la politique, in its
sense of a fight of the parties over power and the exercise of that power. To
speak of le politique and not la politique indicates the principles of law,
power, and community and not the activities of government" (Ranci ère
199 8a : 20).17
Given the importance of the second edition of Aux bords du politique to
Rancière's corpus, it seems likely that a reader picking up Rancière's work in
French over the past decade (a reader such as Deranty) would easily assume
that the difference between la politique and le politique had an important role
to play in Rancière's overall thinking of politics. For example, in the updated
and expanded German version of his book on poli tic al difference, Marchart
(2010) clarifies his account of Rancière specifically by adding a discussion of
this i 998 text. First, Marchart makes explicit the point that 1 suggested above,
that the fundamental "difference" for Rancière must certainly be that between
la politique and la police. He th en goes on to add that "the category of the
political, le politique, does not completely vanish" (Marchart 2010: 180, my
translation). 18 As evidence, Marchart cites the 1998 French translation of Ran-
cière's 1991 talk (originally in English), specifically where Rancière names
the "three terms" and suggests that "the political" is the terrain 19 for the en-
counter between the other two terms (Rancière 1995c [1991]: 64; Rancière
1998a: 84; Marchart 2010: 180). Unlike Deranty's texts from 2003, Marchart's
recent book thereby points directly to the "source" of Rancière's comments on
"the political."20 However, Marchart.'s German text is not widely available
and will surely not reach as many readers as Deranty's two earlier English-
language articles have done. For this reason sorne degree of mystery remains
concerning the three terms, and Deranty's reading still possesses a certain
gravitational force.
1 wish to resist that force by offering my own interpretation of "the politi-
cal" in Rancière's work. Before turning to that reading in the next section, 1
should emphasize here that despite the two very brief references to "the poli ti-
cal" in talks Rancière gave in English in the 2000S, it remains the case that the
vast majority of Rancière's writings on politics maintain no such distinction at
an. Most significantly, Rancière's central works on politics from the 1990S
were aIl produced after the 1991 lecture that had suggested three terms (in
English), yet Rancière did not bother to fold that terminology into La Mésen-
tente - clearly the central text of Rancière's devoted to politics and engaged
with the tradition of poli tic al philosophy. 1 therefore contend that there is
something very problematic about making the three terms of politics funda-
mental to one's interpretation of Rancière. To do so would be to take the French
translation of one short lecture coupled with an eight-page preface to a second
edition of a collection of essays, and use those texts as sorne sort of central
POLITICS 1 57
""',,,,,,",,'<, asserts in the face of a order is also a a
or torsion of the police order and its logic of inequality. In other words, 1 am
trying to apply to Deranty's own reading the anti-ontological torsion that Der-
anty so helpfully identifies in Rancière's wode Thus contend that there are
not really three distinct tellliS in Rancière's argument. Ifthere were three terms,
all three of them could be pure: a realm of domination (police), a realm of dis-
sensus (politics), and a ground upon which they meet (the political). But this
would be to center an essential conception of politics, le politique, as an onto-
logical foundation. This, as Deranty stresses and as 1have been arguing through-
out this chapter, could not be further from Rancière's project. As Rancière and
both consistently emphasize, Rancière avoids aIl ontology (Rancière 20IIC;
Rancière 2009b; Ieven 2009).21 Hence my argument: we do not have three
terms (police, politics, the political) but merely a doubling of one of the two
terms. In his recent essay on method, Rancière refers to "a doubling up of the
notion of politics" (Rancière 2009b: 121). And it seems more than anecdotal
to point out that this essay, specifically devoted to method and dealing at length
with the question of political theory, makes no mention whatsoever of a differ-
ence between politics and the poli tic al (nor one between la politique and le
politique).
PoUtics is doubled, always and already. It is "doubled" in that it is never
singular and never pure - "always and already" because the doubling is not a
secondai)' process that happens to a pre-given poli tics, but an essential feature
of la politique in the first place. Politics, like the logos 1 will discuss in Chapter
Three, is subject to an original taint - split from itself, split into two from the
beginning (Rancière 1999: 16,61). Thus, politics cannot be pure in Rancière's
thought, nor can there be a clear "poli tic al difference" in his work (la poli-
tique/le politique) because in his writings, politics doubles itself; that is, we
cannot distinguish le politique from la politique, given that neither is singu-
lar. 22 Let me unpack this dense formulation of the argument and explore sorne
of its implications.
First, 1 make the case for a "doubled politics" as a solution of sorts to the di-
lemma of how to translate - which is nothing other than the question of how to
read - Rancière: if la politique is never simply itself (never pure, never one),
then we can understand how it is both the disruptive other to the police order and
somehow simultaneously a part of the police order. La politique is always ulti-
mately opposed to and transformative of la police, but since the former is never
simply itself, it cannot be taken to be wholly external to and outside of the latter.
ln grasping for a third term, le politique, Deranty actually goes sorne distance
toward bringing this dimension of doubling into play in Rancière's work, but
1 insist on the crucial importance of the doubling of la politique, rather th an the
preservation of its purity through the introduction of a third teilli.
This approach to reading Rancière works not only for those texts that do
not mention le politique but also for those that do. 1 have been insisting that
POLITICS 1 59
Îs archë. Rancière says, refers a power of the dëmos
that is not authorized by any archë at aIl. Furthermore, Rancière here in-
sists that the political can only emerge out of democracy. All politics is demo-
cratic politics because "the political" appears only when la politique confronts
la police. Rancière expresses the point this way:
Power must become political. For that to happen the logic of the police has to
be thwarted by the logic of politics. Polities means the supplementation of an
qualifications by the power of the unqualified. The ultimate ground on which
rulers govem is that there is no good reason as to why sorne men should rule
others. Ultimately the practice of ruling rests on its own absence of reason
(Ranci ère 2010b: 53).
Thus we might say that in one sense Deranty was right aIl along: le politique
provides the ground for politics. However, this "ultimate ground" tums out to
be absolutely no ground at aIl, and le politique can therefore in no way be
thought as a prior space that mediates the confrontation between politics and
police. Quite the contrary: the political only cornes about because of the irrup-
tion ofpolitics within a police order. Notice here that Rancière repeatedly uses
the word political - again, in English - as an adjective. He does not refer to
"the political" as a fundamental, ontological category that makes poli tics pos-
sible. Instead, he shows how the dissensus of politics brings about "political
govemment" or "political power."
And in this way Rancière's own use of the adjective political points directly
toward the impurity of politics. It is not politics but rather policing that would
seek to predetermine the field of le politique: "The logic of the police consists
in delimiting the sphere of the political" and it does so "in the name of the
purity of the political." Against this notion of purity Rancière caUs on a demo-
cratic poli tics of impurity: "Democratie logic ... consists in blurring and dis-
placing the borders of the political" (Rancière 2010b: 54). This account of
what 1 would prefer to caB politicalness (to distinguish it from the category of
"the political"), pulls together a number of strands of my argument, since we
can see here that the very idea of having "the political" name a demarcated
space - this idea belongs to or at least partakes of police logic. After an, de-
marcating spaces is what policing does. Democratie logic, on the other hand,
unsettles those demarcations, and it often does so by finding or making "politi-
cal" that which did not seem political beforehand: it makes non-qualifications
into qualifications and rend ers the apolitical political. In short, it politicizes.
This aIl means that politicalness is not a third terrn that Rancière would
conceptualize or define. Put differently, "the political" is not a part of his con-
ceptual vocabulary or critical apparatus in the way that la police and la poli-
tique clearly are.lnstead, politicalness would be better described as a dimension
of the struggle of dissensus; it is an aspect of certain distributions of the sen-
sible, and it is a result of conflict, not a theoretical condition for politics. To say
POLITICS 1 61
'-'Bq,nJlU".'" on the non-dialectical nature of Rancière's thought. from
itself (containing the traces of both la politique and le politique within it), poli-
tics could never be pure. am arguing both with and against Deranty here:
agree that to render Rancière's telillS in dialectical fashion is to misconstrue
them badly, but 1 think we best avoid this false construal by avoiding alto-
gether the hypostatization of three terms in Rancière. This gets at a more gen-
eral point: it always proves very hard to avoid dialectics simply by daiming a
position as non-dialectical. Any opposition to dialectics always remains sub-
ject to being captured by dialecticallogic, of turning that "opposition" into the
negative moment on the way to dialectical synthesis. Thus, my goal here with
respect to Deranty's interpretation of Rancière centers on making a more con-
certed effort to avoid a dialectical rendering of Rancière's thought. 26
The three-tenn model tends, as 1 have shown, to purify politics. In addition,
that approach also seems to ignore quite blatantly a crucial point that Rancière
himself frequently makes: politics and police meet within the police order
itself. Politics goes on in the only place where it can go on: within the social
formation where it occurs, that is, within the space of the police order. And
politics must be doubled because of this very fact about its spatio-temporal
location because politics is that which opposes the terms of the police order
but does so within its terms. Only an impure form of politics could do such a
thing. Zizek tries to fit Rancière's thought into the category of "pure politics"
(Zizek 2006: 75) because he wants to lump Rancière together with other "post-
Althusserians" such as Balibar and Badiou - while distinguishing Zizek hi m-
self from the lot of them. But as I have shown, Rancière does not fit into this
"pure poli tics" category, and in trying to force him there, Zizek badly mischar-
acterizes Rancière's thought. Rancière could not be more direct: "There is no
'pure' politics" (Rancière 201IC: 3). This daim does more than just refute
Zizek's characterization, showing why Rancière is no mere "post-Althusserian";
the daim demonstrates that in trying to grasp the meaning and importance of
Rancière's conception of politics as that which iITupts into any given police
order, we must see the interconnected nature of poli tics and police.
In a crucial passage that responds to critics who would (mis)read him as
proposing the purity of politics, Rancière writes (and 1 comment in brackets),
"Politics does not stem from a place outside of the police .... There is no place
outside of the police. [And hence there need not be a third place where politics
and police meet aIl 'meeting' is conftict within the police order itself.] But
there are confticting ways of doing things with the 'places' that it allocates: of
relocating, reshaping or redoubling them" (Rancière 20IIC: 6, emphasis
added). I italicize Rancière's use of "redoubling" because the word itself is a
doubling of double, connecting directly to my broader argument about how to
understand his conception of politics. To remain both impure and non-dialectical
(politics' impurities cannot merely be waiting to be removed through a process
of sublation), politics must always be "redoubled" in this way.27
POLITICS 1
say how we must think and act" 20IIC: But it is no means
to reject "political theory" in a more broadly conceived form, for a commit-
ment to the impurity of polities is a commitment to another task, a reraising of
the question, "How are we to reinvent politics?" (Rancière I995c: 70).
A Rancièrean reinvention of polities must remain committed to the impu-
rity of polities; it must consistently resist the temptation to shelter polities in
its own proper sphere. Above aIl, a reinvention of polities, for Rancière, must
never lose sight of, and must never fail to understand, the sites of domination
and inequality, for these are the very locations of those rare moments of poli-
ties. Polities happens on the telTain of the police. Therefore, a reinvention of
politics must begin not with the ground of equality or the conditions that char-
acterize the free and autonomous individual. Instead, politics begins with the
hierarchy, inequality, and structural domination of aIl social orders. A new
thinking of polities can only start with la police.
POLICE 1
without there would be to contaminate I-.H.H"""''''>J.
This chapter therefore caUs for a shi ft from anarchism to a rearticula-
tion of Rancière's allegiance to democracy. 1mportantly, Rancière's "democ-
racy," as he frequently reminds his readers, is not a regime. As he polemically
explains, "We do not live in democracies" (Rancière 2006c: 73). Therefore, a
theory of democracy inspired by Rancière - which may or may not remain a
"Rancièrean" theory of democracy - depends not on dismissing or rejecting aIl
police orders, but on investigating and grappling with them. It demands further
development of Rancière's provocative but ellipticai comments concerning the
"neutraIity" of la police and about the superiority of sorne police orders to
others.
POLICE 1
resists his associated with more
famous) French theorists, when it comes to his concept of the police, he notes
its connections to one of the most famous French thinkers of aIl, Michel Fou-
cault. Foucault's work shows that "the police" may include an vertical rela-
tionships between human beings, while also bringing in material relations -links
between humans and the world (Foucault 2002a).
Rancière has this context in mind when, immediately after introducing the
term la police in Disagreement, he admits that it "poses a few problems." It is
here that Rancière first insists that we dissociate his thinking of "police orders"
from the actions on the ground of either beat cops or feds. But Rancière stresses
that the distinction should be drawn not as a matter of definitional fiat, since a
"nalTow definition [of police] may be deemed contingent" (Rancière 1999:
And we know this because of the work of Foucault, who se lectures on
seventeenth- and eighteenth-century "reason of state" showed that "the petty
police is just a particular form of a more general order that alTanges that tan-
gible reality in which bodies are distributed in community" (Rancière 1999:
28; see Foucault 2002a; cf. May 2008: 41 and Muhle 20072). The term polic-
ing can therefore be used to designate a broad set of phenomena concemed
with structuring and ordering a social formation. The police arranges reality,
in the sense that it distributes people and things into locations and roles.
The connection to Foucault and the argument made conceming him both
prove crucial at this juncture. As l showed briefly in Chapter One, Rancière's
concept of a "police order" cannot be dissociated from his larger concept of le
partage du sensible. The multivalent phrase contains at the same time both the
sense of dividing up the world, of ordering it, of structuring it, on the one han d,
and the sense of connection, of linkages, and sharing, on the other. Rancière
describes le partage du sensible as that which "define[s] the modes of percep-
tion" that make any order both visible and say able. Any configuration of the
world that we might encounter depends on a prior distribution/partition/shar-
ing of the sensory realm. 3 The distribution is a distribution of "parts" and of
places, of spaces for being in that world. In a crucial formulation, Rancière
writes, "Le partage du sensible is the cutting-up of the world and of 'world'"
(Rancière 2001: par. 20). l call this a crucial way of putting it, because in one
succinct statement Rancière has combined two absolutely essential elements
of his thinking of the partage. First, the idea of a "cutting-up" points to the
multiple senses of partition (of the world) as simultaneously separating and
connecting. To put up a partition means to wall off one area from another, but
erecting partitions also creates a new space where there was not one before.
The partition excludes, and at the same time it makes a new form of participa-
tion possible. Secondly, the "cutting-up" in this statement caBs attention to
sense and the sensible (the "world"); this is a cutting up that determines what
can be seen and what can be heard. Le partage du sensible determines a certain
sort. of intelligibility, of what "is" because it is made legible by the partage. 4
POLICE 1 ]1
will call the first policer: counts actual groups defined
by differences in birth, by different functions, locations, and interests that con-
stitute the social body, without any supplement" 2001: par. The
second, politics, therefore tries to make possible, to bring about, the SUlJPl(::;mem
that police will always seek to exclude. the police order is notjust any sort
of partage du sensible, since what we might cal1 a "police partage" is one that
attempts to account for and to contain aIl. A police order is a partage du sensible
that admits of no remainder, that excludes the possibility of any supplement. The
dissensus produced by politics is indissociable from its introduction of a supple-
ment where there is supposed to be none.
But this does not, according to Rancière, make the police order totalizing in
the sense of determining a repressive state order - hence the importance of the
other intellectual context that Rancière provides, when he insists that the con-
cept of police order must not be confused with Althusser's concept of "state
apparatus" (Rancière 1999: 29; see Althusser 1971).5 State apparatus, says
Rancière, cannot be disconnected from a conception of state standing in op-
position to society, a notion that depends, from Rancière's perspective, on con-
fusing poli tics with police. More than this, to take police as a repressive force
is to miss the crucial disclaimers that Rancière offers concerning his concept
of "police order." In other words, while as readers of Rancière we tend to cel-
ebrate politics in its very opposition to police, it would be too easy to simply
dismiss or denigrate aIl police as repression or violence. Rancière warns his
readers to avoid such a faulty interpretation, yet l wonder if we have paid
proper heed to these alerts. Perhaps they are worth enumerating:
This list opens up an enormous area of inquiry for explaining and developing
Rancière's understanding of police, its role in his politico-theoretic work, and
its salience for a broader thinking of contemporary politics. l will come back
to these dimensions later, for now l simply want to bring my logic here to sorne
closure by pointing out the limitations to an approach that would take la police
in Rancière as nothing more than a counterweight to politics. If we refuse to
reduce police to a mere tirst postulate, a given necessary to Rancière's thinking
of politics, we are left with a different set of questions. Most important among
them is this: what work does the concept do for us? In the context of Ran-
cière' s writings from the mid- 1990s, largue that police serves to specify and
POLICE 1 73
transform a11 confiict into a fOIm of Consensus is thus
the end of democracy - "in a word, the disappearance of politics" (Rancière
1999: I02; see also 2008: I46).
The concept of "the police" provides the crucialleverage for the critique of
consensus democracy. Rancière's ability to take the neoliberal marketing of
"consensus" and show how it boils down to the curious and feeble fonn of
"post-democracy" depends upon the critical lens provided by la police. Ran-
cière's polemic here amounts to much more than merely decreeing that consen-
sus democracy contains no politics, that it is only police. That is, of course, true.
But on Rancière's terms it would a1so be true of almost aIl institutionalized
political regimes. The key to the critique lies in showing that consensus democ-
racy commits itself to the elimination of politics. It is a police order devoted to
its own pure and perpetuaI preservation, a police order that strives for its own
perfection as a police order. Thus, consensus democracy is post-democracy in
the same way that the Platonic kallipolis would be post -democracy. It does not
merely exclude politics from policing; it puts an end to politics. Doubtless, it
does this self·consciously in calling for just that: "the end of politics." This
means that despite operating on very much distinct terrains, post-democracy
functions in a similar manner to political philosophy. For Rancière, the latter is
a philosophical ordering project designed to replace politics with police. The
former is a putatively "political" project airning for the same goal. Both use the
name "politics" as a banner under which to seek the elimination of politics. 8
Clearly, then, Rancière's concept of police works in the service of his own
political interventions. In this context 1 want also to emphasize the different
levels on which Rancière's most explicitly "political" texts operate (i.e.,
Shores, Disagreement, and Hatred). Disagreement, for ex ample, can easily be
read as an abstract and detached philosophical work. After aIl, it opens both its
preface and its introduction with quotes from Aristotle; it operates on a dense
and philosophically obtuse level of logical reasoning; it seems to cite only
historical examples of politics (and not contemporary instances), and to do so
in the service of very broad and general points. And most commenta tors read
Disagreement the way they rnight read Arendt's The Human Condition or any
other work in political theory: as a project of philosophy or, at most, political
ontology. This approach can be encouraged by assigning only the tirst sixtY
pages of the text to students. (1 plead guilty.) Perhaps this is why most explora-
tions of Rancière's political theory center themselves on the tirst half of Dis-
agreement, supplemented by sorne of the theses from "Ten Theses."
The worry is that such an approach tums Rancière into a political philoso-
pher, when he himself has mounted a damning critique of the project of politi-
cal philosophy. How do you theorize politics while avoiding the trap of political
philosophy? Perhaps you link your conception of politics to your assessment
of and engagement with the contemporary political situation. Understanding
Rancière's thinking of politics requires working with his political interventions
Perhaps 1 should remove aIl possibility of confusion at the outset of this sec-
tion: it is not 1 who will be "defending anarchism," but May who does so in his
book, The Political Thought of Jacques Rancière (2008). Indeed, as 1 hinted at
the beginning of this chapter, while May's book offers a vibrant, engaged, and
always thought-provoking set of arguments in and around Rancière's writings,
it seems a very oddly titled work. Simply put, it does not set out to articulate
"the poli tic al thought" of Rancière; rather, it seeks to mobilize a particular
reading of Rancière's work in support of a spirited defense of anarchism (see
May 1994) hence the title of my section. 1 say this not as a critique of May
but rather to set the stage for an engagement with his work. Thus, my daim
that May's book does not provide an overall account of the "political thought
of Jacques Rancière" is not itself a polemical daim. A reviewer of May's book
as sympathetic and knowledgeable about Rancière as Miguel Vatter has said
the same thing, right at the start of his review: "In reality, the book is less an
in-depth interpretation of Rancière than it is a plaidoyer for the daim that
democratic politics belongs within the tradition of anarchism, as opposed to
those of liberalism or Marxism" (Vatter 2008: par. r).
1 tum to May not because his book was the first secondary sourcebook on
Rancière (and remained the only one for a number of years), but because his
POLICE 1 75
aOt,ro,a.ch to Rancière proves invaluable for the stakes of
Rancière's concept of la police. appropriation of Rancière's thought for
anarchist purposes requires a very determined and distinct interpretation of
and this means that his argument helps me to work through what re-
ferred to above as the "poli tics of the police." Let me state the argument suc-
cinctly before unpacking it through my reading of May. "elevates" politics
to a pure form of action, while reducing police to an anti-political and implic-
itly repressive order of domination and injustice. This leads, 1 argue, to an
unproductive conception of "the police" in the service of a limited theory of
politics.
The steps to reach this conclusion prove subtle, because in so many ways
appears to be an exemplary reader of Rancière. Most praiseworthy is
refusaI to make Rancière into a philosopher; May sees clearly, and fre-
quently reminds his readers of, the political stakes of the Rancièrean project.
Bm on my reading, Rancière's politics are not the same as May's, and May is
thereby often forced to appropriate creatively -- or sometimes simply to misread
- Rancière in order to get to the anarchist conclusions that May had quite
clearly decided on from the outset. 9 This divergence likely begins with May's
account of "the police," which, as mentioned above, proves notable because
May gives the police so much attention. May begins by emphasizing Ran-
cière's own point, that the idea of a broadly understood "police order" can be
tied back to Foucault's lectures from the 1970s, where Foucault traces the
genealogical origins of the tenn in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century Euro-
pean thought. May shows the extent to which Rancière's use of the term over-
laps with Foucault's, while noting that Rancière develops the term quite
differently. But when it cornes to that development, May makes a very signifi-
cant interpretive choice. At just this juncture, he writes, "Policing, as Rancière
defines it, is deeply embedded in Western political philosophy" (May 2008:
42). May contends that Rancière locates the first occurrence of such policing
in Plato, and May explicates the concept of the police primarily through a
summary of Rancière's interpretation and critique of the Platonic philosophy
of order (May 2008: 42-43).
But this is a curious exegesis, because when Rancière himself introduces
the term police, he defines it in a context outside the project of political phi-
losophy. As 1 have already argued above, for Rancière, police names an order
of intelligible bodies, a distribution and counting of the parts of society. Police
is "a symbolic constitution of the social" (Rancière 2001: par. 19). Now, it is
very much true that in both Disagreement and "Ten Theses" Rancière goes on,
later, to make a crucial argument about Platonic political philosophy and po-
Iicing. But the claim is not that Plato is an example of policing. The claim is
that Plato's political philosophy substitutes police for politics, that the struc-
ture of Plato's philosophical project operates in such a way that it identifies
poli tics with police. And this identification of the two amounts to the elimination
POLICE 1 77
basic terms of as an to and rh ".,."r-rn.ra
Rancière reminds his readers that poli tics remains inescapably twined with
police. He writes, "We should not forget either that if politics implements a
logic entirely heterogeneous to that of the police, it is al ways bound up with
the latter" (Rancière 1999: 3 1; cf. Rancière 200 1: par. 21) Y
At this point one might accuse me of being either unfair to (in the nar-
rowness of my hermeneutic criticisms) or at least somewhat pedantic. 1 would
respond by arguing that the stakes of the se differences in conceptions of the
police turn out to be qui te high. They begin to emerge in May's reading when
he develops his anarchist account of democratic politics. May's anarchist
framework provides him with a structure in which to interpret sorne of the
most complex, subtle, and/or vexing elements of Rancière's thought. Primary
among these may be the fact that in taking almost everything we thought was
politics and calling it police, Rancière provokes his readers to ask the question
of when or where his poli tics happens. As 1 noted at the beginning of this chap-
ter, Rancière offers a direct response when he openly admits that politics
occurs "rarely" (Rancière 1999: 17). But for most readers, especially political
theorists, such an answer seems necessarily unsatisfying unless and until we
provide one of two possible supplements to it: (1) we can supplement the
response with an account of how to bring about such political moments; or
(2) we can add to this answer a further elaboration of why and to what extent
we should concern ourselves with phenomena that do not always add up to
political moments.
The first option seems the obvious choice for May. Indeed, one of the ways
in which Rancière's writings clearly do resonate with the project of anarchism
is on this point. Whereas so many readers of Rancière balk at the notion of poli-
tics happening so little, May positively likes the fact that democratic politics is
made rare in Rancière's account. Why? Because the rarity of politics fits with
the revolutionary and self-sustaining project of anarchism. May wishes to
define democratic poli tics as a process that enhances the lives of those who
engage in it. Democratic politics should be attractive to potential political actors
for just this reason, and the fact that there are few historical examples of demo-
cratic poli tics, the fact that democratic politics is rare - aIl this only makes it
more attractive. Why be an anarchist if anyone can do it or if it has aIl been done
before? May therefore wants to work within a space of political thought that
calls for an active self-creation of equality - and thereby perhaps implies or
even plans for the possibility of a revolution to come. 13 That Rancière defines
politics so as to make actual occun-ences of it scm"ce poses no problems for
May's political thought; rather, this dimension turns out to be an asset.
May's reading draws out a conception of democratic politics as a pure poli-
tics of the people thereby rendering democracy compatible with anarchism.
Anarchist thought, of course, depends upon maintaining a crucial distinction
between government and the people. 14 For example, May approvingly cites
POLICE 1 79
pnnclplE~S of of "classical anarchism from
Godwin to Kropotkin" (Vatter 2008: par. 1). This first idea of anarchism plays
a role of undoubted importance in Rancière's but problems emerge, as
1 have shown, when tries to interpret Rancière within the terms of this
second tradition of anarchist thought.
Moving past the terminological and historical questions of anarchism,
would insist on a series of more substantive points. For example, when Ran-
cière argues, as 1 quoted above, that politics will always be "bound up" with
police, he continues as follows: "The reason for this is simple: politics has no
objects or issues of its own" (Rancière 1999: 31). These are not isolated
remarks; in later writings Rancière expands and develops this notion in an
attempt to clarify the stakes of his project. In a passage 1 quoted in the previ-
ous chapter, Rancière claims that "the opposition between politics and police
goes along with the statement that politics has no 'proper' object, that aIl its
objects are blended with the objects of police" (Rancière 20IIC: 5). For Ran-
cière, there is no politics without police.
In contras t, May seeks a politics not only de-linked from police, but also
t'ully self-referential and committed to the substantive ground of equality.
Equality, for Rancière, is nothing like a substantive ground. Deranty puts it
succinctly: "Equality is not an essence, a value or a goal" (Deranty 2003b: par.
I). Equality proves to be an assumption that can be verified, but it grounds
nothing at aIl in Rancière's thought. For Rancière, politics therefore proves to
be the demonstration of the assumption of equality; it occurs if and only if
there is an encounter between the logic of equality and the logic of domina-
tion. It i8 just this assumption of equality that makes possible the clash be-
tween heterogeneous logics; the verification of equality results from such
conilict. This explains why equality can be understood in Rancière neither as
a substantive good nor as an ideal telos. But this means, contra May, that poli-
tics does not occur because of equality, nor does politics achieve equality. AIl
politics does is to challenge, to thwart, to disrupt or dislocate, and perhaps
finally to change the police order. 15
As 1 have already discussed in the previous chapter, and as 1 will elaborate
in my final section, below, 1 think this is enough for politics to do. However, at
times, it is not enough for May. Because he insists on reading Rancière with
and against the grain of distributive theories of justice, May repeatedly asks
Rancière for normative grounds (e.g., May 2008: 119). And while he remains
very sensitive to Rancière's own understanding of equality as not providing
such grounds, May still frequently implies that perhaps equality serves this
function in (a reconstructed) Rancièrean thought, after an (cf. May 2008: 118).
Moreover, May frequently hints at the notion that equality might, someday, be
achieved as a substantive end (May 2008: 75; May 2009: 117).
Given that close readers of Rancière will tend to reject the foundationalist
approach of Rawlsian or Habermasian normative political philosophy, the
A polities rnay or rnay not effect change. It is not in the consequence but in the
acting out of a presupposition of equality that politics occurs .... A dernocratie
polities is defined by the actions and the understandings ofthose who struggle,
not by the effects upon or actions taken by those the police order supports.
(May 2008: 72, ernphasis added; cf. May 2009: 1 I3)
Despite the fact that Rancière's own examples of politics aIl seem to involve
new partitions of the sensory realrn, the radical disruption and reordering of
the police order - "the essence of poli tics is to disturb" the police order, says
Rancière (Rancière 2001: par. 21) - May insists here that the ultimate defini-
tion of democratic politics is found not just in the actions but in the under-
standings of democratic subjects. 1 have called this a "self-referential"
definition of politics, not because it is circular, but because it refers politics
back to agents rather than to political effects.
It is just this dimension of May's argument that suggests a need for aug-
mentation in the form of nonnative grounds. In other words, if poli tics only
exists when agents struggle, there needs to be sorne leverage, sorne motivation,
sorne way to mobilize that struggle. Within the ternIS of May's logic, the sub-
stantive comrnitment to equality provides that nonnative edge. However, this
redefinition of democratic politics as emerging out of the self-understanding
of democratic actors has the curious but significant result of further denigrat-
ing the police. If poli tics refers only to itself, police is only important as a foil
for understanding politics. And May himself stresses this point when he insists
POLICE 1 81
orders. Here echoes his lines
from above, during his discussion of anarchism. He argues that anarchism
does not strive for a change in government, a new form of government or a
different set of people in power, but the overcoming of power. first quotes
Colin Ward: "Anarchism ... doesn't want different people on top, it wants us to
clamber out from underneath" and th en goes on to insert the following: "(Com-
pare this statement to Rancière's position that a democratic politics seeks to
undermine police orders, not change or modify them)" 2008: 96; quot-
ing Ward I982: 22).
This seemingly innocent parenthetical requires serious comment. First,
reference to "Rancière's position" is actually an internaI cross-reference
within May's own text, because it is May himself, not Rancière, who argues on
page 72 (cf. 43) ofhis book that politics does not seek to change police orders.
But neither there nor at the moment of this parenthetical statement does May
citc Rancière at aIl. And as 1 have shown, in Rancière's hands politics has no
autochthonous goal that it seeks of its own volition. Politics stands opposed to
police, but always in relation to police. And this opposition always manifests
itself in the form of transformed police orders, not undone police orders. But
second, what 1 say here is surely no surprise to May, or any other reader of
Rancière. Just three pages later, May writes, "Democratic politics ... does not
lead to a final state of justice but perhaps only to better conditions in a police
order" (May 2008: 99). What accounts for the difference, and apparent contra-
diction, between these two quotations from May? The tirst appears as a paren-
thetical commentary on a summary of anarchist thought; the second emerges
during an attempt to sort out Rancière's conception ofpolitics relative to anar-
chist goals. In other words, May's attempt to make Rancière play the role of
resource and support for anarchism leads May to stretchings and distortions of
Rancière's thought that prove readily apparent to most readers of Rancière-
including, at other points in his text, May himself.
Ultimately, however, my disagreement with May centers not on working
toward the "right" reading of Rancière. My primary concern is how to under-
stand the relation between politics and police - how to grasp that relation so as
to give an account of democratic politics. May articulates that relation as fol-
lows: "Politics arises as an alternative to the police. It must arise in a police
order, since otherwise there would be no need for it (because there would be
no inequality). It engages with the police, but not primarily as a struggle
against it. It engages primarily as an expression of equality" (May 20I2: I).
For May, any disruption of the police order, any production of a new distribu-
tion of the sensible, will only come about as side-effects of the internaI cre-
ation of equality that is politics. For me, this entire account severely depreciates
the importance of police orders and along the way undermines the power and
importance of democratic politics. May's commitment to a pure concept of
politics, one that is self-sustaining and never "parasitic upon the police" (May
if the worlds were entirely distinct, if they had no point of contact, every po-
litical struggle would be a fight to the death. Every democratic political strug-
gle would reduce itself to a struggle between two competing visions, only one
of which could prevail. There could be no democratic politics that wasn't en-
tirely revolutionary. (May 2008: 112)
But this is just what happens within the tenns of May's interpretation of poli-
tics and police. Police bec ornes pure domination and politics becomes purely
revolutionary. Further, 1 would suggest that May articulates this problem so
accurately because it plagues his anarchist reinterpretation of Rancière. May
recognizes that democratic politics does not work this way, yet May thinks that
the Manichean separation of worlds is overcome by a sort of dialectical media-
tion of a third tenn: "There is at least one cornmon normative element in any
nominally democratic society that binds those who struggle and those against
whom they struggle. This common element [is] a commitment to equality"
(May 2008: 112). May's misreading ofpolitics and police (as radically separa te)
must therefore be supplemented by a rnisreading of equality (as substantive
POLICE 1 83
as have shown Rancière's own
does not need a third tenu, since in Rancière' s understanding, politics and
never form separate worlds; are always and already "bound up"
with one another. Rancière says it "There is no politics"
cière 201 IC: 3).
And it is in this binding, in this unavoidable meeting of the logic of poli-
tics with the logic of the police, that we may locate a viable and salient
thinking of "the politics of the police." In the final section, then, make the
case for this rendering of police, and 1 counter May's anarchist vision of
poli tics with a reassessment of a democratic politics that retains both impu-
rit y and impropriety.
here has not been to dismiss or even solely to refute but rather to use an
engagement with his quasi-dialectical rendering of the police/politics distinc-
tion so as to call for a reassessment and rethinking of Rancière's own catego-
ries. In other words, the fact that ends up, as showed to
such non-Rancièrean conclusions while working from Rancièrean premises
should lead us to a reinvestigation of those premises. 1 have tried to carry out
such an investigation here by taking seriously Rancière's own understandings
of la police, and by pushing his analysis into a deeper exploration of the mean-
ing and political stakes of his concept of the police. The politics of the police
is not a third tenn, but rather a way to think about the motion already present
between the tirst two terms - a way to consider what is at stake in Rancière's
conception of an impure politics, one necessarily, and always already, bound
up with police orders.
In closing 1 wish to delineate one other crucial dimension of la police and
its politics: namely, "the politics of the police" in the most banal sense. Jump-
ing off and fOl'ward from my discussion from May, 1 insist on a commitment
to and concern with the polities of the police in the quite elemental sense of
changing, transforming, and improving our police orders. As Alex Thomson
has very nicely put it, "There is doubtless much to do in tellliS of developing
better rather than worse forrns of police" (Thomson 2003: 1 1). When it cornes
to police, we require a democratic vigilance, not a utopian dismissal. Rancière
provokes his readers with his succinct assertion that "we do not live in democ-
racies"; instead, and as the only alternative, we live in police orders (Rancière
2006c: 73). May reads these claims as a utopian caU to fashion, someday, a
pure democracy. He reads them as not merely a critique but a denigration of
the world we do live in (a police order) in favor of the ideal of a true democ-
racy. Obviously, 1 read Rancière very differently. On my reading, we do not
live in democracies, and we never will. We never will, not because we will
never achieve what we ought to achieve, not because of failures on our part,
but because that is not what democracy is about. l ?
Democracy is not utopia. For this very reason, "struggle" means something
different to Rancière than it does to traditional Marxism - or even, 1 suspect,
to May. As my engaged reading of May makes clear, he places a certain sense
of "struggle" at the very heart of his conception of politics. More significantly
for my reading, May insists that the importance of struggle lies in its meaning
for those who do it. Rancière says almost the exact opposite when he treats the
POLICE 1
of a workers' strike. strike Îs the qumti;:sSeil1tlal eXélm1Dle of
'-'fHUUIIJL'V
gle" in the sense that uses it. But Rancière says that it is not a given that
a strike and therefore a certain sort of "struggle" in the traditional sense of
workers mobilizing against capital - is political. Rancière "A strike is
not political wh en it caUs for refOlTIlS rather than a better deal or when it attacks
the relationships of authority rather than the inadequacy of wages. It is poli ti-
cal when it reconfigures the relationships that determine the workplace in its
relation to the corn munit y" (Rancière 1999: 32). If a strike does nothing more
than demand better wages, then it simply does not produce a moment of poli-
tics, and in this case it can be clearly and legitimately understood as a negotiat-
ing move within a police order an attempt to improve the terms of that police
order without changing its structure in any significant way. On the other hand,
a strike may become political if it caUs into question the very organization of
the workplace. If the strike marks a moment of dissensus, a disruption of the
given partition/distribution of the sensible, then we can understand the strike
as a moment of politics. But this means that, in the sense used by traditional
accounts of workers' politics, the presence (or lack thereof) of so-called strug-
gle does not determine the possibility of poli tics. Struggle in this limited yet
traditional sense may be a central element of a police order. 18
Rancière has a different sense of struggle. He uses the word as another of
his synonyms for dissensus. Thus, when he writes, "To understand what de-
mocracy means is to hear the struggle that is at stake in the word," he points to
a more radical, more constitutive struggle than a mere dispute and negotiation
over resources (Rancière 2006c: 93, emphasis added). To hear "struggle" in
democracy means, as Rancière continues, to hear not only "anger and scorn"
but also, and more importantly, "the slippages and reversaIs of meaning that
[the word democracy] authorizes" (Ranci ère 2006c: 93). The struggle of de-
mocracy is a struggle over terrns, over places, over roles - over "propriety"
itself. For these reasons, the democratic meaning of struggle in Rancière' s
sense, which 1 am distinguishing here from more traditional Marxist accounts
of "struggle" as any collective action of workers, must not be understood as a
struggle that contains its own telos. What matters, as Rancière shows so lu-
cidly in his example of the strike, is not just that individuals come together, but
what is at stake, and what is put into question, in their coming together. This is
not a struggle merely for the sake of those who engage in it. It is the struggle
that is at stake in democracy.
Understood this way, we also see that democracy does not create equality,
and it does not eliminate government. Democracy is, instead, "the paradoxical
condition of politics" (Rancière 2006c: 94). And as 1 have shown in detail
above, a paradoxical politics is an impure politics. Democracy is both: "Demo-
cracy really means ... the impurity of politics" (Rancière 2006c: 62). This ex-
plains why democratic poli tics necessarily produces, and will continue to
create, "hatred of democracy" (Rancière 2006c: 94). Rancière fights against
POLICE 1
Write everywhere.
LlTERARITY 1
to ask what it would me an to THTn,,,,,,,, non-,mt:tlrC>Dc)centr'ic account of lan-
guage, and what the implications of such an account would be for politics. For
of course, a non-anthropocentIic conception of the language/poli tics
relation cannot be based on or fixed in an ontology. As have already noted in
previous chapters, Rancière's eschewal of ontology always places a certain
bm'den on his readers, as it makes it hard to get outside of his own polemics
without violating his work in a certain way. Here try this trick - the trick of
saying more and other than Rancière would say, but without rejecting or un-
dermining his own claims - by reinterpreting Rancière's arguments in the con-
text of debates over language and by posing to them the question of
anthropocentrism. 2 How can we think politics in a way that is non-anthropo-
centric and also not rooted in ontology? Rancière does not ask this question, of
course, but it can nonetheless be constructed from a reading of his work, and
his writings contain a provocative and rich answer - an answer that takes form
in the concept of literarity.
Rancière writes, "Humans are political animaIs because they are literary
animaIs" (Rancière and Panagia 2000: lIS). This chapter unpacks, unravels,
and twists this provocative and polemical claim. The link between the "politi-
cal animal" and the "literary animal" can only be drawn by literarity; to dem-
onstrate this point is to reveal the politics of literarity at the heart of Rancière's
project. lt goes without saying that the poli tics of literaIity is a democratic
politics and a politics of dissensus. Moreover, it is also a poli tics attentive to
the constitutive political importance of language a discursive politics. How-
ever, this is certainly not a discursive politics in the sense that deliberative
democrats use the word discursive. In clear contrast to a "discourse ethics"
approach that would seek to redeem liberal institutional practices "norma-
tively," the politics of literarity sharpens the contrast between liberal politics
and Rancière's democratic politics. Just as no philosophy of order can contain
"the excess of words," so in its own way does literarity undo liberalism. Liber-
alism cannot manage or process the force of literarity, despite its best efforts to
do so. Literarity opens a split between democracy and the liberal structures
that would narrow and constrain it. For aIl of these reasons literarity proves
centrally important to my broader reading of Rancière and to the arguments of
this book. It provides another layer to the arguments for politics and police that
l have already proposed in the first two chapters, and it sets the stage for my
account of critique in the final chapter.
This chapter traverses much terrain; hence a roadmap is in order. In the first
section, l start where Rancière and so many before him have started: with the
famous opening lines of Aristotle's Politics. l show that Rancière's interpreta-
tion of Aristotle has been fundamentally mis-presented in the English transla-
tion of Disagreement, making it more challenging than necessary for Rancière's
readers to grasp this, his central and opening argument in his most important
text on politics. Having clarified terms, l th en cast Rancière's polemical
L1TERARITY 1 91
on poli tics and his work most often read (or misread) as a book of political
claim: the first few lines of this book do not make sense. am not
suggesting that the 1ines are hard to follow, that their argumentative logic is
their meaning obscure, or their implications obtuse. am saying that a
careful reading of these lines shows them to be nonsensical: not just difficult,
but fully self-contradictory.
The problem lies not in anything that Rancière himself wrote, but in the
overall production of the English translation. In particular, let me spotlight the
coincidence of two different editorial choices made by the translator of Dis-
agreement, Julie Rose. Given the weight placed on Aristotle's words and the
significance of them for Rancière's argument, the words that actually appear,
in on page one of Disagreement prove to be something of a disap-
pointment. Rose says at the beginning of the notes that aIl translations in the
book are her own, but in the case of the Aristotle, that is simply not the case.
Rather than translating Rancière's French or Aristotle's Greek, Rose instead
substitutes a completely unattributed and uncited, but nonetheless verbatim
copy of T. A. Sinclair's 1962 Penguin Books translation (Aristotle 1981). This
is Rose's first choice. At best, it constitutes sloppy scholarship, but that is not
my criticism. 1 am concerned instead with the fact that Sinclair' s is a far from
literaI translation: it is a somewhat dated, somewhat wordy translation that
seems overwritten, especially for the purposes of Rancière's argument. The
Sinclair translation that opens the English version of Disagreement diverges
significantly, sometimes dramatically, from what appears in Rancière's text in
French.
These differences can make it more difficult to grasp Rancière's arguments,
but more importantly, they also lead to a fundamental misrepresentation of
Rancière's reading of Aristotle. This proves to be the case because Rose's
choice of the Sinclair translation has problematic implications for the render-
ing of Rancière's own opening lines. As 1 will discuss in greater detail below,
Aristotle specifies the distinction between voice and speech and the distinct
functions thereof. In Sinclair's translation, voice expresses, whereas speech
indicates. 3 Rose then makes a second choice when, in the lines that follow the
Sinclair version of Aristotle, Rancière uses the words indiquer and manifester.
Below 1 will show that these words, for Rancière, are clearly direct references
to the Aristotle lines that Rancière has rendered himself in French. At this
point 1 focus on only what the reader of the translated English text sees. Rose
has decided to translate indiquer and manifester as "indicate" and "express,"
respectively. Thus, in the English version of the text, one first reads of Aristo-
tle's distinction between voice, which expresses, and speech, which indicates,
and then one reads Rancière's reference to "speech, which expresses, while
the voice simply indicates" (Rancière 1999: 2). This is the specific claim that
makes no sense.
Of aIl the animaIs, only humans have speech [logos]. On the one hand, the voice
[phonë] falls to the other animaIs and is a sign [esti sëmeion] of the painful and
the pleasant. (Their nature has developed to this point: they perceive pain and
pleasure and can indicate these [literaIly: show by a sig n, sëmainein] to each
other.) On the other hand, speech [logos] makes visible [dëloun] the useful and
the harmful, so as [to make clear] the just and the unjust. This, in relation to the
other animaIs, is peculiar to humanity. The human animal alone has a perception
of good and bad, just and unjust, and so on. And the communion of these makes
a household and a city. (Aristotle 195T 1253a9-18, translation mine)5
In Aristotle we can see one sharp distinction, with other subtle differences
mapped onto it in tum. Fundamentally Aristotle means to distinguish between,
on the one hand, mere voice, phonë, which "faIls to" or "accrues" to aIl ani-
maIs, and on the other, "reasoned speech," logos, which only man possesses.
In addition, the relationship between types of animaIs and types of language
works differently in the two different cases. That is, phonë is given (passively)
to aIl animaIs, whereas logos is possessed (more activeIy) only by the human
animal. And finally, phonë and logos function differentIy. Phonë "is a sign"
LlTERARITY 1 93
sëmeion) or "indicates way of a (sëmainein), whereas logos can
make clear or make visible (dëloun). This means that phonë can only indicate
pleasure and pain, whereas logos can show or demonstrate what is just or
unjust. Unsurprisingly, these differences will prove central ta Rancière's read-
ing, and it will be no more of a surprise ta find Rancière, in his translation of
Aristotle, establishing his own distinctions in French, sa as ta set up that
reading.
Here is what Rancière's French translation looks like when rendered in
English:
Alone of aIl the animaIs, man possesses speech [parole]. Without a doubt the
voice [voix] is the method for indicating [indiquer] pain and pleasure. It is also
given to other animaIs. Their nature proceeds only up to a point: they possess
the feeling of pain and pleasure and they can indicate [indiquer] that among
themselves. But speech [parole] is there for demonstrating [manifester] the
useful and harmful and, as a result, the just and the unjust. Ifs this that is
man's own, compared to the other animaIs: man alone possesses the feeling of
good and bad, just and unjust. And it's the community of these things that
makes the family and the city. (Rancière I995a: I9, translation mine)
Let me note right from the start that by quoting the central ternIS of this claim
with Rancière's French left intact, and by presenting it in the context of Ran-
cière's own translation of Aristotle, we can clearly see that Rancière offers a
perfectly coherent, perfectly lucid interpretation of Aristotle. lndeed, in one
sense Rancière is simply repeating in this short quote what his careful transla-
tion of Aristotle already demonstrated: that the voice can only indicate while
speech can demonstrate. Yet he also adds one new dimension, which will prove
to be a very significant wrinkle: in addition to the paired terms that have been at
play from the beginning (animais/man, voice/speech, indicates/demonstrates)
Rancière suggests a third term. Above we see notjust the pair indique/manifeste,
LlTERARITY 1 95
On my own account of Aristotle - and Rancière's aside
briefty - the logos functions as a tool of sorts, one that the human animal can
wield so as to distinguish between good and bad. For citizens to fulfill their
functions within Aristotle's understanding of politics, must actively
engage in the life of the polis through judging and deliberating; to do so they
need the use of language (cf. Arendt 1958: 3). In this account, then, the very
nature of the political cornes to rest upon a certain conception of language,
because the political nature of Aristotle's citizens would prove unrealizable
without language. If one were to start with Aristotle's conception of man the
political animal using logos - and build out from it his the01)' of language, one
would run the risk of both instrumentalizing language (as the possession of
man) and presupposing an autonomous subject. That is, if language bec ornes
a tool to be wielded by human subjects, those subjects must precede the lan-
guage that they can possess and use for their own ends. This is a rather anthro-
pocentric theory that takes the subject as ontologically given and that tums
language into an object that can be controlled by people (Chambers 2003). It
is also, quite clearly, an approach that either proceeds by way of, or at least
invokes along the way, ontology.
Rancière therefore takes a distinct approach. Although he begins with Aris-
totle, Rancière, we might say, begins in disagreement. ln eschewing aIl ontol-
ogy, Rancière also rejects the idea of grounding politics in any theory of
language, and he most certainly denies Aristotle's conception. ln the "Ten
Theses on Politics" (2001), Rancière offers a deconstructive reading of Aristo-
tle, one that makes his "disagreement" with Aristotle stark. Here again, Ran-
cière says that political animaIs are marked by a sign (signe): "their possession
of the logos" (2001: par. 23).8 And Aristotle claims that this sign makes evi-
dent the distinction between the political animal and aIl others. Rancière, how-
ever, wants to provoke Aristotle, to polemicize. Thus, he asks a series of
questions of AIistotle that, l suggest, boil down to the following: How do we
read that sign? Is this signe that putatively marks the difference between
human political animaIs and aIl others so clearly legible as Aristotle seems to
think? Or, is the legibility of that sign precisely what politics would render
problematic? In response to Aristotle, in disagreement with him, Rancière
writes,
LlTERARITY 1 97
oec1ude: the between and 2; 201
DespiteAristotle's own dec1arations to the eontrary, the Aristotelian animal "is
split up from the very beginning" le: 2; cf. 2003a).9
This notion of the primary split, an originary tear, shakes the Aristotelian
foundations to their very depths. The political animal that grounds the Aristo-
telian model of politics, and that determines the implicit Aristotelian theory of
language, is always already riven, according to Rancière. Aristotle wishes to
make the logos, speech, the determining marker for politics, but as Rancière
says eloquently, "The speech that causes poli tics to exist is the same that
gauges the very gap between speech and the account of if' (1999: 26). Politics
ought properly, for Aristotle, to be about the difference between speech and
the making of mere sounds, but only the logos can distinguish between a po-
litical calI and a cry of pain. Thus, as Rancière famously puts it, "The initial
logos is tainted with a primai)' contradiction" (Rancière 1999: 16).
bjectivation
MilToring the broader shift in Foucault's thinking, and the supposed turn from
disciplinary power and institutions to the "care of the self' and the concept of
critique, Foucault transposes the terrns by which he describes the process of
subject formation. As Milchman and Rosenberg indicate, this shift has not
been clearly marked, and its implications not widely discussed in the English
language literature on Foucault. More importantly for my purposes here, in the
absence of specific attention to the clear change of terms - which Milchman
and Rosenberg delineate in their work - a great deal of confusion has perco-
lated. First, and early on, there was little or no consistency or cogency to the
translation of assujettissement. Many translators chose words like subjection,
which emphasized only one side of the dual process that Foucault sought to
describe. Even a close reader of Foucault like Butler, who proved extremely
attentive to the detailed and complex meanings of assujettissement, may have
helped to confuse matters wh en she chose in her discussions of Foucault to
translate Foucault's early terrn, assujettissement, with the direct English cognate
LlTERARITY 1 99
later French 10 This means that Butler's translation
has immediately and decidedly elided the entire distinction that Foucault
draws between assujettissement and subjectivation. And the problem is
exacerbated when English-language literature on the later Foucault writings
fail to make any mention at aIl of his use of subjectivation, or its differences
from assujettissement, and when a variety of terms appear in English - subjec-
tion, subjugation, subjectivation, subjectivization - without a clear sense of
their usage and meaning. For their part, Milchman and Rosenberg favor Niko-
las Rose's translation of assujettissement as "subjectification" as the simplest
term that does not close down Foucault's multiple meanings (Milchman and
Rosenberg 2007: 55). And l concur: to my eye it makes most sense in future
work on Foucault to use "subjectification" for his assujettissement, while using
the same English word, "subjectivation," for the French term subjectivation. 11
What has this to do with Rancière? First of aIl, even if there were no confu-
sions whatsoever, either in Foucault's terminology and translations or in Ran-
cière's own, Foucault's work would still provide a significant context for
understanding what Rancière is up to. At the very least, Rancière seeks to pro-
vide a nontraditional account of the political subject. He decidedly rejects both
the liberal model in which the autonomous subject precedes and serves as the
ground for political action, and the Marxist model (especially in a certain or-
thodox fiavor) of a subject that is fixed in place by a particular economiclsocial
structure. Thus, even if Rancière himself does not mention Foucault, it would
still make a great deal of sense to consider Rancière's arguments in light of
Foucault's, since both thinkers are trying to pro duce a complex account of
subject formation.
Moreover, Rancière's centralline of argument concerning political subject
formation travels on an axis that cuts through Foucault's writings. And Ran-
cière's arguments about the process of producing/becoming political subjects
has been confused in relation to Foucault's work. Let me unpack this last
claim. First, Rancière's most important, sustained, and detailed account of
this process cornes in Disagreement. There, Rancière uses Foucault's later
term, the French subjectivation (Rancière 1995a: 59). Rowever, for Disagree-
ment Rose has translated subjectivation as "subjectification." Renee, in
French, Rancière uses the same term, subjectivation, as Foucault chose in his
later writings, a term that Foucault specifically distinguished from assujet-
tissement; what appears in Rancière's text in English, however, "subjectifica-
tion," is the optimal translation of that earlier term, assujettissement. Thus,
reading the text in English, it is possible to conclude that Rancière is using the
same word in French as Foucault does in his early writings. That is, one might
naturally read "subjectification" as a translation of assujettissement, since
that is what the term renders in the English translation of Foucault's texts. But
this would be a clear mistake: Rancière himself does not use the term assujet-
tissement at aIl. 12
LlTERARITY 1
And want to show here that a fuller of can pro-
vide a different angle into Rancière's conception of politics. The two concep-
tions mutually infOllli one another and remain inextricable: subjectivation
makes sense as a political process, and poli tics only takes shape in and
"modes of subjectivation" (Rancière 1999: 32). As have discussed in sorne
detail in the preceding two chapters, we know that Rancière takes the everyday
actions of poli tics and reinterprets them through the logic of the police. This
fundamental point in Rancière's argument will aways raise the same question:
if democracy is not a regime, if poli tics is not a set of procedures, and if poli-
tics has no proper sphere, no specific location, then how do we grasp the logic
of politics? We know that a police order is a particular type of social order, a
particular type of partition/distribution of the sensible. This point will always
lead readers of Rancière to ask: When does a police order shift of its own
accord (because of sorne set of negotiations and compromises from within)
and when is it fundamentally disrupted or altered by politics? ln the following
passage Rancière offers a response to both these questions, a response that,
while not using the word subjectivation, helps to illuminate what he means by
that term:
The stmggle between rieh and poor is not social reality, which politics then
has to deal with. It is the actual institution of politics itself. There is politics
when there is a part of those who have no part [le compte des incomptés thus,
there is politics when there is the count of the unaccounted-for], a part or party
of the pOOl'. Polities does not happen just because the poor oppose the rich. It
is the other way around: polities (that is, the interruption of the simple effects
of domination by the rich) causes the poor to exist as an entity.... Politics
exists when the natural order of domination is intermpted by the institution of
a part of those who have no part. (1999: II)
lt is the very coming into existence of the poor - those who ought not exist in
the standard order of the police, those who ought not count in the bureaucratic
logic - and their emergence on the stage where they previously had no role,
that produces politics. But the coming into being of the poor, of any party that
was not a party to poli tics beforehand - this is what Rancière calls political
subjectivation. "Political subjectivation" is therefore not a type of subjectiva-
tion, since subjectivation only occurs as a process of politics - through a poli ti-
cal moment that recreates or rearranges le partage du sensible. Subjectivation
occurs only through a disruption of the police order; you cannot have subjec-
tivation without this political conftict with the police.
If political subjectivation brings into existence/appearance those who
should not count, then, fundamentally, poli tics is a miscount: a counting of
those who do not count. Poli tics in this peculiarly Rancièrean sense attests to
the limits of counting models: it shows that the math of interest-group plural-
ism withinliberal regimes can never truly add up. Liberal regimes work under
equation is predicated upon certain exclusions, but ones that can never be
named ones that are never visible as exclusions. Poli tics as subjectivation
might best be understood as a process of naming that which cannot be named
because it cannot be seen or heard. "Politics exists because those who have no
right to be counted as speaking beings make themselves of some account"
(Rancière 1999: 27)·
As 1 stressed in the Introduction, as a certain type of counting system, (as
a certain partage du sensible), liberalism is unprepared for the surprise that
is the emergence of a new political subject. In other words, the liberal count-
ing system can never predict this novel political activity in advance; it can
only count that which should be properly counted within the order of the
police. When the "poor," Rancière' s name for the "other" to the liberal police
order, "make themselves of some account," they expose the very mechanism
of that order as deficient, if not delinquent. And as 1 also hinted at in the In-
troduction, one must take some care to be clear about what Rancière means
by "the poor."
The word paar, as Rancière quite carefully uses it, cannot be presumed
in advance to name an extant socioeconomic class. When Rancière says
above that politics "causes the poor to exist," he distinguishes this political
understanding of the poor from that dominant conception of the poor as
produced within most police orders. According to the logic of the police,
the "poor" are already there to be counted; they are those who faB within a
certain box on the grid of income distributions, as measured by the census,
by polling, or by any other techniques of the police. In contrast, when Ran-
cière speaks of "the poor" in the long quote above, he points to a potential
mode of poli tic al subjectivation. The poor in this sense do not exist in the
order of classes priar to the interruption of politics. Thus, in one important
sense, "the poor" do not even exist at aIl. That is, within the police order,
there may be "poor people," but "the poor" is (one of) Rancière's name(s)
for the demas that only emerges when it makes its very claim to be counted.
Such a claim can only be made ta, and at the same time within, a system that
has never before counted them. "The poor" thus cannot be reduced merely
to "people without much money." The latter is a group within the bureau-
cratie, liberal order of the police, while the former is that which explodes
the logic of the police. Moreover, the former only comes into existence
upan such interrupting. The "poor" are only the poor alter they, the pOOf,
have declared they are the poor.
For this reason, Rancière will say that miscounts (i.e., politics) are "the
work of classes that are not classes" (Rancière 1999: 39). Again we see not
LlTERARITY 1 103
but the never
concems itself with subjects alone, but with subjectivation a process in which
subjectivity is produced through the transformation of an iden-
tity (Rancière 1999: 36). The police order already distributes lots in such a way
as to give each person his or her place in the order of things, a place tied to
identity. Political subjectivation is no t, then, the recognition or embrace of
identity, but the disruption of it; it is the production of a space between the
identity of the police order and a new political subjectivity a production that
is, above aIl, political. Subjectivation brings about subjects through the scene
in which poli tics interrupts the police order; the subject does not come before
politics, but rather cornes about through politics - a "coming about" that
cannot occur outside of language.
We are animaIs within language before we lay c1aim to the very power of
speech that would grant us the status of political animaIs. Language precedes
subjects, even if speech marks them as distinct, and this means that language
lays c1aim to us as weIl. Subjectivation names the process whereby those who
are of no account make a c1aim to be counted, thereby disrupting the math of
the police. As Rancière puts it, "The difference that political disorder in scribes
in the police order can thus, at first glance, be expressed as the difference be-
tween subjectivation and identification" (Rancière 1999: 37). In other words,
subjectivation is disidentification; it is the refusaI to not be counted (cf. Ran-
cière 1995c). The disruption of the equation between subjectivation and iden-
tity is the very pro cess that pro duces the fundamental mis cou nt that is politics.
By refusing the given identity of the police order, political subjects lay c1aim
to the fundamental equality that means they too - those who do not count -
must be counted. Subjectivation produces the addition of those who do not
count into the equation, which throws the equation out of balance - leading to
the miscount that is politics for Rancière.
Political subjectivation creates the fundamental wrong of politics, but this
is not to say that pre-given subjects then go on to take up politics. Subjectiva-
tion still rests upon the c1aim to the logos that is the starting point for Aristotle,
but for Rancière, "Parties do not exist prior to the dec1aration of wrong" (Ran-
cière 1999: 39). 1 wish to emphasize the crucial imp0l1ance of the language
used in this c1aim: it indicates that a wrong will be "dec1ared" but without a
ready-made subject to do the dec1aring. That is to say, the dec1aration cannot
be the dec1aration of one of those parties; the dec1aration must precede them.
But this means that language must come "before" the subject, that the subject
cannot preexist the language that "he" speaks. And if the dec1aration preexists
the parties who wouid dec1are it, then we see the impossibility of dismissing
an investigation of those dec1arations - of language, of phrases as a discus-
sion of mere words. In this case, to investigate language is always, potentially,
to analyze modes of subjectivation. It is to ask after that very formation of
parties to the disagreement.
LlTERARITY 1 105
while point to a related and sometimes set of
anthropocentrism and humanism must not be conflated. Unlike anthropocen-
trism, humanism can function as a of ideology - or as a LH""'<-<f-"U
tlewegg!:;r 1977). In making the human being the measure of all value, hu-
manism does much more th an center its account on the human animal; it
judges and evaluates based on the human being. Across the many fomls it
takes, humanism insists on the importance if not uniqueness of "man" (or of
man and woman). Anthropocentrism, in contrast, need not give such norrna-
tive weight to the human being; it need only center its account on the human
animal, but without necessarily weighing values, choices, and options in terms
of "man." Of course, anthropocentric theories will often have a "humanist
bias," a sort of in-built weighting toward humanism, since to see the world
through the position of the human subject is certainly to run the risk of privi-
leging not only that perspective but also that subject itself.
Second, anthropocentrism must not be confused with anthropomorphism;
despite the very similar names, at certain times these two ideas prove to be
utterly at odds with one another, and at other times they produce productive
tensions. Anthropomorphism is a mu ch more widely known and commonly
used term; it names the process by which we project human attributes, human
forms, or human characteristics onto any nonhuman entities - whether they be
inanimate objects, animaIs, or spirits. Just as sorne forms of humanism find
grounding in a broader anthropocentrism, so sorne types of anthropomorphism
are based in an anthropocentric framework. That is, to project hum an charac-
teristics onto nonhuman entities, one often works from a human-centered per-
spective. What we might caU "anthropocentric anthropomorphism" means that
in speaking, acting, thinking, and viewing the world from and as a human
being, 1 see in nonhuman beings my very own characteristics.
However, as Jane Bennett has recently shown, the relationship between an-
thropomorphism and anthropocentrism can work qui te di fferently. Bennett
operates within a very different context than the one 1 am working in here. She
tums her attention to the vibrancy of matter, the vitality of things, and tries to
discem (and caU to the attention of other political theorists) the poweIful and
impOliant agentic forces of matter - of things as diverse as worms, trash, and
electrical grids (Bennett 2009). Like me, Bennett is struggling against anthro-
pocentrism. She worries that the repeated reassertion of anthropocentrism pre-
vents us from seeing nonhuman agency. By centering our political accounts on
the human animal, we frequently make the mistake of thinldng that only the
human animal can act, that no other creature has agency. It is here that our
very distinct projects cross or overlap: even though Bennett does not do so,
one can trace this mistake back to Aristotle. Aristotle's anthropocentrism
means that he not only sees the human animal as the only political animal, but
also attributes to that creature the possession of logos that, almost magically,
gives the human animal this unique power. Within this context, Bennett reveals
LlTERARITY 1 lOi'
U Rancière brings to bear a direct - even if in his own
!cHVIUV,
hands, tacit - challenge to anthropocentrism. The very dissensus that poli tics
the fact that politics exists, but only exists in impure form - this
Hll·.lV'-'U,,",VLl,
in
For these reasons, my focus lies not (with Althusser, and sometimes Rancière)
on humanism or anthropologism, and it lies not (with Bennett) on anthropo-
morphism. 1 am concemed instead with any conception or model of politics
and language that places the presumed human animal at the center, and pulls
political action or linguistic "usage" toward that center (see also Dillon 2003b).
To clarify the stakes of these differences for my broader reading of Rancière
(and my larger arguments), in this section 1 offer a brief reading of a text that
1 see as an exemplary effort to resist the gravitation al pull of anthropocentrism:
Lyotard's The Differend. 1 contend that Lyotard's self-consciously anti-anthro-
pocentric account helps to highlight a number of aspects of language that
remain implicit in Rancière's theory of politics. 1 make this tum to Lyotard
somewhat polemically, given that Rancière has himself been so highly critical
of Lyotard's work. 15 In a sense then, 1 begin with Lyotard in disagreement with
Rancière. However, in doing so, first, 1 actually follow Rancière's "method,"
about which he writes, "Disagreement is not only an object of my theorization.
It is also its method. Addressing an author or a concept first means to me set-
ting the stage for a disagreement, testing an operator of difference" (Rancière
20l lC: 2). And second, 1 do not intend here to bridge the wide gap that Ran-
cière himself has constituted between himself and Lyotard, as 1 neither focus
on nor contest Rancière's central criticisms of Lyotard - none of which have
much if anything to do with language. 16 My goal in this section, then, is cer-
tainly not to offer a refutation of Rancière or to privilege Lyotard; instead, 1
intend to "test an operator of difference," exploring Lyotard's theory of lan-
guage while respecting Rancière's refusaI to produce such a theory.
In the preface of Disagreement, in his first effort to define the term, Ran-
cière writes, "Disagreement is clearly not to do with words alone. It generally
bears on the very situation in which speaking parties find themselves. In this,
disagreement differs from what Lyotard has conceptualized as differend"
(Ranci ère 1999: xi). In the rather unorthodox style of The Differend - Lyotard
himself refers to it as his "naïve ideal ... to attain a zero degree style" the
book opens not with a preface, but with a "reading dossier" (Lyotard 1988:
xiv). If one looks up "thesis" there, one finds a description that would appear
to mesh with Rancière's brief characterization of the book. Lyotard writes,
"There are a number of phrase regimens [the set of mIes by which phrases are
constituted]: reasoning, knowing, describing [etc.]. Phrases from heterogeneous
Even though Lyotard insists that the pure translation of the logician - in which
the sense of a within one is transferred to the sense
of a new phrase within a different regimen - proves impossible, this
does not mean that links between phrase regimens cannot, and are not, made.
ln fact, almost none of text focuses on the notion that language
games are heterogeneous that was the thesis of Lyotard' s early cen-
tered as it was on deconstructing the grand meta-narratives of modernity
tard 1984; cf. Lyotard and Thébaud 1985). ln this text, on the contrary,
wishes to insist on both the constancy and the profundity of linking. In the
above quote, then, he goes on to say that phrase regimens "can be linked one
onto the other" (Lyotard 1988: xi, emphasis added, cf. 48-50).
Linking happens. Connections between and among language games are
made aIl the time, despite the fact that no rule of translation can properly and
legitimately govern such linking. Lyotard puts it this way: "To link is neces-
sary; how to link is contingent" (Lyotard 1988: 29). The Differend is not merely
an expansion of the notion that language games are incommensurable; it offers
an analysis of the implications of linking. And it would prove difficult to over-
state the fact that, for Lyotard, the issue of linking cannot be reduced to ques-
tions solely of language (of "words alone"), because linking must always be
thought as a matter of polities. On my interpretation, the important section of
the "reading dossier" is not the "thesis" but the "stakes."18 The stakes of the
investigation of phrase regimens and the genres of discourse that link them are
"to convince the reader ... that thought, cognition, ethics, politics, history, or
being, depending on the case, are in play when one phrase is linked onto an-
other" (Lyotard 1988: xii-xiii, emphasis added). My emphasis on politics
might seem skewed, given Lyotard's long list of items on which linking bears.
But it is Lyotard's emphasis as weIl: "The linking of one phrase onto another
is problematic and ... this problem is the problem of politics" (Lyotard 1988:
xiii). From the fact that pure translation between language games is impossi-
ble, Lyotard draws not the nihilistic conclusion that poli tics disappears or be-
cornes meaningless. Rather, he insists that since linking does and will always
occur in a field in which no link is guaranteed no translation can be under-
written by a meta-rule that would assure its arrivaI at the proper destination -
politics must grapple with the problem of linking.
These "problems of translation," these "miscommunications," entail that
meaning remains unfixed. Therefore the problem of linking bec ornes the pos-
sibility of political speech for those who have no part in the language of poli-
tics. And here Lyotard's arguments circle back around to intersect with
Rancière's polemical reading of Aristotle. The problem oflinking crosses with
the question of disagreement. Poli tics must always, thereby, concern itself
with the problem of language. And by this 1 do not mean "problem" in the
sense of limitations -- as if political problems could be solved merely by more
LITERARITY 1 109
information or dearer Hnes of communication. Rancière and agree in
their refutation of that daim. Instead, politics must be thought, as Foucault
suggests, through the language of problematization (I972; cf. 1997).
And the problem of politics is always a problem of language.
Lyotard makes this case in a powerful mannel' when he draws his own con-
nections (through language) between linking and politics. In the reading dos-
sier, Lyotard says that the "stakes" of his own text are,
[t]o refute the prejudice anchored in the reader by centuries of humanism and
of "human sciences" that there is "man," that there is "language," that the
former makes use of the latter for his own ends, and that if he does not succeed
in attaining these ends, it is for want of good control over language "by means"
of a "better language." (xiii)
LlTERARITY 1 111
taken as a genre of discourse that would either be distinct from others, or at-
tempt to rule over them. He shares Rancière's disdain for the reduction of poli-
tics to consensus, what Rancière calls post-democracy (Rancière 1999, chap.
5). Politics bears witness to the differend (Lyotard 1988: 141), where the dif-
ferend "is the unstable state and instant of language wherein something which
must be able to be put into phrases cannot yet be" (Lyotard 1988: 13).
But if we have rejected an anthropocentric view of language, that "some-
thing" that must be put into phrases can itself be a subject. This very possibil-
ity entails that to inquire into the differend of language is to ask after the
potential emergence of the speaking being as such, since the "speaking being"
cannot precede the language in which he or she speaks. This is why the dif-
ferend is not, as Rancière would have it, about "words alone." lt proves impos-
sible to produce, even on Rancière's own telIDs, an argument about only words,
for if the subjects of a dispute can never precede that dispute, then an argument
about words is always already an argument about subjectivation, an argument
about politics.
Literarity
1 entirely agree that there is no subject before language or that wou Id merely
use language in an expressive way. 1 clearly stated [in prior works] that a po-
litical subject is in fact a process of [subjectivation], that the "name of the
subject" is only an element of this process and that the "we" who utters a name
and the "we" that it names do not make one identity. So the issue at stake is not
[subjectivation] versus subject. It does not lie in the conception of linguistic
practice. It lies in the conception of the act of interlocution and of its condi-
tions. It lies in the conception of dissensus in which a theory of language is
embedded. (2003c: 8)
Understanding must be understood in its true sense: not the derisive power to
unveil things, but the power of translation that makes one speaker confrant
another.... Despite what the Phaedrus teaches us, there are not two kinds of
discourses, one of which cou Id be deprived of the power to "help itself" and be
condemned to stupidly repeat the same thing. AlI words, written or spoken, are
a translation that only takes on meaning in the counter-translation. (63-64)
LITERARITY 1 113
Rancière Plato and also that
speech and writing "are not two kinds of discourses," and thus the former can
certainly never be elevated above the latter. 21 AIl language is translation. Com-
munication, moreover, cannot be reduced to the transmission of meaning be-
tween given subjects, since, for Rancière, meaning arises out of the process of
translation and "counter-translation" (cf. Derrida 1982). The very term coun-
ter-translation suggests to me the interminability of the process of translation
itself. Every translation must be translated again, such that meaning can never
be fixed once and for an. There is an excess of words.
Rancière continues the discussion with a quotation from Joseph Jacotot,
which Rancière uses as indirect commentary on the famous Platonic dialogue
(though there's no evidence that Jacotot meant it that way). Jacotot daims,
"Man is condemned to have feelings and to be silent, or, if he wishes to speak,
to speak indefinitely since he must always rectify by adding or taking away
from what he just said" (Ranci ère I991: 64). Here we see the problem of
rhetoric, the problem of the written mark (that it cannot cease to speak), con-
structed as our problem we cannot cease to speak, because our speech al ways
proves inadequate to, and incommensurable with, our meanings, our feelings.
How to describe this speaking indefinitely? How to name this talking too
much? Rancière's first name for the phenomenon appears obliquely, in that it
describes a slightIy different problem: not the problem of mute discourses that
cannot shut up, but the problem of actors in history, "of a living person who
speaks too much" - too much for the requirements of the historian (Rancière
1994 [1992]: 24)· "Excess of Words" is the titIe to the third chapter of Ran-
cière's The Names of History, a chapter that aIiiculates, again, the predicament
produced by people who speak too much, who cannot stop talking. And here
Rancière uses the term literariness, a concept related to but still distinct from
"li terarity" (Rancière 1994: 76).22
But the "excess of words" is no mere problem or predicament. "Excess of
words" not only describes the fundamental condition of the human animal, but
also constitutes the fundamentally political nature ofthat animal. Contra Aris-
totIe, it is not our "possession" of the logos that enables us to become political
animaIs; it is, instead, the very fact of "literariness" - the fact that we are
always bound up, first, within the circulation of words - that makes us always
and already political. In Disagreement Rancière writes, "The modern political
animal is first a literary animal, caught in the circuit of a literariness that undoes
the relationships between the order of words and the order of bodies that de-
termine the place of each" (Rancière 1999: 37; see Robson 2009). Literarity - a
word that Rancière almost, but not qui te, uses here - is at once ours and not
ours. Literarity makes disagreement possible; it serves as the condition of pos-
sibility for disidentification.
Clearly, then, literarity is a political telm for Rancière, and must be care-
fully distinguished from "literature" and "literariness" (Rancière 2004c; cf.
LlTERARITY 1 115
his most The of thus
parallels the politics of disagreement, in that Rancière's alternative to a tradi-
tionai of poli tics" takes shape through his use of and articulation of the
term. In response to an interview question posed to him directly on the ques-
tion of language, Rancière offers the following crucial elaboration:
Here we can see more sharply why Rancière remains so insistent that his work
has nothing to do with philosophy of language, why he remains so adamant
that his conception of politics neither requires nor implies a theory of lan-
guage. In the terms of literarity, Rancière has little interest in writing as such -
and just as little concern, in this sense, with Plato's condemnation of it. As 1
have shown from the beginning of this section, the question does not directly
address speech or writing per se. The political issue at stake centers on the
availability and accessibility of "writing" to everyone. The excess of words.
Even those who are not entitled to the logos, those whom Plato's "order of
discourse" seeks to relegate to nonspeaking status, even they have access to
"writing." Unlike the dialectic, which is only made available to those who
properly deserve it, "writing" cannot be controlled - it goes places it should
not go, including into the hands of those who should not, according to Plato
(according to the philosopher) wield iL Plato's "logic of the proper" seeks to
establish the order of the city through the order of discourse. But the very
excess of words literarity - always disrupts this ordering. 26
Thus, with a heightened sense of literarity, we can now turn to Rancière's
"conclusion," which turns out to be no conclusion at aH, but rather a return to
the beginning, a return in disagreement. "We can conclude, then, that humans
are political animaIs because they are literary animais: not only in the Aristo-
telian sense of using language in order to discuss questions of justice, but also
bec au se we are confounded by the excess of words in relation to things" (Ran-
cière and Panagia 2000: IlS, emphasis added). Aristotle claims that we are
political animaIs because we have possession of the logos and can use it for
political ends. Rancière does not deny that we do, in fact, use language in this
way - to communicate, to deliberate, to judge. Yet our fundamentally political
LlTERARITY 1
a battle over and excess words that
outside the realm of legibility? As literai)' animaIs, we find ourselves caught
up in the excess of and politics happens too, even before we
emerge as animaIs. We are political, Rancière suggests, because we
find ourselves within literarity. Here 1 contend that Rancière's incisive and
powerful depiction of "polemical scenes" (Rancière 199 1: 4 1) as those spaces
that force the emergence of the contradiction between the logic of the police
and the logic of politics, need not and should not describe only cases in whieh
the parties to the dispute are already apparently present. Sometimes the battle
of democratic politics occurs before the appearance of the subject on that
scene. In such cases, the polemical scenes are themselves constituted and
brought to bear at a different level: namely, at the very level of discourse -
within the excess of words that would precede the emergence (or foreclo-
sure) of the subject.
Thus, 1 conclude my argument about the central importance of literarity to
democratic poli tics by giving an account, a rich description, of one such po-
lemical scene. In this example we see again, as we did in Chapter One, the
importance of immigrants as political actors, as 1 draw the background for this
example from Paul Apostolidis's recent research on immigrant workers, par-
ticularly his work at an Ameriean meatpacking plantY Located in the eastem
p0l1ion of the state of Washington, the plant is owned by a giant corporate
entity, Tysoniiowa Beef Processors, and staffed aimost exclusively by Mexi-
can immigrants (sorne illegal, most now legal), whose lives, work, and struggle
within the union Apostolidis studies in sorne (and sometimes gruesome) detail.
1 want to appropriate certain dimensions of Apostolidis's work in order to map
out a Rancièrean polemical scene. 1 do this by reading the intersection of two
distinct narratives that his work draws to light: first, the narrative of immigra-
tion, and second, the narrative of work and activism. Read through Rancièrean
lenses, Apostolidis's interviews and interactions with these workers makes
palpable the extent to which - as "immigrants" - these Mexicans and Mexican
Americans are of no account. Yet, at times, as "workers" and certainly as "ac-
tivists," they make their democratie claim to be counted. My interpretation
describes, then, the potential emergence of the immigrant-worker-activist as a
democratic subject. My reading of the case tries to highlight the literarity pro-
duced by the excess of words that marks these workers.
Narratives of "the immigrant" have, of course, been central to the building
and consolidation of power within the American nation-state. Those nan'atives
have combined a powerful immigrant xenophilia - for the immigrant whose
ethics of hard work and Old World values fuel the belief in class mobility and
build strong communities - with a toxie xenophobia against the immigrant-as-
other who is a parasite on the system and a roadblock to progressive social
change (Honig 2001: 4-18; cf. Apostolidis 2005: 25; cf. Beltrân 2009: 597).
On my reading, Apostolidis's work raises the following central question: how
L1TERARITY 1 119
exists somewhere between and The
thus be a place - but also a time, because the in-between subject is a middle-
voiced subject - between that space from which articulation would be
bIe, the subject position, and the one who offers that articulation, the individual.
Arp0.","'r if subjectivation involves a refusaI of identity, agency must lie in the
*****
That political moment, that moment when those who are not speaking beings
somehow speak - this moment is only made possible by the prior production
LlTERARITY 1 121
movement away from his own polemical interventions and (as 1 have do ne in
my closing example here) a shift toward concerns that Rancière himself may
not share. Thus, in the next chapter continue the process of broadening out
(and pushing beyond) Rancière's fundamental terms, as turn to a concept - or
perhaps better, a theme - that, like 1iterari ty, has hovered at the margins of
Rancière's work: critique.
CRITIQUE 1 12 5
ta the critical at a more while also the mech-
anisms and logics that animate and mobilize any specifie critîcal dispositif.
am particularly concerned with those critical dispositifs that possess a formaI
structure governed by the specifie logic of inversion.
This brings me to a second context, one marked by the sense that the time
for critical theory has passed, that attaining an "unmystified view" of things
does not lead to any necessary consequences (Sedgwick 2003) or, more gener-
aIl y, that "critique has run out of ste am" (Latour 2004). ln contemporary po-
litical theory today, sorne of the very best writings in the field stake out their
own position by taking their distance from a critical tradition,3 and they do so
precisely by characterizing the critical dispositif as marked by a relation or
structure of inversion. ln her recent attempt to turn theorists' attention to the
vibrance and agency of the nonhuman forces in the world around us, Jane Ben-
nett has argued against the project of demystification that we so often take to
be central to the work of critical theory (Bennett 2009: xiv). Her discussion
serves as a useful jumping off point for me, since she both names and pre-
sumes the understanding of critical theory, the very critical dispositif, that pre-
vails today in contemporary thought, but which is often left implicit. Everyone
knows weIl the form that this critical procedure takes: as a system of demysti-
fication, clitical theory works by way of the classic opposition between ap··
pem'ance and essence - that which appears on the surface is only a falsehood
masking the truth of the essential core. The task of the critical theorist is thus
to perform an operation of inversion, whereby the inner essence will be re-
vealed as truth, and the outer appearance will be unmasked as falsehood. This
sense of critical theOl'y can be found in prominent secondary sources (Hoy and
McCarthy 1994) and in central primary works such as Habermas's Philosophi-
cal Discourse of Modernity (1990: 1 I6).4 My efforts to rethink and perhaps
reinvigorate the idea of a "critical theory of X" - to move toward a new and
distinct critical dispositif operate first and foremost by resisting the critical
apparatus of demystification in terms (at least) as strong as others in the field
have done. ln addition, 1 seek to unbalance permanently the equation that
places critical theory on one side and the logic of inversion and the process of
demystification on the other. My goal, then, is to think a concept of critical
theory that does not rely on the appearance/essence dichotomy, that does not
function by way of inversion, and that does not seek to demystify.
This chapter broaches the following question: what would it mean to do
theory critically, to constitute a new critical dispositif, without relying on a
relation, law, or logic of inversion? My aim is not to offer a history of critical
theory, to trace the rise and faH of the Frankfurt School, or to try to account for
and categorize the numerous historical meanings of "critical theory." As my
discussion of Bennett immediately above indicates, 1 focus instead on the cur-
rent status and the contemporary senses of critical theOl)'. Despite their very
significant differences, these senses of critical theory share a commitment to
CRITIQUE 1 127
on the one hand, and a refutation of that tra(lltlOn, on the
other. Rancière ends this essay with sorne tantalizing hints concerning
the idea of a new critical thinking. Tantalizing though they are,
remain but hints. Here plant the seeds of an argument for a critical
theory beyond inversion, for a new critical dispositif.
Rancière's early text on Marx identifies a critical dispositif centered on and
structured by relations of inversion. His most widely read work on politics chal-
lenges that very dispositif, by way of a polemic that simultaneously draws from
and points beyond the same logic of inversion. And his recent writing on criti-
cal thinking calls for a radical reconceptualization of a new critical dispositif
that does without inversion entirely. Woven together, these three distinct and
varied polemical interventions of Rancière's allow me to raise the following
polemical question for today: what would it mean to "do" criticism or to ad-
vance a "cri tic al theory of X" without falling back on the logic of demystifica-
tion, the logic of inversion? Here 1 offer a series of interpretations of Rancière's
work designed to set the terms for a fuller answer to this question. 9
1 contend that Rancière's early essay in Reading Capital proves very much
responsive to the question of "critical theory" that 1 have posed above; how-
ever, it would be a serious hermeneutical mistake to take the essayas a general
philosophical account of critique. "The Concept of Critique" cannot be read
outside of a predetermined and thick context: namely, the framework for rein-
terpreting Marx already established by Althusser in the essays that make up
For Marx (1969 [I965]). The seminal' that produced Reading Capital was con-
vened on the principles of interpreting Marx that those earlier essays of Al-
thusser laid out. This is not a projection on my part: Althusser's introduction to
the text makes the importance of this framework c1ear. More importantly, Ran-
cière's own text marks this framework repeatedly, with consistent direct cita-
tions of For Marx and with repeated use of the Althusserian interpretive
structure. This means that "The Concept of Critique" approaches Marx's tex!
with a few already established givens:
I. Periodization. Althusser famously establishes a timeline that breaks
Marx's writings out into four distinct periods: Early Works, I840-44;
Works of the Break, I845; Transitional Works, I845-57; Mature Works,
I857-83. This periodization entails privileging the later writings, espe-
cially Capital, while categorizing the early writings as under the sway of
either Feuerbach or Hegel (or both). And it means that if an author com-
pares a so-called Early text with a so-called Mature text, as Rancière
does in this essay, then he or she is bound to find a radical difference.
This list suggests something of the set structure in which Rancière's essay on
critique operates. And this framework significantly constrains what Rancière
might say about his putative subject matter, "the concept of critique," since aIl
his claims will have to be formed within the language of Althusser's already
established and highly determined discourse. Rancière opens the essay by
laying out the importance of the concept of critique for Marx and choosing to
focus the investigation on two texts (the 1844 Manuscripts and Capital). He
then immediately specifies the general approach that he will take: "In this
study 1 shaH rely on already established theoretical knowledge constituted by
the work of Althusser" (Rancière 1989a: 75). And when he tums to the 1844
Manuscripts, Rancière invokes Althusser's specific thesis: "The critique which
is carried out in the Manuscripts represents the most systematic form of the
CRITIQUE 1 129
r",..,j-hl-,--.-n,-,Ir>n1r'" 01,-,h"""" carried out
on the basis of the Feuerbachian anthropology" (Rancière 1989a: 75). Thus,
Rancière takes it as given that the concept of in the Manuscripts
is an anthropological (a critical term that have tried to parse and
clarify in the previous chapter), and that the philosophical basis for that cri-
tique can be found in Feuerbach.
Given how mu ch Rancière chooses to assume, based upon established "theo-
retical knowledge," wh en it cornes to the title of his essay, his reading of the 1844
M anuscripts serves more to shore up the Althusserian discourse than it does to
investigate or analyze Marx's text. 12 Vnder the banner of the concept of critique,
Rancière offers a rather brief reading of the 1844 Manuscripts that proves
Althusser's point. Rancière shows that the criticalleverage exercised by Marx in
the manuscripts cornes from outside (outside history, outside the structures of
capitalism) and is smuggled or projected into the critical discourse. Marx thus has
an "ideological" concept of critique in the manuscripts, because that concept rests
upon Feuerbach's philosophy of man. Rather than offer a critique of political
economy on its own terms, Marx illegitimately applies to the discourse of politi-
cal economy a concept of man and alienation that cornes from elsewhere (i.e.,
from Feuerbach). Rancière writes, "So the scheme of religious alienation [the
Feuerbachian anthropology of man] has been projected on to the worker-product
relationship [a relationship theorized by political economy]" (Rancière 1989a:
84, emphasis added). We can say, then, that the concept of critique in the 1844
Manuscripts follows the logic that Althusser, elsewhere in the text of Reading
Capital, identifies as the "classical opposition" between appearance and essence
(Althusser and Balibar 2009 [1965]: I23).13 Critique would amount to revealing
the essence of human alienation hidden by the appearance of the freedom of con-
tract and work under the telillS of a capitalist system.
ln one sense, this is a completely standard conception of critique. However,
within the Althusserian framework that Rancière uses here, critique must be a
particular concept in Marx's writing. Rence in this essay Rancière tends to
ftatten and constrain the multiplicity contained by any particular critical dis-
positif. My own reading resists this tendency: thus 1 prefer to talk about the
critical dispositif that Rancière sees in Marx's writing, a dispositif that con-
tains many logics, but which is dominated by the logic of inversion. In a cer-
tain sense the very idea of a singular concept of critique seems untenable;
certainly Rancière will abandon this notion in future work. Nonetheless, given
his reading of Marx, we can safely say that the Marxist critical dispositif op er-
ates according to a traditional structure of demystification by invoking a logic
of inversion. According to this logic, the essence will be revealed by the criti··
cal mechanism. Rancière does not question the dominant structure of this critical
dispositif here in any way, since, working within the Althusserian framework,
he has already rejected this particular application of critique, though not nec-
essarily the dispositif itself, from the outset.
CRITIQU E 1 131
distinct 201 do wish to elide these but
rather to show that, despite them, both critical dispositifs operate according to
the same general logic, one that can be helpfully named a logic of inversion.
the term is not strictly mine; it is put into play in both cases Ran-
cière himself, where he frequently refers to the "law" or "relation" of inversion
(Rancière I989a: 128, I29).
In his reading of the early Marx text, Rancière uses the specific word in-
version to refer to Marx 's appropriation of the Feuerbachian concept of alien-
ation. "Inversion is produced through alienation: the generic life of man
becomes the means of his individual life" (Rancière I989a: 85). In other
words, the problem of inversion emerges because man lives an "inverted"
existence, and only a second inversion can set things right. In the case of the
"scientific" concept of critique, Rancière's language is quite explicit. He ex-
plains that the logic of inversion is itself the logic of capital, so that Marx, in
Capital, exposes this particular law of motion of capital. "The development
of the form of the process is thus governed by the law of inversion; the forms
in which the process of capitalist production presents itself or appears are
rigorously inverted with respect to its inner determination" (Rancière I989a:
129, emphasis added). In other words, capitalism itself inverts essence and
appearance; capitalism makes appear on the outside exactly the inverted form
of its true interior essence. Thus, a critical dispositif that would understand
the se laws of motion, analyze their mechanisms, and expose their effects -
this dispositif depends fundamentally on a logic of inversion. The critique of
capitalism inverts that which capitalism already inverts. The system hides its
own motor, and only a scientific understanding of that motor can grasp the
structure and its effects (Rancière I989a: 145, ISO). Marx's work is "scien-
tific" because it grasps the phenomenal forms in relation to their inner es-
sence (Rancière I989a: 171).
In unpacking these different strands of argument we can therefore conclude
that the second "concept of critique" in Marx's writings - the concept that
emerges only in his mature, post-transitional works - does not differ dramati-
cally from the early concept: both critical dispositifs place a logic of inversion
at their center. In both cases we have a false outward appearance that disguises
the truth of an inner essence. The first concept has two distinct levels, while the
second has only one, and thus the optical metaphors remain distinct. Nonethe-
less, the key difference lies not in the logic of inversion but in the location of
the true essence. In the early works, that essence lies outside of capitalism. In
fact, the essence is a projection that can only be found in an anthropology of
man "- one that will prove to be false, and one that has little to do with either
the capitalist social fonnation or its historical development. In both the early
and mature works we have an essence that we can counter to the mere surface
appearance. The difference is this: in the mature works, that essence is not 10-
cated outside the structure but is precisely internaI to it. The essence can be
CRITIQUE 1
might critique look like in Rancière's own hands? What critical
dispositif will he rely upon as he makes his own critical, polemical interven-
tions? It will be quite sorne time before Rancière explicitly addresses himself
again to the question of critical thinking, but 1 suggest here that we can effec-
tively reread Disagreement as tacitly mobilizing its own critical dispositif. The
core daims of Disagreement are weIl known, they have been thoroughly dis-
cussed in the literature on Rancière in contemporary political theory, and
have already engaged with them repeatedly and often at length in the preced-
ing chapters.!5 Here 1 have no need to rehearse earlier arguments about poli tics
and police. Rather 1 want to emphasize a different point about Rancière's most
widely read and commonly discussed book. As 1 noted in Chapter Two, many
readings of Disagreement never make it past the opening sixt Ypages where we
find Rancière's accounts of police, politics, and "wrong."16 Here 1 wou Id like
to add: this is for good reason. Armed with Rancière's account of police and
his radically new definition of politics, poli tic al theorists can do a lot of work
in terms of either rethinking the meaning of poli tics or mobilizing their own
critiques (Bowman and Stamp 2009). And there is nothing inherently inadmis-
sible about making these moves: as 1 read Rancière, his texts encourage cre-
ative appropriations such as these, because the last thing he intends is to
constmct a comprehensive theory that aIl his readers would be forced to either
refute or work within (Rancière 2009b: 114).17
Nonetheless, Disagreement goes on for three more chapters (after the open-
ing three that are so weIl known for laying out Rancière's novel account of
politics/police), and in those later chapters Rancière does sorne of his own
work with the concepts he has put into play. Moving beyond the conceptual-
ization done in the early pages, Disagreement offers those who continue with
it two powerful polemics: the first against the entire tradition of political phi-
losophy, and the second against the "consensus" politics of the 1980s and
1990s. 1 have already engaged with the second polemic in Chapters One and
Two. Here 1 am interested in pursuing the li ne of argument put into play in
Disagreement's first polemic, particularly since 1 am trying to account in this
chapter for polemic as a particular form of critique. Thus, 1 want to read this
polemic for the type of critical dispositif that it simultaneously relies on and
animates.
Rancière announces the terms of his polemical attack on political philoso-
phy in the opening pages of his fourth chapter of Disagreement. First, he gives
a creative initial definition of political philosophy as "the name of an encoun-
ter" between politics and police. Political philosophy, says Rancière, names
the scandaI of politics, and that scandaI is none other than politics' "lack of
any proper foundations" (Rancière 1999: 6 1). Although he does so quite
quickly and in a densely packed formulation, Rancière provides a radical,
CRITIQU E 1 135
as the of commu-
nit y and the good attached to its nature in place of the distortion of equality as
wrong, means first eliminating the difference between politics and police. The
basis of politics of the philosopher is the identity of the principle of politics as
an activity with that of the police as a way of detemlining the partition of the
perceptible [partage du sensible] that defines the lot of individuals and pmiies.
(Ranci ère 1999: 63)
Put bluntly, what Plato caBs "politics," Rancière caUs "policing." In order to
ground politics on a proper archë, Plato must eliminate the distinction between
politics and police; he must define his concept of poli tics in the very terms of
policing. Along the way, politics itself - as that an-archic principle that would
irrupt within and utterly transform the police order - has disappeared entirely.
Hence we can derive what we might caB the general formula for poli tic al phi-
losophy: the elimination of politics in favor of the (police) order of the
philosopher.
This reading allows Rancière to redescribe the entire project of political
philosophy as antipolitical in the most total and fundamental sense: political
philosophy is the name given for a philosophical project that tries to eliminate
the political moment of dissensus, of disruption and disorder, so as to establish
a stable (and sometimes timeless) social order. In the bulk of chapter four of
Disagreement, Rancière refines this general formula by showing the distinct
ways in which it manifests in canonical political philosophers. Each variety of
the formula has its own category and its own proper name: Plato = archipoli-
tics; Aristotle = parapolitics; Marx = metapolitics. Archipolitics names the
process by which Plato establishes a social order of hierarchy as a total re-
placement for the disordering logic of equality of democracy (Rancière I999:
6S).20 Parapolitics names the process by which both Aristotle and Hobbes (in
their unique ways) try to create an order of philosophy that can contain within
it the very disorder of politics; theirs is still the elimination of poli tics in favor
of police, but they eliminate politics not by excluding it from the order of the
good (as Plato did) but by including it within the very heart of the social order
they construct - and thereby taming it (Rancière I999: 7 2 , 77).
This brings Rancière to his discussion of metapolitics, and it is here that his
account of political philosophy, as a peculiar project of eliminating politics,
intersects with a modern form of critical theory. In his description of metapoli-
tics Rancière caBs on and caUs up a critical dispositif. As Rancière narrates the
tradition of political thought, metapolitics (as the third and final archetype of
political philosophy) arises out of a problem produced by the modern (Hob-
besian) variant of parapolitics. With the emergence of the sovereign people
cornes the concomitant appearance of that other group that would oppose itself
to the sovereign people and deny their sovereignty. They have many names:
the masses, the population, the rabble (Rancière I999: 80). Metapolitics arises
CRITIQU E 1 137
to a of inversion, because it sees politics as and Meta-
poli tics works by claiming the given politics to be a masking of the truth of the
social that underlies it; the project of political philosophy then becomes one of
unmasking; metapolitical political philosophy obeys a logic of inversion. 21
CRITIQU E 1 '39
how could we encourage or about democratic mo-
ments of true political dissensus if we continue to think that poli tics is going
on when there is nothing but police actions occurring? Rancière's own
narrative therefore silently invokes an opposition between false appearances
and genuine truth, and it implicitly suggests its own of (re)inversion. After
aIl, as readers of Rancière we would leam to see the metapolitical critique
demystification) not as a project of political emancipation (its surface
-lYJl.UC>IU0l
CRITIQUE 1 14'
of how one might rethink critical it on and
working within a framework outside of the logic of inversion. He therefore
gestures toward a new critical dispositif that his own text does not produce.
Moreover, as 1 try to show in the next section, Rancière's recent, explicit return
to the concept of critical thinking does take up this task.
CRITIQU E 1 143
essay tirst drafted in 1973, Rancière raises the of a cIitical . . u"-'!-'ve'HU
that does not rest on the assumption of illusion, ignorance, or darkness. What
would it mean to think cIitically without the presumption or invocation of "a
darkened mirror to be made c1ean by a critical operation which makes it dec1are
aIl there is to say" (Rancière 1989b: 183).27
It is just this possibility that Rancière bIings to the fore and probes in his
2007 essay on cIitical thinking (and its misadventures). The problem that Ran . .
cière attributes in 1973 to a narrow, scientistic, and ultimately bad reading of
Capital, he will attribute in his 2007 essay to the entire tradition of "critical
thinking." This recent essay contains Rancière's fullest challenge to the logic
of inversion and it embodies his c1earest break from a model of critical theory
as demystification. Despite the thirty-five year gap between them, the two ar-
guments are linked: in both cases Rancière is questioning the logic of inver-
sion and suggesting the possibility that there could be a critical dispositif
without this logic. Moreover, in this recent essay Rancière works with the
language of inversion much more explicitly and much more directly, while he
sets his own thinking on a path very much distinct from that logic. Rancière
opens the essay by telling a familiar tale, similar to the one on demystification
that 1 narrated at the outset of this chapter. He suggests that we aIl already
know that in sorne ways critical theory is exhausted, over and done with. There
is no longer a viable space for the type of criticism that operates by way of, as
he puts it in language that echoes the essay from 1973, the "denunciation of a
bright appearance concealing a dark and solid reality" (Rancière 2007C: 1).
Given this, many commentators have naturally conc1uded that there can be no
future for cri tic al thinking because there is no longer any truth; Rancière, how-
ever, distances himself from such an assertion.
Rancière has little patience for the idea of critical theory being over and
done with. In this essay he contends that the very proclamation of eritieal
theory 's end - based on the assertion that there is no longer a truth that we
could oppose to falsity - depends on implicitly reinvoking and thereby rein-
forcing the very same eritieal dispositif In other words, and to use a language
that is not Rancière's: it is a performative contradiction to state that there is no
truth beneath the lies. But it is not a performative contradiction in the c1assical
epistemological sense of refuting the skeptic - not, that is, because the state-
ment makes a c1aim to truth in the name of disavowing truth. Rather, the per-
formative contradiction emerges because in rejecting the standard logic of
traditional critical dispositifs (i.e., the logic of inversion) one relies on exaetly
the same logie.
Thus, says Rancière, we must offer an accounting of this paraIlellogic if we
ever "hope to engage in a true 'critique of the critique,'" a tum of phrase that 1
am translating here into a call to rethink the meaning of cIitical theory and to
create a new critical dispositif (Rancière 2oo7C: 1). Rancière begins this ac-
cou nt through examples of art, reading them for the logic that they deploy and
At first sight we might draw the conclusion that the logic of the critical dis-
positif has been entirely self-cancelled: there is no hidden reality ta unveil, no
feeling of guilt ta arouse. But if it were sa, why keep a dispositif that has no
more relevance? This is why 1 assume that the dispositifitself still works. There
may be no hidden reality behind the curtain. But the logic of the critical mode!
can pelfectly do without it. It is enough that there be something that we cannat
see or don't want ta see. And the very absence of another reality can become
the thing that we are unable or unwilling ta see. (Ranci ère 2007c: 3, emphasis
added)28
CRITIQUE 1 '45
This argument be stated at a more I-J~"~~'~~ level: in ,·t.,>1,-~(,'L'n"," a critical dis-
positif based on inversion, that is, in announcing its demi se, we only sustain
that very same critical dispositif by reasserting its centrallogic of inversion.
With this analysis in place, Rancière can offer a powerful challenge to an
those works that would tell us we are beyond critical thinking, that we can do
without any critical dispositif (or, more to the point, that we are beyond the
need for a critical account of capitalism). Hence Rancière's brief but scathing
critique of Peter Sloterdijk's account of modernity (Rancière 2oo9a: 30--3 l,
citing Sloterdijk 2004).29 For Rancière, Sloterdijk's account "sounds as an
appeal to get free from the fOrills and contents of the critical tradition" but the
logic of the argument remains entirely trapped within that tradition (Ranci ère
2007C: 5). Rancière names this mechanism, "ideological inversion," and he
shows that Sloterdijk (and others who would attempt to casually slough off the
weight of the tradition of critical them'Y) has no choice but to remain trapped
within it. While Rancière himself do es not want to return us to an earlier logic
of ideological inversion, to a simpler model of demystification, he reserves his
harshest indictment for this post -critical critique. The earlier "critical proce-
dures were supposed to be means of arousing awareness and energies for a
process of emancipation," but these later procedures are utterly "disconnected
from that horizon of emancipation." As such, "they become tools against any
process or even any dream of emancipation" (Ranci ère 2007c: 5). The denied
yet recycled criticallogic is ultimately conservative.
Herein, l maintain, lies the true target of Rancière's polemical intervention.
It is not traditional critical thinking (or even its misadventures) that Rancière
is after, but rather those who would simply dismiss the entire tradition of cIiti-
cal thinking, almost out of hand, because of its putatively naive reliance on
sorne conception of truth. However, in a manner very consistent with his ear-
lier approaches to an understanding of cIitical dispositifs, Rancière shows that
the real problem lies in the logic of inversion itself. As he phrases it in re-
sponse to interview questions put to him in 2004, "Where one searches for the
hidden beneath the apparent, a position of mastery is established. l have bied
to conceive of a topography that does not presuppose the position of mastery"
(Rancière 2006d: 49). The language of topography illuminates a great deal
about Rancière's argument: it shows that the alternative to a position of mas-
tery depends upon a rejection of hidden depths that would be plumbed or in-
verted. Topographical maps have contours and elevation, but they do not have
hidden depths; the smface vaIies significantly, but nothing lies below the sur-
face (waiting to be found).
Moreover, in the hands of those who would set aside critical thinking, the
logic of inversion takes its most pernicious fOrill. It assumes the shape of what
Rancière caBs "nihilist wisdom," an approach that "pictures the law of domi-
nation as a force that permeates any will to do anything against if' (Rancière
2007C: 6). This is a logic of inversion operating outside the contours of any
CRITIQU E 1 147
of a of errlanlCH)atlon that is not the of the critical
r.r'"ril1r>r
truth (even if it is the truth of falseness). What else can we do? Rancière sug-
we might find an alternative in a (certain reading) ofhis own
he insists on "disentangling the of emancipation from some 1JA.'-'''UIJIJ\.hH--
tions that the cIitical tradition has uncIitically - borrowed from the
domination." ln contrast, "a true critique of the cIitical tradition might have to
change the very basis of the critical procedures [to reconstitute a critical dis-
positifbased on different logics]." But this would mean to somehow start from
a different assumption entirely. Rancière caUs this "a foolish f..l."'Cl'UU~IJL;'VH
indeed [-] that the disabled are able, that there is no hidden secret of the ma-
chine" (Rancière 2007c: 15, emphasis added).
ln this short essay, Rancière has nothing more to say - he leaves off here - and
Rancière has not taken up his own implicit charge (at least as 1 have read it) to
rethink critical theory, to offer genealogical analyses of the tradition of critical
thinking, or to provide a new outline for a distinct sort of critical dispositif -
one that would eschew or escape the logic of inversion. Nor has he do ne much
to explain what it might mean to assume the disabled are able - the incapable,
capable (Rancière 2oo9a: 47). Here 1 want to suggest that my selective reading
of Rancière in this chapter - both in choices of texts and in the interpretations
thereof - indicates the trajectory needed for such a project.
Rancière stresses that we must disaggregate questions of emancipation
from the tradition of critical thinking. Perhaps we should. However, 1 insist
that we cannot abandon the critical tradition. Building from Rancière's own
insights in this essay we see that it is futile and dangerous to attempt to dis-
pense with any and aIl critical dispositifs. The goal cannot be to do without a
critical dispositif; it must be to animate a critical dispositif that is not domi-
nated by the logic of inversion. Rancière's own work gives sustenance to my
argument, since sorne of the most significant claims that Rancière has ad-
vanced in support of a certain kind of emancipation (in the form of democratic
politics) have themselves rested squarely on the mobilization and effects of his
own incipient critical dispositif. Rancière has never explicitly identified with
critical theOl)'; instead, he has either avoided the tradition (in most of his work)
or distanced himself from it explicitly (in the 2007 essay). Yet my reading has
shown, first, that Rancière cannot do without a critical dispositif of sorts, and
second, as he himself says, any move to reject aIl critical dispositifs is doomed
to failure. Rancière's polemical writings invoke and depend upon their own
sense of a critical dispositif. And Rancière himself suggests that we must
somehow renew critical thinking rather than dismissing it. Furthermore, despite
CRITIQUE 1
the nature its pn~sentaltlOln at the end of a
VHJ'IJU'-'U.> think we can
build on Rancière's suggestion of grounding critical thinking on the assump-
tion that the disabled are able.
take this to mean that we would need to conceive of a ctitical project that did
away with the assumption that some are blind and need to be given sight (by the
always enlightening critical theorist), that some are incapable and therefore need
to be guided by masters. 32 Rancière thus gives us a politics of hope, but one quite
distinct from that which I resisted in Chapter One (a pure hope, a dream of per-
fect revolution). For Rancière, as the '68 slogan says directly, can
come only from the hopeless." The Rancièrean reading of the slogan would place
the emphasis on the paradoxical quality of the hopeless being the bearers of hope.
"The hopeless," on this reading, is not an epistemological category and it does
not name a privileged class, because hope is neither knowledge nor faith. 33 To say
that "hope can come only from the hopeless" is to make another foolish assump-
tien about the equality of intelligences. If hope comes not from the masters or
from those who know, but from the hopeless, we can no longer assume that some
possess a critical sight that others lack. Rancière repeatedly shows that emancipa-
tion and democratic politics are both possible only by way of the assumption of
equality. We proceed based on this assumption and we seek to verify it. What if
critical theOl)' did the same thing? What would it mean to build a critical dis-
positif that put into effect a logic of presuppositional equality - a critical dispositif
that sought as its goal a demonstration of that very presupposition? This logic
entails not just assuming that the disabled are able (as the conditions for a critical
theory), but verifying it as weIl (as the resuit of the critical operation).
Let me shift from these rhetorical questions about what such a critical dis-
positif rnight look like, to a concrete (if still very general) example. If we take
capitalism as a social fOlmation that caUs for critique, the task before us would
be to put into motion a critical theory of that social formation that did not ne-
cessitate blindness. This means to advance a critical theory of capitalism that
does not depend on invisible structures - structures intelligible only to the
critic and not to the agents of capitalism. And it means understanding the
agents of capitalism as capable agents 34 (thus doing away with false conscious-
ness). Working out from this simple sketch, a renewed critical theOl)' would
need to answer two central questions:
r) How can we be sure that there is no blindness? That is, what does it mean
to say that there are no invisible structures and no incapable agents?
2) What is the point or uptake of the new critical dispositif, if it is not inver-
sion? That is, what do we get from a critical theory if it is not simply a
revelation of truth?
CRITIQUE 1 151
well as the theorist? a different
education, Rancière can be seen to raise implicitly the question focus on
here: what would it me an to conceive of critical as a that does
not stultify? Rancière's return to these themes is in his recent work
(Rancière 2oo9a). Jacotot asked: What if the student can learn without the
teacher? What if the student can read the book without a translation? And it is
only by making this assumption that Jacotot was able to create a radical and
emancipatory pedagogy. In turn, we can crea te a distinct logic to animate a
new critical dispositif only by overturning the previous assumptions and start-
ing with new ones. The abled nature of the putatively disabled is not some-
thing to be proven with normative logic, nor demonstrated with empirical
evidence. It is an assumption to be made and then to be verified. It is an ap-
proach we take to the production of critical theory. Using Rancière's radical
pedagogy as a guide, we have a clear response to the first question, above.
The second question, concerning effects, proves more challenging and
more subtle. What does a critical theory have to show us, if it is not the truth
beneath the lies? What does a critical dispositif do, if not reveal? What would
be the modus operandi of critical theory if it were not inversion, and what
would be the function of a critical dispositif if it were not unmasking or de-
mystification? In responding to these queries, 1 want to start by emphasizing
that this second question about effects indicates distinctly the gap that sepa-
rates this new type of critical dispositif from any critical theory based on the
logic of inversion. After aIl, the rough equation of critical theory with demys-
tification, or a logic of inversion, has survived for so long and achieved a cer-
tain hegemony because it holds such an obvious and powerful payoff. The
uptake for critical theory as inversion is obvious. Critical theory as demystifi-
cation offers truth, enlightenment, clarity. It bursts the bonds of ideology and
undoes false consciousness. It frees, it liberates, and it provides the solid epis-
temological grounds for change, for revolution. If we give up aIl that - which
to sorne extent we must when we reject the logic of inversion on which aB of
that is based - what then are we left with? If not consciousness and revolution,
then what?
Traditionally, critical theory brings sight to the blind; it illuminates what is
dark; it is sighted. The alternative begins not with the sight of the theorist, but
with the absence of blindness. To unpack this sense of a critical theory without
blindness, and in an effort to clarify what a new critical dispositif (one not
premised on darkness) might do, let me propose a distinction between "the
hidden" and "the unintelligible." According to a critical logic of inversion,
there are hidden mechanisms within any system or social order. What is hidden
is exactly a deep truth that cannot be seen because of faise smface appear-
ances. Critical theory, according to this line of thinking, must find and locate
the hidden or the invisible; it brings the hidden to light and reveals the truth
CRITIQU E 1 '53
in this context, when he eXl)lamS what is
inadequate about the translation of mésentente as "disagreement": "an entente
is an understanding, and més-entente implies at once a disagreement and a
m.isunderstanding" (Panagia 2006: 89, emphasis added). And the mésentente
for Rancière is not a misunderstanding that can be "c1eared up" or overcome
through more communication (cf. Rancière 2005c). Mésentente names a con-
stitutive misunderstanding: "not the conflict of one who says white and an-
other who says black [but] the conftict between one who says white and another
who also says white but does not understand the same thing by it" (Rancière
1999: x). This famous passage from the preface to La mésentente serves as the
inspiration for Arditi and Valentine's concept of polemicization with which
1 began this chapter and therefore lies at the core of any Rancièrean thinking
of the critical dispositif (I999: 4; cf. Panagia 2006: 89).
The passage also helps to emphasize the extent to which "making sense"
and "understanding" are projects of the police order. ln his effort to rethink
critique through a reconstructive reading of Habermas, Nikolas Kompridis rel-
egates his own critical project to the terms of the police, when he argues that
"critical theory needs above aU to understand" (2006: 29) and that the new
project of critique must be to disc10se meaning (2006: 255, cf. 262). ln stark
contrast, the critical dispositif that 1 am describing rejects the idea of taking
understanding as a goal. The aim of such a critical dispositifhas to be a politics
beyond sense-making, since the police order can easily accommodate such a
goal; indeed, the logic of inversion works perfectly weIl within the terms of
the police order's partition of the sensible. Disagreement and dissensus there-
fore provide the third key element within the ensemble of a new critical
dispositif. 36
Let me further indicate something of the shape of the idea of this new criti-
cal dispositif by returning to Foucault. At the beginning of this chapter 1 sug-'
gested a need to part ways with a Foucauldian rethinking of critique (as a
practice of the self on the self) in order to refashion critical theory (as a project
that offers a critical account of a social formation). Here 1 return to Foucault in
an effort neither to join my project back up with his nor to offer criticism of his
work. Rather, 1 wish, briefty, to mark sorne of the overlaps and sorne of the
distances between the conception of critical theory that 1 am gesturing toward
here, on the one hand, and the well-known work of genealogy, the "history of
the present," and the historical "problematizations" for which Foucault and
Foucauldians are rightly famous, on the other. The type of critical dispositif
that 1 seek to animate here shares with Foucault an understanding of systems
and structures as open and porous. That is, earlier forms of critical theory often
developed a critical theory of a system or structure that relied on the notion of
that system being closed. In fact, the critical dispositif would often presume
that the structure itself could be taken as a total, sealed object. In contra st with
this sort of approach, my sense of a "critical theOl)' of X" requires a conception
CRITIQUE 1 155
in "Introduction." There he argues that the of clas-
sical poli tic al economy cannot stop with, or amount to, the idea of historiciz-
concepts; nor can it historicize capitalism
'-'V'~ULlH"" it to be a contingent social formation 1996). Marx
denies neither of these arguments, but they are not his primai)' claims. The
historically contingent nature of capitalism - and those concepts used to un-
derstand it matters much less than the force and effects of the system itself.
It is to the question of how a capitalist system works, and not that of where it
cornes from, that IvIarx applies himself most assiduously in Capital.
Thus, my account of a critical dispositif is committed te the possibility of
producing a "critical theory of X" that is not a singular refutation or rejection
of X and is at the same time not merely an effort to demonstrate the contin-
gency of for example, a critical theory of capitalism need not and
must not be the same as a critique of capitalism, premised upon the invisibility
of alienation as the true, essential core of capitalism (going on "behind the
backs" of workers).38 A critical theory of capitalism could still be produced out
of the assumption that there is no hidden truth of capitalism, but this means it
would be incumbent on such a theory to show how capitalism operates, how it
works, and what its effects are. And a demonstration of how capitalism func-
tions might also serve to denaturalize, render contingent, and call into question
sorne of the mechanisms of capitalism (perhaps even the system as a whole).
It would do so, however, not by presuming that there is a secret truth to be re-
vealed, but rather by indicating the way a complex system functions.
Perhaps, therefore, a renewed form of critical theory, based on foolish as-
sumptions, could offer insights and possible paths toward political action and
political change, while eschewing the dream of unshakeable epistemological
grounds and rejecting the goal of a guaranteed road to revolution. A cri tic al
dispositif that refuses to impose blindness, that refuses to operate by way of
inversion, might produce its own form of the very Socratic wisdom that Plato
(as the chief architect of a theory based on blindness) so long ago jettisoned:
the wisdom to know that we do not know, that there are no guaranteed out-
cornes or locations of pure epistemological surety. For Socrates, su ch wisdom
was a caU for action. A new critical dispositif could therefore reject the dream
of guaranteed revolution without thereby abdicating democratic politics.
T M1GHT SEEM TO go without saying, but 1 will say it anyway: The Lessons
of Rancière cannot close with an enumeration of, or a report on, those les-
sons. This book must end without a moral to the story. In the final two chap-
ters of the book 1 have started to push Rancière's conception of politics past
itself, to gesture in directions that frequently exceed Rancière's concems and
sometimes work against his intentions. In this way, 1 have already drawn out
the implications and significance of the work 1 do in the book as a whole.
However, trying to come to a specific set of conclusions at the end would only
serve to undercut the very reading of Rancière's writings that this book has
offered.
ln the last lines of the opening chapter of The Ignorant Schoolmaster, Ran-
cière suggests an important first conclusion from the ex ample of Jacotot. In a
formulation often overlooked, Rancière writes, "Whoever teaches without
emancipating stultifies. And whoever emancipates doesn't have to worry about
what the emancipated person learns. He will learn what he wants, nothing
maybe" (Rancière 1991: 18, emphasis added). Radical pedagogy does not
mean verifying what the student has leamed; it means verifying equality, and
nothing more. The conclusion to the lesson cannot attempt to shore up what
has been leamed without either reinforcing earlier stultification, or, worse, in-
troducing a stultifying element to a lesson that had been free of it. What mat-
ters is not endings; rather, "The circle of emancipation must be begun"
(Rancière 1991: 16). Here, then, 1 end this book on Rancière's "lessons" by
beginning a new argument about democratic politics. 1 bring the book to a
close with a set of my own redefinitions that produce their own attendant po-
lemical claims.
My primary polemical claim can be captured by the phrase, a "queer
poli tics of the democratic miscount." This phrase holds together two inter-
connected contend that the most salient and
powerful version of queer politics proves to be a Rancièrean democratic
politics. That Rancière's conception of democratic politics illuminates
what is distinct about queer poli tics vis-à-vis lesbian and gay identity poli-
tics. Second, perhaps more contentiously, claim that Rancière's miscount
proves to be a queer miscount. Over the past two decades queer theory has
advanced and developed a relational understanding of identity, a conception
of political subjectivity not rooted in any preexisting or essential features of
the self, but derived in practice from norms and politics. This positional and
post hoc sense of the queer subject brings into stark relief Rancière's under-
standing of subjectivation, particularly his sense that the subject is an "in-
between" and that the political agent is not simply an agent who enacts
politics, but an agent brought about by politics. It is in these senses, l will
suggest, that we might simultaneously describe democracy as both a poli-
tics of the miscount and a queer politics.
In advancing these polemical claims, l neither reject nor depart from the
arguments and readings of Rancière that make up this book. Quite the con-
trary: l maintain that Rancière's own claims and contentions often gesture
in the direction that l go here, and that these final arguments of mine remain
consistent with the interpretations l have offered from the beginning of the
book. Moreover, Rancière's writings, l insist, can be marshaled in the ser-
vice of ends other than his own, and to make this sort of hermeneutic claim
is not at aIl to violate the spirit of Rancière's writings, but exactly to work
within it. Nonetheless, there can be no doubt that Rancière himself does not
take up the work l do below. While l suggest powerful affinities between
queer theory and Rancière's thinking of democratic politics, Rancière has
explicitly rejected queer theory, and subtly resisted aligning his work with
that field (Davis 2010: 88-90; Davis 2009; Chambers and O'Rourke
200 9).
The potential tension between Rancière's arguments about queer theory
and my reading here should not be a shock, as this tension is but a part of the
larger torsional force l have been applying to Rancière's work. It makes sense
to maximize that force here in the Afterword. Being, literaIly, the word that
cornes after the word, the Afterword should be thought through Rancièrean
tenus as "une part des sans-part." The Afterword must be a part of the book,
yet somehow not a part of the book. The appearance of the Afterword is the
emergence, but never quite the inclusion, of the part that has no part. This
means, also, that any Afterword nms the risk of being one argument too many;
it is the location of the "one-too-many." In this sense, though, nothing could be
more "faithful" to Rancière's thought than the Afterword, since the "one too
many," Rancière says, "constitutes the dëmos as such" (Rancière 1995b: 94; cf.
Rancière 1999: 118). In adding one argument too many, the Afterword threat-
*****
We're here!
We 're queer/
Get used to it. 2
How can we read this slogan and chant, popularized first by Nation and
used widely throughout the 1990S during marches, protests, demonstrations,
and other events? How can we hear the words and what might they tell us
about both so-called queer theory and about democratic politics, today? It is
easy enough to dismiss the idea that this well··known slogan of queer activism
does any genuine poli tic al work. 3 To neutralize the chant we need only read it
through the given terms of today's interest group and identity politics. The
logic of liberalism tells us that rallies and marches need slogans and chants.
And Queer Nation came up with a catchy one: it is easy to remember, easy to
yell, and mixes just the right doses of political force and humor. Liberallogic
tells us there is no need to go much beyond this analysis - nothing else to see
here - since the Queer Nation chant resonates closely with the most popular pro·,
test chant of them all: the one that uses the formula, "What do we want? _ _ !
When do we want it? __ !" The first blank can be filled by aIl sorts of de-
mands: peace, equality, freedom, equal pay, shorter hours, health care, etc. The
second blank, almost invariably, is occupied by the word now, which serves to
intensify and add urgency to the demand. 4 One can complete the logic quite
easily: just as women and blacks demanded their rights, so gays and lesbians
demand theirs. This move situates the chant squarely within the terms of
rights-based (identity-based) liberalism.
But how might we read the chant so as to pull it away from liberalism and
toward democratic politics? In the case of this chant, what would it mean to
continue the effort of this book to prize apart liberalism and democratic poli-
tics? largue that this sort of Rancièrean move produces a reading of the chant
that dovetails with a specifically queer interpretation of the chant. Bath moves
push the Queer Nation chant away from the standard demonstration chant.
While the logic that links the Queer Nation chant to "What do we want?" has
a certain obvious coherence, it proceeds only on the basis of an almost com-
plete disregard for the content of the chant. If we look closely at the Queer
Nation chant, we must notice the stark difference between the two: most im-
portantly, we find no demand here. There is nothing that these queers "want"
and thus no timeline for their wanting it. There are no specific claims whatso-
ever being made in this chant. This is not, in short, a claim for inclusion (Jagose
1996: 112). While the chant does identify sorne hard-to··describe subject- "we're
Afterword 1 159
- Rancière's would alert to the way in which this
subject do es not seem to preexist the chanting itself. The "wrong" being de-
clared by the chant may be the very thing that brings the into exis-
tence. And while the chant does provide a geo-temporal location - "we're
here" - Rancière would alert us to the ambivalent or perhaps paradoxical
nature of this "here." "Here" denotes both the geographical and political space
(at this march, on these streets, in this polity) and also echoes the temporal
"now" of earlier prote st chants. However, it does not situate or locate the citi-
zen in a political district, nor project the subject into a state of nature. Finally,
the last line does not fit the script at aIl. Rather than, "'Ve're here; we're
queer; give us our rights," rather than "We're here; we're queer; we demand
equality," we find nothing at aIl claimed by this "queer" subject, and nothing
at aU demanded from the other. Get used to it.
However, this is surely not to say that the statement "Get used to it" does
nothing. Indeed, 1 will argue here that it does a great deal more than the claims
or demands of interest-group liberalism. Rather than making a claim of inclu-
sion, rather than requesting something of the dominant power structure, "Get
used to if' declares a powerful distance between those who occupy the domi-
nant position and those who chant the slogan, and it refuses an opportunity to
close that gap. It signaIs a resistance by those on the margins to move to the
center. "Get used to it" is also, notably, an imperative sentence; it tells others
what they have to do. And the changes within the norms that are announced by
the imperative must be brought about by those who occupy the center of the
norm. It asserts that those on the margins will continue to be who they are -
namely, queer - and argues that any alterations will have to come about by way
of broader changes to the norm. This is therefore a potentially subversive
claim, since it refuses to reify or even respect heteronormativity.
Here, then, 1 read the Queer Nation slogan as tapping into a number of the
most crucial elements of queer theory; simultaneously, 1 also read it as captur-
ing fundamental elements of Rancière's thinking of democratic politics. Let
me take each dimension of this double reading in turn, before 1 then combine
them. When the term queer first emerged in the early I990s, both its meaning
and its significance pivoted on the difference between queer, on the one hand,
and a fixed, given (gay) identity, on the other. 1 place gay in parentheses here
because one of the texts that played a crucial role in establishing "queer theory"
was Judith Butler's Gender Trouble, a work that did not address itself directly
to a lesbian and gay audience or subject, and that made no explicit effort to
reconsider lesbian and gay sexual identity.5 Moreover, Butler's work, like the
similarly influential books by Sedgwick and Halperin - all of which were pub-
lished in the same year, I990 - made no use of the term queer (Butler I999
[1990]; Sedgwick 1990; Halperin I990).
Butler wrote as a feminist, but she did so in order to challenge the hetero-
sexist assumptions buiIt into second-wave feminism's commitment to the
Afterword 1 161
can thus see a certain convergence in the of Rancière and
Butler, in that they both consistently thwart this liberal assumption and they
both attempt to think the remainder (that which can never be recuperated by
interest groups) of the liberal, identity-based approach (see I993). Here
the relevance of Butler's famous early work on sex/gender becomes clear in
relation to Rancière's understanding of politics. Butler shows most powerfully
in Gender Trouble that the category of "woman" cannot be presumed in ad-
vance. Therefore a feminist theory cannot stubbornly insist that poli tics only
cornes after the subject. If the category of woman - and even the "experience"
of woman only emerges within the terms of politics, feminism must centrally
concern itself with the production of that category (Scott I99I).
Queer theory, 1 would insist, sUl'ely cannot be reduced to a mere analogy to
feminism. Yet there can be no doubt that the third-wave feminist critique of
second-wave feminism parallels and illuminates the queer critique of lesbian
and gay identity politics. Whereas lesbian and gay both name identities based
upon sexual orientation, queer points to no such fixed position. Lesbian and
gay (and also, in their own way, transgender and bisexual) are identities; queer
is a relationality. That is, queer describes a particular, relative position in rela-
tion to norms of sexuality. There is therefore nothing fixed, nothing permanent
about queerness; it is always context-dependent (although heteronOlmativity
aimost always makes up a significant part of the context in contemporary
cases).
To draw out the substantive links between Rancière's account and the proj-
ect of queer the ory and politics requires engaging and activating the paradoxi-
cal qualities of Rancière's account of politics particularly in terms of two
claims that 1 have discussed at greater length in Chapter Three. First, there is
the assertion that "parties do not exist prior to a declaration of wrong" (Ran-
cière I999: 39). Second, there is the claim that the original Aristotelian logos
remains tainted (Rancière 1999: I6). Contra Aristotie (or at Ieast sorne read-
ings of him) the question of speech and voice cannot be determined by a pre-
politicai account. It can only be detelmined politically, through the act of
hearing, of recognition. This is a politics of (in)audibility - those that one
hears and those that one does not hear. It is a politics of (in)visibility - "those
that one sees and those that one does not see" (Rancière I999: 22). Logos
cannot be taken as that tool that makes politics possible, because only the
logos itself can provide a "hearing" for any political articulation. Rancière puts
it this way: "The speech that causes politics to exist is the same that gauges the
very gap between speech and the account of it" (Rancière I999: 26). Aristot-
le's logos is thus not a ground, but a paradox. And Rancière's politics, like a
queer politics, proves to be both paradoxical and groundiess.
Rancière's rereading raises the question of where the "account" will come
from. How do we read, hear, or see a creature as human or animal? If we cannot
make the political/nonpolitical distinction prior to politics, the difference will
Afterword 1
would declare it. The declaration cornes before exist. have this
is not mere double-speak. Rancière uses this paradoxieal language in order to
insist upon his deconstructive reading of Aristotle. We will know if the chant we
hear is the slogan of a political group, if we hear that chant as a political
articulation and not as mere babbling. And the slogan itself, that which declares
the wrong, will also constitute the party to the wrong. But the process cannot be
guaranteed in advance, and Rancière's polities leaves ample room for the pos-
sibility of failure. This means that sometimes, perhaps often, a slogan or chant
constitutes nothing more than mere noise (phëmë). Sometimes, however, a claim
is heard as a political claim (as logos), and it thereby serves to articulate a
wrong. When this occurs, at just this poli tic al moment, we have the miscount
that, for Rancière, defines democratic polities.
Rancière's understanding of democracy as a miscount helps to highlight the
specificity of queer theory, while queer theory's understanding of identity and
nonTIS shows why Rancièrean politics always proves to be, over and beyond his
own intentions, queer politics. Rancière's approach resonates most strongly
with queer theory on "the question of identity."l0 Rancière's radical and polemi-
cal rendering of the original Aristotelian political scene can be used to throw
into stark relief the distinction between a lesbian and gay identity politics, on
the one hand, and a queer politics, on the other. As l have argued previously, a
gay identity can be established through an expressive act the declaration of
coming out, literalIy saying, "1 am gay." But a queer identity can only be articu-
lated within the context of particular norms, particular sets of power relations -
that is, within a determinate political context (Chambers 2003). If, as Rancière
insists, the wrong is itself that which constitutes the party that would declare it -.
and if both the constitution of the party and the dedaration of the wrong come
about through the action of politics - then the polities involved here can never
be based on identity. 1dentity - and with it interests, demands, and daims - can
never precede the politieal dedaration of a wrong.
Identity is therefore relational for Rancière, just as it is in que el' theory, a
key point that Rancière renders lucid when he calls the subject an "in-between"
(Rancière 1995c: 67). l quoted this passage in Chapter Three, but its full sig-
nificance can be brought to light by the context of queer theory. To calI the
subject an "in-between" is to speak as if the subject is not a thing, but a space
between things. But this is exactly one of the senses of the statement "1 am
queer." To say l am queer is not to identify with a given identity, but to disiden-
tify. It is to give an account of my positionality with respect to norms. Just as
queer "identity" must always be grasped in relation to norms (and therefore as
an "identity" only in a unique sense), so Rancière thinks identity in relation to
the political moment. And this means that the subject as in-between must be
grasped not merely in the spatial sense but in its temporal dimension as weIl.
The in-between subject is much like the middle-voiced subject that l discussed
in Chapter Three: a subject that finds itself/is found at both spatial and temporal
Afterword 1
as
P'fir',,'Hl"V/,t-U,'? but rather an insistence that the normal
will persist. After aIl, what "we," as those who hear the chant, are supposed to
used to" is precisely the fact that "they" are queer - not that are like
us but that never will be. What " (those who used to are
announcing is our deviance from the normal, our distance from "them" (those
who hear the chant and who are thought to occupy a place closer to the median
point on the normal curve). If queer is that which resists normativity, 12 getting
used to it must mean not normalization but a persistence of queerness.
There is therefore something about the Queer Nation chant that do es not
add up. It introduces a new term into the equation, but without balancing out
the equation. In fact, the chant establishes a new variable in such a way as to
throw the equation out of balance. For Rancière, su ch "fuzzy math" is the
very stuff of democracy. Democracy, we might say, is the regime that cannot
count properly. This is what makes democracy a space or moment of impro-
priety, and it is also why democracy, in truth, is not a regime at aIl (Rancière
2006c: 69-73). Rancière describes the democratic subject (thus, the political
subject par excellence) as "le compte des incomptés" - the count of the unac-
counted-for. Democracy is a miscount because democratic poli tics only
comes about when those who have no part in the social order stake a claim
and take a part within it. "There is politics" argues Ranci ère, only "when
there is a part of those who have no part, a part or party of the poor" (Rancière
1999: II).
1 once glossed this argument by calling democratic politics "the taking-part
of those who have no part" (Chambers 2005: par. 1). This translation has the
benefit of expressing the point in its properly paradoxical foml (those who
have no part, take part), but it flirts with the danger of overstating the willed
participation of a party prior to politics. ln other words, that earlier construc-
tion comes perilously close to the liberal interest-group model of politics that
1 have been at pains throughout this Afterword and throughout this book - to
distinguish from Rancièrean politics. As Rancière stresses, the "party of the
poor" that has a part only when "there is politics" - this party does not initiate
political action but rather is brought about by political action. In other words it
is only politics "that causes the pOOl' to exist as an entity" (Rancière 1999: II,
emphasis added). And this paradoxical formulation can be elaborated (if never
quite "explained") wh en we see that unlike any other political system, democ-
racy involves a fonn of mIe in which there is no title to mIe. It is not aristoc-
racy, rule by the best; it is not oligarchy, rule by the rich; instead, democracy
is mIe by anyone at aIl. The title to rule in democracy is the lack of any title
whatsoever (Rancière 2006c: 41; cf. Rancière 1995b: 94). But this is why de-
mocracy always involves a miscount: It always amounts to "counting" those
who do not, who ought not count.
This cannot be a simple addition, an inclusion of those who were once
excluded. Democracy is not a second count, but a fundamental miscount, and
To be oppressed means that you already exist as a subject of sorne kind, you
are there as a visible and oppressed other for the master subject. ... To be op-
pressed you must first become intelligible. To find that you are fundamentally
unintelligible (indeed, that the laws of culture and language find you to be an
impossibility) is to find that you have not yet achieved access to the human, to
find yourself speaking only and always as if you were human, but with the
sense that you are not ... (Butler 2004: 30, emphasis added)
We can easily draw the connection that Butler leaves implicit here: to find
yom'self rendered unintelligible is sUl'ely to find yourself in a queer relation to
dominant nOffilS, To be unintelligible means to exist in a zone of inaudible,
invisible marginality, such that nonns of gender and sexuality make one illeg-
Afterword 1
ible. of con-
text of theorizing marginalized genders and sexualities, particularly
transgenderism. Yet her arguments here also fit weIl with the broader and more
abstract frame in which Rancière theorizes politics, and Butler has '-'"'+'<-<u,-"....,u
her theory to think about "rogue viewpoints" that are rendered unthinkable and
unspeakable by norms of legitimacy as weIl as by govemmental policy (Butler
2009: 795). In the rare moments when politics does occur, the conflictual con-
junction of the logic of equality with the logic of domination serves, on the one
hand, to render that order of domination visible and, on the other, to expose
(as intelligible) the very subject of politics that had previously remained
unintelligible. But, put in the language of queer theory, this means that politics
both exposes the norm and questions its dominance in the name of that which
it would make queer. As Rancière says, poli tics occurs through the democratic
miscount. We can add: poli tics occurs when the unintelligible make them-
selves/are made intelligible.
His insistence on the miscount makes Rancière's a very queer thinking of
politics (even if he would never put it that way). By refusing any conflation of
le compte des incomptés with the excluded, the marginalized, or the victim-
ized, Rancière consistently queers democracy. By saying that Rancière "queers
democracy" I point to two related phenomena. First, Rancière's fidelity to the
sense of dissensus and to the possibility of disagreement - thought as a situa-
tion of conflict not over the object of speech but "over what speaking means"
(Rancière 1999: xi) - is also a fidelity to a certain queerness, a commitment to
a marginality that cannot merely be included within the dominant frame of the
CUITent police order. Second, the distinction between the queer or the unintel-
ligible (thought as une part des sans-part), on the one hand, and the marginal-
ized or excluded, on the other, hinges on the difference between a liberal police
order and a possible democratic politics. The democratic miscount is a queer
form of counting and a queer form of politics.
*****
Rancière says that to teach without emancipating is to stultify - thus implying
that to teach without stultifying is to emancipate. And if the teacher creates the
conditions under which the student emancipates himself (no teacher ever ac-
tively emancipates a student), it is of no concem to the former what the latter
go es on to do (Ranci ère 1991: 18). Something similar must be said about both
"the lessons of Rancière" and The Lessons of Rancière. Rancière will not tell
his readers what to conclude nor what to do with his arguments, and neither
will 1. Rancière aptly chastises Plato for his belief that the circulation of words
can be controlled, that we can keep them out of the "wrong" hands or contain
their meaning. There is always an excess of words, and they are always
beyond our control. In this Afterword I attest, as really any afterword must, to
that "excess of words" that is literarity, and which makes democratic poli tics
It is not necessarily scandalous to hear it said that words are merely words. To
dismiss the fantasies of the word made flesh ... , to know that words are merely
words ... , can help us arrive at a better understanding of how words and
images, stories and pelformances, can change something of the world we live
in. (Ranci ère 2009a: 22-23)
If words change the world it is not because those words draw maps for readers
to follow, or provide models for readers to build; it is not because those words
explicate. Ifwords change the world it is because they emancipate; it is because
they caB on that power of literarity that is the excess of words thereby bringing
about a new configuration of the world (le partage du sensible).
Afterword 1
N
Introduction
I. Rancière gave his first book the title La leçon d'Althusser (Rancière 1974a). The
book is widely referred to for marking Rancière's famous "break" with Althusser, but
little attention has been given to the specificity of Rancière's title. While it may also
allude to Althusser's larger "teaching," the singular Lesson in question in the title is Al-
thusser's "Reply to John Lewis" (Althusser 1976). Rancière interprets this text - along
with Althusser's short early essay "Student Problems" (Althusser 2011) - as a "les son in
orthodoxy" (Rancière 201 ra: xxiii). His critique of Althusser starts with a set ofreadings
of Marx that show the gap between Marx's own texts and the "M-L" figure that oc cu pies
Althusser's "lesson" to John Lewis. This makes Althusser's "les son" nothing less than a
les son of mastery - one that establishes the mastery of "M-L" and of Marxist orthodoxy,
while constituting the blindness of John Lewis and his common sense. For more on the
critique of Althusser over questions of mastery, see the recent exchange in Radical Phi-
losophy convened in response to the long-awaited translation of Rancière's first book
(Rancière 20IIa; Montag 2011; Brown 20II). BothAlain Badiou and Slavoj Zizek have
previously used slight variations of the title 1 have chosen for my book .- Badiou's in
French, and Zizek's in the singular (Badiou 2009; Zizek 2006).1 briefiy address the rela-
tion between Badiou and Rancière at various points in the book, and 1 formulate an indi-
rect response to Zizek's critique in the first two chapters. Here 1 would stress that neither
of these authors shows any interest at aIl in the questions of lessons, of mastery, and of
radical pedagogy that prove central to Rancière's work and my reading of it. My choice
of title is therefore designed both to resonate with Rancière's own book titles and to fore-
ground the importance of these issues to both Rancière's writings and to my project
here.
2. Two very fine introductory texts on Rancière's writings have recently appeared,
both of which provide a broad overview of Rancière's writing, proceeding chronologi-
cally across his corpus and both raise just this problem. Tanke responds by saying that
his book offers a "reading" of Rancière rather than an "exegesis"; this, he suggests, allows
him to provide commentary and arguments on Rancière's oeuvre without "undermining
the supposition of equality" (Tanke 20 II: 1). For his part, Davis asserts that his "book
about Rancière cannot with any confidence claim to be Rancierian"; Davis has a different
goal, that of making possible an engagement with "Rancière's singular project" by pro-
viding the needed context (Davis 20IO: xi). In the text above and in the chapters that
follow implement my own "solution" to the dilemma of reading Rancière without stul-
tifying. By declining the temptation to produce an "overview" or "introduction" to Ran-
cière's work, by rejecting a chronological approach, and by refusing to discuss aU of
Rancière's writings systematically, my goal is to produce a book that is less "on Ran-
cière" and more "Rancièrean."
3. In Chapter One 1 offer sorne brief comparisons and contrasts between Arendtian
and Rancièrean accounts of politics. Arendt's commitment to a politics of natality is in a
certain way a commitment to a politics of novelty, of newness, and creation. This sort of
project has affinities with the Rancièrean politics of surprise that 1 describe in the text.
However, 1 do not think it amounts to the same sort of genuine surprise that Rancière
believes in. As 1 show in Chapter One, despite their commonalities, one fundamental
point separates them: for Rancière there is no proper sphere of the political.
4. In this, liberal theorists and social scientists display classic symptoms of para-
noia. As D. A. Miller writes: "surprise ... is precisely what the paranoid seeks to elimi-
nate" (Miller 1988: 164; quoted in Sedgwick 2003: 130). Sedgwick also shows that a
certain sort of paranoid structure, and a resistance to surprise, inhabits and determines
the traditional approaches to critical theory, which she identifies with Ricoeur's phrase
"the hermeneutics of suspicion." ln Chapter Four 1 outline an alternative critical dis-
positif, one that differs in many ways from Sedgwick's "reparative reading" but that
shares with her both the rejection of demystification as stultifying and an openness
to surprise.
5. In my frequent references to "liberalism," 1 mean to call attention to a broad cluster
of concepts including the idea of government based on consent that protects the rights and
property of individuals conceived as autonomous agents. It is this core of liberalism that
matters to me - below 1 call this "doctrinalliberalism" especially as it is connected to a
political philosophy premised on a certain order and hierarchy. 1 neither deny nor mask
over the great variety of liberalisms and the significant extent of tension between and
among them. 1 also do not mean to imply that seventeenth-century liberalism can compre-
hend aIl of the politics or political philosophy of today. Twenty-first-century neoliberal-
ism looks very different from seventeenth- or eighteenth-century liberalism, and the
Lockean state of nature theory looks very different from the Rawlsian original position
theory. That said, for my limited purposes here, two points will suffice. First, a variant of
Lockean liberalism (with the same core terms of equality, rights, and limited government
based on consent) appears to provide the only terms of challenge or resistance to the
growing hegemony of twenty-first-century economic neoliberalism. The former is just as
impoverished as the latter is dominating. Second, the explicit effort to create a political
philosophy of order marks Rawls (e.g., "the well ordered society") even more perspicu-
ously than Locke. For the links between neoconservative thought and neoliberalism, see
Brown (2006).
6. This is not to say that social scientists themselves will not often produce unex-
pected or unanticipated results. But those results will still have to be surprising, or not,
within the terms of order laid out by the social scientific approach; the "surprise" can
Notes 1 173
r6. The contradiction in terms "police politics" must be kept distinct from the idea
of the "politics of the police;' which 1 discuss in detail in Chapter Two. As 1 show there,
while policing must never be confused with or directly associated with politics, there are
still political implications and effects of various police orders.
17. 1 call Schmitt's critique "infamous" because his criticisms ofWeimer-era liberal
democracy prove so difficult to dissociate from his own support of the Nazi regime and
his later refusai to participate in denazification. This is just one reason why, in clarifying
my argument about the difference between democracy and IiberaIism, Mouffe's mobili-
zation of Schmitt's work makes for a much better comparison than wou1d any direct
comparison between Rancière and Schmitt. As a distinct contrast 1 would also note that
Schmitt's concept of "the political" offers a perfect example of just the sort of poIiticaI
onto1ogy that Rancière rejects - as 1 discuss below (see Marder 20IO).
18. 1 am not suggesting that commenters on an Internet article are representative of
anything at a11, nor that these arguments should be given any particu1ar weight. These
responses simply suggest how hard it sometimes is, within the prevailing common sense,
to see a difference between the democratic and the given liberal political order.
19. For Iiberalism, the question of how to implement political rule always comes
after the liberal framework has been established. Like Locke's discussion of political in-
stitutions late in the Second Treatise (r988), the question of age requirements for office-
holding would thus be a secondary topic of debate, regarding the issue of how to uphold
Iiberal rights and the sovereignty of the people while still making it possible for govern-
ment to protect life, liberty, and property.
20. This discussion also hints at the key differences in political rhetorics between norrna-
tive liberal theory, on the one hand, and Rancièrean democratic polemics, on the other, in that
here we also see two distinct ways to think about the relation between a rule and an instance
of it. Liberal theory does not typically use examples to show or embody how something
works; rather, liberal theory itself produces rules, and examples are meant to illustrate a rule
that is already there, to provide pro of ofthe rule's existence. In contrast, in my discussion here
1 am using the examp1e as an analogy of the general process by which liberalism operates - to
make that process clearer and easier to grasp. (See Finlayson and Atkins forthcoming).
2 r. As 1 show in Chapter Two, while it remains crucial to see the 10gica1leverage that
this move gives Rancière - by, in short, freeing him to rethink poli tics - one shou1d not
conclude that Rancière means nothing more by police than "what we usually mean by
politics." Rancière's concept of la police has a longer history and a greater conceptual
reach than that notion wou1d indicate, and that concept does a great dea1 of important
work in his writings.
22. 1 do not engage in specific detai1 with Rancière's writings on literature and
cinema. Further, while the concept of le partage du sensible lies at the very heart of aIl
Rancière's writings - and 1 therefore address it in numerous locations throughout the
book - 1 do not offer an explicit treatment of Rancière's contribution to art and aesthetics.
Crucially, Rancière himse1f does not consider "aesthetics" a separate category from poIi-
tics, as he says, "Politics is aesthetics in that it makes visible what had been excluded
from a perceptua1 field, and that it makes audible what had been inaudible" (Rancière
2004b: 226; Rancière 2005a; see a1so Ferris 2009). In trying to unravel the meaning of
this claim in political theory, Davide Panagia's work proves exemplary (Panagia 2006;
Panagia 2009, which quotes the line above in its first footnote, r65).
Notes 1 175
that Connolly would not recognize his own approach to ontology in Rancière's
critique, and that there are at least three positions at stake -- heavy ontology, ontopolitical
interpretation, and Rancière's rejection of aU ontology. Nevertheless, the wide gap be-
tween Connolly's insistence on the ineluctability of ontology, on the one hand, and Ran-
cière's own insistence on eschewing all ontology, on the other, helpfully serves my
purpose in the text of drawing out the contours and stakes of Rancière's overall approach
to ontology.
29. Chapter Three not only explores Rancière's conception of subjectivation in more
depth but also provides a much fuller explanation of the use and meaning of the tenTI in
English and th en explores the question of translation from Rancière's French.
30. See Chapter Four for a much fuller discussion of the uniquE: publishing history
of Lire le Capital, including Rancière's contribution, which was excluded from English
translations of the work. Chapter Four also includes a close reading of this text and a
discussion of its significance for Rancière's broader corpus. Rancière's single essay first
appeared in English translation broken into separate pieces, in various journals in the
1970s. A complete, translated version of the essay did not appear until 1989, but this ver-
sion was published in a little-read and little-known edited volume that is now out of print
and very hard to find: hence my claim in the text that it has not been properly published,
since it surely is not yet widely available to Rancière's very large English-speaking
audience.
3 1. One way to understand the complicated and difficult reception of Rancière by
British and North American audiences is by emphasizing that Rancière does not produce
arguments in the same way as so many political theorists do, and therefore Rancière's
writing often does not fit the established reading habits of these audiences. Understood in
a traditional way, an argument presupposes a set of criteria for validation of that argu-
ment, but Rancière insists that politics undoes and denies any sort of pre-established cri-
teria. In this sense we might call "argumentation" a process of the police, whereas
polemicization is a process of politics. Polemics is an alternative genre to argument, one
that intervenes, affirms and resists, but does so without presurning the validity of a prior
set of conditions that would legitimate political claims. Polemics is thus itself a form of
"part-taking." In this context, 1 first wish to stress that Rancière's polemics, and his writ-
ings in a more general sense, can also be understood to offer their own sort of arguments -
so long as we are willing to broaden our conception of what constitutes an argument.
Nonetheless, since my goal is not to recreate Rancière's polemical engagements - a proj-
ect that wou Id be doomed to failure in any case, given the conjectural nature of those very
engagements - my style is not Rancière's. Those that try to write about Rancière by writ-
ing like Rancière often do very Httle to open their readers to an encounter with his work.
Indeed, their style ends up being more isolating and alienating than Rancière's own;
mimicking his style does litt le to allow Rancière's thinking to reach a broader audience.
Since 1 do not consistently polemicize the way that Rancière does, there are times when
my own approach may even appear to be at odds with his. In other words, 1 often make
arguments where Rancière refuses to do so; sometimes 1 even engage in exposition or
exegesis. My goal is to animate Rancière's polernics, to illurninate them, and to transform
them for my own ends. My audience is also different from Rancière's. Rancière's writ-
ings do not speak to a pre-given discipline; rather, they contest, perhaps even exp Iode, the
bounds of disciplinarity; his work thrusts toward anti-disciplinarity (Mowitt 1992) or
Notes 1 177
neutrality) would be to substitute a generic individual for the definite individual to which
Rancière is always referring. Faced with this difficulty, will occasionally alternate be-
tween a concrete "he" and a concrete "she," as do in the discussion of radical pedagogy
in the text below.
39. Throughout this section 1 provide a particular reading of "liberalism" and liberai
theory designed to clarify the contours of Rancière's conception of equality and at the
same rime to mark the stakes of my own argument for democratic poli tics. We might
helpfully name this variant of liberalism, and its approach to seventeenth-century authors
such as Hobbes and Locke, "doctrinalliberalism." It is a widely recognized account of
liberalism, one that resonates with les sons given each year in history of political thought
courses, and one that dovetails with arguments made by Rawls and other important con-
temporary liberal theorists. Nonetheless, one couid certainly reread authors like Hobbes
and Locke against this very doctrinalliberalism for which their texts have been appropri-
ated by contemporary liberai thinkers. Such an interpretation might actually complement
Rancière's thinking of equality and democracy. On this reading, one would first empha-
size the rhetorical and to some extent practicai force of Hobbes's and Locke's arguments
about equality: namely, to tear down any naturalization of aristocracy and politicai role of
"birth." Equality was therefore not so substantive for Hobbes and Locke as it is for doc-
trinalliberalism. Second, their arguments for equality were ultimately designed to legiti-
mate inequality, since it was obvious to Hobbes and Locke that some are legitimated to
rule others. Equality was therefore not so central for Hobbes and Locke as it is for doc-
trinalliberalism. Third, the Rancièrean sense of politics as "calling a system of domina-
tion into question" looks a great deal more like what Hobbes and Locke were up to
politically when they wrote their texts, that is, prior to the constitution of "liberalism" as
a doctrine. This means that Hobbes' and Locke's arguments, as originally put, and when
thought as explicit political interventions (which they were) prove significantly more
Rancièrean than the decontextualized version out of which liberal "theory" has been con-
structed as "what liberalism is" - that is, modern doctrinalliberalism. Finally, one might
add that just as May '68 was an irruption of politics in Rancière's sense, so were the
events in Europe of 1848, events led by "revolutionary liberals" - a term that makes no
sense when understood through doctrinal liberalism, but is nonetheless historically ac-
curate. When read this way, of course, Hobbes and Locke would, quite simply, not be
liberals in the current doctrinal sense. For just this reason, while 1 am sympathetic to this
more historically situated and also more radical reading of Hobbes and Locke, 1 stand
behind my own effort to contrast liberalism in the doctrinal sense with Rancière's account
of equality. Moreover, the hegemony of doctrinal liberalism minoritizes the historical
reading of Hobbes and Locke. On this issue, 1 owe a debt to Terrell Carver for extended
engagement, deep insights, and a few turns of phrase.
Chapter One
1. ln this chapter 1 cite a large number of the early texts on Rancière and poli tics, but
1 do not discuss a few key essays that should be mentioned here: Michael Dillon (2003a),
Kirstie McClure (2003), Aamir Mufti (2003), and Paolo Palladino and Tiago Moreira
(2006). At the time of this writing, a wealth of literature on Rancière has either just
emerged or is about to appear, including special issues of journals and secondary source
books on Rancière's work. It goes without saying that it is impossible to cite aU of this
Notes 1 '79
politics for argumentative leverage (as a tool of critique) is to read his project quite nar-
row ly and to limit the overall import of his work. Thus, this first "use" of Rancière' s defi-
nition of politics is surely "critical work," but only in a relatively thin sense that must be
distinguished from the idea of a developed critical the ory.
7. As just one example, Markell demonstrates that the territorial reading of The
Human Condition leads to a conftation of the "philosophical representation of work" and
"the phenomena Îtself' (Markell zo II: 35). In this argument 1 hear important echoes of
Rancière's critique of the tradition of political philosophy, as 1 will discuss in the next
chapter.
8. It is also worth nothing that the text where Honig caUs on Rancière the most, De-
mOCl'acy and the Foreigner (Z001), is also the text where she relies on Arendt the least.
9. For non-native French speakers such as myself, 1 would interrupt here to coyer
the basics: this "distinction," in French, is tirst of an nothing more than the difference
between feminine and masculine - and thus becomes no difference at aH when translated
into the "genderless" English language. In regular French usage, la politique connotes
more of the everyday business of politics (e.g. "department politics" as used in English)
while le politique suggests something broader, more systematic, more philosophical.
IO. And it does seem to be Zizek's claim - and not a misreading by Marchart as
Zizek opens his reading of Rancière in The Ticklish Subject by referring to "la politique!
police" as a singular entity that would be "perturbed" by a "political mode of rebellion"
(Zizek 1999: 17 Z ).
II. In his translator's introduction to The Politics of Aesthetics, Gabriel Rockhill
do es make reference, if only in passing, to a distinction between "politics" and "the po-
litical," but he gives no French translation of those terms in his English introduction, and
his translation of the French marks no distinction either (Rockhill 2006: 3). 1 will return
to this point in the text below.
12. Tanke follows Deranty entirely here, when he says, "The political [le politique]
is this third space of contestation, an indeterminate and always shifting meeting point of
the police and politics" (Tanke 201 1: 5 1, emphasis added). In making this claim, Tanke
provides no citation of any texts at an - neither those of Rancière nor of anyone else. A
few lines later, on a different point, Tanke does cite Deranty.
13. Or better, the distinction emerges from the French translations of those English
texts, as 1 exp Iain in more detail in the text below.
14. All translations from this I998a edition are mine.
15. The French translation leaves out these first two paragraphs, and begins instead
with Rancière simply asking, of himself and the reader, "Qu'est-ce que le politique, nous
est-il demande?" (Rancière I998a: 83).
16. It seems plausible to make this move, but technically it is surely a mistranslation,
since any English-to-French dictionary will give la politique as the translation for policy.
Here we see even more starkly that in this lecture Rancière proposes differences that
really hoid only in English. A direct translation back into French of the English Rancière
uses would give us the "difference" between la politique and le politique.
17. Even here, where Rancière explicitly clarifies what might be at stake for him in
the difference between la politique and le politique, we still see nothing like the stark
"political difference" (as Marchart tinds in so many other authors) nor a clear delineation
of three terms as suggested in Deranty's work.
Notes 1 181
between la and le politique in his retranslation of "The Ten Theses"
and Panagia 2001). Perhaps it would make sense to leave la politique and le politique in
French (at least in parentheses) in future translations of Rancière's work.
26. In this vein, Deleuze's project to articulate a non-dialectical opposition in Ni-
etzsche proves exemplary, and, of course, in many ways the entire Derridean project
devotes itself to a thinking of non-dialectical difference, that is, différance (Deleuze
1983; Derrida 1982). Numerous commentators on Rancière have either addressed the
issue of "dialectical thinking" in his work directly (Thomson 2003), applied dialectics to
Rancière (Zizek 1999), or offered a putatively Rancièrean understanding of politics that
obeyed its own dialectical logic (May 2008). For the purposes of my specific argument
here, the question of "dialectics" is not the essential one, since what matters, ultimately,
is whether or not politics can be rendered pure, or if politics is that which always renders
itself (through its doubling) and its other, impure. A dialectical overcoming produces a
purified result, so in that sense a dialectical approach to Rancière would arrive at the
same problematic telos of a purified politics. For the sake of clarity my argument here
largely avoids the language of dialectics. 1 address this argument from a different angle
in Chapter Two.
27. On impure politics, see David Kaplan's notion of "impure democracy" in the
work of Paul Ricoeur (Kaplan 2008: 207; cf. Marchart 2007).
28. In Chapter Three 1 offer an in-depth discussion of Rancière's notion of the
"excess of words," including both a genealogy of the phrase's emergence in his writing
and an argument about its relation to the concept of "literarity." At this point, 1 should
mention only that the notion of an "excess of words" is neither an abstraction nor a eu-
phemism for Rancière. The phrase points to two distinct but related claims that Rancière
makes across his writings: first, a general claim about political philosophers' repeated
attempts to eliminate the excess of words (going back to Plato's efforts to regulate dis-
course and banish the poets and sophists); and second, a specific historical claim. In this
second sense "excess of words" names a phenomenon produced by eighteenth-century
democratic revolutions whereby names proliferate without titles to fix them in place.
Democracy offers unruliness, then, because in it names circulate without any authority
(whether epistemological or political) to pin them down to a fixed identity. "Excess of
words" therefore offers a different way of expressing the impurity of politics: namely, the
impropriety of anyone and everyone counting as a citizen, of having "citizen" itself count
as a proper title. This note owes a deep debt to an anonymous reviewer.
29. In the Afterword to the English translation of The Philosopher and His POOl;
Rancière refers to his own "theory of politics." To my knowledge, this is the only place
Rancière uses such language in a positive sense, though even here he complicates it sig-
nificantly, saying that it "moved considerably away from what is generally understood by
that name" (Rancière 2004b: 225).
30. It is also why the moment a putatively democratic project becomes purely self-
referential- concerned only with those who struggle and not with the stmggle itself - is
the moment that it is no longer "political" in Rancière's sense (Thomson 2003: 17).
Two
1. In this chapter 1 stage a detailed engagement with, and offer a close reading of,
May's central book on Rancière (May 2008), but May's other writings on Rancière (May
Notes 1
le partage du sensible la police in Rancière's later the idea
of a police order but on a broader level. But that only lends more credence to the idea that
"the police" serves a particular purpose in terms of Rancière's political intervention in the
mid-1990s.
8. In this context, however, would insist on not conftating Rancière's analysis of
post-democracy with his articulation of archipolitics, parapolities, and metapolitics. The
difference matters because it is a difference in both objects and levels of analysis. Ran-
cière's analysis of archipolitics (for ex ample) provides a critique of the project of poli tic al
philosophy, whereas his analysis of post-democracy provides a critique of contemporary
politics. The latter therefore constitutes a political intervention in a sense different from
the former. As 1 show in the text below, 1 think May sometimes elides these differences.
9. Another way of putting this would be to say that May did not discover anarchism
through a reading of Rancière. Quite the contrary, May was already a committed, well-
known, and forceful defender of anarchist thought before he came to Rancière's writings
and folded Rancière's thought into May's own anarchist project. See May (I994); see
also Ward (1982).
10. For a fuIler reading of Rancière's arguments about archipolitics, parapolities,
and metapolities, see my discussion in Chapter Four.
1 1. Zizek outlines the paradox of this dialectieallogie and accuses Rancière himself
of falling prey to it (a faIse accusation, according to my argument, and as 1 show below).
Alex Thomson had earlier worked through a similar logie in Rancière's work and arrived
at more subtle and productive conclusions. See Thomson (2003), Zizek (2006); cf. Valen-
tine (200S).
12. Although 1 present this reading as a critique of May, May himself might freely
admit to the difference between his position and Rancière's, on this point. May departs
from Rancière's notion that politics begins with a wrong, with what Deranty helpfully
caUs an "ontological torsion" (Deranty 2003a: par. S). Explicitly ftagging his claim as an
argument against Rancière, May claims that poli tics "is not necessarily antagonistie"
(May 2008: SI-S2). May must, in a way, mark this difference from Rancière, because
Rancière's politics always remains impure, always occurs in medias res. In contras t, and
as 1 exp Iain through my reading of May in the text below, anarchist politics must be self-
contained, self-referential and sui generis. May sees in this difference a need to tweak
Rancière; 1 see in this difference the very reason not to read Rancière as May does. In a
later text May explicitly states that Rancièrean polities "is not simply an affair of self-
involvement" - a distinction that does not seem so clear in May's earlier book (May 2009:
1I6).
I3. May would insist on the distinction between his conception of anarchism and
"revolutionary anarchism," and would even suggest (rightly, in my opinion) that Ran-
cière's thought undermines the traditional distinction between reform and revolution
(May 2012). My point in the text is neither to pigeonhole May's thought within the tradi-
tion of revolutionary anarchism, nor to enter into debates about the nature of anarchist
thought. My disagreement with May centers on the idea of politics as autochthonous and
self-sustaining. It is the idea that poli tics concems only itself that 1 think takes May far
afield from what 1 see as Rancière's more radical conception of democracy (and in so
doing, this account of politics seems to imply an attendant sense of "revolution," even if
that is not May's stated position within anarchist thought).
Notes 1
Dost-SeDtemtJer II'' (Dean 2009a: I4). the case of the first critique, Dean has attrib-
uted to Rancière an argument that is not his own, bur rather is the object of his critique.
"Post-democracy" (Rancière's term) is not a regime we live in, but a critical conceptual-
ization of the very goal of "consensus democracy" (Ranci ère 1999: lO2). In the case of
the second critique, Dean quotes Rancière's description of early I990S France and then
asserts strongly that it does not capture late 2000S USA. Her statement is certainly true,
but 1 am not sure it has the critieal force she would appear to attribute to it. In not taking
Rancière's conception of democratic polities seriously, Dean may miss out on a potential
ally in her battle against neoliberal "communicative capitalism."
18. For reminding me of the connotations of the word struggle in traditional ac-
counts, and thereby helping to clarify and refine the important senSè of "struggle" in
Rancière's understanding of democratie politics, 1 owe a debt to Benjamin Arditi.
Three
1. Reading Oliver Davis's helpful summary of the work done in the I970S by Ran-
cière and his collaborators at Les révoltes logiques, one can see clearly that Rancière's
work made a certain turn to language, to words, to logic, and to a polemical sense of argu·,
ment from very early on. As Davis puts it, reflecting on the meaning of the title of the
journal (borrowed from a Rimbaud poem): '''Logiques' reflects less the inexorability of
spontaneous resistance and points more to the words, the language, involved in that resis-
tance" (Davis 20lO: 39-40). Rancière himself formulates the point succinctly: "What is
called rebellion or revoit is also a scene of speech and reasons" (Rancière 20r rb: lo).
This chapter develops the account of literarity within the context of philosophieal debates
over language, but 1 should stress at the outset that the question of literarity, of the excess
of words, always exceeds the often narrower terms of language or discourse. Rancière's
is a polities of the unsayable and the inaudible, and also of the invisible and unpresentable
(Panagia 2006: 88). In this chapter 1 center my account on the former only as a matter of
fOCllS and never to the exclusion of the latter.
2. This maneuver must not turn into an ontologizing move. The idea is not to ontolo-
gize something in Rancière but to get at sometlzing that Rancière himself would never get
at, to put his arguments into motion toward ends he does not conceive.
3. Sinclair's translation stands out from others in its unique rendering of the distinction
between phonë and logos as the difference between expressing and indicating; only Sin-
clair's translation uses the word express to describe whatphonë does (Aristotle 1981). Rack-
ham, Barker, and Everson aU choose the word indicate for the role of phOnë, while they
differ on the work done by logos: Rackham uses indicate a second time; Barker pieks de-
clare; and Everson goes with setforth (Aristotle 1944; Aristotle 1958; Aristotle 1996).
4. Because of this, as 1 show below, it turns out that a fairly literaI translation of Ar-
istotle's Greek into English looks very similar to a translation of Rancière's French trans-
lation back into English. And both ofthese versions diverge significantly from the Sinclair
version used by Rose.
5. 1 calI the translation "mine" because 1 have chosen the final rendering and because
1 take full responsibility for any mistakes, but for making this translation possible 1 am
deeply indebted to the indefatigable work of Nathan Gies.
6. Immediately after the quote, Rancière digresses very briefly, noting that these
famous words of Aristotle have quite obviously been read by many political philosophers
Notes 1
introduction mentions it again in her next chapter and then she uses it repeat-
edly and explicitly (more than a dozen times) in her discussion of Foucault (84'-149).
can only assume that Milchman and Rosenberg have mistaken Butler's broader project
in the book, which involves what she calls "theories of subjection, with her specifie
rendering of Foucault's assujettissement. As mention in the text, her term of choice
does, in fact, prove problematic, but not for the reasons that Milchman and Rosenberg
in their otherwise invaluable study.
II. One other wrinkle worth noting: of the more than a dozen French dictionaries
(hat 1 have consulted, none contains an entry for "subjectivation," leading me to conclude
that the word is most likely a coinage (by Foucault or someone else) derived from the
French words subjectif and/or subjection. Milchman and Rosenberg make no explicit
argument for how to translate the French subjectivation into English, but they implicitly
support the case 1 make in the text above by frequently using the English "subjectivation"
as a direct translation of the French word (Milchman and Rosenberg 2007: 56).
I2. 1 made this mistake in an early article on Rancière (Chambers 2005).
r3. Sorne commentators/translators in English have muddled what in Rancière's
French might otherwise be clear. Thus, in the widely consulted "Glossary of Technical
Terms" that appears as an appendix to The PoUtics of Aesthetics, Rockhill translates
subjectivation as "subjectivization," listing "subjectification" and "subjectivation" as
alternate translations (Rockhill2006: 92). This move cornes close to collapsing a number
of potentially important distinctions, especially when one considers the connotations
that sorne of those terms have vis-à-vis Foucault's work. In recently released secondary
works on Rancière by Davis (2010) and Tanke (2011), there is an apparent consensus,
which 1 support, for the English subjectivation. However, neither of these authors says
anything about the context, and neither mentions the fact that Rancière's subjectivation
has been translated many other ways (even, in an important sense, by Rancière himself).
Moreover, Tanke's discussion of subjectivation explicitly turns to Foucault, but Tanke
fails to mention that while Rancière uses but the one French term in his publications,
Foucault actually introduces subjectivation in order to mark a distance from his earlier
assujettissement.
14. This line of argument from Rancière's famous 1995 book Disagreement con-
nects quite clearly, if indirectly, to his earliest work at Les révoltes logiques: "There is no
voice of the people. There are fragmented, polemical, voices which split the identity they
put forward every time they speak" (quoted in Davis 2010: 41).
15. Rancière has articulated a number of important and powerful criticisms of Lyo-
tard's worle. In particular, he challenges Lyotard's opposition between the "grand narra-
tives" of modernity and the proliferation of language games in postmodernity. Perhaps
most significantly, Rancière opposes Lyotard's move toward an aesthetics without eman-
cipation and the construction of a "univers al victim" (Rancière 1995c: 64; see also Ran-
cière 1999: 39; cf. Rancière 201 IC). This means that Rancière targets both the earlier
(I984) and later (I990) Lyotard texts and does not focus on the work that is central to my
reading here (Lyotard I988). For a more detailed comparison of différend and mésen-
tente, see Déotte (2004).
16. As Rancière indicates in a footnote to the now published version of "The Think-
ing of Dissensus," 1 gave a paper in 2003 that did, in fact, try to demonstrate, at turns,
either the ontological proximity between Lyotard and Rancière on language, or the extent
Notes 1
23. Rancière will go on to argue that literarity forms the centrallink between poUtics
and literature (2004a: I08).
24. have tried to be very clear in this discussion to distinguish between, on the one
hand, when the idea of literarity emerges and takes shape in Rancière's writings, and, on
the other, when the specific term itself first appears. To summarize, the term literariness
appears earliest; it is then followed by a very particular use of the word literary (in the
sense of the political animal as a "literary animal"); and this is followed in tum by the
coinage of the word literarity (at the end of Flesh ofWords). In ber otherwise helpful sum-
mary chapter on Rancière's concept of literarity, Alison Ross runs the risk of confusing
matters greatly when she says directly, "The concept of 'literarity' first appears in the 1995
book - La mésentente" (Ross 20 IO: 136). Ross then goes on to summarize the arguments
in Disagreement that do, 1 agree, help to ftesh out what Rancière means by literarity. How-
ever, her presentation implies that La mésentente actually uses the tenn littérarité. This is
simply not true. Rockhill's glossary entry for "literarity" indicates, in outline, a similar
genealogy as the one 1 work through in the text (Rockhil12006: 87; cf. Rockhill 2006: 5).
25 We probably should not forget -- though Rancière does not bother to remind us -
that Plato himself took the risk of the excess of words by deciding, unlike his teacher
Socrates, to write his philosophy as dialogues. Thus the threat to his kallipolis, to his
entire philosophy of order, is a threat that he himself puts into play. Thanks to Bonnie
Honig for reminding me of this important point.
26. 1 have consistently framed this discussion in tenns of Rancière's critique ofPlato,
but it could also be expressed in terms of his consistent admiration for a writer like Flau-
bert. Rather than denying the excess of words, Flaubert's literary style depends upon em-
bracing a certain literarity: "His very refusaI to entrust literature with any message
whatsoever was considered to be evidence of democratic equality" (Rancière 2006d: 14).
27. Here 1 focus on one piece of Apostolidis's early published research on immigrant
workers (Apostolidis 2005); he has recently published a much larger body of research in
book form (Apostolidis 2010).
Chapter Four
1. In so doing 1 also mean to lay out a Iogic quite distinct from the conservative one
that Berlant and Wamer criticize in their important "What Does Queer Theory Teach Us
about X?" (1995).
2. Read in the context of the partage, we might say that a dispositifis a mechanism
that apprehends a particular distribution of the sens ory realm. Thought in this sense, a
dispositif would not represent reality, but would capture it. This particularly Rancièrean
reading of the dispositif points already toward my conclusion in this chapter: a critical
dispositif beyond inversion. 1 will take these points up again in the final section; at this
juncture 1 wish only to delineate the tenns through which 1 will address a variety of no-
tions of critique.
3. In other words, much work today rightly resists the idea that a theory of the politi-
cal must be a critical theory, and 1 join my colleagues in insisting that not all political
theory needs to be critical in the sense 1 want to articulate here. Creative, imaginative, and
very positive reconsiderations and reenvisionings of political theory prove absolutely cru-
cial to the possibility of a renewed sense of politics - to new political possibilities. For
just two of the numerous recent examples of such work, see Shapiro (2009) and Connolly
analysis.
4. Bennett also makes a not-so-common argument when she suggests that the critical
logic of inversion "presumes that at the heart of any event or process lies a human agency
that has illicitly been projected into things" (Bennett 2009: xiv). Thus, for Bennett, the
logical inversion performed by the critical theorist operates by way of, and smuggles in,
a certain form of anthropocentrism - because the essence that inversion uncovers is
always ultimately human will and human agency (a human essence). As l discussed in
Chapter Three, Bennett and 1 share a desire to challenge anthropocentrism. More signifi-
cantly, in making this argument Bennett also echoes (though again, in a distinct key) the
Althusserian critique of the humanist reading of Marx; according to Althusser, Marx's
early writings always smuggle in an elicit anthropology that serves as an ethical ground
for critique. Bennett's methodological anti-anthropocentrism and Althusser's method-
ological antihumanism thus share important affinities, in that both authors argue that in
order to understand structures, processes, and (ultimately) politics aright, we must reject
the tendency to trace their origins and causes back ta human sources. This means that the
Marx that Bennett gestures toward in her brief account of demystification (a humanist),
and the Marx that Althusser wants to bring to light (perhaps not an antihumanist, but
certainly a non··humanist) - these are not at all the same Marx. At stake between them is
the possibility of a non-anthropocentric reading of Marx; l do not pursue such a reading
in this chapter, but 1 do try to keep such a possibility alive.
5. To the extent that one could trace the current dominant connotations of "critical
theory" (as Bennett and others use it) back to specifie authors and texts, it seems that the
most prevalent understanding today fits better with Horkheimer's early work - especially
his famous, and widely read within social science circles, essays on ''Traditional and Criti-
cal Theory" and "The End of Reason" (Horkheimer l 972) - than with, for example, that
of Adorno, who was already struggling (as so many others have) to move past the logic of
inversion (Adorno 2005).1 offer this sense of the dominant understanding of critique so as
to provide contrast for my own tum away from this understanding. However, 1 have no
wish to reify the concept of critique that 1 try to resist here. 1 recognize the great diversity
of efforts to articulate a critical theory - and realize that the logic of inversion that 1 chal-
lenge is not the only way of thinking critique in social and political theory today - just as
1 recognize that mine is not the only project designed to rethink critique. For one promi-
nent and important example of rethinking critique, and a source for further overviews of
the contemporary state of criticism and critical theory, see Kompridis (2006).
6. 1 address these three locations in chronological order, but this move has nothing to
do with progressivism (either in Rancière's work or in my account). Rancière's polemics
have a punctual temporality that undermines any sort of linearity. Each piece of writing
1 address contains an engagement by Rancière with a particular conjuncture, and my own
account of these three pieces produces its own encounter with the current conjuncture.
Thus, there is no inevitability about the development of Rancière's thinking; such prog-
ress that there has been was never guaranteed in advance (progressivism); and there is
absolutely no end point or final state to it (teleology). Rancière's "ending," as 1 show, is
surely no more than a beginning to the task of rethinking critical theory.
7. For clarity and simplicity, in this list 1 will give the translated English title coupled
with the original publication date (in French for aU but the last text, which was drafted in
Notes 1 19'
English). The strange timing of the translation of Rancière's work into English has had a
number of interesting consequences for the reception and understanding of Rancière's
writings by an English-speaking audience. For more on this matter see the Introduction
(see also Chambers 20roa).
8. In addition to many other scattered references to Marx throughout his writings,
in my move from point l to point 2, l skip over entirely Rancière's critique of Marxism
in The Philosopher and His Poor (1983). This move probably demands a few words of
explanation. As 1 read his discussion of Marx in that text, the key issue for Rancière is the
concept of the proletariat as the "pure proletariat," kept in its place within the social order.
Rancière reads Marxism as an inverted form of Platonism: where Plato kept the shoe-
maker in his place so as not to disrupt the Platonic order, so Marxism keeps the artisan in
his place so as to make a revolution possible. In laying out this argument, Rancière does
quote Marx (Rancière 2004b: 80), but he offers a very selective and highly edited selec-
tion from Marx's text; 1 would interpret the full passage much differently. In any case, the
book does not really set out to offer a reading of Marx, but rather to show that both Pla-
tonism and Marxism can be seen to participate in the same logic of the philosopher. This
is an argument about Platonism and about Marxism (especially a certain Marxist sociol-
ogy), about a philosophy of order, and about sociological accounts of class, but it is not
reall y a reading of Marx.
9. Although it falls weIl beyond the scope of either this chapter or this book, 1 also
hint at the idea that such an answer might lie in a different understanding of Marx than
that provided either by traditional Marxism or by Rancière's own critique of Marx: one in
which Marx himself rejects the classical opposition between essence and appearance, one
in which Marx's critique of capitalism operates not by inversion (or demystification) but
according to a distinct logic of denaturalization. Such a reading would have to ask, in
Rancièrean fashion: What if Marx himself made the very assumption that Rancière says,
with genuine praise, is "foolish"? What if Marx privileged the proletariat not because (as
so many Marxists after Marx have often suggested) they had he Id sorne special knowl-
edge, not because they occupied a unique epistemological space, but sim ply because they
were less disabled than they were taken to be?
10. Crucially, then, such texts are not called "scientific" because they are empirical
in nature or because they operate by way of empiricist epistemology. Althusser uses the
word science in the way that his contemporary French historians of science used it (he is
concerned with scientific revolutions in the Kuhnian sense of paradigm changes) and not
in the way that twentieth-century North American social scientists used it. Empiricism is
always Althusser's ultimate opponent.
II. As a corollary, this means that when used rigorously, the antihumanist methodol-
ogy might enable an anti-anthropological reading of the so-called early works. Thus,
Althusserianism breaks with the hermeneutics of antihumanism in order to denigrate the
early works (Althusser and Balibar 2009 [1965]).
12. One finds other places in the text of the essay where Rancière reads Marx at a
very close textuallevel, and it is actually here - deep inside the text, as it were - that one
locates Rancièrean insights that often break out of and exceed the overall Althusserian
framework. As one example 1 would point to the powerful illumination of what Rancière
calls the "impossible equation" in Marx, and in capitalism, of "x commodity A = y com-
modity BOO (Rancière I989a: I06-ro).
Notes 1 193
to philosophize post hoc, and perhaps even to understand philosophy as a project com-
patible with the an-archic politics of the dêmas. Socratic elenchus may be much more
untimely than Platonic political philosophy.
19. This point powerfully separates Rancière's thinking of democracy from that of
Chantal Mouffe, thereby illuminating a contrast l drew in the Introduction. Mouffe de-
fines democracy as a form of rule, but for her this means specificaIly "the principle of the
sovereignty of the people" (Mouffe 2000: 2). From the perspective l have developed here,
such a move amounts to an inept and untenable attempt to transform the kratas of democ-
racy into an archê (Rancière 2006c: 76).
20. While Rancière takes perhaps the most radical and polemical approach to the
tradition of political thought imaginable, in his own way he agrees with the most conser-
vative defenders of that tradition: Plato is the most important figure in it.
2 I. Rancière goes on to say more about metapolitics, and thereby about critical
theory as inversion. It is not simply that the social is the truth underlying and masked
by its distortion: the logical structure of a metapolitical critique entails that the social
cornes to function not just as truth, but as the untruth of the political. Rancière shows
how the concept of class, in Marx and after, oscillates: sometimes functioning just like
an archipolitical truth, yet often operating according to a "nihilism of the falseness of
aIl things" (Rancière I999: 84). The metapolitical inversion can be understood as either
a revelation of the truth that underlies falsity, or merely the revelation of falsity as aIl
that there is.
22. Alain Badiou calls this Rancière's "median" style (Badiou 2009: 40). Perhaps by
"median" he means to distinguish Rancière from the "zero degree style" that Lyotard
takes up, as l discussed in Chapter Three (Lyotard I988: xiv). In any case, and to be clear,
my point is not that Rancière's style allows him to smuggle in a so-called normative posi-
tion, but that the style makes it harder to discern the logic of his critical project. l reject
Habermas's account of Foucault as a "cryptonormativist" because l think Foucault's work
undoes the normative/non-normative distinction on which Habermas bases his argument.
1 would refuse the application of this label to Rancière on similar grounds (Habermas
I990: 284)·
23. This interpretation can be bolstered by reading further into Rancière's text: in
chapter five Rancière turns to an ev en more explicit critique, this time of "consensus de-
mocracy." Here Rancière quite clearly attempts to demonstrate that what appears to be the
ultimate political solution (third way social democracy) turns out, in reality, not to be
politics at aIl. Consensus politics only appears political on the surface; in truth, it is noth-
ing but a new order of police. l have engaged more fully with these critiques in Chapter
One and Chapter Two.
24. Along this line of thinking, one could also argue that there are different types
of inversion within the complex history of critical theory, but for purposes of clarity in
my reading of Rancière here, 1 will maintain the distinction between inversion and
reversaI.
25. In 2007 and 2008, Rancière gave a number of talks at various universities in the
USA, aU of which shared the title "The Misadventures of Critical Thinking"; at the time
of this writing, sorne video recordings of these talks are available on YouTube. The Dart-
mouth undergraduate philosophy journal, Aparia, published a transcript of the lecture he
gave there (Rancière 2007b). Rancière also shared written drafts of the talk with students,
Notes 1 195
32. This move in the project takes it in a direction distinct from other contemporary
efforts to rethink "ideology critique" (see Laclau 2006; cf. Laclau 1996; 1994;
Lievens 2012).
33. This reading of hope resonates with that of Cornel West's vision of a
politics of hope that would actually "be betrayed by naive projections of a better future
that ignore the necessity of doing the real work" (West 2011).
34. Todd May has suggested that one can eschew the assumption of blind agents -
that one can affirm the Rancièrean equality of intelligence - without abandoning the idea
that sometimes such agents are "mistaken." In this way the (critical) theorist attempts to
show people something they did not see before, without presuming that they were blind
and now have sight. To me, the distinction makes intuitive sense and does not obviously
contradict anything that Rancière says about the abled and the disabled. However, l am
leery of the need to hold on to "mistaken" agents, as it seems to flirt with the danger of
sneaking in an "explicative order" through the back door. Surely students are sometimes
mistaken, but as 1 read Rancière, to make the assumption of equality is to require a radical
pedagogy in which teachers never presume mistaken students (May 20 11). Indeed, in
Rancière's radical pedagogy, teachers need know nothing. (This may weIl make Socrates
the first ignorant schoolmaster, and Plato the first stultifier.)
35. Deleuze's account of the "new" in relation to dispositifs helps shed light on what
remains critical in the critical dispositif that 1 am outlining here. Deleuze says, "We
belong to social apparatuses and act within them" (Deleuze 1991: 164), a description that
again makes dispositif resonate with le partage du sensible. To take up a critical orienta-
tion to the police order in which we find ourselves does not, therefore, require a logic of
inversion, because the critical dimension need not concern fundamental truths masked by
lies, but rather can hinge on the dimension of newness, of becoming, of change that trans-
forms and ruptures the police order.
36. It goes almost without saying that the police order can co-opt any polities, not
just one of "sense-making." 1 am showing here, however, that the polities of "sense-
making" has already adapted itself to an order of the police in which an can be known, aIl
can be seen, aIl can be understood. For pressing me on Rancière's rejection of under-
standing and sense-making, and for reminding me of the richer meaning of la mésentente,
1 again thank an anonymous reviewer.
37. David Couzens Hoy provides an excellent example to illustrate my pejorative
description in the text: Hoy affirms just the account that 1 here resist. He reads genealogy
as a project of critical theory committed to the repeated assertion of historical contin-
gency. His persuasively written and widely read account of critical the ory thus serves as
strong support for my argument that today the tradition of critieal theory and the broad
idea of a critical dispositif is often conflated with a generalized conception of genealogy
as a project that renders historically contingent anything that would appear ahistorical,
universal, or natural (Ho Y and McCarthy I994, especiaIly chapter 6). In tlùs context it is
helpful to cite Gabriel Rockhill's introduction to the recently translated Mute Speech,
where he argues that Rancière's own contribution to critical thinking "only approxi-
mates . .. radical historicism" (Rockhill 20 II: 5).
38. As a critique of capitalism, Marx (or better, Marxism) is often understood to
assert that capitalism alienates the worker by separating him from the object of his labor
(and from labor itself, and from his fellow laborers, and from his species being). Capitalism
Afterword
1. Thanks go to Nathan Gies for helping me to think the connection between After-
word and miscount.
2. 1 use the slogan as a prompt for pulling together sorne of the strands of the book,
and thus 1 offer my own reading of these eight words. 1 am by no means the first to do so.
Düttmann (1997) provides a detailed and lengthy exegesis in the context of theorizing the
politics of recognition, while Arditi and Valentine (1999) draw from Düttmann's own
work to help them render their crucial distinction between polemic and polemicization.
Both texts offer rich accounts from which 1 see no need to take a critical distance. None-
theless, my emphasis remains distinct; Arditi and Valentine interpret Düttmann (rightly, 1
think) as arguing that "on the surface, this is a demand for recognition" (Arditi and Val-
entine 1999: 1). But 1 would contend that even "on the surface" the Queer Nation chant
resists this reading. Düttmann explores a certain negative dialectics of recognition through
his extended meditations on the chant, but on my account the slogan itself refuses the dia-
lectical game of recognition in the first place. To read it otherwise is to run the risk of
reducing it to the standard formula of minority identity politics, as 1 discuss in detail in
the text below.
3. The dismissal can operate on a more general level, as weIl, particularly since it
proves easy to argue, and even simpler just to presume, that the realms of academic
theory and direct action on the street remain irreconcilably distant. It is child's play to
offer proof for this sort of daim: essays and arguments published in journals and books
are self-evidently not the same as the passing of legislation, the signing of laws, the issu-
ing of executive orders, or the judgment of judges. Of course, this sort of argument only
shows how potentially significant Rancière's thinking of politics can be; it does so be-
cause this very list of activities is not at aU what Rancière means by politics. Moreover,
what 1 am tempted to caU the "academic politicallament" the enunciation of the worry
that writing and argument never change anything - always seems to constrict the realm of
the political and to severely constrain the concept of change. After aU, who wants to cede
poli tics to politicians? If they are our only hope, there is not much hope at aIl. Moreover,
are not the best politicians the ones who refuse just this very move - the ones who think
Notes 1
that does have something to do with the And if professional politicians
can refuse a radical theory/practice dichotomy, perhaps so-called theorists can resist it as
weIl.
4. Matt (2008) provides an interesting, hands-on illustration of the tactical
uses of this slogan. The strategic arguments about using the chant provide good evidence
for my reading of its politics in the form of demands for equal rights and inclusion.
5. With these claims 1 emphasize the original appearance of the book in 1990 and
attempt to reconstruct a context that is easily lost sight of given the impact of the book.
That is, the effects of the book make it easy to rewrite its origin story. Nonetheless, in
1990 queer theory did not exist as a field and Butler's text was not written as a part of
lesbian and gay studies. Sedgwick's Epistemology of the Closet (1990) was published
earlier that year, but Butler's book was already in press. Moreover, Sedgwick's book was
not itself an intentional contribution to "queer theory." Theil' books - along with Halp-
erin's text from the same year, and others from much earlier (e.g., Foucault 1978) -- were
only retroactively claimed as "canonical texts" in the coming years, when works by de
Lauretis (1991), Warner (I993), and others helped (still mostly unintentionally) to form
a field around the name "queer theory." To say all this is not to deny or downplay the
importance of Gender Trouble in helping to radically reconceive gender and sexual iden-
tity, in helping to bring into existence, and then serve as a founding text for, the very
field of queer theory. It is merely to emphasize, as Butler herself do es in the I999 pref-
ace, that the book was not written with these goals in mind, and the context in which we
now situate it proves very different from the one in which it was produced (Butler
I999)·
6. Given the increasing confusion surrounding these terms today, it may be helpful
if 1 clarify my limited use of the language of "waves" of feminism. 1 refer to the "second
wave" to describe the women's movements and feminist theories of the I960s and I970s.
In the second wave, political struggles for the right to work, the right to fair pay and equal
treatment, reproductive rights, protection from rape and domestic abuse, challenges to
sexual harassment and many other goals, were loosely associated with daily practices
such as consciousness-raising and were variously linked with theoretical work concem-
ing the unique experiences of women, the epistemological primacy of women, or the
particular values and ethos of women. Nothing about the second wave has come to an
end; hence the metaphor of waves. 1 associate thinkers like Dworkin, MacKinnon, and
Harding with the second wave. In the 1980s and 1990s, a third wave of feminism took
shape and emerged in its own form, out of elements that were already a part of the second
wave. Like the second, the third wave proves very diverse, but it loosely congeals around
certain critiques of the ide a of a unified "experience" of woman, of the epistemological
primacy of women, or of the notion that politics can begin only after the subject of woman
has been established. Early lesbian feminism, Black feminist thought, pro-sex feminism,
and Butler's work aH have affinities in this sense, and many of these ideas can be traced
back to the 1970S (see, for example, Lorde 1984 [1979]). For this reason, referring to the
"waves" by time periods is always a very rough approximation: what matters most in
distinguishing the waves are the ideas and arguments, which historically are themselves
mixed up (like water in the ocean). More significantly, 1 do not use the label "third wave"
to define generational differences, and 1 entirely reject any linking of third wave feminism
with "post-feminism" (this last move is what forces some feminists to try to identify
Notes 1 199
does not simply or directly make visible what before had been invisible before.
the invisible visible is the project of tradition al critical thinking and of linear politics.
14. In many cases the "struggle against oppression" will best be waged within the
terms of the police order - that is, by improving those tenus and that order. To say this, as
have stressed through the book, i8 not to denigrate such work, but merely to retain a
clear sense of the difference between such work, on the one hand, and the action of demo-
cratic polities, on the other.
Works Cited 1
Rattansi,Ali, ed (1989). ldeology, Method, and Marx: Economy
London and New York: Routledge.
Rawls, John (1971). A TheOly of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls, John (1993). PoUtical Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Repo, Jemima (2011). The Biopolitics ofGender. PhD Dissertation. Helsinki: University
of Helsinki.
Robson, Mark (2009). "'A Literary Animal': Rancière, Derrida, and the Literature of
Democracy." Parallax, 15.3: 88-IOI.
Rockhill, Gabriel (2004). "The SHent Revolution." SubStance, 33. 1: 54-76.
Rockhill, Gabriel (2006). "Preface, Introduction, and Glossary," in Gabriel Rockhill (ed),
The Poliûcs of Aesthetics. London and New York: Continuum; vii-x; 1-6; 80-93.
Rockhill, Gabriel (2011). "Through the Looking Glass: The Subversion of Modernist
Doxa," introduction to Mute Speech: Literature, Critieal Theory, and PoUties.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Rorty, Richard (1991). Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers, Volume
2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ross, Alison (20 IO). "Expressivity, Literarity, Mute Speech," in Paul Bowman and Richard
Stamp (eds), Reading Raneière. London and New York: Continuum; 133-50.
Ross, Kristin (2002). May '68 and Its Afterlives. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Ross, Kristin (2009). "Historicizing Untimeliness," in Philip Watts and Gabriel Rockhill
(eds), Jacques Rancière: His to ry, PoUtics, Aestheties. Durham: Duke University
Press; 15-29.
Schaap, Andrew (2011). "En acting the Right to Have Rights: Jacques Rancière's Critique
of Hannah Arendt." European Journal of Political TheOly, 10.1: 22-45.
Schmitt, Carl (1988). The Crisis of Parliamentmy Democracy. Translated by Ellen
Kennedy. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Scott, Joan (1991). "The Evidence of Experience." Criticallnquiry, 17-4: 773-97.
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky (1990). Epistemology of the Closet. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky (2003). Touching Feeling: Affect, Pedagogy, Pelformativity.
Durham: Duke University Press.
Seery, John (201 la). Too Young to Run? A Proposal for an Age Amendment to the U.S.
Constitution. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Seery, John (20 lIb). "Wh y Should Holding Office Be for Old People Only?" Salon
(Online). Available from: http://www.salon.comlnews/politics/wacroomI201 1/06/
26/john_seery_age/index.html (Accessed: July 7,2011).
Shachtman, Noah (20Il). "Pentagon's Prediction Software Didn't Spot Egypt Unrest"
(Online). Available from: http://www.wired.comldangerrooml201 l/02/pentagon-
predict-egypt-unresU (Accessed: June 16,2011).
Shapiro, Michael (2009). Cinematie Geopolitics. New York: Taylor & Francis.
Skinner, Quentin (1988). "Meaning and Understanding in the History ofIdeas," in James
Tully (ed), Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and His Critics. Princeton:
Princeton University Press; 29-67.
Sloterdijk, Peter (2004). Spharen 1//: Schtiwne. Berlin: Suhrkamp.
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty (1988). "Can the Subaltern Speak?" in Cary Nelson and
Lawrence Grossberg (eds), Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture. Bloomington:
Indiana University Press; 271-313.
Index 1 21 5
education. See pedagogy Foucault, Michel
Egyptian revolution (2011) and Arab and Butler, 99-100, 187nlO
Spring, 7-9, 173n7, 173n9, on critique, 44, 124, 154-55
173nnll-12, 177n32, 177n33 on dispositif, 125
emancipation, 5, 54, 146, 147-49, 157, and liberalism, 173n14
167,168-69,188n15 and normative grounds, 44, 179n6,
equality 194n22
in anarchism, 67, 77, 78, 79, 80, 82, and ontology, 175n27
83-84, 196n34 and polemics, 175n23
and critique, 36, 150--52, 196n34 and police, 42, 70, 76, 183n2
dialectical account of, 50, 53, and queer theory, 198n5
83-85 Rancière's affinities with, 42,69--70,
and hope, 150 175nn23-24,194n22
in the liberaI tradition, 13,25-27, °
on subject formation, 17, 89, 98-1 1,
28-29,159,161, 177nn34-35, 187nlO, 188nl1, 188n13
178n39,198n4 Frankfurt School, 124, 155, 191n5
and May '68,24,29, 117, 150
and normative grounds, 13,26-27, gay and lesbian politics. See queer
63-64,80-81,85,150-52 politics: distinct from identity
and ontology, 25-27, 29, 80-81, 85 politics
and pedagogy, 4,30-31, 151--52, Gender Trouble (Butler), 160-62, 198n5,
196n34 199n7
and subjectivation, 29-30, 43
verification of, 10,25, 27-30, 63-64, Habermas, Jürgen
66,80,119,150--52 on critique, 124, 126, 154
ethics, 18, 107, 175n25, 191n4 on language, 90, 187n9
event and "liberal democracy," 11-12,
in Deleuze, 25 173n15,185n17
Egyptian revolution (2011) and Arab on normative grounds, 80, 194n22
Spring as, 7-9, 177n32 Hatred of Democracy (Rancière), 74, 75,
in Foucault, 177n33 183n7
and history, 21, 24-25 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 40, 50,
in liberalism, 25, 178n39 57, 128
May '68 as, 24, 177n32 See also dialectics
politics as rare, 8, 28, 66, 121, 141, Heidegger, Martin, 106, 111
168, 177n32 heteronormativity, 160--61, 165-66,
Revolutions of 1848 as, 178n39 167-68, 199n7, 199n12
and surprise, 5, 8, 173nlO hierarchy. See police
See also history; surprise; temporality history
excess of words. See literarity and critique of capitalism, 132-33,
explication. See pedagogy; stultification 155-56, 1961137
and event, 5, 8, 23-25, 1771133
feminism, 160-62, 198n6 and Foucault, 177n33
Feuerbach, Ludwig, 128, 130-32 as location, 23, 25, 31--32
Flesh ofWords, The (Rancière), 115, and ontology, 19,21,45
190n24 of Rancière's publications in
For Marx (Althusser), 128-29 translation, 21-23
Index 1 21 7
liberalism non-anthropocentric view of language
and deliberative democracy, 11-12, in, 89-90, 108-13, 120, 188n16,
173n15,185n17 189n19
democratic poli tics distinguished from, Rancière's criticisms of, 175n25,
10-14,17,159,160,166,168, 188n15,189nn17-18
173nnl4-15, 174nn17-18, 174n20,
185n17 Manicheanism. See impurity of politics;
doctrinal, 172n5, 178n39 pu rit Y of politics
and equality, 13,25-27,28-29, 159, Marchart, Oliver, 51-52, 56, 179n2,
161, 177nn34-35, 178n39, 198n4 180nl0, 180n17, 181nn19-20
and event, 25, 178n39 Markell, Patchen, 19,46, 180n7
and gay and lesbian identity, 159-65 Marx, Karl
passim and anthropologism, 107, 128-33,
and literarity, 90, 117 191n4,192n11
neoliberalism distinguished from, 172n5 Marxism vs. works of, 171n1,
as police order, 10-11, 14,29,67, 172n5 192nn8-9
political subjects in, 16--17,26,29, as political philosopher, 39, 77,
100, 102--3 194n21
and queer politics, 37, 159-68 passim, and social order, 65
197n2, 199n8 See also critical theory
and revolution, 178n39 Marxism
and surprise, 6-·8, 103, 172n4 and anthropocentrism, 191 n4
See also consensus; Habermas; Hobbes; hopein,63
identity; interests and interest group "the poor" in, 5, 17, 100, 192n8
politics; Locke; Rawls struggle in, 5, 85-86
literarity See also Althusser; critical theory
and anthropocentrism, 112--13 mastery,4, 13,24,30-31, 111, 146, 150,
and Butler, 195n30 171n1,175n23
exceedslanguage, 186n1 See also pedagogy
genealogy of the concept, 113-14, May '68,23-25,29,71,117,150,
189n20, 189n22, 190n24 177n32, 178n39, 199n8
and impure politics, 41,63, 182n28 May '68 and its Afterlives (Ross), 23-24,
and liberalism, 90, 117 29
and literature, 91, 114-15, 189n22, May, Todd, 34,45,67-68, 75-87, 179n2,
190n23, 190n26 183n2, 184nn8-9, 184nn12-13,
and partage du sensible, 115-16, 169, 185n14-15, 196n34
195n30 McClure, Kirstie, 178n 1
and pedagogy, 168--69 metaphysics. See ontology
and police orders, 88, 113, 121 metapolitics, 127, 136-39, 140-41,
and subjectivation, 114-21 184n8, 194n21
as untimely, 117, 120-21 See also political philosophy
See also language "Mis ad ventures of Critical Thinking,
Locke, John, 6, 17,26-27, 172n5, The" (Rancière), 127, 142, 144-49,
174n19, 177n34, 178n39 194n25
See also liberalism miscount
logos. Seelanguage and Arendtian framework, 47
Lyotard, Jean-François consensus as suppression of, 73
Index 1 21 9
Plato as pure category, 34, 62, 67-68
anthropologism of, 107 and queer politics, 165
on democracy, 59, 74, 135, 163 and subjectivation, 43, 101, 117-21
on language, 113--14, 115-17, 189n21, supplement excluded by, 40-41,
190nn25-26 43, 72
and pedagogy, 196n34 Zizek's interpretation of, 52
as political philosopher, 39, 76-77, See alsa poli tics of the police
135-37, 192n8, 193n18, 194n20 political, the
pluralism. See interests and interest group as doubling, 58-63, 181n22
politics and ontology, 174n 17
polemicization opposed to police and politics in
and critical theory, 124-25, 175n23 Rancière's sense, 52, 180nlO
distinct from argumentation, politics as Rancière's term for, 51
176-77n31 Rancière's use of the term, 53-56,
and intelligibility, 123 59-60
and untimeliness, 191 n6 in Schmitt, 174n 17
police as theme in twentieth-century political
and Althusser, 24, 65, 72, 183n5 thought, 51-52
and anarchism, 7 S.-84 as "third term" in Rancière's thought,
and anthropologism, 107 32-33,40-41,45,50,53-62,
better and worse forms of, 10, 72, 83--85, 180n12, 180n17, 181n20,
200n14 181n22, 181n25
concept as intervention, 73-75, 139, political difference. See Marchart;
183-84n7 political, the
consensus as, 33, 44, 67, 68, 73-75 political philosophy, 39-40, 61, 74,
and critical theory, 154, 183n6, 196n36 76-77,88,127,134-42,179n2,
in Foucault, 42, 70, 76, 183n2 180n7, 182n28, 184n8, 192n8,
genealogy of the term, 183n7 193n18,194n19
as hierarchieal order, 28, 33-34, See alsa arehipolities; parapolities;
42-43,65-66,179n4 metapolities; and specifie authars
irreducible to law enforeement, 42, politieal subjects
70-71 in Arendt, 17
liberalism as, 10-11, 14,29,67, 172n5 and feminism, 160-62, 198n6
and literarity, 88, 113,117-19,121 in Foueauldian aecounts, 17
and May '68, 24 in liberal theory, 16-17, 26, 29, 100,
as neutral term, 72, 83 102--3
and ontology, 65-66 in Marxist theories, 5, 17, 100, 192n8
and "ordinary polities," 14,39,41,68- and ontology, 181n2l
69,174n2l politieal the ory
as partage du sensible, 42,60,70-72, and politicians, 197n3
76, 102-3, 183n6, 183-84n7 Rancière's resistance to, 3--5, 14,32,
and polemicization, 176-77n31 63-64, 182n29
and politieal philosophy, 134-36 reception of Rancière in discipline of,
politics as dismption of, 8-9, 28, 38, 38,41-42,44-57,74
43,86-87 See alsa specifie authars
polities blended with, 49-50, 61-64, Palitical Thaught af Jacques Rancière,
65,80,82,84-85 The (May), 75-84, 184n14-15
Index 1 221
social body/formation/order/whole. See supplement, 40-41, 43,58-63, 72,
police 182n26, 183n3
social science, 6-8, 139, 172n4, 172n6, See also impurity of politics; paradox
173n8,192nlO surprise
Socrates in Arendt, 5, 39, 46, 172n3
and critique, 148, 156, 196n34 and event, 5-8, 9, 173nlO
and political philosophy, 39, 135, 137, and intelligibility, 172-73n6
190n25, 193n18 and liberalism, 6-8, 103, 172n4
speech. See language; phonë/logos and revolution, 7, 173n9, 173n Il
distinction and social science, 6-8, 172n4, 172n6,
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty, 199n8 173nlO
state of nature, 6, 16-17,27, 172n5,
177n34 Tanke, Joseph, 71, 171-,-72n2, 180n12,
Strauss, Leo, 39, 186-87n6 188n13
struggle, 5, 29, 81, 83, 85-86, 182n30 teaching. See pedagogy
stultification temporality, 8, 15-17,31-32
and critique, 151-52, 172n4, 196n34 See also event; history; untimeliness
and emancipation, 148, 157, 168 "Ten Theses on Politics" (Rancière), 42,
as interpretive challenge, 30-31, 74,96-97, 183n5, 183n7
171-72nnl-2 See also translation: of "Dix theses sur
and police, 66 la politique"
See also pedagogy Thomson, Alex, 85, 184n11, 184n16
subject. See political subjects; torsion
subj ecti vation as queering, 165
subjectivation as reading practice, 58, 88-89, 95, 125,
in Butler, 99-100, 162, 187nlO 158, 199n11
compared with other terms for subject wrong as, 57-58, 88, 184n12
formation, 98-101 translation
as disidentification, 49, 104, 120, of assujettissement, 89,99-101,
193n16 187nlO
and equality, 29-30, 43 and counter-translation, 113-14
in Foucault, 89, 98-101, 187nlO, of dispositif, 125-26, 195n28
188n11,188n13 of "Dix thèses sur la politique," 53,
and identity, 101, 104, 112, 119-20, 181-82n25
164-65, 193n16, 199n10 history of Rancière's publications in,
andlanguage,34-35,104-5 21-23,41
and literarity, 117-21 ofindice, 95, 187n8
and ontology, 20 of indiquer, 92-95
and partage du sensible, 102-3 of la mésentente (concept), 154
and police orders, 43,101,117-21 of La mésentente (Rancière), 35,
and queer politics, 159-60, 162-63, 53-54,91-95,100-1, 181n25,
164 186n4, 188-89n16
translation of, 89,98-101, 188nlO, of [apolitique, 51-54, 58, 180n16,
188n13 180n9, 181n2~ 181n25
See also political subjects; pOOl', the; of le politique, 51-63, 58, 180n16,
untimeliness 180n9, 181n22, 181n25
Index 1 223