The Subjunctive in That Clause
The Subjunctive in That Clause
Such modal operators not only introduce a set of alternatives, but also order them function of how
close they come to the envisaged ideals. Modal judgements of these type imply not only a modal
base (a set of alternative worlds), but also an ordering source, i.e., a set of principles /
propositions imposing an ordering among the considered alternatives. Ordering sources capture
the observation that the understanding of a modalised sentence often implies the use of idealised
states of affairs, describing the world as it should be (according to the law, according to the
normal course of events, according to what is desirable, etc.). An ordering source, which is also a
set of propositions describing the ideal, orders the worlds in the modal base according to the
degree to which they realise the ideal described by the ordering source itself. Ordering sources
may be explicitly introduced by such phrases as, in view of what is normal, according to the law,
etc. Worlds in the modal base are ordered according to how many propositions in the ordering
source (in the ideal) they realise, i.e., how close they get to the ideal.
Verbs and other operators which have a stronger or weaker normative component
invariably imply a non-realistic modal base, in the sense that we do not require that there should
be any intersection between the worlds determined by the conversational contexts and these
ideals.
Two semantic parameters are essential in the analysis of modality: the modal base and
the ordering source (cf. Kratzer (1981), (1991)). A modal base specifies the world(s) in which the
proposition in the scope of the modal is evaluated. The worlds in the modal base are possibly
ordered by the ideals in the ordering source, if the respective modality implies one. The joint
effect of the modal base and the ordering source is to force the evaluation of the modalised
proposition in those worlds of the modal base that better realise the given ideal or norm.
The modality of the sentence signals the context of evaluation of the modalized
proposition, a set of propositions with respect to which the speaker chooses to consider a
particular proposition. In that sense, modality signals a particular attitude of the speaker. The
view of modality proposed above comes very close to that proposed by Jespersen (1924), namely
that mood describes a characteristic of sentence use. More precisely, it concerns the speaker's
commitment about the truth of the sentence in the actual world. It is the notion of speaker
commitment that was formalised in terms of the semantic environment where a sentence is to be
evaluated.
(3) non-null > non-realistic > weakly realistic > realistic > totally realistic ordering base.
Generally the occurrence of the subjunctive in a sentence is the effect of the (implicit
or explicit) presence of a modal operators. Modal operators may be lexical categories (verbs,
adjectives, nouns) or they may be functional categories, such as negation.
As a result, there is a distinction between lexically licensed subjunctive and operator licensed
subjunctive. Since we are interested in mood choice in subordinate clauses, we shall mostly be
concerned with the lexically licensed subjunctive, since it is the main verb which is the modal
operator chiefly responsible for the selection of a particular modal base and ordering source,
determining the context of evaluation for the subordinate clause.
3.1. Lexical licensers of modality. To understand why the subjunctive and the indicative
appear where they do, a classification of the subordinate contexts is needed, function of the
semantics of the main verbs. The semantic mechanism is, roughly, the following: the modal
operator, i.e., the main verb, determines the context of evaluation, and the context of evaluation is
signalled by the choice of grammatical mood (indicative vs. subjunctive). Several semantic
features which may characterise verbal concepts prove relevant in classifying evaluation contexts
and thus in determining mood choice.
Farkas (1982) offers an insightful characterization of the difference between verb like
believe, hope which use the indicative, even though they express modal concepts, and verbs like
desire, wish, which use the subjunctive. Verbs like believe, hope are labelled weak intensional.
They may be said to introduce just one alternative to the context-world, that possible
situation/world where the proposition believed or hoped for is true. Since normativity (= an
ordering source) is not involved, it is not necessary to introduce an ordering on possible worlds,
so one alternative course of affairs is sufficient. On the other hand, verbs like desire, wish, prefer
are strong intensional verbs. They introduce ideals and thus impose an ordering on the alternative
courses of affairs. Talk in terms of ordering implies the existence of more than on possible world.
Weak intensional verbs often require the indicative in their complement, strong intensional verbs
require the subjunctive.
Let us now examine the distribution of the Indicative and the Subjunctive in English,
starting from contexts that select only the indicative or only the subjunctive and continuing with
verbs that allow dual mood selection.
b) Expectedly, clauses embedded under assertive verbs, i.e., clauses whose complements
make assertions (truth claims) also select the indicative. These verbs are weak intensional. The
main verb introduces one world, in which the complement is evaluated. The intersection of this
world with the common background is non-null, so that the modal base is weakly realistic. The
ordering base is null. Using the terms of Farkas (1982), these verbs, even if they are modal
operators, are extensionally anchored, i.e. they introduce one world with respect to which the
complement is evaluated, and in which the complement clause is true.
In English, all assertive verbs (strong assertive, semi factive and weak assertive verbs)
select the indicative, since, as explained, they are weak intensional verbs, extensionally anchored.
(6) They have just reported that the enemy has been defeated. (strong assertive verb)
They claim that the enemy has been defeated.
(7) They have realized that they are defeated. (semi-factive verb)
They have discovered that they have been defeated.
(8) They believe that they will win. (weak assertive verb)
The indicative appears to be the mood of assertion (see Quirk e.a. (1972)). Several
characteristics follow from this characterization. The indicative is factual, descriptive, presenting
the world "as it is". Indicative propositions are typical for informative, referential discourse.
Indicative tenses are deictic, directly or indirectly placing an event in real time, as discussed
above.
Hope, an indicative selector, differs from desire. It is possible to hope only as long as one
still believes there is a chance of satisfaction. In other words, the modal base of hope intersects
with the common ground, with what is known to be possible in the real world. Hope requires a
weakly realistic modal basis and this explains why the indicative rather than the subjunctive is
used. On the other hand, the verb desire naturally calls for the subjunctive. One cannot desire a
type of situation unless one believes both that the situation does not exist in the real world (i.e.,
the modal base is non-realistic) and that it still could come to exist. The desired situation thus
must be future. Intuitively, desires are for states of affairs that are believed to be unrealized as of
yet, which are future, but undetermined as to whether they will be actualized (cf. (10a), and
(10b)). A nonrealistic modal base and an ordering source are clearly present (the 'ought to do'
component of the subjunctive). This explains why the subjunctive is compatible with desire, but
not with hope.
The subjunctive always signals the presence of norms and ideals, so that the ordering
base is non-null and the modal base is non-realistic. The verbs which require the subjunctive are
strong intensional verbs, since, as already explained, they need to introduce a set of (ideally
ordered) worlds, with respect to which the complement clause is evaluated.
The subjunctive is normative, prescriptive, essentially involved in the choice and
evaluation of human agency. The subjunctive "tenses" are not deictic. They do not place an event
in real time. The Past Subjunctive, merely expresses anteriority with respect to a reference
expressed in the main clause.
(12) ask, beg, advise, demand, decree, decide, instruct, prohibit, forbid, interdict, recommend,
rule, command, order, give orders, suggest, etc.
(13) a. She demanded that I should stay with her. b. God forbid that you should take any road, but
one where you will find and give happiness. c. The carrier proposed that my pocket
handkerchief should be spread upon the horse's back to dry. d. Now they ask that this sordid
episode be sealed from public knowledge.
(14) a. We ask that this food be blessed. (LG)
b. The medicine man then ordered that there should be no mourning for the dead child.
(LG)
(15) a. He demands that he be told everything.
b. It is ordained in heaven that women should work in the home.
These sentences report exercitive acts, acts whose point is to bring about the fulfilment of
some volitional act denoted by the complement clause and carried out by an explicit or implicit
Agent in the subordinate clause. There are a number of constraints on the propositional content of
the complement clause. The verb in the complement clause should be non-stative, and should
denote a volitional, controllable act of an Agent. The time sphere of the complement is future.
These constraints explain why sentences (16b, c) are ungrammatical:
The subjunctive is also required after exercitive verbs of permission: allow, authorize,
suffer, permit, etc. In this case, in the alternative courses of affairs introduced by the main verb,
the volitional act denoted by the subordinate act is not prevented from occurring:
(18) a. Do you permit that I should smoke in here? b. The committee allowed that the bridge
should be restored. c. The doctor allowed that John should drink a glass of whisky every
evening.
Exercitive verbs of command and permission very clearly illustrate the normative,
prescriptive dimension of the subjunctive. There are also a few modal adjectives which are non-
factive, even though they are hardly emotive, that is they can hardly be said to express an
emotional reaction: (un)necessary, impossible, imperative, likely, unlikely, possible. They are
nearly always used with the subjunctive.
b. A second group of verbs that select the subjunctive, often to the exclusion of the
indicative, are volitional verbs, expressing volition, intention, planning or activity intended to
prepare the fulfilment of some desirable state of affairs. There are several verbs and adjectives in
this class:
(21) a. verbs: want, wish, intend, prefer, desire, arrange, see to, etc.;
b. adjectives: eager, anxious, willing, reluctant, can't stand, can't bear, etc.
(22) a. I want / am anxious that he should get the job. b. They arranged that we should be met at
the station. c. Who will see to it that things should turn out well?
Volitional verbs, like exercitive verbs may be described as strong intensional verbs. They
introduce a set of alternative worlds, ordered function of the ideal of what is wanted, intended,
prepared, etc. The complement clause is evaluated with respect to these alternatives, not with
respect to the real world. The normative, ideal semantic component is again clear, which is why
volitional verbs select the subjunctive cross-linguistically.(Giorgi & Pianesi (1997)).
(23) agree, tell, say, confess, declare, explain, suggest, inform, point out, write, telephone,
convince, persuade, repeat, remark, state, warn, etc.
When the complement clause is in the indicative, these verbs are used as (strong)
assertive verbs, the complement clause makes an assertion, and there are no constraints on the
propositional content of the complement clause. It is interpreted in a weakly realistic background,
since the verb is extensionally anchored. This use of the verbs is the one described in 3.1. above
When they are used with the subjunctive, they are interpreted as exercitive verbs. Since
they become exercitive verbs, in this use, they observe all the constraints mentioned above for
exercitive verbs: The complement clause should denote a volitional act, controlled by an Agent. If
there is a direct or indirect object, it is either coreferential with the Agent in the subordinate
clause, or at least understood as responsible for fulfilment of the action in the complement clause.
These differences are clearly brought out by pairs of examples like the following:
(26) a. Bill told Suzy that she should go to the dentist's. b) Mother convinced me that I should
keep indoors another day. c. The secretary informed the students that they should take the
final test on the 25th of May.
Verbs of communication exhibit this dual interpretation in many languages, among which
Romanian. Recently Quer (1998), discussing the phenomenon of "double mood selection", has
proposed that the semantic structure of the subjunctive-taking verb is more complex than of the
indicative-taking verb. Quer starts from the empirical remark that in many languages, if causative
verbs accept finite clauses at all, the complement of the causative verbs is in the subjunctive. The
caused event represents a distinct future situation in comparison with the causing situation. And it
is this introduction of a new situation which explains why causative verbs that embed finite
clauses (may) use the subjunctive. (Romanian is a case in point ( cf. a face pe cine săfacăceva)).
In English, the verb cause might perhaps illustrate this, since most causative verbs are infinitive
or gerund takers.
(27) The doctor caused it that the patient should be operated on.
Quer's proposal (1998: 58) is that the subjunctive taking verbs involves a more complex
semantic structure: the verb of communication does not directly take the subjunctive complement,
but is co-ordinated with another VP headed by CAUSE, a verb which selects the subjunctive. The
verb of communication merely expresses a manner of causing. In other words a sentence like (28) is
roughly 'equivalent with' (29):
(28) The doctor said that the patient should be operated on.
(29) The doctor caused it that the patient should be operated on by saying it.
The presence of the CAUSE component explains the exercitive meaning and the selection
of the subjunctive.
b) Evaluative predicates/ emotive predicates represent another class of predicates that
exhibit double mood selection in English. Emotive predicates fall into several classes:
b1) Non-factive emotives. This semantic class includes a large number of adjectives that
take subject clauses, and express evaluative modalities: good, bad, right, wrong, best, better,
essential, legal, moral, natural, normal, urgent, vital, inconvenient, troublesome, unlikely, amazing,
anomalous, astonishing, awful, annoying, etc., natural, neat, nice, notable, noteworthy, okay,
(un)lucky, paradoxical, peculiar, preferable, ridiculous, silly, untypical, unfair, understandable,
upsetting, wonderful. There is also a group of 'importance adjectives': advisable, critical, crucial,
desirable, essential, fitting, imperative, important, necessary, obligatory, vital
b2) Factive emotives fall into several syntactic classes: emotive factive adjectives: odd, tragic,
quaint, crazy, bizarre, amazing, surprising, bothersome, etc.; emotive, subject-clause taking verbs (=
psych verbs): amaze, alarm, surprise, bother, annoy, irritate, astound, disturb, etc.; transitive emotive
verbs: regret, resent, deplore, etc.
Interestingly, in English, all emotive predicates, factive and non-factive alike, exhibit
double mood selection. This possibility, which is attested cross-linguistically, is inherent in the
semantic make-up of evaluative predicates. The meaning of an emotive predicate may be
decomposed into a descriptive component and an evaluative, normative component (cf. Hare
(1952)).
Emotive predicates are descriptive by virtue of our knowledge of the adequate standards
of functioning or behaviour which entitle us to speak about 'a good deed', 'a right decision', 'a
good car'. In terms of the analysis adopted here, given their descriptive meaning, the
complements of evaluative predicates may always be interpreted against a weakly realistic
epistemic modal base, and are thus extensionally anchored predicates. Hence the use of the
indicative with evaluative predicates.
But these predicates also express normative concepts through the implicit commending or
condemning attitude that they express. When one commends or condemns anything, it is always
against standards and ideals, and one does so in order to guide choices (usually of action) of one's
own or of other people. In other words, these predicates may make reference to ideals and norms,
and when the subjunctive is used, normative judgements are made explicitly. Choice of the
subjunctive over the indicative stresses the prescriptive, normative component in the meaning of the
emotive predicates. The contrast can best be appreciated in pairs of the following type:
(33) a. It is sensible that the breeding animals receive the highest protection.
b. It is preferable that the marked cells should be identical in their behaviour to the
unmarked cells.
(34) a. It is essential that the two instruments should run parallel to the microscope stage.
b. It is vital that leaking water is avoided
c. It is important that it be well sealed from air leakage.
d. It is desirable that it be both lined and insulated.
c) Factives. English is a languages that allows the use of the subjunctive with factive-
emotive predicates regret, resent, odd, etc.), even though this appears to be an inconsistency.
Quer (1998: 94) comments that these predicates have two components in their meaning. On the
one hand, their complements are interpreted factively, i.e., they are presupposed to be true in the
real world; this makes them compatible with the indicative. On the other hand, emotive factive
predicates express reactions or emotions to situations, or relate situations to an implicit set of
normative criteria, and this makes them compatible with the subjunctive.
(35) a. It seemed to Mor a little quaint that she should refer to the boys as children. b. It is not
strange therefore that the Tudors should have been able to exercise a great influence. c. It
irritated Mor that his wife should combine a grievance about her frustrated gifts with a
lack of any attempt to concentrate. d. I'm ashamed that you should have me for a mother.
In order to better understand double mood selection with these verbs, one should notice, with
Quer (1998:95) "that factivity (in the sense of presupposed truth of the complement clause) is not an
inherent property of the lexical semantics of these predicates.", but depends on the contexts where
they are used. Their complements are indeed presupposed when the main predicate is in an episodic
tense (such as the Past Tense or the Present), but they are not presupposed in all the tenses or moods
of the verb. Notice the different interpretation of the complement clauses in the examples below.
Since the factive component can be suspended, one understands why these verbs allow a
modal normative reading, whose specific interpretation has long been noted by grammarians.
Quirk e.a. (1972) remarks that when the subjunctive is used with these verbs, what counts is not
that the complement is true, but that "it is imagined as true", that is, the complement is merely
possible. Rosenberg (1975) stresses that with emotive factives, the proposition often refers to
actual events only "due to a pragmatic principle of emotional reactions" which says that "people
react emotionally to states and events that exist, rather than to non-existent fictitious ones."
However, taking into accounts their own normative standards, people may express emotional
reactions on the strength of beliefs that something has happened, may happen, will happen and
they may be proved wrong in their beliefs.
(38) He regrets that that the little girl should be sick, but I know that the little pert is
shamming.
Thus in a sense the use of the subjunctive signals the absence of factivity, or rather it
signals lack of concern for what is actual. The judgement is evaluative, not descriptive. As aptly
expressed by Curme (1947) " even when the subjunctive is used of actual facts, it presents them
as conceptions of the mind, as general principles rather than facts."
3.5 Operator licensed subjunctives. In the examples discussed so far, the subjunctive has
been lexically licensed by the semantics of the main verb. The subjunctive may also be licensed
by other operators, such as negation, the question operator, etc. (cf. Quer (1998), Giorgi &
Pianesi (1997)) Thus in the example below, the subjunctive is triggered by negation, rather than
by the main verb, as shown by the difference between the affirmative sentence and its negative
counterpart:
(40) a. The dean does not believe that the students should deserve a prize, but I do.
b. ?The dean does not believe that the students should deserve a prize, and neither do I
(41) a. They do not believe that Godot should come.
b. They do not believe that Godot will come.
Quer comments that there is a difference between such pairs. When the indicative is used,
the presuppositions of the complement sentence normally become part of the common ground.
When the subjunctive is used, the presuppositions of the complement clause are not accepted as
common ground presuppositions. The use of the subjunctive signals that the complement
proposition is contrary to the common ground expectations or presuppositions. This is the so
called contrary to expectations subjunctive.
The contrary to expectations subjunctive is found not only with negation, but also with
lexical predicates that include an element of doubt, uncertainty, implicit negation, such as: doubt,
think, believe, matter, fancy, imagine, complain, reproach, etc. But this subjunctive also may
appear with verbs that fail to express uncertainty, to suggest that the complement clause is
contrary to the presuppositions in the common ground. Here are examples:
(42) a. And that you should deceive me –well, I don't exactly understand it, but I can imagine
it. b. It doesn't matter that Max should have bought a Cadillac. c. To think that he should
have done it at last! d. I doubt that he should succeed.
Conclusions
1. The indicative and the subjunctive represent the main propositional modalities of
English. Each of the two grammatical moods is associated with a semantic content that limits its
distribution.
2 Grammatical mood is (one of ) the linguistic manifestation(s) of semantic modality.
The indicative/ subjunctive dichotomy represents a binary classification of the contexts with
respect to which propositions are evaluated. The contexts are classified function of a basic
designated one, identifiable as that of basic simple non-modalised assertion. In this case the base
is totally realistic. Contexts sufficiently alike to the basic one use the indicative, contexts
sufficiently remote from the basic one use the subjunctive.
3. The indicative mood appears whenever the complement proposition is asserted or at
least evaluated with respect to a realistic background. This is in line with its factual, descriptive
nature.
4. The subjunctive signals a non-realistic conversational background and the presence of
an ordering source. This is in line with its normative ('ought to be'), prescriptive ('ought to do')
character.