Evolution and The Problem of Other Minds
Evolution and The Problem of Other Minds
discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/261743198
CITATIONS READS
16 158
1 author:
Elliott Sober
University of Wisconsin–Madison
246 PUBLICATIONS 9,455 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
Replies to Kristin Andrews's, Gordon Belot's, and Patrick Forber's reviews of Ockham's Razors View
project
All content following this page was uploaded by Elliott Sober on 17 July 2016.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal
of Philosophy.
http://www.jstor.org
________________________________+-
-+l 0
,+- 0 +
*My thanks to Colin Allen, Martin Barrett, Marc Bekoff, Tom Bontly, Nancy Cart-
wright, James Crow, Frans De Waal, Ellely Eells, Mehmet Elgin, Berent Encs,Branden
Fitelson, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Daniel Hausman, George Kampis, Richard Lewontin,
Barny Loewer, David Papineau, Daniel Povinelli, Lariy Shapiro, and Alan Sidelle for
useful comments. I also have benefitted from discussing this paper at London School
of Economics and Political Science, at University of Illinois/Chicago, at Caltech, at
E6t6s University, at the University of Vienna, and at Northern Illinois University.
I This terminology is from Larry Shapiro, "Presence of Mind," in Valerie Gray
Hardcastle, ed., Biology Meets Psychology: Constraints, Connections, and Conjectures
(Cambridge: MIT, 1999), pp. 133-50.
Self Other
Behavior B B
Self to Behavior
Other to Mind
Mind M M?
Figure 1
mental problem which I think forms the core of the problem of other
minds, and this is the problem which I want to address here.2
I
Although the problem of other minds usually begins with an intro-
spective grasp of one's own mental state, it can be detached from that
setting and formulated more generally as a problem about "extrap-
olation." Thus, we might begin with the assumption that human
beings produce certain behaviors because they occupy particular
mental states and ask whether this licenses the conclusion that mem-
bers of other species that exhibit the behavior do so for the same
reason. None of us knows just by introspection, however, that all
human beings who produce a given behavior do so because they
occupy some particular mental state. In fact, this formulation of the
problem of other minds, in which it is detached from the concept of
introspection, is usually what leads philosophers to conclude that
inferences about other minds from one's own case are weak. The fact
that I own a purple bow tie should not lead me to conclude that you
do, too. This point about bow ties is supposed to carry over to the fact
that I have a mind and occupy various mental states. I know that I
own a purple bow tie, but not by introspection.3
Discussion of the problem of other minds in philosophy seems to have
died down (if not out) around thirty years ago.4 Before then, it was
discussed as an instance of "analogical"or "inductive"reasoning and the
standard objection was that an inference about others based on your
own situation is an extrapolation from too small a sample. This problem
does not disappear merely by thinking of introspective experience as
that it had become so closely connected with questions about logical behaviorism.
When logical behaviorism went out of fashion, so did the problem of other minds.
Behaviorism was replaced by a version of mentalism that emphasized the idea that
third-person mentalistic hypotheses are to be judged, like other scientific hypoth-
eses, on the basis of their ability to explain and predict. In consequence, the
Self-to-Other problem was replaced by the behavior-to-mind problem.
368 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
furnishing you with thousands of data points. The fact remains that they
all were drawn from the same urn-your own mind. How can sampling
from one urn help you infer the composition of another?
When the problem is formulated in this way, it becomes pretty clear
that what is needed is some basic guidance about inductive inference.
The mental content of Self-to-Otherinference is not what makes it prob-
lematic, but the fact that it involves extrapolation. Some extrapolations
make sense while others do not. It seems sensible to say that thirst makes
other people drink water, based on the fact that this is usually why I
drink. Yet it seems silly to say that other folks walk down State Street at
lunchtime because they crave spicy food, based just on the fact that this
is what sets me strolling. By the same token, it seems sensible to attribute
belly buttons to others, based on my own navel gazing. Yet it seems sillyto
universalizethe fact that I happen to own a purple bow tie. What gives?
The first step toward answering this question started to emerge in
the 1960s, not in philosophy of mind, but in philosophy of science.
There is a general point about confirmation that we need to take to
heart: observations provide evidence for or against a hypothesis only
in the context of a set of background assumptions. If the observations
do not deductively entail that the hypothesis of interest is true, or that
it is false, then there is no saying whether the observations confirm or
disconfirm, until further assumptions are put on the table. This may
sound like the Duhem/Quine thesis, but that way of thinking about
the present point is somewhat misleading, since Pierre Duhem5 and
W. V. Quine6 discussed deductive, not probabilistic, connections of
hypotheses to observations. If we want a person to pin this thesis to,
it should be I. J. Good.7 Good made this point forceftlly in connec-
tion with Carl Hempel's8 formulation of the ravens paradox. Hempel
thought it was clear that black ravens and white shoes both confirm
the generalization that all ravens are black. The question that inter-
ested him was why one should think that black ravens provide stron-
ger confirmation than white shoes. Good responded by showing that
empirical background knowledge can have the consequence that
5 In The Aim and Structureof Physical Theory (Princeton: University Press, 1914/
19r.4).
6 In "Two Dogmas of Empiricism," in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge:
9 In fact, there are many important circumstances in which the evidence relation
must be four-placed-a set of observations favors one hypothesis over another,
relative to a set of background assumptions. This is the proper format for likelihood
inference; see Richard M. Royall, Statistical Evidence: A LikelihoodParadigm (Boca
Raton: Chapman and Hall/CRC, 1997), and my "Testability," Proceedingsand Ad-
dressesof the AmericanPhilosophicalAssociation, LXXIII (1999): 47-76; the latter is also
available at the following URL-http://philosophy.wisc.edu/sober.
10 I am not going to discuss in this paper what it means for two individuals to
exhibit "the same behavior," but I shall make two comments. First, there is no
requirement that they exhibit the same muscular movements; on this point, see
Berent Encs, "Units of Behavior," Philosophyof Science,LXII (1995): 523-42. Second,
however behaviors are individuated, it is important that one be able to say that two
individuals share a behavioral trait without already knowing what the proximate
370 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
II
The problem of other minds has been and continues to be important in
psychology (actually,in comparative psychology), except that there it is
formulated in the first-personplural. Suppose that when human beings
perform behavior B, we usually or alwaysdo so because we have mental
property M. When we observe behavior B in another species, should we
take the human case to count as evidence that this species also has
mental property M? For this problem to be nontrivial, we assume that
there is at least one alternativeinternal mechanism, A, which also could
lead organisms to produce the behavior. Is the fact that humans have M
evidence that this other species has M rather than A?
Discussion of this problem in comparative psychology has long
been dominated by the fear of naive anthropomorphism.11 This
attitude was crystalized by C. Lloyd Morgan,12 who suggested that, if
we can explain a nonhuman organism's behavior by attributing to it
a "higher" mental faculty, or by assigning it a "lower"mental faculty,
then we should prefer the latter explanation. Morgan's successors
embraced this "canon" because of its prophylactic qualities-it re-
duces the chance of a certain type of error. It is important to
recognize, however, that there are twotypes of error that might occur
in this situation:
O lacks M O has M
Morgan's canon does reduce the chance of type-1 error, but that is
not enough to justify the canon. By the same token, a principle that
encouraged anthropomorphism would reduce the chance of type-2
error, but that would not justify this liberal principle, either.
13
For discussion, see my "Morgan's Canon," in Colin Allen and Denise Dellarosa
Cummins, eds., The Evolution of Mind (New York: Oxford, 1998), pp. 224-42.
14
See, for example, Niles Eldredge and Joel Cracraft, PhylogeneticPatterns and the
EvolutionaryProcess (New York: Columbia, 1980).
372 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
characters w w -w w w -w
taxa Sparrows Robin Crocs Sparrows Robin Crocs
ancestralcharacterstate -w -w
(SR)C S(RC)
Figure 2
15
Cladistic parsimony does not entail that all similarities are evidence of common
ancestry. For example, the two hypotheses depicted in Figure 2 would be equally
parsimonious if wings were ancestral rather than derived. For discussion, see my
Reconstructingthe Past: Parsimony,Evolution, and Inference(Cambridge: MIT, 1988).
16 Figure 3 illustrates a pattern of inference that is important in the study of
human evolution. Why should features that are shared among current hunter-
gatherer societies be thought to provide an indication of the ancestral human
condition? After all, we cannot assume that hunter gatherers are "living fossils."
The reason the inference makes sense is that current hunter gatherers are very
distantly related to each other; this is what makes any similarities they may exhibit
relevant to estimating the character state of the most recent common ancestor
shared by all human lineages.
EVOLUTION AND THE PROBLEM OF OTHER MINDS 373
Figure 3
]7 We might have evidence that not-B is the ancestral character state by looking
at a number of further individuals, besides Self and Other, who provide relevant
"out-groups," as in Figure 3.
18 Notice that, if no assumption is made about the character state at the root of
the tree, (SAME) is more parsimonious. But if A is the ancestral character state,
(SAME) and (DIFF) are equally parsimonious.
19 In "Complementary Methods and Convergent Evidence in the Study of Primate
Social Cognition," Behaviour, cxviii (1991): 297-320, and in "Anthropomorphism
and Anthropodenial: Consistency in Our Thinking about Humans and Other
Animals," Philosophical Topics (forthcoming).
374 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
not-B not-B
(SAME) (DIFF)
Figure 4
Self Other
B [a not-B - ] B
M neitherM norA ?
Figure 5
-B, PO -B, PO
(SAME) (DIFF)
Figure 6
21
See the essays collected in Peter Carruthers and Peter K. Smith, eds., Theoriesof
Theoriesof Mind (New York: Cambridge, 1995), and C. M. Heyes, "Theory of Mind
in Nonhuman Primates," Behavioral and Brain Sciences,XXI (1998): 101-48.
EVOLUTION AND THE PROBLEM OF OTHER MINDS 377
(SAME) (DIFF)
Figure7
22
Some of the most interesting experiments on whether chimps have a theory of
mind have been carried out by Daniel Povinelli; he looks for a B2 and finds that it
is absent. I discuss his "knower/guesser" experiment in "Black Box Inference."
More recently, Povinelli and Steve Gambrone have argued that "a novel psycholog-
ical system for generating and sustaining higher-order representations, including
the representation of other minds, may have evolved in the human lineage without
radically altering our basic behavior patterns [italics mine]"-see their "Inferring
Other Minds: Failure of the Argument by Analogy," Philosophical Topics (forthcom-
ing). The words I have italicized in this quotation are important; the authors do not
deny that there are behavioral differences between present day human beings and
chimps that reflect the fact that the former have a theory of mind while the latter
do not. Their suggestion is that the initial appearanceof second-ordering intention-
ality may have had little or no immediate effect on behavior, but may have been a
building blockthat allowed more substantial behavioral divergence to occur later.
23 Suppose there is a behavior that human beings sometimes produce by using
find behaviors that are probableif subjects have a theory of mind but improbableif they
have first-order intentionality only. The behavior need not be impossiblein the
absence of a theory of mind.
EVOLUTION AND THE PROBLEM OF OTHER MINDS 379
This proposition says that Self and Other are correlated (noninde-
pendent) with respect to the traits M and A. It also says that there is
a likelihood justification for anthropomorphism.29 The observation
that Self has M is rendered more probable by the hypothesis that
Other has M than by the hypothesis that Other has A. Such differ-
ences in likelihood are generally taken to indicate a difference in
support-the observation favors the first hypothesis over the sec-
ond.30
The likelihood concept also throws light on De Waal's proviso-
that parsimonious anthropomorphism is on firmer ground for our
near relatives than it is for those individuals to whom we are related
more distantly. We may translate this into the claim that the two
influenced by the environment. And a trait can be genetically determined and still
not be heritable; the traits male (XY) and female (XX) provide examples.
29 Hybrids aside, two species have a unique species that is their most recent
common ancestor. Sexually reproducing individuals are not like this, however.
Full-sibs have two parents as their most recent common ancestors. And first cousins
usually overlap only partially in the set of ancestors they have two generations back;
each has four grandparents, but (usually) only two of them are shared. How, then,
does the Reichenbachian picture of common causes apply to human genealogies?
The simplest way to connect them is to think of the common causes as sets of
individuals, not as singletons. Thus, two full-sibs have the same parental pair as a
common cause. And two first cousins can be thought of as tracing back to a set of
six individuals; this is the set of all their grandparents, including the ones they do
not share. Standard Mendelian genetics assures us that the state of this set screens
off one cousin's genotype from the other's. Of course, this set is not limited to the
two cousins' commnon ancestors. It can be shown that the common ancestors do
screen off, however, since the ancestors in the set who are not shared influence one
cousin's genotype but not the other's; see my and Martin Barrett's "Conjunctive
Forks and Temporally Asymmetric Inference," AustralasianJournal of Philosophy,LXX
(1992): 1-23.
30 See Royall; and my "Testability."
EVOLUTION AND THE PROBLEM OF OTHER MINDS 381
X Y Z
a b
Figure 8
31I hope it is clear that this claim does not underwrite racist, nationalist, or
species-istconclusions. The argument does not provide a reason for denying that
individualsoutside one's own "group"have minds. For one thing, it is a mistaketo
think of one's self as belonging to just one group; each organism belongs to
multiple, nested groups. For another, the argument presented here does not
concern acceptance or rejection. And, finally, it is important to remember that
Self-to-Otherinference is not the only pathwayby which we form beliefs about the
internal statesof others. There is, in addition, the possibilityof strictlythird-person
behavior-to-mindinference. Much of our confidence concerning the mental states
of others presumablyrests on this second sort of inference. The point I am making
about the incremental Self-to-Other problem is that the increment provided by
knowledge of Self falls off as genealogical relatednessbecomes more distant.
382 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
IV
M
Pi
P2
A
Figure 9
that I have the flu can be evidence that Other does, too, if the two of
us live in the same community.
I list these alternatives, not because they apply with equal plausi-
bility to the problem of other minds, but to give an indication of the
range of alternatives which needs to be considered. Genealogical
relatedness is only an example; the fundamental question is whether
there are common causes impinging on Self and Other that induce
the correlation described in (P). If there are, then there will be a
likelihood justification for extrapolating from Self to Other.34
V
What, exactly, does cladistic parsimony and its likelihood analysis tell
us about the problem of other minds? When I cry out, wince, and
remove my body from an object inflicting tissue damage, this is
(usually) because I am experiencing pain. When other organisms
(human or not) produce the same set of behaviors, is this evidence
that they feel pain? This hypothesis about Other is more parsimoni-
ous (if the behaviors are homologous and there are no known
relevant neurophysiological differences), and it is more likely (if
Reichenbachian assumptions about common causes apply). Does
that completely solve the problem of other minds, or does there
remain a residue of puzzlement?
One thing that is missing from this analysis is an answer to the
question-how much evidence does the introspected state of Self
provide about the conjectured state of Other? I have noted that the
likelihoods in proposition (P) become more different as Self and
not essential for the parsimony or likelihood arguments I have presented. Suppose
that Mand A are epiphenomenalconsequencesof the physical states P1 and P2, and are
related to the behavior B as shown in Figure 9. If P1 suffices for M and B while P2
suffices for B and A, parsimony and likelihood are relevant to deciding whether M/I
or A should be attributed to Other, given that Self has M.
384 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
36
To be sure, it is possible to tell whether the behavior B is heritable (since B is
observable), but the heritability of B is neither necessary nor sufficient for the
heritability of M and A. I thank Branden Fitelson and Richard Lewontin for helping
me clarify this point.